thinking about tradition, religion, and politics in egypt today – critical inquiry

57
by Talal Asad I I have used the term “tradition” in my writings in two ways: first, as a theoretical location for raising questions about authority, time, language use, and embodiment; and second, as an empirical arrangement in which discursivity and materiality are connected through the minutiae of everyday living.[1] The discursive aspect of tradition is primarily a matter of linguistic acts passed down the generations as part of a form of life, a process in which one learns/relearns “how to do things with words,” sometimes reflectively and sometimes unthinkingly, and learns/relearns how to comport one’s body and how to feel in particular contexts. Embodied practices help in the acquisition of aptitudes, sensibilities, and propensities through repetition until such time as the language guiding practice becomes redundant. Through such practices one can change oneself—one’s physical being, one’s emotions, one’s language, one’s predispositions, as well as one’s environment. Tradition stands opposed both to empiricist theories of knowledge and relativist theories of justice. By this I mean first and foremost that tradition stresses embodied, critical learning rather than abstract theorization. Empiricist theories of Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today

Upload: nidhish-k-sundar

Post on 21-Dec-2015

11 views

Category:

Documents


3 download

DESCRIPTION

talal asad

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 1/57

by Talal Asad

I

I have used the term “tradition” in my writings in two ways: first, as atheoretical location for raising questions about authority, time, language use,and embodiment; and second, as an empirical arrangement in whichdiscursivity and materiality are connected through the minutiae of everydayliving.[1] The discursive aspect of tradition is primarily a matter of linguisticacts passed down the generations as part of a form of life, a process in whichone learns/relearns “how to do things with words,” sometimes reflectively andsometimes unthinkingly, and learns/relearns how to comport one’s body andhow to feel in particular contexts. Embodied practices help in the acquisition ofaptitudes, sensibilities, and propensities through repetition until such time asthe language guiding practice becomes redundant. Through such practicesone can change oneself—one’s physical being, one’s emotions, one’slanguage, one’s predispositions, as well as one’s environment. Traditionstands opposed both to empiricist theories of knowledge and relativist theoriesof justice. By this I mean first and foremost that tradition stresses embodied,critical learning rather than abstract theorization. Empiricist theories of

Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today

Page 2: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 2/57

knowledge assert the centrality of sensory experience and evidence, but indoing so they ignore the prior conceptualization carried by tradition. Mysensory experience is incommensurable with yours. It is only throughlanguage (integral to a shared form of life), and the conceptualization thatlanguage makes possible, that we can develop argument and knowledge ascollective processes. Critique is central to a living tradition; it is essential tohow its followers assess the relevance of the past for the present, and thepresent for the future. It is also essential for understanding the nature ofcircumstance, and therefore the possibility of changing elements ofcircumstances that are changeable. Relativist theories of justice assert that"justice" is simply the name for the norms that actually guide and regulate apeople's form of life. And yet what other people consider to be justice is part ofthe circumstance that confront the followers of every living tradition. As such itconstitutes a challenge to every critical tradition, an invitation to changecontingent aspects of one's tradition, or of the circumstances in which it isembedded, or both. This is not a challenge of abstract theories but ofembodied (and yet criticizable) ways of life.

Discursive and embodied tradition do not refer to two separate types oftradition, two mutually exclusive principles of social organization (likeGesellschaft and Gemeinschaft, say). In general I use the concept of traditionto address now the use of inherited language and now the acquisition ofembodied abilities by repetition. One might suggest that having a tradition isan expression of a desire for the completion of a present that is simplyunfinished time. Ludwig Wittgenstein once wrote: “Tradition is not something aman can learn; not a thread he picks up when he feels like it; any more than aman can choose his own ancestors. Someone lacking a tradition who wouldlike to have one is like a man unhappily in love.”[2] For Wittgenstein, in otherwords, tradition represents for someone who doesn’t have it the object of anunattainable longing: the condition of belonging to another, being accepted assuch by him or her, and of hoping to learn (and construct) through friendshipwho one is. Of course the language and practice of tradition can and must belearnt (people do enter traditions they have not inherited) but Wittgenstein’semphasis is on the fact that what is learnt is not a doctrine (rules) but a modeof being, not a thread one can pick up or drop whenever one feels like it but acapacity for experiencing another in a way that can’t be renounced.

I use the concept of embodiment to address questions of beginning, growth,and completion, of finitude, of hope and of failure; I use the idea of discoursein the same context to explore how citizens talk about and engage with power

Page 3: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 3/57

and authority in shifting moments of time.[3] I understand tradition to be givennot invented. Even when reform is proposed there is an assumption, explicit orimplicit, that “the tradition’s essence”—what is perceived as essential to it—isnot to be changed but defended through purification, the process of separatingwhat is contingent from what is essential. Thus contrary to those who see anirreconcilable opposition between tradition and genealogy, I suggest that thevery act of “purifying tradition” draws on genealogical arguments.Genealogical critique is not (as Alasdair MacIntyre, for example, has insisted)a rejection of all grounding; its ground is “today,” the place from which onethinks on the difference between time present and time past, and aspires tofuture time. The purification of tradition uses violence (or the threat ofviolence) to restore an obscured origin that can then accommodate itself moresmoothly to the real, progressive world. This process of critical purification(modernization) is a process of what must be transgressed if tradition is tobecome civilized. As a consequence, actual traditions, descriptively soidentified, can disintegrate or implode.[4]

Discourses and acts that found a tradition are not exhaustive becausesubsequent events become part of those foundations, by virtue of interpretingor developing them. In any living tradition there are arguments about whetherexegetical texts, or texts belonging to other traditions, have any value for one’sown tradition, and if so why. Disagreements therefore arise not only about thesubstance of interpretation but also over where exactly the limits of a traditionlie. These arguments and exchanges suggest that founding narratives aremoments in ongoing conversations: so in principle tradition can accommodaterupture, recuperation, reorientation, and splitting—as well as continuity.Tradition is singular as well as plural. For subjects there are not onlycontinuities but also exits and entries. Tradition accommodates mistakes aswell as betrayal; it is not by accident that “tradition” and “treason” have acommon etymology.

So in what follows I want to think about politics in Egypt today, especially byattending to ideas about Islamic tradition that have been explicit or implicit inmuch of the discourse of participants and commentators of the events sinceJanuary 2011. In particular, I want to ask what a liberal state, which is said tobe a precondition of individual freedom (including religious freedom), makesdifficult or even impossible. I note that of course not all liberal states areidentical, but they do share something that enables them to be identified as“liberal.” I begin, however, by asking what it is about “tradition” that secularistsfind antipathetic, and then discuss how a learned follower of Islamic tradition

Page 4: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 4/57

interpreted aspects of it to me. I then argue that modern sovereignty (ofsubject and state) makes it difficult for certain kinds of embodiment, certainkinds of ethics, to flourish in our globalized, speeded­up world. I explore inwhat follows some openings and closures brought about by modern conceptsof ethical and political practice in post­2011 Egypt.

II

Over the last several decades, before the coup in July 2013, whenever Ivisited Egypt I often heard the so­called Islamic Awakening (as­sahwaislāmiyya) censured. The critics regarded themselves as “modern,” and sosigns of what they identified as religion in public offended them. What theyfound offensive wasn’t always political. Their anxiety was focused on twoaspects of what they saw as dangerous: on the one hand, the fastidiousemphasis on ritual as evidence of blind obedience to authority, and thereforethreatening to the autonomous modern self; on the other hand, the insistenceon the priority of the shari‘a in the constitution of the state—a form of“religious” law that is politically divisive and archaic in its assumptions ofpersonal relations. The radical secularist position (not the most vocal in Egypt)is that religion belongs to the past, as do all illusions from which one hasemancipated oneself; the more common view among secularists is that“religion” is essentially a private matter of personal ethics and that while it mayperhaps be expressed in public ceremonies it must under no circumstancesenter the same space as politics. Many modernizers view the present “crisis”of Arab society as being rooted in an unquestioning attachment to “religioustradition.” The famous poet Adonis, for example, has written at length on theneed to break decisively with tradition (salafiyya). As an advocate ofrevolutionary change in Arab society he urges “the necessity of freeing theArab from all dependence on tradition, the necessity of eliminating the past’ssacredness and of considering it part of an experience or knowledge towardwhich one has no obligation whatever (ghayr mulzima itlāqan).”[5] Thismodern idea of choice stands defiantly against the idea of a past to which oneis bound by language, capability, and affection.

The censure my secular friends made of what they considered Islamictradition echoes a historical debate about “religion” since the earlyEnlightenment that is partly based on a new psychology that emerged inEurope in early modernity, a psychology focusing on such interior states assincerity, authenticity, and the will—and claiming a clear­cut antithesisbetween freedom and authority.[6] Since the seventeenth century, ritual has

Page 5: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 5/57

been spoken of very much as tradition has: it looks to the past as continuousand unchanging, it consists of formal and inauthentic action, it is based onnon­rational thought, it submits one’s own will to that of another, it prioritizessocial convention over personal sincerity and freedom of action. This view wasepitomized in the Protestant rejection of Catholic ritualism,[7] eventually tobecome part of modern common sense.[8]

The old assumption that tradition is “antimodern” has been countered inseveral ways. Thus Adam Seligman and his colleagues have recently arguedthat the formal character of ritual has the function of smoothing social lifewhere a rigid adherence to one’s actual feelings (“being sincere”) wouldseriously disturb it. The theoretical object of submission to ritual is thereforenot the suppression of authentic feeling but its management by the use ofconventional formalities so that social life becomes possible.[9] Again: Theprinciple of precedent in tradition is also known to be crucial to modern law. Inboth common law and the principle of stare decisis, the reasoning in priorjudicial decisions is followed unless there are strong legal reasons to dootherwise.[10] And in liberal democratic countries the constitution is thefoundation to which future politics is expected to be bound and which citizensmust venerate. Finally, respectful attention to the objects, texts, buildings andlandscapes that have survived from the past become valuable evidence in thepresent for reconstructing that past, and a critical assessment of suchevidence is essential to the making of veridical historical narratives. Discursivefidelity to the past, and attention to the way in which language has constructedits categories (used by people who lived in the past as well as those used byscholars who have studied them) is central to the modern discipline of history.[11]

And yet one may object: None of this, surely, proves that religion should havea place in modern politics. Some continuity with the past may be necessarybecause it facilitates social intercourse, or because it provides a measure ofpredictability to the law (and therefore to the state), but religious traditionbases itself on unquestionable authority whereas democratic politics requirespublic debate capable of being brought to a rational conclusion.[12] I’ll returnto this and other liberal claims about politics later but first I want to talk a littleabout the Islamic concept of tradition so that it might help us think about thetimes and authorities of politics in Egypt.

In 2009 I was in Cairo for several months and had weekly conversations withShaykh Usama Sayyid al­Azhari, occasional khatīb of Sultan Hassan mosque,

Page 6: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 6/57

and also a protégé of Shaykh Ali Gum‘a, one­time Grand Mufti of Egypt. I wasinitially concerned with hearing about his views on human rights in Islam, butas he spoke I became more interested in what he had to say about theformation of personal virtue within Islamic tradition. Thus at one point ShaykhUsama commented “We say al­a‘māl bi­nniyyāt (deeds are to be judged byintentions) but where do intentions come from?” And then went on to say thatthe process by which human beings were formed (takwīn al­insān) was whatformed intentions, and therefore the possibility of a just social life: Theconstitution of intentions by behavioral and verbal action takes place in variouscontexts of social life. He went on to talk about the education of goodcharacter (tahdhīb al­akhlāq) through the practices of devotion and discipline,but insisted that the ethical formation of the individual was not a matter for theindividual alone, that it took place through interactions among people andthings in several social locations: “household, school, mosque, the media, andthe street.” In each location there were proper and improper ways of behavingand interacting with others, behavior that had to be learnt and being enactedwas part of the process of learning. It was not simply that practice mattered; itwas that learning to practice aptly what was learnt that was critical. That waswhy, said Shaykh Usama, when ibn Taymiyya spoke of faith (imān) assomething expressed primarily in and through actions (a‘māl), he cited a well­known hadith about the foundational status of devotional practices (‘ibādāt) inIslam: “Islam is built on five [pillars]” (mabniya al­islām ‘ala khams). The ritualscited are: a public articulation of faith (shahāda), the formal worship of Godfive times a day (salāt), fasting in the month of Ramadan (sawm), and givingcharity (zakāt).[13] The required declaration of intention (niyya) precedingevery act of devotion was part of the devotion and the verbal articulation wassupposed to sink into the act: it was therefore different from the formation andimplementation of intention in acts that belong to matters in commerce andpolitics that might or might not be realized.[14] For ibn Taymiyya, as forGhazali, so Shaykh Usama reminded me, the unthinking religiosity of ordinarypeople was more important for the tradition than the formal reasoning ofphilosophers and theologians precisely because it was embodied in everydaylife.

What was crucial in traditional devotion was both its initial guidance by anauthoritative teacher, whether parent, friend, or shaykh, and its perfectibility. Itwas in this exercise of the soul, as Ghazali put it, that spiritual orientations andsensibilities could be learnt and confirmed.[15] Thus repetition of the samecreates (paradoxically) something different, so that vice turns into virtue and

Page 7: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 7/57

inability into ability. The conception of time here stands in clear contrast to thelinear time of historical progress. In the former, time can be completed, thepast bound to present and future; in the latter there is no completion, onlycontinuous improvement into an indefinite future, and an indefinitelyaccumulating past that must be left behind.

It is easy to confuse what Shaykh Usama was saying with what is called self­fashioning, a process well known in the ancient world and revived in theEuropean Renaissance. Christian thought and practice had rejected self­making and developed an alternative in the monastic discipline that taughtwilling submission to tradition. Augustine expressed this rejection in amemorable warning: “Hands off yourself. Try to build up yourself, and youbuild a ruin.”[16] The individual, in other words, should not assume that he orshe was sovereign. The subject did not have the authority to makehim/herself; that authority resided in the practice of submitting oneself to thediscipline of tradition. “Submission” is here conceived of not as a passive orcoerced state but as an act of connecting to the authority of a tradition.Submission was therefore not unqualified, because opposition to false claimsto authority was itself an essential form of obedience. Islam (“submission”)shares this orientation, and the ethical language that goes with it, withpremodern Christianity, and has developed it even more vigorously in thesharī‘a tradition, of which the practice of amr bi­l­ma‘rūf is a part. This shouldnot be surprising, incidentally, because Islam developed in late Antiquity in aworld where Byzantine and Sassanian empires ruled and Christian, Judaic,and Mazdaean traditions flourished, and so, as Muslims interacted with non­Muslims, they inherited institutions and ideas from that complex history, andwent on to develop them in diverse but distinctive ways.

With the growth of commercial society, however, the possibilities of self­invention have opened up for much of the population and have been justifiedas the right of the sovereign self. Many critics have pointed out that that formof embodiment is based on the illusion of sovereignty because and to theextent that the individual’s behavior is a response to the market. According tothis critical view the market that organizes modern commercial society, like alltranscendent force, requires consumers and investors to fall into line.However, this view is not persuasive to most people who feel that they aremaking free choices in the market, that the market offers them a means offulfilling their own desires, but this assumption rests on the belief that coercionis always and only external, always what is apparent to consciousness. Itignores the old problem of internal coercion and therefore the possibility that

Page 8: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 8/57

one cannot be free until the inner compulsion that clouds one’s judgment anddistorts one’s conscious action is dissolved. As philosophers of antiquity andthe Renaissance put it, one’s emotions (passions) imprison one, and it is onlythe intentional use (action) of reason that can liberate one from this prison. Sothere is a crucial difference between self­care that is entirely subject to theindividual’s choice and responsibility (self­invention), and the discipline of theself whose experience and authority lie in tradition. The former rests on theassumption that the self is self­contained (“buffered” in the word of onemodern philosopher) and the latter on the recognition that it overlaps with, andcontains, other selves.[17]

A modern secular version of self­care is institutionalized in Freudianism, butwith the interesting twist that the unconscious past is made the source ofpsychic blockages whose removal can be secured through a talking cure. Butto regard the authority of the past as only the source of blind obedience is toignore the possibility that the past may be reached in the present not onlythrough the discovery of unconscious desires and fears formed in the past thatact as coercive forces in the present but also in an opposite direction, throughconscious repetition that aims at making one’s self­conscious actions unself­conscious in the future. When one acts unself­consciously one is notsuppressing desires—and therefore coercive forces—into one’s unconscious.One is educating one’s desires so that one does not encounter them asobstacles to living. The disciplined body is not a coerced body but a “docile”body, in the older sense of a body that is “teachable.” To be teachable is notonly to be able to listen to another person (one’s teacher) but also andespecially to be able to listen to oneself; that is a skill to be acquired andperfected through tradition. Of course one may be taught to do wicked thingsbut that is a general problem about persuasion and learning, not one specialto living through tradition.

What Shaykh Usama was trying to describe was thus more interesting thanthe disapproval of my friends in Cairo. What he sought to convey was the ideaof intention itself being constituted in the repeated acts of body­and­mindwithin a social context. In fact, like the mastery of all grammar, the ability toperform devotions well (to devote oneself) required not only repetition but alsoflexibility in different circumstances. It was not simply a matter of acting as inthe past but of acquiring a capability for which the past was a beginning andby which the need to submit consciously to a rule would eventually disappear.When one mastered the capability, its exercise did not require a continuousmonitoring of oneself (“Am I following the rule correctly?”).

Page 9: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 9/57

According to Shaykh Usama there was always a social dimension to thedisciplines of devotion, as in the traditional duty of every Muslim “to urge whatis good and oppose what is reprehensible” (amr bi­l­ma‘rūf wa nahy ‘an al­munkar),[18] including advice (nasīha) and warning (tahdhīr). What I foundintriguing about his discourse was the attempt to tie amr bi­l­ma‘rūf to thevirtue of “friendship” (suhba, ikhwa), to present it as a matter of responsibilityand concern for a friend rather than simply of policing.[19] The language andattitude in which one carried out that duty was integral to what amr bi­l­ma‘rūfwas, because, “Every Muslim is a brother to every other Muslim.” What isknown historically in Christian history as “pastoral care” is here diffusedamong all Muslims in relation to one another.

Michael Cook has pointed out in his valuable historical survey of amr bi­l­ma‘rūf that the duty to “forbid wrong” finds expression in a rich vocabulary: “Awide variety of locutions are used for this besides ‘command’ (amara) and‘forbid’ (naha). A man may speak to (qāla li­) the offender, exhort him (wa‘aza),counsel him (nasaha), censure him (wabbakha), shout at him (sāha), and soforth. … [O]ther things being equal, one should perform the duty in a civilfashion. … But although in general one should speak politely, there are timeswhen rudeness is in place.”[20] Clearly the performance of that duty is incrucial measure dependent on the vocabulary used, and the differences inlanguage cannot be reduced simply to two imperatives—obligatory andforbidden actions—that are central to what we would today call law. Theyarticulate a range of interactions belonging to tradition. And yet despite hisreference to the rich vocabulary employed in it, Cook reduces this tradition tothe imperative of “forbidding wrong,” a move that, among other things,distracts attention from the complex process of “encouraging right.” Of course,the former logically presupposes a conception of what is right, but cultivatingright behavior is not exhausted by prohibitions as Shaykh Usama clearlyrecognized—it is usually a longer and more complicated process of learning,in which the substantive language and the repeated practice of the tradition,as well as the contingent circumstances in which they occur, are interlaced. Itrequires speaking to those whose behavior one wants to change in the wayone would speak to a friend.

According to Shaykh Usama, a just society was possible only if its individualmembers learnt the virtues through tradition, and were helped to do so byrelatives, teachers, and friends. He insisted that even if you meet a strangeryou should behave towards him as though he were a friend unless you havegood reason not to do so. One could reprove a person kindly but if urging him

Page 10: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 10/57

to reform failed to produce a positive result, one should boycott him until hechanged, because countering the misguided behavior of a friend was a duty offriendship.[21] One implication here—although Shaykh Usama did notarticulate it—is that speaking harshly (as Cook notes in his review of thehistorical vocabulary) may sometimes be necessary to make even a friendchange his or her behavior.[22] Pointing out explicitly that something isunconditionally forbidden is of course part of that tradition—but only part of it.In a modern context this would include political boycott, mass protest and civildisobedience, all responding to a particular or cumulative injustice of stateauthority.[23]

In his analysis of the Nasr Hamid Abu Zayd case, Hussein Agrama contrastshisba as a form of care of the self and also as a legal device: “While hisba, inits classical Shari‘a elaborations, was part of a form of reasoning and practiceconnected to the cultivation of selves, in the courts it became focused on themaintenance and defense of interests aimed at protecting the publicorder.”[24] His account demonstrates that when the shari‘a tradition of amr bi­l­ma‘rūf is incorporated into the judicial system of the state, it becomes part ofthe state’s coercive power and legalized suspicion in the interest of publicorder, and this makes friendship not merely impossible but also a distortion ofthe modern (impersonal) concept of justice. Agrama argues that thepremodern shari‘a as practiced in the Fatwa Council is not law but a traditionthat seeks to resolve the moral blockages encountered in everyday life bysubjects who recognize themselves as Muslims. With the development of themodern state, however, another part of the shari‘a has been transformed intoand treated in the Personal Status Courts as “law.” His insightful account ofthe work of the Fatwa Council brings it close to the tradition of amr bi­l­ma‘rūfas a form of care of the self—with the difference that amr bi­l­ma‘rūf is initiatedby someone concerned about another’s behavior, whereas the Fatwa Councilresponds to requests for advice and help from someone perplexed or worriedabout the rightness of their own behavior as a Muslim. It is for this reason thatAgrama traces the authority of the fatwa not to doctrine (the normative rule)but to the work done together by the shaykh and the individuals who come tohim seeking the right way to go on as Muslims. The authority of this care ofthe self is rooted not in the sovereign subject but in the sovereign shari‘a thatpreceded him/her and yet remains always co­present.[25]

Agrama draws on the argument of a famous article by Wael Hallaq thatpresents the shari‘a not as a timeless structure but as a complex temporalitybest grasped in terms of evolving tradition.[26] Agrama is also aware that the

Page 11: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 11/57

premodern, prestate shari‘a is not “law” in the modern understanding of thatconcept, not a system of legal doctrines backed by sovereign state power, buta tradition consisting of normative practice and commentary that includes (butis not exhausted by) justiciable cases. In part the shari‘a is applied to mattersthat are justiciable, and in part (through such traditions as amr bi­l­ma‘rūf) toindividual or collective pressure at a political level, as well as to attempts atblaming, warning, advising, urging, etc., to encourage friends, kin, andcolleagues to act in a praiseworthy way. Which is why, as Agrama shows,although the work of the Fatwa Council is fully informed by the shari‘a, it doesnot deal with “law”[27] but with a nonmodern conception of ethics.

Five years after I met Shaykh Usama, Abdul Mun‘im Abu­l­Futuh, (aPresidential candidate in 2012) invoked the tradition of amr bi­l­ma‘rūf inanswer to questions about the uprising and the coup, and the role of Egyptianreligiosity in those events. “This religiosity (tadayyun) is a definite fact,” hereplied.

The Egyptian personality includes deep faith and devotion to thesacred, and [a sense of] considerable interpenetration betweeneveryday life and the sacred. But this religiosity is not alwaysaccompanied by a social, political, and legal consciousness, andsometimes it is [merely] formal or superficial or ritual. The importanceof religiosity in the January 2011 revolution was that it formed themoral background to the conscience of the revolution even if itsdiscourse didn’t display that clearly. As for the events of 3 July 2013and later, the powerful propaganda that preceded 3 July joined indistorting and treating with contempt the Islamists in preparation forthe events of 3 July and after. And the matter reached the point ofdoubting even what is sacred. . . . This was what weakened thevalues and meanings of fundamental religiosity that forbids theshedding of blood and commands what is right and forbids what iswrong and tyrannical (al­qiyam wa ma‘āni at­tadiyyun al­asāsiyyaallatī tahrum safk ad­dimā wa ta’mur bi­l­ma‘rūf wa tanhi ‘an al­munkar wa­z­zulm) and so millions of people confirmed and excusedand supported ugly behavior that was without historical precedent.So here was where superficial religiosity failed because of itsseparation from values and norms.

Abu­l­Futuh’s observation on the massacres[28] of pro­Mursi protesters by themilitary regime extends amr bi­l­ma‘rūf into an explicitly political context. He

Page 12: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 12/57

invokes amr bi­l­ma‘rūf as a religious tradition that authorizes the cultivation ofpolitically relevant virtues. What he sees that tradition as offering is not a ruleabout right and wrong (as in a court of law) but the ability to recognize aparticular injustice and to react to it by demanding “a return” to justice—without having to calibrate the matter by reference to generalizable moralprinciples. Even if that ability is not always acquired perfectly, it is what thattradition, as embodied practice, seeks to build. And where the building issuccessful, it enables daily life to be lived without having to find justificationsfor moral—or political—obligation.[29]

III

So I turn to the January 2011 uprising and what followed the ouster ofPresident Mubarak, and ask how religion, authority, and tradition are linkedtogether in that story. One cannot seriously maintain that “religious tradition”was a significant inspiration to that overthrow of authority,[30] but there can beno question that since the fall of Mubarak religion has been involved in acomplicated way in what followed that remarkable event. In a well­knownessay Hannah Arendt has traced a very specific concept of tradition that wascentral to European history, in which it was bound closely to both authority andreligion, such that undermining of the one inevitably led to the undermining ofthe other two.[31] This historical sketch of tradition is relevant to the MiddleEast because it begins with the Greco­Roman experience that is part of theclassical heritage of both the northern and the southern lands of theMediterranean,[32] and it ends with post­Enlightenment European politicalthought and practice that have had a profound impact on Muslim societiesever since the beginning of the nineteenth century.

Arendt argues that with the rise of modern science the authority of “religion”was irretrievably lost, and so tradition as idea and practice was alsoundermined—or, at any rate, radically transformed. The idea and practice oftradition that post­Revolutionary Europe identified and critiqued emerged, saysArendt, not with the Greeks but with the Romans, and crucial to thatconception were two things: The notion of foundation (the sacred foundation ofRome, the state that Roman politics sought to preserve and extend) and areligion of the ancestors essential to Roman political identity. Arendt notes thatthe Latin for “authority” (auctoritas) derives from the verb “to augment”(augere), and that what those in authority sought to augment was the

Page 13: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 13/57

foundation. Although authority was rooted in the past, this past was present inthe actual life of the city especially in the domestic rituals of the Romans.Authority, tasked with augmenting the foundation, was vested in the Senateand distinguished from power (potestas)—or the capacity to use force—thatthe people possessed. In the early centuries of the Christian era, says Arendt,the Church took over Rome’s political constitution, the most significant aspectof which was its adoption of the distinction between authority and power,conceding political force to the secular arm (the princes) and reserving foritself the authority of the keeper of the Christian tradition. There was,nevertheless, a link between the two—as there was in medieval Muslimgovernance between the collective authority of the ulama and the individualamir’s power, where the latter was expected to adjust his civil actions to thenormative demands of the shari‘a as articulated and maintained by the former.[33] The important difference, of course, is that the ulama did not have amonopoly on pastoral care as the Church did. With the modern attempts atbuilding the sovereign nation­state, religious authority was detached frompolitical tradition and political authority was thereby secularized—which is notto say that “religion” was henceforth never used by the state to legitimate itsactions but that “politics” has come to be very differently articulated from theconfigurations of power and authority that had previously prevailed.[34]

One of Arendt’s points is that although the bond between authority and religionhas dissolved in Europe, the Roman experience of foundation has survived—and therefore, too, a crucial sense of tradition. In fact since a foundation isitself a rupture from the past and an opening to the future, this very ambiguitylends itself to the concept of revolution. But when the Roman conception offounding a political tradition becomes sharply separated from religiousauthority in thinkers such as Robespierre, the authority of a popular revolutionbecomes merged with the necessity of violence. The violent founding of anation­state becomes a kind of tradition for as long as the state’s foundation isinvoked and explicitly augmented. Arendt tells us that since the American andFrench Revolutions a fused form of authority­power becomes instrumental. Inthe concept and practice of revolution it was not the use of violence that wasnew but its role in constituting a new legitimate order for the good of thePeople’s future. What she doesn’t note, however, is that coup d’ètat belongs tothe same family of political violence as revolution but differs from the latter inbeing a challenge from within the governing elite, one that aims to change onlythe rulers of the state not the system itself, but that legitimates itself in terms ofnecessity (saving the nation and ensuring its progress).

Page 14: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 14/57

So not only is the dominant tradition of political authority in Europe today not“religious” in either the Roman or the Christian sense, that authority makes“the people”—“the nation”—sacred as an eternal subject, and it claims thatnational memory (“recovering the past”) and the People’s will (“making thefuture”) are functions of one and the same national subject.[35] Of course,Arendt is not the first to maintain that modern society (or capitalism) hasdestroyed tradition.[36] However, she does point out that the demand to createnew concepts with which to think and act in a broken time reflects the humanability to make new beginnings. But she does not attend to the resultingparadox: to the extent that what is new actually marks a beginning it alsoinitiates a tradition. It could be said, therefore, that the repetition of beginningsin modernity represents an enduring aspiration for continuity that is continuallybetrayed—an unhappy yearning for tradition that eludes one.

The 25 January 2011 uprising in Egypt expressed an aspiration that wasneither “religious” nor “secular”: to overthrow the old system and make a newbeginning, to initiate a “democratic tradition” that would flow from thatbeginning, a desire that the People’s political obligation be founded on loyaltyto the nation and not on fear of the state’s violence: from now on no morepolitical cruelty and deception; justice and progress will follow naturally ifgovernment is truthful and visible. (Yet it should not be overlooked that thesecurity police too believed in visibility, as when they exposed tortured victimsfor people to see and become afraid, or when the judiciary stages show trialsfor the same reason in order to defeat the nation’s enemies.)

But an aspiration is not a realization. Some years later, well after the July 3military coup, looking back at the January uprising, it becomes apparent thatthere never was a “revolution” because there was no new foundation. Therewas a moment of enthusiasm in the uprising, as in all major protests andrebellions, but the solidarity it generated was evanescent. A hopeful attempt atbeginning a tradition never guarantees the hoped for future: clear aims, goodjudgment, patience, and willingness to learn a new language and how toinhabit a new body, are required to respond to the various dangers andopportunities that emerge from attempts to found a new political order.Paradoxically, the first attack on the promise of a new political tradition in theJanuary uprising was the removal of Mubarak—by the military. Most activistswere delighted at what they saw as the solidarity of the army with the People:īd wāhid! (“one hand!”) was the slogan that met the soldiers as they enteredTahrir Square, but the army generals saw Mubarak’s resignation more clearlyas a first step toward an orderly restoration of state power. They understood

rd

Page 15: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 15/57

that it was not the uprising that undermined state authority but the erosion ofstate authority—of its credibility—that had allowed the popular uprising toexplode and the military to move in. The state was no longer the one Sadatinherited from Nasir: the army,[37] big capital, and the Interior Ministry had bythis stage fragmented the state’s singular purpose and authority into a numberof reconcilable interests among the major leftovers from the Mubarak regime.It was the rebels’ failure to recognize that fact that gave them an exaggeratedsense of their own power.[38] When people talked about “a transitional”period, there was, therefore, some confusion of the time required forinstitutionalizing “the People’s will” (irādat ash­sha‘b) with the time for restoringthe sovereign state’s authority and majesty (haybat ad­dawla), because bothtimes sought the legitimacy of political rule.[39]

Arguments about political legitimacy raged in Egypt after the July 2013 coupd’état, although it was not always clear how those who made the claims andcounter­claims saw the relationship of legitimacy to legality. Max Weber’sclassification of political authority (legitimate domination) into three ideal typesis perhaps the most famous in the social sciences, but it gives only one ofthem a basis in legality: rational­legal authority. The other two, “tradition” and“charisma,” are unconnected to law. Carl Schmitt, by contrast, saw legitimaterule in terms not of consent to authority but of the right (the power) to resist,arguing that the loyalty of citizens to the state was in effect another name forthe fact that that right was not being exercised. His assumption was that thenation­state must be homogeneous, sharing a single normative order forpolitical and legal reasons: The right/power to break the claim to legitimatedomination is not, in other words, derived from positive law but from thenormative order of society that exists prior to the constitution of the state andits law, an order that provides the constitution with its foundation.[40] It is theSchmittian conception of legitimacy, incidentally, that makes it possible formass street protests against an established political authority to claim thatthey are exercising the People’s will. Politics that derives from the sovereigntyof a modern liberal state is always open to a continuous fear—the fear that thestate’s authority may be violently undermined by the secret work of internalenemies.

“Terrorists” in authoritarian Egypt, as in liberal democratic America, are such athreat, and therefore also a spur to reinforcing the devices aimed at meeting it.In theory the liberal state may concede the legitimacy of political dissent, butwhen popular protest threatens to become politically effective, when it seeksto change the fundamental way the state is run, then concern for the state’s

Page 16: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 16/57

authority opens up different forms of action. “Traitors” are close to “terrorists”but more dangerous to the state’s legitimacy because while feigning to beordinary citizens they abandon their traditional obligation to the state andconvey their loyalty to its enemies. It is therefore rational for the state toextend its security systems (all the while arguing for their necessity andlegality) through technologies of surveillance (directly, or indirectly with thehelp of private sector enterprises), a strengthened police force, and openrepression.

One approach to understanding attitudes to state violence in Egypt is througha consideration of some remarks by a well­known journalist, Hilmi Namnam,speaking at a meeting shortly after the coup d’ètat in which he refers inpositive terms (as many did) to the necessity of violence against pro­Mursiprotesters by the security forces: “No democracy or society,” Namnam insists,“has ever advanced without the shedding of blood.”[41] Namnam’s concern isnot simply to assert that the necessary price of progress is the physicalelimination of its enemies but also to suggest that progress is not a matter ofcompleting a particular project but of an indefinite advance subject totranscendent principles and it is this that constitutes secularity, the real natureof society. “We must get rid of the lie that Egypt is by natural disposition (bi­l­fitra) a religious state,” Namnam goes on, “because Egypt is secular bynature.” The deliberate violence of the progressive Egyptian movement issecular because it wants to make an increasingly better future in this world;the coercive activity of Islamists, by contrast, seeks conformity with a divineplan. It is motive not effect that distinguishes the two kinds of violence. Thuswhen Islamists appeal to “religious authority,” instead of “the People’sauthority,” they obscure Egypt’s real nature. In making this claim Namnamdraws on a revolutionary tradition that affirms the necessity of political violencein this world as a means of making historical progress. The necessity of thissecular violence is called for by an unseen future, a force in which all rationalindividuals should have faith.

Hannah Arendt had this to say about the origins of this tradition:

Necessity and violence, violence justified and glorified because itacts in the cause of necessity, necessity no longer either rebelledagainst in a supreme effort of liberation or accepted in piousresignation, but, on the contrary, faithfully worshipped as the greatall­coercing force which surely, in the words of Rousseau, will ‘forcemen to be free’ – we know how these two and the interplay between

Page 17: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 17/57

them have become the hallmark of successful revolutions in thetwentieth century, and this to such an extent that, for the learned andthe unlearned alike, they are now outstanding characteristics of allrevolutionary events.[42]

According to Arendt, therefore, all projects in which the use of violence and thecreation of terror among those subjected to it are regarded as essential to thecreation of free human beings, must be distinguished from the active rejectionof oppression presenting itself as necessary or from its passive acceptance asinevitable. “Necessity,” she suggests, has changed from being an excuse forparticular cruelties to being the truth of a sacred cause.[43]

Reflecting on the left­wing romance with revolution, Michel Foucault oncedescribed the devious path of revolutionary “necessity” as follows: Marxist andMarxisant movements that aimed to capture the state apparatus because itwas a historical necessity encountered a typical dilemma. Not only was itdeemed necessary for the revolutionary party to model itself on the powerstructure of the reactionary state in order to fight it effectively, it also found itnecessary not to destroy state apparatuses entirely when it took over thebourgeois state. It was necessary for state apparatuses to be retained in orderto fight the class enemy. Furthermore, in order to run the appropriated stateapparatuses, revolutionaries had to turn to technicians and specialists fromthe old regime who had the necessary experience—that is to say, who weremembers of the old class and who therefore brought with them the continuityof old time.[44] This fatal dilemma about clashing necessities—central toEgypt’s brief experience of “liberal democracy”—was intimately connected tothe aspiration of “revolutionaries” to control the sovereign state. I will return tothis point below when I discuss the encouragement by the military governmentof a growing body of patriotic citizens who voluntarily denounce their fellows tostate authorities.

The question of how political intentions are formed and then expressed inaction within a fluid, evolving situation—or even to what extent intentionsmatter for understanding what happens in the political world—is morecomplicated than accounts such as Namnam’s would have one believe.[45]The eminent jurist Tariq al­Bishri makes a more interesting observation: Thehatred of secularists toward the Muslim Brothers, he argues, has beenpolitically far less significant than the enmity of the state apparatuses towardthem because self­styled secularists had neither mass organizations nor directaccess to the repressive instruments of the state.[46] As a relatively small

Page 18: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 18/57

cultured elite from the middle and upper classes, secularists were wellrepresented in and by the media. However, whereas their hostility toward“political Islam” was ideological, notes Bishri, the regime in control of the stateapparatuses was concerned not with “Islam” but with the threat to their powerand privilege issuing from the only major movement for genuine systemicchange in the character of the state. The state therefore saw the Brotherhoodas a serious political challenge: on the one hand as represented by theprofessional unions of doctors, lawyers, teachers, engineers, etc., that weredominated by the Brotherhood; and on the other hand, by the Brotherhood’snationwide organization with its considerable popular following. Bishri saysthat after the uprising of January 2011 he had hoped the deep state, thesecularists and the Brotherhood would all come together peacefully toestablish and consolidate “democracy” in Egypt because the alternative wouldspell disaster. The fact that that comprehensive alliance didn’t take place was,in his opinion, the fault of all three.[47] However, what actually took place, Iwould suggest, was not a collective moral failure, a fault, but a particularpolitical success in recapturing the sovereign state in which the winners werepropelled by powerful emotions and used state violence (which theirsupporters endorsed) in order to save political time—by cutting short theelected President’s period of legitimate rule. It is often suggested by liberalsand secularist militants that the Freedom and Justice Party government shouldhave reached out to them as potential allies against the deep state, butsupporters of the Brotherhood point to the longstanding hostility of theseelements towards them (which no doubt was reciprocated) and ask rhetoricallywhat value there would have been in reaching out to a small, unfriendly, yetpolitically powerless current. This is the kind of mutual distrust, based on along history of contradictory political experience, that renders new foundationsvirtually impossible.

Many critics have talked about “popular anger at Mursi’s arrogance andincompetence,”[48] and about the fear that he was “Brotherhoodizing” thestate and “Islamizing” Egyptian society. But Dina Khawaga, Professor ofPolitical Science in Cairo University, has made several perceptiveobservations about the anti­Mursi protests in 2013: thus while she recognizesthe tensions and criticisms within the so­called “Islamic Awakening,” sheexplains the hostility to Mursi’s presidency by reference to the idea of “moralpanic” (al­hala‘ al­akhlāqi), the sense that what was sacred to the nation(muqaddisāt wataniyya) was being undermined by what was sacred to religion(muqaddisāt dīniyya).[49] Of course, this is not the only time that someone has

Page 19: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 19/57

used that expression in the context of general public tensions (it was first usedin English at the beginning of the nineteenth century) but Khawaga’scharacterization of the general atmosphere of anxiety, hostility, and volatility inthe period leading up to the coup does raise a question that neither secularistsnor Islamists in Egypt have debated publicly: In what sense can it be said thatthere were different notions of “the sacred” in this political contest? And howdid one notion threaten the other?

Some left critics have insisted that to focus on the Sisi coup (as the MuslimBrotherhood and its supporters do) obscures the fact that Mursi’s governmentwas itself a part of the “counterrevolution,” because it continued to rely on therepressive apparatuses of the interior ministry and the military.[50] But thatdoesn’t, I think, quite explain the ferocity of the winners against theBrotherhood that never had control of those apparatuses, lacked aparamilitary force, and was prepared (so its enemies say) to make an alliancewith more powerful elements of the “counterrevolution” such as the army: thesweeping arrests of its leaders, the death sentences on its alleged supportersin mass trials, and the savage repression of public protesters. I was struck, asmany other observers were, by the passionate expressions of hatred againstthe Muslim Brothers coming from liberal and left members of the middle andupper classes. “You don’t understand,” I was assured over the phone byWestern­educated friends in Cairo shortly after the coup, “the MuslimBrotherhood is a reactionary, terrorist organization.” And when the securityforces massacred hundreds of peaceful Brotherhood supporters some leftactivists insisted: “That tragedy was also the fault of the Brotherhood.” Thisenthusiasm for the successful exercise of political violence is striking, andclearly very different from the sentiment of inclusive solidarity that challengedstate repression in the January 2011 uprising. The emotional undertone ofpolitical alignments and responses tends to be ignored or underestimated inmany accounts that attribute rationalistic motives to the struggling forces.

The motives of people who called or were encouraged to call for Mursi’sremoval were no doubt complex. They included traditional lower­classdeference toward the elite that took the initiative, as well as a desire on thepart of middle­class militants to revolutionize the nation­state, and a fear onthe part of those who owed their privileged position to the Mubarak regime thattheir lifestyle was threatened by the Muslim Brotherhood. Motives are oftencolored by the concealed desires and misguided views that people have ofthemselves. Once one insists on putting everything into boxes labeled“revolution” or “counterrevolution” according to attributed motives one has

Page 20: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 20/57

already appropriated the right to describe every political event in terms ofhis/her attitude toward “freedom” (for or against) and thus foreclosed morecomplicated accounts attending to shifts in perspective, fluid motivations,revised judgments of persons and events, and accidental happenings—andthus the collapse of attempts to build a new tradition.

Sometimes the attempt to explain political protest takes a more sophisticatedform. Thus a day after the coup the sociologist Hazem Kandil wrotereassuringly: “Those who grieve over this affront to ballot box democracyforget that Egypt, like any new democracy, has every right to seek popularconsensus on the basic tenets of its future political system. RevolutionaryFrance went through five republics before settling into the present order, andAmerica needed a civil war to adjust its democratic path. It is not uncommon inthe history of revolutions for coups to pave the way or seal the fate of popularuprisings. Those who see nothing beyond a military coup are simply blind.”[51]

Kandil sees the June protests and the July coup as the work of a singlesubject (“Egypt, a new democracy”) following a clear cut road (“the democraticpath”). But invocations of “democracy” are part of a discourse that allconflicting sides share, and it is not always clear what they mean by it otherthan something self­evidently “good.” Those who carried out and supportedthe military coup were defending “democracy.” Those dismayed by the forcibleremoval of a legitimately elected (albeit widely criticized) President feared thatthis act would damage the prospect of establishing “democracy.” For some,installing “democracy” meant following a model supposedly embodied inWestern states—different from country to country, of course, but sharing apolitical tradition of ideas and practices. For others “democracy” meant an endto the pervasive corruption and cruelty of Mubarak’s regime, for yet others ajust distribution of wealth in Egyptian society. Kandil’s casual reference toFrance’s history of failed republics (entangled as it was with colonial empireand its aftermath) and to America’s bitter civil war to construct a strongcentralized state (that now extends militarily across the globe in collaborationwith international corporations) is not relevant to the anxieties generated bySisi’s coup today. What constitutes Sisi’s authority—the necessity of hisintervention to save democracy, or the People’s acclamation? Of course,holding a national election is no guarantee of having entered a “democraticpath,” whatever that might be, but surely dismissing electoral procedures isn’t“democracy” in any sense. Kandil may be justified in saying that “Egypt hasevery right to seek popular consensus on the basic tenets of its future politicalsystem,” but the unanswered question remains: How, other than by the ballot

Page 21: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 21/57

box, can one determine that that right is indeed being exercised?[52]

Echoing Kandil, the noted historian Khalid Fahmi wrote two weeks after thecoup, “We were taught in schools that we were a patient and passive people,and for generations we accepted facile sayings about the genius of Egypt, itstranquil landscape, its gentle river and undemanding people. And yet here weare, proving to ourselves that we write our own history and that we candepose our rulers if they do not succumb to our will.”[53] Fahmi tells hisreaders that this traditional representation of popular submission is no longercredible because the coup has proved that “we” (all the classes, rich and poor,men and women, Muslims and Copts?) have the ability to “depose our rulers.”This claim attributes to the Egyptian People a transcendent power—the powerto make happen what is true (to unseat disobedient rulers), and to say what istrue (to write a triumphant history), a power no longer constrained by religiousauthority. Yet the considerable numbers of Muslim Brotherhood supporters inEgypt’s cities and villages discovered that they could not retain their“legitimate rulers.” It appears that the People’s power exhibits itself only indeposing but not in installing or reinstalling its rulers.[54] Because the nationincludes those who are persecuted as well as their persecutors, those whowant stability at any price and those who want justice at any price, thepermanent victory of either side is never guaranteed. A paradox of the modernnation­state, including Egypt, is that on the one hand it minimizes theexistence of significant internal differences in order to assert nationalhomogeneity, and on the other hand it emphasizes difference as significant inorder to exercise the violence that is “necessary” to its sovereignty.

Whatever coherent sense the idea of “sustained unity” has, it comes not fromcommon sentiment but from the shared life of a tradition—and even that doesnot preclude bitter disagreement among those who follow the same tradition,and mutual accusations of taking what is contingent for what is essential andworth defending to the last. The disputes themselves make for a kind of unity.The modern sovereign territorial state, by contrast, doesn’t have such a unitybecause the lives of people within it are too disparate in the things they value,in the pasts to which they attach themselves, in their sense of what group theybelong to, in the bodies they inhabit, and in the authorities they invoke. It isprecisely because of this diversity that democracy (for all its obscurities andambiguities) has emerged as an assemblage of political and legal devices—including elections—for addressing the ineradicable presence of difference,disagreement, and mutual hostility within the modern state with minimumdamage, and why the skills and sensibilities required to engage effectively in

Page 22: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 22/57

democratic politics is acquired by experience, sustained by goodwill andblessed by good luck, and why the ballot box is an indispensible part of“democracy” whatever else “democracy” might be.

As hostility to the Mursi government mounted, the secular activists joined thestate apparatuses and their business allies (who had been working to unseatMursi from at least November 2012) allowing the army to enter the politicalarena publicly yet again.[55] Certainly Mursi’s incompetence was linked to hisexaggerated sense of presidential power and immunity and to hisunderestimation of the resources and tactical skills of his enemies. The June2013 popular movement that drew on a variety of complaints and fears (somegenuine, some grossly inflated by the pro­Mubarak media) was ostensiblyaimed at “the restoration of the January 25 revolution,” but what it did was tofacilitate the coup.[56] In the 2014 military­backed constitution, references tothe 25 January uprising present in the previous constitution were removed—and hardly anyone noticed. In general, 25 January has been erased orvilified by the state media[57] and military violence has openly claimedauthority by invoking its own version of “revolutionary tradition.” The possibilityof democratic time has collapsed, and it will not—at least for an indefiniteperiod—be retrievable.[58]

The military coup consisted not merely in the removal and imprisonment of thePresident and the violent suppression of opponents to the new/old order, butin getting various social actors to accept Sisi’s claim to be exercisingtemporary authority over “the [contending] sides” (al­atrāf)—the nationallyelected President on the one side and the opposition on the other—in hisgiving the street protests military protection, and in requiring “the two sides” toresolve their disagreement within a short, specified period of time. In thuspositioning himself (and the military) above “a crisis of the state” Sisi wasenabled by the emotional rhetoric of popular sovereignty to present hisunilateral resolution of that crisis (for which Mursi’s obduracy was said byopponents to be entirely responsible) as an affirmation of the People’s will.[59]

In his book published shortly after the January 25 uprising the poet YasirAnwar recounts incidents that exemplify secular feelings of unease andrepugnance for the vocabulary of Islamic tradition, including such banalphrases as inshā’allah.[60] But the main interest of that book lies in its desireto transcend the political categories used by Marxists, liberals, and Islamists intheir polemics:

th

th

th

th

Page 23: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 23/57

We have escaped from a prison of politics to a prison of old books.No one sees this world with his own eyes, only with the eyes ofothers: this one is a Marxist, that one a Wahhabi, and a third a Sufi.We are all in need of a translator because we don’t share a commonlanguage (lughatnā laysa wāhida). How can Ibn Taymiyya debatewith Marx? How can Hegel converse with Ibn Arabi? If disagreementis considered a source of culture and a sign of its fertility and vitality,cultural despotism and polarized thinking reign supreme over thepresent scene. Faced by the dominance of [social] fragmentation andsplintering, the idea of eliminating the other has taken the place ofaccepting the other, of the relationship of neighborliness, of theinterweaving [of different ideas] – all this has disappeared.[61]

Anwar’s complaint that “no one sees this world with his own eyes” isproblematic, of course, because no one can do without authoritativeknowledge accumulated from the past; in that sense our own eyes are alsothe eyes of others who have preceded us. But he is right to draw attention tothe significance of friendship and antipathy in exchanges between people whodo not always recognize the disparity of times to which the people they drawon or dismiss belong. Heated debates across radically different traditions, hesays, seem endless and fruitless because appropriate sensibilities and theexercise of imagination are both lacking. Certainly mutual distrust and hostilityhave been major features of political life in Egypt ever since January 2011.Especially in times of political upheaval, fear, suspicion, and misattributions ofintention render trust—and therefore friendship—extremely fragile.

But first: why is rational debate of primary importance to democracy?One answer is that it has a decisive outcome and is therefore the best way, inpolitics as in law and natural science, of determining the truth. Liberalstypically represent “religion” as appeals to divine authority, and that is why(liberals believe) debates about “religious belief”—or debates generated by it—are passionate, inconclusive, and prone to violence.[62] Less well known isthe liberal state’s dependence on early modern arguments for capitalism,[63]in which the idea of “interest” increasingly displaced the idea of “passion” asthe principal mode of politics. The good that is calculable (“economic value”)was considered superior in politics to the good that isn’t (“religious value”)because only the former could be conclusively assessed. This discursivemove gave the market its ideological claim to being a neutral mediator forresolving conflicts over value, a claim that has since become central to thesecular tradition of the modern liberal state. The electoral process itself has

Page 24: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 24/57

adapted itself in several ways (resource investment, targeting swing voters,gaining and losing seats) to the idea and practice of the market. The markethas become part of liberal commonsense and liberal governance: no pursuit ofsectional “interests” within the sovereign state, no politics; no free commerce,no paradigm of political liberty. It’s this formula that underlies the emergenceof the modern state according to which politics now comes to be the interest ingaining access to the total system of social control embodied in the sovereignstate for the realization of calculable goods. Although the inconclusiveness ofdebate about “religious belief” was originally a reason for proposing thatappeals to transcendence be excluded from the domain of politics andconfined to the private sphere, today inconclusiveness is no longer groundsfor excluding debate from politics. Indeed the inconclusiveness of argument(such as over the manner and degree of state intervention in the economy orin religion), the turnaround of party government, is part of thatinconclusiveness that is now regarded as a political virtue, a sign that “liberaldemocracy” is at work.

To understand how the “democratic promise” of the past appears in thepresent, how the authority of the 2011 uprising was aborted and replaced byanother, one needs to attend not only to connections between the power of thestate and popular resistance to it, but also to the constitution of subjects whoadjust fully to modern sovereignty—as well as of those whose conditions ofexistence are incompatible with it. The subject is not only, of course, what heowns and thinks but also how he/she has learnt to move and sit and speakand feel in different situations—and what he or she wears and eats. So myfinal comment on Anwar’s complaint is this: It is not simply that public viewsare now mutually unintelligible (which they are), or that debate is interminable(which it is). It is that, like the destructive shifts following capitalist crises, thefractious time of petty dispute and distrust overwhelms the temporality oflearning discursive traditions, on recognizing how dependent one is on others,and living accordingly.[64] The power of the modern sovereign state residesnot only in what it promotes but also—and especially—in what it disableswhen it joins with a particular economy (capitalism) and a particularmetaphysic (nationalism).

IV

There are several excellent studies of Egypt’s acquisition of liberalism—including a vocabulary of “freedom,” “equality,” “progress,” “the moralsovereignty of the individual,” and so forth—since the latter part of the

Page 25: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 25/57

nineteenth century, interrupted only partly by its socialist phase under Nasir,and then resumed in the liberal policies of Sadat.[65] These are, however, notsimply moments in Egypt’s past; they are integral to a contradictory present inwhich people invoke aspects of the country’s political traditions: The beginningof state welfare, state funded education, and secularization—as well as thegrowth of the secret police and the military.[66] Nasir’s state reforms ofEgyptian society and economy are usually set in opposition to the “liberal”periods that preceded and succeeded his rule. Thus much Egyptian politicalhistory since the defeat of 1967, and especially after the death of Nasir in1970, is seen by the left as the unraveling of the state structure even thoughthe military and security apparatuses retained and even enlarged theirpresence in it: various state functions and projects were privatized, and the so­called Islamic Current in urban society emerged as the most importantorganized opposition to the secularizing state.[67] There are certainly differentways of marking out political times in Egypt but underlying all of them sincethe late nineteenth century is the aspiration of its ruling classes to “catch upwith” modern time, whether in a “liberal” or a “socialist” Egypt.

It is not always remembered that Nasir’s land reforms benefitted farmers whowere considered to be “efficient” and “productive,” as against the very largepopulation of poor peasants,[68] that after Nasir’s death the long­standingproject of increasing efficiency and productivity helped to promote argumentsfor free enterprise rather than state ownership as the engine of growth and theprecondition for national welfare. Whether the state is or is not despotic,“efficient growth” is its primary function together with maintaining its continuityand strength, and rulers have thus become receptive to arguments forprivatization and marketization. And it is the continuous dislocation effected bythe logic of the market that renders tradition increasingly precarious. Theunities enabled by market­promoted lifestyles—fashions in clothes, foods,corporal appearance—are not to be confused with the embodied disciplines oftradition that Shaykh Usama talked about because fashion is ephemeral. Onecan take up fashion or abandon it whenever one feels like it.

As in other parts of the globe, the idea of freedom of the individual in modernEgypt has merged with the idea of the free market, expressed in part in theSupreme Constitutional Court’s reforms of the bureaucratic laws that wereseen to be holding back private enterprise.[69] In the period of economic andpolitical liberalization a plethora of NGOs has created an expanding space of“civil society”: middle­class activists, with institutional funding from Euro­America and entry to Western networks, telling their fellow­citizens to claim

Page 26: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 26/57

their rights as free persons from their state and to produce more efficiently in afree economy.[70] One result has been that this “civil society” has becomefurther alienated from the predicament of the urban and rural poor.[71] Markettime with its emphasis on the sovereign consumer not only undermines muchof the continuity of everyday life but also disrupts the time necessary forcultivating trust that goes beyond the interests of the individual.

Over the last few decades the increasing circulation of money from rentierincome has contributed to rapid social mobility that has helped undermine pastsolidarities and commitments, and created personal aspirations together withresentment at the failure to realize those aspirations.[72] Several years ago,the prominent Egyptian social critic and political economist Galal Aminbewailed what he saw as a change in people’s behavior: Promise keeping,pride in one’s work, and loyalty to old relationships, are, he wrote, now rarelyvalued.[73] Hisham al­Hamamy, advisor to Abdul Mun‘im Abu­l­Futuh, cites anexpression to describe what he sees as the growth of self­interest in Egyptiansociety: gildi wa gaybi, literally, “my skin and my pocket,” that is, “all thatmatters is what affects my body and my money.”[74] From a relativisticperspective (according to which the successful individual is the sole judge ofwhat is ethical behavior and the successful nation is the sole criterion of whatis justice) the principle of gildi wa gaybi cannot be faulted.

With the increasing complexity of social­economic life, relationships have atendency to become oversimplified and crude. The space of genuinefriendship, critics say, is disappearing. With the growth of consumerismdeepening differences among life chances grow too;[75] continuity with thepast, essential to friendship, is devalued.[76] When some people speak ofgrowing corruption (fasād) in Egyptian society it is the autonomous self theyclaim to see emerging everywhere. To what extent these reactions reflect asense of anxiety on the part of the older middle classes about rapid socialmobility that sometimes seems to threaten them is difficult to say. If looked atcarefully, of course the matter is complicated: People still belong to familiesand associations, and they claim they have friends. Nevertheless, commitmentto others—and trust in them—is in considerable tension with the liberalincitement to individual autonomy. It would be interesting, in this regard, totrace the changing discourse of ethics as it reflects the increasingsubjectivisation of morality—that is to say, the increasing shift of moralauthority to the “conscience” of the autonomous individual. Thus today, inEgypt as elsewhere, secular moderns—especially those belonging to themiddle class—define ethical behavior by appeal to conscience, or by

Page 27: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 27/57

reference to good/bad consequences. This subjectivization of morality (sodifferent from shari‘a traditions like amr bi­l­ma‘rūf) makes it much moredifficult to develop a coherent moral language with which citizens cancollectively criticize state policies.

When the middle classes welcome the modernization of Egyptian society, theypoint to individual autonomy as the basis of economic enterprise andefficiency and to its rejection of religious group identity in politics. Thenineteenth­ and twentieth­century restructuring of Egyptian society and politytowards what was conceived of as modernity encouraged a new form ofgovernmentality: subjective self­fashioning (based on freedom from externalconstraint) that has increasingly eroded the conditions for tradition inembodiment. But it is not quite correct to say that the pervasive corruption ofEgyptian society that accelerated with marketization has removed any spacefor ethics. What one sees, I suggest, is a new form of ethics that is graduallyovertaking the old: a morality modeled on the law in which the individuallegislating his or her transcendental principles for him/herself stands in tensionwith the legislation of the sovereign state.

Hostility to the presence of “religion” in the public sphere is part of beingmodern. It is a reflection of the fact that the concept and practice of “religion”—as well as of “politics” and “ethics”—are in process of being formed or radicallyreformed in modern liberal society. Thus one might point out that “religion” hasnot been excluded from the state: Azhar has acquired an increasingly publicrole in the post­coup era. Working in close collaboration with the Ministry ofReligious Endowments, the present Grand Shaykh of al­Azhar, Ahmad at­Tayyib (who supported the military coup), aspires not only to greaterprominence in the public domain but also to greater collaboration with thestate in the extended regulation of mosques, preachers, Islamic researchcenters, some university faculties, etc., and seeks to project an Islam“appropriate to the twenty­first century,” as he has put it. But two points needto be noted about that Islam. First, “true Islam” is the product of a calibration; itexcludes “extremism,” that is to say, Islam that uses “illegitimate” violence;hence it is more often referred to as “moderate” or “liberal” Islam that assignsthe use of violence to the state. Second, its attachment to the state is a form of“administration,” not “politics.” Although politics takes place within theframework of the modern state its typical form is the political party by which itcompetes for power with other parties. In that sense “moderate Islam” is notpolitical. It is a force in the service of state authority, an instrument of modernsovereignty for the protection of modern sovereignty—an aim to which the

Page 28: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 28/57

Muslim Brotherhood has also been committed.

In his oration before an audience of senior military and police officerscelebrating the “October 6 victory” in the 1973 war against Israel, Shaykh AliGum‘a, previous Grand Mufti of Egypt, denounces the Muslim Brotherhood asa sectarian minority, as “heretics and traitors” (khawārij), as “dogs of hellfire”(kilābu­n­nār), and therefore as deserving of slaughter by the militaryprotectors of the nation. In the video of this event the military authorities arevisibly satisfied with this theological denunciation, one that conforms to thegovernment’s branding of the Muslim Brotherhood as a terrorist organization.[77] Shaykh Ali Gum‘a’s posture is neither surprising nor new because as aSufi adept he is known to have close religious connections with manymembers of the security police (and, so it is said, of Sisi himself) whotherefore come to him for spiritual advice.

There is “true religion” and “false religion” for everyone (including the state) towhom “religious tradition” matters. Making this distinction is part of whatconflicting claims to orthodoxy within tradition do, as articulated by Shaykh AliGum‘a. But the construct of religion itself allows outsiders to attribute beliefs,practices, and attitudes to other traditions (“yes, that is their religion, and thatis why all its believers are our enemies”). In the Schmittian politics thusgenerated, friends are essentially those who share one’s enmity towardsdefined others. The aim of this politics is to defeat the enemy and eliminate orconvert him to “real” orthodoxy and orthopraxy—whether inspired by divinity orby humanity.

V

A question I have tried to address in this essay is why liberals and the left inEgypt sought to exclude “religion” from political space. The short, familiaranswer is: they tend to see the future as the continuous progress of mankindled by secular states, and therefore tradition (especially “religious” tradition) asdivisive and a source of political discord. The result is not only a distrust ofreligion’s attempt to enter politics (the space that seeks to control society as awhole) but a visceral hostility towards “religion” as the political enemy ratherthan the military or multinational coporations.

I have already argued against the claim that religious disagreements aretypically inconclusive and therefore should be excluded from the rationaldebate that democracy requires. I might add that theological disagreements

Page 29: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 29/57

are themselves resolved—which is one way that religious traditions evolve. Itis true that such resolutions presuppose certain assumptions that others maynot share, but that is a problem common to all situations where opponents areunable to reconcile their fundamental values. This impasse doesn’t in itselfinevitably lead to violence, and not all eruptions of violence draw on “religious”values. However, my aim in this essay is not to “defend religion”; it is toexplore a problem that remains generally obscured in the secular hostility towhat is assumed to be “religion.” I argue that the problem with “politicalreligion” is not religion but the politics that derives from the sovereign state.

Many Egyptians have an understandable concern at the attempts to imposean Islamic personality on a country containing diverse traditions and identities.[78] But the crucial question is not why should an Islamic identity not beimposed on Egypt. It is: What is there about the modern state that requires ahomogeneous political identity? The modern state seeks a singular personalityfor itself in the exercise of sovereignty, and claims that this is necessary for theprogress and modernization of its subjects. The desire to assert and preservethe unity of the People rests on a political metaphysic that is shared by liberalsand Islamists alike, a metaphysic that underpins the modern concept ofsovereignty: The belief that there is such a thing as a homogeneous nation,that a homogeneous nation has the right to absolute independencerepresented by a state, and that the state must reflect the nation’s singularpersonality. Thus a common complaint against Mursi was that he was notacting as the leader of all Egyptians. This was never problematized publicly byquestioning in what sense a President elected by a majority of citizens in aheterogeneous state can be “the leader of all Egyptians” as opposed to beingthe legitimate head of state and defender of its constitutional personality(made more difficult by the repeated rewriting of the constitution). Like allheads of liberal democracies, he responds to the conflicting interests of fellowcitizens by yielding to those who exert effective pressure on his government,whether through elections or financial pressures or personal allegiances. Eventhe Supreme Constitutional Court is not the ultimate guardian of a unifiedpeople in Egypt.

One may recall here a remark Michel Foucault once made in relation to theIranian revolution: “Concerning the expression ‘Islamic government,’ why castimmediate suspicion on the adjective ‘Islamic’? The word ‘government’suffices, in itself, to awaken vigilance.”[79] Naive critics of Foucault have takenhis interest in the Islamic Republic of Iran as evidence of his “romance withpolitical Islam” (in response perhaps to his early criticism of the left­wing

Page 30: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 30/57

romance with “revolution”). But they are mistaken: Foucault’s reaction to theIranian revolution is his concern (as so often in his writings) to think beyondclichés, and in particular to formulate questions about how truth is manifestedin connection with the exercise of self on self, “the relation between the truthand what we call spirituality”—a topic that preoccupied him in his last years.[80] In the comment I quote he is posing a question about the modern state’spractice of sovereignty and the sovereign subject in that state. For the modernstate (including varieties of the liberal state) is held together not by moralideals and social contracts but by technologies of power, by instrumentalknowledge—and also, importantly, by the way it requires dependence on anddemonstration of truth: traitors are those who conceal the truth.

The genealogy of the modern state is to be found primarily not in legal,constitutional histories but in the evolution of the concept and practice of“politics” conceived of as the autonomous apparatus of control by the state—and by those who have access to the state through political parties—over thelife of an entire society. This evolution emerged in and helped define modernEurope, later to be adopted, adapted, and imposed in the Middle East (andelsewhere). Medieval European legal theories of status regni tended to have apersonal view of power according to which the ruler possesses or evenembodies the institutions of government, although the modern state’sgenealogy, as Quentin Skinner has pointed out, lies in advice­books formagistrates and in the mirror­for­princes literature that emerged from them,especially in Renaissance Italy. In that retrospectively traced tradition it wasargued that the most important requirement for the prince to maintain his stateas a prince was to keep control of the power structure within one’s regnum orcivitas. This vindicated the idea that there is an autonomous “civil” or “political”authority whose purpose is to regulate the public affairs of an independentcommunity, and to reject interference by any outside power in its own civitasor respublica.[81] Thus according to Hobbes, sovereign power is alienated toand vested in “an artificial man” who is neither the ruler nor the ruled but theapparatus of government that it is the duty of rulers and ruled to maintain. Theconcept and practice of the state’s monopoly of legitimate power, as well as ofits external and internal sovereignty, together belong to this discursivetradition. Liberal celebrations of the modern state do not recall that itsemergence involved the crushing of city freedoms by rising territorialprincedoms based on modernized military force and centralized socialdiscipline.[82]

Crucial to political sovereignty today is the founding distinction between

Page 31: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 31/57

“citizen” and “alien.” But in premodern times the distinction between someoneborn and bred in a particular place and another who has come from elsewhereto settle in that place was socially recognized but that fact defined no legalprivileges and disabilities. The distinction that mattered in premodern law (andis not recognized today) was between “free” and “slave.” The distinctionbetween “alien” and “citizen” is not only massively evident in the modern statebut has been a crucial step in its formation.[83] Since the paramount aim andduty of the modern state is the maintenance of its sovereignty, it assumes theauthority to expel or intern aliens where their presence constitutes a “threat tosecurity.” Under circumstances it perceives as critical, the state may evendeprive citizens of their civil rights, defining them by emergency laws as actualor potential “enemies of the state”—as in the case of members of the MuslimBrotherhood in Egypt, who find themselves (like Palestinian and Syrianrefugees) in the modern category of “aliens.”

There is a tendency nowadays to identify the modern state with “liberaldemocracy,” a political arrangement to which, minimally, the rule of law, theseparation of powers, the election of parliamentary representatives, and theright to public dissent are said to be central. But “modernity” is usually used tomark historical time, and also to refer to an assemblage of values, institutions,and projects that are not entirely coherent—two senses that are oftenassumed to overlap. This identification seems to me problematic, however, forat least two reasons. First: There are states—authoritarian and/or religious—that have an arguable claim to being considered “modern.” How would onecharacterize the Islamic Republic of Iran? As not modern but still Islamic? Asnot really Islamic but modern? As neither modern nor Islamic? Thesequestions are relevant to any serious assessment of Mursi’s alleged attempt to“Islamize” the state in Egypt: Was he trying to turn the state back to apremodern—because “religious”—time or was he simply moving forward onthe modern principle of state sovereignty as the representative of apredominantly Muslim society?

The second reason why the identification of the modern state as a “liberaldemocracy” is not satisfactory can be put this way: The liberal democraticstate can transform itself into forms that are neither “liberal” nor “democratic.”Thus there are clear indications in the secular United States that civil rights—the freedoms that a liberal state is constitutionally required to articulate anddefend—are being openly eroded. This is not due to accident, or to someeternal human vice. Many of the reasons for such transformation are intrinsicto its liberal character—most importantly, its commitment to securing the life

Page 32: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 32/57

and property of its citizens, to making them fully safe. Popular struggle tooppose that erosion is extremely difficult because it is not simply a matter ofthe restoration of rights but of confronting an elaborate structure of stateprotection, control and secrecy that is almost impossible to dislodge.[84]Hence the typical liberal problem of “how difficult the trade­off between libertyand security can be in a democratic society”[85] that is confronted in Egypt (aselsewhere in the “war against terror”) today. This gives cause for worry aboutliberty to some citizens while offering to others an opportunity for extendingstate security and state power—for the sake of property if not always of life.

The crucial point about the modern nation­state is precisely its mobile andcontradictory character: on the one hand its commitment to defending thecitizen and securing general welfare and progress, on the other hand todefending the state so that it can fulfill this commitment. Because the lattertask takes priority over the former, it calls for the accumulation of secretinformation about the entire subject population in order to preempt anypossibility of subversion by a minority within it. In societies heavily dependenton information technology (like the US) this can be done by sophisticatedtechniques such as the National Security Agency uses. But in all revolutionarysocieties this has been done by recruiting as many of the ordinary populationas possible into becoming secret informers on neighbors, colleagues, friends,and relatives. What is at stake, after all, is the patriotic citizen’s duty to defendhis/her nation­state, and the latter’s task of defending and transforming societyin a progressive direction.[86] The incidental result of this mode of defense,ironically, is a general increase in fear and anxiety, and thus a greater desirefor social tranquility. A recent documented study by Husni Hammada[87] hasshown how Gamal Abdul Nasir, committed as he was to creating modernEgyptian subjects,[88] sought to build a comprehensive network of informersin “revolutionary Egypt” to make sure that people were speaking and thinkingin the right way. Writing about the increase of denouncers in the urban flow ofordinary life in Cairo, the journalist Belal Fadl speculates as to whether Sisi willbe able to realize Nasir’s dream of a nation in which everyone is a potentialdenouncer of his or her fellows.[89] The denouncer­patriot is essential to thenational project of transforming Egyptians into a secular democratic people.This kind of system is made less important by the new informationtechnologies for collecting “private” data that liberal democratic governmentsin the West now use.

The Anglican philosopher Stephen Clark has argued that looked at critically,liberal arguments for political obligation within the modern state have no force,

Page 33: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 33/57

and that consequently the only alternatives are between anarcho­capitalismand a theocratic state, and it is the latter he endorses: “Either the state canhave no authority beyond that of a simple police force (if it has that much), orelse it must be supposed to embody a sacred, moral purpose that constrainsor contains all lesser purposes within society.”[90] The questionableassumption here, shared by those who urge the sacralization of the state andthose who don’t, is that in the absence of political sovereignty nothing butsocial chaos and ruthless individualism can obtain.

Instead of answering the question “A secular or a religious state?” one mighttry to imagine what politics not focused on the sovereign territorial state mightlook like. In order to do so one would need to draw on older ideas that havebeen pushed out by the narrative of secular progress since premodern times,such as the absence of rigid territorial boundaries and the presence ofoverlapping authorities. One can belong to “a People” without thinking that itmust therefore complete itself by governing its own territorial state.[91] It isonly with the arrival of the modern concept of sovereignty that jurisdiction andterritoriality have come to be defined in terms of each other, although someambiguity remains on this point in international law, most acutely as it relatesto the new humanitarian norm of “Responsibility to Protect” (R2P).

The primary question is how far rights and duties attaching to civil status canbe negotiated (just as they now are in international law) without anoverarching authority. But whereas the latter regulates relations amongsovereign states one might think of a plurality of groupings, each with itsinstitutional order and purpose, but overlapping in membership and/or territoryand each capable of being continually readjusted through negotiation. In theabsence of sovereignty there would be no distinction between internationaland domestic law. The negotiation between relatively equal parties would buildmutually recognized custom (“urf”) through precedent, difference that can berecognized and negotiated as difference—difference in time as well as inpurpose. Some parties would be subsidiary to others for narrowly definedpurposes and times but none would have the comprehensiveness, the finalauthority, and unchanging continuity claimed by the sovereign territorial state.The customs could develop into traditions not defined by bounded territory orexclusive membership but embedded in networks of commercial andintellectual relations and political and spiritual movements extending unevenlyand intermittently, beyond various existing borders—a state of affairs thatGarth Fowden in his book on the world of late antiquity has called a“commonwealth.”[92] The experience of having to live together, the learnt

Page 34: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 34/57

ability to negotiate practical problems by reference to techniques andknowledge acquired from the past (or from a very different region) is the open­ended, cooperative way of a commonwealth.

I stress that my concern is not with democratic relations between internationalunits,[93] still less with a decentralized utopia in which all power is held locally.Autonomous local groups can be almost as cruel as the state, but my point isthat one might try to think of ways in which no sovereign center of power,whatever its scale, can actually exist. That the individual can recognize—andact on the recognition—that he/she is partly reflected in other selves, just ashis/her group is partly reflected in other groups.

The idea of numerous nonhierarchical domains of normativity opens up thepossibility of a very different kind of politics—and policies—that would alwayshave to address numerous overlapping bodies and territories. Procedures todeal with differences and disagreements would include civil pressure directedagainst authorities, such as civil disobedience, to make office holdersaccountable. But the differences would not take the form of a legal distinctionbetween “citizen” and “alien,” or between Muslim and non­Muslim. Thetradition of amr bi­l­ma‘rūf could form an orientation of mutual care of the self,based on the principle of friendship (and therefore of responsibility to andbetween friends) not on the legal principle of citizenship. This sharing wouldbe the outcome of continuous work between friends or lovers, not anexpression of accomplished cultural fact. The same tradition might find its wayto collective acts of protest against excessive power (and so there have to benotions of power’s temporalities and bounds). There would be neither thepower nor the technical ability of “state apparatuses” to impose a single legalauthority, or to deploy an institutionalized force. The risk of a military forcebeing formed to create an exclusive territorial body would have to be met notmerely by constitutional barriers but also by the work of tradition in theformation, maintenance, and repair of selves who are bonded to one another.The longing for tradition by someone who doesn’t have one that Wittgensteinspoke of is not a frightened wish for the comfort that comes from submissionto authority; it is a desire for being transformed through friendship, throughbelonging to others who belong to you, as they themselves are also changedby that mutuality.

The late Neil MacCormick, legal philosopher and a Scottish member of theEuropean Parliament, has published an interesting exploration of how aspectsof such an arrangement might be made to work in the context of the European

Page 35: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 35/57

Union,[94] although the European Union remains a bounded territorial unitcontaining states and their subdivisions, overridden by a power centerconsisting primarily of the European Central Bank and the Brusselsbureaucracy. In a stateless order it would be impossible to aim at capturingstate power or to impose a single identity and a single destiny. In sum, only ifsovereignty were to be replaced by more complex forms of authority, time, andbelonging, would both “secularism” and “political Islam” have no raison d’être.

Of course, even in a world where political sovereignty no longer exists, thepast would continue to be necessary to a coherent form of life, or to a lifeaspiring to coherence. The familiar claim that “tradition is a model of thepast...in the present” tends not only to separate the past unthinkingly from thepresent; it also renders tradition as a representation of time sited in acircumscribed reality (“the present”). However, whenever people quarrel aboutwhether or not they can continue to live essentially as they do now becausethe world is (or is no longer) the way it is claimed to be, we have a morecomplicated relationship between tradition, time, and place. Tradition may turnout to be not so much a model of the past that is inseparable from itsinterpretation in the present, as a set of practices that presuppose “today” as apart of unfinished time. Whether the present in Egypt is still in some significantsense part of the time of January 2011 (when an attempt was made toestablish a new political tradition) or that time now belongs to an irretrievablepast is perhaps too early to say. But certainly the project of doing away withsovereignty (of state and subject) is part of unfinished time—although toidentify time as unfinished is not to say that there is still time enough.

Finally: One may gesture at what one thinks of as a possible solution to theintolerable cruelties and injustices of the sovereign state but applying thatsolution successfully is quite another matter. The interests of governing elitesas well as of the classes that benefit from the opportunities provided byEgypt’s sovereign state have to be reckoned with. The sentiment of nationalloyalty and pride may be fluid, unevenly distributed, and indeterminate but it isstill powerful. In Egypt the considerable numbers of voluntary policedenouncers guarding against “traitors, spies, and terrorists” is one symptom ofthat sentiment of patriotism—although Egypt is by no means exceptional inthis regard. Given the world we live in, the mere suggestion that sovereigntybe dismantled therefore borders on fantasy. Today no state accepts theviolation of its sovereign right—although that is precisely what happens toweak states that are unable to do much about it. For in practice there arerights overriding the principle of sovereignty that powerful sovereign states can

Page 36: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 36/57

exercise.[95] Thus the US—and Israel—insist on their right to use preemptiveviolence against another state, or against a foreign population, on grounds ofself­defense, as well as of the duty to intervene by force in another state inorder to protect a population against imminent massacre by its own rulers orby sectarian elements whom the state is unwilling or unable to restrain.

All modern sovereign states, including Egypt, are invested in the continuoussearch for global markets and investment capital, as well as dependence onmilitary security and access to the most sophisticated weaponry. They aredriven by an ever­present desire for increasing profit, consumption, andpower, all under the auspices of financial and industrial corporations. Theresults, with which virtually everyone is familiar, include accelerating climatechange, systematic environmental degradation, impending nuclear disastersand financial collapse, developments that cannot, so it seems, be stopped. Itis this excess, expressed by continuous desire and willfulness, that traditionalforms of life have sought to control—even if often they have failed to do so.But in our world the (morally) sovereign individual and the (politically)sovereign state, each reflecting the other, neither able to change this world forthe better, are both trapped, gridlocked. That is the tragedy not merely ofEgypt but of our time.

[1] I am grateful to the following friends for critical comments on early versionsof this essay: Hussein Agrama, Gil Anidjar, Ayça Çubukçu, David Scott, AlexisWick, and Gary Wilder. During the months of March, April, and May 2014,while I was teaching in New York, Mohammed Tabishat carried out interviewsfor me in Cairo with a number of Egyptians, only some of whom I knowpersonally; I thank him for this work.

[2] Culture and Value, p. 76.

[3] For a remarkable exploration of temporality in relation to politics—withspecial reference to the failed Grenada revolution—see David Scott, Omens ofAdversity; Tragedy, Time, Memory, Justice, Duke University Press, 2014.

[4] I draw here, of course, on Michel Foucault, who opposed genealogy totranscendental critique. In endorsing the former, he observes that “this critiquewill be genealogical in the sense that it will not deduce from the form of what

Page 37: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 37/57

we are what it is impossible for us to do and to know; but it will separate out,from the contingency that has made us what we are, the possibility of nolonger being, doing, or thinking what we are, do, or think. It is not seeking tomake possible a metaphysics that has finally become a science; it is seekingto give new impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undefined work offreedom.” Michel Foucault, The Politics of Truth, edited by Sylvère Lotringer,Semiotext(E), p. 114.

[5] Ath­thābit wa­l­mutahawwil, 4th revised edition, Beirut, 1983, vol.1, p. 34.

[6] See, for example, Susan James, Passion and Action, Oxford: 1997; AntonyFlew and Godfrey Vesey, Agency and Necessity, Oxford: Blackwell, 1987;Albert O. Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests, Princeton, 1977; LionelTrilling, Sincerity and Authenticity, Harvard University Press, 1971.

[7] Historians of ideas trace the beginnings of the modern critique of traditionto the so­called “Quarrel of the Ancients and the Moderns” in the second halfof the seventeenth and the first half of the eighteenth century, when religiousand political apologetics confronted each other (See Paul Hazard, The Crisisof the European Mind, 1680­1750, New York: NYRB, 2013 [1961]). TheAncients were not totally rejected by Moderns but re­situated: they werecriticized, historicized, and used for new purposes.

[8] The prominent British anthropologist Maurice Bloch elaborated the conceptof traditional authority by arguing that the very “formality” of oratory (as in theformality of manners) was a means of social control and political dominationbecause it rested on the repetition of a priori forms as opposed to authenticexpression. Formal speech and behavior—whether in religious ritual or inpolitical oratory—should be seen for what it really was: the denial of choiceand therefore blind submission to authority. (See his “Introduction” to PoliticalLanguage and Oratory in Traditional Society, ed. by Maurice Bloch, London:Academic Press, 1975) This approach to ritual therefore reinforced the ideathat to think and speak autonomously and rationally the subject needed tobreak from tradition and claim the legitimacy of her own beliefs. The book thathas had the greatest impact on anthropological thinking on tradition is TheInvention of Tradition edited by Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger,Cambridge University Press, 1983. My approach to tradition is quite different,and draws on the work of MacIntyre.

[9] Adam Seligman et al., Ritual and Its Consequences: An Essay on the

Page 38: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 38/57

Limits of Sincerity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.

[10] See David Lieberman, “Law/Custom/Tradition: Perspectives from theCommon Law,” Questions of Tradition, Toronto: University of Toronto Press,2004.

[11] Walter Benjamin’s “The Work of Art in the Age of MechanicalReproduction” (in Illuminations, ed. by Hannah Arendt, New York: SchockenBooks, 1969 [Original German in 1955]) has become especially attractive tocritics of the concepts of authenticity and tradition. But contrary to the simpleway this famous essay has usually been read, we should note that it actuallyarticulates a problem that was quite apparent to its author. Here is theproblem: Since the Benjaminian notion of aura spells uniqueness andauthenticity, the destruction of aura undermines tradition. The difficulty withthis is that tradition not only guards the uniqueness of authentic things, it alsoconveys historical knowledge of them. “The authenticity of a thing,” writesBenjamin, “is the essence of all that is transmissible from its beginning,ranging from its material duration to its testimony to the history which it hasexperienced. Since the historical testimony rests on [its] authenticity, theformer, too, is jeopardized by reproduction when material duration ceases tomatter. And what is really jeopardized when the historical testimony is affectedis the authority of the object.” (p. 221) So Benjamin explicitly recognized that“tradition” was the process by which something authentic was preserved andpassed on down the generations. A humanly­made object—say an old dagger—has aura by virtue of the fact that it displays its uniqueness in its shape andmaterials, as well as in its scratches and discolorations, all signs of its ancienthistory. An old document that embodies specific traces of the past, similarlyhas an aura. Memory is central to the way the past is conveyed and re­presented, a point Benjamin makes more elaborately in “The Storyteller,”where he also emphasizes what we now know about Homeric poetry—namely, that the memory embodied in the epic, and also the recall required forits performance, both depend on a process of iteration, on the same beingrepeated with perhaps occasional slight modifications. The time employed inthe work of tradition is not simply the homogeneous time of modernprogressive history. It is the complex time of everyday experience,remembrance, and practice. Thus memory, too, may be authentic orinauthentic, just like any physical object. The distinctive question for Benjaminis whether it inhabits more than one time.

[12] Can there be a rational basis for choosing between contending traditions?

Page 39: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 39/57

MacIntyre, who has done most to rehabilitate the idea of tradition inAnglophone philosophy, proposes how such a rational choice can be made.Citing Aquinas’s debate with the followers of the Muslim Aristotelianphilosopher Ibn Rushd, MacIntyre argues that Thomist Aristotelianismprovides “a standpoint which suffers from less incoherence, is morecomprehensive and more resourceful in one particular way. For among thoseresources. . . is an ability not only to identify limitations, defects and errors inthe light of the standards of the opposing view itself, but also to explain inprecise and detailed terms what it is about the opposing view whichengenders just these particular limitations, defects and errors and also what itis about the view which must deprive it of the resources required forunderstanding, overcoming, and correcting them” (MacIntyre, Three Modes ofMoral Inquiry, p.146). This is an attractive argument, but can’t one reasonablyclaim that in time it may be possible to overcome apparent incoherence by aproper resort to the resources of one’s own tradition? In other words, whileMacIntyre points to criteria for judging the rational vulnerability of particulartraditional beliefs in transcendental form, he doesn’t say when argumentsbased on those criteria become decisive, and why time is crucial topersuasiveness. Being able to grasp the force of a criticism leveled at one’stradition from outside it, of being persuadable, one has to be a person living aparticular form of life who is yet prepared to change his/her opinion entirely ata particular point in time. If that move occurs it may be closer to a conversionthan to a deductive conclusion, because the truthfulness of a tradition isessentially a matter not of propositions but of a form of obligation carried outover time, achieved not by theoretical proof but by persuasion throughconversation and demonstration in and appeal to the solidities of everyday life.Persuadability is the measure of a subject’s capacity to be persuaded—andtherefore also the precondition of a successful process of persuasion. Thereis, of course, no special virtue in persuasion: one can be persuaded to commitserious intellectual mistakes and crimes.

[13] And a fifth of the spoils of war (khums) that, according to Sunnis, lapsedafter the Prophet’s death. See Shaykh al­Islam Ibn Taymiyya, Al­Imān, Beirut:al­Maktab al­Islami, 1996, p. 12.

[14] Wael Hallaq has an excellent analysis of this aspect of the shari‘a in TheImpossible State, New York: Columbia University Press, 2013.

[15] In Ghazali’s words, by “exercising the soul” (riyādat an­nafs) one candevelop a virtuous constitution—by learning orientations of faith and

Page 40: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 40/57

exigencies of a lived form of life in which destructive desires are graduallyrestrained. See Ihyā’ ‘Ulūm ad­Dīn, Cairo: Dar Ihya’ al­Kutub al­‘arabiyya, vol.3, p. 47 ff. (kitāb riyādat an­nafs). Shaykh Usama often cited Ghazali, andused the latter’s psychological vocabulary.

[16] Peter Brown, Religion and Society in the Age of Saint Augustine, London:Faber and Faber, 1972, p. 30.

[17] “The buffered self” is a term used by Charles Taylor to distinguishmoderns from “the porous self” of premoderns: “Modern Westerners have aclear boundary between mind and world, even mind and body. Moral andother meanings are ‘in the mind.’ They cannot reside outside, and thus theboundary is firm.” But the question that Freud has helped us to ask is whetherbeing buffered is in fact how moderns live, or simply what they consciouslyassume must be how they ought to live. One can accept that there aresignificant differences between moderns and premoderns, but does the simplebinary of “buffered” and “porous” catch that difference adequately? Believingthat the self is buffered (when it isn’t) has a repressive function, so that whatconflicts with that belief is pushed into the unconscious, ready to resurface inirrational ways. (Augustine: “Try to build up yourself, and you build a ruin.”) Ihave discussed the buffered self briefly in “Thinking about Religion, Belief, andPolitics” (Robert Orsi, ed., Cambridge Companion to Religious Studies,Cambridge University Press, 2012).

[18] A Qur’anic reference to amr bi­l­ma‘rūf wa nahy ‘an al­munkar is to befound at 3:110.

[19] In one of our discussions Shaykh Usama cited the famous hadith fromMuslim: man ra’a minkum munkaran falyughayyaruh biyadih, fa in lam yastati‘fabilisānih, fa in lam yastati‘ fabiqalbih fa dhālik ad‘afu­l­‘imān (“Any one fromamong you who sees an evil doer, let him change him by action, and if hecannot do that, then by speaking out, and if he cannot do that then silently inhis [own] heart – and that is the weakest form of faith”).

[20] Michael Cook, Commanding Right and Forbidding Wrong in IslamicThought, Cambridge University Press, 2000, p. 96.

[21] Ghazali, whom Shaykh Usama often quoted, has written at length aboutthe duties of friendship. See Adāb us­suhba wa­l­mu‘āshara, Beirut: Dar al­Kutub al­‘Ilmiyya, 2007. On the duties and correct ways of advising and

Page 41: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 41/57

instructing friends, see especially pp. 66­9.

[22] See Chapter 1: “The Legalization of Hisba in the Case of Nasr Abu Zayd”of Hussein Ali Agrama, Questioning Secularism; Islam, Sovereignty, and theRule of Law in Modern Egypt, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012.

[23] I have discussed nasīha in the context of state policy in Saudi Arabia inChapter 6 of Genealogies of Religion, Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993.

[24] Agrama, op. cit., p. 20.

[25] Understanding the shari‘a as “tradition” as opposed to a fixed structure(even as the context for understanding it as a normative ideal in relationship tothe time of “real history”) seems to me essential. Thus although the wellknown account of the shari‘a’s primary sources include the Qur’an, Hadith, aswell as reasoning by analogy, the authority of doctrinal consensus, andindependent reasoning, “custom” (‘urf) is also incorporated into the shari‘a bydevices such as “necessity” (darūra), so long as it doesn’t contravene theprimary sources.‘Urf is that which is ma‘rūf (good custom, fitting practice,decent behavior) as in amr bi­l­ma‘rūf. “Good custom” was not recognized atfirst as an independent source of law even though it was continually integratedinto the shari‘a, however since the sixteenth century ‘urf has been formallyrecognized as a legal category. The changing character of allowable practiceis therefore also part of that tradition so long as the changes don’t affect whatis allowable. So one might suggest that (allowable) habitual practice isn’tmerely a possible source for the shari‘a, it is in a deep sense what the shari‘ais – by which I mean that the authority of the shari‘a resides not in (written)rules and commands but in embodied practices (including “soundinterpretation put into practice” of what the sources say) in accordance withliving tradition. The changing character of custom in different historicalcircumstances inevitably affects the way in which Qur’anic and propheticauthority is interpreted and argued over in the shari‘a tradition. Hence thetradition of amr bi­l­ma‘rūf can be seen not only as coming within the purviewof the shari‘a but also as an expression of the everyday concern of friends andkin for the welfare of one another’s souls, as well as an expression of theoccasional need for addressing the holders of power.

[26] Wael Hallaq, “Was the Gate of Ijtihad Closed?” International Journal ofMiddle East Studies, vol. 16, 1984.

Page 42: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 42/57

[27] See Chapter 7 of my Formations of the Secular, Stanford UniversityPress, 2003 (entitled “Reconfigurations of Law and Ethics in Colonial Egypt”)in which I tried to argue that in its premodern form the shari‘a is not a primitiveconfusion of “morality” and “law” but something quite different from both asthey are understood in modern society.

[28] See Human Rights Watch report, All According to Plan: The Rab‘aMassacre and Mass Killings of Protestors in Egypt, 14 August 2014,http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/egypt0814_ForUpload_0_0.pdf

[29] What both Shaykh Usama had to say, as well as Abdul Mun‘im Abu­l­Futuh, is consistent in some respects with what has been written by severalWestern critics who take a long historical view of Western liberal culture,although their sources of inspiration are different. For example, in a well­known essay Elizabeth Anscombe describes the emergence of a modernconcept of ethics in which the Aristotelian concept of virtue ethics has beenhistorically abandoned and yet a quasi­legal notion of obligation has beenretained in secularized fashion (“Modern Moral Philosophy,” Philosophy, Vol.33, No. 124, 1958). She thinks that philosophers since Hume are correct inasserting that there is an unbridgeable gap between what is the case andwhat ought morally to be the case—but that is only because in the absence ofa divine commandment “morally ought” has no content. Her criticism is thatthe modern concept of “moral obligation” tends to rely on notions of“conscience,” or of “self­legislation,” or of “consequentialism,” all of which areeither meaningless (their usage allows for any or no content) or are confusedabout what comes under the notion of “practice” and “intention.” Thus“conscience” as the founding criterion of “moral obligation” is absurd becauseone’s conscience may dictate anything—including unjust behavior—and“legislating” for oneself is meaningless because of the metaphor used.Anscombe thinks that it would be better, in modern philosophy and commondiscourse, to abandon the modern liberal notion of “moral obligation”altogether (rooted as it is in the idea of the self­contained—“buffered”—self.Her philosophical argument is consistent with an understanding of the shari‘a(especially of amr bi­l­ma‘rūf) that I encountered at length in Shaykh Usama’swords, and more briefly in Abu­l­Futuh’s statement.

[30] And yet “religion” was not absent from the uprising—see my article, “Fearand the Ruptured State: Reflections on Egypt After Mubarak” Social Research,vol. 79, no. 2, 2012.

Page 43: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 43/57

[31] “What Is Authority?” in Hannah Arendt, Between Past and Future,Penguin Books, 1977.

[32] Garth Fowden has argued recently for an extension of the temporal andspatial limits of antiquity as traditionally defined—from the sixth century (“therise of Islam marks the end of antiquity as well as the split between theNorthern and Southern Mediterranean lands”) right up to the end of themillennium (Islamic lands and the Northern Mediterranean belong to a singlecomplex history with traditions shared as well as diversely developed). Hisbook, Before and After Muhammad: The First Millenium Refocused (Princeton,2014), is primarily an intellectual history, but it constitutes an important newchallenge to the writing of quite separate histories of what is now calledEurope and the Middle East.

[33] Wael Hallaq, has an impressive analysis of the political context in whichpremodern sharī‘a rule operated, including this separation between power andauthority in The Impossible State, New York: Columbia University Press, 2013.

[34] In A History of Islamic Societies (Cambridge University Press, 2002), IraLapidus has traced this separation to the Mihna (the so­called inquisition) inninth­century Baghdad through which the defiant ulama emerged triumphantin their challenge to the Caliphate’s pretension to theological authority.However, Lapidus’s claim that this represents “secularization” is quitemistaken.

[35] In On Revolution, where Arendt claims that there was only one successfulfoundation that was relatively nonviolent: the American Revolution based onthe pre­existing power of self­governing colonies. In making this claim,however, she ignores the constitution of the United States as an expandingpolitical power based on violence—expanding geographically and socially—from the very beginning: Indian massacres and forced removals, slavery, thecivil war, institutionalized racism, the US­Mexican war, and the extension ofFederal state power and authority, all of which have helped to constitute theUnited States. It is only in retrospect, and when this revolutionary history is setaside, that the writing and formal adoption of the constitution in 1787 on thebasis of pre­Revolutionary power of the colonies can be regarded as the“founding” of the American republic. In other words, apart from the manyverbal emendations that were made to the text of the constitution, the republicwas constituted—often very violently—both before and after 1787. In The TwoFaces of American Freedom Aziz Rana convincingly shows how the

Page 44: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 44/57

contemporary US drive for global hegemony is part of its complex politicaltradition in which the continuous continental expansion, the transformation ofan agrarian into an industrial economy, and the waves of always useful but notalways welcome immigration, were reflected in the often violent reconstitutionof state authority and power.

[36] Arguing, as Walter Benjamin did in “The Work of Art in the Age ofMechanical Reproduction,” that if techniques of reproduction are continuouslyrevolutionized tradition as continuity ceases to exist. But Benjamin had a moreconflicted view of tradition as something at once inconsistent with and yetessential to modernity. See note 11 above.

[37] See Yazid Sayigh, “Above the State; The Officer’s Republic in Egypt,” TheCarnegie Papers, August, 2012.

[38] The Muslim Brotherhood suffered from the opposite fault. Its hesitation injoining the 2011 uprising (for which they were repeatedly criticized by secularliberals and leftists) may partly be explained by a fear of repression. Thuswhen Kifaya organized a public protest against Mubarak’s rule in 2005 theMuslim Brotherhood immediately called for their members in large numbers tojoin it. They also mobilized their own protests demanding political reform.These protests collapsed without any positive results, and were followed byfurther severe penalization of the organization. See Bruce Rutherford, EgyptAfter Mubarak: Liberalism, Islam, and Democracy in the Arab World,Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008, p. 14.

[39] See, for example, the very interesting account of developments from therevolt of January 2011 to the coup and its aftermath in July 2013 by Ibrahim al­Hudaiby, “Hukm al­qitā‘ayn al­amny wa­l­‘askary fi misr: tahālufātmutaghayyira wa qam‘ mustamirra” Mubādirat al­islāh al­‘araby, April 2014,p.22. In spite of the many valid criticisms that can be made of the MuslimBrotherhood (and Hudaiby makes many of them) his representation of theMuslim Brothers as essentially part of the “counterrevolution” seems to meunconvincing. The evolving situation was too fluid, confused, and emotionallycharged for the categories of “revolution” and “counterrevolution” to be usefulin describing what happened.

<http://www.arab­reform.net/ar/%D8%AD%D9%83%D9%85­%D8%A7%D9%84%D9%82%D8%B7%D8%A7%D8%B9%D9%8A%D9%86­%D8%A7%D9%84%D8%A3%D9%85%D9%86%D9%8A­

Page 45: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 45/57

%D9%88%D8%A7%D9%84%D8%B9%D8%B3%D9%83%D8%B1%D9%8A­%D9%81%D9%8A­%D9%85%D8%B5%D8%B1­%D8%AA%D8%AD%D8%A7%D9%84%D9%81%D8%A7%D8%AA­%D9%85%D8%AA%D8%BA%D9%8A%D8%B1%D8%A9­%D9%88%D9%82%D9%85%D8%B9­%D9%85%D8%B3%D8%AA%D9%85%D8%B1>

[40] Carl Schmitt, Legality and Legitimacy, Duke University Press, 2004.

[41] Mafīsh dimūqrātiya wa mafīsh mugtama‘ intaqal ila­l­amām bidūn damm.See the video of the workshop organized by the journalist Hilmi Namnamdiscussing the making of the new constitution by the military­appointedcommittee (halaqa niqāshiya lil­hay’at al­injīlīyya hawl dastūr misr ba‘d 30yūnyū). Many middle­class workshops, Muslim and Christian, have been heldon this topic, especially in Cairo. <http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=__rdetkbS_s>

[42] Hannah Arendt, On Revolution, Penguin Books, 2006, p. 106.

[43] Before Arendt, Maurice Merleau­Ponty had analyzed revolutionaryviolence in Humanism and Terror, New York: Beacon Press, 1969 [originalFrench, 1947].

[44] See “Body/Power” in Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge, edited by ColinGordon, 1980, pp. 59­60.

[45] One might ask why so many ordinary Egyptians come to hold a mistakenview of their country’s identity, seeing it as “religious” when it is not. Oneanswer often given by liberals is that the masses are ignorant and theIslamists provide a reactionary leadership that renders violence against themnecessary in the cause of progress. This is not an explanation, of course, buta claim. In a sophisticated study, Carrie Wickham has recently provided anaccount of the ruralization of the Muslim Brotherhood and its influence on itsleadership, as well as the consequent greater emphasis on ritual amongordinary members, trends that she connects to the group’s increasingconservatism and quietism in relation to what she calls the “predatoryMubarak state.” But here and elsewhere in her study Wickham’s approachmakes explicit something Namnam misses: that it is the interaction of differentgenerations of the Brotherhood’s leaders with individuals from differentclasses, and with authoritarian state institutions, that helps explain their

Page 46: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 46/57

political sensibilities and predispositions. Carrie Wickham, The MuslimBrotherhood: Evolution of an Islamist Movement, Princeton University Press,2013.

[46] The mobilization of large numbers of lower middle­class Egyptians for“restoring the revolution” was largely the achievement of those who workedthrough the big business community, the ministry of the interior, and themedia, warning the populace that instability would lead to a decline inincomes, that government mismanagement had led to crucial shortages, etc.Some of the activists eventually turned against the army whom they hadinitially welcomed, but by then it was “too late” (see http://www.alquds.co.uk/?p=136030).

[47] Tariq al­Bishri, interview, May 2014.

[48] “By intimating that Morsi and the Muslim Brotherhood had, in some way,hijacked Egypt’s political process, the United States, in the crucial weeks afterthe July coup, effectively legitimated the logic that the coup was necessary inorder to salvage Egyptian democracy. As we have shown, Morsi’s year inoffice was more democratic than his critics allege, and the military­backedgovernment that seized power in the coup is significantly more autocratic thanMorsi ever was.” Shadi Hamid and Meredith Wheeler, “Was Mohammed MorsiReally an Autocrat?” in The Atlantic, March 31, 2014.<http://www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2014/03/was­mohammed­morsi­really­an­autocrat/359797/. The other familiar complaint against Mursiwas that he simply played along with “counterrevolutionary forces.” And yetcompared to the old constitution, the one drafted under the MuslimBrotherhood government was more concerned to define and restrict thepowers of the President. For example, Article 73 of the 1971 constitution gavethe President extraordinary powers to fight any “danger to the safety of thenation”; Article 136 allowed him to dissolve parliament “whenever necessary.”Such articles were removed in the new constitution.

[49] Dina Khawaga, interview, May 2014.

[50] In a recent interview with the London based daily Al­quds al­‘arabi, thespokesman for the Muslim Brotherhood in Europe, Ibrahim Munir, claimed thathad the Brotherhood kept quiet about the massive corruption of the Egyptianmilitary Mursi would have remained President. Apart from reference to theenormous properties owned by the generals (it is estimated that the army

Page 47: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 47/57

controls about 40% of the Egyptian economy, but its budget is not open togovernment inspection), Munir claimed that the military had authorized theredrawing of Egypt’s maritime boundaries and ceded thereby considerableareas containing vast underwater gas resources to “other states,” all inexchange for personal bribes. See Ibrahim munīr li­“al­quds al­‘arabī”: lawsakat al­ikhwān ‘ala­l­fasād fi misr lazalla mursi ra’isan, November 22, 2014,http://alquds.co.uk/?p=254556

[51] Hazem Kandil, “The End of Islamism?” London Review of Books Blog, 4July 2013.

[52] In a second piece, published eight months after the coup, Kandil writes:“There is no getting around it. What Egypt has become three years after itsonce inspiring revolt is a police state more vigorous than anything we haveseen since Nasser. As in the dark years of the 1960s, the enemy iseverywhere, and any effort to expose and eradicate him is given popularassent.” Hazem Kandil, “Sisi’s Turn,” London Review of Books, Vol. 36, No. 4,20 February 2014. The main theme of Kandil’s story is “religious fascism.” Byits dishonesty, incompetence, and hunger for power, says Kandil, the MuslimBrotherhood facilitated the emergence of a police state for which they aretherefore responsible: From the Brotherhood’s scheming there emerged themilitary government’s repression. But “religious fascism” is merely a term ofabuse echoing Christopher Hitchens’s coinage “Islamo­fascism.” Kandilundertakes no reassessment of the reasons for his earlier optimistic judgmentabout the coup, nor why it is right to attribute political disaster only to theMuslim Brotherhood and not also to the “revolutionaries.” His account rests onclaims and allegations drawn uncritically from the Brotherhood’s fiercestenemies on the right and on the left. Kandil’s message, like that of the militarygovernment and its supporters, is that there are enemies of the state(“enemies of society”), and that the state has the authority—the duty—toidentify and deal firmly with them. He seems to be perturbed only by the factthat the state’s suppression of “enemies” has now also begun to affect left andliberal members of the middle classes. Unfortunately he doesn’t address thefamiliar claim that it is the state’s rhetoric of national security, its identificationof “potential enemies” within the nation, its appeal to nationalist sentiment, andits celebration of a military officer as the savior of the nation, that constitutesthe logic of fascism and not the inflated political aspirations of the leadershipof a movement that lacked a paramilitary wing and that, as a government, wasimprisoned within a hostile political environment, faced by intractableeconomic problems, and that displayed a profound lack of political judgment.

Page 48: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 48/57

Whether the entire leadership of the Muslim Brotherhood was utterly deviousor merely obtuse is a minor question: it was certainly a fatal mistake for it tomake a bid for the presidency—despite earlier assurances that they would notdo so. But the idea, held by many critics of Mursi, that his governmentnaturally chose to work with rather than attempt a major reform of the securityestablishment fails to address the problem of the Interior Ministry’s entrenchedpower that included the support of the army generals and intelligence officialsso long as their autonomous power and privilege remained unaffected—not tomention a hostile higher judiciary and media. Kandil does not considerwhether the orchestrated movement of protest at the end of June thateventuated in and supported the military coup compromised the attempts,however limited, to build a democratic tradition. (Incidentally, the term“religious fascism” is now commonly and uncritically used in the authorizedpress to describe the military suppression of the Muslim Brotherhood. See, forexample, Mahmoud al­‘Alayly, “Min ath­thawra ila ad­dawla,” al­Shurūq daily,Sunday, 16 November, 2014.http://www.shorouknews.com/columns/view.aspx?cdate=16112014&id=1446390b­cae9­4837­97f1­106cdc3a7e11.)

[53] Khalid Fahmi, “A Revolutionary People,” Ahram Online, 15 July 2013.

[54] There is some dispute about the actual numbers of anti­Mursi protesters,given the interest of the latter in exaggerating the numbers and of theiropponents in minimizing them. (See “Exactly How Many Millions Were We, MyGeneral?” International Boulevard, 17 July 2013,http://www.internationalboulevard.com/exactly­how­many­millions­were­we­my­general/). It will take some time to make reasonable assessments of howmany and who were involved. Several observers have noted that Mursi’ssupporters were largely poor. The British journalist Robert Fisk visited Egyptbefore as well as after the coup, and reported on massacres and populardemonstrations with considerable perspicacity. In an article published threeweeks after Mursi’s ouster by the military Fisk described two protests in verydifferent parts of Cairo: “One point that stood out – and it may beunfashionable to say so – is that the Brotherhood supporters were generallypoor and looked poor in their grubby abayas and plastic sandals. Some of theTahrir demonstrators, who were truly revolutionaries against Mubarak in 2011,trooped over the Nile bridges waving posters of General al­Sisi. And one hasto say, painful as it is to do so, that the sight of well­heeled people holding aloftthe photograph of a general in sunglasses – albeit a wonderful and verydemocratic general – was profoundly depressing. What really happened to the

Page 49: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 49/57

25 January 2011 revolution?” see Robert Fisk, “As Impoverished CrowdsGather In Support Of Mohamed Morsi, The Well­Heeled March Behind TheirImages Of The General,” The Independent, July 27, 2013.

[55] Supported by the United States. See Julian Pecquet, “Kerry says MuslimBrotherhood ‘stole’ Egypt’s revolution,” The Hill, November 20, 2013.

[56] See Sheera Frenkel and Maged Aref, “How Egypt’s Rebel MovementHelped Pave the Way for a Sisi Presidency,” BuzzFeed World, April 15, 2014.http://www.buzzfeed.com/sheerafrenkel/how­egypts­rebel­movement­helped­pave­the­way­for­a­sisi­pre

[57] See “Sabāhi: ad­dākhiliyya tafrut fī istikhdām al­quwwa…wa­l­i‘lām yaqūdhamlat isā’a did 25 yanāyir,” al­Shurūq daily, 11 January 2014.

[58] The sporadic fighting by protesters against the coup (not necessarilymembers of the Muslim Brotherhood, although they were usually described as“Mursi supporters” in the Egyptian media), in the Sinai as elsewhere, providesthe military with a modern form of legitimacy: the violent suppression of“religious terrorists” who threaten the safety and integrity of the People and itsstate. On the one hand, the military arrests and massacres Islamists; on theother, churches are conspicuously left unguarded to face vengeful MuslimBrotherhood supporters. (It should be noted, however, that rights activistshave raised serious questions about the degree to which the ministry of theinterior has been actively involved in incidents aimed at increasing sectarianhostility and general alarm. See, e.g., Fahmy Huwaidy’s column, in al­ Shurūqdaily, Tuesday 6 January, 2014.)

[59] State sovereignty was restored even though prior agreement with Israeland financial support from the Gulf countries were apparently necessary toensure it. General Sisi sought support from both Saudi Arabia and Israelshortly before the coup, the former promising money and the latter militarycoordination against Hamas in Gaza. On prior knowledge of the coup bySaudis see Esam Al­Amin, “The Grand Scam: Spinning Egypt’s Military Coup,”CounterPunch, July 19­21, 2013; on Israel, see “Al­Sisi informed Israel of thecoup three days prior,” MEMO: Middle East Monitor, Tuesday, 16 July 2013.See also “A Grande Entente,” in Baheyya: Egypt Analysis and Whimsey,Tuesday August 12 2014, http://baheyya.blogspot.com/?m=0 for an excellentanalysis of the overlaps between regional democratic struggles and thestruggle to end the Israeli occupation of Palestine.

Page 50: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 50/57

[60] Anwar recounts his exchange in a meeting at a cultural event with anaggressively secular woman poet sitting beside him who belonged to theEgyptian communist movement (“whose infidelity we had forgiven but who didnot forgive us our faith,” alladhīna sāmahnāhum ‘ala kufrihim wa lamyusāmihūna ‘ala īmānina). “We began to talk,” he continues, “and when sheasked me whether I was going to recite a poem, I said to her: ‘inshāllah.’ Andthe doctor of philosophy immediately responded: ‘How backward!’ I wasastonished that the expression inshāllah should have irritated her so. I smiledat her outburst but that didn’t help in restraining her loquacity – and from herelaborate interpretation of inshāllah and other common expressions as thecause of this nation’s backwardness, and from her urging me to beenlightened. So I said to her: ‘I am an Other. Do you not speak of respect forthe Other (ihtirām al­ākhir)? I am, dear lady, that Other.’ I realized at thatmoment that the nation’s crisis was hidden within its cultural elites – to whom Ihope I do not belong.” Yasir Anwar, Al­‘almāniyūn wa­l­islāmiyūn; muhāwala li­fad al­ishtibāk, Cairo: Shams, 2011, p. 7.

[61] Yasir Anwar, p. 24.

[62] Passion, it is still said, is a force that overcomes one as opposed to actionthat one undertakes. It is common knowledge that this aspect of secularismemerged in Europe out of the theological polemics and wars, thus helping toform the early modern state that had to administer mutually hostile Christianchurches. By contrast, modern Middle Eastern states grew mostly out of theprocesses of colonial deconstruction and anti­colonial attempts to constitute “anation” that therefore had the right to its own state. The ruptures in theirrespective traditions were different but the concept of sovereignty as theorganizing principle of the modern state was shared.

[63] Albert O. Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests, Princeton, 1977.

[64] This was already apparent to observers in the emerging culture ofmodernity in late nineteenth­century Europe. Thus Paul Valéry: “Interruption,incoherence, surprise are the ordinary conditions of our life. They have evenbecome real needs for many people, whose minds are no longer fed. . . byanything but sudden changes and constantly renewed stimuli. . . . We can nolonger bear anything that lasts. We no longer know how to make boredombear fruit.” Quoted in Zygmunt Bauman, Liquid Modernity, Cambridge: Polity,2005, p. 1.

Page 51: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 51/57

[65] For an account of the critical period in Egypt’s political liberalism, see AfafLutfi Al­Sayyid­Marsot, Egypt’s Liberal Experiment 1922­1936, Berkeley andLos Angeles: University of California Press, 1977.

[66] For a critical but not entirely unsympathetic account of Nasir’srevolutionary project by a Marxist, see Anouar Abdel­Malek, Egypt: MilitarySociety, New York: Random House, 1968.

[67] See Tariq al­Bishri, Misr bayn al­‘isyān wa­t­tafakkuk, Cairo: Dar alSharouk, 2006.

[68] The expropriation of large landed property was essentially political, aimedat undermining Egypt’s ruling elite. “While the direction of the redistribution ofagricultural income has in general been from richer to poorer groups,” wrotePatrick O’Brien, “the reduction of rents, the elimination of middlemen, and theabolition of interest charges by the Agricultural Bank affords greater benefits tothose who cultivate, borrow, and sell on a larger scale than to smaller and lessaffluent farmers. Moreover the selection of owners for land redistributed underthe agrarian reforms did not favour the most impecunious families in thecountryside but was biased, on efficiency grounds, towards existing tenants orthose considered to be competent farmers.” The Revolution in Egypt’sEconomic System, Oxford University Press, 1966, p. 295. See also EvaGarzouzi, Old Ills and New Remedies in Egypt, Cairo: Dar Al Maaref, 1958,pp. 100­103. For a later account of the way “development” has reinforcedinequality in rural Egypt, see the excellent article by Timothy Mitchell,“America’s Egypt: Discourse of the Development Industry,” MERIP, No. 169,March­April 1991.

[69] See Tamir Moustafa, The Struggle for Constitutional Power; Law Politicsand Economic Development in Egypt, Cambridge University Press, 2007.

[70] NGOs often aim to encourage economic development throughentrepreneurship among craftsmen and the poor whom they employ. See JuliaElyachar, Markets of Dispossession: NGOs, Economic Development, and theState in Cairo, Durham: Duke University Press, 2005, especially chapter 1,“The Power of Invisible Hands.” But these NGOs rarely address the reallypoor. For an interesting journalistic account of the predicament of the urbanpoor, the mutual understanding between the police and businessmen, and theassistance that poor squatters typically received from the Muslim Brothers,see Tom Dale and Abdelkasim al­Jaberi, “Land rights, labor and violence in a

Page 52: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 52/57

Cairo slum,” Egypt Independent, 15/07/12. The claim of critics that the MuslimBrothers were in league with big business and the police is a generalizationthat requires careful examination.

[71] The elitist character of NGOs in Egypt, their inability or unwillingness toreach the mass of ordinary citizens, is described in Mohamed Hussein ElNaggar, “Human Rights Organisations and the Egyptian Revolution.” IDSBulletin, January 1, (43) 1, 2012.

[72] In Misr bayn al­‘isyan wa­t­tafakkuk, (see note 38 above) Tariq al­Bishriattributes the new corruption to the governing elite—but other commentatorsregard it as far more widespread.

[73] “Patterns of behavior that were highly regarded in a more stable societysuch as sticking to one’s word or promise, pride and personal integrity, arenow less prized. Such values are less fit for a rapidly changing society whereloyalty to old relationships, be they friends, spouses, places or principlesappears as nothing more than an excessive sentimentality unbecoming in onewho is on the make.” Galal Amin, Whatever Happened to the Egyptians?Changes in Egyptian Society from 1950 to the Present, Cairo: AUC Press,2000, p. 24.

[74] Video interview with Hisham al­Hamamy, May 2014.

[75] In Misr wa­l­misriyūn fi ‘ahd Mubārak, 1981­2008 (Cairo: Dar Mereet,2009), Galal Amin elaborates on the effect of the national and global economyon the moral state of politics and society under Mubarak. A crucial part of hisaccount—see especially chaper 6—is concerned with the enormousexpansion of the middle class from Nasir’s “socialist” revolution onward, andits recruitment into the expanding state bureaucracy that remains overblown.The “open­door” economic policy, initiated by Sadat and continued underMubarak, led to the amalgam of a massive bureaucracy with a consumeristculture fuelled by the infusion of “rent” income—from overseas remittances,expanded tourism, and the Suez Canal. The creation of a consumerist culturerequires not only the flow of unproductive income but also the expectation ofcontinuous economic growth and the material aspirations of the middle andupper classes that go with it.

[76] Thomas Hobbes, the great theorist of modern sovereignty, writes in amemorable passage on its psychological preconditions: “By MANNERS, I

Page 53: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 53/57

mean. . . those qualities of man­kind, that concern their living together inPeace, and Unity. To which end we are to consider, that the Felicity of this life,consisteth not in the repose of a man satisfied. For there is no such Finisultimus, (utmost ayme,) nor Summum Bonum, (greatest Good,) as is spokenof in the Books of the old Morall Philosophers. Nor can a man any more live,whose Desires are at an end, than he, whose Senses and Imagination are at astand. Felicity is a continuall progresse of the desire, from one object toanother; the attaining of the former, being still but the way to the later. Thecause whereof is, That the object of man’s desire, is not to enjoy once onely,and for one instant of time; but to assure for ever, the way of his future desire.”Leviathan, Chapter XI, 1651 (Everyman’s Library edition, Introduction byA.D.Lindsay, 1914, p.49). The process of ceaseless desire strikes at the rootof the discipline that is fostered by tradition, and already by the nineteenthcentury this was becoming apparent to many observers (see note 51 above).

[77] See <http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=dTBgYcJaAgo>

[78] Thus Tarek Osman writes in criticism of the Muslim Brothers: “in Egypt,Islam—as a frame of reference, an identity, and a major social component—has always (sic) existed alongside Arabism, Mediterraneanism, Levantinism,Christianism, and pharoahism” (Tarek Osman, “Egyptian Dreams,” The CairoReview of Global Affairs, May 14, 2014, italics added). But these are elementsof a nationalist ideology, not of an actual historical sense of belonging ofvarious peoples in Egypt. It is the function of statist ideology to suppress theuntidy formation, diverse experiences, and multiple attachments of people inhistorical societies.

[79] Michel Foucault, “Open Letter to Prime Minister Mehdi Bazargan,” in Afaryand Anderson, Foucault and the Iranian Revolution, p. 261. For an excellentreview of the Afary and Anderson book, see Jonathan Rée, “The Treason ofthe Clerics,” The Nation, August 15, 2005.

[80] See, Michel Foucault, On the Government of the Living, PalgraveMacmillan, 2014.

[81] See Quentin Skinner, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, 2volumes, Cambridge University Press, 1978.

[82] See, for example, Richard Mackenney, The City­State, 1500­1700:Republican Liberty in an Age of Princely Power, London: MacMillan, 1989;

Page 54: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 54/57

Philip Gorski, The Disciplinary Revolution: Calvinism and the Rise of the Statein Early Modern Europe, University of Chicago, 2003. Mackenney sees theprocess as essentially secular, Gorski as religious, but both recognize thecentrality of power—repressive as well as productive—in the formation of themodern state.

[83] See Keechang Kim, Aliens in Medieval Law; The Origins of ModernCitizenship, Cambridge University Press, 2000.

[84] For a discussion of that institutional structure see the very interestinginterview with Glenn Greenwald on the significance of the congressional reporton CIA Torture.http://www.salon.com/2014/12/11/exclusive_corrupt_toxic_and_sociopathic_glenn_greenwald_unloads_on_torture_cia_and_washingtons_rotten_soul/

[85] George Packer, “The Holder of Secrets,” The New Yorker, October 20,2014.

[86] Foucault, incidentally, failed to mention this in his discussion of theparadoxes of revolutionary “necessity” that I mentioned above: every citizen adenouncer.

[87] Husni Hammada, Abdul­Nāsir wa tanzīm at­talī‘i as­sirrī.

[88] In his opening speech to the first session of the National Assembly on 22July 1957, President Gamal Abdul Nasir proclaimed: “We must ever keep inmind that the most important, the most difficult and the most crucial of ourproblems is to rear in this part of the world a lively, vigilant and consciousnation and that human beings are the raw material of which such a nation ismade. The real effort, therefore, in building the new Egypt lies in the adequatedevelopment of the latent potentialities with which the Creator has endowedthis raw material.” Quoted in E. Garzouzi, Old Ills and New Remedies inEgypt, Cairo, 1958, p.5.

[89] Belal Fadl, “Hal yanjah as­sīsī fi tahqīq hilm ‘abdu­n­nasir bi an yasbah kulmuwātin mukhbiran,” Mada Masr, Sunday, 9 November 2014.

[90] Stephen R. L. Clark, Civil Peace and Sacred Order, Oxford: ClarendonPress, 1989, p. 82. Clark goes on to cite Simone Weil, but he doesn’t note thatWeil wrote this in a time of despair, when Nazi Germany was occupyingFrance and the felt need for rallying resistance against the occupier seemedcritical, so I give a much longer quotation from her book:

Page 55: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 55/57

Since the people’s obedience towards the public authorities is anecessity for the country, this obedience becomes a sacredobligation, and one which confers on the public authoritiesthemselves, seeing that they form the object of it, the same sacredcharacter. This doesn’t mean an idolizing of the State in associationwith patriotism in the Roman style. It is the exact opposite of this. TheState is sacred, not in the way an idol is sacred, but in the waycommon objects serving a religious purpose, like the altar, thebaptismal water or anything else of the kind, are sacred. Everybodyknows they are only material objects; but material objects which areregarded as sacred because they serve a sacred purpose. That isthe sort of majesty appropriate for the State. If we are unable toinspire the people of France with a conception of this nature, they willhave only the choice between anarchy and idolatry. Idolatry mighttake a communist form. That is probably what would happen. It mightalso take a nationalist form, in which case it would presumably haveas its object the pair of idols so characteristic of our age, composedof a man acclaimed as leader and at his side the iron­bound machineof State. But we mustn’t forget that, first, publicity is able tomanufacture leaders, and secondly, if circumstances place a man ofgenuine ability in such a situation, he rapidly becomes a prisoner ofhis rôle. In other words, in the language of today, the absence of apure source of inspiration would leave the French people no otheralternatives than anarchy, Communism or Fascism. [Simone Weil,The Need for Roots, London and New York: Routledge, 2002, pp.177­8.]

Sacralizing the state, whether as an idol or as common objects serving areligious purpose, seems to me equally dangerous. Weil is of course right tostress the need for roots as a condition for transcendent commitments (thesubtitle of her book is: “Prelude to a Declaration of Duties towards Mankind”).But having roots doesn’t logically presuppose the nation­state.

[91] Thus even the word umma, usually taken nowadays to signify “a nation,”has a Qur’anic sense of ethical formation and creatureliness detached fromterritoriality. As used to signify a human grouping, umma has evolvedhistorically. Originally it carried no sense of exclusive descent or territoriality.The word occurs several times in the Qur’an, generally in the sense of the

Page 56: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 56/57

followers of a prophet or the beliefs and practices that distinguish them fromothers—and so of the moral space they share. It also refers to a moralexemplar, Abraham (16:120), and to the world of natural creatures as aparadigm of divine justice (6:38), but never—in the Qur’an at least—to a polity.Ridwan as­Sayyid has traced the evolution of its meanings from pre­Islamicusage, through the Qur’an and the “constitution of Medina,” and into theclassical period in al­Umma wa­l­jamā‘a wa­s­sulta (Beirut: Dar Iqra, 1984),especially at pp. 19­87. The dominant secular sense that umma has acquiredin modern times is that of “nation,” as in al­umma al­‘arabiyya, “the Arabnation”—and therefore of a nation­state—and as in al­umam al­muttahida,“United Nations.”

[92] See Fowden , Before and After Muhammad: The First MilleniumRefocused, Princeton, 2014.

[93] See Global Democracy: Normative and Empirical Perspectives, edited byDaniele Archibugi, Mathias Koenig­Archibugi, and Raffaele Marchetti,Cambridge University Press, 2012. Interesting though this collection is, itsinterest is quite different from mine: not the ideal conditions of national andinternational “democracy,” but the possibilities of fluid and overlappingidentities that may escape some of the dangers of the modern state.

[94] See Neil MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty: Law, State, and Nation inthe European Commonwealth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. The EUparliament has very little power.

[95] In a perceptive historical review David Scott has traced the changesunderlying the different ways sovereignty is conceptualized in international lawand invoked by strong Euro­American states when applied to weak ThirdWorld states. See David Scott, “Norms of Self­Determination: ThinkingSovereignty Through,” Middle East Law and Governance, 4, 2012.

Home Current Features Book Review Blog Forthcoming Archive Info Share Search

Page 57: Thinking About Tradition, Religion, And Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

19/04/2015 Thinking About Tradition, Religion, and Politics in Egypt Today – Critical Inquiry

http://criticalinquiry.uchicago.edu/thinking_about_tradition_religion_and_politics_in_egypt_today/ 57/57

© Copyright 2015Critical Inquiry