the period of transition by jehan van den hoven

Upload: umut-atmaca

Post on 24-Feb-2018

221 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    1/61

    PROBLEMS OF THE PERIOD OF TRANSITION

    Jehan van den Hoven

    Published in the magazine Bilan no 28, 31, 34, 35, 37, 38

    Part I

    The title of this study should not lead anyone to the conclusion that we're going to startpeering into the mists of the future or sketching out a solution to the many and complex tasks

    which will confront the proletariat when it has become the ruling class. Such a project wouldnot be in accordance with the whole framework and spirit of Bilan. We will leave it to the

    "technicians" and the recipe-mongers or to the self-proclaimed "orthodox" marxists to indulge

    in such anticipations, to stroll down the byways of utopia, or to offer the workers formulaewhich have been emptied of any class content.

    For us it can never be a question of inventing panaceas which are valid once and for all andwhich can be adapted to any historic situation. Marxism is an experimental method and not a

    game of guesses and forecasts. It has its roots in a historic reality, which is a moving,

    contradictory, process; it is nourished by past experience, tempered and corrected by the

    present, so that it can be enriched by further experience to come.

    By synthesising the events of history, marxism has shown the true meaning of the state, laid

    bare of all idealist prejudices; it has developed the theory of the dictatorship of the proletariat

    and affirmed the necessity of the transitional proletarian state. But although it is possible to

    define the class content of such a state, we are as yet still limited to a mere outline of its social

    forms. It has still not been possible to situate the principles for running a proletarian state on a

    solid basis, or to clearly draw the lines of demarcation between party and state. Thisimmaturity inevitably weighed heavily on the character and evolution of the Soviet State.

    But it is precisely the task of those marxists who have survived the shipwreck of the workers'

    movement to forge the theoretical weapons which will make the future proletarian state an

    instrument of the world revolution and not a cog in the wheels of world capitalism.

    This contribution to that theoretical task will examine:

    a) the historic conditions in which the proletarian revolution arises;

    b) the necessity of the proletarian state;

    c) the social and economic categories which will inevitably survive in the transitional period;

    d) finally, certain requirements for a proletarian management of the transitional state.

    The historical context of the proletarian revolution

    It became axiomatic to say that capitalist society, overflowing with a productive capacity

    which it can longer make full use of, drowning in a flood of commodities which it can't sell,

    has become a historic anachronism. From this it is but a short step to conclude that thedisappearance of capitalism must open up the reign of abundance.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    2/61

    In reality, capitalist accumulation has reached the extreme limits of its progressive evolution

    and the capitalist mode of production is nothing but a fetter on historical progress. This

    doesn't mean that capitalism is like a ripe fruit which the proletariat simply has to pluck in

    order to find true happiness; it simply means that the material conditions exist for constructing

    the base (and only the base) of socialism, for preparing the ground for a communist society.

    Marx said that: "The very moment civilisation begins, production begins to be founded on the

    antagonism of orders, estates, classes, and finally on the antagonism of accumulated labour

    and actual labour. No antagonism, no progress. This is the law that civilisation has followed

    up to our days. Till now the productive forces have been developed by virtue of this system ofclass antagonism".2 In his Anti-Duhring Engels asserted that the existence of a society

    divided into classes: "was the necessary consequence of the deficient and restricted

    development of production in former times" and from this he deduced that "if, upon thisshowing, division into classes has a certain historical justification, it has this only for a given

    period, only under given social conditions. It was based upon the insufficiency of production.It will be swept away by the complete development of modern productive forces". 3

    It is clear that the final stage of capitalist development does not correspond to "the complete

    development of modern productive forces" in the sense that all human needs can now be

    satisfied. But what we do have today is a situation in which the persistence of class

    antagonism not only stands in the way of any social development, but actually leads to the

    regression of society.

    This is what Engels was getting at when he said that the: "abolition of

    classes...presupposes...the development of production carried out to a degree at which

    appropriation of the means of pro-

    duction and of the products, and, with this, of political domination, of the monopoly of

    culture, and of intellectual leadership by a particular class of society, has become not only

    superfluous, but economically, politically, intellectually a hindrance to development".4And,

    when he added that capitalist society had reached this state and that we now had: " the

    possibility of securing for every member of society, by means of socialised production, an

    existence not only sufficient materially, and becoming day by day more full, but an existence

    guaranteeing to all the free development and exercise of their physical and mental faculties"there can be no doubt that he was envisaging the possibility of moving towards the full

    satisfaction of needs and not saying that we already had the material means for immediately

    achieving this.

    As Engels said, the liberation of the productive forces: "is the one precondition for an

    unbroken, constantly accelerating development of the productive forces, and therewith for a

    practically unlimited increase of production itself".5 Consequently the period of transition

    (which can only unfold on a world scale and not within one state) is a political and economic

    phase which will inevitably be characterised by the inability of production to satisfy all

    individual needs, even when we take into account the prodigious levels which the productivity

    of labour has already achieved. The suppression of capitalist relations of production and of

    their antagonistic expression makes it possible to immediately begin providing for essentialhuman needs (if we leave out the necessities of the class struggle which could temporarily

    reduce the level of production).

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    3/61

    To go beyond this requires an incessant development of the productive forces. The realisation

    of the formula "to each according to their needs" will come at the end of a long process,

    which will go forwards not in a straight line but through a winding course of contradictions

    and conflicts, and in conjunction with the world-wide development of the class struggle.

    The historic mission of the proletariat is, as Engels said, to lead humanity "from the kingdomof necessity to the kingdom of freedom"; but the proletariat can only carry out this mission if it

    analyses the nature and limits of the historic conditions in which this act of liberation takes

    place, and applies this analysis to the whole of its political and economic activity. The

    proletariat cannot abstractly pose socialism against capitalism, as though they were twoentirely independent epochs, as though socialism was not the historic prolongation of

    capitalism and fatally scarred by it, but something clean and new which springs form the

    virgin womb of the proletarian revolution.

    It wasn't because of indifference or negligence that the founders of marxism didn't go into the

    details of the period of transition. But Marx and Engels were the antithesis, the living

    negation, of the utopians. They didn't try to construct abstract schema, to imagine thingswhich could only be resolved scientifically.

    And in 1918, Rosa Luxemburg, who made an immense theoretical contribution to marxism,

    still felt it necessary to point out that: "For from being a sum of ready made prescriptions

    which only have to be applied, the practical realisation of socialism as an economic, social

    and juridical system is something which lies completely hidden in the mists of the

    future...(socialism) has as its prerequisite a number of measures of force against property,

    etc. The negative, the tearing down, can be decreed; the building up, the positive, cannot".6

    In his preface to CapitalMarx had already indicated that: "When a society has discovered the

    natural laws which regulate it own movement (and the final purpose of my book is to reveal

    the economic laws of motion of modern society), it can neither overleap the natural phases of

    evolution, nor shuffle them out of the world by decrees. But this much, at least, it can do; it

    can shorten and lesson the birth pangs."

    A policy of proletarian management, therefore, can only envisage the general tendenciesand

    orientation of economic development, while historic experience (of which the Russian

    revolution is a gigantic though incomplete example) can provide the proletariat with an

    understanding of the social forms suitable for the implementation of its economic programme.This programme will only have a socialistcontent if it follows a way which is diametrically

    opposed to capitalism - if it aims at a constant and progressive elevation of the livingconditions of the masses, and not at holding them down or lowering them.

    ***

    If we want to understand the revolution not as an isolated phenomenon but as a product of anhistorical development, we must relate it to the fundamental laws of history - to the dialectical

    movement generated by the class struggle, which is the living substance of historical events.

    Marxism teaches us that the causes of revolutions are not to be found in philoso-

    phy, but in the economy of a given society. The gradual changes that occur in the mode ofproduction and exchange, spurred on by the class struggle, inevitably culminate in a

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    4/61

    revolutionary "catastrophe" which tears through the envelope of the existing social and

    productive relations.

    In this respect the 20th century is for capitalist society what the 18th and 19th centuries were

    for feudal society - an epoch of violent revolutionary convulsions engulfing the whole of

    society.

    In the epoch of bourgeois decadence, then, proletarian revolutions are the product of the

    historical maturity of society as a whole, links in a chain of events which, as history since

    1914 has shown, can easily alternate with defeats of the proletariat and wars.

    The victory of one proletariat, although the immediate result of particular circumstances, is

    definitely part of a whole: the world revolution. For this reason there can be no question of

    assigning an autonomous development to this revolution because of any social or

    geographical peculiarities.

    Here we come up against the problem underlying the theoretical controversy which ledRussian centrism (and subsequently the Communist International) to put forward the theory of

    "socialism in one country". We are referring to the interpretation of the unequal development

    which has been a constant factor in historical evolution.

    Marx observed that economic life was in some ways analogous to biological processes. Once

    life has transcended a given period of development and gone from one stage to the next, it

    begins to obey other laws, even though it is still dependent on the fundamental laws which

    regulate all manifestations of life.

    It's the same for each historical period, which has its own laws, even though history as a

    whole is regulated by the laws of dialectical evolution. For example, Marx denied that the lawof population was the same in all times and all places. Each stage of development has its own

    particular law of population and Marx pointed this out when refuting the theory of Malthus.

    In Capital, in which he dissected the mechanisms of the capitalist system, Marx didn't dwell

    on the many uneven aspects of its expansion, because for him: "What we are concerned withprimarily is, not the higher or lower degree of development of the social antagonisms which

    arise out of the natural laws of capitalist production, but these laws in themselves, the

    tendencies which work out with an iron necessity towards an inevitable goal. A country in

    which industrial development is more advanced than in other simply presents those others

    with a picture of their own future".7From this passage we can see clearly that what has to beconsidered as the fundamental element is not the uneven development of the different

    countries which make up the capitalist system - as though there was some kind of law

    ensuring the historical necessity of uneven development - but rather the specific laws of

    capitalist production, which regulate the whole of society and which are themselves

    subordinated to the general laws of dialectical evolution.

    The geographical milieu explains why the historical evolution and the specific laws of asociety manifest themselves in varied and uneven forms of development, but it cannot explain

    the historical processitself. In other words, the geographical milieu is not the activefactor in

    history.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    5/61

    Marx pointed out that while capitalist production is favoured by a moderate climate, this is

    merely a potential factor which can only be made use of in historical conditions which are

    independent of geographical conditions. "It by no means follows that the most fruitful soil is

    the most fitted for the growth of the capitalist mode of production. This mode is based on the

    dominion of man over Nature...It is not the tropics with their luxuriant vegetation, but the

    temperate zone, that is the mother country of capital. It is not the mere fertility of the soil butthe differentiation of the soil, the variety of its natural products, the changes of the seasons,

    which form the physical basis for the social division of labour, and which, by changes in thenatural surroundings, spur man on to the multiplication of his wants, his capacities, his

    means and modes of labour".8

    The geographical milieu is thus not the primordial element which determines the way

    different countries will develop. If we locate this development in the sphere of geographical

    conditions, and not in the context of the general historical laws of a whole epoch, then we

    would have to come to the conclusion that each country has developed in an autonomousmanner, independent of any historical context.

    But history has only unfolded because of the intervention of men acting (with the exception of

    primitive communism) within a framework of antagonistic social relations, which have varied

    according to the historical epoch and which have imposed a particular form on the class

    struggle: slave against master, serf against landlord, bourgeois against feudal lord, proletariat

    against bourgeois.

    Obviously this doesn't mean that various pre-capitalist social formations - Asiatic, slave,

    feudal - always succeed each other in a mechanical way and that their specific laws have a

    universal validity. Such a pattern of evolution was ruled out by the fact that these social

    formations were all based on modes of production which by nature were very progressive.

    Each of these societies was unable to expand beyond a certain geographical radius (e.g. the

    Mediterranean basin in classical antiquity), while outside this radius other modes of

    production could exist, in a more or less evolved manner, and under the influence of various

    factors, of which the geographical factor was not the most essential.

    But, with the arrival of capitalism, the whole course of history broadens out. Although

    capitalism inherited a historic situation characterised by considerable differences in

    development, it did not take it long to overcome these differences.

    Dominated by the need to accumulate surplus value, capitalism appeared on the historicalarena as the most powerful and progressive mode of production ever seen, the most expansive

    of all economic systems. But although it was characterised by a tendency to universalise its

    mode of production and although it partially succeeded in creating a world in its own image, it

    never completely destroyed all previous social formations. Rather it annexed them, sucked

    them dry, or pushed them aside.

    We have already expressed our opinion (see "Crises and cycles") on the perspective of the

    advent of a pure and balanced capitalist society, which Marx is supposed to have put forward;

    we don't want to go back over this here, since the facts of history have eloquently refuted not

    Marx's pseudo-predictions, but the hypotheses of those who have used it to reinforce

    bourgeois ideology. We know that capitalism entered into its epoch of decomposition beforebeing able to complete its historic mission because its internal contradictions developed faster

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    6/61

    than the system could expand. But capitalism was still the first system of production to give

    rise to a world economy, which is characterised not by homogeneity and balance, which

    would in any case be contrary to its nature, but by a strict interdependenceof all its parts. It is

    this which, in the final analysis, subjugates the whole world to the laws of capital and to the

    yoke of the imperialist bourgeoisie.

    The development of capitalist society, spurred on by competition, has produced this complex

    and remarkable worldwide division of labour which can and must be perfected and purified

    (this is the task of the proletariat) but which cannot be destroyed. It is not called into question

    at all by the phenomenon of economic nationalism, which, with the general crisis ofcapitalism, appears as a reactionary manifestation of the exacerbated contradiction between

    the universal character of the capitalist economy and this division into antagonist national

    states. In fact, this is further confirmed by the stifling atmosphere created by the existence of

    what might be called obsidian economies. Under the cover of an almost hermetically sealed

    protectionism, we are seeing a prolific growth of industries built up on the basis of enormouswaste expenditure, the development of war economies which exact a heavy tribute from the

    living conditions of the masses. These are economically unviable, parasitic growths whichwill be eliminated in a socialist society.

    A socialist society is obviously inconceivable without this global division of labour.

    The interdependence and reciprocal subordination of the various spheres of production (which

    is today confined within the framework of bourgeois nations) is a historic necessity, and

    capitalism has taken this to the highest possible level, both from the economic and political

    point of view. The fact that, once this social structure appears on a world scale, it is shaken by

    a thousand contradictory forces, does not mean that it doesn't exist on this scale. It is based on

    a distribution of the productive forces and of natural resources which is the product of thewhole historical development. It is not at all dependent on the desire of imperialist capitalism

    to counter-act the strict interdependence of all the regions of the world by retreating behindnational frontiers. If capitalism is attempting this mad project today, it is because it is being

    driven by its own contradictions, but it can only do this by destroying the riches which

    concretise the surplus value produced by generations of workers, by precipitating a gigantic

    destruction of the productive forces into the holocaust of imperialist war.

    The international proletariat cannot afford to ignore the laws of historical evolution. Once a

    section of the proletariat has made its revolution, the price of the theory of "socialism in one

    country" is the abandonment of the worldwide class struggle, and thus the defeat of that

    revolution.

    ***

    The idea that uneven development is a historical law giving rise to the necessity of

    autonomous national development is a denial of the concept of society as a worldwide

    phenomenon.

    As we have shown, uneven economic and political development, far from being an "absolute

    law of capitalism",9 is simply a sum of phenomena determined by the specific laws of the

    bourgeois system of production.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    7/61

    In its period of expansion, capitalism, through a tortuous and contradictory process, tendedto

    even out inequalities of development, whereas now, in its regressive phase, the necessities of

    its evolution have led to a deepening of these inequalities: the advanced capitalisms suck the

    backward countries dry and destroy any possibility of their development.

    The Communist International sees this retrograde and parasitical development, and concludesthat "uneven development is augmented and accentuated even further in the imperialist

    epoch"; it thus puts forward its theory of "national socialism", by pointing out the

    impossibility of a world proletarian revolution as asimultaneousact, and confusing national

    socialism and a revolution which breaks out in a national framework.

    In order to back up these arguments, it elaborates on certain of Lenin's writings, notably his

    article of 1915 "On the Slogan for the United States of Europe" (Against the Stream) where he

    said that "Uneven economic and political development is an unconditional law of capitalism.

    Hence it follows that the triumph of socialism is to begin with possible in a few, or even asingle capitalist country."10

    Trotsky has dealt quite adequately with these falsifications in The Third International After

    Leninand we don't need to refute them again here.

    But all the same, Trotsky, seeking to follow Marx and Lenin, thinks that it is possible to use

    the "law" of uneven development - which he also makes into an absolutelaw of capitalism -

    to explain both the inevitability of the revolution assuming a national form and also why it

    should first break out in the backward countries: "The uneven, sporadic development ofcapitalism gives the socialist revolution an uneven and sporadic character, but the advanced

    degree of mutual interdependence between all countries means that it is both politically and

    economically impossible to build socialism in one country"11and again that: "the prediction

    that Russia, a historically backward country, could undergo a proletarian revolution before

    an advanced country like England, was based entirely on the law of uneven development."

    First of all, although Marx recognised the necessity of national revolutions, he never invoked

    a law of uneven development, and he always made it clear that the necessity for national

    revolutions derived from the fact that society was divided into capitalist nations, which was

    simply the corollary of the fact that it was divided into classes.

    The Communist Manifestosays that: "Since the proletariat must first of all acquire politicalsupremacy, must rise to be the leading class of the nation, must constitute itself thenation, it

    is, so far, national, though not in the bourgeois sense of the word."12In the Critique of theGotha ProgrammeMarx goes on say: "It is altogether self-evident that, to be able to fight at

    all, the working class must organise itself at home as a classand that its own country is the

    immediate arena of its struggle. In so far its class struggle is national, not in substance, but as

    the Communist Manifestosays in form'."13

    When the national struggle breaks out into a proletarian revolution, it shows that it is the

    product of the historical maturation of the social and economic contradictions of capitalist

    society as a whole. The dictatorship of the proletariat is a point of departure, not the final

    goal. It is an expression of the worldwide class struggle, and can only live by remaining part

    of that struggle. Only in the sense of this continuous revolutionary process can we talk about a

    "permanent" revolution.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    8/61

    Although Trotsky absolutely rejects the theory of "socialism in one country" and considers it

    to be reactionary, the fact that he bases his argument on the "law" of uneven development

    leads him to distort the significance of proletarian revolutions. This "law" is incorporated into

    his theory of permanent revolution which, according to him, consists of two basic theses: one

    based on a "correct" conception of the law of uneven development, the other on a precise

    understanding of the world economy.

    If, during the imperialist epoch the various expressions of uneven development are the result

    not of the specific laws of capitalism (whose effects are intensified by the general crisis of

    decomposition) but of a historical law of uneven development which has the character ofnecessity, it is impossible to understand why the effects of this law should limit themselves to

    national revolutions which begin in the backward countries. Why shouldn't they also permit

    the development of autonomous economies, i.e. of "national socialism"?

    By ascribing a preponderant importance to the geographical milieu (because this is what

    happens when you make uneven development into a law) rather than to the real historical

    factor - the class struggle - you are opening the door to a justification of a "socialism" basedon the physical possibilities of independent development. As far as Russia is concerned, this

    means opening the door to centrism.

    In vain Trotsky accuses Stalin of "making a fetish of the law of uneven development and

    declaring it as a sufficient condition for the build up of national socialism" because,

    beginning from the same theoretical premise, he must logically come to the same conclusions,

    unless he arbitrarily stops half way. Trotsky said of the Russian Revolution that: " it was the

    greatest of all expressions of the unevenness of historical development; the theory of the

    permanent revolution, which predicted the October cataclysm, was itself based on this law."

    The backwardness of Russia can to a certain extent be used to explain why the revolution had

    to jump over the bourgeois phase, although the essential reason for this was that it took place

    in a period when the national bourgeoisie was incapable of carrying out its historic tasks. But

    the real significance of this backwardness was expressed on the political level, because the

    historic impotence of the Russian bourgeoisie was accompanied by an organic weakness

    which was aggravated by the pressures of imperialist conflict. In the chaos of the imperialist

    war, Russia was revealed as the weak link in the imperialist chain. The world revolutionbegan in the place where conditions were favourable for the proletariat and the building of its

    class party.

    ***

    To conclude the first part of this study, we would like to look at the theory of countries being

    "ripe" or "unripe" for socialism, a theory which is especially favoured by the "evolutionary

    socialists" but which has found some echo in the thought of the communists of the opposition

    when it comes to defining the character of the Russian Revolution or seeking the origins of its

    degeneration.

    In his preface to the Critique of Political EconomyMarx summed up his position on what it

    meant to say that a phase of social revolution had arrived at a level of maturity: "No social

    formation is ever destroyed before all the productive forces for which it is sufficient have been

    developed, and new superior relations of production never replace older ones before thematerial conditions for their existence have matured within the framework of the old society.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    9/61

    Mankind thus inevitably sets itself only such tasks as it is able to solve, since closer

    examination will always show that the problem itself arises only when the material conditions

    for its solution are already present or at least in the course of formation."14This means that

    the condition of maturity will always have its repercussions on the whole society regulated by

    the dominant mode of production. Moreover, the notion of maturity can only have a relative,

    not an absolute, meaning. A society is "ripe" to the extent that its social structure and juridicalframework have become too narrow in relation to the material forces of production which it

    has developed.

    At the beginning of this study we underlined the fact that although capitalism has powerfullydeveloped the productive capacity of society, it has not succeeded in developing the

    conditions for an immediate passage to socialism. As Marx indicated, only the material

    conditions for resolving this problem exist "or are at least in the process of formation".

    These restrictions apply even more strongly to each national unit in the world economy. All ofthemare historically ripe for socialism, but noneof them are ripe in the sense of possessing all

    the material conditions needed for the building of an integral socialism. This is true whateverlevel of development they may have reached.

    No nation on its own contains all the elements for a socialist society. The idea of national

    socialism is in diametrical opposition to the international nature of the imperialist economy, to

    the universal division of labour, and the global antagonism between the bourgeoisie and the

    proletariat.

    It is a pure abstraction to see socialist society as a sum of complete socialist economies. The

    world-wide distribution of the productive forces (which is not an artificial product) makes it

    impossible both for the "advanced" countries and for the "backward" countries to complete

    the transition to socialism within their own borders. . The specific weight of each of the

    countries in the world economy is measured by the degree to which they are reciprocally

    dependent, not by how independent they might be. England, which is one of the most

    advanced sectors of capitalism, a country in which capitalism exists in an almost pure form,

    could not operate in isolation. Facts today show that, even when only partially cut off from

    the

    world market, the productive forces begin to break down. This is the case with the cotton and

    coal industries in England. In the U.S.A, the automobile industry can only go into decline if itis limited to the home market, no matter how vast the latter is. An isolated proletarian

    Germany would soon see its industrial apparatus breaking down, even if it initiated a hugeexpansion of consumption.

    It is thus an abstraction to pose the question of countries being "ripe" or "unripe" for

    socialism, because on these terms you would have to say that neither the advanced countries

    nor the backward countries were mature enough.

    The problem has to be posed in the light of the historical maturation of social antagonisms,

    which in turn results from the sharpening conflicts between the productive forces and the

    relations of production. To limit the question to the material factors at hand would be to take

    up the position of the theoreticians of the Second International, of Kautsky and the German

    Socialists, who considered that because Russia was a backward economy dominated by atechnically weak agrarian sector, it was not ripe for a proletarian revolution, but only for a

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    10/61

    bourgeois revolution. In this their conception was the same as that of the Russian Mensheviks.

    Otto Bauer declared that the proletarian state inevitably had to degenerate because of Russia's

    backwardness.

    In theRussian Revolution, Rosa Luxemburg remarked that, according to the conception of the

    social democrats, the Russian revolution ought to have stopped after the fall of the Tsarism."According to this view, if the revolution has gone beyond that point and has set as its task the

    dictatorship of the proletariat, this is simply a mistake of the radical wing of the Russian

    labour movement, the Bolsheviks. And all difficulties which the revolution has met with in its

    further course, and all disorders it has suffered, are pictured as purely a result of this fatefulerror."

    The question as to whether Russia was or was not ripe for the proletarian revolution can't be

    answered by looking at the material conditions of its economy, but at the balance of class

    forces, which had been dramatically transformed by the international situation. The essential

    condition was the existence of a concentrated proletariat - despite the fact that it was a tiny

    minority in relation to the huge mass of peasant producers - whose consciousness expresseditself through a class party powerfully armed with revolutionary ideology and experience. We

    agree with Rosa Luxemburg that: "The Russian proletariat has to be seen as the vanguard of

    the world proletariat, a vanguard whose movement is the expression of the development of

    social antagonisms on a world scale. What is happening in St Petersburg is the result of

    developments in Germany, England, and France. It is these developments which will decide

    the outcome of the Russian revolution, which can only achieve its goal if it is the prologue to

    the revolution of the European proletariat." Certain comrades of the communist opposition

    have however, based their appreciation of the Russian revolution on the criterion of economic

    "immaturity".

    In his study "Classes in Soviet Russia", comrade Hennaut takes up this position. In his

    interpretation of those statements of Engels which we looked at earlier, Hennaut sees them ashaving a particular significance which can be applied to a given country, rather than as

    referring to a whole social order that has reached the historic limitations of its development. If

    this were the case, Engels would obviously be contradicting what Marx said in his preface to

    the Critique of Political Economy. But as we shall see, this is not the case. According to

    Hennaut, it is the economic factor and not the political factor which is most important when

    we are trying to establish whether or not a proletarian revolution is possible. He says: "if we

    apply them to the present period of human history, these considerations (of Engels) can only

    mean that the seizure of power by the proletariat, the maintenance and use of this power for

    socialist ends, is only conceivable where capitalism has already cleared the path forsocialism, i.e. where it has given rise to a numerically strong proletariat which comprises, ifnot the majority, then a powerful minority of the population, and where it has created a

    developed industry which is able to stamp its seal on the further development of the whole

    economy." Further on, he stresses that: "In the final analysis it was the cultural and economic

    capacities of the country which determined the final outcome of the Russian revolution when

    it became clear that the proletariat outside Russia wasn't ready to make the revolution. The

    backward state of Russian society had to make all its negative sides felt." But perhaps

    comrade Hennaut might have added that, whether we like it or not, anyproletarian revolution

    that tries to draw its "legitimacy" from the material conditions in one country will be drawn

    irresistibly into the trap of "national socialism".

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    11/61

    We repeat that the fundamental condition for the life of the proletarian revolution is its ability

    to link up on a world scale, and this consideration must determine the internal and external

    policies of the proletarian state. This is because, although the revolution has to begin on a

    national scale, it cannot remain indefinitely at that level, however large and wealthy that

    nation might be. Unless it links up with other national revolutions and becomes a world

    revolution it will be asphyxiated and will degenerate. This is why we consider it an error tobase one's arguments on the national conditions of one country.

    On the basis of these political considerations we can arrive at an understanding of the "leap"

    the Russian revolution made over the various intermediary phases. The October revolutionshowed that in the epoch of imperialist decadence the proletariat cannot stop at the bourgeois

    phase of development, but must go beyond it by taking the place of a bourgeoisie incapable of

    carrying out its historic tasks. In order to attain this objective, the Bolsheviks did not spend

    their time drawing up an inventory of the productive forces at their disposal, but based their

    activity on an evaluation of the balance of class forces.

    Again, this leap was not conditioned by economic factors, but by political ones, since the onlyway the Russian revolution could give rise to a material development of the economy was by

    linking up with the world revolution. The "immaturity" of the backward countries - which

    makes such "leaps" necessary - as well as the "maturity" of the advanced countries, must all

    be incorporated into the same process of the world-wide class struggle.

    Lenin gave a clear answer to those who reproached the Bolsheviks for having taken power. "It

    would an irreparable error to say that, because there is an obvious imbalance between our

    economic strength and out political strength, we shouldn't have taken power! To argue in

    such a way you have to be blind, you have to forget that such a balance will never exist and

    can't exist in any process of social revolution, and that it is only through a whole number ofexperiences, each one of which will be incomplete and marred by a certain imbalance, that

    the triumph of socialism can be realised by the revolutionary co-operation of the workers ofall countries."

    No matter how "poor" a proletariat might be it does not have to wait for the "richer"

    proletariats to make its own revolution. The fact that such a revolution might encounter many

    more difficulties than would confront a stronger proletariat is undeniable, but history doesn'toffer other alternatives.

    The historic epoch of bourgeois revolutions led by the bourgeoisie is over. The survival of

    capitalism has become an obstacle to progress, and thus also to the development of thebourgeois revolution, since we are now faced with a saturated world market. Moreover, the

    bourgeoisie can no longer win the support of the working masses like it did in 1789; even as

    early as 1848, 1871, and 1905 in Russia, it was unable to do this.

    The October revolution was a striking example of one of these apparent historical paradoxes;

    it showed a proletariat completing a short-lived bourgeois revolution but then compelled to

    realise its own objectives in order to avoid being strangled by imperialism.

    The Russian bourgeoisie had been weakened from birth by western capital's domination of the

    economy. The price of keeping Tsarism going was that a considerable portion of the national

    revenue was soaked off by foreign capital, and this was an obstacle to the economicdevelopment of the Russian bourgeoisie.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    12/61

    1905 was an attempted bourgeois revolution marked by the absence of the bourgeoisie. A

    highly concentrated proletariat already appeared on the scene as an independent revolutionary

    force; this forced the politically impotent liberal bourgeoisie into the arms of the feudal

    autocracy. But the bourgeois revolution of 1905 couldn't end in a victory for the proletariat,

    because although it was a product of the convulsions caused by the Russo-Japanese war, it

    wasn't accompanied by a maturation of social antagonisms on an international scale. ThusTsarism was able to receive financial and material aid from the whole European bourgeoisie.

    As Rosa Luxemburg said, "The Revolution of 1905-1907 roused only a faint echo in Europe.

    Therefore, it had to remain a mere opening chapter. Continuation and conclusion were tiedup with the further development of Europe".15 The revolution of 1917 arose in a more

    developed historical situation. In The Proletarian Revolution and the Renegade Kautsky

    Lenin traced its successive phases: "First, with the whole' of the peasantry against themonarchy, against the landlords, against medievalism (and to that extent, the revolution

    remains bourgeois, bourgeois democratic). Then, with the poor peasants, with the semi-proletarians, with all the exploited against capitalism, including the rural rich, the kulaks, the

    profiteers, and to that extent the revolution becomes a socialist one. To attempt to raise anartificial Chinese Wall between the first and the second, to separate them by anything else

    than the degree of preparedness of the proletariat and the degree of its unity with the poor

    peasants, means monstrously to distort Marxism, to vulgarise it, to substitute liberalism in its

    place. It means smuggling in a reactionary defence of the bourgeoisie against the socialist

    proletariat by means

    of quasi-scientific references to the progressive character of the bourgeoisie as compared

    with medievalism."16

    The dictatorship of the proletariat was the instrument which made it possible first to completethe bourgeois revolution, then go beyond it. This is the explanation behind the Bolshevik

    slogan "land to the peasants", which - mistakenly, in our opinion - was opposed by RosaLuxemburg.

    With Lenin, we say that: "...the Bolsheviks...strictly differentiated between the bourgeois-

    democratic revolution, and the socialist revolution: by carrying the former to its end, they

    opened the door for the transition to this latter. This was the only policy that wasrevolutionary and Marxian".17

    (Bilanno. 28, March-April 1936)

    1Collected Works, Vol.21.

    2The Poverty of Philosophy. Collected Works, Vol. 6.

    3Collected Works, Vol.25.

    4Ibid.

    5Ibid.

    6The Russian Revolution

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    13/61

    7Preface to the first German edition of Capital.

    8Capitalvol. 1, Part V, Chapter XVI "Absolute and relative surplus value".

    9Programme of the 6th Congress of the CI.

    10Collected Works, Vol. 21.

    11The Third International after Lenin.

    12Collected Works, Vol. 6.

    13Collected Works, Vol. 24.

    14Collected Works, Vol.29.

    15The Russian Revolution.

    16Collected Works, Vol. 28.

    17The Proletarian Revolution and the Renegade Kautsky.

    Part II

    In our introductory study, we tried to show that there is not and cannot be a direct

    simultaneity between the historicmaturity of the proletarian revolution and its material andcultural maturity. We are living in the epoch of proletarian revolution because social progress

    can now only take place after the disappearance of the very class antagonisms which, in whatwe might call the prehistory of the human race, have been the motor-force of all progress until

    now.

    But the collective appropriation of the wealth developed by bourgeois society simply does

    away with the contradiction between the socialformof the productive forces and their privateappropriation. It is simply the sine qua non for the further development of society. In itself

    it doesnt lead automatically to a higher stage of development. In itself it doesnt contain all

    the constructive solutions of socialism, nor does it immediately wipe out all forms of social

    inequality.

    The collectivisation of the means of production and exchange is not socialism - it is a point of

    departure, a fundamental precondition for socialism. It is still only a juridical solution to

    social contradictions and doesnt eliminate all the material and spiritual deficiencies that the

    proletariat will inherit from capitalism. In a sense history will surprise the proletariat and

    force it to carry out its mission in an unprepared state which no amount of revolutionaryidealism and dynamism can immediately transform into an ability to resolve all the

    formidable and complex problems the revolution will pose. Both before and after the conquestof power, the proletariat will have to make up for the historical immaturity of its

    consciousness by relying on its party, which will remain its guide and educator in the period

    of transition from capitalism to communism. At the same time the proletariat will only be able

    to overcome the temporary insufficiency of the productive forces bequeathed to it bycapitalism by having recourse to a state, to an:

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    14/61

    evil inherited by the proletariat after its victorious struggle for class supremacy, whose

    worse sides the victorious proletariat, just like the Commune, cannot avoid having to lop off

    at once as much as possible until such time as a generation reared in new, free social

    conditions is able to throw the entire lumber of the state on the scrap heap.[1]

    The necessity to tolerate a state during the transition period between capitalism andcommunism derives from the specific character of this period, which Marx defined in his

    Critique of the Gotha Programme:

    What we have to deal with here is a communist society, not as it has developedon its own

    foundations, but on the contrary, just as it emerges from capitalist society; which is thus in

    every respect, economically, morally and intellectually,still stamped with the birth marks of

    the old society from whose womb it emerges (our emphasis).[2]

    Later on we will examine these birth marks when we analyse the economic and social

    categories which the proletariat will inherit from capitalism and which are going to have to

    wither away alongside the proletarian state.

    It would obviously be a mistake to cover up the mortal danger which the survival of this

    instrument of servitude, this state, will pose to the proletarian revolution, even though its a

    workers state. But to conclude that the revolution is bound to degenerate simply because this

    state will exist would be to ignore the dialectic of history and to abandon the revolution itself.

    Similarly, to delay the unleashing of the revolution until the masses have fully acquired the

    capacity to wield power would be to run away from the reality of the historical problem, to

    negate the necessity of the transitional state and of the party. This idea is the logicalaccompaniment to the notion of basing the revolution on the maturity of material

    conditions, which we examined in the first part of this study.

    Later on we will consider the problem of the ability of the proletarian masses to run the state

    and the economy.

    The state: instrument of the ruling class

    While the victorious proletariat will be forced by historical conditions to tolerate a stateduring a more or less prolonged period, it is important that it understands what kind of state

    this will be.

    The marxist method allows us on the one hand to uncover the meaning of the state in class

    society, to define its nature; and, on the other hand, by analysing the revolutionary

    experiences of the proletariat last century, to determine what attitude the proletariat must have

    with regard to the bourgeois state.

    Marx and above all Engels succeeded in ridding the idea of the state of all idealistexcrescences. Laying bare the real nature of the state, they showed that it was nothing but an

    instrument of oppression in the hands of the ruling class of a given society; that its only

    function was to safeguard the economic and political privileges of this class: through coercion

    and violence, its role was to impose the juridical rules which corresponded to the forms of

    property and mode of production upon which these privileges were based. They also showedthat the state was the expression of the domination of the majority of the population by a

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    15/61

    minority. The backbone of the state, the concrete expression of the fact that society was

    divided into classes, was its armed force and coercive organs, which were placed above and

    against the mass of the people, and which prevented the oppressed class from maintaining its

    own spontaneous forms of armed defence. The ruling class could never tolerate the

    existence of an armed force of the people alongside its own instruments of repression.

    To take just one example from the history of bourgeois society: in France the revolution of

    February 1848 armed the workers who were now a power in the state (Engels). The

    bourgeoisie had but one concern: to disarm the workers. So it provoked them by liquidating

    the national workshops and crushed them during the June uprising. Again in France, afterSeptember 1870, a national guard mainly composed of workers was formed to defend the

    country.

    almost at once the antagonism between the almost completely bourgeois government and

    the armed proletariat broke into open conflictTo arm Paris was to arm the revolution.Thierswas compelled to realise that the supremacy of the propertied classes was in constant

    danger so long as the workers of Paris had arms in their hands. His first action was toattempt to disarm them.[3]

    Thus came March 18th and the Commune.

    But once it had penetrated the secret of the bourgeois state (whether monarchical or

    republican, authoritarian or democratic) the proletariat still had to clarify its own policy

    towards this state. The experimental method of marxism gave it the means to do this.

    At the time of the Communist Manifesto Marx clearly recognised the necessity for theproletariat to conquer political power, to organise itself as the ruling class, but he was less

    clear about the fact that the proletariat had to create its own state. He had already foreseen that

    all forms of state would disappear when classes had been abolished, but this remained a

    general and somewhat abstract formulation. The French experience of 1848-51 provided

    Marx with the historical evidence which allowed him more firmly to grasp the idea of the

    destruction of the bourgeois state, but it did not enable him to trace the contours of the

    proletarian state which would arise in its place. The proletariat had appeared on the scene as

    the first revolutionary class in history destined to annihilate the increasingly centralised police

    and bureaucratic machine, which all exploiting classes had used to crush the exploited masses.

    In his 18th BrumaireMarx stressed that up till now all revolutions perfected this machineinstead of smashing it.[4] The centralised power goes back to the absolute monarchy; the

    rising bourgeoisie used it to struggle against feudalism; the French revolution simply rid it ofits feudal vestiges, and the First Empire completed the formation of the modern state. A

    developed bourgeois society transformed the central power into a machine for oppressing the

    proletariat. In the Communist Manifesto, Marx explained why all previous revolutionary

    classes had conquered the state instead of destroying it: the means of production and of

    exchange, on whose foundation the bourgeoisie built up, were generated in feudal society.[5]

    Having gradually conquered economic power, the bourgeoisie had no need to destroy a

    political organ in which it had already installed itself. It didnt have to do away with thebureaucracy, the police, or the armed forces, but simply to subordinate these instruments of

    oppression to its own interests, because its political revolution was only a juridical

    replacement of one form of exploitation by another.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    16/61

    Proletarian state and bourgeois state

    In contrast to this the proletariat is a class which expresses the interests of humanity rather

    than any particular interest; it cannot therefore embed itself in a state based on exploitation.

    The proletarianshave nothing of their own to secure and to fortify; their mission is to

    destroy all previous securities for, and insurance of, individual property.[6]

    Despite its limitations, the Paris Commune was the first historical response to the question of

    the difference between the proletarian state and the bourgeois state. The rule of the majority

    over a minority deprived of its privileges eliminated the need for a specialised bureaucratic

    and military machine in the service of particular interests. The proletariat replaced this

    machine with its own armament - to break the resistance of the bourgeoisie - and a political

    form which allowed it to progressively assume the task of managing society In this sense the

    Communewas no longer a state in the proper sense of the word (Engels). Lenin stressed

    the fact that the Commune had the gigantic achievement of replacing certain institutions byinstitutions in principle essentially different.

    Nevertheless, the proletarian state still has the essential character of all states. It is still an

    organ of coercion and, although it ensures the rule of the majority over a minority, it can stillonly express the temporary impossibility of doing away with bourgeois right. In Lenins

    phrase it is a bourgeois state without the bourgeoisie, and unless it is constantly subjected to

    the direct control of the proletariat and its party it will always tend to turn against the class.

    ***

    The theory of the dictatorship of the proletariat, already developed in the Manifesto butfinding a historical elaboration in the Commune of 1871, juxtaposed the idea of the

    destruction of the bourgeois state with that of the withering away of the proletarian state.

    With Marx, the idea of the final disappearance of the state can be found in embryonic form in

    The Poverty of Philosophy; it was mainly developed by Engels in The Origins of the Family

    andAnti-Duhring, while later on Lenin commented on the problem brilliantly in his State and

    Revolution. The fundamental distinction between the destruction of the bourgeois state and

    the dying away of the proletarian state was rigorously drawn by Lenin and we dont have to

    go into it here, especially because our previous considerations have dealt with any doubt

    about this question.

    What we must keep in mind is that the hypothesis of the withering away of the state is bound

    to become the touchstone of the content of proletarian revolutions. We have already indicatedthat the revolution breaks out in a historical milieu which obliges the proletariat to tolerate the

    existence of a state. But this can only be: a state in the process of withering away, that is, a

    state so constituted that it begins to wither away from the start and cannot but wither away

    (Lenin).

    The great achievement of marxism is to have shown irrefutably that the state has never been

    an autonomous factor in history, but is simply the product of a society divided into classes;

    the existence of classes preceded the state, and the latter will disappear when classes

    themselves disappear. After the dissolution of primitive communism the state has always

    existed in a more or less developed form, since it is inevitably superimposed on any form of

    exploitation of man by man; but at the same time it will inevitably die out at the end of aperiod of historical evolution which will make all oppression and constraint superfluous, since

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    17/61

    bourgeois right will have been eliminated and, in Saint-Simons phrase, politics will be

    entirely reabsorbed into the economy.

    But marxist science has still not elaborated a solution to the problem of how exactly the state

    will wither away, a problem which is directly linked to the question of the relationship

    between the proletariat and its state.

    The Commune was the first attempt to set up the dictatorship of the proletariat and was an

    experience of enormous importance, but it couldnt avoid defeat and confusion, because, on

    the one hand, it took place in a period of historical immaturity; and, on the other hand,

    because it lacked the theoretical guide, the party. It can thus provide us only with a vague

    outline of the relationship between the state and the proletariat.

    In 1875, in the Critique of the Gotha ProgammeMarx was still posing the question: what

    transformation will the nature of the state undergo in communist society? [Marx is talking

    about the period of transition here - ed. Note] In other words, what social formation will

    remain in existence there that are analogous to the present functions of the state. Thisquestion can only be answered scientifically,and one does not get a flea-hop nearer to the

    problem by a thousand-fold combination of the word people with the word state (ouremphasis - ed. note).[7]For Marx, the Commune was: a thoroughly expansive political form,

    while all previous forms of government had been emphatically repressiveit was the

    political form at last discovered under which to work out the economic emancipation of

    labour.[8]

    The Commune simply provided a framework for solving the fundamental problem of the

    education of the masses, who had the task of progressively freeing themselves from the

    burden of the state and ensuring that the state would finally disappear with the creation of a

    classless society. In this sense, the Commune was a signpost on the road to emancipation. It

    showed that although the proletariat could not immediately do away with the system of

    delegation, it had to: safeguard itself against its own deputies and officials, by declaring

    them all, without exception, subject to recall at any moment. And, for Marx: Nothing could

    be more foreign to the spirit of the Commune than to supercede universal suffrage [in the

    election of deputies - ed. note] by hierarchic investiture.[9]

    The theoretical elaboration of the problem had to stay at this point. Forty years later, Lenin

    was unable to go any further in this sphere. In State and Revolutionhe was limited to a fewsummary and even banal formulae which emphasised the necessity to: transform the

    functions of the state into functions of control and checking that are so simple that they can becarried out by the enormous majority of the population and little by little by the entire

    population.[10]

    Like Engels, he was limited to the assertion that the state would disappear in an era of real

    freedom, as would democracy, which would have lost all social meaning. As for the exact

    process whereby all the habits of servitude left over from capitalism would be eliminated,

    Lenin said that: the question of the concrete way in which the state will die out remains an

    open one, since we dont have the historical data that would allow us to settle it.[11]

    Thus the problem of the management of a proletarian state and economy in the interests of the

    international revolution remained unsolved. In October 1917, when the Russian proletariatembarked upon the most crucial of historical experiences, the class found that it lacked the

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    18/61

    political principles to define the relationship between the state and proletariat. The Bolsheviks

    inevitably suffered from the crushing weight of this theoretical deficiency.

    The power of the proletariat and the state in the period of transition

    Taking a step back and looking at the Russian experience, it seems probable that if theBolsheviks and the International had been able to acquire a clear vision of this fundamentalquestion, the reflux of the revolution in the West, despite being a considerable obstacle to the

    October revolution, would not have altered the latters internationalist character and provoked

    it to break with the world proletariat by straying into the impasse of socialism in one

    country.

    But in the middle of the most terrible contingent difficulties, the Bolsheviks did not consider

    the Soviet state as an evil inherited by the proletariat whose worst sides the victorious

    proletariatcannot avoid having to lop off as much as possible, but as an organism which

    could be completely identified with the proletarian dictatorship, i.e. with the party.

    The result of this important modification was that the foundation of the dictatorship of the

    proletariat was no longer to be the party, but the state; and through the ensuing reversal of

    roles the latter found itself in a course of development which led not to the withering away of

    the state but to the reinforcement of its coercive and repressive powers. Once an instrument of

    the world revolution, the proletarian state was inevitably converted into a weapon of the

    global counter-revolution.

    Although Marx, Engels and above all Lenin had again and again emphasized the necessity to

    counter the state with a proletarian antidote capable of preventing its degeneration, theRussian revolution, far from assuring the maintenance and vitality of the class organs of the

    proletariat, sterilised them by incorporating them into the state; and thus the revolution

    devoured its own substance.

    Even in Lenins thought, the idea of the dictatorship of the state began to predominate. At

    the end of 1918, in his polemic against Kautsky, (The Proletarian Revolution and the

    Renegade Kautsky[12]) he was unable to distinguish between two conflicting concepts: the

    state and the dictatorship of the proletariat. He replied resoundingly to Kautsky on the

    definition of the dictatorship of the proletariat, on its basic class meaning (all power to the

    soviets), but he made a connection between the necessity to destroy the bourgeois state and

    crush the ruling class and the idea of transforming the proletariats organisations into state

    organs. Its true, however, that this position wasnt an absolute for Lenin, since he wasreferring to the period of civil war, of the overthrow of bourgeois rule, during which time the

    main function of the Soviets was to be instruments of oppression against the bourgeoisie and

    its state apparatus.

    The enormous difficulty in finding the right answer to the question of the relationshipbetween the state and the proletariat, a question which Lenin was unable to resolve, derives

    from this dual, contradictory necessity: the need, on the one hand, to retain the state, an organ

    of economic and political coercion controlled by the proletariat (and thus by the party), while

    at the same time ensuring a greater and greater participation of the masses in the running and

    administration of the proletarian social order, even though this participation can for a whole

    period only take place through state organs, which by their very nature tend to lead tocorruption.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    19/61

    The experience of the Russian revolution shows just how difficult it is to produce a social

    climate which will allow the maximum development of the activity and culture of the masses.

    The controversy about democracy and dictatorship centres round this problem, whose solution

    is crucial to the success of future proletarian revolutions. Here we should emphasize the fact

    that despite Lenin and Luxemburgs differences about proletarian democracy, they showeda common pre-occupation - the desire to create the conditions for an incessant expansion of

    the capacities of the masses. But for Lenin the concept of democracy, even proletarian

    democracy, always implies the oppression of one class by another - whether it is the rule of

    the bourgeoisie over the proletariat, or the dictatorship of the proletariat over the bourgeoisie.And as we have said democracy will disappear with the abolition of classes and the state,

    i.e. when the concept of freedom becomes a reality.

    Against Lenins idea of a discriminatory democracy, Luxemburg (in the Russian

    Revolution)defended the idea of unlimited democracy, which for her was a precondition

    for: the unobstructed participation of the popular masses in the dictatorship of the

    proletariat.[13] This could only be realised through the total exercise of democraticfreedoms: unlimited freedom of the press, full political freedom, parliamentarism (even

    though later on, in the Spartacus programme, the future of parliamentarism was subordinated

    to the needs of the revolution).

    Luxemburgs overriding concern not to see the organs of the state machine getting in the way

    of thepoliticallife of the proletariat and its active participation in the tasks of the dictatorship

    prevented her from grasping the fundamental ro le of the party, since she ended up opposing

    the dictatorship of the class to the dictatorship of the party. However, she had the tremendous

    achievement of showing the difference in social context between the rule of the bourgeoisie

    and the rule of the proletariat, as Marx had done for the Commune: the class rule of thebourgeoisie has no need for the political instruction and education of the mass of the people,

    or at least for no more than an extremely limited amount; but for the dictatorship of theproletariat, it is the vital element, the oxygen without which it cannot live.[14]

    In the programme of Spartacus, she dealt with the crucial problem of the education of the

    masses (which has to be solved by the party), saying that: history is not going to make our

    revolution an easy matter like the bourgeois revolutions. In those revolutions it sufficed tooverthrow that official power at the centre and to replace a dozen or so persons in authority.

    But we have to work from beneath.[15]

    The inability of the Bolsheviks to maintain the state in the service of the revolution

    Caught up in the contradictory process of the Russian revolution, Lenin nevertheless

    continued to emphasize the need to pose a proletarian corrective: organs of workers

    control, against the corrupting tendencies of the transitional state.

    In his report to the Congress of Soviets in April 1918, The Immediate Tasks of the Soviet

    Government, he underlined the necessity to constantly supervise the functioning of the

    Soviets and the Soviet power:

    There is a petty-bourgeois tendency to transform the members of the Soviets into

    parliamentarians, or else into bureaucrats. We must combat this by drawing allmembers ofthe Soviets into the practical work of administration.[16]

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    20/61

    In order to achieve this Lenin said it was necessary:

    to draw the whole of the poor into the practical work of administration, and all steps that

    are taken in this direction -the more varied they are, the better - should be carefully recorded,

    studied, systematised, tested by wider experience and embodied in law. Our aim is to ensure

    that every toiler, having finished his eight hours task in productive labour, shall performstate duties without pay; the transition to this is particularly difficult, but this transition alone

    can guarantee the final consolidation of socialism. Naturally, the novelty and difficulty of the

    change lead to an abundance of steps being taken, as it were, gropingly, to an abundance of

    mistakes, vacillation - without this, any marked progress is impossible. The reason why thepresent position seems peculiar to many of those who would like to be regarded as socialists

    is that they have been accustomed to contrasting capitalism with socialism abstractly, and

    that they profoundly put between the two the word leap.[17]

    The fact that in the same report Lenin was led to justify giving dictatorial powers to

    individuals was the expression not only of the grim contingent situation which gave rise to

    War Communism, but also of the contradiction between a necessary coercive regime imposedby the state machine, and the need to safeguard the proletarian dictatorship, to immerse the

    regime in the growing activity of the masses.

    The more resolutely we now have to stand for a ruthlessly firm government, for the

    dictatorship of individuals in definite processes of work, in definite aspects of purely

    executive functions, the more varied must be the forms and methods of control from below in

    order to counteract every shadow of a possibility of distorting the principles of Soviet

    government, in order repeatedly and tirelessly to weed out bureaucracy.[18]

    But three years of civil war and the vital necessity to restore economic life prevented the

    Bolsheviks from finding a clear political solution to the problem of the relationship between

    the proletariat and state organs. Not that they were unaware of the mortal dangers which

    threatened the whole development of the revolution. The programme of the 8th Congress of

    the Russian Party in March 1919 talked about the danger of a political rebirth of bureaucracy

    within the Soviet regime, despite the fact that the old Tsarist bureaucratic machinery had been

    destroyed from top to bottom. The 9th Congress in December 1920 also dealt with the

    question of bureaucracy. And at the 10th Congress, which saw the beginning of the NEP,Lenin discussed the question at great length and came to the following conclusion: that the

    economic roots of the Soviet bureaucracy were not implanted in the military and juridical

    apparatus as in the bourgeois state, but that they grew out of the services; that the bureaucracy

    had sprung out of the period of War Communism and expressed the negative side of thisperiod. The price paid for the necessarily dictatorial centralisation of this period was the

    increasing authority of the functionaries. At the 11th Congress, after a year of the New

    Economic Policy, Lenin vigorously emphasised the historic contradiction involved in the

    proletariat being forced to take power and use it before being fully prepared ideologically and

    culturally:

    We have sufficient, quite sufficient political power, we also have sufficient economic

    resources at our command, but the vanguard of the working class which has been brought tothe forefront to directly supervise, to determine the boundaries, to demarcate, to subordinate

    and not be subordinated itself, lacks sufficient ability for it. All that is needed here is ability,

    and that is what we do not haveNever before in history has there been [such] asituation.[19]

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    21/61

    Concerning the state capitalism that it was necessary to put up with, Lenin urged the party

    thus:

    You Communists, workers, you, the politically enlightened section of the proletariat, which

    undertook to administer the state, must be able to arrange it so that the state which you have

    taken into your hands, shall function the way you want it to. Well, we have lived through ayear, the state is in our hands; but has it operated the New Economic Policy in the way we

    wanted this past year?How did it operate? The machine refused to obey the hand that

    guided it. It was like a car that was going not in the direction the driver desired, but in the

    direction someone else desired[20]

    By saying that the task was to build communism with non-communist hands Lenin was

    only restating one of the fundamental problems of the proletarian revolution. By pointing out

    that the party had to lead an economy managed by others in the direction that itwanted it to

    go, he was simply showing that the function of the party is not the same as that of the state

    machine.

    The safeguard of the Russian revolution, the guarantee that it would stay on the tracks of the

    world revolution, was therefore not the absence of all bureaucracy - which is an inevitableexcrescence of the transition period - but the vigilant presence of proletarian organs in which

    the educational activity of the party could be carried out, while the party itself retained a

    vision of its international tasks through the International. Because of a whole series of

    historical circumstances and because of a lack of indispensable theoretical and experimental

    equipment, the Bolsheviks were unable to resolve this basic problem. The crushing weight of

    contingent events led them to lose sight of the importance of retaining the Soviets and trade

    unions as organs which could be juxtaposed to the state, controlling it but not being

    incorporated into it.

    The Russian experience doesnt allow us to see the extent to which the Soviets could have

    been, in Lenins phrase, the organisations of the workers and the exploited masses which

    will allow them to organise and govern the state themselves; the extent to which they could

    have concentrated the legislative, the executive, and, the judiciary into themselves if

    centrism had not emasculated their revolutionary potential.

    In any case, the Soviets appeared as the Russian form of the dictatorship of the proletariat

    rather than having an international validity. What makes them an acquisition from theexperimental point of view is the fact that during the phase of the destruction of Tsarist

    society, the soviets were the backbone of the armed self-organisation which the Russianworkers put in place of the bureaucratic and military machine and the autocracy, and then

    used against the reaction of the dispossessed classes.

    As for the trade unions their function was altered in the process of the degeneration of the

    whole apparatus of the proletarian dictatorship. In his Infantile Disorder (early 1920) Lenin

    underlined the importance of the trade unions: by means of which the Party is closely linked

    up with the class and with the masses, and by means of which, under the leadership of the

    Party, the dictatorship of the class is exercised.

    After the seizure of power: the Party must more than ever and in a new way, not only in the

    old way, educate and guide the trade unions, at the same time bearing in mind that they areand will long remain an indispensable school of Communism and a preparatory school

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    22/61

    that trains the proletarians to exercise their dictatorship, an indispensable organisation of the

    workers for the gradual transfer of the management of the whole economic life of the country

    to the working class (and not to separate trades), and later to all the working people.[21]

    The question of the role of the trade unions really came into its own at the end of 1920.

    Trotsky, basing his position on his experience in the sphere of transportation, considered thatthe unions had to become state organs responsible for maintaining labour discipline and the

    organisation of production. He even went so far as to propose that the unions be done away

    with, claiming that, in a workers state, they simply duplicated the tasks of state organs!

    The discussion gathered pace at the 10th Congress of the party in March 1921 under the

    pressure of immediate events (Kronstadt) Trotskys ideas were opposed both by the Workers

    Opposition led by Shliapnikov and Kollontai, who called for management of production by

    the unions, and by Lenin, who considered that the statification of the unions was premature

    and that since the state is not a workers state, but a workers and peasants state withnumerous bureaucratic deformations, the unions had to defend the workers interests against

    such a state. But Lenin emphasised that his disagreement with Trotsky was not over aquestion ofprinciple, but simply over contingent considerations.

    The fact that Trotsky was defeated at this Congress did not mean that the confusion about the

    role of the unions under the proletarian dictatorship had been cleared up. In fact the theses of

    the 3rd Congress of the CI repeated this confusion, on the one hand saying that: before,

    during, and after the seizure of power, the unions remain a broader, more massive, more

    general form of organisation than the party, and in relation to the latter, to some extent play

    the part of the circumference to the centre.

    And also that: the communists and sympathising elements must form within the unions

    communist groupings entirely subordinated to the communist party as a whole.

    While on the other hand saying that: after the seizure and strengthening of proletarian

    power, the activity of the trade unions will be concerned mainly with the tasks of economic

    organisation and they will dedicate nearly all their energy to the building of the economy on

    a socialist basis, thus becoming a truly practical school of communism.

    We know that, after this, the unions not only lost any control over the management of

    enterprises, but also became organs responsible for stimulating production and not for

    defending the interests of the workers. In compensation for this, trade union leaders were

    recruited into the administration of industry and the right to strike was maintained in theory.But in fact strikes broke out in opposition to the trade union leadership.

    ***

    The clearest criterion which marxists can use to back up their affirmation that the Soviet state

    is a degenerated state, that it has lost any proletarian function and has become an instrument

    of world capitalism, is the historical evolution of the Russian state between 1917 and 1936. Inthis period the state, far from tending to wither away, has become stronger and stronger, a

    process which could only lead it to becoming an instrument of oppression and exploitation

    against the Russian workers. This is an entirely new historical phenomenon, the result of an

    unprecedented historical situation: the existence within capitalist society of a proletarian statebased on the collectivisation of the means of production, but one in which we are seeing a

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    23/61

    social process determining a frenzied exploitation of labour power; and at the same time this

    exploitation cannot be ascribed to the domination of a class which has juridical ownership of

    the means of production. We do not think that this social paradox can be explained by

    saying there is a bureaucracy which has become a ruling class (from the standpoint of

    historical materialism, these two notions mutually exclude each other); it can only be seen as

    the expression of a policy which has delivered the Russian state into the hands of worldcapitalism, whose laws of evolution are driving it towards imperialist war. In the part of this

    study dedicated to the question of the management of the proletarian economy, we will comeback to the concrete aspects of this essential characteristic of the degeneration of the Soviet

    state, which has meant that the Russian proletariat is at the mercy not of a national exploitingclass but of the world capitalist class. Such a political and economic relationship obviously

    contains within it all the conditions for the restoration of capitalism in Russia in the turmoil of

    a new imperialist war, unless the Russian proletariat, with the aid of the international

    proletariat, manages to overthrow the forces which threaten to lead it into another massacre.

    Bearing in mind what we have said about the historic conditions in which the proletarian state

    is born, it is clear that the withering away of this state cannot be seen as an autonomousprocess limited to the national framework, but only as a symptom of the development of the

    world revolution.

    It became impossible for the Soviet state to begin withering away as soon as the party and the

    International stopped seeing the Russian revolution as a step towards the world revolution and

    assigned to it the task of building socialism in one country. This explains why the specific

    weight of the state organs and the exploitation of the Russian workers have increased with the

    development of industrialisation and the economy; why the liquidation of classes has led

    not to a weakening of the state, but to its reinforcement, as expressed by the re-establishment

    of the three forces which have always been the backbone of the bourgeois state: thebureaucracy, the police and the standing army.

    This phenomenon in no way indicates the falsity of marxist theory, which bases the

    proletarian revolution on the collectivisation of the productive forces and on the necessity for

    a transitional state and the dictatorship of the proletariat. It is simply the bitter fruit of a

    historic situation which prevented the Bolsheviks and the International from imposing an

    internationalist policy on the state, and which on the contrary made them the servants of the

    state against the proletariat by leading them onto the path of national socialism. In the face of

    economic difficulties which confronted them, the Bolsheviks were unable to formulate a

    policy which would have immunised them from confusing the apparatus of repression (which

    should only have been used against the dispossessed classes) with the class organs of theproletariat, which should have exercised control over the administration of the economy. Thedisappearance of these organs obliged the proletarian state, in its efforts to carry out a national

    programme and keep the economic apparatus going, to use its repressive organs against the

    proletariat as well as against the bourgeoisie. The state, that necessary evil, turned against

    the workers, despite the fact that, while the principle of authority will have to be recognised

    during the transitional phase, bureaucratic coercion can never be justified.

    The whole point was to try not to widen the gap between the political and cultural immaturity

    of the masses and the historic necessity for them to run society. The solution that was aimed

    at, however, tended to exacerbate this contradiction even further.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    24/61

    We are with Rosa Luxemburg in saying that in Russia the question of the life of the

    proletarian state and the building of socialism could only be posed and not answered. It is up

    to the marxist fractions today to draw from the Russian revolution the essential lessons which

    will allow the proletariat to resolve the problem of the world revolution and of the building of

    communism in the next revolutionary wave.

    [1]. Engels, Introduction to The Civil War in France, 1891. Marx, Engels, Collected Works,

    Vol. 27.

    [2]. 1875. Marx, Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 24.

    [3]. Engels, Introduction to The Civil War in France, 1891. Marx, Engels, Collected Works,

    Vol. 27.

    [4]. 1852. Collected Works, Vol. 11.

    [5]. 1848, Collected Works, Vol. 6.

    [6]. Manifesto. Ibid.

    [7]. 1875. Marx, Engels, Collected Works, Vol. 24.

    [8]. The Civil War in France, 1871, Collected Works, Vol. 22.

    [9]. Ibid.

    [10]. 1917, Lenin, Collected Works, Vol.25.

    [11]. Ibid.

    [12]. 1918. Lenin, Collected Works, Vol. 28.

    [13]. In:Rosa Luxemburg Speaks, Pathfinder press 1970.

    [14]. Ibid.

    [15]. Speech to the founding congress of the German Communist Party in Rosa Luxemburg

    Speaks.

    [16]. 1918. Collected Works, Vol.. 27.

    [17]. Ibid.

    [18]. Ibid.

    [19]. Political report of the Central Committee of the RCP (B) , 1922. Collected Works,

    Vol. 33.

    [20]. Ibid.

  • 7/25/2019 The Period of Transition by Jehan van den Hoven

    25/61

    [21].Left-wing communism: An infantile disorder, 1920. Collected Works, Vol. 31

    Part III

    The stigmata of the proletarian economy

    Marxism always bases its analyses and perspectives on dialectical materialism and not on

    idealistic aspirations. Marx said that "even when a society has got upon the right track for the

    discovery of the natural laws of its movement - and it is the ultimate aim of this work, to laybare the economic law of motion of modern society - it can neither clear by bold leaps, nor

    remove by legal enactments, the obstacles offered by the successive phases of its normal

    development. But it can shorten and lessen the birth-pangs".[1] In the same way, the

    proletariat, having taken society through a "leap" as a result of its political revolution, cannot

    help but put up with the natural laws of evolution, while at the same time doing all it can to

    speed up the process of social transformation. If it is to achieve its historic goals, the

    proletariat has to ensure that the intermediate, "hybrid" social forms which arise in the phase

    between capitalism and communism wither away; but it cannot abolish them by decree. Thesuppression of private property - even if it's a radical step - does not ipso facto get rid of

    bourgeois ideology or bourgeois right: "The traditions of the dead generations weigh like anightmare on the brains of the living".[2]

    The persistence of the law of value in the transitional period

    In this part of our study we will be looking at some length at certain economic categories

    (labour-value, money, wages), which the proletarian economy will inherit from capitalism

    without the benefit of an inventory. This is important because there has been a tendency(we're thinking i