fuko, autonomija

Upload: martin-sivc

Post on 04-Apr-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    1/14

    Studies in Philosophy and Education 17: 163176, 1998.

    1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.163

    Review Article

    KENNETH WAINUniversity of Malta

    James D. Marshall, Michel Foucault: Personal Autonomy and Education.

    Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1996.

    Foucault the Destroyer

    In a review she wrote for Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinows book MichelFoucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, Maxine Greene (1983, p. 105)

    remarked that if we examine Foucaults work from the vantage point of institu-

    tionalized education or educational research he will appear to us as the Great

    Destroyer or, in the most literal of senses, a deconstructionist . By the end of

    the article she had softened her attitude to the extent that she recommended Dreyfus

    and Rabinows book for reading but still concluded her review tongue in cheek

    with the words: Sometimes even educational researchers must allow themselves to

    play (p. 110). Of course, deconstruction is not destruction, as Jacques Derrida

    has observed repeatedly to his critics, mainly Anglo-saxon philosophers, over the

    years. Beside, although, as Greene herself observed in his essay, Foucault has been

    classified in different ways by different critics over the years, deconstructionist is

    not usually one of them.Finally, her last remark reflects another criticism often made against post-

    modernists (among whom Foucault is often included, courtesy of Habermas) that

    they are not serious. But, again, it seems off-mark also. Although, in fact, Foucault

    did cultivate an image of elusive playfulness in his early work, he seems actually,

    on this matter at least, to have followed Rortys precept and kept it private, except

    perhaps for when he was being interviewed when pun, irony and paradox were,

    for him, the order of the day. There is certainly nothing very playful about his

    narratives of the modern world nor about the way he engaged personally in politics.

    I begin this critical essay with Greenes mistatements on Foucault because they

    are typical of many of his Anglo-saxon critics. In this sense he shares the fate of

    those who have been variously labelled as poststructuralist, postmodernist, decon-

    structionist, romantic, post-Nietzechean, and so on. The more usual criticism ofthese writers is that they are irrationalist because of their attack on traditional West-

    ern foundationalist epistemology and its conception of truth and reason (what

    Derrida calls its logocentrism), and irresponsible because of their disinclination

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    2/14

    164 KENNETH WAIN

    to align themselves with any of the traditional or standard political metanarratives

    of hope, liberty, and emancipation that have driven reformist and revolutionary

    politics in the modern age, or indeed to take up any ethical or political project or

    position at all. Foucaults politics, in particular, have been described by Walzer as

    a species of infantile leftism, by Merqiour as neo-anarchist and nihilist, and byCharles Taylor as simply incoherent.

    Greenes essay is also rather typical of a lot of philosophers of education writ-

    ing from the vantage point of institutionalized education or educational research

    when confronted with Foucault. She doesnt know quite what to make of him or

    his work so her review is mainly confined to a summary of what Dreyfus and

    Rabinow had to say about him in their excellent book, and she practically left the

    matter there. The difficulty philosophers of education encounter with Foucaults

    work in two-fold; first, they find difficulty with identifying his writing and interest

    as philosophical, second, he wrote very little directly about education. The latter

    may explain, to some extent at least, why, although a considerable amount has been

    written about the significance of Lyotards and Rortys (who are usually positioned

    more or less in the same postmodern/poststructuralist camp as Foucault) work

    for education, the same cannot be said for Foucault. What little has been written

    about Foucault and education, or about education from a Foucauldian perspective,

    usually corresponds with Greenes concession that, at least, his writings about the

    internal relation between knowledge and power, particularly in the various social

    sciences or sciences of man, may be of the greatest potential relevance for the

    educational researcher (1983, p. 108).

    This potential relevance was explored in a 1990 article by a decidedly

    sympathetic James Marshall who, while describing Foucault as one of the more

    interesting and controversial thinkers to have emerged in the Western world in the

    twentieth century, observed that it is not easy to say exactly how he impinges

    upon traditional mainstream philosophy and education (1990, p. 81). At the time,Marshall had already produced one general article on Foucault and Education in

    1989. Before that his publications reveal a distinct interest in the subject of punish-

    ment in education and one could conjecture that this was how he first came to take

    an interest in Foucaults work. Since then he has taken up the challenge of showing,

    nearly single-handedly one needs to acknowledge, how Foucault impinges upon

    traditional mainstrean philosophy and education. In the process he has produced

    a steady stream of further articles and essay contributions to different books on

    the subject, including another article about Foucault and educational research in

    Stephen Balls 1990 book, Foucault and Education: Disciplines and Knowledge.

    Michel Foucault: Personal Autonomy and Education (FPAEin what follows) may,

    in more senses than one, be regarded as the culmination of this work.

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    3/14

    REVIEW ARTICLE 165

    Negative Genealogies

    Before FPAE, Balls book was the first and, to my knowledge, the only, book dedi-

    cated specifically and entirely to Foucault and education, and it was an entirely

    different book from Marshalls. It consisted in a number of articles written bydifferent authors nearly all engaging in a Foucauldian genealogical analysis of

    educational institutions and practices. It addressed various aspects of the history of

    education and of some of the discourses and disciplinary disputes currently being

    formed, developed, and reformed in the educational field (Ball 1990, p. 2). But

    it was not about Foucault himself. In its preface Ball identified the more obvious

    relation between Foucaults work and education. The books concern, he said, was

    with the role of education and its interrelation with politics, economics and history

    in the formation and constitution of human beings as subjects (1990, p. 2). The

    statement illustrates perfectly the breath of scope and application of Foucaults own

    writing and provides an excellent reason why educationalists should be interested

    in it.

    Returning to Greens comments quoted earlier on, the articles in Balls bookare the most limpid proof that her judgement of Foucault as simply the great

    destroyer of educational research is far off the mark. Or, to be more precise, it

    is true of the conventional human and social sciences which Foucault did, indeed,

    consistently critique negatively in his work. But the book does not seem to escape

    the other criticism of Foucaults genealogical writing, that it is entirely negative. (2)

    This is a judgement of Foucaults work which, on the evidence, Marshall himself

    shares in the writing ofFPAE, and which, in my view at least, constitutes the books

    major shortcoming. With regards to the contributors to Balls book the explanation

    for the criticism is simple; they drew their inspiration nearly exclusively from just

    one of Foucaults works, Discipline and Punish (1979), which is a thoroughly

    dystopian narrative of the rise of modernity, an utterly negative analysis of the

    modern state. I suspect the same is true with Marshall, he continues to be influ-enced chiefly by the Foucault of Discipline and Punish also, despite the extensive

    bibliography at the end of his book which includes also Foucaults important later

    interviews and the second and third volumes of History of Sexuality.

    Marshalls 1990 contribution to Balls book, entitled Foucault and Educational

    Research, concludes that more than the mere potential relevance described by

    Greene, Foucaults genealogical analysis offers educational research a new frame-

    work not for studying the past, but for assessing the present . . . constituted by an

    analytic grid of power-knowledge. In the same article, he also refers to a failure

    on Foucaults part to articulate his theory of genealogy adequately, a failure which,

    he continued to say, makes its application problematic so that, rather than

    theorize about its limits of application, it may be better to see what can be done

    in practice (1990, p. 23). This last statement is problematic in its suggestion thatone can choose between theory and practice, but there is clearly some point to

    it. Genealogy is not a type of analysis or critique which can be defined in terms of

    the rules of a method, to the contrary it is personal and idiosyncratic, like a literary

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    4/14

    166 KENNETH WAIN

    work. No two genealogical analyses of a phenomenon will yield the same result or

    tell the same story.

    Marshall does not himself attempt a sample of genealogical writing in his article

    in Balls book, instead his writing aims to open a way to Foucault for education

    researchers to follow. In this connection he says that the methodological imper-ative Foucaults work imposes on us is to examine processes of modern power

    in modern schools (1990, p. 23). This is conventionally perceived as the work of

    the social sciences, particularly that of sociology and social psychology. But a part,

    a disconcerting but important part, of what Foucault was about in his genealogies

    was the unmasking of the social sciences. Laying bare their pretence towards being

    objective, reliable modes of analyses, or trustworthy methods of reproducing the

    truth about individuals and social practices, he shows them up as instruments of

    the modern states disciplinary power, as technologies of domination, dividing

    practices, or games of truth, as he called them. They are articulated through

    a norm-ridden discourse in terms of which individuals are studied, judged and

    categorised as normal, sane, competent, educated, or not. Foucault describes how,

    concurrently with the creation of the sciences, institutions and practices were

    invented for the purpose of discipline and study of the human subject, body and

    mind; asylums, hospitals, military barracks, prisons and schools. His general point

    is that the human and social sciences are part and parcel of the disciplinary tech-

    nologies or instruments of government and policing of the modern state. They are,

    therefore, to be regarded with suspicion rather than hope.

    Marshall explains Foucaults alleged failure to articulate his genealogical theory

    to his general, inbred opposition to all forms of systematization, his concern

    throughout that genealogy should not be turned into just another game of truth.

    Thus, though its concern with how questions qualifies it as a way of writing

    about the past, or writing history, it differs from conventional histories in that

    it is not concerned with the truth about the past through an accurate representa-tion of events. Historians of the present, as Foucault describes himself, do not

    reach outwards for objective truths that capture reality or mirror facts as they

    are supposed to have occurred, but inwards so that their writings are narratives,

    myths, fabrications, about themselves as much as about the world they describe.

    Genealogists are uninterested particularly in the humanist conception of history as

    linear development or progress and emphasise discontinuity and rupture instead.

    This characterization clearly establishes the subjective character of the

    genealogical mode of writing. Indeed, not only did Foucault not hide under the

    mantle of truth or objectivity, he always insisted on the biographical nature of his

    writing; each of my works is a part of my own biography (p. 13), he claimed,

    and my books have always arisen from personal problems with madness, prison,

    sexuality . . . (p. 36). Foucault emphasises this subjectivenss by referring to hisgenealogies as fictions, fictions abut the modern subject and its constitution

    through different technologies of power. Fictions with a purpose, however, a polit-

    ical purpose: to show people that they are much freer than they feel, that people

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    5/14

    REVIEW ARTICLE 167

    accept as truth, as evidence, some themes which have been built up at a certain

    moment during history, and that this so-called evidence can be criticized and

    destroyed (Martin et al., 1988, p. 10). This unmasking of power is liberating in

    a negative sense and the obvious response to it is to transgress the limits of what

    we are, but in the last stage of his life and work, which he termed ethical, Foucaultpassed on to a more positive account of freedom than mere transgression, this is

    freedom conceived as care for the self.

    To be honest, and to return to Marshalls point, I disagree that Foucault failed

    to articulate the nature of his genealogical writing. Although he was, indeed,

    against systematization of all kinds there are various places where he spelled out

    its purposes in the most explicit fashion. Certainly Nietzsche, genealogy, history

    and What is Enlightenment? are key essays in this respect. They constitute well-

    articulated explanations of genealogical writing by any account even if they stop

    short of describing a method. Indeed, in the first of these essays, borrowing from

    Nietzsche, Foucault identifies two concepts, two bare concepts, that guide the

    genealogists work; those of descent (berkunft) and emergence (enstehung).

    Bare as they may be, these concepts still set up the parameters within which

    the genealogist writes, and he discusses them in some detail. In the second essay

    Foucault goes beyond the negative characterization of genealogy as the unmasking

    of technologies of domination for the purpose of refusal and presents us with a

    more positive description of genealogy as a critical ontology of ourselves . . . to

    be considered not, certainly, as a theory, a doctrine, not even a permanent body of

    knowledge that is accumulating, it has to be conceived as an attitude, an ethos, a

    philosophical life in which critique of what we are is at one and the same time the

    historical analysis of the limits that are imposed on us and an experiment with the

    possibility of going beyond them (Foucault 1984, p. 50). That ethos, or attitude,

    or philosophical life, is the ethos of self care.

    Postmodernism and Politics

    Although Marshalls book covers these developments in Foucaults thought, he

    fails to take up and follow this revolutionary twist in Foucaults genealogical writ-

    ing with the claims that he made on its behalf to the end. The book is, therefore, in

    my view, only half written. I have another problem of a different kind with it; FPAE

    adds very little if anything to what Marshall has already written about Foucault

    and education previously, in his earlier articles and essays. It is built around the

    self-same themes though he does flesh them out with three important introduc-

    tory background chapters two of which are biographical. The book also makes

    the same arguments as the articles. The first two chapters discuss the formative

    intellectual and political influences on Foucault, while the third is an account ofliberalism and liberal education which introduces the reader to what the books

    title advertises as its central thrust; the issue of personal autonomy in education.

    The book ends with a short conclusion which summarizes the content of the book

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    6/14

    168 KENNETH WAIN

    and recalls its purposes. These Marshall describes as twofold: first to provide an

    introduction to Foucault for educators and students of education and to draw out

    the educational implications of some of his writings; and, second, to provide a

    critique, derived from Foucault, of the notion of personal autonomy in so far as this

    is conceived in liberal writings as an important aim, if not the aim, of education(1996, p. 213).

    I have the feeling that it would have been a better book had he published a selec-

    tion of his articles and essays in their original form instead with an introductory

    preface to them which could have included in more summary form the first two of

    the books chapters. Indeed, the account they contain of the intellectual influences

    on Foucault, his cultural background, and the French post-war intellectual scene

    within which he grew are indispensable material for the reading public Marshall

    identifies, educators or students who are still coming to grips with his writings. The

    short discussion of the influence on Foucault of the different thinkers and teachers

    he encountered in his formative years (Bachelard, Canguilhelm, Blanchot, Bataille,

    Lefebrve, Descombes etc.) is useful also for those who seek more than a mere

    acquaintance with his work. In point of fact, they tell us little if anything more than

    is to be found already in the Foucault biographies that have been written since his

    death by Eribon (1989). Macey (1993) and Miller (1993), but Marshalls summary

    is important for those have not read any of these books.

    His need to include a concluding chapter, on the other hand, appears strange

    since it more or less reproduces the summary of what the books purposes and

    argument is about which already appears in the Introduction. There are also

    two chapters which seem like odd fits within the books general scheme, these

    are chapters 5 and 7 which are entitled On Education and Doing Philosophy

    of Education respectively. These chapters are unconnected with the theme of the

    book and their inclusion raises puzzling questions. Chapter 5, which is a discussion

    of Foucaults own personal characteristics as an educator and of his connectionswith the French university reforms in the late 1960s, could easily have been

    summarised into a section in Chapter 2. Instead, Marshall reproduces his full article

    on Pedagogy and Apedagogy: Lyotard and Foucault at Vincennes, already printed

    in Michael Peterss Education and the Postmodern Condition. Marshall closes the

    chapter with a look at how educationalists have used Foucaults work, which, again,

    should have come earlier, at the beginning. He distinguishes them into modern

    (Sarap, 1982; Walkerdine, 1984; Jones and Williamson, 1979; Hoskin, 1990), and

    postmodern (Kiziltan et al., 1990).

    Marshall is out of sympathy with the latters attempt at a Foucauldean post-

    modernist critique of education. He affirms that Foucault cannot be used in general

    but rather his insights should be used either to problematise certain givens such

    as the pursuit of personal autonomy or in more particular genealogical studies(1996, p. 164). This statement and these limitations he places on Foucaults work,

    are part of the evidence I mentioned earlier of his sympathy with the standard

    complaint against postmodernism which he quotes from Beyer and Liston that it

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    7/14

    REVIEW ARTICLE 169

    cannot deliver and provide support for the type of political project that educational

    transformation must be (1996, p. 160). Marshall clearly states that Foucaults

    genealogical writings cannot inspire a positive educational project. In this case he

    clearly aligns Foucault with postmodernism.

    Indeed, Marshall takes up the question whether Foucault is a postmodernistin Chapter 6. Identifying Lyotard as the typical postmodernist, he concludes

    that, whatever the similarities between them, Foucault both refused to side with

    Lyotard, because he did not wish to be seen as any enemy of reason and enlight-

    enment, and to accept the label of post-modernist (1996, p. 185), I doubt that

    Lyotard wishes to be seen as an enemy of reason either (note his famous strug-

    gles with the notion of justice). Marshall concludes with Hoy that Foucault is

    neither modernist nor anti-modernist but leaves the question whether he was a

    postmodernist open (unless he tacitly takes post-modernist to be anti-modernist

    which would be a mistake) (1996, p. 187).

    But is it important whether Foucault could be described as a postmodernist

    or not? He himself did not think so, being against all forms of labelling. How

    does the issue contribute to the books purpose to critique the liberal notion of

    personal autonomy? Chapter 6, entitled Personal Autonomy Revisited, refers

    to Habermass famous critique of postmodernism as neo-liberal in its political

    inspiration. Marshall, rightly (and against Habermas), does not include Foucault

    as postmodern in this sense. He argues, to the contrary, that the promises of choice

    and freedom made by the new-right left Foucault, who had just begun to address

    the neo-liberalism that was about to sweep Europe and other areas of the Western

    world (1996, p. 187) when he died, unimpressed, for they merely signify changes

    in the form that governmentality takes (Foucault, 1979b) (1996, p. 188). In short,

    Marshall disassociates Foucault also from the recent trend (a major shift he calls

    it) in the rising neo-liberal discourse to divert the notion of autonomy away from

    its traditional liberal sense; to refer to the autonomous chooseras part of the widerdiscourse of a dominant consumer culture fed by a free-market economic agenda.

    The main difference he notes between the two conceptions of autonomy is that in

    traditional liberalism the autonomous selfs power of choice was authentic, while

    the neo-liberal autonomous chooser is merely a creature of consumerism, whose

    formative forces effectively constitute the states new technologies of government

    with education playing its part.

    This, indeed, is a crucial objection against continuing to make the liberal notion

    of personal autonomy the aim of education. The situation, Marshall points out, was

    well-understood by Lyotard, but where does it leave us with Foucault? A proper

    Foucauldian response to neo-liberalism, in Marshalls view, is an increased vigi-

    lance, and an increased imagination and inventiveness, to deal with the complex

    problem it represents. But what about something more positive? Marshall suggestsa neo-social democratic approach to these crises of education (and the welfare

    state) and the increasing demand for autonomy. This, however, is not, he

    remarks, explicit in the extant works of Foucault (1996, p. 193). And he is right

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    8/14

    170 KENNETH WAIN

    in this respect, Foucault, however, described care for self as having both an active

    erotic and a political dimension with important pedagogical implication. True, he

    remained unwilling to develop a political theory or position out of the elements of

    an ethos of self-care, to tell people what to do, but they clearly point to a form of

    social and political responsibility which renders the characterization of Foucaultas a mere prophet of extremity, or of the nihilistic politics of transgression for

    its own sake, as inaccurate as the judgement that he is a mere destroyer. In any

    case, Marshalls book cries out for a critical chapter on Foucaults politics. His tacit

    assumption that Foucault is a straightforward anarchist will not do.

    Liberalism, Liberal Education and Autonomy

    One gets the feeling that Marshall may have felt the need for his concluding chapter

    because he may have felt that, by the end, the book had lost its sense of direction.

    The chapter could be read as an effort to recapture the books central thrust, to

    return it to its advertised focus, the issue of liberal autonomy and education, afterthe detours of the previous chapters. But it does not solve the books problems in

    this respect. For some reason or other the author seems to have been determined

    to include in it the whole array of themes about Foucault explored in his earlier

    articles. Either that or he did not have enough mileage on his central theme to

    justify a book about it and had to resort to other themes on Foucault to beef it up.

    The result is that it struggles for coherence. Somehow I also got the feeling that

    Marshall had not worked his material enough into a book. It does not help either

    that the book is littered with gross typographical and other errors of production

    of different kind, beginning with the contents page itself, errors which certainly

    should not feature in a publication of this standard. The problem in this case, of

    course, is with the books production not with its writing, but production errors are

    off-putting and do detract from a books overall quality.Apart from its biographical purpose, which is aimed at education students for

    whom, in general, Foucault is a shadowy presence, Marshall uses Chapter 2 of

    the book to introduce Foucault the genealogist. This he does by illustration, by

    describing the writing of Discipline and Punish. In Chapter 7 he also illustrates

    an alternative Foucauldian philosophical approach to education by drawing on

    the same book, thus confirming my earlier thesis that Discipline and Punish has

    remained Foucaults central work for him. In describing their impact on his work

    in Chapter 2, Marshall emphasises that Foucaults readings of the writers who

    influenced him, including Heidegger and Nietzsche, were never straightforward

    but always subversive; all who were adopted were not merely adopted, but adapted

    and then made to groan (1996, p. 21).

    Having fulfilled the first purpose of his book Marshall passes on to discussliberalism and liberal education. Ignoring its notorious complexity he divides

    the liberal political tradition into three strands each corresponding with different

    understandings of freedom, individualism and state power. Apart from the dubious

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    9/14

    REVIEW ARTICLE 171

    merit of this kind of typology, one is struck by the absence from his account

    of the established superstars of liberal political philosophy today like Rawls,

    Gutmann, Ackerman, Taylor, Habermas, Dworkin, Walzer. Instead of drawing on

    recent liberal political theory he classifies his liberalisms around the theories of

    the classical pregenitors of liberalism, Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, Voltaire, Mill,Spencer, Hayek, etc. His only reference to a contemporary is to Robert Nozick

    who he treats, however, as a straightforward descendant of Locke. The obvious

    question that occurs to ones mind is, why classify at all? The answer in this case is

    that Marshall wanted to find a manageable way of approaching liberal philosophy

    of education. His preliminary classification of liberalism enables him to classify

    liberal philosophy of education also into three corresponding strands.

    Still, I am not sure that he needed to classify liberal philosophy of education into

    strands either. All that seemed necessary for him at this stage was to establish, as

    he does, that all these liberalisms and possible variations on them possess a number

    of common elements which find their articulation in the notion of rational personal

    autonomy which they all share. Marshalls three strands of liberal philosophy of

    education are represented by the work of R.S. Peters, John Dewey and Kenneth

    Strike. Peters is taken to represent the British liberal philosophical tradition. Strike

    the neo-liberal in the Hayek mode (though Marshall concedes that this position-

    ing is not unproblematic and would probably be challenged by Strike himself).

    But where does Dewey fit in? Surely he doesnt fit within the third strand of

    libertarian liberalism Marshall identifies with Locke and Nozick! At one stage he

    refers in passing to Rortys fascinating thesis about similarities between Dewey and

    Foucault but dismisses it on different grounds. One, more credible, option would

    be to align Dewey with the communitarian liberalism of Arendt and Habermas.

    Perhaps he could have taken up another suggestion of Rortys that Deweys politics

    are consonant with Rawlss post-A Theory of Justice brand of liberalism which, in

    Rortys view, prioritizes democracy over philosophy. At the very least, Rortyattempts to open up a strand of contemporary liberalism other than the three identi-

    fied by Marshall consonant with Deweyan politics, one Foucault would have been

    sympathetic with, which does not begin politics with a foundational philosophical

    statement about truth or justice, or about human nature.

    One thing is apparant; Dewey does not fit Marshalls three-fold typology. In

    fact, Marshall is sometimes plainly wrong about Dewey. One case in point is when

    he includes Dewey among those philosophers who focus on the teachers authority

    in the classroom instead of on the micro-technologies of power at work in it. This

    characterisation does not square with Deweys view about the regulative role of

    the social environment, of living together, which led him to discuss power in

    terms of control, guidance and direction rather than the personal authority of the

    teacher. What is at issue for Dewey is how power can be exercised non-coercivelywithin democratic environments. His answer is that it must be internal, achieved

    through that identity of interest and understanding (1916, p. 39) reached by

    players participating in a game, not as a mere function of the teachers authority,

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    10/14

    172 KENNETH WAIN

    however this authority may be justified. Indeed, if anything, Dewey has been

    criticised for neglecting the importance of the teachers authority. This is not, in

    my view, correct either. But the point I want to make here is that to join Dewey

    with Peters as one for whom authority is the correct concept for the discussion

    of social control (Marshall, 1996, p. 78), is off the mark. Moreover, Deweysdetailed discussion of control, direction and guidance inDemocracy and Education

    contradicts Marshalls other claim about Dewey that for him power is emphatically

    off stage. Indeed, this discussion amounts to an in-depth treatment of the different

    forms of power Dewey deemed relevant to schooling.

    But these are particular examples of the the more general problem with

    Marshalls treatment of Dewey which is that Dewey does not really fit into his

    typology of liberalism, and cannot therefore be assigned positions that are typi-

    cally liberal. Indeed, Dewey does not fall easily within the liberal category at

    all, not because he did not share the traditional liberal values and the liberal faith

    in reform as a tool of progress, but because his emphasis on the social has often

    been criticised by traditional liberals as bordering on the illiberal. This is because

    it runs counter to the unconditional value liberalism places on individuality. The

    charge of communitarianism which was frequently levelled against him in the

    past was a sinister one for old liberals but holds less water in todays intellectual

    climate. There are well-known sections of Deweys writing (including Democracy

    and Education) where he defended and celebrated individuality, or at least a certain

    version of individuality, and his view of community was far from collectivist

    in form or spirit. But Deweys case illustrates perfectly the perils of employing

    classifications such as Marshalls, and one cannot help suspecting that the reason

    why he avoids the more contemporary liberal political philosophers is perhaps

    because, like Dewey, they defy such easy categorisation and would hopelessly

    complicate matters for him.

    And, of course, these same remarks hold true also for Marshalls classifica-tion of liberal educational philosophies; it may be neat and pat and easy to work

    with, but it does no justice at all to the complex phenomenon that has come to

    be recognised as liberal philosophy of education over the past forty or fifty years.

    Curiously again (because he does not explain it) it leaves out all the contemporary

    protagonists (Strikes book dates back fifteen years) within liberal philosophy of

    education. And this ommission is more serious than the ommission of the political

    philosophers, because, as he claims himself The concern of this book has been to

    mount a critique of liberal education, in particular the notion inherent in liberal

    thought of developing personal autonomy (1996, p. 137), and one queries the

    extent to which such a critique is adequately served by a discussion of Peters,

    Dewey and Strike, who cannot collectively be taken as representing the differences

    within liberal philosophy of education today. Marshall tries to reassure us that thisdoes not really matter because Regardless of these differences . . . within the liberal

    framework there is a certain view of human beings and society, which permits a

    general view of education to be articulated, formulated and put into practice, and

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    11/14

    REVIEW ARTICLE 173

    that within liberalism and liberal education there is a very strongly espoused thesis

    about the centrality of rational autonomy, which is reflected in liberal theories of

    schooling. But why, in that case, to return to my previous point, complicate matters

    with dubious typologies?

    Autonomy Revisited

    Marshall follows his chapter on liberalism and liberal education with a more

    detailed discussion of autonomy in education arguing with Colin Lankshear (1982)

    that many who wish to advance personal autonomy as an educational aim are also

    prepared to argue for considerable constraint upon the young (Marshall, 1996,

    p. 83). The examples of the many he cites are Dearden, Peters, Hirst, and White.

    He goes on to describe several possible conflicting positions on autonomy (1996,

    p. 89) and asks how Foucault would consider them. Since he considered persons

    to be socially constructed beings, he would certainly reject, Marshall rightly points

    out, the idea that being autonomous is part of human nature. Moreover, as socialconstructs, Foucault showed that modern individuals are not constituted as free

    individuals but as docile beings, beings who are disciplined to be governable. Their

    education, of course, contributes significantly to this outcome. Thus, in reality,

    Marshall concludes his Foucauldian critique of the liberal ideal of cultivating

    personal autonomy, what appears as an ethical and educational ideal is a masquer-

    ade for the political aim of constituting selves as subjects of a certain kind (1996,

    p. 111). Which, in reality, is no startling thesis since the Marxists got there before

    Foucault some time ago.

    The question which follows is whether Foucault, like Horkheimer and Adorno

    before him (with whom he shares the joint influences of Heidegger and Weber),

    represents the socially constructed individual as a totally administered being also.

    Whether, in short, his account of power leaves us with any room for notions offreedom and autonomy, and, therefore, education, to be meaningful. Or whether

    we should merely accept our fate as determined beings. Marshall rightly answers

    no to these questions. Foucaults account of power, he says, becomes mellowed by

    notions of resistance, freedom and hope (1996, p. 90). I would say that becomes

    mellowed, is a mild way of putting it and, again, fails to do justice to Foucaults

    account of the workings of genealogy in the final ethical stage of his intellectual

    development. This phase, represented also in the last two volumes of The History

    of Sexuality, turns on Foucaults perception that the replacement in priority of the

    Greek maxim, to care for thyself, with the maxim, also Greek, to know thyself,

    was fundamentally mistaken (p. 103). But it also rested on Foucaults radical

    reassessment of the function of genealogy which I referred to earlier.

    Marshall does identify an emerging liberal critique in the work of StefaanCuypers which represents care for the self as a fundamental educational aim.

    Cuypers, however, does not wish to replace personal autonomy with self care, he

    believes that we need both. Marshall disagrees insisting that there are too many

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    12/14

    174 KENNETH WAIN

    problems with personal autonomy to justify retaining it as an educational aim, he

    also finds Cuypers notion of caring for oneself distinctly different from Foucaults

    and unacceptable on several grounds. Marshall concludes the chapter by noting

    that none of the accounts of autonomy furnished by the liberal philosophers of

    education he discusses would be acceptable to Foucault. But, again the questionarises by itself, what did Foucault say about freedom and self care himself? It

    is not taken up in Education and Power either, the next chapter of the book.

    Instead, Marshall returns to the argument already more than amply explored in

    his earliest articles on Foucault and education, that power is essentially off-stage

    in philosophy of education and needs to be brought to centre-stage, and that the

    discourse on power is really suppressed by a liberal philosophical framework which

    operates with an inadequate conception of power and shows a marked propensity

    to talk about authority instead.

    The chapter contains a detailed account of Foucaults twin notions of bio-

    power and governmentality which are closely tied to his other complementary

    notion of policing as the central characteristics in the display or power in the

    modern state. Marshall also challenges Walzers view that Hobbes was Foucaults

    major intellectual antagonist, arguing instead that his real opponent was Rousseau.

    Though Foucaults characterisation of juridico-discursive power depends heavily

    on legal models from Hobbes to Austin, Marshall argues, governance and bio-

    power are Foucaults real targets and Hobbes and juridico-legal theories only

    a target because they mask bio-power (p. 118). Again Marshall continues to

    pursue Foucaults account of power as an oppressive instrument in the chapter. He

    describes Foucaults account of bio-power, of the political technology of the body

    (p. 127), and observes that its minute techniques are at work also in the school, its

    practices creating a complex power/knowledge web which disciplines the bodies

    and minds of children in different ways, whether in their best interests or not.

    Liberal philosophers of education, he observes, have viewed power as neces-sarily negative, as always acting contrary to childrens interests. Their tendency to

    focus on authority, he argues, means that they have ignored the actual mechanisms

    of power which feature in the classroom, though he admits to recent important

    correctives to this trend coming mainly from Burbules and White. The overall

    conclusion of the chapter is again damning for liberal education which in its

    pursuit of personal autonomy, masks the power relations operating, and hence the

    thrust for governmentality, by its talk of authority and the development of mind

    (1996, p. 215). Again, it follows from Foucaults genealogy of power/knowledge.

    But what are the positive things Foucault had to say about power and freedom, how

    can they be turned into classroom strategies that operate in the childrens interests?

    Perhaps they cannot, but surely the question requires serious discussion!

    In Chapter 7 entitled Doing Philosophy of Education. which is his finalchapter apart from the Conclusion, Marshall refers to a current impasse of

    philosophy of education. Foucaults genealogical writing, he contends, shows us

    a way out of it. He illustrates how by returning to the theme of the punishment

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    13/14

    REVIEW ARTICLE 175

    of children, contrasting Foucaults approach to the subject with the traditional

    analytic approach. What is particularly interesting in this chapter is the blending

    of Wittgenstein into the Foucauldean critique, but, again, this is not new either, it

    reproduces an article which Marshall had already published in 1995. His critique

    of punishment, and his argument about the deficiencies of the liberal approachto power and autonomy, is where Marshalls own critique on modern education

    is most interesting and persuasive. It is in this chapter that he elaborates briefly

    on Foucaults notion of freedom as transgression, but he fails to pursue it for its

    potential educational implications, for example in terms of cultivating the strong

    poet, which Rorty, for instance identifies as the function of liberal universities in a

    postmetaphysical age.

    The answer to the question why occurs explicitly on page 216 of the book where

    Marshall summarizes his approach to Foucault in the following way: A general

    conclusion which might be drawn, he says, is that Foucault has little to offer

    to practising educators in terms of a way forward or a way out. This conclusion

    explains Marshalls failure to examine the positive side of Foucaults genealogical

    writing, his elaboration of freedom or autonomy, the new counter-modern ethos

    of responsibility, in terms of self-care which could have rendered the book, in

    my view, complete. Given his dismissal of Cuyperss model Marshall could have

    turned to Foucault himself for clues about how self-care could be an educational

    aim teachers could work with against the humanistic definitions of autonomy.

    Rortys account of how transgression could be a form of education through the

    cultivation of poetic irony which edifies the individual and enables self-overcoming

    could have provided a starting point. Rorty, of course, limits the cultivation of

    poetic irony to ones private life, socialisation into the prevalent culture is the form

    he gives public education, and this solution runs smack into Foucaults critique

    of power.

    But what about an account of self-care which restores unity to the educationalenterprise? This would, indeed, be a revolutionary possibility and certainly one

    worth exploring in-depth in a world where education is in crisis and where the

    individualism of a market mentality is constantly glorified, particularly in the

    media. Foucault himself sought it in pre-modern times, in antiquity. Like so many

    other philosophers discontented with modernity he goes back to classical Greek

    and Roman times when the ethical project, in his view, took the wrong turn. I feel

    that Marshall has surrendered too readily to the prevalent view among Foucaults

    Anglo-saxon critics that Foucault has nothing politically interesting or meaningful

    to say to education. Taking that judgement up critically should be the first step

    towards a deeper analysis of Foucault and education which could be exceedingly

    rewarding.

  • 7/29/2019 Fuko, autonomija

    14/14

    176 KENNETH WAIN

    Notes

    1 The list could have included Cleo H. Cherryholmess (1990) Power and Criticism, Teachers

    College Record, but Cherryholmess book appeared in the same year as Marshalls article.2 See, for instance, Jeffrey Roths review article Of What Help is He? A Review of Foucault and

    Education, American Educational Research Journal, Winter 1992, Vol. 29, No. 4, pp. 683694:The problem is that Foucaults ideas about the constitution of human subjects have been transferred

    almost exclusively as negative critique, emphasizing domination, silencing, and categorization

    (p. 683).

    References

    Ball, S. (ed.): 1990, Foucault and Education: Disciplines and Knowledge, Routledge, London.

    Foucault, M: 1984, What is Enlightenment?, in P. Rabinow (ed.), The Foucault Reader, Penguin,

    Harmondsworth.

    Greene, M: 1983, Foucault, Structuralism, Hermeneutics, and Education: a Perspective, Compara-

    tive Education Review (Fall) 2(2), 105110.

    Marshall, J.D.: 1989, Foucault and Education, Australian Journal of Education 33(2), 97111.

    Marshall, J.D.: 1990, Asking philosophical Questions about Education: Foucault on Punishment,Educational Philosophy and Theory 22(2), 8192.

    Marshall, J.D.: 1995, Wittgenstein and Foucault: Resolving Philosophical Puzzles, Studies in

    Philosophy and Education 14, 329344.

    Martin, L.H., Gutman, H. and Hutton, P.H. (eds.): 1988, Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with

    Michel Foucault, Tavistock Publishers.