artistic philosophy and philosophical art: vitalism in

28
Artistic Philosophy and Philosophical Art: Vitalism in María Zambrano, Henri Bergson, and José Lezama Lima [Forthcoming in Madeline Cámara (ed.), María Zambrano: Between the Caribbean and the Mediterranean. This is a draft, please, do not cite without the author’s permission.] Adriana Novoa University of South Florida In this essay I will analyze how philosophical vitalism is crucial to understanding the way in which cultural dilemmas derived from Darwinian ideas were addressed in Spain and Cuba during the first half of the twentieth century. I will analyze vitalism in the work of Henri Bergson (1859-1941), María Zambrano (1904-1991), and José Lezama Lima (1910-1976), whose relationship with Zambrano is well known. 1 My intention is to show how in the first half of the twentieth century their philosophical approach became the source of an intellectual renewal that reconstituted philosophical humanism in the context of modernity. The study of these ideas reveals exchanges that addressed pervasive questions about identity, origins, and the existential resolution of challenges posed by biological racism. Bergson was a central figure in the cultural politics of Spain and Spanish America during the first half of the twentieth century because, among other things, he implied a notion of modernity associated to “a subject of action, centered upon the dynamic body” (Guerlac i). This attention to passivity and action also appears in the work of Zambrano and Lezama Lima, particularly as related to their interest in the intersection between philosophy and poetry. I will show how their development of this connection is concerned with a different way to do philosophy that is similar to Bergson’s, who believed that the artist had a role in philosophy, and that a new way to understanding consciousness had to be linked to artistic practice. As we will see, this approach opened

Upload: usf

Post on 27-Jan-2023

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Artistic Philosophy and Philosophical Art: Vitalism in María Zambrano, Henri Bergson, and José Lezama Lima [Forthcoming in Madeline Cámara (ed.), María Zambrano: Between the Caribbean and the Mediterranean. This is a draft, please, do not cite without the author’s permission.]

Adriana Novoa

University of South Florida

In this essay I will analyze how philosophical vitalism is crucial to understanding

the way in which cultural dilemmas derived from Darwinian ideas were addressed in

Spain and Cuba during the first half of the twentieth century. I will analyze vitalism in

the work of Henri Bergson (1859-1941), María Zambrano (1904-1991), and José Lezama

Lima (1910-1976), whose relationship with Zambrano is well known.1 My intention is to

show how in the first half of the twentieth century their philosophical approach became

the source of an intellectual renewal that reconstituted philosophical humanism in the

context of modernity. The study of these ideas reveals exchanges that addressed

pervasive questions about identity, origins, and the existential resolution of challenges

posed by biological racism.

Bergson was a central figure in the cultural politics of Spain and Spanish America

during the first half of the twentieth century because, among other things, he implied a

notion of modernity associated to “a subject of action, centered upon the dynamic body”

(Guerlac i). This attention to passivity and action also appears in the work of Zambrano

and Lezama Lima, particularly as related to their interest in the intersection between

philosophy and poetry. I will show how their development of this connection is

concerned with a different way to do philosophy that is similar to Bergson’s, who

believed that the artist had a role in philosophy, and that a new way to understanding

consciousness had to be linked to artistic practice. As we will see, this approach opened

  2

up a reflection on the relevance of the knowledge originated by the arts, and the search

for a new form of knowing. Bergson believed that our perception of things had to be

widened and that this should be accomplished through a philosophy “where nothing in

the data of the senses or the consciousness would be substituted for the rest ostensibly to

explain it.” It was for this reason that philosophers needed to look at the work of those

who for centuries had worked with a more amplified perception, the artists. According to

Bergson, art “would suffice then to show us that an extension of the faculties of

perceiving is possible” (Perception, 113).

The poetic reason of Zambrano and the philosophical grounding of Lezama

Lima’s poetry were also part of the same attempt to re-signify modernity through a vital

artistic force that helped to transform notions of cultural identity and agency. It is

important to clarify that I will not follow a top-down model of reception of ideas; quite

contrary, what I propose is that all the intellectuals analyzed were searching for similar

things around the same time, and that they have common motivations, but also some that

were related to their local reality. I will discuss the work of Zambrano, Lezama Lima, and

Bergson in a horizontal field of exchanges that imply that they all should be taken as

equally valuable to the understanding philosophical ideas related to vitalism and their

connection to poetry.

Vitalism, Philosophy, and Art

Before the stir originated by the publication of Ariel by José Rodó in 1900, the

intellectuals of Spanish speaking countries experienced a great deal of difficulty

reconciling philosophical ideas and scientific thinking after Darwin. José Martí (1853-

  3

1895) harshly attacked intellectual passivity, and the interest that intellectuals from the

region had in derivative and imitative philosophical systems during the years that

preceded his death in 1895. At the time, racist and deterministic ideas saw in the so-

called inferior races the inability to compete successfully for a place in the future. In both

the Americas and Europe, science seemed to corroborate the impression that certain

human populations had diverged enough to have different evolutionary paths. Latin races

were presented as if they were in the process of degeneration, while the Anglo-Saxon

race was the expression of humankind’s future. This was a widespread vision that can be

found in scientific and popular literature among conservatives, socialists, and liberals in

Europe and the Americas. For example, in the United States, the magazine The Nation

published in 1896 an article entitled “Are the Latin Races Doomed?”, in which there is a

discussion of this possibility according to the ideas that were popular at the time.

Those who were part of this “doomed” population became less interested in

science and found in philosophical idealism a new way to understand the meaning of

humanity. This movement was popular by the 1890s in Spain, France and Spanish

America. In these areas thinkers developed a mixture of idealism and vitalism to create a

philosophical renewal that contradicted biological determinism, questioning the

understanding of humans in scientific terms only. In 1911, the Peruvian diplomat and

writer Francisco García Calderón (1883-1953) described this situation mentioning the

influence that the French philosopher Alfred Fouillée (1838-1912) and his “philosophy of

hope” had had in Spanish America. According to him, by “its noble idealism, by its

admirable wealth, its serene rationalism, and its essentially Latin character, the

  4

harmonious system of M. Fouillée has won considerable popularity among the youth of

America” (278).2

García Calderón also related this renovation to the aesthetic influence of French

philosopher and writer, Jean-Marie Guyeau (1854-1888), who had been Bergson’s

teacher.3 This “young poet” was the “professor of idealism to two generations of

America. In Ariel José Enrique Rodó has enlarged upon his finest metaphors; and a

Peruvian thinker, Gonzalez Prada, has popularised [sic] the suggestions of this Platonic

thinker upon death” (278). Rodó (1871-1917) was very influential in his call for a

connection between poetry, philosophy, and vitalism; the latter through his understanding

of the work of the German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900).

This was the first stage of the reaction against dogmatic positivism, which had led

by the 1910’s to a period of “dissolution and criticism”, in which “all the new doctrines

[were] making their way: pragmatism, Bergsonism, the philosophy of Wundt and Croce,”

and “the philosophy of contingency” (279). This change made García Calderón hopeful

that from “this variety of imitations perhaps an American system” would arise in the

future (Ibid.). Meanwhile, it was clear to him that in “accepting influences” coming from

English, German, and French sources, “the old faith in science, in Comte and Spencer,

[was] evaporating. Two young philosophers, Antonio Caso in Mexico and Henriquez

Ureña in San Domingo,” had contributed to this analysis inspired “by the ideas of M.

Emile Boutroux”, who had attacked the narrow interpretation of scientific laws (279).

Boutroux (1845-1921) was an important figure in the spreading of vitalism,

together with Nietzsche, the pragmatist William James (1842-1910), and Henri Bergson.4

Under the term vitalism there were many contradictory ideas that by the 1910’s provided

  5

an umbrella for those attacking the dominance of the science linked to Darwinist

thinking, which created a philosophical debate in both the Americas and Europe. In 1911,

for example, the journal Science, published in the United States, explained that every

person who had studied the controversy around vitalist ideas had to confront “the lack of

either clear or generally accepted definitions of the terms (“vitalism” and “mechanism”)

used to designate the opposite doctrines under discussion” (Lovejoy 610). This article,

written by the philosopher Arthur O. Lovejoy (1873-1962), points to the main problem

intellectuals faced at the time regarding the understanding of the origins of life, and the

supremacy given to materialism by evolutionary thinkers.5

On the contrary, “vitalism” implied that “organisms not only have unique laws on

their own,” but that these laws “cannot even be stated in terms of the number and

arrangement of the organism’s physical components” (ibid., 612). This questioned two

basic tenets of positivist thinking; first, the possibility that some biological phenomena be

shown to be autonomous; second, that this phenomena could be shown to have parts

“existing in the organism or cell” at the moment in which the former took place (ibid.,

613). The German biologist and philosopher Hans Driesch (1867-1941) had proposed

these ideas, changing the understanding of how human organisms worked. But, this neo-

vitalism achieved its most known philosophical expression in the work of the French

philosopher Henri Bergson.

In 1889 Bergson’s Time and Free Will was published, followed in 1896 by Matter

and Memory, and in 1907 Creative Evolution. According to him, it was wrong to assume

that the same laws applied to all organisms. The idea that “the living body might be

treated by some superhuman calculator in the same mathematical way as our solar

  6

system” should be abandoned (Creative, 20). This implied, as Lovejoy recognized at the

time, the existence of a discontinuity “between the “laws” or modes of action of matter

dealt with by biology and the “laws” of all the sciences of the inorganic” (614). The key

concept introduced by Bergson was “élan vital,” which was understood to imply that

“something absolutely new and novel came into the world when living beings came, and

that this came as a special force, or principle, or factor” that was “not material” (Ritter,

438).

Bergson’s writings became popular in Spanish America by the 1900’s because he

was rightly perceived as a follower of ideas that were developing in the area before his

work was known. He was interested in a science that was still evolutionist while, at the

same time, contradicted previous ideas on three important grounds. First, mechanism

“does not explain certain observed characteristics of growth and regulation in

organisms”; second, “conscious introspection demonstrates that voluntary choice in

human beings is not mechanistically determined”; third, the “adaptative character of

behavior is not fully described in mechanistic terms” (Warren 600). His “doctrine of

organic autonomy” eliminated many of the limitations and constraints placed by

positivist ideas, which connected his work to racial ideas, since it involved the limits of

the materiality of the body and the same understanding of humanity.

Donna V. Jones has explained in her study of Negritude that those who applied

Darwinists ideas to social policy “insisted that as the truth of living beings is bio-logical,

only physical race could sustain the social bond, and society was the theater of human

animals’ struggle of all against all and the domination of one group of subspecies over

another” (8). As it was the case in the Caribbean, Bergson’s work was viewed in Spain

  7

and its ex-colonies as the first post-positivist philosophical project that had a “categorical

importance to European aesthetics and social thought, including its disturbing racialism”

(20). Jones’s claim that vitalism is connected “not only to European racism but also to the

defensive racial forms of African and Caribbean self-understanding” also applies to the

cases of Spain and Cuba (21). In these two countries Bergson’s vitalism was used to

address concerns about a science that reinforced the primacy of the material forces of

evolution, while his defense of intuition and downgrading of Cartesian rationality was

important in the world of the arts and literature.

Bergson also provided a culmination to the French philosophy that had been

influential among Spanish American intellectuals since the 1890’s. From the vitalism of

Emile Boutroux and Jules Lachelier (1832-1918) to Jean-Marie Guyau’s interest in

aesthetics and the expansion of vital forces through creation, Bergson seemed to

condense their work into a new way to understand philosophy and humanism. Gilles

Deleuze’s explanation of the role of philosophy for Bergson can be used to understand

his influence in Spain and its ex-colonies. According to him, “To open us up to the

inhuman and the superhuman (durations which are inferior or superior to our own), to go

beyond the human condition: this is the meaning of philosophy” (28). If the end of the

nineteenth century was characterized by the philosophical devotion to the study of natural

law and the survival of the fittest, Bergson’s work brought a radical change to this view

of humanity through his different understanding of nature. According to him, nature

“warns us by a clear sign that our destination is attained. That sign is joy.” This

experience is different from pleasure, which “is only a contrivance devised by nature to

obtain for the creature the preservation of its life, it does not indicate the direction in

  8

which life is thrusting.” But the experience of enjoyment “always announces that life has

succeeded, gained ground, conquered.” This was a triumph that exalted vital forces,

which were visible because “wherever there is joy, there is creation; the richer the

creation, the deeper the joy” (Mind-Energy, 29).

The restoration of this particular notion of humanism is very important to

recognize the context in which Zambrano and Lezama Lima conceived their work on

poetry and philosophy. As we will see, while the materialists saw intelligence and the

logos exclusively as the result of material processes, vitalist ideas circulating in Spain,

France and Spanish America started to debate the importance of spiritual forces in the

development of the will, freedom, and agency. Bergson’s critique of the philosophical

approaches of his time also affected literature, particularly poetry, which explains why

many ideologies of racial renewal came from literature in the first half of the twentieth

century. In Spanish America this attitude had roots in Modernismo, a literary movement

that had made literature the core of Spanish American thought by the end of the

nineteenth century.

Robert Haas has explained how in Time and Free Will (1889) and Laughter: An

Essay on the Meaning of the Comic (1900), “Bergson rejects the idea that there is a clear

correspondence between sensation and expression [...] Words, like numbers,

measurements, or concepts, are discrete units of thought that organize a stream of

constantly changing sensations.” But, even when ”words help us communicate ideas

efficiently, they nevertheless distort consciousness by fixing qualitative differences into

vague generalizations” (164). This explains why the work of poets “should release us

  9

from the various conventions that condition our quotidian perception and restore us to a

primordial consciousness that lies beneath the surface of ordinary awareness” (164).

According to Hass, a modernist aesthetic related to the stream-of-consciousness,

and their subordination of “the objective world to the dream-like processes of the mind

and their rendering of constantly changing subjective states serves as a kind of ideal

model for a Bergsonian aesthetic” (165). The access, then, to the flow of life, the actual

source of the élan vital, might be seen as related to the work of artists and poets that

disrupted the linear progression of events. Bergson “disparaged the intellect as an

instrument of analysis, one that is unable to capture the mobility of changing experience--

--although, of course, vitalism, like all philosophies, relies on discursive procedures of

the intellect to convey its particular claims to truth” (Moses 170). This possibility to go

beyond rationality fit perfectly in areas where the realm of reason seemed to be divorced

from local reality, as it was the case in Spain and Spanish America.

Philosophy and Vitalism in Cuba and Spain

The philosophical connection between Cuba and Spain predates Zambrano, and

she was one of the individuals who benefitted from this link through the work of José del

Perojo (1852-1908), born in Santiago of Cuba, but educated in Spain and Germany. He

lived in Madrid and became the most important philosopher of his time. He is considered

the first neo-Kantian philosopher from Spain, and with the creation of the Revista

Contemporánea in 1875 responsible for the spread of a German philosophy that

combined kantianism and positivism (Mülberger 161). He had studied philosophy in

Heidelberg and translated books by Kant and other important German-language

  10

philosophers who were not well known in Spanish-speaking areas. He was also a

participant in the discussion of Cuban coloniality, and politics related to this issue. His

work aided the neo-Kantianism that coexisted with the reception of Bergson’s work, and

drew attention to the connection between the German and French thoughts. Del Perojo

also provided Zambrano with the roots of a discussion that was very important both in

Spain and Spanish America, the possibility of a national philosophy and national thought

(Mora García 1064).

Both Spain and the nations that emerged from its colonies labored under the

certainty of their peripheral status in European culture. As Stephen D. Gingerich has

explained, “Spain had a consciousness—documented in literature, the arts, and popular

discourse—of being on the margins of Europe, of never quite fitting in with the rest of

the continent” (193). By the end of the nineteenth century, those who belonged to the

peoples deemed “degenerate” or marginal by comparison with northern Europe began to

look into German thought for sources that connected Kantianism, the works of Nietzsche,

vitalism, and the Greek classics, into a project of racial regeneration. This project dealt

with the development of a philosophy that connected the notions of being and becoming

with artistic practice.

María Zambrano shared with Spanish American intellectuals an understanding of

her country as a space of not-being, of lack, deprived of a modern identity that structured

the understanding of the future. As noted, this act of meditating about the meaning of the

country had its roots in Del Perojo, but it had become an important component of the

ideas of the Generation ’98 through the writings of Miguel de Unamuno (1864-1936),

“who began his series of essays back in the 1880s” (Gingerich 57). Unamuno’s work was

  11

very important in Spanish America because it shared the same concerns expressed by

Rodó and those who adhered to the principles of literary Modernismo. It also allowed the

possibility of thinking about circumstances and locality. Between the years 1906 and

1911 there was an active epistolary exchange between Unamuno and the Cuban scholar

Fernando Ortiz (1881-1969). This exchange reveals how the latter saw in the former’s

work, particularly in his take on Don Quijote, a way to wake up from passivity, the

“modorra tropical,” that afflicted Cubans. This emphasis on agency and will was

connected to a more active historical subject that was very important among the members

of Ortiz’s generation. They all followed the ideas of the “regeneracionistas” with interest,

as is shown in this Ortiz’s comment from Entre Cubanos:

No podrá germinar la cultura en Cuba sin que todos, así los grandes del

pensamiento y de la acción, como los pequeños humildes laborantes, nos

brindemos a la tarea regeneradora, nos consagremos al trabajo para roturar el

virginal terruño de nuestra psicología... (qtd. in Serrano, 301).

This sense of generational renewal was also connected to Bergson’s ideas in his

emphasis on action, agency, and becoming. His work was used to affirm the existence of

free will, and the development of sentiments and perception. In 1906 the writer Luis

Baralt (1849-1933), founder of the “Ateneo de la Habana,” gave a talk at the Cuban

Academy of Sciences, drawing attention to the increasing importance of the education of

sentiments and the will. According to him, such education was another factor that favored

evolution, together with “heredity, the cosmic environment, and the circumstances” that

surrounded the individual. Education, according to Baralt, “was the only thing that could

neutralize and defeat the law of heredity” in its creation of a new and superior population

  12

(159). But he immediately added that he was not interested merely in the intellectual

fruits of educational efforts. Following Spencer, Guyau, Fouillé, Le Bon, and Bergson,

among others, Baralt made it clear that he was against the domination of sentiment by the

intellect. The “supreme goal of education” was the formation of character, which was

primarily organized by sensibility and will (159).

Baralt described will as “a sentiment” and an active component of psychic life

(160). The most sublime such sentiment was love. Love for the truth gave rise to science,

love for beauty to the arts, love for family to the “patria” and humanity, and love for

social solidarity to morality and religion. Love brought together human sympathy,

compassion, pity, and tenderness. Only through love could a truly worthy action occur, in

a series that progressed from love to good feeling or sentiment, desire, resolution, effort,

and finally, the unselfish act. Baralt’s ideas belonged to the sphere of moral philosophy

which strove to increase “this special force that allow us to put behind personal wishes

and interest in the name of collective ones that reflected ideals” that were each day

“higher and most powerful, subjecting animal instincts, selfish by nature, to the orders of

reason and consciousness” (160).

This capacity to feel, to empathize, to love others, is what characterized the Latin

races in the writings of Rodó, Vasconcelos and most post-positivists in Spanish America

by the 1930’s. Moral law replaced Darwinian natural law, and this moral law opened the

door to connect spiritual and natural life. Drawing on Herbert Spencer’s 1902 Facts and

Comments, a text quite critical of the consequences of progress, Baralt placed at the

center of civilization sentimental action based on the “knowledge of the psychological

laws of human nature,” which in time would give Cubans “the victory” (163). The result

  13

of this victory would end up being future survival through a harmonious life created by

the individuals’ will and actions.

Baralt’s speech captured the main vitalist ideas circulating at the time, including

those of Bergson. According to the latter, “the sources of morality and religion are always

a matter of love.” This is not romantic love, but a love that “expresses what is creative

and evolving; this love responds to attraction----wholeheartedly, if you will----and

“aspires” to moral progress,” which made morality less related to evolutionary outcomes.

In addition, this kind of aspirational love was characteristic of “progress”----the

exceptional, the “evolving,” the creative, the open” (Kelly 77). This is a superior emotion

that “expresses time-flowing in the person and the social “ (ibd. 76). It also “has no object

because it will create a new object, a new idea, because it is pregnant with it. It is all

activity, all free movement that responds to the appeal of love of humanity rather than the

pressures of social conscience” (ibid. 81).

In Spain, where, as we have seen, a similar process of regeneration had been

taking place since the 1890s, the work of José Ortega y Gasset (1883-1955) contributed

to a new philosophical current connecting German and French traditions. Zambrano’s

generation saw in his work the beginning of a process that redefined the importance of

human agency and action. In 1927 the publication of his Rebellion of the Masses created

a stir similar to the one Rodó had provoked with Ariel. As Zambrano described it, it was

a statement for the youth, and one that implied the important role of vitalism after the

pessimism that dominated the end of the nineteenth century:

[Ortega] was one of those rate writers who allow a reader to believe he

himself has written what he’s reading. I believe this is what many Spaniards felt

  14

as they read him; they believed they were the authors. “Vitality, soul, spirit”:

didn’t write this myself, wasn’t perhaps mine? [...] I believe that each of us had

written it, each of us young people.

Yes, reading Ortega made you want to live. You saw that life is something

good, intelligent in itself, that life is intelligent---or more so---qua “intelligence,

as what you had thought was intelligence, reason: you saw that life is reason and

sticks to reason, its own reason deep within life itself. Ans this enable you to love

life, to want to live it with faith, hope, and joy (Zambrano 59).

Jaime Ferreiro Alemparte has explained how José Ortega y Gasset defended

rational knowledge, but not as an independent and abstract reality. He was in favor of a

rationality understood as a dimension and manifestation of human life as such, which

meant as a historical process. His defense of these ideas continued with the foundation of

the Revista de Occidente in 1924. Its publication made works published in German

available to Spanish speaking audiences, among them those of Max Scheler and Georg

Simmel. As it was the case in Spanish America, Zambrano’s generation used abundant

and eclectic sources in an effort to answer their own philosophical questions. But

Bergson was an important reference in her reconstitution of vitalism and his work a

constant companion during her time at the university in the 1920’s (Laurenzi 23).

Ortega knew the different notions of philosophical vitalism circulating at the time,

including Bergson’s, and used them for both philosophical and political reasons. He

linked the affirmation of action and will with their role in the cultural and social

transformation of the individual, for example. According to him the decisions we take are

key to understanding the connection between past and future, and the process of making

  15

oneself. His “razón vital” was similar to Bergson’s “good reason,” a commonality that

Ortega characterized in this way:

Lo llamado por Bergson “buen sentido” es lo que yo he llamado formalmente

“razón vital”, una razón más amplia y para la cual son racionales no pocos objetos

que frente a la vieja raison o razón conceptual o razón pura son, en efecto,

irracionales (327).

But Ortega’s vital reason may be contrasted with the poetic reason of Zambrano,

who argued with her teacher about this precise issue. Zambrano’s poetic reason has a

different take on passivity, and in its connection with mysticism emphasizes a different

subjectivity. She said in an interview that her work had always stood between the rescue

of passivity and receptivity, and that her poetic reason had remained the same since it had

appeared in her essay “Hacia un saber sobre el alma”, published in Revista de Occidente

in 1934. At the beginning she had thought that she was following Ortega’s vital reason,

but after a while she understood that her work was departing from her teacher’s.

Zambrano recalled showing this essay to Ortega. After reading it he said, “we are still

here and you wanted to jump ahead”, which made it obvious to her that while he had

directed his reason to historical reason, she was directing hers to poetic reason (Quoted in

Lapiedra Gutiérrez, 66-67).

Philosophy and Poetry in Zambrano and Lezama Lima

Like most thinkers of her time, Zambrano was concerned with the meaning of

modernity, and its relationship to ways to define humanity. She was interested in a

philosophy that not only developed an independent and omnipotent subject, but one who

  16

also set the limits of existence. Guillermo Lapiedra Gutiérrez correctly captures the

difference between Ortega and Zambrano in two essential issues: “passivity and

transcendence.” For Zambrano, “being born means that life is a path between two

absolutes; one of more passivity, which is the sleep; and transcendence, which is given in

love and hope” (68). While Ortega focused, like many Spanish American thinkers, on

action and immanence, Zambrano was interested in the opposite. According to Ortega,

the relationship between what surrounds the subject and the subject itself explains our

decisions and how we act. Everything we know is in relation to life, to immanence, and

nothing can be done outside it. Zambrano, on the other hand, paid attention to receptivity,

to the possibility of stepping out of oneself to leave space for the other.

According to Roberta Johnson, Zambrano disagreed with leaving the study of the

soul to psychology, which was only interested in its connection with scientific ideas. For

her the soul “is the key to the process of bringing external political and ethical matters

into the realm of the individual subject, because it situates itself in that central and

facilitating space between “the I and the natural exterior”” (228), which explains why

literature became for Zambrano “the ideal intermediary between the external self and the

socio-political world, because it participates equally in the public and private spheres”

(Ibid.). Creative writing was very helpful in conceiving a different way to think

philosophically because it is “uniquely situated to unite the individual emotions with

public political life in Zambrano’s “poetic reason”” (ibid.).

Zambrano’s interest in the relationship between poetry and philosophy was also

important in Latin America since the 1900s, as it was mentioned. Poetry and the

philosophy of Bergson were articulated to negate the traditional understanding of

  17

rationality by means of a process organized around creativity. The Mexican philosopher

José Vasconcelos (1882-1959), for example, did not limit his contributions to the

emergence of the cosmic race. One of his main interests was aesthetics, and, as in the

case of Zambrano, he based many of his ideas on this subject in the reading of Greek

texts and the function of rhythm to experience the flow of life. Vasconcelos’s study of

Pythagorean ideas in music, for example, was published in the journal Cuba

Contemporánea in 1916, among other studies that searched for the relationship between

philosophy, poetry, and the exploration of a new subjectivity.

In Spain, Zambrano trod the same path. But her approach led to a way of finding

that is not structured around conscious, mental, active, and controlled processes, but

around passive ones related to an affectivity that limited the dominance of reason.

According to her, the deification of humanity, its occupying of otherness, had made men

experience solitude, a process that had to be reversed via the limitation of reason and the

restoration of a difference that she called “the divine” (Zambrano, 1987, 29).6 Our

relationship with “lo divino” had to be restored in order for us to recover our humanity,

and our sense of otherness. It is in the process of this recovery that passivity becomes a

necessity and pure action, the act of occupying everything, is limited. Zambrano

connected poetry to space and philosophy to time. As a result, poetic space is related to

myth, while the time of philosophy is that of history. Poetic reason intersects both, and is

also the point of origin that preceded reason.

Zambrano gives a larger role to reception, and in her work this concept is much

more relevant than in most of other philosophers or intellectuals interested in vitalism.

Her mystic ex-tasis, her interest in a state of not-being and the denial of self, makes her

  18

quite different to others who saw in the “élan vital” a possibility of enhancing the self.

Obviously she does not see the mystic act as sadomasochistic, but, to contrary, as an

attempt to experience difference in order to know it. The point at which we transcend our

humanity is the point at which we know what humanity truly is.

The act of mysticism is not, then, a religious expression, but a deeply humane

one. In a letter written to a theologian friend she noted her interest in “opening reason,

uniting reason and devotion, reason and fundamental sentiment, philosophy and poetry”

(Quoted in Morán, 13). Following the model of Greek philosophers, Zambrano saw in the

search for the divine a way to achieve true knowledge. In the work of the Spanish mystic

and poet San Juan de la Cruz (1542-1591) she found a perfect example of poetic reason.

According to her, his writings showed that “his being is finally able to manage not to be,”

but he received this state not as an act of death, but “as an imperative that came from life

itself. The mystic’s revolution is in complete self-alienation, in becoming other, in the

complete destruction of self, putting self aside so that another comes to exist in the

mystic. Having consumed all the dimensions of being, mental, moral, and so on, all that

remains is ‘all-consuming love’” (ibid.). The possibility of evolutionary death seems to

be transcended in this analysis of Zambrano, since the negation of self seems to be related

to life and not to death.

Zambrano went to live in exile after the defeat of the Spanish Republic in 1939.

She stayed in Cuba from 1940 through 1946, and from 1948 through 1953. She knew the

country already, having visited it in 1936 with her husband. Her arrival was received with

enthusiasm among the youth, since the philosophical topics that concerned Zambrano

were also, as we have seen, similar to those already being discussed in Cuba, and

  19

everywhere in Spanish America. The philosopher Medardo Vitier, father of Cintio, noted

in his book about philosophy in Cuba that Zambrano’s “influence among a reduced group

of young people was considerable. She might ignore it herself. All of them had rekindled

their philosophical interests” (qtd. in Dosil Mansilla, 143). Among them, José Lezama

Lima became one of her closest intellectual companions. This connection was helpful to

both of them in many respects, but for the purpose of this essay I will confine myself to

the analysis of the poetic in its relationship with philosophy.

In Cuba the interest in a poetry that dealt with philosophy was incubating before

Zambrano’s arrival, finally emerging in a group that gathered around the publication of

Orígenes from 1944 to 1956. This publication reflected an interest in exploring questions

related to identity, nationality, and modernity, with an editorial philosophy that reflected

the preoccupations of Lezama Lima’s generation. Like Zambrano, Lezama was also

interested in finding a way to eliminate the dualisms that resulted from rationalism, such

as material/immaterial, sensual/spiritual, or sacred/secular. According to him, through

poetry one can access the world of mystery, and the function of the poet was to resignify

the world through a perception that transcended the ordinary, which connected him to

Bergson’s intuitionism. Cintio Vitier, another member of the group Orígenes, put it in

very Bergsonian terms when he explained that the voice of poetry was better heard in the

space of the written than in the sequential temporality of the spoken word.

These poets, called “transcendentalists” by the critic Roberto Retamar, searched

for a way in which they could leave behind the knowledge that came through the

materiality of the body, since according to many the limitations imposed by such form of

knowing explained Cuba’s political failures. As we saw, the narrative of racial inferiority

  20

in Spanish America was based on racist and scientific accounts that emphasized

materialism, so this new poetic approach wanted to transcend the latter as a way to

establish the country’s existence. Lezama Lima’s understanding of the poetic was related,

as it was in Zambrano, with the ability to be removed from oneself, to be receptive to a

different way of knowing, also related to the transcendental. Poetic action was not only

something that one did by writing, but also a way to develop a modernist identity to aid a

politically frustrated country. In the case of the Cuban writer, though, this process

emphasizes memory, which is for him the material for poetry.

According to Lezama Lima, we know through what we remember. But for him

memories are not a static enumeration of events in relation to time. Memory belongs to

the world of the obscure, of the primal world that can be accessed by the poetic. This also

resembles Bergson’s conception of perception as something that “is entirely absent from

memory, a reality intuitively grasped” (85). In this “state of pure perception we are

actually placed outside ourselves, we touch the reality of the object in an immediate

intuition” (Bergson, 1911, 84-85). Perception adds a different source for history, since

remembering is not about an organized narrative of the present, past, and future, but

about the perception of different durations. Myth and history have to be linked through

creative practice, and poetry and history cannot, then, be separated. This narrative can

only be expressed metaphorically, which led Lezama Lima to talk about metaphorical

justice, the restoration of the world we want to access. Metaphor is the key poetic

element here, and its use hearkens to Bergson’s understanding of this concept.

It is helpful in this context to have in mind Gaston Bachelard’s analysis of

Bergson, according to which the “linguistic impulses, which stand out from the ordinary

  21

rank of pragmatic language, are miniatures of the vital impulse. A micro-Bergsonism that

abandoned the thesis of language-as-instrument in favor of the thesis of language-as-

reality would find in poetry numerous documents on the intense life of language” (xxvii).

Bachelard’s notion of poetry-as-reality is very helpful to understanding Lezama Lima’s

approach, and his attempt to articulate a relationship between cultural practice and Cuban

history. Like Bergson, he seems to imply that “imagination is entirely metaphorical”, and

that metaphor is “related to a psychic being from which it differs” (Bachelard 74).

Philosophically, Lezama Lima’s interest in notions of uncovering, becoming and

being, might be seen as somewhat connected to the work of Heidegger. According to

Michael Bell, for the later “the royal road to remembrance of Being is through the non-

discursive rout of art and locality,” and in his work the connection between poetry and

philosophy is also very important (206). But local concerns made Lezama Lima’s reading

of Heidegger’s conception of being-toward-death very literal, so he rejected this idea and

replaced it with a notion of man-to-life through a poetic creation that served the purpose

of resurrection, evoking a being that defeats death, the arrival of pure life (Huerta, 10).

Death, of course, was a dangerous word to use in areas in which population had been

deemed inferior and already well along the path to evolutionary extinction.

The possibility of entering into the flow of life, and linking oneself with the other,

means, as Elizabeth Grosz has explained, that this inner continuity is that “through which

[individuals] can access the world of matter and the world of objects, through which a

different kind of knowledge is possible” (48). The new vitalist form developed by

Zambrano and Lezama Lima, though, is less interested in the possibilities of matter and

more focused on the possibility of a logos achieved through spirituality and

  22

immateriality. The state of ex-tasis, of being outside oneself, results from the interactions

between philosophy and poetry that were common practice among many avant-garde

artists worldwide by the 1930s.7

Lezama Lima shared with Zambrano an interest in a form of vitalism that

mediated rationalism with an eclectic collection of philosophical material, including

Bergsonian intuitionism. Through this intuitionism a subject can access the internal life

of things, the flow of life paralyzed by rationalism. But this continuous movement that

refers to action has to be experienced. This access grants us the power to link the logical

with the pre-logical, and our ordinary existence with our primal world. This connection

between literature and Bergson’s work was widespread in Europe and the United States,

but among Spanish American writers it was also related to local politics in a unique way.

Locality explains Lezama Lima’s interest in a different vitalist position than

Zambrano’s. His uses of memory and metaphor are linked to an artistic search for an

identity that revealed the creative subject of a modern nation. Artistic subjecthood is very

important in his understanding of the poetic, and in his entering into the stream of life

there is a conception of poetry as a way to know locality: the revelation of a country

through its language and metaphor. It is for this reason that critics of his writings can

identify in them both a universal modern project, and a project for Cuba. For example,

according to one analysis of his novel Paradiso, there are traces of “Proust and Gide” in

it, together with the discovery “of multiple facets of our peninsular reality” (López

Segrera, 96). In 1957 he developed some of these ideas with the publication of La

Expresión Americana, in which there is a return to Spain and its baroque poetry. If for

Zambrano poetic reason is related to self-denial, in Lezama the writing of poetry is an act

  23

of self-affirmation, and the encounter with self through language. As Tania Gentic puts it,

“his counterpoint is not a dialogic theory of movement rooted in binary dichotomies, but

rather a complex, spatially metaphorized figuring of identity created by a sistema poético,

the imago, and the sujeto metafórico. These interrelated mechanisms create the

expression that, according to him, makes America unique but also allows for a non-

hierarchical connection between it and Europe to exist” (187).

In this type of artistic renewal we can see how creative practice was developed

through philosophy, and, in the case of Zambrano, how philosophy was expanded

through artistic practice. Lezama Lima, the writer, wanted to use the philosophical

vitalism of his time in order to claim an artistic practice rooted in the knowledge of his

country; Zambrano, the philosopher, wanted to create a different way to do philosophy

through creative writing, a poesis that sustained the possibility of a different knowledge.

For both, this new way to understand reality had important political consequences and

uses, which allowed them to integrate their countries within the universal flow of life that

characterized their humanism.

Conclusions:

In this essay I showed how by the beginning of the 20th century the paths of Spain

and Spanish America were reunited in a search for a philosophical system that could

effectively address the limitations imposed by biological determinism and racism. This

concern with creating a more spiritual identity that fostered the production of knowledge

in locality, was aided early on by the French philosophers who renewed the interest in

pure philosophical and speculative approaches. This brought a reconnection with

  24

vitalism, classical ideas, German philosophy, and the work of Bergson who seemed to

synthetize many of the philosophical currents that had been relevant since the emergence

of literary Modernism in the 1890s.

Bergson became a link to both scientific thought and art in a way that allowed for

the restoration of will and freedom in the search for self-realization. But Zambrano and

Lezama Lima moved a step away from Bergsonian ideas in their attempt to develop new

forms of knowing that restored poetry and creation as the basis of logos. This was also

common to other intellectuals of the time, including the Mexican poet Octavio Paz (1914-

1998), another friend of Zambrano. This exploration of the links that existed between

poetry and philosophy was helpful in the process of creating a more inclusive modernist

culture through the connection to local experience.

These cultural-political reconstitutions allowed intellectuals like Zambrano and

Lezama Lima to create an alternative way of knowledge. Zambrano’s approach is linked

to the recovery of Spanish mysticism as an example of the way in which otherness could

be accessed and reconciled. The culture of the sacred is the opening to the mystery that

reveals true humanity and the flow that connects us to otherness and our limits. In the

case of Lezama Lima, the politics of his aesthetic model seems to make him an aristocrat

removed from the popular tastes and reality of his country, a charge that was quite costly

after the Cuban Revolution. But paying attention to the historical discussion of this essay,

the attacks on Lezama Lima’s appears to be disconnected from the reality his generation

had to faced. The constitution of a modern national identity was quite elusive during the

second half of the nineteenth century for intellectuals in Spain and Spanish America. It is

for this reason that the intellectual movements of the next century moved the discussion

  25

of nation and modernity away from extinction and death, and into the realm of life and

creation. The artistic path to explore a different way to produce national culture was not

limited in terms of class, but in terms of the ability to become an artist. But this

exploration intended to reveal the nation through the artist, did not imply that this was a

pure individualist effort, since what it was discovered, the source of life, was universally

shared. The anti-essentialism of a project that emphasized vital energy and becoming

turned out to be negative in the 1960s, but it meant resurrection, life, and possibility, as

Lezama Lima put it, in the 1940s.

                                                                                                               Endnotes 1 For example, see: Zambrano, María. "Cuba y la poesía de José Lezama Lima." Insula 23 (1968): 260-261; Zambrano, María, and Cintio Vitier. "Breve testimonio de un encuentro inacabable." Paradiso. Ed. Cintio Vitier. España: Archivos (1988); Zambrano, María. "Hombre verdadero: José Lezama Lima." Lezama Lima. Taurus Ediciones, 1987; Poumier, María. "José Lezama Lima y María Zambrano “sembrados” en La Habana” Vivarium, IX. La Habana (1994); Álvarez, José Manuel González. "Insularismo, literatura y cubanidad en la poética de José Lezama Lima." Espéculo: Revista de Estudios Literarios 21 (2002): 52; Johnson, Roberta. "María Zambrano's Theory of Literature as Knowledge and Contingency." Hispania (1996): 215-221; Sainz, Enrique. "La obra inicial de María Zambrano en José Lezama Lima y Cintio Vitier: algunos apuntes." República de las Letras: revista literaria de la Asociación Colegial de Escritores 84 (2004): 133-149. 2 García Calderón is probably referring to these two books by Fouillée: Le Mouvement Idéaliste et la Réaction contre la Science Positive. Paris: Alcan, 1896; Le Mouvement Positiviste et la Conception Sociologique du Monde. Paris: Alcan, 1896. 3 The work of Guyeau was also known through this book by Fouillée, La morale, l'art et la religion d'après Guyau. Paris: Alcan, 1901. 4 “Emile Boutroux, like Bergson and James, reoriented inquiry into the philosophical tradition. Boutroux saw the major philosophers as taking from the past rather than as embodying an historical moment of universal spirit. Like Bergson he privileged the experiential over the a priori and individual development over social order.” See: Robert T. Conn. The Politics of Philology: Alfonso Reyes and the Invention of the Latin American Literary Tradition. Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press, 2002, 53. 5 Lovejoy was a disciple of Henry James, and himself very influential among poets. He had, for example, a great influence on the work Robert Frost.

  26

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         6 This idea of solitude is also very similar to the one that Octavio Paz will develop in his work about Mexican identity. See: The Labyrinth of Solitude: The Other Mexico, Return to the Labyrinth of Solitude, Mexico and the United States, the Philanthropic Ogre. New York, Grove Press, 1994 7 In fact Zambrano’s ex-tasis has similarities with Sergei Eisenstein’s conception of it in that the latter also search through art a way in which the spectator could be removed from his ordinary life and perceptions. His interest in the baroque also follows a model that is similar to Lezama Lima’s. On Eisenstein, see: Salazkina, Masha. In Excess: Sergei Eisenstein's Mexico. University of Chicago Press, 2009. Works Cited “Are the Latin Races Doomed? The Nation 69 n. 1800 (Dec. 28, 1899): 477-478. Baralt, Luis A. “Educación de los Sentimientos y de la Voluntad.” Anales de la Academia de Ciencias Médicas, Físicas y Naturales de la Habana 43 (1906-1907): 159-166. Bell, Michael. Open Secrets: Literature, Education, and Authority from J. J. Rousseau to J. M. Coetzee. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. Bergson, Henri. Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness.

Translated by F.L. Pogson. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1910. ------------------- Creative Evolution. New York: Henry Holt, 1911. ------------------ Laughter; An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic. London:

Macmillan & Co., 1911. ------------------- Matter and Memory. Translated by Nancy Margaret Paul. New York:

Macmillan, 1912. ------------------ Mind-energy: lectures and essays. Translated by Herbert Wildon Carr. New York: H. Holt, 1920. ------------------ “The Perception of Change,” in his The Creative Mind: An Introduction

to Metaphysics. Translated by Mabelle L. Andison. Mineola, N.Y.: Courier Dover Publications, 2010.

Deleuze, Gilles. Bergsonism. New York: Zone Books, 1988. Dosil Mancilla, Francisco Javier, «El exilio en Cuba de María Zambrano», In María Zambrano. Pensamiento y exilio. Antolín Sánchez Cuervo, Agustín Sánchez Andrés y Gerardo Sánchez Díaz (coords.). Morelia: Universidad Michoacana / Comunidad de Madrid, 2004: 125-172.

  27

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                          Ferreiro Alemparte, Jaime. “José Ortega y Gasset y el pensamiento alemán en España.” Glossae: Revista de Historia del Derecho Europeo 2 (1989-1990): 143-159. García Calderón, Francisco. Latin America: Its Rise and Progress. Translated by Bernard Miall. New York: C. Scribner’s Sons, 1915. Gentic, Tania. "Creating Poetic Subjectivity in María Zambrano and José Lezama Lima." Revista Hispánica Moderna 63.2 (2010): 173-192. Guerlac, Suzanne. “Foreword.” In Understanding Bergson, Understanding Modernism. Gontarski, S. E., Paul Ardoin, and Laci Mattison, eds. London: Blackwell, 2013: i-iv. Gingerich, Stephen D. "Europe's Frenzy: European and Spanish Universality in María Zambrano." CR: The New Centennial Review 8.3 (2008): 189-214. Hass, Robert Bernard. "(Re) Reading Bergson: Frost, Pound and the Legacy of Modern Poetry." Journal of Modern Literature 29.1 (2006): 55-75. Huerta, David. “Trece Motivos para Lezama.” In, José Lezama Lima. Muerte de Narciso: antología poética. Ediciones Era, 1988: 9-31. Kelly, Michael R. “A Reading of Two Sources of Morality and Religion, or Bergsonian Wisdom, Emotion, and Integrity,” in Understanding Bergson, Understanding Modernism. Gontarski, S. E., Paul Ardoin, and Laci Mattison, eds. London: Bloomsbury, 2013: Jones, Donna V. The Racial Discourses of Life Philosophy: Négritude, Vitalism, and Modernity. Columbia University Press, 2010. Jones, Rufus M. “Bergson.” Present Day Papers 1 (1914): 270-273. Laurenzi, Elena. "El funámbulo y el payaso. Notas sobre Friedrich Nietzsche y María Zambrano." Aurora: papeles del Seminario María Zambrano 9: 21-27. Lezama Lima, José. Paradiso. Translated by Gregory Rabassa. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1968. ----------------------- El reino de la imagen. Caracas: Fundación Biblioteca Ayacucho, 1981. ----------------------- La Expresión Americana. Mexico: Fondo de Cultura Económica, 2013.

López Segrera, Francisco. "Lezama Lima‚ figura central del grupo Orígenes." Cahiers du monde hispanique et luso-brésilien (1971): 87-97.

  28

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         Lovejoy, Arthur O. "The meaning of vitalism." Science 33.851 (1911): 610-614. McIntire, Gabrielle. Modernism, Memory, and Desire. Cambridge University Press, 2008. Mora García, José Luis. “Sobre el Sentido de Expresarse así entre Nosotros.” ARBOR Ciencia, Pensamiento y Cultura 734 (November/December 2008): 1061-1070. Morán, Jesús. “Transfering Self to Other.” Claritas: Journal of Dialogue and Culture, 2:2 (October 2013): 12-19. Mülberger, Annette. "Spanish experience with German psychology prior to World War I." Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 44.2 (2008): 161-179. Ortega y Gasset, José. ¿Qué es la Filosofía? In Obras Completas vol. 7. Madrid: Revista de Occidente, 1969. Ortiz, Fernando. Entre Cubanos: Psicología Tropical. La Habana: Editorial de Ciencias Sociales, 1987. Ritter, E. “Controversy between Materialism and Vitalism.” Science 33.851 (1911): 437-441. Rodó, José. Ariel. Translated by Margaret Sayers Peden. Austin: University of Texas Press, 1988. Serrano, Carlos. "Miguel de Unamuno y Fernando Ortiz (un caso de regeneracionismo trasatlántico)." Nueva Revista de Filología Hispánica (1987): 299-310. Herbert Spencer, “Some Regrets,” in Facts and Comments (New York: Appleton & Co., 1902), 6-11. Vasconcelos, José. “Pitágoras.” Cuba Contemporánea 4:12 (September/December 1916): 66-94; 201-224. Warren, Howard C. "Mechanism versus Vitalism, in the Domain of Psychology." The Philosophical Review (1918): 597-615. Zambrano, María. Delirium and Destiny: A Spaniard in Her Twenties. Translated by Carol Maier. Albany: SUNY Press, 1999. --------------------- Hacia un Saber sobre el Alma. Madrid: Alianza Editorial, 2000.