hobbes on justice, property rights, and self-ownership

28
1 This is the draft of an article forthcoming in History of Political Thought (2015) PLEASE DO NOT CITE THIS DRAFT [email protected] HOBBES ON JUSTICE, PROPERTY RIGHTS, AND SELF-OWNERSHIP 1 This paper explores the conceptual relations Hobbes perceived between justice, law, and property rights. I argue that Hobbes developed three distinct arguments for the State-dependency of property over time: the Security, Precision, and Creation Argument. On the last and most radical argument, the sovereign creates all property rights ex nihilo through distributive civil laws. Hobbes did not achieve this radically conventionalist position easily: it was not defended consistently until the redefinition of distributive justice as a virtue of arbitrators in Leviathan. The argument is partly advanced as a critique of C.B. Macpherson’s possessive individualist reading of Hobbes. KEYWORDS: Thomas Hobbes; property; justice; self-ownership; C.B. Macpherson INTRODUCTION Hobbes’s views on property are rarely discussed in great detail. 2 Stephen Buckle omits him from his study of natural law theories of property on the grounds that Hobbes has ‘no place for a 1 For valuable comments on earlier drafts, thanks is due to Adrian Blau, Al Martinich, David Runciman and especially Quentin Skinner, as well as to audiences at a Graduate Conference in the History of Political Thought, Queen Mary, Univ. of London, and the Second Meeting of the European Hobbes Society, King’s College London (both in May 2012). 2 Abbreviations and editions used: BH: Behemoth, or The Long Parliament, ed. Paul Seaward (Oxford, 2009). DCv: On the Citizen, ed. Richard Tuck and Michael Silverthorne (Cambridge, 1998). DIB: Grotius, De Iure Belli ac Pacis, ed. Richard Tuck (Indianapolis, 2005). DH: ‘De Homine’, in Man and Citizen, ed. Bernard Gert (Indianapolis, 1991). DPS: ‘A Dialogue Between a Philosopher and a Student, of the Common Laws of England’, in Thomas Hobbes. Writings on Common Law and Hereditary Right, ed. Alan Cromartie and Quentin Skinner (Oxford, 2005). EL: The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic, ed. J.C.A. Gaskin (Oxford, 1994). EW: The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, ed. William Molesworth (London, 1839-45). L: Leviathan, ed. Noel Malcolm (Oxford, 2012). LL: ‘Latin Leviathan’, in Leviathan, ed. Noel Malcolm (Oxford, 2012). OL: Opera Philosophica quae Latine Scripsit, ed. William Molesworth (London, 1839-45). Where applicable, references are to chapter and paragraph, otherwise to page number.

Upload: kuleuven

Post on 19-Jan-2023

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

1

This is the draft of an article forthcoming in History of Political Thought (2015)

PLEASE DO NOT CITE THIS DRAFT

[email protected]

HOBBES ON JUSTICE, PROPERTY RIGHTS, AND SELF-OWNERSHIP1

This paper explores the conceptual relations Hobbes perceived between justice, law, and property

rights. I argue that Hobbes developed three distinct arguments for the State-dependency of

property over time: the Security, Precision, and Creation Argument. On the last and most radical

argument, the sovereign creates all property rights ex nihilo through distributive civil laws. Hobbes

did not achieve this radically conventionalist position easily: it was not defended consistently until

the redefinition of distributive justice as a virtue of arbitrators in Leviathan. The argument is partly

advanced as a critique of C.B. Macpherson’s possessive individualist reading of Hobbes.

KEYWORDS: Thomas Hobbes; property; justice; self-ownership; C.B. Macpherson

INTRODUCTION

Hobbes’s views on property are rarely discussed in great detail.2 Stephen Buckle omits him from

his study of natural law theories of property on the grounds that Hobbes has ‘no place for a 1 For valuable comments on earlier drafts, thanks is due to Adrian Blau, Al Martinich, David Runciman and

especially Quentin Skinner, as well as to audiences at a Graduate Conference in the History of Political Thought,

Queen Mary, Univ. of London, and the Second Meeting of the European Hobbes Society, King’s College London (both

in May 2012). 2 Abbreviations and editions used: BH: Behemoth, or The Long Parliament, ed. Paul Seaward (Oxford, 2009). DCv: On the

Citizen, ed. Richard Tuck and Michael Silverthorne (Cambridge, 1998). DIB: Grotius, De Iure Belli ac Pacis, ed. Richard

Tuck (Indianapolis, 2005). DH: ‘De Homine’, in Man and Citizen, ed. Bernard Gert (Indianapolis, 1991). DPS: ‘A

Dialogue Between a Philosopher and a Student, of the Common Laws of England’, in Thomas Hobbes. Writings on

Common Law and Hereditary Right, ed. Alan Cromartie and Quentin Skinner (Oxford, 2005). EL: The Elements of Law,

Natural and Politic, ed. J.C.A. Gaskin (Oxford, 1994). EW: The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, ed.

William Molesworth (London, 1839-45). L: Leviathan, ed. Noel Malcolm (Oxford, 2012). LL: ‘Latin Leviathan’, in

Leviathan, ed. Noel Malcolm (Oxford, 2012). OL: Opera Philosophica quae Latine Scripsit, ed. William Molesworth

(London, 1839-45). Where applicable, references are to chapter and paragraph, otherwise to page number.

2

theory of property’.3 James Tully and Jeremy Waldron mention Hobbes only in passing, while

Peter Garnsey summarizes his position on property in a single footnote.4 Even Hobbes-scholars

have by and large ignored his views on property. The only article in English devoted to it dates

from the 1970s.5 Bracketing a noteworthy essay by Y.C. Zarka,6 research on the subject is limited

to a few scattered remarks.7 One explanation for this general neglect is that Hobbes’s position on

property is difficult to miss: time and time again he insists that private property rights are

introduced by the civil laws and remain dependent on the will of the sovereign.8 As we know

what Hobbes’s ideas on property are (whatever they amount to: he hasn’t got a theory), why study

them further?

This paper aspires to show that Hobbes does have a theory of property. It deserves that

title because his views on property are systematically linked with such prima facie disparate notions

as justice, distributive laws and the right to all things. Due to these theoretical interconnections,

the mentioned scholarly neglect has repercussions for our understanding of Hobbes’s political

theory as a whole. His views on distributive justice, in particular, suffer from scholarly

misunderstanding as a result. The topic is studied, if at all, from the perspective of equity or

natural law, the central question being whether equity sets substantive limits to the sovereign’s

conduct.9 Yet distributive justice plays a much larger role in his political theory. This role cannot

3 Stephen Buckle, Natural Law and the Theory of Property: Grotius to Hume (Oxford, 1991), p. 3. 4 James Tully, A Discourse on Property: John Locke and his Adversaries (Cambridge, 1980); Jeremy Waldron, The Right to

Private Property (Oxford, 1988); Peter Garnsey, Thinking about Property: From Antiquity to the Age of Revolution (Cambridge,

2007), 136n. Hobbes’s views on property are discussed neither in Richard Tuck, Natural Right Theories: Their Origin and

Development (Cambridge, 1979), nor in Alan Ryan, Property and Political Theory (Oxford, 1984). 5 B.B. Lopata, ‘Property Theory in Hobbes’, Political Theory, I (2) (1973), pp. 203-18. 6 Y.C. Zarka, ‘La Propriété chez Hobbes’, Archives de Philosophie, LV (4) (1992), pp. 587-605. 7 The most extensive of these are Richard Schlatter, Private Property: The History of an Idea (Woking and London, 1951),

pp. 138-43; M.M. Goldsmith, Hobbes’s Science of Politics (New York, 1966), pp. 193-4, 197-200, 207-12; T.A. Horne,

Property Rights and Poverty: Political Argument in Britain, 1605-1834 (Chapel Hill, NC, 1990), pp. 24-32; J.P. Sommerville,

Thomas Hobbes: Political Ideas in Historical Context (London, 1992), pp. 49-51, 54-6, 87-95, 163-5; Christopher Pierson,

Just Property: A History in the Latin West, Vol. I: Wealth, Virtue, and the Law (Oxford, 2013), pp. 172-8, 186-8, 252. 8 E.g. EL: 24.2; EL: 27.8; DCv: ED: 9; DCv: 6.15; DCv: 12.7; DCv: 14.9; DCv: 17.10; L: 15.3; L: 18.10; L: 24.5; DPS:

9-10; DPS: 36-7. 9 E.g. Larry May, ‘Hobbes on Equity and Justice’, in Hobbes’s Science of Natural Justice, ed. Craig Walton and Paul

Johnston (Dordrecht, 1987), pp. 241-52; William Mathie, ‘Justice and Equity: And Inquiry into the Meaning and Role

of Equity in the Hobbesian Account of Justice and Politics’, published in the same volume, pp. 257-76; D.D.

Raphael, Concepts of Justice (Oxford, 2001), pp. 65-79; Dieter Hüning, ‘From The Virtue of Justice to the Concept of

Legal Order: The Significance of the suum cuique tribuere in Hobbes’s Political Philosophy’, in Natural Law and Civil

3

be understood, I submit, as long as distributive justice is examined in isolation from his theory of

property. The converse also holds: I argue that Hobbes’s developing insights concerning

distributive justice drastically altered the nature and status of property rights.

This paper explores the conceptual connections Hobbes perceived between justice, law,

and property by critically assessing one of the few sustained analyses of the topic: the one offered

by C.B. Macpherson. In The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism (1962) and various smaller

writings, Macpherson argued that Hobbes’s political theory presupposes an essentially capitalist

conception of man and society: man as natural proprietor over his own person and capacities,

society as a set of market relations, and the state as a human contrivance instituted for the

protection of the individual’s property in his person and goods.10 These capitalist assumptions

partly manifested themselves, Macpherson claimed, in Hobbes’s reduction of justice ‘to a market

concept’.11 Hobbes rejected non-market standards for assessing the justness of contracts and

allocations, insisting instead that the value of all things (including human beings) is determined

wholly by demand. While Macpherson’s possessive individualist reading of Hobbes is not widely

acclaimed nowadays,12 his claims about justice appear relatively uncontroversial – that is to say,

critics have by and large refrained from challenging them.13 In fact, a prominent recent article on

Sovereignty, ed. Ian Hunter and David Saunders (New York, 2002), pp. 139-52; Perez Zagorin, Hobbes and the Law of

Nature (Princeton, 2010), pp. 92-5; Dennis Klimchuk, ‘Hobbes on Equity’, in Hobbes and the Law, ed. David

Dyzenhaus and Thomas Poole (Cambridge, 2012), pp. 165-85. 10 Macpherson discusses Hobbes in the following publications: ‘Hobbes Today’, Canadian Journal of Economic and

Political Science, XI (4) (1945), pp. 524-34; The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke (Oxford, 1962);

‘Natural Rights in Hobbes and Locke’, in Political Theory and The Rights of Man, ed. D.D. Raphael (London, 1967), pp.

1-15; ‘Introduction’, in Hobbes: Leviathan, ed. C.B. Macpherson (Baltimore, 1968) pp. 9-63; ‘Leviathan Restored: A

Reply to Carmichael’, Canadian Journal for Political Science, XVI (4) (1983), pp. 795-805; ‘Rise and Fall of Economic

Justice’, in C.B. Macpherson, Rise and Fall of Economic Justice and Other Papers (Oxford, 1985), pp. 1-20; and ‘Hobbes’s

Political Economy’, published in the same work, pp. 133-46. 11 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, pp. 64, 86. 12 On the reception of Macpherson, see James Tully, ‘The Possessive Individualism Thesis: A Reconsideration in the

Light of Recent Scholarship’, in Democracy and Possessive Individualism: The Intellectual Legacy of C.B. Macpherson, ed. J.H.

Carens (New York, 1993), pp. 19-44; Jules Townshend, ‘Hobbes as Possessive Individualist: Interrogating the C.B.

Macpherson Thesis’, Hobbes Studies, XII (1999), pp. 52-75; Michael Bray, ‘Macpherson Restored? Hobbes and the

Question of Social Origins’, History of Political Thought, XXXVIII (1) (2007), pp. 56-90. 13 As claimed by Townshend, ‘Interrogating’, p. 69. An exception is William Letwin, ‘The Economic Foundations of

Hobbes’ Politics,’ in Hobbes and Rousseau: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Maurice Cranston and R.S. Peters (Garden

City, 1972), pp. 155-7.

4

Hobbes on justice plainly endorses Macpherson’s interpretation (albeit largely implicitly).14 Even

without this recent endorsement, Macpherson’s analysis of Hobbesian justice is, in my view,

interesting enough to deserve careful rebuttal. For he duly observed that Hobbes redefined

commutative and distributive justice in such a way that they lose much of their critical potential.

His analysis suffers, however, from a profound misunderstanding of Hobbes’s account of

distributive justice. Or so I will argue.15

My contention is that Hobbes’s account of distributive justice, properly understood,

chimes badly with the distinctively bourgeois theory of property and self-ownership that

Macpherson attributes to Hobbes. The reason is as follows. Hobbes’s two concepts of justice –

commutative and distributive justice – generate two distinct accounts of property. Each account

ascribes a different status to property rights, and assigns a different role to the State.

Macpherson’s interpretation receives some support from Hobbes’s remarks about commutative

justice. However, the account of property developed in his writings on distributive justice is

much less sympathetic to a possessive individualist reading. And it is this account, I argue, that

Hobbes decisively favours from Leviathan onwards.

The paper is structured as follows. Section one discusses Hobbes’s developing insights

concerning commutative and distributive justice. This serves a dual purpose: it allows me to

evaluate Macpherson’s analysis of Hobbes on justice, and it introduces the conceptual

background against which I will examine Hobbes’s theory of property. Section twee and three

differentiate three distinct Hobbesian explanations for the State-dependency of property. The

Security and the Precision Argument, both premised on commutative justice, presuppose provisional

pre-political claims to property. The Creation Argument, premised on distributive justice,

emphatically does not – it states that the sovereign creates property rights at will. Leviathan, I

contend, eventually discards the Security and the Precision Argument in favour of the Creation

Argument. My analysis thus corroborates M.M. Goldsmith’s suggestion that Hobbes did not attain 14 Luc Foisneau, ‘Leviathan’s Theory of Justice’, in Leviathan After 350 Years, ed. Tom Sorell and Luc Foisneau

(Oxford, 2004), pp. 105-22, esp. p. 113. 15 This paper does not engage Macpherson’s main argument for his possessive individualist interpretation of Hobbes.

That argument combines an appeal to Hobbes’s remarks about power and natural right to demonstrate the

competitive and invasive character of Hobbesian agents, with the claim that Hobbes must have assumed a possessive

market society as only that model permits and requires continual non-violent invasion of each man’s powers by those

of others. This argument has been challenged by D.J.C. Carmichael, ‘C.B. Macpherson’s Hobbes: A Critique’,

Canadian Journal for Political Science, XVI (1) (1983), pp. 61-80; Isaiah Berlin, ‘Hobbes, Locke and Professor

Macpherson’, Political Quarterly, XXXV (1964), pp. 444-68; Letwin, ‘Economic Foundations’, pp. 144-52; Peter

Hayes, ‘Hobbes’s Bourgeois Moderation’, Polity, XXXI (1) (1998), pp. 53-74.

5

his radically conventionalist position on property easily. Section four, finally, argues against

Macpherson that natural self-ownership has no place in Hobbes’s theory of property. For

Hobbes, all propriety, including the right to one’s own body, is conventional and presupposes the

State.

1. THE DEATH OF ECONOMIC JUSTICE

In The Rise and Fall of Economic Justice (1985) Macpherson writes: ‘The death of the concept of

economic justice may be said to have been proclaimed by Thomas Hobbes in 1651’.16 Economic

justice is defined trivially as a norm purporting to ‘regulate economic relations in light of some

ethical principle’.17 ‘The received concepts of commutative and distributive justice’, first

explicated by Aristotle, were such norms. Commutative justice calls for fairness in exchange

(both in voluntary exchanges, such as barter and trade, and in involuntary ones, such as murder

and theft). Distributive justice regulates the allocation of common goods (according to merit).

Both norms ‘suppose the validity and the enforcement of standards of reward other than those

determined by the market’.18 According to Macpherson, Hobbes strips the two kinds of justice of

their capacity to assess the moral quality of transactions and allocations by making demand the

standard of both value and merit. Justice is thus ‘reduced to a market concept’.19

It is true that Hobbes effectively dismisses commutative justice as a norm of economic

justice by making demand the measure of value. On the Aristotelian/Thomist theory,

commutative and distributive justice express relations of equality: the equal value of goods

exchanged and the proportionality to merit of goods distributed.20 Hobbes ridicules this view: ‘As

if it were Injustice to sell dearer than we buy; or to give more to a man than he merits’ (L: 15.15).

The fair value, he claims, is merely the price buyers are willing to pay: ‘The value of all things

contracted for, is measured by the Appetite of the Contractors; and therefore the just value, is

16 Macpherson, ‘Rise and Fall’, p. 9. 17 Ibid., p. 2. 18 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, p. 63. 19 Ibid., p. 64, also p. 86. 20 To be precise, Aristotelian commutative justice calls for rectification of unjust transactions (‘corrective justice’). A

third type of particular justice, reciprocal justice, demands the equal value of things exchanged. Aquinas applied the

term ‘commutative justice’ to both corrective and reciprocal justice. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, V 2-5; Aquinas,

Summa Theologiae, II-II, q.61.1-3. On the history of particular justice, see Izhak Englard, Corrective and Distributive Justice:

From Aristotle to Modern Times (Oxford, 2009).

6

that which they be contended to give’ (L: 15.14).21 This is true also of humans: ‘as in other things,

so in men, not the seller, but the buyer determines the Price’ (L: 10.16). Macpherson understood

what this means: ‘Since there is no measure of value except market price, every exchange of

values between freely contracting persons is by definition an exchange of equal values’.22 Any

contract entered is just, by virtue of having been entered. Having no use for a measure of fair

exchange, Hobbes turns commutative justice into the virtue to keep agreements made. ‘To speak

properly, Commutative Justice, is the Justice of a Contractor; that is, a Performance of Covenant,

in Buying, and Selling; Hiring and Letting to Hire; Lending, and Borrowing; Exchanging,

Bartering, and other acts of Contract’ (L: 15.14).23

With regard to distributive justice, Macpherson’s analysis is less compelling. Distributive

justice traditionally calls for the allocation of common goods according to merit. As Aristotle put

it: ‘all men agree that what is just in distribution must be according to merit’.24 Macpherson claims

that ‘there is in Hobbes’s model no measure of merit other than the actual market assessment of

a man’s merit’ .25 Merit is determined by brute market forces (‘what the market will award him’).

It follows that ‘any actual distribution is by definition a distribution in proportion to men’s

merits, and hence just; it cannot be judged by any non-market standard’.26 In support,

Macpherson quotes Leviathan 10.16: ‘the Value, or WORTH of a man, is as of all other things, his

Price; that is to say, so much as would be given for the use of his Power’.27 While prima facie

indicative of the influence of market logic, the quote does not in fact support him. Macpherson

conflates value with merit.28 Hobbes’s attack on distributive justice as traditionally conceived does 21 Also EL: 16.5; DCv: 3.6, DCv: 3.32. 22 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, p. 63. 23 Also EL: 16.5; DCv: 3.6. Samuel Pufendorf later objected: ‘It is so far from being true that justice can be entirely

reduced to keeping one’s pact that, on the contrary, before one can know whether some pact ought to be fulfilled,

one must be certain that it was entered into at the command or at least by the permission of natural laws.’ Pufendorf,

On the Law of Nature and Nations, 1.7.13. Brian Barry voices essentially the same critique in A Treatise on Social Justice

(Berkeley, 1989), pp. 52-4. 24 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, V 3. 25 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, p. 64. 26 Macpherson, ‘Rise and Fall’, p. 9; also Macpherson, ‘Introduction’, pp. 51, 58. 27 Macpherson, ‘Rise and Fall’, p. 9; Macpherson, ‘Hobbes Today’, p. 527; Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, pp. 37-

38; Macpherson, ‘Introduction’, p. 35. Also Foisneau, ‘Leviathan’s Theory’, p. 112. 28 An example of this conflation is: ‘values, entitlements, and hence actual rights, are in fact determined by [market

forces]’. Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, 80. Also Macpherson, ‘Introduction’, 50-1. Keith Thomas mentions this

conflation in ‘The Social Origins of Hobbes’s Political Thought’, in Hobbes Studies, ed. K.C. Brown (Oxford, 1965),

pp. 230-1.

7

not appeal to his ‘demand theory of value’.29 On the contrary, his critique assumes that merit is

analytically distinct from value. A person’s value or price depends on the use she has for others;

what she deserves on the actual conferment of rights through a contract or gift. ‘Merit,

praesupposeth a right, and that the thing deserved is due by promise’ (L: 10.54; also LL: 10.53).

Hobbes’s critique of distributive justice is twofold. First, he argues that it is no ‘injustice if I

give someone more of my own than is due’ – where what is due depends on what was previously

promised (DCv: 3.32).30 ‘Christ himself, witnesses to this in the Gospel’ (DCv: 3.6). Second, in

Leviathan he differentiates between merit in commutative and merit in distributive justice: ‘In

Contract, I Merit by vertue of my own power, and the Contractors need; but in this case of Free

gift, I am enabled to Merit onely by the benignity of the Giver’ (L: 14.17).31 Hobbes denies that

distributive justice is responsive to a previously existing notion of merit (e.g. άξία or dignity,

need). Merit in distributive justice depends on grace alone. Unlike commutative justice,

distributive justice does not track merit, rather it creates it. It does so by apportioning rights to

persons: ‘if [the sovereign] performe his Trust, he is said to distribute to every man his own: and

this is indeed Just Distribution, and may be called (though improperly) Distributive Justice’ (L:

15.15). In short: you deserve what you get, not the other way around.32 Hobbes never says that,

as a matter of distributive justice, rights and goods must be (or are) conferred according to a

person’s market value. Gifts are free: we may give a person as much as we like (EL: 16.5). This

may seem a minor quibble – after all, I agree with Macpherson that merit is no intrinsic property

of a person, but dependent on gifts or promises from others. Yet at bottom is a larger

disagreement: I deny that for Hobbes merit in distributive justice is determined by market forces.

Indeed, it has nothing to do with contracting at all.

To elucidate this claim, more needs to be said about Hobbes’s conception of distributive justice.

Hobbes’s ideas about distributive justice were slow to develop, and were revised quite

dramatically over time. Elements (1640) and De Cive (1642, 2nd edition 1647) talk of distributive

justice or equity as regulating disposal of ‘our own benefits’.33 Not until 1651 did Hobbes identify

distributive justice with the virtue (or natural law duty) of sovereigns: ‘Distributive Justice, the

29 For Hobbes’s ‘demand theory of value’, see L: 10.16; L: 38.25; L: 42.2. 30 Also EL: 16.5; DCv: 3.6; L: 15.15. 31 Also L: 15.14; L: 28.24. Cf. EW: 4, 380-1. 32 The politically convenient implication is that citizens cannot claim a share of the distributed goods. Nor can they

complain that they have received less than they deserve. Johan Olsthoorn, ‘Hobbes’s Account of Distributive Justice

as Equity’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, XXI (1) (2013), pp. 13-33. 33 EL: 16.5; DCv: 3.6; DCv: 3.15; DCv: 3.32.

8

Justice of an Arbitrator; that is to say, the act of defining what is Just’ (L: 15.15). Not incidentally,

the same text first calls commutative justice ‘the Justice of a Contractor’ (L: 15.14).34 ‘The Justice

of a Contractor’ is, in practice, a virtue of citizens – the virtue of keeping one’s promise to simply

obey the sovereign.35 For the sovereign does not promise or covenant anything to anyone – his

role in the original covenant is to receive authority.36 The virtues of commutative and distributive

justice thus apply to citizens and sovereigns respectively.37 We shall see that this reformulation of

the site of distributive justice had important implications for the nature and status of property

rights.

Hobbes supported his redefinition of distributive justice as a virtue of arbitrators with a

second redefinition. From Leviathan onwards, he began thinking about distributive justice in

terms of the old Roman law definition of justice, associated with Ulpian (c.170-223): ‘justice is

the constant and perpetual will to give everyone his due/own’ (suum cuique tribuere).38 Scholastics

usually took this formula to signify both commutative and distributive justice (i.e. particular

justice).39 Hobbes, however, identified the dictum exclusively with distributive justice. He took

the definition literally: distributive justice really means giving each person his due (section three).40

The sovereign gives each his own by distributing ‘Lands, and Goods, [so] that each Man may

know what is proper to him, so as none other might pretend a right thereunto, or disturb him in

the use of the same. This distribution is Justice, and this properly is the same which we say is

ones own’ (DPS: 10).41 In other words, the sovereign fulfils his duty of distributive justice by

instituting rules of propriety. Considered as a norm, distributive justice no longer constitutes a

standard external to the actual division of rights to goods. Rather, since citizens are first given

their ‘own’ through the institution of propriety, distributive justice is the division itself.

34 Cf. EL: 16.5; EL: 17.2; DCv: 3.6; DCv: 3.15. 35 EL: 29.2; L: 42.96; L: 43.4-5; L: 46.31; DH: 13.9; DPS: 36. 36 EL: 21.2-3; DCv: 7.14; L: 18.3-4. 37 Both are examples of natural laws that oblige ‘only some condition of men’ (L: 26.14; cf. BH: 165-6). 38 Esp. L: 15.15; L: 24.5; DPS: 8-10, 35. For Ulpian’s definition, see Corpus Iuris Civilis, Institutiones, 1.1; Digest,

1.1.10. The Institutiones are discussed in L: 26.29-36. On Hobbes’s relation to the Roman law tradition, see Deborah

Baumgold, ‘Slavery Discourse before the Restoration: The Barbary Coast, Justinian’s Digest, and Hobbes’s Political

Theory’, History of European Ideas, XXXVI (4) (2010), pp. 412-8; Daniel Lee, ‘Hobbes and the Civil Law’, in Hobbes and

the Law, ed. David Dyzenhaus and Thomas Poole (Cambridge, 2012), pp. 210-35. 39 E.g. Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, II-II q.58.1; Suárez, De Legibus, I.ii.4. 40 For the suum cuique formula, see DCv: ED.9; DCv: 17.10; DCv: 18.3; L: 15.3; L: 15.15; L: 18.3; L: 24.5; L: 26.8; L:

30.12; L: 43.4; DPS: 8-10, 35. 41 Also L: 15.15, 24; L: 24.5; DPS: 35.

9

Macpherson pays no attention to Hobbes’s creative reworking of the suum cuique formula.

He consequently misunderstands the site and object of Hobbesian distributive justice. He

wrongly assumes that Hobbes has a modern conception of distributive justice as social justice.

This is evident from his claim that ‘[d]istributive justice required that a society’s produce should be

distributed in proportion to men’s merits’.42 Yet neither Hobbes, nor any other seventeenth-

century thinker regarded societal property arrangements as subject to distributive justice. The

concept of social justice, or the fair division of social costs and benefits in a society, is widely

regarded to be at most two centuries old.43 In the early modern period, distributive justice was

understood as regulating the distribution either of one’s own or of common goods. For Hobbes,

distributive justice expresses the moral duty of arbitrators to allocate property rights fairly and

impartially. This suggests that for Hobbes, a person’s desert (what is due to her) is determined by

civil law, and not, as Macpherson claims, ‘by the actual competitive relationship between the

powers of individuals’.44 To corroborate this suggestion and grasp the full implications of

Macpherson’s misreading, the next sections analyse how Hobbes envisioned the relation between

distributive justice and property rights.

Before proceeding further, two last words about Hobbes’s eulogy of economic justice.

First, as noted, for Hobbes distributive justice is not a norm external to the actual division of

goods, but the division itself. Was Macpherson therefore right when he said that Hobbes

dismissed distributive justice as a norm regulating economic relations? Not completely. Hobbes

makes equity the moral norm governing the act of distributing. In fact, he subsumes distributive

justice under equity: ‘[what] men mean by distributive justice… is properly termed EQUITY’ (EL:

17.2).45 The natural law precept of equity commands fair distributions and impartial

jurisprudence, and prohibits corruption and partiality (‘acception of persons’).46 Impartiality and

fairness require treating humans as equals. Equity is met if the sovereign allocates rights to goods

in an equal manner, without regard of person. Subsequent laws of nature clarify what treating

humans as equals in practice requires.47 One of them mentions lot, described by Macpherson ‘as a

42 Macpherson, ‘Rise and Fall’, p. 9, emphasis added; also Macpherson, ‘Introduction’, p. 51. 43 E.g. David Miller, Principles of Social Justice (Cambridge, MA, 1999), pp. 2ff; Samuel Fleischacker, A Short History of

Distributive Justice (Cambridge, MA, 2004); Brian Barry, Why Social Justice Matters (Cambridge, 2005), pp. 4-5. 44 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, p. 86. 45 Also DCv: 3.14; DCv: 14.14; L: 15.15; L: 15.24. 46 L: 15.24; also DCv: 14.14; L: 30.15. 47 L: 15.25-28; also EL: 17.3-5; EL: 18.7; DCv: 3.16-18; DCv: 4.14-15.

10

standard deliberately emptied of all social valuation’.48 This is quite wrong. Lot is the morally

sound procedure for allocating indivisible goods which cannot be kept in common because this

procedure alone acknowledges human natural equality (L: 15.26). This brief discussion of equity

evinces that ‘economic justice’ did not die in the hands of Hobbes. It is true that Hobbes

recognized no independent criterion specifying what counts as a just arrangement of rights,

defined prior to the procedure (e.g. wealth, virtue, sex, age). Yet in the form of equity, distributive

justice continued to express non-market norms for the fair distribution of goods.49 While Hobbes

left economic justice seriously wounded, it wasn’t dead just yet.

Second, Macpherson’s explanation of what Hobbes was doing when stabbing at the

received notions of justice is problematic. Macpherson believes that Hobbes was adapting justice

to the new realities of the market-based society: ‘Hobbes is drawing the logical conclusions from

his model of [a possessive market] society’.50 Elsewhere he roundly declares: ‘Hobbes’s problem

was the legitimation of the early capitalist state’.51 It is somewhat surprising that Macpherson

ignores the obvious political advantages Hobbes’s redefinitions bring.52 By denying that justice

constitutes a substantive norm external to civil law, Hobbes ensures that the sovereign cannot act

unjustly. It allows him to claim that ‘there are no authentic doctrines of just and unjust… except

the laws established in each commonwealth’ (DCv: P.8).53 I will not outline these political

benefits further. This would not disprove Macpherson’s thesis, which is after all not about

Hobbes’s motives or intentions, but about ‘the social content of some of his assumptions’.54 It is

possible that Hobbes’s political conclusions are hostile to capitalism, yet based on possessive

individualist assumptions.55 Instead, I will analyse the theory of property implied by Hobbes’s

48 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, p. 64. 49 This paragraph is indebted to Olsthoorn, ‘Hobbes’s Account’. It substantiates the confused but ultimately correct

objection of Berlin to Macpherson that ‘Hobbes does sometimes, however inconsistently, speak of iniquitous laws’.

Berlin, ‘Hobbes, Locke’, p. 457. 50 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, p. 64. 51 Macpherson, ‘Hobbes’s Political Economy’, p. 145. 52 As noted by Letwin, ‘Economic Foundations’, pp. 156-7. 53 Also EL: 29.8; DCv: 6.9; DCv: 12.1; DCv: 17.10, 14; L: 18.10; L: 26.4; L: 29.6; L: 42.96; L: 46.11; DH: 13.9; DPS:

30; EW: 4, 370. 54 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, pp. 14-5. 55 Likewise, Macpherson can coherently grant that Hobbes has aristocratic sympathies, while insisting that he has an

essentially bourgeois conception of man and society. Macpherson, ‘Introduction’, p. 52; Townshend, ‘Interrogating’,

pp. 54, 61-3.

11

two concepts of justice. My contention is that justice does not legitimate property allocation by

brute market forces, but rather the arbitrary sovereign demarcation of mine and thine.

2. ENFORCING THE JUSTICE OF CONTRACTORS

Hobbes radicalized the commonplace claim that private property is of conventional origin by

insisting that property is somehow existentially dependent on the State.56 Property rights (as

opposed to de facto possessions, which entail no correlative duties) have no place in the state of

nature.57 Goldsmith has pointed out that ‘Hobbes did not achieve his radical position in regard to

property rights easily’.58 Elements, it is true, already states that private property rights are ‘derived

from the sovereign power’ (EL: 24.2).59 Yet Goldsmith shows, citing a crossed-out paragraph in

Hobbes’s hand in the manuscript of Elements, that Hobbes initially accepted pre-political property

rights acquired through covenants. In its oldest version, the paragraph stated: ‘Of the law of

nature also it is: that entering into peace every man be allowed those rights which he had acquired

by the covenants of others. That is to say, right against him that have covenanted’. In its newer

form: ‘men entering in peace, retain what they have acquired’.60 I believe that Hobbes’s early

struggle with pre-political property rights explains two interpretive problems facing scholars. The

first concerns an anomalous remnant of natural self-ownership (section four). The second

concerns the question of in what sense private property is State-dependent.

We can distinguish three Hobbesian arguments for the State-dependency of property: the

Security, the Precision, and the Creation Argument. Each has independent textual support, and was

endorsed by Hobbes at some point in time. On the Security Argument, private property rights are

56 E.g. EL: 24.2; EL: 27.8; DCv: ED: 9; DCv: 6.15; DCv: 12.7; DCv: 14.9; DCv: 17.10; L: 15.3; L: 18.10; L: 24.5;

DPS: 9-10; DPS: 36-7. 57 On the distinction between property rights and possessions, see DCv: 14.7. Cf. C.B. Macpherson, ‘The Meaning of

Property’, in idem, Property: Mainstream and Critical Positions (Toronto, 1978), pp. 1-13. 58 Goldsmith, Hobbes’s Science, p. 199; M.M. Goldsmith, ‘Introduction’, in Hobbes: The Elements of Law, ed. Ferdinand

Tönnies (London, 1969), pp. xi-iii. 59 Also EL: 20.2; EL: 27.8. Goldsmith’s contention that ‘[i]n the Elements of Law men are expected to acquire property

in the state of nature’ is therefore dubitable. Goldsmith, ‘Introduction’, xiii. Cf. Johann Sommerville, ‘Lofty Science

and Local Politics’, in Cambridge Companion to Hobbes, ed. Tom Sorell (Cambridge, 1996), pp. 256-8. 60 Hobbes, The Elements of Law, ed. Ferdinand Tönnies (London, 1969), p. 89n. The preceding paragraph (EL: 17.2)

states: ‘Seeing then many rights are retained, when we enter into peace one with another, reason and the law of

nature dictateth, Whatsoever right any man requireth to retain, he allow to every other man to retain the same’. Cf. DCv: 3.14; L:

15.22.

12

non-existent in the natural condition because general insecurity invalidates any contract by which

agents could bind themselves to respect the rights of others. ‘Covenants, without the Sword, are

but Words, and of no strength to secure a man at all’ (L: 17.1). On this argument, the State does

not create property rights, but merely provides the safety necessary for private contracts to be

valid. Presumably, the first such contracts involved no transfers of rights (each agent already

having a right to everything). Rather, agents promised each other to refrain from interfering with

some particular set of goods.61 Danger rendered all such promises void – until the State with its

coercive power to punish pact-breakers came along.

The Security Argument is the most popular explanation for the State-dependency of

property amongst scholars, perhaps because it fits neatly with Hobbes’s well-known doctrine of

the invalidity of promises outside the commonwealth (L: 15.3).62 The argument sounds rather

impractical though: exclusive property rights would presuppose a myriad of bilateral contracts. By

allowing for tacit consent the worst such impracticalities are overcome – witness the theories of

Grotius and Pufendorf.63 Yet unlike these philosophers, Hobbes never explained when

appropriation from the commons can be assumed to be universally (if tacitly) consented with

(section three). These obvious difficulties notwithstanding, the Security Argument has clear textual

support. Consider the following passage from the 1642 De Cive: ‘each man has his own right and

property by particular contracts, so that one man may say of one thing and another of another thing

that it is his own’ (DCv: 6.1). Later in the same paragraph we learn that private property does not

yet exist in the state of nature ‘because there is as yet none of that security which we showed

above [DCv: 5.3] was a prerequisite of the practice of the natural laws’.

The Security Argument (which really applies to the maxims of natural law generally, and was

also endorsed by Locke and Kant) was from the start accompanied by the Precision Argument.64

The Precision Argument states that for property to be practically efficacious some measure of

precision is required, which humans, in perennial and passionate disagreement, cannot agree 61 Cf. EL: 15.3; EL: 22.3; DCv: 2.4; L: 14.6. 62 E.g. A.P. Martinich, A Hobbes Dictionary (Cambridge, MA, 1995), p. 236; Foisneau, ‘Leviathan’s Theory’, p. 109.

Sommerville attributes a version of the Security Argument to Hobbes: people cannot institute a scheme of property

rights in the natural condition, because the agreement it presupposes cannot be rendered binding due to the

prevailing insecurity. Sommerville, Thomas Hobbes, pp. 54-6, 165; Sommerville, ‘Lofty Science’, p. 257. 63 See the discussion in Buckle, Natural Law, ch. 1-2. Locke still objected: ‘If such a consent as that was necessary,

Man had starved, notwithstanding the Plenty God had given him’. Locke, Second Treatise, 5.28. 64 The terms ‘precision’ and ‘security’ are borrowed from Waldron. He attributes similar considerations to Locke in

The Right to Private Property, pp. 162-7. Jean Hampton ascribes a version of the Precision Argument to Hobbes in Hobbes

and the Social Contract Tradition (Cambridge, 1986), pp. 99-100.

13

upon. Sovereign arbitrage is needed to authoritatively specify what each person is due.65 The civil

law, Hobbes stresses, is the only common measure of mine and thine:

‘[A]ll disputes arise from the fact that men’s opinions differ about mine and yours, just and

unjust… and everyone decides them by his own judgement. Consequently, it is the

responsibility of the same Sovereign Power to come up with rules or measures that will be

common to all, and to publish them openly, so that each man may know by them what he

should call his own and what another’s’ (DCv: 6.9; also EL: 20.10).

Consider an example adapted from Waldron.66 Assume that everyone agrees that A has a right to

the field by the old oak tree. Yet absent agreement about where this field begins and ends (or

which is the oak tree in question) A’s property right will be nigh worthless.

Both the Security and the Precision Argument assume that private individuals have the

capacity to create provisional claims to property. By enforcing and authoritatively specifying

private contracts, the State elevates such pre-political claims into legally effective property rights.

As Zarka writes, ‘political power does not give property its content, but its legal efficacy’.67 The

two arguments thus make sense in relation to commutative justice or ‘the Justice of a Contractor’.

As Foisneau notes in connection to the Security Argument: ‘Since justice is embodied in keeping

covenants, and the state guarantees that these covenants will be honoured, Hobbes is right to say

that the state gives meaning to the terms ‘just’ and ‘unjust’’.68 Let citizens privately buy, sell,

barter, borrow and lend. The State, ‘as guarantor of private contracts, and particularly of private

property’ will make sure that these contracts are kept, keeping in line potential pact-breakers and

peacefully resolving conflicts between contracting parties.69 In Macpherson’s terms, the task of

the State is thus to ‘enforce the rules necessary for the operation of a [market society]’.70

The Security and Precision Argument thus provide some support to Macpherson’s thesis that

Hobbes’s redefined justice to legitimate a capitalist market society. Premised upon commutative

65 EL: 20.10; EL: 29.8; DCv: 6.9; DCv: 17.10, 12; EW: 4, 378. Cf. L: 6.5; L: 46.11; DH: 13.8-9. 66 Waldron, The Right to Private Property, p. 163. 67 Zarka, ‘La Propriété’, p. 589: ‘le pouvoir politique ne donne pas à la propriété sa matière, mais son effectivité

juridique’. 68 Foisneau, ‘Leviathan’s Theory’, p. 109. 69 Ibid., pp. 109, 114. 70 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, p. 98, also 19, 29. Also Macpherson, ‘Hobbes Today’, p. 533; Macpherson,

‘Introduction’, p. 48; Macpherson, ‘Hobbes’s Political Economy’, p. 142.

14

justice (requiring the performance of valid covenants), both arguments assign to the State the

limited task of setting up the conditions required for private contractors to be able to mutually

engage in commercial transactions. Macpherson’s reading receives less support from the Creation

Argument, premised upon distributive justice. And to this argument, I claim, Hobbes eventually

turns in Leviathan.

3. THE CREATIVE JUSTICE OF ARBITRATORS

Instead of providing the conditions that allow individuals to obtain effective property rights, the

State actually creates these rights on the Creation Argument. The sovereign introduces private

property by arbitrarily carving out mine and thine from the common stock, giving each their own

through distributive civil laws. In a possible allusion to Cicero’s De Legibus, Hobbes writes:

‘the Introduction of Propriety… is the act onely of the Soveraign; and consisteth in the Lawes,

which none can make that have not the Soveraign Power. And this they well knew of old,

who called that Nomos, (that is to say, Distribution,) which we call Law; and defined Justice, by

distributing to every man his own’ (L: 24.5).71

The sovereign is thus literally the source of all property. This radically conventionalist theory of

property is defended at length in Leviathan and the Dialogue.72 It is not found in the earlier works

because, I argue, it presupposes a conception of distributive justice as a virtue of arbitrators first

introduced in Leviathan.

The Creation Argument is premised on distributive justice, understood as the will ‘to

distribute to every man his own’ (L: 15.15). The maxim ‘give each person his due’ (suum cuique

tribuere) is often understood metaphorically as ‘respect another’s rights’.73 This is not how Hobbes

understood the dictum. He took the ‘tribuere’ in the formula literally: distributive justice is done

by really giving each his own, i.e. by instituting ‘propriety’ and demarcating mine from thine. Only a

literal reading explains why distributive justice is ‘the Justice of an Arbitrator’ (L: 15.15) – after all,

citizens can respect others’ rights, too. The non-metaphorical reading also explains why Hobbes

associated the formula exclusively with distributive justice (and not also with commutative

justice). Further support is found in the Dialogue: ‘Justice is the constant will of giving to every 71 Cf. Cicero, De Legibus, I 19. 72 L: 15.15; L: 24.5-10; DPS: 9-10, 36, 192-5. 73 E.g. Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, II-II, q.58.1 ad 5.

15

Man his own; that is to say, of giving to every Man that which is his Right, in such a manner as to

Exclude the Right of all Men else to the same thing’ (DPS: 35). It is difficult to see how citizens

can respect another person’s right (to φ) in such a way as to exclude the right of all others (to φ).

The laws which introduce propriety Hobbes calls ‘distributive laws’, in contradistinction

to penal laws.74 Penal laws speak to officers, declaring the penalties that should be inflicted for

specific crimes. Distributive laws speak to citizens, defining the rights citizens have against each

other: ‘the law by which his own right is distributed to each man, that is, the law which lays out

the rules for all things, by which we may know what belongs to us and what to others’ (DCv:

14.6).75 In line with Hobbes’s general conception of law as restraint, the allocation of propriety is

understood not as enabling citizen’s conduct, but as curtailing it by diminishing the amount of

lawful actions open against fellow-citizens.76 A’s propriety in x consists in obligations (imposed

by law) on A’s fellow-subjects not to interfere with A’s enjoyment of x. ‘[W]hat Goods [a person]

may enjoy, and what Actions he may doe, without being molested by any of his fellow Subjects:

And this is it men call Propriety’ (L: 18.10).

Strictly speaking, propriety differs from right. Right, for Hobbes, is a kind of liberty: an

absence of obligation. To have a right to φ means to be at liberty to φ (or not to φ).77 Hobbesian

rights are akin to Hohfeldian privileges.78 Propriety, by contrast, consists in obligations citizens

have with respect to (the goods of) another subject. Injustice consists in actions without right.

Since being under an obligation (not to φ) means lacking the right (to φ), any violation of

propriety is unjust.79 Interfering with A’s right, by contrast, is not unjust per se. On Hobbes’s

theory, acting unjustly towards A consists not in violating A’s right, but in acting towards A

without right (by breaking an agreement or the law). The difference between propriety and right

is important for understanding why individuals have no propriety outside the State – not even in

their own bodies. I return to this below.

Distributive laws establish both what and in what way citizens can trade, thus creating the

legal framework enabling commercial transactions. Liberties permitted to citizens by (the silence

74 DCv: 14.6-7; L: 26.38; cf. EL: 29.6. 75 Also L: 18.10; L: 26.38. 76 EL: 29.5; DCv: 14.3; L: 14.3; L: 26.43; DPS: 37. 77 E.g. L: 14.3; L: 26.44. 78 W.N. Hohfeld, ‘Fundamental Legal Conceptions, I’, in idem, Fundamental Legal Conceptions, ed. W.W. Cook (New

Haven, 1923), pp. 35-50. 79 E.g. DCv: 3.3; L: 14.7. Cf. the marginalia to L: 18.10: ‘Rules, whereby the Subjects may every man know what is so

his owne, as no other Subject can without injustice take it from him’.

16

of) the law include the right ‘to buy, and sell, and otherwise contract with one another’ (L: 21.6).

Hobbes insists, however, that all rules about holding, transferring and enjoying goods (rules of

contracts, of inheritance, &c.) are conventional, and determined by the sovereign.80 Some

distributions (e.g. of spoils of war) are concrete hand-outs to particular persons. Hobbes

discusses the division of land by the victorious Israelites to twelve tribes and by William the

Conqueror to ‘English-men and others’.81 Other distributive laws are more abstract formulations

determining when a property right is obtained, e.g. ‘let that be yours which you have caught with your own

net in the sea’ (DCv: 14.7).

On the Creation Argument, the sovereign institutes propriety ex nihilo, as it were, by

imposing obligations on subjects through distributive laws. The property rights thus created do

not supervene on dikaiologically ineffective pre-existing claims to property (based on first seizure,

private contracts, &c.). Like any sovereign act, the institution of property is arbitrary in the sense

that it depends entirely on the sovereign’s will and discretion (L: 24.6).82 This does not mean that

the distribution of property is morally arbitrary. Equity, Leviathan’s eleventh law of nature, governs

the allocation of propriety. It commands arbitrators to distribute rights to goods equally and

impartially, i.e. without respect of persons:

‘if a man be trusted to judge between man and man, it is a precept of the Law of Nature, that he

deale Equally between them... The observance of this law, from the equall distribution to each

man, of that which in reason belongeth to him, is called EQUITY, and... distributive Justice’

(L: 15.23-4).

Subsequent laws of nature spell out which procedures are equitable for different kinds of goods.83

For example, rights to things which can neither be divided, nor be enjoyed in common, ‘ought to

be adjudged to the First Possessor; and in some cases to the First-Borne, as acquired by Lot’ (L:

15.28).

80 L: 24.10; L: 26.38; DCv: 17.10: ‘Our Saviour… gave no rules by which a citizen could know how to distinguish

what is his own from what is another’s, nor what were the appropriate formulae, words or circumstances for giving,

passing, entering upon, and possessing a thing, so that it would be regarded as rightly belonging to the recipient, entrant or

possessor. The only inference possible is that individual citizens should get those rules from the commonwealth.’ 81 L: 24.6; DPS: 193-201; BH: 266. 82 For Hobbes’s use of ‘arbitrary’, see L: 24.8; L: 28.10; L: 31.10-11; L: 46.35; L: R&C.8. 83 The claim that equity should be understood as a form of pure procedural justice is advanced in Olsthoorn,

‘Hobbes’s Account’, pp. 29-31.

17

It does not follow that primogeniture and first seizure generate provisional claims to property

which are afterwards validated by civil law. Dividing goods according to first seizure undeniably

bases property titles on previous actions (namely, first seizure). Yet the rights to these goods are

created ex nihilo by distributive laws – not by enforcing or specifying pre-existing claims to

property, but by literally giving each his own. The laws of nature expound how rights to goods

should be allocated; they do not themselves allocate rights. Merit, Hobbes insists, is always due to

promise (in contract or gift). Natural law may declare a person worthy to own some good,

because she possessed it first or is the first-born. But worthiness does not equal merit: ‘merit

presupposes a right resulting from a promise, whereas worthiness does not presuppose a right’

(LL: 10.53).84 Moreover, inequitable laws are legally valid, and create property rights just the same.

When the sovereign fails to give a subject what ‘in reason belongeth to him’, he is accountable to

God alone. To his subjects, who authorized his every action, his word is law: ‘whatsoever is

commanded by the Soveraign power, is as to the Subject (though not so always in the sight of

God) justified by the Command; for of such command every Subject is the Author’ (L: 22.15).85

The possibility of legally valid inequitable laws shows that distributive laws create property rights

ex nihilo, even though the sovereign is morally and rationally obliged to divide goods equitably.86

The Creation Argument is not defended before Leviathan. The earlier political tracts

occasionally state that property ‘came… from the commonwealth’ (DCv: 12.7).87 Yet the

argument for this was negative. Since the natural right to all things rules out exclusive property

rights, the latter presuppose alienation of natural right. As this alienation occurred with the

advent of the State, in a sense otherwise unspecified ‘property and commonwealths came into

being together’ (DCv: 6.15).88 A positive argument had to await Hobbes’s redefinition of

84 As Hobbes states in the context of land division: ‘Subjects... have no title at all to demand any part of the Land, or

any thing else but security’ (DPS: 193). 85 Also EL: 21.3; EL: 28.1; DCv: 6.13n; DCv: 7.14; L: 18.6; L: 21.7; L: 24.7; L: 26.23; EW: 5, 177-8; DPS: 31. 86 The same analysis applies to the sovereign’s duty to provide necessities of life to those unable to work. This duty,

too, is owed only to God. L: 30.18; LL: 30.18. Interpreting the laws of nature as guidelines to how property rights

must be allocated, rather than as themselves allocating these rights, removes the tension Pierson perceives between

the sovereign’s absolutism and the “rather extraordinary account of the proper basis of the initial allocation of

property” expressed by natural law. Pierson, Just Property, pp. 176-7, 187. 87 Also EL: 24.2; DCv: 13.17. 88 EL: 20.2; EL: 27.8; DCv: 12.7; DCv: 14.7, 9. DCv: 12.7 forms a confusing exception to this rule. It states that

propriety originated in each person’s renunciation of the right to everything to the commonwealth: ‘Tell me, then,

where this property came to you from, if not from the commonwealth? And from where did it come to the

commonwealth, except that each man transferred his right to the commonwealth?’ The passage suggests that the

18

distributive justice as a virtue of arbitrators. Only then could he justifiably claim that sovereigns

‘distribute to every man his own’ (L: 15.15), so ‘that each Man may know what is proper to him’

(DPS: 10). As argued in section one, this new account of distributive justice, with its concomitant

non-Aristotelian conception of merit, is first developed in Leviathan.89 Henceforth, ‘a person’s

property’ is no longer ‘what he can keep for himself by means of the law’ (DCv: 6.15). It is what

distributive laws have allotted to him.

The new prominence of the Creation Argument is manifest in Hobbes’s justification of

distributive law. Elements and De Cive invoke the Precision Argument: a common measure is needed

to prevent constant quarrels about what belongs to whom.90 On this justification, distributive

laws authoritatively specify to quarrelsome subjects what belongs to each. It thus presupposes

pre-political claims to property (however insecure). Leviathan, by contrast, simply restates the

Creation Argument: by instituting mine and thine, distributive laws end the ‘right to all things; which

necessarily causeth Warre’ (L: 18.10). The claim that the natural right to everything rules out

propriety is already found in Elements.91 Yet such ‘common ownership’ is not, prior to Leviathan,

ended by coercive allocation of exclusive rights through distributive law. Rather, the commonality

of goods was resolved by alienating natural right in private contracts, the validity of which

depends on safety provided by the State.

Why did Hobbes opt for the Creation Argument? The main advantage of this argument is

that it adequately explains which goods are up for trade. The Security and Precision Argument suffer

from Hobbes’s failure to explain how agents can lawfully appropriate from the common stock

and simultaneously impose obligations on all other agents to respect their claim to the

appropriated goods.92 Both arguments assume the existence of provisional claims to property,

which the State merely needs to enforce and specify. Where do these provisional titles come

sovereign redistributes rights received in the original covenant, as noted by Sommerville, Thomas Hobbes, p. 95.

Envisioning how this redistribution works is difficult, given Hobbes’s diverging conceptions of natural right as

liberty-rights, and of propriety as claim-rights. 89 Although De Cive alludes to the suum cuique formula several times (DCv: ED.9; DCv: 17.10; DCv: 18.3), only once

does it hint at its future use of a ‘sovereign virtue’ (DCv: 14.6, on distributive laws). De Cive consistently presents

distributive justice as a virtue of citizens (DCv: 3.6, 15, 32). Furthermore, not the sovereign, but ‘humans have

distributed what nature had placed in common’ (DCv: ED.9, emphasis added). 90 EL: 20.10; EL: 29.8; DCv: 6.9. Cf. DCv: 14.6. 91 EL: 20.2; EL: 24.2; EL: 27.8. Also DCv: 6.1, 15; DCv: 12.7; DCv: 14.7, 9. 92 ‘Hobbes said very little about how property was acquired and transferred – the very questions which made up the

bulk of the work of early modern natural lawyer’. Michael Lobban, ‘Thomas Hobbes and the Common Law’, in

Hobbes and the Law, ed. David Dyzenhaus and Thomas Poole (Cambridge, 2012), p. 40, also pp. 61-2.

19

from? If all the State must do is enforce private contracts, then how did citizens acquire a right to

the goods traded away?

One possible solution to the problem of initial acquisition is postulating a natural right to

the product of one’s labour. Hobbes, however, altogether rejects the possibility of propriety

without consent (section four). Nor does he embrace the historically dominant ground of pre-

political property rights: explicit or tacit consent outside the State. According to Grotius, ‘the

Original of Property… resulted from a certain Compact and Agreement, either expressly, as by a

Division; or else tacitly, as by Seizure’ (DIB: 2.2.2.5). To avoid conflict and promote commodious

living, humans tacitly agreed that long possession and first acquisition generate property titles. As

Pufendorf pointed out, the exclusive nature of propriety requires the consent of all: ‘that one

Man’s seizing on a thing should be understood to exclude the Right of all others to the same

thing, could not proceed but from mutual Agreement’.93 Hobbes’s conflict-ridden state of nature,

however, has no place for stable conventions. People, subject to passions and partial to their own

interests, cannot even agree on what natural law requires (DH: 13.8-9). The only thing humans

agree on is that the natural condition must be left by instituting a final arbitrator to authoritatively

decide on all things that might fall into controversy, including issues of mine and thine.94

Natural law, assented to by all rational individuals, provides criteria for morally adequate

divisions of rights (L: 15.25-8). Yet, as noted, these laws do not themselves allocate rights (‘a

due’); they rather constitute guidelines to arbitrators. For Hobbes, to have something as ‘due’

presupposes some agreement or gift (L: 10.54; L: 14.17). Even the pre-political property rights in

the passage deleted from Elements are acquired by covenants, rather than granted by natural law.

In principle, humans could agree to divide provisional property titles amongst themselves in

accordance with natural law principles. Yet Hobbes’s bleak view on the possibility of extra-Statist

consensus suggests they won’t. This complicates the Security and Precision Arguments, as they

presuppose provisional property titles. Elements suggests that a person can acquire property

outside the commonwealth if another agrees to give away ‘his right of common’ (EL: 17.3).

However, as an older variant points out, this right holds only ‘against him that have

covenanted’.95 Incalculable bilateral agreements are thus needed for full-fledged property rights to

arise.96 In light of perennial disagreement amongst Hobbesian agents, rights are more plausibly

established by sovereign gift, than by countless private contracts. 93 Pufendorf, Of the Law of Nature and Nations, 4.4.4. 94 E.g. EL: 29.8; DCv: 6.9; L: 5.3. 95 Hobbes, The Elements of Law, ed. Tönnies, p. 89n. 96 Goldsmith, ‘Introduction’, xii.

20

Moreover, unlike the two other arguments, the Creation Argument explains why private

property rights do not exclude the sovereign. Hobbes emphasizes throughout his works that

‘propriety’ expresses exclusive rights citizens may uphold against fellow-subjects, not against the

sovereign. ‘Propriety therefore being derived from the sovereign power, is not to be pretended

against the same’ (EL: 24.2).97 Neither the Security, nor the Precision Argument explains why this is

so. How would enforcing private contracts and peacefully arbitrating disputes between

contracting parties make the sovereign rightful master over private property? Elements and De Cive

advance an independent argument instead, maintaining that the sovereign owns the property of

his citizens, just as a master owns the property of his slaves (EL: 22.4; DCv: 8.5). The Creation

Argument, by contrast, can draw on the established Hobbesian doctrine that the sovereign is not

subject to civil law (e.g. L: 26.6; L: 29.9). The sovereign can at will alter and withdraw distributive

laws – and hence the property rights they institute.

What happens to the Security and the Precision Argument in Leviathan? While enforcement of

private contracts and arbitrage of disputes remain necessary for effective property rights, the two

arguments are no longer invoked to explain the State-dependency of property. The Creation

Argument takes over this role.98 However, the Security Argument continues to explain the non-

existence of injustice in the state of nature (L: 15.3). And remnants of the Precision Argument are

found in the doctrine that the civil law constitutes the authoritative measure of good and evil, just

and unjust, &c. (e.g. L: 46.11; DH: 13.8-9).

So far I have spoken about rights over things. Yet in line with seventeenth-century

usage,99 Hobbes understands ‘property’ and ‘propriety’ (Latin: proprietas) in a broad sense as

including any entitlement the right-holder can lawfully claim his own ‘in such manner as to

97 Also EL: 27.8; DCv: 6.15; DCv: 8.5; DCv: 12.7; L: 24.7; L: 29.10-11; L: 30.14; DPS: 200. Pace Macpherson, the

perennial insecurity generated by citizens’ incapacity to uphold property rights against the State, makes Hobbes’s

theory of property not very conducive to the interests of possessing classes. Thomas, ‘Social Origins’, pp. 222-7. 98 The Security Argument recurs in the Latin Leviathan: ‘before the names of Just, and Unjust can have place, there must

be some civil power which can avenge the violation of covenants, and assure to each person that property of his

which he has acquired by covenants’ (LL: 15.3). Cf. L: 15.3; L: 30.1. 99 Locke, for example, employs the term ‘propriety’ in a similarly broad sense. Jacob Viner, ‘“Possessive

Individualism” as Original Sin’, The Canadian Journal of Economics and Political Science, XXIX (4) (1963), pp. 548-59; Alan

Ryan, ‘Locke and the Dictatorship of the Bourgeoisie’, Political Studies, XIII (1965), pp. 210-30; Karl Olivecrona, ‘The

Term “Property” in Locke’s Two Treatises of Government’, Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, LXI (1975), pp. 109-15.

21

Exclude the Right of all Men else to the same thing’ (DPS: 35).100 ‘Propriety’ signify anything that

is ‘proper’ to a person, including a ‘right or liberty of action’ (L: 26.38; also DCv: 17.10). ‘[W]hat

Goods [a man] may enjoy, and what Actions he may doe, without being molested by any of his

fellow Subjects: And this is it men call Propriety’ (L: 18.10). ‘Of things held in propriety, those that

are dearest to a man are his own life, & limbs; and in the next degree, (in most men,) those that

concern conjugall affection; and after them riches and means of living’ (L: 30.12). Propriety is

used interchangeably with meum and tuum.101 The latter terms also have a wide field of application:

‘[C]oncerning Mens Titles… some Goods are Corporeal, as Lands, Money, Cattel, Corn, and

the like, which may be handled, or seen; and some Incorporeal, as Priviledges, Liberties,

Dignities, Offices, and many other good things, meer Creatures of the Law, and cannot be

handled or seen: And both of these kinds are concerning Meum, and Tuum’ (DPS: 45).

This broad conception of propriety may lead us to think that distributive laws bring into

existence all enforceable rights citizens have against each other. Leviathan’s account of distributive

laws and propriety certainly allows for such a radically conventionalist theory. Yet we need not

adopt this reading: perhaps exclusive rights to one’s ‘own life, & limbs’ are generated by the

collective renunciation of the right to everything, rather than by sovereign demarcation of mine

and thine. Nevertheless, on both accounts, law is a necessary condition for the existence of any

exclusive personal rights, including to one’s own body. For Hobbes, all exclusive rights are of

conventional origin, whether created by mutual covenant or by authoritative allocation through

civil law. This insight is problematic for Macpherson: his possessive individualist reading

presupposes an account of natural self-ownership absolutely alien to the philosopher from

Malmesbury.

4. HOBBES’S DENIAL OF NATURAL SELF-OWNERSHIP

A comprising assumption of possessive individualism is natural self-ownership: ‘The individual is

essentially the proprietor of his own person and capacities, for which he owes nothing to

100 Leviathan consistently employs the term ‘propriety’ to signify exclusive rights; it uses ‘property’ only in its technical

sense of ‘accident’ (L: 24.10, L: 31.37, L: 38.4; L: 42.50, L: 44.22). Elsewhere ‘property’ and ‘propriety’ are used

interchangeably (e.g. EL: 22.5, 8; EL: 27.8; DPS: 36, DPS: 192-3). 101 E.g. DCv: 6.15; DCv: 12.7; L: 15.3; L: 24.5.

22

society’.102 What Macpherson exactly means with self-proprietorship is not completely clear. The

term appears to capture at least two ideas: 1) humans as egoistic and infinitely desirous

consumers of utility; and 2) as rightful owners of their own labour (if nothing else). In both

respects individuals owe nothing to society. So understood, possessive individualism has a

psychological and a juridical dimension.103 This section questions the appropriateness of

attributing juridical self-ownership to Hobbes.

Juridical self-ownership is a necessary postulate of the possessive market society model

Macpherson attributes to Hobbes.104 On this model, the primary task of the State is to enforce

and authoritatively define private contracts. Possessive market societies are distinctive in having a

market in labour as well as in products. Commodification of labour presupposes some form of

self-ownership, namely the right to sell one’s labour and its fruits. It is true that Hobbes accepts

commodification of labour: ‘a mans Labour also, is a commodity exchangeable for benefit, as

well as any other thing’ (L: 24.4).105 I deny, however, that this implies that a person is ‘absolute

natural proprietorship of his own capacities’.106

I do not dissent that Hobbesian agents have a bundle of natural rights part of which they

contract away upon entering society. Nor do I dispute that Hobbes took over Grotius’s ‘modern’

concept of subjective rights (‘moral powers’ or freedoms the right-holder has).107 What I deny is

that this bundle of natural rights involves claims of self-ownership in the relevant sense of posing

limits on how others may lawfully treat you. The extensive natural rights Hobbesian agents have

102 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, p. 263, also pp. 3, 54-5, 264. C.B. Macpherson, Democratic Theory: Essays in

Retrieval (Oxford, 1973), p. 199: ‘Man, the individual, is seen as absolute natural proprietor of his own capacities,

owing nothing to society for them. Man’s essence is freedom to use his capacities in search of satisfactions…

Freedom is therefore possession. Everyone is free, for everyone possesses at least his own capacities’. Cf. David

Miller, ‘The Macpherson Version’, Political Studies, XXX (1) (1982), pp. 120-7. 103 Tully, ‘The Possessive Individualist Thesis’, p. 27. On the history of the idea of self-ownership, see Janet

Coleman, ‘Pre-Modern Property and Self-Ownership Before and After Locke; or, when did Common Decency

Became a Private Rather than a Public Virtue’, European Journal of Political Theory, IV (2) (2005), pp. 125-45. 104 Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, pp. 53-68, 105-6, 263-5. 105 For additional support, Macpherson refers to Hobbes’s definition of a man’s value as price (L: 10.16).

Macpherson, Possessive Individualism, p. 37; Macpherson, ‘Hobbes’s Political Economy’, pp. 137-9. Cf. Macpherson,

Possessive Individualism, pp. 66ff. 106 On Hobbesian individuals as commodity-owners, see Macpherson, ‘Hobbes Today’, pp. 532-3; Macpherson,

‘Introduction’, pp. 48-51; Macpherson, ‘Hobbes’s Political Economy’, pp. 137-9. 107 DIB: 1.1.4. See Karl Olivecrona, ‘The Concept of a Right according to Grotius and Pufendorf’, in idem, Law as

Fact (London, 1971), pp. 275-96; Knud Haakonssen, ‘Hugo Grotius and the History of Political Thought’, Political

Theory, XIII (2) (1985), pp. 239-65.

23

cannot be claimed or upheld against others. Individuals are not naturally ‘owed’ such rights. For

Hobbes, all propriety – even the right to one’s body – is conventional, and presupposes the State.

In other words, I deny that natural self-ownership, an essential element of possessive

individualism, is a premise of Hobbes’s theory of property.

Zarka disagrees with me on this point: ‘But this dependency [of property on the State]

cannot be justified except by reference to a more fundamental absolute: the property each has in

his own body and limbs’.108 This is questionable. Hobbes endorses natural self-ownership only

once – in EL: 23.1, in the context of parental rights over offspring: ‘every man by the law of

nature, hath right or propriety to his own body’. Significantly, Hobbes justifies the claim by

reference to EL: 17.2 – the passage Goldsmith discovered was amended. So Hobbes’s only

endorsement of self-ownership purports to be validated by a passage that didn’t even make it into

the 1640 manuscript of Elements. In all likelihood, Hobbes ditched the idea of self-ownership

before 1640, but forgot to remove the reference to it in Element’s chapter on patrimonial

kingdoms. Parallel passages to EL: 17.2 and EL: 23.1 in De Cive and Leviathan confirm this: nil

references to self-ownership.109

For Hobbes, if not for Macpherson,110 property rights are by definition exclusive rights.

‘What is required for a man to have property in goods is not that he may be able to use them, but

that he alone may be able to use them’ (DCv: 14.7, emphasis added). Exclusive property rights are

non-existent ‘in the state of nature where all things are common to all men, the same thing is

both yours and another’s’ (DCv: 14.7).111 Nothing is exclusively mine as long as other agents

retain their right to all things. The right to everything extends ‘even to one anothers body’ (L:

14.4). This claim directly contradicts any meaningful form of self-ownership. It reminds us that

Hobbesian natural rights are peculiar in entailing no corresponding duties on others to respect

these rights. Nothing is due to us by nature; absent any agreement to the contrary, our life, limb

and liberty may be invaded without injustice.

In the natural condition, ‘any one may legitimately subdue or even kill Men, whenever

that seems to be to his advantage’ (DCv: 8.10; also EL: 22.9). The rationale behind this claim is

108 Zarka, ‘La Propriété’, p. 595: ‘Mais cette relativité ne peut se justifier que par référence à un absolu plus

fondamental, la propriété que chacun a sur son corps et sur ses membres’. 109 Compare EL: 17.2 with DCv: 3.14; L: 15.22; L: 21.11-12. Compare EL: 23.1 with DCv: 9.1-2; L: 20.4-5. 110 Macpherson, ‘The Meaning of Property’, p. 4. 111 EL: 14.10; EL: 24.2; EL: 27.8; DCv: ED.9; DCv: 1.10; DCv: 6.15; DCv: 12.7; DCv: 14.7-9. According to

Leviathan, outside the State ‘every thing is his that getteth it, and keepeth it by force; which is neither Propriety, nor

Community; but Uncertainty’. L: 24.5; also L: 13.13; L: 15.3; DPS: 9-10; DPS: 36-37.

24

not that self-defence trumps the rights of other agents not to be harmed. Rather, it is because

reason dictates agents to sincerely attempt to pursue peace as the most advantageous course of

action. The laws of nature do not express duties owed to others; they are mere moral and rational

desiderata. For this reason, absent civil law or some valid agreement to the contrary, no action

can wrong another agent. In the state of nature ‘[m]en are justly killed… for where there is no

law, there no killing, nor any thing else can be unjust’ (EW: 5, 152). For without law, all belongs

to all: ‘Without law every thing is in such sorts every Mans, as he may take, possess and enjoy

without wrong to any Man, every thing, Lands, Beasts, Fruits, and even the bodies of other Men’

(DPS: 9).112

The denial of natural self-ownership is presupposed in Hobbes’s definition of injustice as

‘the not Performance of Covenant’ (L: 15.3). This definition assumes that ‘[t]here can therefore be no

wrong against a particular man except after transfer of a right to him’ (DCv: 3.4n). All wrongs or

injuries are breaches of promises only because nothing is due to us by nature. Had Hobbes

allowed for natural rights that cannot be infringed without injustice, then he could not

consistently have claimed that a ‘wrong and unjust action or failure to act have the same meaning,

and both are the same as breaking an agreement or breaking faith’ (DCv: 3.3).

What about the right of nature? According to Tuck, this right implies ‘a minimal level of

private property, at least of a kind, in the state of nature’, since it entitles everyone ‘to the material

objects necessary for their survival: food, water, housing, and so on’.113 The right of nature

persists in the State in the form of inalienable rights to resist force with force, to take necessities

of life and to refuse dangerous and dishonourable tasks unnecessary for the commonwealth’s

survival.114 Surely inalienable rights are, in some sense, ‘our own’? Perhaps. But they do not

qualify as propriety on Hobbes’s account. For Hobbes, ‘RIGHT, consisteth in liberty to do, or to

forbeare’ (L: 14.3). Inalienable rights permit citizens to disobey the sovereign ‘without Injustice’

(L: 21.10). They are privileges: citizens are ‘under no duty not to’ disobey. Propriety, by contrast,

consists not so much in liberty, as in obligations of others not to interfere with the owner’s

enjoyment of the thing owned. A thing is exclusively my own only if others cannot lay claim to it.

Hobbesian natural right is neither exclusive, nor regulated by justice: others are under no

112 Cf. L: 13.10; DCv: 14.9; L: 18.5; L: 20.10; L: 27.3; DPS: 36. 113 Richard Tuck, Hobbes (Oxford, 1989), p. 70 114 L: 21.10-17. For extensive discussion, see Susanne Sreedhar, Hobbes on Resistance: Defying the Leviathan (Cambridge,

2010).

25

obligation to respect my natural right and may rightly claim the same object.115 Infringing

property rights, by contrast, is unjust – in virtue of violating obligations (injustice being nothing

else than an action without right). The right of nature is logically independent of the justice-

governed entitlements constituting mine and thine. Thus, pace Tuck, the inalienable right to ‘take

the food by force, or stealth’ without which one cannot live does not equal a right of property

(which others should respect as a matter of justice).116 It merely excuses actions that would

otherwise be unjust, and has no normative implications for others. In this respect, the Hobbesian

right of necessity differs markedly from that of the tradition.117

Hobbes’s plain rejection of natural personal rights governed by justice – even to life and

liberty – constitutes a foundational, if often overlooked, premise of his practical philosophy.118 It

contrasts sharply with the central role of the natural suum in Grotius, Pufendorf and Locke.119

The suum ‘denotes the realm over which the individual is sovereign’.120 A failure to respect the

rights naturally due to each agent wrongs the right-holder. According to Grotius, ‘[a] Man’s Life

is his own by Nature… and so is his Body, his Limbs, his Reputation, his Honour, and his

Actions’ (DIB: 2.17.2.1, also DIB: 1.2.5.7). These natural property rights cannot be violated

115 Tuck elsewhere points out that Hobbes endorsed the Roman law idea, revived by sixteenth-century humanists,

that both parties in a conflict may be acting with right. Richard Tuck, The Rights of War and Peace: Political Thought and

the International Order From Grotius to Kant (Oxford, 1999), p. 31. 116 L: 27.26; cf. EL: 17.2; DCv: 3.14; L: 21.12; LL: 30.18. 117 On the right of necessity, see Buckle, Natural Law, pp. 45-8, 108-20, 160-1; S.G. Swanson, ‘The Medieval

Foundations of John Locke’s Theory of Natural Rights: Rights of Subsistence and the Principle of Extreme

Necessity’, History of Political Thought, XVIII (3) (1997), pp. 399-458; John Salter, ‘Grotius and Pufendorf on the Right

of Necessity’, History of Political Thought, XXVI (2) (2005), pp. 284-302; Siegfried Van Duffel and Dennis Yap,

‘Distributive Justice Before the Eighteenth Century: The Right of Necessity’, History of Political Thought, XXXII (3)

(2011), pp. 449-64. 118 That is, overlooked today. George Lawson wrote in 1657 that Hobbes’s rejection of a natural suum ‘makes all men

brutes, nay wild and ravenous beasts, and birds of prey’. See ‘An Examination of the Political Part of Mr. Hobbs his

Leviathan’ in Leviathan: Contemporary Responses to the Political Theory of Thomas Hobbes, ed. G.A.J. Rogers (Bristol, 1995)

pp. 67–8. Pufendorf states that animals have no suum in On the Law of Nature and Nations, 4.4.5. An exception is

Martin Harvey in ‘Grotius and Hobbes’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy, XIV (1) (2006), pp. 41-4 and in

‘Hobbes’s Voluntarist Theory of Morals’, Hobbes Studies, XXII (1) (2009), pp. 51-5. 119 For an excellent discussion, see Karl Olivecrona, ‘The Two Levels in Natural Law Thinking’, ed. Thomas

Mautner in Jurisprudence, I (2) (2010), pp. 197-224. See also Karl Olivecrona, ‘Appropriation in the State of Nature:

Locke on the Origin of Property’, Journal of the History of Ideas, XXXV (1974), pp. 211-30; Tully, Discourse on Property,

pp. 80-90, 112-4; Buckle, Natural Law, pp. 29-37, 77-80, 91-2, 169-74. 120 Mautner in Olivecrona, ‘Two Levels’, p. 202.

26

without injustice: ‘For our Lives, Limbs, and Liberties, had still been properly our own, and could

not have been, (without manifest Injustice) invaded’ (DIB: 1.2.1.5).121 Pufendorf likewise claimed

that agents by nature have a right to their own ‘life, body, chastity and liberty’.122 And Locke

famously maintained that ‘every Man has a Property in his own Person. This no Body has any Right

to but himself’.123 No such claim is found in Hobbes’s corpus. Indeed, Hobbes explicitly

distinguishes between harm (damnum) and wrong (injuriam), the latter consisting in a breach of

covenant (DCv: 3.4). It is noteworthy, furthermore, that Hobbes nowhere affirms the Lockean

ground of self-ownership: that God gave us our bodies for some purpose, and that our bodies

ultimately belong to Him.124

Despite Hobbes’s encompassing conception of ‘propriety’, the Creation Argument need not

be extended to all rights citizens have against one another. Upon entering the commonwealth,

individuals collectively renounce their right to all things, thus incurring obligations

(conceptualized as ‘absence of right’). Combined, these obligations arguably suffice to establish

some types of propriety. If citizens relinquish their right to pre-emptively attack and harm others

in the original covenant, then this amounts to granting each an exclusive right to bodily integrity.

The creation of some exclusive personal rights could thus be explained without reference to

distributive laws. Grounded in a mutual promise of non-interference, these rights are then

regulated by commutative justice and depend on the State in the sense explained by the Precision

and Security Argument.

An objection against this suggestion is that citizens do not divest any rights to fellow-

citizens in the original covenant. Citizens mutually covenant to freely transfer their rights to a

third-party beneficiary: the sovereign (DCv: 6.20; L: 17.13).125 The only mutual obligation citizens

acquire is the duty to obey the civil law. It is unclear whether alienation of right to the sovereign,

in combination with the mutual promise to respect this free gift, can generate the obligations

constitutive of personal property rights. In any case, the argument cannot be extended to rights

over things because Hobbes does not explain how individuals can obtain property titles in the

121 The suum thus consists of perfect rights, with corresponding obligations on others to respect these rights (DIB:

1.1.8.1). Before the introduction of private property, agents have a right not to be hindered from appropriating

goods for consumption from the common stock, the violation of which is ‘a real Injury’ (DIB: 1.2.1). 122 Pufendorf, The Whole Duty of Man, According to the Law of Nature, 1.6.3; Pufendorf, On the Law of Nature and Nations,

3.1.1. 123 Locke, Second Treatise, 5.27. 124 Cf. Locke, Second Treatise, 2.6: ‘sent into the World by his order and about his business, [we] are his Property’. 125 Larry May, ‘Hobbes’s Contract Theory’, Journal of the History of Philosophy, XVIII (2) (1980), p. 205.

27

natural condition through appropriation of common goods. As a result, there are no uncontested

provisional rights to goods which individuals can agree to respect, by laying down their right to

them in the original covenant. Only the Creation Argument can explicate the genesis of rights in

things.

Regardless of which explanation of the conventional origin of propriety in one’s ‘own life,

& limbs’ we prefer, Hobbes rejects natural self-ownership. Moreover, contrary to what

Macpherson and Zarka maintain, self-ownership plays no role in his theory of property. Hobbes

acknowledged no natural right to the fruits of one’s labour; any such right is established by

distributive civil law.

Macpherson has been criticized for misidentifying the problems seventeenth-century

natural right theorists were addressing. They were concerned with the right of resistance, critics

claim, not with the right to the products of one’s labour; with politics, not with economy.126 My

criticism is of a different order. I have argued that natural self-ownership is positively inconsistent

with Hobbes’s thoroughly conventionalist theory of property. It is ruled out by various

interlocking doctrines, including the right to all things, the absence of justice and injustice in the

state of nature, the definition of justice as the performance of covenants, and Hobbes’s peculiar

understanding of distributive justice as the creation of private property rights by sovereign fiat.

CONCLUSION

Macpherson regards Hobbes’s writings on justice as strong evidence for his bourgeois theory of

property and self-ownership; critics and fellow-travellers alike agree. This paper challenged this

view by examining the way in which property depends on the State. The explanations Hobbes

advances in Elements and De Cive (the Security and the Precision Argument) are somewhat supportive

of Macpherson’s reading. Both arguments rely on commutative justice (the justice of

contractors). They assign a limited role to the State and allow for provisional pre-political claims

to property. Yet Leviathan discarded these two arguments in favour of the Creation Argument. That

explanation of the State-dependency of property, premised on distributive justice, fits ill with

Macpherson’s thesis. For Hobbes, the task of the State goes beyond enforcing private contracts

and arbitrating disputes – it arbitrarily creates private property and other civil rights. What one

deserves is not determined by brute market forces, but by civil law. To further complicate

126 Tully, ‘Possessive Individualism Thesis’, pp. 25-31.

28

Macpherson’s reading, Hobbes rejects a basic assumption of possessive individualism: natural

self-ownership.

The analysis I provided of the conceptual connections Hobbes perceived between justice,

law and property rights is not just of interest to students curious about the plausibility of

Macpherson’s thesis. Further contributions of the paper are three. First, I systematically traced

Hobbes’s developing insights concerning law, property, and distributive justice. I argued that

Hobbes’s most radical State-based theory of property was not defended consistently before

Leviathan. In that text Hobbes first reinterpreted the Roman law definition of justice as the duty

or virtue of sovereigns to institute private property rights. Second, I drew attention to a

distinctive and foundational premise of Hobbes’s practical philosophy: his rejection of a natural

suum. Considerations of space prevented me from further elaborating on this point. I suspect,

however, that this denial underlies the most salient differences between Hobbes’s philosophy of

right and that of Grotius and other early modern natural lawyers. Third, the paper elucidated

theoretical connections between several apparently disparate Hobbesian doctrines: including the

right to all things, distributive laws, his redefinitions of distributive justice and merit, his denial of

natural self-ownership, propriety in its broad sense, and justice more generally. The highlighted

interconnections hopefully convince readers that Hobbes had a full-blown theory of property

that deserves further study.