generative methods in urban design: a progress assessment

20
This article was downloaded by: [217.111.223.226] On: 26 May 2015, At: 03:49 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Journal of Urbanism: International Research on Placemaking and Urban Sustainability Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjou20 Generative methods in urban design: a progress assessment Michael W. Mehaffy a a Environmental Structure Research Group , Lake Oswego, OR, USA Published online: 23 May 2008. To cite this article: Michael W. Mehaffy (2008) Generative methods in urban design: a progress assessment, Journal of Urbanism: International Research on Placemaking and Urban Sustainability, 1:1, 57-75, DOI: 10.1080/17549170801903678 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17549170801903678 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

Upload: iaac

Post on 21-Apr-2023

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

This article was downloaded by: [217.111.223.226]On: 26 May 2015, At: 03:49Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

Journal of Urbanism: International Researchon Placemaking and Urban SustainabilityPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscriptioninformation:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjou20

Generative methods in urban design: aprogress assessmentMichael W. Mehaffy aa Environmental Structure Research Group , Lake Oswego, OR, USAPublished online: 23 May 2008.

To cite this article: Michael W. Mehaffy (2008) Generative methods in urban design: a progress assessment,Journal of Urbanism: International Research on Placemaking and Urban Sustainability, 1:1, 57-75, DOI:10.1080/17549170801903678

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17549170801903678

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”)contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and ourlicensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, orsuitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publicationare the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor &Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independentlyverified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for anylosses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilitieswhatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to orarising out of the use of the Content.

This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantialor systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, ordistribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and usecan be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

RESEARCH PAPER

Generative methods in urban design: a progress assessment

Michael W. Mehaffy

Environmental Structure Research Group, Lake Oswego, OR, USA

The year 2007 marked the 20-year anniversary of A New Theory of Urban Design (1987),a slender volume by Christopher Alexander and colleagues that serves as a notablemilepost within the half-century old ‘‘design methods movement’’ in which Alexanderhimself played a seminal role. The ‘‘generative’’ design method of A New Theory focusedless upon the specification of a final form through schematic planning, and more on thestepwise process by which a form might emerge from the evolutionary actions of agroup of collaborators. In so doing, it challenged the notion of ‘‘design’’ as a progressiveexpression of schematic intentions, and argued for a conception of design as a stepwise,non-linear evolution in response to a series of contextual urban factors. In the 20 yearssince, significant progress has been made to develop the insights of generativity in urbandesign, as in other fields. Some of Alexander’s ideas have been incorporated – notablyby practitioners of The New Urbanism – and some have been challenged and dismissed,including, notably, by Alexander himself. The author assesses progress since thismilepost volume – substantial, he argues – as well as setbacks and shortcomings, andsignificant opportunities still remaining.

Keywords: generative methods, design methods; process; organic growth

Introduction

Just recently we passed the 20-year anniversary of the publication of a slim and influential

volume titled A New Theory of Urban Design (1987). In it the mathematician, architect,

and theoretical iconoclast Christopher Alexander sought to establish ‘‘a new theory of

urban design which attempts to recapture the process by which cities develop organically’’

(Alexander et al. 1997, p. 2).

This organic development, writes Alexander and co-authors, ‘‘is not a vague feeling of

relationship with biological forms. It is not an analogy.’’ It is, they say, a specific structuralquality: ‘‘namely, each of these towns grew as a whole, under its own laws of wholeness’’

(Alexander et al., p. 1). Alexander and co-authors then proceed to develop these ‘‘laws of

wholeness’’ with detailed structural logic, and to propose a method by which this quality can

be attained again in a contemporary context – not through a conventional kind of master

plan, but through a process involving the sequential collaboration of a series of participants.

We can describe such a method as generative. That is, we cannot know in advance the

nature of the geometric results that will emerge from the complex process, though we may

know the general aims of the participants. We will generally avoid simplifying mechanismssuch as large-scale diagrammic concepts, rigid typologies, or so-called ‘‘design partis’’ (i.e.

schemata),1 especially in the early stages. Instead, the collaborating participants will

together generate an evolving form that grows out of a complex transformation of the

existing place and its people, together with all its environmental, social, and cultural

*Email: [email protected]

Journal of Urbanism

Vol. 1, No. 1, March 2008, 57–75

ISSN 1754-9175 print/ISSN 1754-9183 online

# 2008 Taylor & Francis

DOI: 10.1080/17549170801903678

http://www.informaworld.com

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

factors. Such a generative process is continuous, and cannot be frozen in a standardized

master plan.2

In this sense, A New Theory of Urban Design was a challenge to the very idea of urban

design as an act of conventional schematic ‘‘master planning’’, and an assertion that designmust be a continuous evolutionary response to a complex environment of urban conditions.

While the performance criteria may be clear at the outset, the designer’s role is not to specify

the final form, but rather the intermediate process that will generate that form.

Twenty years later, we can take stock of the developments since. Has anything like

Alexander’s ‘‘generativity’’ been incorporated into conventional urban design methodol-

ogies? What of the efforts to engage citizens in participatory design processes? What of the

efforts of New Urbanists to conduct collaborative ‘‘charrettes’’ and apply ‘‘many hands’’

in the production of the result? What of other efforts to incorporate complexity into designstrategies, or, in some cases, partially to abdicate the authority of the designer in the face

of urban complexity (as was famously argued, for example, in Rem Koolhaas’s (1995)

essay ‘‘Whatever happened to urbanism?’’). What have been the lessons learned from these

experiences, and the opportunities still to be developed?

We will argue that progress has indeed been made, but important opportunities remain

to be developed. We will point to flaws in previous efforts, including Alexander’s own

methods and assumptions (flaws that in many cases Alexander himself has already noted);

and we will discuss more recent efforts, their promises and drawbacks, and further

opportunities remaining.

Generative methods before New Theory

The holism described by Alexander and colleagues was not, of course, a new theoretical

recognition of Alexander’s team: indeed, the subject has been an active one in many

scientific fields over the last half century or so, from quantum mechanics to cognition to

neuroscience to embryology to genetics. Alexander, the Cambridge-trained physicist,

mathematician, and polymath, was well aware of these parallel trends.

In fact, Alexander was one of the early pioneers of the so-called ‘‘design methods’’

movement, an effort to establish systematic evolutionary methods in design, through

which a designer (or group of designers) can move methodically through the steps in a

design process, and not merely rely upon more intuitive and unpredictable approaches,nor on rigid typological prescriptions. The field was driven by the need to cope with

increasing complexity in technological problems in the era after World War II, fueled by

the development of cybernetics and computer software (Broadbent 1979). It was believed

that the old intuitive methods of design experts were simply not reliable enough to manage

this complex challenge. Within this field, Alexander’s work focused on the ‘‘decomposi-

tion’’ of a design problem, and the synthesis of the parts into a new form on the basis of

various design inputs.

Problems with the so-called ‘‘first generation’’ of design methods (including criticisms

by Alexander himself and others) led to the development of a ‘‘second generation’’. Forinvestigators like Horst Rittel, we would need to distinguish between ‘‘tame problems’’

(which were dealt with well enough in the first generation) and the more common ‘‘wicked

problems,’’ which include multifaceted problems like those that are typical at a larger

urban scale. To cope with this complexity, the new methodology must therefore

incorporate an ‘‘argumentative process’’ within a network of issues. Moreover, the

designer is no longer a solitary ‘‘expert’’ but a collaborator with the client and with other

experts (Fowles 1977).

Yet a ‘‘third generation’’ of design method, around 1980, accelerated the emphasis oncollaborative process, and offered a model in which the designer (or collaboration of

58 M.W. Mehaffy

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

designers) would propose ‘‘refutable hypotheses’’ for consideration by the client.

Moreover, there need not be a single proposal for consideration; indeed, a ‘‘plurality ofviews’’ was necessary (Dulgeroglu-Vuksel 1999).

Alexander himself grew disinterested with the movement he helped pioneer, and ceased

to interact significantly with its proponents. But his work clearly evolved in a similar

direction, as he began to incorporate users in the design process, and as his method

featured a cycle of evaluation for testable design propositions.

Alexander’s development of pattern languages was also an outgrowth of his strategy to

deal with what Simon (1962) had earlier termed ‘‘the architecture of complexity.’’ His

‘‘patterns’’ were in essence recurring clusters of design configuration, which could be

recombined adaptively to create new design solutions. Alexander had long noted as well

that the structure of cities included overlap and structural plurality. His ‘‘patternlanguages’’ offered a grammatical system whereby the patterns could be recombined in

redundant, overlapping ways.

As noted above, all these insights had their corollaries in the scientific developments of

that time, the understanding of the ways that complex systems exhibited interrelations of

their elements – and the implications for designers.

Generative methods and ‘‘organized complexity’’

A classic exposition of the implications of the phenomenon of ‘‘organized complexity’’ for

city planners and urban designers was made by Jane Jacobs in the last chapter of her

landmark book The Death and Life of Great American Cities (1961). Its influence on theplanning discipline in general, and on subsequent thinking about process and generativity in

particular, is difficult to overstate. (For example, Google Scholar lists over 2000 citations.)

In a remarkably prescient chapter called ‘‘The kind of problem a city is,’’ Jacobs

lucidly analyzed the implications of the scientific advancements that were then occurring –

in particular, the understanding of complex systems in which a number of factors were‘‘interrelated into an organic whole’’ (p. 432). This was important for urbanists because

they needed to be sure they were thinking about the right kind of problem, and using the

right tools to solve it.

Science, Jacobs wrote, had grown in the last 400 years from Newtonian, ‘‘two-

variable’’ science, to the other extreme of statistical phenomena, in which myriad variables

interacted. This trend reached its zenith in the early 20th century, and powered thephenomenal growth of industrial technology in its early phases.

Gradually, however, 20th-century science began to understand the realm in between,

in which more than two variables interacted in important ways. This new domain opened

up ‘‘immense and brilliant progress’’ for the life sciences, which has fueled much of the

revolutionary work in genetics and other fields. Indeed, since 1961, progress in the fieldhas only accelerated and delivered astonishing new revelations in embryology,

morphogenesis, cognition, and many other fields outside the life sciences too. Jacobs

was one of the first to spot the implications for urban design and planning.

But planning and architecture, she noted, were lagging behind – still trying to treat the

problems of the city as either simple two-variable problems of simplicity (this many jobsover here, that many houses over there) or problems of statistical populations to be

managed, almost as files in a drawer. They misunderstood ‘‘the kind of problem a city is’’

– with devastating results.

This amounted to a devastating critique on the top-down master-planning approach –

from the highly influential Garden Cities movement, which sought to isolate and neatly

segregate planning variables such as housing and jobs (Figure 1), to the statistically informed‘‘towers in the park’’ of Le Corbusier and other modernists, relying upon statistical

Journal of Urbanism 59

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

management of family sizes and income groups into schemes that conceptually resemble

nothing so much as giant filing cabinets (Figure 2):

With these techniques, it was possible not only to conceive of people, their incomes, theirspending money and their housing as fundamentally problems in disorganized complexity,susceptible to conversion into problems of simplicity once ranges and averages were workedout, but also to conceive of dry traffic, industry, parks, and even cultural facilities ascomponents of disorganized complexity, convertible into problems of simplicity. (Jacobs 1961)

But this is a disastrous strategy, she argues, likely to miss critical organic relationships, and

likely to result in dysfunctional, sterile and oppressive environments:

As long as [we] cling to the unexamined assumptions that [we] are dealing with a problem in thephysical sciences, city planning cannot possibly progress. Of course it stagnates. It lacks the firstrequisite for a body of practical and progressing thought: recognition of the kind of problem atissue. Lacking this, it has found the shortest distance to a dead end. (Jacobs 1961, p. 439)

Processes, Jacobs says, are of the essence in cities – and in the ways we must interact

with them. The neat segregation of earlier planning methods must be discarded, in place of

a more diverse, more mixed model – managed not by simplistic top-down schemes, but by

a kind of diagnostic approach, seeking to understand and treat the existing system,

transforming it to a healthier state – almost as a medical professional would do.

In the years since Jacobs’s landmark work, many authors and practitioners paid

homage to her insights. Yet Jacobs reportedly found this vexing.3 Planners, in particular,

were the subject of her harsh and continuing criticism for failing to respond to her

critiques – worse, pretending to honor her ideas while in fact continuing with disastrous

conventional policies. For her, apparently, the lessons of process and generativity

embodied in organized complexity were not being taken nearly seriously enough.

Figure 1. Ebenezer Howard’s Garden Cities plan sought to segregate into neat binary relationships

the variables of housing, employment, and other urban factors.

60 M.W. Mehaffy

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

In the intervening years, a number of other prominent planners have taken up the

challenge to deal more effectively with ‘‘organized complexity.’’ Bill Hillier, Professor of

Urban and Architectural Morphology at University College London’s Bartlett School of

Planning, developed his theory of so-called ‘‘space syntax,’’ a methodology that maps the

connective relationships within a spatial system, and expresses the global connective

properties of each element. In so doing Hillier has devised an elegant tool to show, in discrete

units, the results of a complex set of connections of a number of globally interacting spatial

variables. A street segment that is well connected within its global context shows high

connectivity, and thus might be especially appropriate for a retail function, or a civic element.

In this way, the local functions emerge from the generative properties of the global ones –

exactly, Hillier argues, the way they did in many traditional organic cities (Hillier 1989, 1999).

Mike Batty, Hillier’s colleague at UCL, has also developed a number of methodologies to

analyze and manipulate environmental complexity. His ‘‘Center for Advanced Spatial

Analysis’’ has used generative algorithms to analyze various organic patterns and their

generative rules. Batty and his team have paid special attention to the properties of ‘‘self-

organization,’’ the tendency of systems to develop patterns of organized complexity

spontaneously as a result of algorithmic sequences of activity. Just as bird flocks form

large-scale coherent patterns from simple rules of distance followed by each bird, so residents

of an informal city can build roads and other remarkably coherent structures by following

relatively simple rules (Batty 1991, Batty et al. 1997).

These insights parallel, and clearly draw from, the rapid developments in complexity

science in general, and in particular the phenomenon known as ‘‘emergence.’’ Investigators

have been able to identify with mathematical precision the processes that give rise to complex

structures from an apparently simple set of rules, with useful implications for game theory,

economics, biology, physics, meteorology, and many other fields. In the fields of planning and

urban design, the insights can be used to understand the relationship between complex urban

form and relatively simple generative rules – like those followed by a group of actors in a

building process.

The significance of Hillier’s and Batty’s tools is that they have applied these insights to the

urban toolkit available to conventional practitioners, in effect to re-grow the urban

complexity that previously existed or could potentially exist, with desirable results. Hillier’s

analytical technique in particular has been put to the test a number of times with notable

Figure 2. Le Corbusier’s unbuilt Voisin Plan for

Paris, which would have replaced much of that

city’s organic fabric with neat, filing cabinet-like

housing for statistically managed populations.

Figure 3. Cathedral design. A relatively simple

system of nested centers with moderate overlap.

Journal of Urbanism 61

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

success. His analysis of the proposed modification of London’s Trafalgar Square predicted

an increase of pedestrian activity of some 16-fold. The actual results of the work, Hillier

reports, were very close to that prediction.4

The publication of A New Theory of Urban Design (1987)

Twenty-six years after Jacobs’s The Death and Life (1961), Alexander and colleagues

published A New Theory of Urban Design (1987) – containing more than a strong echo of

Jacobs’s emphasis on process, and on the understanding and treatment of existing organic

wholes. To Jacobs’s insights, Alexander made several significant additions. Chiefly, he

wanted to propose a methodology by which such a collaborative process could produce

geometries that had the characteristic of organized complexity – the characteristic he

identified as ‘‘wholeness.’’

A New Theory of Urban Design is not among Alexander’s best-known works. It is

surely eclipsed by such familiar works as his landmark PhD thesis, which became his first

book, Notes on the Synthesis of Form (1964); his elegant little paper on differential urban

geometry, ‘‘A city is not a tree’’ (1965); his perennial bestseller A Pattern Language

(Alexander et al. 1977), reportedly the best-selling treatise on architecture of all time; and

its companion volume, The Timeless Way of Building (1979). According to Harvard Design

Review Editor William Saunders, A Pattern Language ‘‘could very well be the most read

architectural treatise of all time’’ (Saunders 2002). By comparison, A New Theory was a

modest seller, and did not seem to have anything like the professional impact of the others.

Yet two decades later, the little volume seems to carry an influence far beyond its initial

sales would suggest. We hear its ideas still discussed today,5 and we may find it sitting

prominently on rather unlikely bookshelves. Moreover, as argued herein, it serves as a kind of

milestone in the discourse on process and generativity in urban design.

Even Alexander’s own assessment would not suggest that A New Theory should have

the legacy it has. Alexander himself argued later that the book’s focus was still too heavily

upon the formal design product, and did not deal sufficiently with processes of social

interaction, site assessment, financial arrangements, or construction sequencing and

management. Even the basic problem of geometric form was not dealt with sufficiently, he

argued. All these topics would be taken up in far greater detail in his much more recent

magnum opus, The Nature of Order (2003–04).

Yet in this volume, Alexander and colleagues did squarely reintroduce the notion of

process into the debate about urban design – a process that aims, above all, to generate

wholeness within the urban structure:

We have therefore used the phrase urban design in the title of this book, since it seems to usthat urban design, of all existing disciplines, is the one which comes closest to acceptingresponsibility for the city’s wholeness. (Alexander et al. 2003–04, p. 3)

But Alexander wants to challenge the very notion of design, and its sovereignty over city-

making as a technical exercise or a creation of ‘‘master plans:’’

But we propose a discipline of urban design which is different, entirely, from the one knowntoday. We believe that the task of creating wholeness in the city can only be dealt with as aprocess. It cannot be solved by design alone, but only when the process by which the city getsits form is fundamentally changed. (Alexander et al. 2003–04, p. 3)

The echoes of Jacobs are readily recognizable. But there are also echoes of Alexander’s

own earlier work on the overlapping networks within cities, discussed in ‘‘A city is not a

tree’’ (Alexander 1965). There are echoes of the earlier preoccupation with the problem of

morphogenesis, the synthesis of form, and in particular the mereological relation of parts

and wholes, that has been Alexander’s focus from the beginning of his career to this day.

62 M.W. Mehaffy

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

The significance of A New Theory of Urban Design may be that it did, tentatively, propose

a specific process by which a group of collaborators on an urban project might create such

organic wholes more successfully, following a series of explicit rules.

In the experiment that forms the second section of the book, Alexander had 18

graduate students play various roles in a simulated process of urban growth. The roles

included designers, developers, citizens, administrators, and others, making up a

population not unlike that involved in the growth of a historic small city, or the

community-led development of an actual neighborhood.

The role-players followed one overriding rule: every increment of construction must be

made in such a way as to heal the city. Here he uses the word ‘‘heal’’ in the original sense

of ‘‘to make whole.’’ That is, we must take a series of incremental steps in construction,

and at each step we must make an assessment about whether the proposed construction

adds to, or takes away from, the wholeness of the city.

He further defines this rule as follows: every act of construction has just one basic

obligation: it must create a continuous structure of wholes around itself. That is, we

must look at the way that the construction forms and changes patterns, and whether

those patterns are patterns of coherent wholes, or of poorly related fragments and

slivers. An extreme example of the latter is what planners derisively call ‘‘SLOAP’’ –

‘‘space left over after planning.’’ An example of the former is a nicely formed new spot

that we would find appealing to be in, and that we would find well related to the spaces

around it.

How are these wholes to be understood and manipulated? Alexander, ever the

Cambridge mathematician, introduces a geometric entity he calls a ‘‘center’’ – a key element

of the theory explained in more detail in his later and much larger work, The Nature of Order

(2003–04). Philosophers of process will recognize strong similarities to Alfred North

Whitehead’s system of ‘‘actual entities’’ in that philosopher’s magnum opus, Process and

Reality (1928). But in essence, centers are simply localities, or ‘‘spots,’’ embedded within a

field of other centers. A center is not a ‘‘point,’’ but rather, a field – as Alexander puts it, ‘‘a

whole, made of subsidiary wholes.’’

A field of centers, then, is a nested series of localities that frame one another and

variously connect to one another in a pattern of relationships. Such a field comprises its

own center at a larger scale. Conversely, every such center is embedded in a field of other

centers that affect its structure and the structure of the wholes that result from their

combinations. This field is contextual and infinite, but the contextual influence of more

remote centers will generally recede with distance.

So too, every center incorporates other centers at smaller and smaller scales: houses,

rooms, corners, floor tiles, patterns, etc. However, these smaller centers need not all fit neatly

within the larger center: they can overlap with other larger centers as well.

The usefulness of this approach can be understood in a series of examples.

The cathedral design in Figure 3 can be seen as a relatively simple series of

geometrically related centers. Every part of the structure feels coherent and well related to

the other parts. Every region sits neatly nested within larger regions, with some occasional

overlap, while every region is simultaneously composed of smaller regions. At the scale of

a building, the plan feels whole and appealing. If it were a larger structure – if it were the

plan for a city, for example – it might feel much too rigid and imposed.

Figure 4 shows a much more complex series of centers from Giambattista Nolli’s

engraved plan of Rome (1748). Highlighted are only a small number of them to illustrate

the point. Note again that at the scale of buildings the centers are fairly neat and

symmetrical. At larger scales, the centers tend to overlap and wend around one another,

forming much more ‘‘organic’’ patterns. As Jacobs described, the ‘‘organic’’ character of

Journal of Urbanism 63

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

these patterns is nothing other than the complex set of relationships by which they are

‘‘interrelated into an organic whole.’’

Figure 5 shows an obvious counter-example. The large, undifferentiated geometry

makes no attempt to adjust itself to its surrounding space. The shape of the paving,

fencing, and other elements bears strikingly little relation to the space around them, and

the overall form is unappealing in the extreme. This is a good example of the kind of

outdoor space that planners derisively refer to as ‘‘SLOAP.’’

The structuring process the students followed is as follows.

As one center ‘X’ is produced, so, simultaneously, other centers must also be

produced, at three well-defined levels:

Larger than X. At least one other center must be produced at a scale larger than X, and in sucha way that X is part of this larger center, and helps to support it.

The same size as X. Other centers must be produced at he same size as X, and adjacent to X, sothat there is no ‘‘negative space’’ [i.e. SLOAP] left near X.

Smaller than X. Still other centers must be produced at a scale smaller than X, and in such away that they help to support the existence of X.

Alexander and his students structure the centers of their projects with seven ‘‘detailed rules

of growth.’’ Each of these is composed of still other sub-rules:

N Piecemeal growth governs the increment of growth, the distribution of elements, and

the diversity of uses.

N The growth of larger wholes governs the way that emergent wholes are identified and

reinforced, so that they become large-scale features of the urban plan. In this way,

Figure 4. Giambattista Nolli’s engraved plan of Rome; a detail from his Nuova pinata di Roma

(1748). Note the much more complex system of messy, overlapping regions and centers.

64 M.W. Mehaffy

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

such large-scale features as main streets, public squares and the like emerge from the

sequential process, not unlike the way they did in many historic cities.

N Visions ensure that the human participants will use their perceptual and imaginative

ability at each step to assess the coherence of each increment. This is necessary to

ensure that each increment is a well-adapted human space, with attributes of most

value to human beings.

N Positive urban space ensures that there is no SLOAP around the structures, and that

pedestrian space, gardens, streets, and other exterior spaces are well formed and

coherent.

N The layout of large buildings provides detailed steps for the successful layout of area,

size, entrance, main outdoor elements, major interior areas, and so on, for each

large building. This section of the process comes very close to what Alexander later

came to call a ‘‘generative code’’ (see below).

N Construction deals with the details of a building, and the iteration between how it is

to be built and how it is to appear.

N Formation of centers provides detailed guidance of the geometric shaping of centers,

as a kind of tension between its own internal tendency to create local symmetry, and

the larger adaptation that tends to pull the symmetry apart. For Alexander the

geometer, this is a characteristic feature of whole systems:

One of the reasons we can always recognize a real structure of centers as fast as we do is

that we can always detect the truth in the balance of symmetry and asymmetry, even when

we do not know what is going on functionally:

Thus, we may see the creation of the field of centers, as the creation of a loosely connectedsystem of local symmetries, always relaxed, always allowing necessity to guide it, in such a wayas to produce the deepest possible structure of centers, at every scale. (Alexander et al. 2003–04,p. 95)

Thus, Alexander’s approach is fundamentally contextual, relying upon a continuous

cyclical, stepwise response to existing conditions. In actual projects, Alexander often asks

participants to walk the site, set stakes, meet residents, spend time, and let the site’s

Figure 5. An example of ‘‘space left over after planning’’ (‘‘SLOAP’’). This is residual space with a

purely accidental and fragmentary structure of centers. Not surprisingly, as urban space it often

functions very poorly.

Journal of Urbanism 65

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

attributes seep in (see Figures 6–9). He often continues this process through the design and

the construction, even into the maintenance and repair of a completed project. In this

exercise, Alexander and his students used a large-scale model as an approximation of the

actual site. They did visit the actual site, and incorporated a number of its existing

structures into the model at the outset.

Alexander’s challenge

A New Theory of Urban Design amounted to a gauntlet thrown down to conventional

urban design, not unlike that thrown down by Jacobs 26 years earlier.

Alexander himself was tentative about the particular methodology he proposed.

Indeed, as discussed, he later offered his own critique of its shortcomings. But he was not

then, nor has he been since, tentative about the key theoretical points on which this

methodology differed from conventional practice:

N Urban design must not be an act of tabula rasa imposition of a form designed

remotely, based upon an abstract program. It must understand, respect, and seek to

improve the existing conditions.

N Urban design must incorporate the decisions and needs of the local stakeholders, as

a matter not only of fairness, but also of the intrinsic quality of the result.

Figures 6–9. Alexander’s generativity from natural and cultural sources can be seen in the examples

here. Figure 6 (top left), the cultural expression of a Japanese school; and, Figure 7 (top right), a

California farmer’s market. Figure 8 (bottom left), a generative process to stake out a new

neighborhood in Colombia; and, Figure 9 (bottom right), a drawing of such a community after it has

been staked on site.

66 M.W. Mehaffy

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

N Above all, urban design must be a generative process, from which a form will emerge

– one that cannot be pre-planned or standardized, but will of necessity be, at least in

some key respects, local and unique.

Implementation: the ‘‘many hands’’ of the New Urbanism

Perhaps the most notable example of an effort to implement Alexander’s ideas – and

Jacobs’s in equal measure, it should be added – has been the New Urbanism movement.

The Congress for the New Urbanism was formed by six architects, growing out of a 1991

workshop at the Ahwahnee Lodge in California’s Yosemite Park. It was rather ironically

modeled on the Congres International d’Architecture Moderne (CIAM), the highly

effective organization that propagated the modernist movement in architecture, which

accelerated the kind of segregation and top-down formalism in city-planning that both

Jacobs and Alexander decried.

By contrast, the New Urbanism is explicitly about mixed use, and, its proponents

would argue, about process.

By all accounts, Andres Duany has played a leading role in the creation of New

Urbanism. His plan for Seaside, Florida, attracted enormous attention and prompted

the coining of the term ‘‘new urbanism’’ by author Peter Katz (with Duany’s

encouragement). Duany credits Alexander as being a major influence on the New

Urbanism, and has gone so far as to tell this author that Alexander’s ideas are the basis

of ‘‘everything that we’re doing now’’ (Mehaffy 2004b). The New Urbanism includes a

Charter with 27 principles for the structuring of urban form, including emphasis on

mixed use, socio-economic diversity, historic preservation, walkability, and related

objectives. It also includes a set of methodologies for the urban design process, at the

heart of which is a workshop tool called a charrette.

Named after the cart that once gathered student drawings at the famous Ecole de

Beaux-Arts in Paris, the charrette is an intensive design workshop that typically runs from

four to nine days. It brings together urban designers, transportation planners, civil

engineers, government officials, local residents, and other stakeholders and technical

experts as the project may require. The Jacobsian and Alexandrian aim is to focus

collaboration on design, and to produce an emergent result.

It is important to understand that a charrette is not merely a ‘‘user consultation,’’ of the

sort that was commonplace before The New Urbanism, but a real-time design process in

which users provide collaborative input, along with an interdisciplinary mix of professionals.

It is, according to Duany, an exercise to provide exactly the kind of collaborative synthesis

that Alexander described in A New Theory of Urban Design.

Alexander’s critique

For Alexander, however, the charrette is a laudable effort at reform that is still woefully

inadequate for the challenge. His criticism rests on three principal objections:

N The charrette process is still a relatively brief and isolated act of master planning

done in a remote room, away from the site, and away from the opportunities and

constraints that might turn up in a longer and more direct process of contextual

engagement.

N The participants, especially the local residents, are forced to play a highly

circumscribed role, in which the ‘‘outside experts’’ disproportionately influence the

process.

Journal of Urbanism 67

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

N The master plan is then usually turned over to a developer, who can then interpret

the master plan in a variety of usually disastrous ways. Most importantly for

Alexander, the developer typically builds structures that are not at all generative,

but based upon standardized templates, with the result that they feel lifeless andunsuccessful. They may have the outward appearance of a more organic

neighborhood, but they are, in the end, standardized reproductions.

For Alexander, the most serious problem is the fact that the output of the charrette – a

‘‘master plan’’ – is usually turned over to developers:

I think that many of the people who are involved in the CNU actually have not understood theproblems that the developer represents, and what has got to be done in order to change thatsituation. It’s very very serious. (Mehaffy 2004a)

Alexander clearly feels great sympathy with the New Urbanists, but equally clearly feels

unease at the result of New Urbanist work:

I’m proud of them, because they’ve really done something to help change things. But whenyou say, well, what are the rules that they actually live by? I’m talking about ‘‘live by’’ whenthey’re shaping something, modeling it, drawing it, planning it, things like that – building it,and so forth – the concepts that they are living by there are not those which I’ve just beenspeaking about, having to do with whether you’re making part of nature. They’re actuallysomething highly artificial …. (Mehaffy 2004a)

The New Urbanists’ rebuttal – and a counter-critique

For New Urbanists such as Duany, Alexander’s critique misses a key point. Yes, there are

standardized templates within The New Urbanism – as, for example, the so-called ‘‘parti,’’

a basic plan drawing of the scheme. But that structure can then be adapted and allowed to

serve as a skeletal form for more organic growth. In effect, it can serve as a kind of well-designed ‘‘trellis’’ on which organic growth can self-organize. Duany notes that such

combinations of the standard and the contextual are common in nature.

Duany and others point to Alexander’s own patterns as typological structures that are,

in part, standardized elements within his own design system (though a networked one, and

not a strict hierarchy). They are then adapted to the specific context, and used in a kind of

flexible grammar. Duany believes he is doing something very similar (and indeed, often

using Alexander’s own patterns). ‘‘I am the best Alexandrian,’’ he recently told the author.

Moreover, Duany believes Alexander is failing to come to terms with a core reality of

modern technological society:6 that large numbers demand top-down management

methods. In a mass society, the norm quickly reverts to chaos and kitsch. In order to

implement Alexander’s methods, this demands expert, top-down leaders for the design andconstruction process – a role, Duany points out, that Alexander himself often plays in his

own projects. But the scale of reform does not permit the kind of painstaking one-off

approach for which Alexander is known.

These points were evident in comments by Duany in an interview with the author

(Mehaffy 2004b). He was asked to expand on his comment that ‘‘getting things implemented

on a large scale’’ was one of the aspects of modernity that interested him:

Isn’t there a danger, as Chris Alexander has warned, that that kind of large scale doesn’t allowthe grain of adaptation that’s going to be required for good urbanism and good architecture?Isn’t scale one of the key things that the modernists screwed up on so badly?

Duany replied:

Yes scale is a prime problem, but it is also THE reality of modernity. It cannot be avoided. Ibelieve it was Giedion, the theoretician of modernist architecture who said: ‘‘Ours is the problem

68 M.W. Mehaffy

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

of large numbers’’. These early modernists were very smart. There is immense population growth,even in the U.S.; there is the blinding speed of communication, of automatic decision protocolsand of mass production. If we return only to the crafting of cities, what we do may be of highquality but it will not be important. (Mehaffy 2004b)

For Duany and other critics, Alexander’s proposal is to return to a painstaking one-off

process of organic design, which is simply not up to the scale of the present challenge.

Rather, we must create more automatic processes that generate the same result, not unlike

seeds that generate vast numbers of living structures:

… What we must craft now are not the communities, but the programs that create themquickly automatically, replicating the organic process of sequential decisions. This mustachieve the authentic variety and resilience of traditional communities. These protocols mustbe propelled by the power grids, and not be tied to the limits of our personal efforts. Every oneof our ‘‘adversaries’’ operates from automated protocols. Protocols that flow 200 mortgagesfor 200 parametric strip shopping centers, all bundled for purchase in a single transaction byan insurance company. What would they do with our one-off creations? Inspect themindividually? They can’t. (Mehaffy 2004b)

The reference to ‘‘power grids’’ echoes a discussion that Duany and Alexander had in

1988. According to Duany, Alexander said to him, ‘‘we both know what the appliance is.

What we need to do now is to design the plugs to connect to the current power grid’’

(Mehaffy 2004b). For Duany, Alexander has neglected this task, whereas the New

Urbanists have pursued it with full force – accounting for the latter’s much more

prodigious output of projects.

So Duany and other New Urbanists have turned to a new project: the development of

codes that replace the old, destructive protocols with new ones that allow good urbanism

to flourish, as if on well-constructed trellises. The ‘‘SmartCode’’ is a form-based code that

replaces the segregated ‘‘Euclidean’’ zoning of an earlier era with a series of parametric

specifications designed to ensure coherent streetscapes and public realms. The code uses a

‘‘transect’’ system to organize contextual responses to the urban condition, from the most

intense urban setting to the most pristine natural environment.

Alexander’s ‘‘generative’’ code

But for Alexander, again, this kind of code does not address the core prerequisite of

generativity, and without such guidance for growth the result is still likely to be well-

aligned, lifeless junk. It prescribes a series of static parameters within which generative

events may occur, but it does not in any way facilitate or guide their generation. Moreover,

even to specify such parameters is to constrain the emergence of organic wholes, which

require an environment in which adaptation of form can occur as needed.

Almost in response to the New Urbanists, it would seem, Alexander has proposed an

alternate kind of code, based explicitly upon rule-based, generative processes of the kind

outlined in A New Theory of Urban Design. Alexander’s ‘‘generative code’’ addresses not

physical parameters of the built environment, but steps that the participants should take

together in laying out and detailing a given structure. Alexander likens it to a recipe, or a

medical procedure, in which the steps always follow a logically similar pattern, but the

actual actions continuously adapt to the context – the taste and texture of the food in the

case of a recipe, or the condition of the patient’s tissues in a medical procedure. But in this

case, the ‘‘recipe’’ or the ‘‘procedure’’ guides the unfolding of environmental form.

In its fullest form, this kind of generative code can be thought of as a design–build

system, addressing all of the conditions of building – financing, ownership, management,

sourcing, and, crucially, changes to the design along the way. For Alexander, the issue of

cost control is a manageable process, and indeed, is done regularly within existing design–

Journal of Urbanism 69

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

build approaches. He points out that much of the direction of technology is today aimed

favorably for such an approach – one-off manufacturing, customization, niche marketing,

and so on. He is convinced of the possibility and even the inevitability of this

transformation of technology, in a more adaptive, ultimately organic direction.

Nonetheless, Alexander recognizes that there are enormous challenges ahead to

making a practical version of such a system. He continues to work with a growing group

of collaborators (including the author) on such a project, and he has repeatedly stated that

he welcomes the opportunity to develop collaborations with New Urbanists like Duany, as

well as others.

Alternative approaches to generativity

Duany’s discussion of the ‘‘problem of large numbers’’ would find a sympathetic audience

with the architect and theorist Rem Koolhaas, his forensic opponent in a rather lackluster

debate in 1999 at Harvard’s Graduate School of Design. For Koolhaas – perhaps

representing many other contemporary ‘‘neo-modernist’’ architects – the modern city is

simply too complex to yield to a reform agenda like that of the New Urbanists. In the face

of sheer quantity, architecture is powerless to change the direction of the urban wave, and

therefore is wiser to seek merely to surf that wave with skill:

This century has been a losing battle with the issue of quantity. … In spite of its early promise,its frequent bravery, urbanism has been unable to invent and implement at the scale demandedby its apocalyptic demographics. (Koolhaas 1995)

Koolhaas challenges Duany’s faith in planning, and suggests that urbanism is now the art

of accommodating generativity, rather than the futile attempt to ‘‘design’’ it:

If there is to be a ‘‘new urbanism’’ it will not be based on the twin fantasies of order andomnipotence; it will be the staging of uncertainty; it will no longer be concerned with thearrangement of more or less permanent objects but with the irrigation of territories withpotential; it will no longer aim for stable configurations but for the creation of enabling fields thataccommodate processes that refuse to be crystallized into definitive form …. (Koolhaas 1995)

Another approach to generativity is typified by Peter Eisenman, Alexander’s partner in a

famous and telling debate in 1982, since billed as ‘‘Contrasting Concepts of Harmony in

Architecture’’ (Eisenman and Alexander 1982). In his book Code X: The City of Culture of

Galicia (Eisenman Architects 2005), Eisenman discusses his theory of coding as a

generative method of producing form. The theory was put to the test in the City of Culture

of Galicia project in Santiago de Compostela, Spain, the most urban in scale of

Eisenman’s projects (see Figures 10–13).

The project narrative describes a transition from an architecture of semiotics (symbolic

expressions) to an architecture of generated geometries or ‘‘traces:’’

This post-semiotic sensibility is not dominated by easily consumed imagery of signs andsignifieds, but rather is understood as a series of traces, marks that produce an alternativecondition of figure and ground. The City of Culture evolves from the superposition of threesets of traces. First, the plan of the medieval center of Santiago is placed on the hillside site,which overlooks the city. Second, a Cartesian grid is laid over these medieval routes. Third, thetopography of the hillside is allowed to distort the two flat geometries, thus generating atopological surface that superposes old and new in a simultaneous matrix.

The original center of Santiago conforms to a figure/ground urbanism. The buildings are figuraland the streets, residual. Through this transformative mapping operation, our project emerges asa warped surface that is neither figure nor ground but both a figured ground and a figured figurethat supercedes the figure-ground urbanism of the old city. Santiago’s medieval past appears notas a form of representational nostalgia but as an active present found in a tactile, pulsating newform. (Eisenman Associates 2007)

70 M.W. Mehaffy

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

The generativity in Eisenman’s approach can be contrasted with the generativity exhibited

in the nearby historic town it echoes (Figure 10). The latter has emerged from the

collaborative and rule-based actions of many actors over time, and from the

environmental conditions to which they have adapted. Artistic abstractions and planning

schemata do occur, but are expressed as local elements within the more global adaptations

to environment, culture, human activity and need.

By contrast, Eisenman’s generativity is used solely as a resource for one artist’s

expressive master plan, imposed on the site at a very large scale. In that sense its semiotics

is in fact alive and well, but disguised within a subtler artistic reference to incidentally

generated traces of its natural subject. It regenerates only the most skeletally abstract

aspects of the historic evolutionary pattern, so as to avoid ‘‘representational nostalgia.’’ It

is otherwise a static and non-adaptive work of art.

Koolhaas’s and Eisenman’s positions here can be contrasted with Jacobs’s.7 For

Jacobs, urban practice was a proper intervention in the interest of the health of an urban

system, accomplished by patient inductive study and by manipulation of subtle catalytic

factors. Art was a dimension of this work, but far from its only dimension. She would

arguably regard Koolhaas’s nihilism as little more than the predictably frustrated reaction

to a continued failure to adopt the most recent and most accurate model of ‘‘the kind of

problem a city is.’’ She would arguably regard Eisenman’s position as an altogether

different model – a hijacking of the city by fine artists, who would see it transformed into

an enormous abstract sculpture gallery. This, she frequently warned, was a dangerous

attitude: ‘‘The city cannot be a work of art’’ (Jacobs 1961, p. 372).

Figures 10–13. Figure 10 (top left), the relation of the plan to the organic terrain and medieval city;

and, Figure 11 (top right), the conceptual diagram of the plan. Figure 12 (bottom left), a site model;

and, Figure 13 (bottom right), the project under construction. Courtesy: Eisenman Architects.

Journal of Urbanism 71

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

Interestingly, both Koolhaas and Eisenman have recently expressed remarkably

pointed misgivings about the efficacy of their approach, and the larger artistic culture of

which it is part. Speaking in Montreal in June 2007, Koolhaas lamented the effect of

laissez-faire market forces on the profession:

If you look back over the past 2,000 years, architecture dignified civic and public life. Then themarket economy happened, replacing all former values and erasing almost all ideology overthe entire world. What it represents for all of us today is an invitation to simply be extravagantand spectacular. … The work we do is no longer mutually reinforcing, but I would say thatany accumulation is counterproductive, to the point that each new addition reduces the sum’svalue. … So there are many problems, first of all our work, which is not able to find its wayout of this recurring dilemma, then there are the many reasons to question our sincerity andmotives. (quoted in La Giorgia 2007)

Eisenman, speaking at the same event, argued that we are in the late period of modernism

– its ‘‘death rattle’’ – but we are struggling to find a new paradigm to replace it:

We are in the rococo phase of modern architecture. … The problem we need to solve is theurgency of media to have something new to look at and talk about all the time. Our need to bein the news all the time. … The slowness required to find and understand meaning inarchitecture no longer has any attraction. [We need an architecture] that asks how, at thismoment in time, without a new paradigm, can we understand our discipline and our culture ina different way. (quoted in La Giorgia 2007)

Or perhaps we need to look more deeply for a new paradigm within the insights of modern

science and philosophy. This is precisely what Alexander has said he is seeking.8

In the planning disciplines, generativity has continued to develop in the work of other

investigators. In particular, the trend toward engagement of residents evident in the ‘‘third

generation’’ of the design methods movement has continued and accelerated. A notable

example is so-called Communicative Planning, which seeks to build inclusiveness,

incorporate difference, reach out to marginalized groups, and sensitize planners to a

wide variety of viewpoints and alternative ways of knowing (Qadeer 1997, Sandercock

2000, Harwood 2005). Sandercock (1998) describes the evolution of a ‘‘utopia with a

difference’’ (pp. 5, 119) a similar concept to Friedmann’s (2002) ‘‘open city’’ of diverse

peoples, united by applied principles of ecology, citizenship, and regional governance. The

planning profession has been plagued by the lack of a workable knowledge base about

how to communicate with diverse population groups (Wallace and Milroy 1999), but we

now see how ‘‘a thousand tiny empowerments’’ can help to constitute a more socially

transformative planning process (Sandercock 2000).

Communicative planning seeks to achieve collaborative consensus-building by, in effect,

developing ‘‘‘conversations’ between stakeholders from different social worlds’’ (Healey

1997, p. 219). Innovation, ‘‘drama,’’ and ‘‘a sense of play’’ are ways to ‘‘move the players and

embed their learning deeply’’ (Innes and Booher 1999, p. 19).

Conclusion

For all their disagreements, the cross-fertilizations between Alexander’s process advocates

and the New Urbanists continue, with constructive results. The topic of generativity

continues to loom large.9 Duany’s SmartCode – now adopted by dozens of municipalities

and under consideration as the national planning code of Scotland, among others – has

begun to take on some stepwise layout guides very similar to Alexander’s. (Some Alexander

allies, including this author, continue to urge the expansion of this offering.) Duany argues

that his code also incorporates many other aspects of generativity. For his part, Alexander

has continued to develop his proposal for a ‘‘generative code,’’ and to address the ‘‘massive

72 M.W. Mehaffy

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

process difficulties’’ that are posed by conventional building protocols, using many of the

New Urbanists’ insights.10

To be sure, Alexander faces daunting challenges that the more pragmatic New

Urbanists seem uniquely positioned to help meet. In fact, each seems to have a

complementary grasp on aspects of the problem that the other, through area of focus or

through sheer personality, seems much less able to address. This emerging model of

collaboration may hold more promise than either may realize.

A growing group of collaborators has assembled around this sharable, complementary

agenda, and begun to pursue lines that Alexander (for one) does not seem to find as

interesting – most significantly, ‘‘open-source’’ collaborations with biologists, ecologists,

sociologists, computer scientists and others. Such ‘‘open source’’ methods have yielded

remarkable results for the computer software developers who exported Alexander’s ideas

into that realm with remarkable effect.11

In an age of critical ecological and economic challenges, in which human technology

seems at nearly irreconcilable odds with ecological sustainability, Alexander argues that we

must have a much more serious look at the way that natural systems use generative processes

to achieve sustainable morphologies, and work to integrate those lessons into our own

human systems.12 Though progress has been slow – and yet, as has been argued herein,

substantial – Jacobs and Alexander demonstrate that this is a comprehensible problem, and

not one that is (to quote from Jacobs’s caricature, paraphrasing Warren Weaver) ‘‘in some

dark and foreboding way, irrational.’’ The opportunity remains to develop further

generative processes as a means to deliver more robust and more efficacious results – that is,

more sustainable results – within the field of urban design. But that task will surely demand

the combined and synergetic efforts of Alexander, Duany, and many others.

Notes

1. A ‘‘design parti’’ was a schematic diagram used early in the Beaux-Arts design process. ‘‘Parti’’

means to divide, hence to organize basic regions of the plan schematically in a diagrammatic

scheme.

2. Note, however, that Alexander does use master plan drawings as a form of design

communication, or entitlement documentation. He is, however, careful to emphasize that they

are snapshots in a longer process, and not any sort of ‘‘final’’ result. He does so by including

explicit generative processes as part of the planning documents. See, for example, The Master

Plan and Process for Harbor Peak (Alexander 2006: http://www.livingneighborhoods.org/

library/brook-1.pdf).

3. Several correspondents have related discussions with Jacobs along these lines. The author is

particularly indebted to Arun Jain, Chief Urban Designer for the City of Portland, who

discussed these matters with Jacobs on a number of occasions.

4. Reported in a seminar discussion at University College London, where the author was present.

5. Most recently, the author spotted a well-thumbed copy sitting conspicuously on the shelf of the

Executive Director of a major New Orleans preservation charity. As it was pointed out to her,

she remarked, ‘‘Oh, yes – I love that book!’’

6. The author is indebted to Andres Duany for a number of conversations on this topic. Any errors

in representing his views are entirely the author’s own, for which apologies are given in advance.

See in particular his interview in Mehaffy (2004b).

7. At any rate, Jacobs did seem to regard the urban interventions of Koolhaas’s contemporaries,

including Eisenman, with dismay. In a letter to the author in 2001, she related that she was

‘‘appalled’’ at the proposals for Ground Zero in New York. She only refrained from getting

involved, she said, because she was no longer a New Yorker. But she referred the author to other

colleagues in New York who were said to be preparing to oppose the plans.

Journal of Urbanism 73

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

8. There is an extensive discussion of this topic in Grabow (1983). Alexander also discussed this

topic in the present author’s interview with him (Mehaffy 2004a, 2007).

9. Indeed, even at the time of writing, it is the subject of a very animated exchange on a New

Urbanist listserv, including Duany, his colleague Sandy Sorlien, the present author, and others.

10. At the Congress for the New Urbanism in 2006, Alexander held a meeting at which some 30

people, including a number of prominent developers, pledged to collaborate with him. A listserv

was formed, and plans were made for a symposium – which was put on hold when Alexander

was unable to finalize an agreement with the Prince’s Foundation for the Built Environment to

host it.

11. See, for example, the explosive growth of the ‘‘design pattern’’ movement in software, based on A

Pattern Language, and begun by former Tektronix engineers Ward Cunningham and Kent Beck.

Alexander’s ideas have thus directly spawned the development of such familiar titles as Wikipedia

and The Sims. Cunningham has been involved in the more recent collaborations to develop

Alexander’s ideas on generativity further.

12. For example, very promising and hopeful work is being done within game theory and

economics, notably in the realm that seeks to integrate so-called ‘‘externalities’’ within more

sustainable economic processes. This echoes Alexander’s efforts to ‘‘change the rules of the

game’’ of real estate development.

References

Alexander, C., 1964. Notes on the synthesis of form. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Alexander, C., 1965. A city is not a tree [2 parts]. Architectural Forum, 122 (1), 58–62 (Part I);

122 (2), 58–62 (Part II). Available from: http://www.arq.ufmg.br/rcesar/alex/alexander/

alexander1.html/.

Alexander, C., 1979. The timeless way of building. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Alexander, C., 2003–04. The nature of order, Books 1–4. Berkeley, CA: Center for Environmental

Structure.

Alexander, C., 2006. The master plan and process for Harbor Peak: a model creation process for 21st

century cities. Berkeley, CA: Center for Environmental Structure.

Alexander, C., Ishikawa, S., Silverstein, M., Jacobson, M., Fiksdahl-King, I. and Angel, S., 1977. A

pattern language. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Alexander, C., Neis, H., Anninou, A. and King, I., 1987. A new theory of urban design. New York,

NY: Oxford University Press.

Batty, M., 1991. Cities and fractals: simulating growth and form. New York, NY: Springer.

Batty, M., Couclelis, M. and Eichen, M., 1997. Urban systems as cellular automata. London (UK):

Pion.

Broadbent, G., 1979. The development of design methods a review. Design Methods and Theories, 13

(1), 41–45.

Dulgeroglu-Vuksel, Y., 1999. Design methods theory and its implementation for architectural

studies. Design Method: Theories, Research, Education and Practice, 33 (3), 2870–2877.

Eisenman Architects with Davidson, C.., ed., 2005. Code X: the city of culture of Galicia. New York,

NY: Monacelli.

Eisenman Associates, 2007. Narrative for design of City of Culture, Santiago de Compostela, Spain

[online]. Columbia University Graduate School of Architecture, Planning and Pre-

servation. Available from: http://www.arch.columbia.edu/index.php?pageData532552/.

Eisenman, P. and Alexander, C., 1982. Contrasting views of harmony in architecture. Transcript of a

debate at Harvard Graduate School of Design [online]. Katarxis 3, Available from: http://

www.katarxis3.com/.

Fowles, B., 1977. What happened to design methods in architectural education? Design Methods and

Theories, 11 (1), 17–31.

Friedmann, J., 2002. City of fear or open city? Journal of the American Planning Association, 68 (3),

237–243.

74 M.W. Mehaffy

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5

Grabow, S., 1983. Christopher Alexander: the search for a new paradigm in architecture. Boston, MA:

Oriel.

Harwood, S.A., 2005. Struggling to embrace difference in land-use decision making in multicultural

communities. Planning, Practice and Research, 20 (4), 355–371.

Healey, P., 1997. Collaborative planning – shaping places in fragmented societies. London (UK):

Macmillan.

Hillier, B., 1989. The social logic of space. London (UK): Cambridge University Press.

Hillier, B., 1999. Space is the machine: a configurational theory of architecture. London (UK):

Cambridge University Press.

Innes, J.E. and Booher, D.E., 1999. Consensus building as role playing and bricolage: toward a

theory of collaborative planning. Journal of the American Planning Association, 65 (1), 9–26.

Jacobs, J., 1961. The death and life of great American cities. New York, NY: Vintage.

Koolhaas, R., 1995. Whatever happened to urbanism. In:Koolhaas, R. S, M, L, XL. New York, NY:

Monacelli, 958–971.

La Giorgia, G., 2007. Market v. meaning. Architecture Week, 5 September [online]. Available from:

http://www.architectureweek.com/2007/0905/design_3-1.html/.

Mehaffy, M., 2004a. A conversation with Christopher Alexander. Katarxis 3. Available from: http://

www.katarxis3.com/.

Mehaffy, M., 2004b. An interview with Andres Duany. Katarxis 3. Available from: http://

www.katarxis3.com/.

Mehaffy, M., 2007. On the nature of order: an interview with Christopher Alexander. Urban Design

International, 12, 51–57.

Qadeer, M.A., 1997. Pluralistic planning for multicultural cities: the Canadian practice. Journal of

the American Planning Association, 63 (4), 481–494.

Sandercock, L., 1998. Towards cosmopolis. Chichester (UK): Wiley.

Sandercock, L., 2000. Cities of (in)difference and the challenge for planning. Dokumente und

Informationen zur Schweizerischen Orts-Regional und Landesplanung (DISP), 140, 7–15.

Saunders, W., 2002. Book Review: A Pattern Language. Architectural Record, May, 93. Available

from: http://www.gsd.harvard.edu/research/publications/hdm/back/16books_saunders.html/.

Simon, H., 1962. The architecture of complexity. Proceedings of the American Philosophical

Association, 106, 467–482.

Wallace, M. and Milroy, B., 1999. Intersecting claims: planning in Canada’s cities. In: T. Fenster, ed.

Gender, planning and human rights. London (UK): Routledge, 55–73.

Whitehead, A.N., 1928. Process and reality. New York, NY: Free Press.

Journal of Urbanism 75

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

217.

111.

223.

226]

at 0

3:49

26

May

201

5