04+cenite%2c+borat+informed+consent+2009

Upload: sol-lopez

Post on 15-Oct-2015

6 views

Category:

Documents


2 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    1/19

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    This article was downloaded by: [Pontificia Universidad Catlica de Chile]

    On: 7 July 2010

    Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 906706830]

    Publisher Routledge

    Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-

    41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Journal of Mass Media EthicsPublication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t775653682

    Ethical Learnings from or ton Informed Consent for Make Benefit Filmand Television ProducersMark CeniteaaWee Kim Wee School of Communication & Information, Nanyang Technological University,

    To cite this ArticleCenite, Mark(2009) 'Ethical Learnings from Boraton Informed Consent for Make Benefit Film andTelevision Producers', Journal of Mass Media Ethics, 24: 1, 22 39

    To link to this Article DOI 10.1080/08900520802689365URL http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08900520802689365

    Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf

    This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial orsystematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply ordistribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.

    The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contentswill be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug dosesshould be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss,actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly

    or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.

    http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t775653682http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08900520802689365http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdfhttp://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdfhttp://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08900520802689365http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t775653682
  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    2/19

    Journal of Mass Media Ethics, 24:2239, 2009

    Copyright Taylor & Francis Group, LLC

    ISSN: 0890-0523 print/1532-7728 online

    DOI: 10.1080/08900520802689365

    Ethical Learnings from BoratonInformed Consent for Make Benefit

    Film and Television Producers

    Mark CeniteWee Kim Wee School of Communication & Information

    Nanyang Technological University

    When is it ethically justifiable to mislead participants about the nature of a film

    or television program? Producers of the 2006 film Borat: Cultural Learnings of

    America for Make Benefit Glorious Nation of Kazakhstanused brilliantly crafted

    releases to undermine potential fraud claims from participants misled about the

    comedy. This article argues that if portraying participants can result in foreseeable,

    substantial negative consequences for them, the portrayal must serve an overriding

    public interest. The test is applied to scenes inBorat.

    The British comedian Sacha Baron Cohen plays obnoxious, clueless characters

    mostly in real-life encounters with ordinary people who have signed appearance

    releases not knowing he is a comedian and they are part of the joke. Cohenused this formula to portray Ali G, a white man who more or less affects the

    manner of an urban black rapper. Ali G got his own internationally distributed

    television program, in which Cohen also played Borat, a television reporter

    supposedly from Kazakhstan, and Bruno, a gay Austrian fashion designer. Borat

    journeys across America in the 2006 filmBorat: Cultural Learnings of Americafor Make Benefit Glorious Nation of Kazakhstan, holding up a mirror to Amer-

    icans through reactions he provokes. The film was an international commercial

    Correspondence should be sent to Mark Cenite, 31 Nanyang Link, Singapore 637718. E-mail:

    [email protected]

    22

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    3/19

    ETHICAL LEARNINGS FROM BORAT ON INFORMED CONSENT 23

    success. It was acclaimed by critics and nominated for an Academy Award for

    best adapted screenplay (Academy of Motion Picture Arts & Sciences, n.d.).

    While concentrating on examples from Borat, the first feature film of its kind,

    but not confining arguments to it, this article explores ethical issues raised by

    how producers of such works get participants.

    Issues related to whether participants are fully informed about what theyare getting into when they consent to get involved are common in journalism,

    documentary and reality televisionin any genre with nonfiction elements.

    Participants always risk being cast or perceived in ways they did not anticipate.

    Controversial surprises have occurred in reality programming when participants

    who signed away all rights find editing has distorted their stories. For example,Ruthie Alcaide, whose drinking on the 1999 The Real World: Hawaiibecame

    a focal point of the season, has claimed that she was misrepresented (Fletcher,

    2006). Segments of Comedy Centrals fake news shows, The Daily Show withJon Stewart, and its spin-off, The Colbert Report, are prominent examples of

    work that use the same basic formula for some interviews; only after signingconsent forms and participating do people find they were part of a comedy and

    that they were targets of a joke. Bill Mahers 2008 film Religulous, directed by

    Borats director Larry Charles, also relies on less than fully informed consent

    (Goldstein, 2008).

    This article proposes a test for determining when it is ethically permissible

    to deceive participants in such works and applies the test to scenes from Borat.To demonstrate how the producers protected themselves legally, this article first

    discusses when an agreement between producers and participants can be voided

    by misrepresentations in the negotiations, and shows how Borats producers

    escaped liability. Drawing on ethical principles debated in regard to documen-

    taries, journalism, and entertainment, as well as principles underlying Americanprivacy law, this article argues that including footage obtained without fully

    informed consent can be justified in two cases: if the depiction is harmless or

    if a public interestsuch as addressing an important social issueoutweighs

    potential harm to participants.

    SOME SCENES FROM BORATTHAT RESULTEDIN LITIGATION

    Cohen first faced legal action for Boratfrom two University of South Carolina

    fraternity brothers. The young men drank with some of the Boratteam at a bar

    and then signed appearance release forms. The young men are shown picking up

    Borat on the highway and drinking heavily with him in a recreational vehicle.The young men animatedly spoke about women and minorities in derogatory

    ways and said it is a shame that America does not have slavery. After the

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    4/19

    24 CENITE

    films release, the young men sued for fraud, claiming that the producers

    misrepresentations, including that the film would not be shown in America or

    name them, voided their appearance releases. Their suits were dismissed under a

    California law that bars legal claims based on expression about issues of public

    interest unless the plaintiff can demonstrate likelihood of prevailing on the merits

    (Doe v. One America Productions, 2006).In another sequence, Borat meets an etiquette coach. Then he is shown

    attending a social club dinner in Birmingham. In the Alabama Supreme Courts

    statements, the guests were told the film was a documentary being filmed for

    Belarusian television about the experiences of a foreign reporter traveling in

    the United States (Ex parte Sacha Baron Cohen, 2008, p. 2). After insulting aguest on her appearance, Borat excuses himself to go to the bathroom and brings

    back what appears to be a plastic bag full of feces, asking where to dispose

    of it. When Borats uninvited friend arrives at the dinner partya scantilyclad African American woman portraying a prostituteBorat is kicked out.

    Guests sued for fraud and other claims, but complications related to standingand venue prevented the suit from going forward (Streit v. Twentieth Century

    Fox, 2008).

    Another case involves the films opening scene, in which Borat is shown

    leaving his Kazakh hometown for America. It is actually filmed in a very

    poor rural village in Romania whose residents speak limited English (Kole,

    2006). They claim they were told it was a documentary about their poverty(LaPorte, 2006), and they did not sign releases (Barkham, 2006). Borat is seen

    off by, among others, a man with an amputated hand; a man shown welding,

    whom Borat calls the town mechanic and abortionist; and a woman he kisses

    and identifies as my sister, number four prostitute in all of Kazakhstan. The

    depiction of their poor rural lifestyle was in other ways embellished; a womanwas asked to bring a pig into her home and have her child pose with a toy rifle

    (Kole, 2006). When Borat is shown returning home to the village in the final

    scene, the amputee is shown with a new hand, a hand-shaped sex toy from an

    earlier scene. The villagers filed a $30 million lawsuit, but their case foundered

    when they were required to amend their complaint for failure to state a cause

    (LaPorte, 2006).A scene in which Borat visits a Pentecostal meeting in Mississippi and feigns

    being born again resulted in a suit over a three-second segment showing

    the plaintiff, a worshipper, waving her arms in apparent religious ecstasy. The

    court ruled, It is : : : undisputed that the defendants did not obtain the plain-

    tiffs explicit permission to be featured in any other film except a religiousdocumentary that would be shown in a foreign countrynot a major motion

    picture shown across the nation and internationally (Johnston v. One AmericaProductions, 2007a, pp. *23*24). Her case for misappropriation of her image

    and false light invasion of privacy survived a motion to dismiss.

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    5/19

    ETHICAL LEARNINGS FROM BORAT ON INFORMED CONSENT 25

    LEGAL DECEPTION: APPEARANCE RELEASES ANDALLEGED NEGOTIATIONS

    Agreements between video producers and participants, known as appearance

    releases, are contracts whose enforceability is determined by well-established

    general contract law principles. Underlying legal issues are crucial to understandsome of the core ethical issues this article concentrates on. Regarding his fake

    news show, Stephen Colbert joked in an interview, We get people to sign

    releases that basically say that we get their kidneys (Gross & Miller, 2005).

    One might argue that the law allows Borats producers to lie to participants and

    get away with it. Using fairly standard and sweepingly powerful language, therelease gives the producer rights to use the recorded material without restriction

    in any media throughout the universe and through perpetuity and without liability

    to the Participant. (Standard consent agreement, n.d.). It then disclaims 16specific kinds of liability, including defamation, false light, misappropriation,

    and infliction of emotional distress. Other disclaimers appear specifically tai-lored to protect against liability for the deception Borats producers engaged in

    (Standard consent agreement, n.d.).

    The Borat team appears to have brilliantly avoided fraud claims. To prevail

    in fraud, the defendant producers must have made false statements of matters

    of fact fraudulently that are material and that relate to the present or past,

    not the future: assertions about future events cannot be deemed contrary tofact (Farnsworth, 1990). If indeed the Borat producers asserted that the film

    would not show in America, it appears that they knew that these arguably

    material assertions were extraordinarilylikelyto turn out false because Twentieth

    Century Fox was behind the production and the United States is a major film

    market. Nonetheless, the producers were legally safe making such assertionsabout future events. The Borat release also contains a nonreliance clause in

    which the participant acknowledges that she is not relying on any promises

    or statements made by anyone about the nature of the Film or the identity

    of any other Participants or persons involved in the Film (Standard consent

    agreement, n.d.). The release also contains a merger clause, which reduces the

    agreement to the written contract, stating simply, This is the entire agreementbetween the Participant and the Producer or anyone else in relation to the Film

    (Standard consent agreement, n.d.). A principle of contract interpretation that

    buttresses these clauses and makes pre-contractual statements irrelevant is the

    parol evidence rule, which creates a legal presumption that evidence extrinsic to

    the written contracti.e., evidence-regarding oral or written negotiations beforeit was signedis inadmissible to challenge (or supplement) a contract reduced

    to writing (Farnsworth, 1990). Some may argue that Borats producers usedlegal loopholes to obtain consent, but the rationales for these various rules are

    central in contract law: the need to reduce an enforceable agreement to one that

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    6/19

    26 CENITE

    is unambiguous and archived rather than one that is oral and turns upon parties

    imperfect recollections, and the need to honor the final agreement rather than

    preliminary negotiations (Farnsworth, 1990). It is only when one party appears to

    deploy such devices to undermine another that they seem surprising and unjust.

    WHEN IS LACK OF INFORMED CONSENT JUSTIFIED?

    A common approach to media ethics cases is to attempt to classify the work

    and then deduce applicable principles. Although their precise approaches differ,

    many media ethics textbooks lay out ethical principles for each areafor ex-

    ample, journalism, entertainment, advertising, public relationsand then applythem to cases (e.g., Christians, 2001; Patterson & Wilkins, 2005). Similarly,

    ethics codes are largely domain specific. When a work is difficult to classify, asBoratis, this deductive approach may ultimately be inconclusive. Court decisions

    document the ambiguity aboutBorats format (Johnston v. One America Produc-

    tions, 2007b, p. *4, Johnston v. One America Productions, 2007a, pp. 1415).The ethics of consent in documentary, and the related area of journalism and

    entertainment, will be examined. The purpose is not to offer conclusive answers

    as to whether Cohens work is ethical but to inform the analysis. Scholars from

    multiple ethical traditions agree that deception and lack of informed consent are

    prima facie unethical. In deontological ethics, such practices violate individual

    autonomy and affront victims dignity, treating them as means to an end (Kant,1785/1998). In utilitarian ethics, such practices can be justified only if greater

    good results (Mill, 1863/2001). The analytical frameworks of documentary,

    journalism, and privacy law mix utilitarian and deontological considerations.

    These perspectives will be discussed before explicating my approach to theBoratformat.

    INFORMED CONSENT IN DOCUMENTARY:PRINCIPLES AND QUESTIONS

    The release thatBoratparticipants signed states it is a documentary-style film(Standard consent agreement, n.d.). The definition of documentary is contested

    even by documentarians; for example Nichols (2001, p. 38) offers a definition

    based on that of the early British documentarian John Grierson: a creative treat-

    ment of actuality, not a faithful transcription of it : : : : Documentaries marshal

    evidence but then use it to construct their own perspective or argument : : : ;

    their own poetic or rhetorical response to the world. In defining documentary,Gross, Katz, and Ruby (1988, p. 20) speak of a contract between producers

    and audiences that the image maker will be held to standards of truthfulness,

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    7/19

    ETHICAL LEARNINGS FROM BORAT ON INFORMED CONSENT 27

    while yet aspiring to art, that is, to a personal vision and statement. Because

    of its admixture of fictional main characters (Borat and his assistant) and some

    purely fictional scenes, Borat cannot be grouped with typical documentaries.

    However, because it is partly a treatment of actual events (or at least partially

    unscripted events) and arguably makes a statement, documentary ethics warrant

    further examination.Questions regarding informed consent are familiar and controversial in docu-

    mentary. For instance, can producers withhold information about the production

    to help get participants, or portray participants in a different light than antici-

    pated? (Gross, Katz, & Ruby, 1988). Anderson and Benson (1988, p. 81) note

    a dilemma likely to arise in this genre: Without the informed consent of thesubjects, the form lacks ethical integrity; without freedom for the filmmaker,

    it lacks artistic integrity. Nichols (2001) argues that ethics of documentary

    production are more complex than ethics of fiction. Because participants appearas themselves, questions abound:

    What will others think of you : : : What aspects of your life may stand revealed

    that you had not anticipated? What pressures : : : come into play to modify your

    conduct, and with what consequences? These questions have various answers,

    according to the situation, but they are of a different order from those posed by

    most fictions. They place a different burden of responsibility on filmmakers who

    set out to represent others rather than to portray characters of their own invention.

    (Nichols, 2001, p. 6)

    Nichols simply defines informed consent as participants : : : should be told

    of the possible consequences of their participation (p. 10). This is very bad

    news indeed for Borat.

    Among the most famous documentary filmmakers, Michael Moore has oftenbeen accused of misrepresentation, but the controversies are usually about por-

    trayal of factual matters regarding public issuesfor example, the bin Ladenfamily members flights out of America after September 11, 2001 (Hitchens,

    2004). Controversies about Cohens work, however, involve the process of get-

    ting participants to appear or how individuals are portrayed after they give

    consent.

    There is no consensus among documentarians about ethical standards forunanticipated portrayals that are not false. Brian Winston (1988) takes what

    is perhaps the most extreme position, arguing that more information about

    possible consequences is required for adequately informed consent. He asserts

    that documentarians duty to provide information about possible consequences

    of participation is comparable to social scientists duty to research participants.

    Although Winston acknowledges that his proposed duty of care would mas-sively reduce access to subjects (p. 284), he still supports it, saying decades of

    documentaries have patently done more good to the documentarists than they

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    8/19

    28 CENITE

    have to the victims, [therefore] I see no cause to mourn a diminution of these

    texts (p. 284). Winston argues that because documentary substitutes empathy

    for analysis and privileges effect over cause, : : : it seldom results in any : : :

    actions taken in society as a result of the program to ameliorate the conditions

    depicted (p. 274). Similarly, Australian filmmaker Philip Noyce said he stopped

    making documentaries because of the intrusion into peoples lives and becausethe subject inevitably doesnt always realize how the audience will judge their

    behavior (Ryan, 2004).

    Principles from Newsgathering Ethics

    Documentary ethics are in some ways related to journalism ethics. Both focus

    on actual events rather than fiction (Nichols, 2001), though most journalism

    approaches lack the personal vision and statement of documentary (Gross,Katz, & Ruby, 1988, p. 20). The introduction of pure fiction precludes classifying

    Borat as journalistic. However, journalism ethics are explored further because

    some parts of the film are actual events. A court ruling for misappropriation,

    or using a participants image without permission, corroborates that Borat hasqualities of journalism. When a New York pedestrian sued for a portrayal of him

    as rude and frightened, a federal district court stated that it is beyond doubt

    that Boratfits squarely within the newsworthiness exception to New Yorks

    misappropriation law and clearly falls within the wide scope of what New

    York courts have held to be a matter of public interest (Lemerond v. Twentieth

    Century Fox, 2008, pp. 67). When the pedestrian sued, the court concludedthat though the film uses much childish and vulgar humor,

    At its core, : : : Borat attempts an ironic commentary of modern Americanculture, contrasting the backwardness of its protagonist with the social ills af-

    flict[ing] supposedly sophisticated society. (Lemerond v. Twentieth Century Fox,

    2008, pp. 67)

    The plaintiffs portrayal was deemed as serving the broadly defined public

    interest, and the case was dismissed. This case demonstrates how public interest

    is balanced with consent in newsgathering cases. Although the decision that thiscase served a public interest is not conclusive according to the ethical analysis

    proposed in this article, it is a useful precedent for ethical reasoning.

    A standard interpretation of the ethics of deception in newsgathering is that

    it is unethical except when there is no other way to get a story that serves

    the public interest (Black, Steele, & Barney, 1999). Boratmay be analogized

    to undercover reporting, although the subjects of undercover reporting do notknow they are being targeted at all, whereas Borats participants do not know

    the circumstances. The Society of Professional Journalists (1996) ethics code

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    9/19

    ETHICAL LEARNINGS FROM BORAT ON INFORMED CONSENT 29

    says, Avoid undercover or other surreptitious methods of gathering information

    except when traditional open methods will not yield information vital to the

    public (emphasis added). The San Francisco Chronicle, which has unusually

    detailed ethics guidelines, has a three-part test for determining when journalists

    are allowed not to identify themselves as such. It requires consideration of

    public importance (Is the resulting news story or photograph of such vitalpublic interest that its news value outweighs the potential damage to trust

    and credibility?), alternatives (Can the story be recast to avoid the need

    not to disclose ones identity in gathering the information?), and last resort

    (Have all other reasonable means of getting the story been exhausted?) ( San

    Francisco Chronicle, 1996). This test is almost completely consequentialist; thepotential harm of undercover reporting is described as potential damage to trust

    and credibility rather than harm involving deception. Similarly, Don Hewitt,

    producer of CBSs 60 Minutes, defended journalistic deception that serves thepublic interest: Its the small crime versus the greater good (Smith, 2003,

    pp. 283284). In American Privacy law, privacy rights are seen as limited bycompeting public interest concerns (Diaz v. Oakland Tribune, 1983; Time v.

    Hill, 1967; Contrell v. Forest City Publishing, 1974). First Amendment cases

    make clear that protection for expression on matters of public concern does

    not depend on whether the content is entertainment or journalism: The line

    between the informing and the entertaining is too elusive for the protection of

    : : : [freedom of the press] (Winters v. New York, 1948, p. 510). In this article,the proposed ethical reasoning also requires balancing public interest concerns

    with potential harms. The approach of journalists and the courts is even more

    clearly consequentialist than approaches of documentary experts.

    Consent and Entertainment

    Ethics principles for entertainment are less codified compared to other fields, butin cases involving consent to appear, the standards are generally uncontroversial,

    unforgiving, and involve no weighing of consequences. Typically, entertainers

    make fully informed artistic choices rather than being cast in works that differ

    from what they believe they have consented to. The ethical standard mirrors the

    legal standard: consent is ethically obligatory and releases are legally advisablefrom all participants except those who appear incidentally in public; written or

    recorded releases can head off legal action, especially for misappropriation of

    participants images (Dehn, 2005).

    Some may suggest that hidden camera shows can serve as a model for

    work such as Cohens: producers get participants fully informed consent after

    recording. Allen Funt, host of Candid Camera, which originated in the 1940s,said, We get 997 out of every thousand releases without pressure (Pryluck,

    2005, p. 196). In MTVs Punkd, celebrities are recorded being duped into

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    10/19

    30 CENITE

    ridiculous situations, and all but a few ultimately consent to air the footage after

    they have full knowledge of the situation (Another of Ashtons, 2004). The

    hidden camera format, however, differs from the format discussed here in that

    the ridiculous situations created are generally quite benign. By contrast, Cohen

    sometimes provokes more controversial responses from ordinary people who

    have little to gain from the publicity, so getting consent may be more difficult.

    STANDARDS FOR A NEW GENRE

    Fully informed consent is not an option in the Borat genre. It relies on less

    than fully informed consent to survive and cannot be justified to those taking

    a deontological approach that forbids deception. It is too much to require that

    producers announce their approaches and goals, or attempt to anticipate andwarn participants of likely audience reactions, or obtain consent after recording.

    Such requirements would effectively tame the genre: producers would likely

    avoid sensitive matters and outraging participants. The ability of undercover

    journalism and documentaryor new formats like Boratto reveal anythingwould be seriously compromised because airing of situations that make subjects

    uncomfortable would be greatly diminished. The gotcha moment has potential

    value, and participants should not be given total editorial power when a scene

    serves a public interest. If the genre is to survive, and the argument here is that

    it should continue because of its potential public benefits, then it can be justifiedin particular cases through consequentialist balancing of individual harms and

    public interest. The purpose of this article is to evaluate when portrayals in such

    works can be justified. The aim is not to change the minds of deontological

    purists who believe that such justification is impossible but to address the choicesof those who have chosen to make a film relying on deception. Although they

    have dispensed with deontological concerns such as fully informed consent, theycan still be ethically evaluated based on consequences. Entertainment ethics are

    generally unforgiving of nonconsensual portrayals, but in newsgathering and

    documentary ethics, as well as in American privacy law, many advocate balanc-

    ing of harm to participants and public benefits. This balancing test should apply

    to other works containing nonfiction elements, like Cohens work. Essentially,when there is substantial foreseeable harm to participants, the harm can only be

    justified by a greater good: an overriding public interest.

    Winstons argument that documentaries without fully informed consent are

    indefensible because they generally have failed to solve social problems does not

    consider documentaries potential and, ultimately, immeasurable effects. Though

    participants may not benefit directly from attention to a problem, incrementalchanges in viewers awareness and attitudes may eventually be manifested in

    change. Requiring documentaries or other works similar to Cohens to have a

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    11/19

    ETHICAL LEARNINGS FROM BORAT ON INFORMED CONSENT 31

    magic bullet effect to justify their tactics ignores that social change usually

    happens incrementally. This article weighs the incremental good that may be

    triggered against the harm to an individual who is portrayed in an unflattering

    way, but who had nonetheless consented to be on camera.

    There are practical reasons for not requiring fully informed consent beyond

    the fact that many potential participants would not consent if they knew allthe circumstances. Providing complete information in all cases is impractical

    because producers cannot fully anticipate the consequences when they begin

    filming. In addition, requiring producers to obtain consent after recording a

    scene would entail potential investment losses.

    THE TEST

    This article addresses narrowly defined situations in which consent is given

    but not fully informed. The ethical debates and principles regarding deceptionand informed consent in journalism, documentary, and privacy cases inform the

    proposed balancing test:

    If portraying participants without fully informed consent can result in foreseeable,

    substantial negative consequences for participants, the portrayal must serve an

    overriding public interest.

    Public interest is classically and broadly defined as the common good, although

    this definition is difficult to operationalize (Martinson, 1995). Public interest is

    not public curiosity, but involves matters that are in the interest of the public

    to know about because the public has a stake in them; for example, matters ofethical controversy or wrongdoing. In the context of producing video, serving

    the public interest involves exploring matters of public controversy and willinvolve latitude in its interpretation. In the context of Borat, the public interest

    involves exploring matters of prejudice, but it could involve a broader array of

    issues. Certainly, serving the public interest must survive Boks (1978) test of

    publicity. That is, it must be capable of public statement and defense (p. 92;

    Martinson, 1995). The test proposed in this article does not require serving avitalpublic interest, as some journalism code provisions regarding deception require.

    The test assesses whether the portrayal serves an overriding public interest, that

    is, one that outweighs potential harm to participants. It allows for relatively

    harmless portrayals that are common in entertainment programming. Thus, in

    cases where potential harm is absent and the public interest is also absent (for

    example, a participant in a silly situation looks silly), the portrayal is justifiable.Objectionable cases under this test are those in which no point of public

    interest is made and a participant is being held up to ridicule, a type of emotional

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    12/19

    32 CENITE

    and reputational harm. The approach outlined here emphasizes public interest

    against individual harm. Some satirists, however, are more deontological in their

    approach, emphasizing participants innocence and blameworthiness, or respect

    for fundamental beliefs, in their ethical evaluations. Comedian Steve Carell

    emphasizes the need to make a point, which, according to the present argument,

    serves the public interest. In an interview with National Public Radio, Carellspoke of what he found acceptable and objectionable when working for The

    Daily Show, where he worked before Jon Stewart became host in 1999. For

    his audition field piece, he was asked to interview a Colorado man who, Carell

    came to believe, was mentally ill. We werent making any sort of point. We

    were just mocking the fact that he believed what he believed, Carell said Itslike shooting fish in a barrel. These people just cant fight back (Gross &

    Miller, 2007). He contrasted interviews with people who deserve it, such as

    people of intolerance, including neo-Nazis (Gross & Miller, 2007). Similarly,satirical columnist Molly Ivins wrote, Satire has historically been the weapon of

    powerless people aimed at the powerful. When you use satire against powerlesspeople it is like kicking a cripple (Krugman, 2007).

    Stephen Colbert publicly discussed his own tests for determining whether

    to include material targeting ordinary people. He emphasized respect for and

    culpability of participants, classic deontological concerns. Colbert regularly con-

    tributed a religious news segment to The Daily Showtitled This Week in God.

    When deciding what to include in the segment he would consider, Does [thematerial] disrespect the concept of their belief? Another of his tests is not

    making a joke more important than being humane. This means, for example,

    not talking about tragedy or not questioning someones dearly held [religious]

    beliefs (Gross & Miller, 2005). But if they are : : : using religion as a tool in

    ways that are hypocritical or destructive, he said, then its fair game (Gross& Miller, 2005).

    The approaches of these satirists appear to be deontological: Carell and

    Ivins emphasize not targeting the vulnerable who are not culpable; Carell and

    Colbert aim to call attention to, and perhaps even punish, hypocrites and other

    wrongdoers; Colbert also aims to respect peoples dignity, or at least not disre-

    spect it. Carell and Colberts justifications for targeting some individuals andnot others are consistent with the test outlined here requiring consideration

    of public interest, though they emphasize deontological concerns: innocence

    versus culpability, and respect for the participant. In the test proposed here,

    portrayals can be justified even if the participant is not somehow culpable. For

    example, in the case of Borat, the New York pedestrian is unfriendly, perhapseven rude, but what justifies including footage of him is the public interest

    served (i.e., is the illustration of Americans wariness of unusual strangers)rather than his blameworthiness (Lemerond v. Twentieth Century Fox, 2008). In

    the proposed test, portraying vulnerable people like the mentally ill cannot be

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    13/19

    ETHICAL LEARNINGS FROM BORAT ON INFORMED CONSENT 33

    justified because their delusions cannot be considered matters of public interest,

    and mocking them may be emotionally harmful. This test does not address

    respect for participants, their exploitation, or their culpability, but such portrayals

    are deemed objectionable because they serve no public interest. In formulating

    the test, it is acknowledged that those who make works in this genre have already

    stepped outside the normal web of obligations by deceiving their participants;evaluating their actions based on duties such as respecting their subjects seems

    somewhat contradictory.

    For producers, a temptation may be to use deception merely to entertain,

    create buzz, and attract audiences, just as journalists have sometimes been

    accused of doing with undercover reporting (Smith, 2003). This test requiresmore careful consideration of consequences when potential harm is involved.

    While acknowledging that the test outlined here is necessarily somewhat vague

    and that reasonable people might reach different conclusions when applying it,it is preferred to having no standard at all.

    Applying the Test to Borat

    Can Cohens deception, on which his satire relies, serve a public interest that

    overrides harm to participants? The issues that Cohens work raises about prej-

    udice are almost undeniably of public interest from an ethical standpoint, as

    Cohen asserted in an interview. I think part of the movie shows the absurdity

    of holding any form of racial prejudice, whether its hatred of African-Americansor of Jews, he said. He also added,

    Boratessentially works as a tool. By himself being anti-Semitic, he lets peoplelower their guard and expose their own prejudice, whether its anti-Semitism or an

    acceptance of anti-Semitism. Throw the Jew Down the Well [a song performed at

    a country & western bar duringDa Ali G Show, where the audience spontaneously

    sang along] was a very controversial sketch, and some members of the Jewish

    community thought that it was actually going to encourage anti-Semitism. But to

    me it revealed something about that bar in Tucson: : : : And the question is: Did it

    reveal that they were anti-Semitic? Perhaps. But maybe it just revealed that they

    were indifferent to anti-Semitism. (Strauss, 2006)

    Borat also targeted xenophobia, provincial attitudes, prejudices, and naivet of

    ordinary people about foreigners. Simply put, participants who treat a character

    like Borat as real demonstrate their lack of worldliness. While facing the Kazakh

    governments criticism forBorat, Cohen argued, The joke is not on Kazakhstan.

    I think the joke is on people who can believe that the Kazakhstan that I describecan existwho believe that theres a country where homosexuals wear blue

    hats and the women live in cages and they drink fermented horse urine and the

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    14/19

    34 CENITE

    age of consent has been raised to nine years old (Strauss, 2006). The Rolling

    Stonewriter essentially agreed, saying those jokes and all the rest about beating

    gypsies, throwing Jews down wells, exporting pubic hair and making monkey

    porn are clearly parody but the homophobia, xenophobia, racism, classism,

    and anti-Semitism Borat encounters are all too real (Strauss, 2006).

    Even if one accepts that Cohens ends could justify his means, one mightcounter that Borat reveals nothing new. We knew there was prejudice and

    ignorance in America and the United Kingdom before Ali G, Borat, and Bruno

    showcased them. Furthermore, Cohens three characters cover much of the same

    territory. At best, it seems that Cohen is calling attention to prejudice rather

    than revealing unfamiliar prejudices. But there is potential value in renewingawareness of prejudices, and viewing their latest incarnations. Any public interest

    value must be considered alongside consequences to participants, not just work-

    by-work, but scene-by-scene within a work. Different scenes with differentparticipants and locations can have different rationales and effects.

    The following analysis of scenes from Boratis necessarily limited in beingbased only on the film itself, media coverage, and allegations of participants who

    complained or filed suit. These are serious limitations because, as the analysis

    shows, the film can be an incomplete or misleading record of actual events and

    their sequence.

    In Borat, the Romanian villagers poor rural lifestyle, no doubt chosen for

    its backwardness, is held up for ridicule and used to suggest that it couldproduce a boor like Borat but not to make any larger point. Although few in the

    audience would believe that those portrayed included an abortionist, a rapist, or

    a prostitute, all that is gained is a laugh at the expense of the participants. One

    might think that no harm was done, but some participants attested otherwise;

    the portrayals caused emotional harm (Kole, 2006). On balance, including thescenes is not justifiable because harm is inflicted and no public interest is served.

    Moreover, similar scenes could probably have been constructed with actors or

    the informed consent of some participants. According to press reports, at least

    some participants enjoyed participating in the film even after they knew the type

    of film they were involved in (Kole, 2006).

    In the fraternity brothers case, an overriding public interest is arguablyserved, demonstrating casual racism and sexism, matters of deep public interest.

    At least in the way the scene is constructed, their offensive words appear to

    be spoken with little provocation. Though the brothers alleged that they were

    encouraged to drink, they did not appear to be too incapacitated to be legally

    bound by contract, a high standard to meet (Farnsworth, 1990). A questionin all such cases is the representativeness of the participants; their attitudes

    and actions matter less if they are unique, more if they represent even a smallminority. If exceptional efforts were made to find people with unusual attitudes,

    the case for using the footage is weaker. Regarding this scenario, we are in a

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    15/19

    ETHICAL LEARNINGS FROM BORAT ON INFORMED CONSENT 35

    poor position to draw conclusions because Cohens teams are nontransparent

    about their methods, in part for legal reasons. The fraternity boys are likely to

    suffer embarrassment as a result of the film, and they may even lose job offers,

    but such consequences are justifiable given the attention the film brings to their

    aggressively hateful words.

    A similar analysis applies to scenes at a rodeo and a gun shop. In Salem,Virginia, a rodeo manager, who is named, tells Borat that his moustache makes

    him look like a terrorist, and says, I see a lot of people and think: : : doggone

    Muslim, I wonder what kind of bomb hes got strapped to him. When Borat

    mentions that in Kazakhstan homosexuals are hanged, the manager says, Thats

    what were trying to get done here. Again, an overriding public interest isarguably served by documenting casual and freely offered prejudice. In the

    scene in which the gun shop owner readily responds to Borats question about

    the best gun to defend against a Jew with a recommendation of a 9 mm or a.45, his coolness can be interpreted as indifference to anti-Semitism and to how

    a gun he sells might be used. Foreseeable harms to either of these participantsare speculative and outweighed by bringing a mass audiences attention to their

    responses to Borat.

    Whether an overriding public interest is served can be difficult to assess

    because of the manipulations possible in video production. Film critics have

    interpreted the scene at the dinner party as indicative of racism (Streit v. Twen-

    tieth Century Fox, 2008). The gullible guests patiently endure a lot, but drawthe line when the uninvited, scantily clad African American woman arrives. The

    scene appears to be constructed to suggest the guests racism. Long before the

    African American prostitute arrives, an establishing shot shows a street sign,

    Secession Drive, presumably where the party takes place. The dinner guests

    judicial complaint states that Secession Drive is not where the dinner was heldand they do not know where that street is located (Streit v. Twentieth Century

    Fox, 2008). Indeed, the address of the hall where the filming reportedly took

    place is different (Marchese & Paskin, 2006). The reaction to the uninvited

    guest may not be because of prejudice as much as her timing in the evenings

    sequence of events. The complainants also assert that they apologized to the

    prostitute when she arrived, not knowing she was a professional actress whowas part of the ruse. The apology, however, was not included in the film ( Streit

    v. Twentieth Century Fox, 2008). If the Secession Drive footage was from

    somewhere else and the apology was omitted, such manipulation helps miscast

    the participants and deceive the audience. Editing suggests the dinner guests

    acted from prejudiced motives that, according to their account, they did not.This allusion to racism could cause reputational harm to them. Demonstrating

    racism could redeem the scene, but manipulative editing to suggest prejudicefor which there is no evidence serves no public interest. Therefore, the scene is

    not justifiable.

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    16/19

    36 CENITE

    In the scene in which Borat feigns a born-again experience, it seems excep-

    tionally unlikely that any reasonable viewer would regard the plaintiff as making

    fun of her own religion when shown raising her hands, despite that her claim

    for false light portrayal on that basis survived a motion to dismiss (Johnston

    v. One America Productions, 2007a). Nonetheless, was it ethical to film the

    frenzied activities of charismatic Christians after telling them that filming wasfor a religious documentary? In addition, was it justifiable to waste their time

    and excite their emotions with Borats false conversion? The case is easier than it

    might be in a church, because the event was a public meeting. Also, a Mississippi

    congressman and the chief justice of the state Supreme Court spoke. The latter

    said, Were a Christian nation. Such appearances make what transpired at themeeting more an issue of public interest than it might otherwise be, enough

    to make the scene justifiable, especially given the unlikelihood of harm to the

    unnamed participants. A public interest arguably outweighs any harm from anapparently accurate portrayal.

    Some scenes in Boratdo not appear to present serious ethical issues. Suchscenes show reactions of participants surprised by silly situations, reminiscent

    ofCandid Camera. No public interest is served, but the harm suffered from

    being depicted in a harmless way (i.e., as a bit credulous and overly polite

    person) is also absent. Because they touch on social issues, some scenes may

    appear to involve public interest when actually they are just silly and harmless.

    A feminist artist complained about the scene in which she and two other womenof a feminist group discussed feminism with Borat. Regarding Borats comment

    that women have smaller brains, she observed,

    [W]hat exactly is he trying to unmask when he ridicules women? Borat could cause

    a sensation by pressing his small brain commentary on people like Lawrence

    Summers, the former president of Harvard who resigned after saying that women

    cant be scientists. Instead, for the sake of a cheap laugh, he chooses to reinforce

    the stereotype of women as the inferior sex, at the expense of women. How funny

    is that? (Stein, 2006)

    One might respond in two ways. First, the feminists appear to be targeted only in

    the way that many ideological purists are targeted onDa Ali G Show. Cohen uses

    a standard, reliable comedic strategy, forcing interaction between irreconcilablecharacters for comedic effect. He confronts a group of passionate feminists

    with their worst nightmare: an aggressively clueless adversary played by Borat,

    a ridiculous misogynist. Cohens characters also have vexed and provoked an

    animal rights activist, a Christian rocker, and a neo-Nazi, among many others, of

    all ideological stripes. Second, it seems a stretch to say that Borat is reinforcing

    stereotypes of female inequality. His comments that in Kazakhstan more than fivewomen can only legally be together in a brothel or a grave, and his question about

    whether women should be educated despite their smaller brains, are too absurd

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    17/19

    ETHICAL LEARNINGS FROM BORAT ON INFORMED CONSENT 37

    to have bite in contemporary debates about womens equality. The feminists

    are not humiliated; they remained in control of the situation and ended the

    interview. The joke appears to be mostly the situation itself. Though feminism

    is potentially fraught with controversy, no public interest is served, and no

    harm is done, making the scene acceptable. Another interpretation of the scene

    may be that Borats own sexism, rather than feminism, could be viewed as thetarget. This interpretation was considered by the artist when she analyzed Borats

    statement about womens smaller brains: You could argue that his statement

    is so ridiculous that the very utterance of it proves the reverse, and therefore

    is an unmasking of his characters small mindedness (Stein, 2006). In this

    interpretation, the scene would serve the public interest while causing little, ifany, harm to participants.

    It may be difficult, though probably not impossible, to probe the hearts of

    the victims of Borats satire without deception, but Boratexplores some issuesin a novel way that, when interspersed with purely entertaining scenes with no

    larger point, reached millions of viewers worldwide. On balance, scenes inBoratcan generally be justified in a utilitarian analysis, except the Romanian

    villagers case. Likewise, the dining society scene strains too hard to give an

    interpretation that may be inaccurate, and thus serves no public interest.

    CONCLUSION

    Even though theBoratteam brilliantlycovered their legal bases through carefully

    chosen words and the releases that participants signed, ethical issues associated

    with deception remain. The test proposed in this article allows a scene-by-scene

    evaluation of the work, building on principles from documentary, journalism,entertainment ethics, and privacy law. In many scenes, Borat appears to pass

    the test, but in others it does not. What should the consequences be if a work

    fails to meet the ethical standards outlined here? Industry organizations such

    as the Motion Picture Association of America, which administers its voluntary

    ratings system, could extend their reach into formulating ethics codes. In lieu

    of that, the informal sanctions of criticism, and perhaps the greater pressures ofinvestors, studios, and audiences, will have to suffice.

    REFERENCES

    Academy of Motion Picture Arts & Sciences. (n.d.). 79th Academy Awards. Retrieved July 30, 2008,

    from http://www.oscars.org/79academyawards/nomswins.htmlAnderson, C., & Benson, T. W. (1988). Direct cinema and the myth of informed consent: The case

    ofTiticut Follies. In L. Gross, J. S. Katz, & J. Ruby (Eds.), Image ethics: The moral rights of

    subjects in photographs, film, and television (pp. 5890). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    18/19

    38 CENITE

    Another of AshtonsPunkdpranks goes wrong. (2004, May 8). World Entertainment News Network.

    Retrieved June 20, 2008, from http://factivia.com

    Barkham, P. (2006, November 24). The Borat backlash. The Guardian, p. 10.

    Black, J., Steele, B., & Barney, R. (1999). Doing ethics in journalism. Boston: Allyn & Bacon.

    Bok, S. (1978). Lying: Moral choice in public and private life. New York: Vintage.

    Cantrell v. Forest City Publishing, 419 U.S. 245 (1974).

    Christians, C. G., Fackler, M., Rotzoll, K. B., & McKee, K. B. (2001). Media ethics: Cases and

    moral reasoning. New York: Longman.

    Dehn, F. X. (2005). Reality TV and the new reality of media law. Delaware Lawyer, 23, 1418.

    Diaz v. Oakland Tribune, 139 Cal. App. 3d 118 (1983).

    Doe v. One America Productions, No. SC091723 (L.A. County Super. Ct., 2006).

    Ex parte Sacha Baron Cohen et al. (In re: Kathie Martin v. Sacha Baron Cohen et al.). Ala. LEXIS

    10 (Alabama, 2008).

    Farnsworth, A. E. (1990). Farnsworth on contracts (2nd. ed.). Boston: Little, Brown & Co.

    Fletcher, H. (2006, October 29). Drink up. Its not like you have lines to learn. New York Times,

    Section 2, p. 32.

    Goldstein, P. (2008). Bill Maher hates your (fill in the blank) religion. Los Angeles Times. RetrievedNov. 13, 2008, from http://latimesblogs.latimes.com/the_big_picture/2008/08/bill-maher-hate.html

    Gross, T., & Miller, D. (2007, October 24). Fresh air from WHYY. Philadelphia: WHYY. Retrieved

    July 12, 2008, from http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyIdD91471205&ftD1&fD

    13

    Gross, T., & Miller, D. (2005, January 24). A fake newsmans fake newsman: Stephen Col-

    bert (radio broadcast). Philadelphia: Fresh Air from WHYY. Retrieved July 12, 2008, from

    http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyIdD4464017

    Gross, L., Katz, J. S., and Ruby, J. (1988). Introduction: A moral pause. In L. Gross, J. S. Katz,

    & J. Ruby (Eds.), Image ethics: The moral rights of subjects in photographs, film, and television

    (pp. 333). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Hitchens C. (2004, June 21). Unfairenheit 9/11: The lies of Michael Moore. Slate. Retrieved Nov.

    13, 2008, from http://slate.com/id/2102723

    Johnston v. One America Productions, 2007 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 62029 (N.D. Miss., 2007a).

    Johnston v. One America Productions, 2007 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 73450 (N.D. Miss., 2007b).

    Kant, I. (1998). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. (M. Gregor, Trans.). Cambridge: Cam-bridge University Press. (Original work published 1785).

    Kole W. J. (2006, November 15). Now Romanians say Borat misled them. Associated Press.

    Retrieved July 12, 2008, http://factivia.com

    Krugman, P. (2007, February 2). Missing Molly Ivins. New York Times, Section A, p. 19.

    LaPorte, N. (2006, December 6). Court wants more on Borat. Daily Variety, p. 5.

    Lemerond v. Twentieth Century Fox, 2008 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 26947 (S.D. N.Y., 2008).

    Martinson, D. L. (1995). Ethical public relations practitioners must not ignore public interest.

    Journal o f Mass Media Ethics, 10, 210222.

    Mill, J. S. (2001). Utilitarianism (2nd ed.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing. (Original work

    published 1863).

    Nichols, B. (2001). Introduction to documentary. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Patterson, P., & Wilkins, L. (2005). Media ethics: Issues & cases (5th ed.). New York: McGraw

    Hill.

    Pryluck, C. (2005). Ultimately we are all outsiders: The ethics of documentary filming. In A. Rosen-

    thal & J. Corner (Eds.), New challenges for documentary (2nd ed.) (pp. 194219). Manchester

    and New York: Manchester University Press.

    Ryan, T. (2004, December 18). Reality film. The Age. Retrieved June 17, 2008, from http://www.

    theage.com.au/news/Film/Reality-film/2004/12/17/1102787257543.html

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010

  • 5/25/2018 04+Cenite%2C+Borat+informed+consent+2009

    19/19

    ETHICAL LEARNINGS FROM BORAT ON INFORMED CONSENT 39

    Smith, R. F. (2003). Groping for ethics in journalism (5th ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    San Francisco Chronicle. (1996). Ethical news gathering.Retrieved June 17, 2008, from www.media-

    accountability.org/library/USA_SF_Chronicle.doc

    Society of Professional Journalists. (1996). Code of ethics. Retrieved June 17, 2008, from http://www.

    spj.org/ethicscode.asp

    Standard consent agreement (n.d.). Retrieved June 20, 2008, from http://www.tmz.com/2006/11/09/

    borat-lawsuit-high-five

    Strauss, N. (2006, November 14). The man behind the mustache. Rolling Stone. Retrieved July

    30, 2008, from http://www.rollingstone.com/news/coverstory/sacha_baron_cohen_the_real_borat_

    finally_speaks

    Time v. Hill, 385 U.S. 374 (1967).

    Stein, L. (2006). How I was duped by Ali G. Downtown Express 19(22). Retrieved June 23, 2008,

    from http://www.downtownexpress.com/de_179/howiwasduped.html

    Streit v. Twentieth Century Fox, No. CV-07-J-1918-S (N.D. Alabama, 2008).

    Winston, B. (1988). The tradition of the victim in Griersonian documentary. In A. Rosenthal (Ed.),

    New challenges for documentary (pp. 269287). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Winters v. New York, 333 U.S. 507 (1948).

    Downl

    oad

    ed

    By:[

    Pontifi

    ci

    a

    Uni

    versid

    ad

    Catli

    cad

    e

    Chil

    e]

    At:15

    :097

    Jul

    y2010