can bad science be good evidence

Upload: palmite9

Post on 08-Aug-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    1/40Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1448744

    University of Virginia School of LawPublic Law and Legal Theory Research Paper Series No. 2009-14

    Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence? Lie Detection,

    Neuroscience and the Mistaken Conflation of Legal and

    Scientific Norms

    Frederick SchauerUniversity of Virginia School of Law

    October 2009

    This paper may be downloaded without charge from the

    Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection:

    http://ssrn.com/abstract=1448744

    A complete index of University of Virginia School of Law research papers is available at

    Law and Economics:http://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-LEC.html

    Public Law and Legal Theory:http://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-PUB.html

    http://ssrn.com/abstract=1448744http://ssrn.com/abstract=1448744http://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-LEC.htmlhttp://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-LEC.htmlhttp://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-LEC.htmlhttp://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-PUB.htmlhttp://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-PUB.htmlhttp://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-PUB.htmlhttp://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-PUB.htmlhttp://www.ssrn.com/link/U-Virginia-LEC.htmlhttp://ssrn.com/abstract=1448744
  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    2/40Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1448744

    Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence? Lie Detection,

    Neuroscience and the Mistaken Conflation of Legal and

    Scientific Norms

    Frederick Schauer

    Abstract

    As the capabilities of cognitive neuroscience, in particular functional magnetic resonance

    imaging (fMRI) 'brain scans,' have become more advanced, some have claimed that fMRI-based

    lie-detection can and should be used at trials and for other forensic purposes to determine

    whether witnesses and others are telling the truth. Although some neuroscientists have

    promoted such claims, most aggressively resist them, and arguing that the research on

    neuroscience-based lie-detection is deeply flawed in numerous ways. And so these

    neuroscientists have resisted any attempt to use such methods in litigation, insisting that poor

    science has no place in the law. But although the existing studies have serious problems of

    validity when measured by the standards of science, and true as well that the reliability of such

    methods is significantly lower than their advocates claim, it is nevertheless an error to assume

    that the distinction between good and bad science, whether as a matter of validity or of

    reliability, is dispositive for law. Law is not only about putting criminals in jail, and numerous

    uses of evidence in various contexts in the legal system require a degree of probative value far

    short of proof beyond a reasonable doubt. And because legal and scientific norms, standards,

    and goals are different, good science may still not be good enough for some legal purposes,

    and, conversely, some examples of bad science my, in some contexts, still be good enough for

    law. Indeed, the exclusion of substandard science, when measured by scientific standards, may

    have the perverse effect of lowering the accuracy and rigor of legal fact-finding, because the

    exclusion of flawed science will only increase the importance of the even more flawed non-

    science that now dominates legal fact-finding. And thus the example of neuroscience-based lie

    detection, while timely and important in its own right, is even more valuable as a case study

    suggesting that Daubert v. Merrill-Dow Pharmaceuticals may have sent the legal system down a

    false path. By inappropriately importing scientific standards into legal decision-making with

    little modification, Daubert confused the goals of science with those of law, a mistake that it is

    not too late for the courts to correct.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    3/40Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1448744

    1

    Forthcoming in Cornell Law Review, vol. 95 (2010), draft of 09/08/2009

    CAN BAD SCIENCE BE GOOD EVIDENCE? NEUROSCIENCE, LIE-DETECTION, AND BEYOND

    Frederick Schauer1

    I. INTRODUCTION

    How should the legal system confront the advances in the brain sciences that may

    possibly allow more accurate determinations of veracity lie detecting than those that now

    pervade the litigation process? In this Essay I seek to question the view, widespread among

    the scientists most familiar with these advances, that the neuroscience of lie-detecting is not,

    or at least not yet, nearly reliable enough to be used in civil and criminal litigation or for related

    forensic purposes. But in challenging the neuroscientists and their allies, I make no claims for

    the science of lie-detecting that go beyond the current state of scientific knowledge or, more

    importantly, my own ability to speak about the relevant scientific developments. Rather, I

    1David and Mary Harrison Distinguished Professor of Law, University of Virginia. This Essay was

    presented on September 5, 2009, at the Mini-Foro on Proof and Truth in the Law, Institute for

    Philosophical Research, Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mxico (UNAM), on April 7, 2009,

    as an Inaugural Lecture at the University of Virginia School of Law, and on June 1, 2009, at theDuck Conference on Social Cognition. Many of the ideas presented here were generated during

    various meetings of the John D. and Catherine T. MacArthur Foundations Law and

    Neuroscience Project, whose tangible and intangible support I am delighted to acknowledge.

    Detailed and constructive comments by Charles Barzun, Teneille Brown, Greg Mitchell, John

    Monahan, and Bobbie Spellman have made this version immeasurably better than its

    predecessors.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    4/40

    2

    argue that because laws goals and norms are different from those of science, there is no more

    reason to impose the standards of science on law than there is to impose the standards of law

    on science. Law must and should use science, and should always prefer good science to bad,

    but in some contexts good science may still not be good enough for law, and in other contexts

    hence the title of this Essay bad science, if measured by the standards of scientists, may still

    have valuable legal uses. To be clear, however, my goal in this paper is decidedly notto argue

    that neuroscience-based lie detection should, now or even in the foreseeable future,

    necessarily be admissible in court or legitimately used for other forensic purposes. Rather, it is

    to argue that the question whether neuroscience-based lie detection should be used for legal-

    system purposes is a question that cannot be answered exclusively according to scientific

    standards of reliability and validity. Science can (and should) inform the legal system about the

    facts, including facts about degrees of reliability and the extent of experimental validity, but the

    ultimate normative and institutional question of whether and when, if at all, a given degree of

    validity or reliability is sufficient for this or that legal or forensic purpose is a legal and not a

    scientific question.

    In important respects the analysis of the potential legal uses of neuroscience-based lie-

    detection is more case study than discrete topic. Most of what I argue here applies to other

    forms of lie-detection, to other forms of scientific evidence, and indeed to evidence generally.

    And as I elaborate in the latter part of this Essay, my central theme may call into doubt some

    dimensions of the modern revolution in the standards for the admission of scientific evidence.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    5/40

    3

    Starting with Daubert v. Merrill Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc.,2and continuing through General

    Electric Co. v. Joiner3and Kumho Tire Co., Ltd. v. Carmichael,

    4the Supreme Court over the past

    sixteen years has attempted to deal with the very real problem of junk science by imposing

    increasingly stringent scientific standards of reliability and experimental validity on the

    admissibility of scientific evidence and expert testimony in the federal courts. In dealing with

    science and experts but not with the myths and superstitions that pervade the fact-finding

    process, however, the Court may, unintentionally have lowered the quality of evidence

    generally. By discouraging poor science while leaving non-science untouched, the Daubert

    revolution may perversely have increased reliance on the even worse science that dominates

    the litigation process by not masquerading as science at all. There may not be an easy solution

    to this problem, but its identification suggests that Daubertmay have created as many

    problems as it solved. The revolution in scientific and expert testimony that started with

    Daubert, therefore, is, or at least should be, far from over.

    II. NEUROSCIENCE-BASED LIE-DETECTION: CLAIMS AND COUNTER-CLAIMSI commence by describing the current controversy over the legal and forensic

    5uses of

    neuroscience-based lie-detection. In some respects the controversy should come as no

    surprise. The common law litigation process places huge reliance on the sworn testimony of

    2509 U.S. 579 (1993).

    3522 U.S. 136 (1997).

    4526 U.S. 137 (1999).

    5In this Essay I use forensic, as distinguished from legal, to refer to those dimensions of

    criminal investigation that precede or exist apart from the trial

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    6/40

    4

    witnesses, a phenomenon that is itself worthy of note.6

    Many other methods of factual

    investigation, after all, employ dramatically different approaches relying far more heavily on

    primary rather than secondary sources of knowledge. The scientist who seeks to determine

    whether drinking red wine reduces the likelihood of heart disease does not summon

    representatives of the wine industry and the Temperance League to each make their cases,

    following which she decides which of the two advocates is more believable. Rather, she

    engages in the kind of primary research we call experimentation. So too with historians when

    they do original archival research, psychologists when they conduct experiments on subjects,

    empirical economists when they perform multiple regressions with large data sets,

    oceanographers when the explore the sea with scientific instruments or submersible

    watercraft, and researchers for policy-makers when they combine techniques such as these and

    others to determine the factual terrain for which they will make policy.7

    6Although sworn witness testimony also plays a large role in the civil law, the qualification in

    the text to the common law is a function of the somewhat larger role that judges play in many

    civil law countries in managing the process of direct factual investigation, especially in criminal

    cases. See Mireille Delmas-Marty & J.R. Spencer, European Criminal Procedures (2002);

    Jacqueline Hodgson, French Criminal Justice: A Comparative Account of the Investigation and

    Prosecution of Crime in France (2005).

    7Testimony and other forms of indirect evidence do play a significant role outside of law. See,

    for example, C.A.J. Coady, Testimony: A Philosophical Study (1992); Elizabeth Fricker,

    Testimony: Knowing Through Being Told, in Handbook of Epistemology 109 (I. Niiniluoto, M.

    Sintonen, & J. Wolenski, eds., 2004); Axel Gelfert, Indefensible Middle Ground for LocalReductionism about Testimony, 22 Ratio (new series) 170 (2009); John Hardwig, The Role of

    Trust in Knowledge, 88 J. Phil. 693 (1991). Nevertheless, law is noteworthy in relying on

    testimony and authority more than most other disciplines, and, conversely, and especially in

    courtroom settings, relying substantially less on direct investigation and experimentation.

    *A+uthority and hierarchy play a role in law that would be inimical to scientific investigation.

    Richard A. Posner, The Problems of Jurisprudence 62 (1990).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    7/40

    5

    Once we grasp the diverse array of primary techniques for determining facts -- for

    figuring out what is or was the case we can understand how unusual the legal system is in

    routinely using party-generated witnesses to provide information as to which they, but not the

    trier of fact, have first-hand knowledge,8

    and as to which the trier of fact is ordinarily precluded

    from obtaining the first-hand knowledge that in other domains remains the gold standard for

    empirical reliability. Still, the legal system we have, idiosyncratic as it is within the realm of

    empirical inquiry in relying so heavily on second-hand knowledge, is one in which it is often

    important to determine which of two opposing witnesses is telling the truth.

    Of course not all of litigation involves a conflict between a truth-teller and a liar. Honest

    misperceptions and more-or-less honest omissions, exaggerations, shadings, fudgings,

    slantings, bendings, and hedgings9

    are an omnipresent feature of modern litigation. But so too

    is flat-out lying, and it should come as no surprise that because the legal system relies far more

    heavily on the reports of witnesses than on primary investigation by the trier of fact, the law

    has long been preoccupied with trying to assess whether the witnesses who testify in court (or

    otherwise provide information for legal or forensic decision-making) are telling the truth.

    Historically, the law relied on the oath to serve the truth-warranting function. When

    people genuinely believed that lying under oath would send them to hell, the law could

    8Fed. R. Evid. 609.

    9See Frederick Schauer & Richard Zeckhauser, Paltering, in Deception: From Ancient Empires to

    Internet Dating 38 (Brooke Harrington, ed., 2009).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    8/40

    6

    comfortably rely on a witnesss fear of burning for eternity to provide confidence that

    witnesses were unlikely to say things they believed to be untrue.10

    As religious belief diminished, or at least as laws confidence in it as a guarantor of truth

    waned, the legal system had its own substitute, increasingly relying on faith in the lie-exposing

    powers of vigorous cross-examination. As celebrated in the Perry Mason television series of the

    1950s and 1960s, and as reinforced by numerous items of popular culture since, the legal

    system has long believed that cross-examination will so reduce the effectiveness of lying that a

    truth-determining system relying on witness testimony and subsequent cross-examination

    would not be unacceptably vulnerable to intentional deception.11

    More importantly, and

    because cross-examination is far less effective in exposing lies and liars than television writers

    and their viewers believe, the legal system has placed its faith in judges and juries. Now, the

    task of determining veracity, and credibility in general, has been assigned largely to the trier of

    fact,12

    most visibly even if not most frequently the jury, which in engaging in this task is asked

    10See Thomas Raeburn White, Oaths in Judicial Proceedings and Their Effect upon the

    Competency of Witnesses, 51 U. Pa. L. Rev. 373 (1903); Daniel Blau, Note, Holy Scriptures and

    Unholy Strictures: Why the Enforcement of a Religious Orthodoxy Demands a More Refined

    Establishment Clause Analysis of Courtroom Oaths, 4 First Amend. L. Rev. 223, 226-29 (2006).

    11See 5 John Henry Wigmore, Evidence in Trials at Common Law 32 (James Chadbourn ed.,

    1974).

    12See, e.g.,United States v. Barnard, 490 F.2d 907, 912 (9

    thCir. 1973) (the jury is the lie

    detector in the courtroom); State v. Christensen, 163 P.3d 1175 (Idaho, 2007) (holding thatadmission of polygraph evidence would invade the province of the jury); Bloom v. People, 185

    P.3d 797, 807 (Colo. 2008) (same); State v. Lyon, 744 P.2d 231, 240 (Or. 1987) (Linde, J.,

    concurring) (same). See also United States v. Thompson, 615 F.2d 329, 332-33 (5th

    Cir. 1980)

    (stating that issues of credibility in general are for jury); State v. Myers, 382 N.W.2d 91, 97

    (Iowa, 1986) (same). A comprehensive historical account is George Fisher, The Jurys Rise as Lie

    Detector, 107 Yale L.J. 575(1997).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    9/40

    7

    to assess, among other things, the demeanor of a witnesses, their past record of truth-telling

    (or not), the internal coherence of their stories, and the external coherence of their stories with

    the stories of others, all in order to determine who is telling the truth and who is not.

    Enter science. Because the criteria traditionally employed by judges and juries to

    evaluate the veracity of witnesses have been notoriously unreliable,13

    the quest for a scientific

    way of distinguishing the truth-teller from the liar has been with us for generations. Indeed,

    what for many years was the prevailing legal standard for determining the admissibility of

    scientific evidence the Frye test14

    arose in 1923 in the context of an unsuccessful attempt to

    admit into evidence a rudimentary lie-detection machine invented by William Moulton

    Marston. Marston is perhaps better known as the creator of the comic book character Wonder

    Woman, whose attributes included possession of a magic lasso, forged from the Magic Girdle of

    Aphrodite, which would make anyone it encircled tell the truth without fail. The device at issue

    in Frye was a simple polygraph and not a magic lasso, but not only did Frye set the standard for

    the admission of scientific evidence for more than half a century, its exclusion of lie-detection

    13Useful summaries of the research are in Aldert Vrij, Detecting Lies and Deceit: The Psychology

    of Lying and the Implications for Professional Practice (2000); Jeremy A. Blumenthal,A Wipe of

    the Hands, A Lick of the Lips: The Validity of Demeanor Evidence in Assessing Witness Credibility,

    72 Nebr. L. Rev. 1157 (1993);Lindsley Smith,Juror Ability to Determine Deception and Veracity,

    4 Comm. L. Rev. 4 (2000); Olin Guy Wellborn III, Demeanor, 76 Corn. L. Rev. 1075, 1082-88

    (1991).

    14Frye v. United States, 293 F. 1013, 1014 (D.C. Cir. 1923) (holding that scientific evidence must

    use methods generally accepted in the relevant scientific community).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    10/40

    8

    technology also paved the way for the continuing exclusion, with few exceptions, of lie-

    detection evidence in American courts.15

    The science of lie-detection has improved considerably since 1923, but not by so much

    as to lead to large-scale changes in judicial attitudes. Indeed, after the replacement (in federal

    courts) in 1993 ofFryes general acceptance test by Daubert v. Merrill Dow Pharmaceuticals

    Inc.16

    and its insistence on various indicia of scientific reliability as a precondition of the

    admissibility of evidence purporting to be scientific, the situation has remained much the

    same.17

    What makes the foregoing important is the rapidly changing state of cognitive

    neuroscience the study of human thinking using various methods of (indirectly) measuring

    15See, e.g., Brown v. Darcy, 783 F.2d 1389, 1394 (9

    thCir. 1986) (excluding lie-detection

    evidence); United States v. Gilliard, 133 F.3d 809, 815 (11th

    Cir. 1998) (same); United States v.

    Sanchez, 118 F.3d 192 (4th

    Cir. 1997) (same); Wilkins v. State, 190 P.3d 957 (Kan. 2008) (same);

    State v. Jones, 753 N.W.2d 677 (Minn. 2008) (same); People v. Richardson, 183 P.3d 1146 (Cal.

    2008) (same). Decisions more sympathetic to the use of polygraph evidence under someconditions include United States v. Cordoba, 104 F.3d 225, 228 (9

    thCir. 1997) (holding that a per

    se exclusion of polygraph testimony does not survive Daubert); Rupe v. Wood, 93 F.3d 1434 (9th

    Cir. 1996) (holding polygraph evidence admissible to support defendants statement at

    sentencing hearing); United States v. Posado, 57 F.3d 428 (5th

    Cir. 1995) (rejecting per se

    exclusion); United States v. Crumby, 895 F. Supp. 1354 (D. Ariz. 1995) (limiting polygraph use to

    corroborating or impeaching defendants testimony); United States v. Galbreth, 908 F. Supp.

    877, 896 (D.N.M. 1995) (allowing polygraph evidence if examiner is properly qualified);

    Commonwealth v. Duguay, 720 N.E.2d 458, 463 (Mass. 1999) (same). The issue is sometimes

    dealt with by statute. Such statutes typically exclude polygraph evidence, as in California

    Evidence Code 351.1 (2008), but New Mexico is an exception. New Mexico Rules of Evidence

    11-707 (2008).

    16509 U.S. 579 (1993). Further refinements were added by the Supreme Court in Kumho Tire

    Co., Ltd. v. Carmichael, 526 U.S. 137 (1999), and General Electric Co. v. Joiner, 522 U.S. 136

    (1997).

    17See Christopher B. Mueller & Laird C. Kirkpatrick, Evidence 701-04 (4

    thed., 2009).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    11/40

    9

    brain activity, as opposed simply to examining the overt behaviors that such brain activity

    generates. The tools of modern neuroscience are numerous, but the most prominent of them

    is fMRI functional magnetic resonance imaging.18

    Commonly called brain scanning, fMRI

    examination holds out the possibility of being able to determine which parts of the brain are

    being used for which cognitive tasks. Although novices seeing an fMRI scan sometimes believe

    that certain parts of the brain light up when engaged in certain tasks,19

    what actually occurs is

    that the portion of the brain being used recruits more oxygenated blood cells to help it in its

    task, and thus what appears to be a lit up part of the brain is actually a part of the brain that has

    more oxygenated hemoglobin in it than it had when it was less or differently cognitively

    engaged.

    As should by now be apparent, the development of fMRI technology has led some

    researchers to believe that this technology can be effective in distinguishing liars from truth-

    tellers.20

    Ifand it is a huge if different parts of the brain are used for lying than for truth

    18Accessible explanations of the fMRI include Scott A. Huettel, Allen W. Song, & Gregory

    McCarthy, Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (2004); Marcus Raichle,A Brief History of

    Functional Brain Mapping, in Brain Mapping: The Systems 33 (Arthur W. Toga & John Mazziotta

    eds., 2000); Marcus E. Raichle,A Brief History of Human Brain Mapping, 32 Trends in

    Neuroscience 118 (2008); Marcus E. Raichle & Mark A. Mintun, Brain Work and Brain Imaging,

    29 Ann. Rev. Neuroscience 449 (2006).

    19See Teneille Brown & Emily Murphy, Functional Neuroimaging as Evidence of a Defendants

    Past Mental States, 62 Stan. L. Rev. (forthcoming 2010), manuscript, at 64.

    20See Christos Davatzikos, et al., Classifying Spatial Patterns of Brain Activity with Machine

    Learning Methods: Application to Lie Detection, 28 NeuroImage 663 (2005);G. Ganis, et al.,

    Neural Correlates of Different Types of Deception: An fMRI Investigation, 13 Cerebral Cortex 830

    (2003); Joshua D. Greene & Joseph M. Paxton, 106 Patterns of Neural Activity Associated with

    Honest and Dishonest Moral Decisions, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA

    12506 (2009); F. Andrew Kozel, Tamara M. Padgett, & Mark George, Brief Communications: A

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    12/40

    10

    telling, or for deception rather than honesty, then the possibility exists of using a brain scan to

    determine whether the person whose brain is being scanned is lying or telling the truth. Or so

    it is claimed. And so especially is it claimed by those who see the commercial potential for just

    this technology. For-profit companies, in particular No Lie MRI21

    and CEPHOS,22

    have already

    begun marketing their lie-detection services, and these companies and their principals have

    been at the forefront of those touting the courtroom and forensic potential of the new

    technology.

    Replication Study of the Neural Correlates of Deception, 118 Behavioural Neuroscience 852

    (2004); Andrew Kozel, et al., Detecting Deception Using Functional Magnetic Imaging, 58

    Biological Psychiatry 605 (2005); Andrew Kozel, et al.,A Pilot Study of Functional Magnetic

    Resonance Imaging Brain Correlates of Deception in Healthy Young Men, 16 J. Neuropsychiatry

    & Clinical Neuroscience 295 (2004); Daniel D. Langleben, Detection of Deception with fMRI: Are

    We There Yet?, 13 Legal Criminological Psych. 1 (2008); Daniel D. Langleben, et al., Telling Truth

    from Lie in Individual Subjects with Fast Event-Related fMRI, 26 Human Brain Mapping 262

    (2005), pp. 262-72;Daniel D. Langleben, et al., Brain Activity During Simulated Deception: An

    Event-Related Functional Magnetic Resonance Study, 15 NeuroImage 727 (2002); Tatia M.C.

    Lee, et al., Neural Correlates of Feigned Memory Impairment, 28 NeuroImage 305 (2005);TatiaM.C. Lee, et al., Lie Detection by Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging, 15 Human Brain

    Mapping 157 (2002); Donald H. Marks, Mehdi Adineh, & Sudeepa Gupta, Determination of

    Truth From Deception Raising Functional MRI and Cognitive Engrams, 5 Internet J. Radiology

    (2006); Feroze Mohamed, et al., Brain Mapping of Deception and Truth Telling abut an

    Ecologically Valid Situation: Function MR Imaging and Polygraph Investigation Initial

    Experience, 238 Radiology 679 (2006);Jennifer Maria Nunez et al., Intentional False Responding

    Shares Neural Substrates with Response Conflict and Cognitive Control, 25 NeuroImage 267

    (2005); Sean A. Spence, et al., Speaking of Secrets and Lies: The Contribution of Ventrolateral

    Prefrontal Cortex to Vocal Deception, 40 NeuroImage 1411 (2008), pp. 1411-18;Sean A.

    Spence, at al., Behavioural and Functional Anatomical Correlates of Deception in Humans, 12

    Brain Imaging NeuroReport 2849 (2001);Paul Root Wolpe & Daniel D. Langleben, Lies, Damn

    Lies, and Lie Detectors, 86(2) Harv. Bus. Rev. 25 (2008); Paul Root Wolpe, et al., Emerging

    Neurotechnologies for Lie_Detection: Promises and Perils, 5 Am. J. Bioethics 39 (2005).

    21Seehttp://noliemri.com

    22Seewww.cephoscorp.com .

    http://noliemri.com/http://noliemri.com/http://noliemri.com/http://www.cephoscorp.com/http://www.cephoscorp.com/http://www.cephoscorp.com/http://www.cephoscorp.com/http://noliemri.com/
  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    13/40

    11

    Neuroscience-based lie detection follows a long history of lie-detection technology. The

    earliest polygraphs were based on blood pressure, and more modern techniques include

    electroencephalography, which measures electric current generated by the brain,23

    the analysis

    of facial micro-expressions of the kind developed by the psychologist Paul Ekman and now at

    the center of the television series Lieto Me,24

    periorbital thermography,25

    which measures

    the temperature around the eyes, and near-infrared spectroscopy,26

    which uses infrared light

    to measure changes in blood flow and is thus the precursor of the even newer fMRI technology.

    These techniques each have their adherents, but I focus here on fMRI primarily because it

    appears by all accounts to be the most reliable of these techniques, although plainly not

    reliable enough, as we will see, to be endorsed for courtroom or forensic use by the vast

    majority of those most familiar with the technology.

    Indeed, in legal and policy debates almost as much as in physics, every action appears to

    produce an equal and opposite reaction. And so it has been with the reaction of mainstream

    academic neuroscientists to the claims regarding the lie-detection potential of fMRI scans. A

    prominent article by Stanford law professor Henry Greely and neuroscientist Judy Illes surveyed

    23See Lawrence A. Farwell & Sharon S. Smith, Using Brain MERMER to Detect Knowledge

    Despite Efforts to Conceal, 46 J. Forensic Sci. 135 (2001).

    24Paul Ekman, Telling Lies: Clues to Deceit in the Marketplace, Politics, and Marriage (3rd

    ed.,

    2001).

    25Ioannis Pavlidis & James Levine, Monitoring of Periorbital Blood Flow Rate Through Thermal

    Image Analysis and its Application to Polygraph Testing, 2 Engineering Med. & Biol. Socty 1183

    (2002).

    26See Britton Chance, et al.,A Novel Method for Fast Imaging of Brain Function, Non-Invasively,

    with Light,, 1 Optics Express 411 (1998).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    14/40

    12

    all of the existing studies of neuroscience-based lie-detection through 2006, concluding that

    each of the studies fell far short of existing scientific standards of rigor and that the studies,

    both individually and in the aggregate, did not come close to establishing the reliability of fMRI-

    based lie-detection.27

    Accordingly, Greely and Illes urged a legally imposed moratorium on the

    use of the technology for courtroom or forensic purposes until its reliability according to

    scientific standards could be established to the satisfaction of a federal regulatory agency.28

    Similarly, one leading neuroscientist has insisted that the data offer no compelling evidence

    that fMRI will work for lie detection in the real world.29

    Another has concluded that *a+t

    present we have no good ways of detecting deception despite our very great need for them.30

    And still another has concluded that using laboratory findings on fMRI lie-detection in settings

    that can potentially impact individuals legal rights should, on the current state of knowledge,

    27Henry T. Greely & Judy Illes, Neuroscience-Based Lie Detection: The Urgent Need for

    Regulation, 33 Am. J. L. & Med. 377(2007). See also Henry T. Greely, Neuroscience-Based Lie-

    Detection: The Need for Regulation,in Using Imaging to Identify Deceit: Scientific and EthicalQuestions 46 (American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 2009); Henry T. Greely, Premarket

    Approval Regulation for Lie Detection: An Idea Whose Time May Be Coming, 5 Am. J. Bioethics

    50 (2005); Jane Campbell Moriarty, Visions of Deception: Neuroimages and the Search for Truth,

    42 Akron L. Rev. 739 (2009); Michael S. Pardo, Neuroscience Evidence, Legal Culture, and

    Criminal Procedure, 33 Am. J. Crim. L. 301 (2006).

    28Greely & Illes, supra note 27, at 419-20.

    29Nancy Kanwisher, The Use of fMRI Lie Detection: What Has Been Shown and What Not, in

    Using Imaging to Identify Deceit, supra note 27, at 7, 12. The word compelling is important,

    because it sets the standard, or at least Kanwishers standard, for usability. Perhaps there is

    plausible evidence, or some evidence, or more persuasive than not evidence, even if

    there is not compelling evidence, and the question, to which I shall turn presently, is why

    compelling rather than some other standard is the one to be used.

    30Marcus E. Raichle,An Introduction to Functional Brain Imaging in the Context of Lie Detection,

    in Using Imaging to Identify Deceit, supra note 27, 3, at 6.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    15/40

    13

    remain a research topic, instead of a legal tool.31

    An editorial in Nature Neuroscience joined

    the chorus of skepticism,32

    as did a report from a National Research Council committee.33

    And

    several published articles by researchers and practitioners from various disciplines insisted that

    fMRI lie-detection was not ready for the real world.34

    Lying at the core of the campaign against the use of fMRI in real world legal settings is

    the conviction that the existing state of the research is poor science. And it is poor science, it is

    said, not only because of doubts about the reliability rates of neuro-science-based lie detecting

    methods, but also because the validity of the research alleged to support those methods and to

    determine the announced reliability rates is deeply flawed. The tests that have been

    conducted, they critics claim, are different in material ways from real-world lying and truth-

    telling, and thus it is a mistake to draw an inference from the accuracy of neural lie-detecting in

    experimental settings to the potential accuracy of those methods in detecting real-world liars.35

    31

    Elizabeth A. Phelps, Lying Outside the Laboratory: The Impact of Imagery and Emotion on theNeural Circuitry of Lie Detection, in Using Imaging to Identify Deceit, supra note 27, 14, at 20.

    32Editorial, 11 Nature Neuroscience 1231 (2008).

    33National Research Council, Committee on Military and Intelligence Methodology for

    Emergent Neurophysiological and Cognitive/Neural Research, Emerging Cognitive Neuroscience

    and Related Technologies (2008).

    34James R. Merikangas, Functional MRI Lie Detection, 36 J. Am. Acad. Psychiatry & L. 499 (2008);

    Michael S. Gazzaniga, The Law and Neuroscience, 60 Neuron 412 (2008); Jed S. Rakoff, Lie

    Detection in the Courts: The Vain Search for the Magic Bullet, in Using Imaging to IdentifyDeceit, supra note 27, at 40;Joseph R. Simpson, Functional MRI Lie Detection: Too Good to Be

    True?, 36 J. Am. Acad. Psychiatry & L. 491(2008); Sean A. Spence, Playing Devils Advocate: The

    Case Against fMRI Lie Detection, 13 Legal & Criminological Psych. 11 (2008).

    35Greely & Illes, supra note 27. To the same effect is the argument that *r+eports of finding

    brain patterns of activation corresponding to deception almost always use subjects (often

    university students) who are told to lie about something (usually a relatively unimportant

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    16/40

    14

    Part of the difference, indeed the major difference, is that in most instances the experimental

    subjects have been instructed to lie, and whether an instructed lie is even a lie at all presents

    substantial questions of construct validity whether the experiment measures what it purports

    to measure that cast significant doubts on the research conclusions.36

    There are also serious

    questions about sample size, levels of reliability, potentially confounding variables (whether

    subjects are left- or right-handed, for example, or whether the subject moved, factors that

    make a difference in evaluating fMRI results), external validity (whether experimental results

    would exist in even a parallel real-world situation), and the significant possibility that subjects

    could take counter-measures that would render the test results especially unreliable.37

    Thus,

    the existing research stands accused of being flawed even as pure laboratory research, and far

    less applicable to non-laboratory settings than its proponents have typically claimed.

    The charges against the existing research go even further. Many of the results have not

    been published in peer-reviewed journals and have not been replicated, thus failing to satisfy

    the normal standard for assessing scientific outcomes.38

    And quite a few of the experiments

    indeed, most of them -- have been conducted by those with some connection with No Lie MRI

    or CEPHOS and consequently with a commercial interest in the outcome. And, finally, the

    matter). Equating the lies told in such an artificial setting to the kind of lies people tell in reality

    is pure fantasy at this point. Editorial, supra note 32, at 1231.

    36See especially Kanwisher, supra note 29, at 12. See also Greely, Neuroscience-Based Lie-

    Detection,, supra note 27, at 50.

    37Greely, Neuroscience-Based Lie-Detection,supra note 27, at 50-51; National Research Council,

    supra note 33; Raichle, supra note 30, at 6.

    38Kanwisher, supra note 29, at 12.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    17/40

    15

    alleged degree of accuracy as high as 90%, according to some claims39

    of neural lie-

    detecting is considerably higher than what the experimental data actually show.40

    To the extent that the proponents of neural lie-detecting maintain that their claims

    about the reliability and accuracy of their methods are scientifically sound as the product of

    scientifically valid experimentation, they appear to have been exposed as relying on flawed

    science. Without better evidence of external validity, without dealing with the construct

    validity problem of distinguishing the genuine lie from following an instruction to utter words

    that are not literally true, without more rigorous scrutiny of the existing claims of reliability,

    without higher verified rates of accuracy, without replication, and without subjecting the

    research to peer review by financially disinterested scientists, the claimed ability to use fMRI

    testing to identify liars appears to be just that a claim and far from what good scientists take

    to be a sound scientific conclusion.

    III. ON THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENTIFIC AND LEGAL STANDARDSThe fact that the science to date appears both to be methodologically flawed and less

    than compelling in its conclusions is far from the end of the story, the arguments of the skeptics

    notwithstanding. The rest of the story, however, is not a story about science, but is instead

    primarily a story about law,41

    and about why there may be good reasons to doubt that the

    39Kozel (2005), supra note 20. See also Langleben (2005), supra 20 (76%); Davatzikos, supra

    note 20 (89%).

    40Greely, Neuroscience-Based Lie Detection,, supra note 27, at 51.

    41See Dale A. Nance, Reliability and the Admissibility of Experts, 34 Seton Hall L. Rev. 191, 203

    (2003) (arguing for use of legal standards in evaluating scientific expertise).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    18/40

    16

    many scientific failings of fMRI-based lie-detection are or should be dispositive for the legal

    system.

    First, law is about far more than putting criminals in jail, although that particular type of

    legal decision appears to generate the fear that motivates so much of the existing scientific

    criticism. One of the scientists quoted above has also said that the results would be especially

    unreliable if the subject believed that the results could send him to prison,42

    and another

    participant at the same symposium worried about a future in which the police may request a

    warrant to search your brain.43

    These may well be legitimate worries, but their seriousness

    depends largely on a view of the Fifth Amendment privilege against self-incrimination that

    would characterize an involuntary lie-detection test of whatever kind as physical and non-

    testimonial,44

    an outcome that seems unlikely, albeit not impossible, under current law. Given

    that law enforcement authorities may not require a suspect to talk at all, it is difficult to

    imagine a legal state of affairs in which a defendants statement is subject to an involuntary

    neuroscientific evaluation of its validity, and thus the circumstances in which an involuntary

    fMRI would be usable against a defendant would not only require a court to reject an earlier

    Supreme Court statement that the results of lie detector tests would be testimonial and thus

    42Statement of Nancy Kanwisher, as quoted in A Good Lie Detector is Hard to Find,

    http://web.mit.edu/newsoffice/2007/lying.html.

    43See Science News, Science Daily, February 19, 2007, at

    http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2007/02/070218184515.htm.

    44Schmerber v. California, 384 U.S. 757 (1964).

    http://web.mit.edu/newsoffice/2007/lying.htmlhttp://web.mit.edu/newsoffice/2007/lying.htmlhttp://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2007/02/070218184515.htmhttp://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2007/02/070218184515.htmhttp://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2007/02/070218184515.htmhttp://web.mit.edu/newsoffice/2007/lying.html
  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    19/40

    17

    encompassed by the Fifth Amendment,45

    but would also require that the fMRI not be used in

    conjunction with, or to test the validity of, any statement made by the defendant.46

    But even conceding for the sake of argument that a future that included brain scan

    warrants is a legitimate worry,47

    it is nevertheless a rather large leap to transpose that worry to

    a concern about numerous other potential courtroom and forensic uses of lie-detection

    technology. Most importantly, the question of what evidence the prosecution can use against a

    defendant is very different from the question of what evidence a defendant can use to attempt

    to establish his innocence under existing defendant-protective burdens of proof. Suppose, to

    attach some arbitrary but conservative numbers to the existing research, that an fMRI

    evaluation of a defendants claim of innocence I was somewhere else, or He started the

    fight, for example has an accuracy rate of 70%.48

    It is of course clear that we should not

    imprison people on a 70% probability of their guilt, and we do not do so. But whether to

    45Schmerber, 384 U.S. at 764.

    46See Benjamin Holley, Its All in Your Head: Neurotechnological Lie Detection and the Fourth

    and Fifth Amendments, 28 Developments in Mental Health L. 1 (2009); Sarah E. Stoller & Paul R.

    Wolpe, Emerging Neurotechnologies for Lie Detection and the Fifth Amendment, 33 Am. J. L. &

    Med. 359 (2007).

    47The worry is fueled in part by a case in Mumbai, India, in which an involuntary fMRI scan was

    used by the prosecution to challenge the veracity of a criminal defendant. SeeEditorial, supra

    note 32.

    48Note that the accuracy rate for identifying truth may differ from the accuracy rate foridentifying a lie. Suppose a defendant claims he was somewhere else when the crime was

    committed and suppose further that an fMRI indicates he is telling the truth. On the existing

    state of the research, see Kanwisher, supra note 29, at 8,this fMRI result is more reliable has

    a smaller percentage of errorsthan an fMRI result that indicated that the defendants

    statement was false. In other words, truths are identified as lies less often than lies are

    identified as truths.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    20/40

    18

    imprison people who are 70% likely to be guilty is not the question, or at least not the only

    question. An equally important question is whether if there is a 70% chance that a defendants

    claim of innocence is accurate, we would want to conclude that his guilt has been proved

    beyond a reasonable doubt? Indeed, this was exactly the issue in the 1998 Supreme Court case

    ofUnited States v. Scheffer,49

    involving a defendant in a military court martial who sought to

    introduce in his own defense a polygraph test supporting the accuracy of his assertion of

    innocence. The test results had been excluded under Rule 707 of the Military Rules of

    Evidence,50

    and the defendant challenged the constitutionality under the Due Process51

    and

    Compulsory Process52

    Clauses of Rule 707s absolute exclusion of polygraphic evidence. The

    Supreme Court, over Justice Stevens dissent and in the face of at least some concern about a

    blanket rule of exclusion expressed by four other Justices who concurred in the judgment but

    not with what all of Justice Thomas wrote in announcing the conclusion of the Court, held that

    there was no federal constitutional right of a defendant to offer polygraphic exculpatory

    evidence. That there may not be such a constitutional right, however, does not answer the

    non-constitutional legal policy question of whether such evidence ought to be admitted when

    offered by a defendant under these or similar circumstances. Nor does it answer the question

    whether the majoritys simple distinction between reliable and unreliable masks the

    important distinction between how reliable evidence must be in order to allow its use to a

    49523 U.S. 303 (1998).

    50Mil. R. Evid. 707.

    51U.S. Const. amend. V.

    52U.S. Const. amend. VI.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    21/40

    19

    defendant who wishes to raise the possibility of a reasonable doubt as to his guilt, whether by

    buttressing the defendants claim of innocence or, perhaps even more likely, by attacking the

    credibility of a police officer or some other prosecution witness.

    Of course any scientific test will have some level of reliability. Whether that level of

    reliability is high enough for admissibility, however, depends on the purposes for which it is

    being employed. If the outcome of a test is being used as the sole or principal evidence of

    whether a defendant should go to prison, as it more-or-less is in some current uses of DNA

    identification,53

    we should demand extremely high levels of reliability. If the evidence is being

    used as merely one component of a larger story about whether a defendant should go to

    prison, then perhaps the level of reliability can be lowera brick is not a wall, as the famous

    adage in the law of evidence goes.54

    After all, it is not true that just because the standard of

    proof for conviction of a crime is proof beyond a reasonable doubt that every piece of evidence

    admissible to (cumulatively) establish proof beyond a reasonable doubt must be capable of

    individually proving beyond a reasonable doubt that the defendant is guilty.55

    Nor is it true that

    every piece of evidence introduced by the prosecution must be reliable beyond a reasonable

    doubt, for such a conclusion would collapse the standard for determining guilt into the

    53See, for example, United States v. Beasley, 102 F.3d 1440 (8

    thCir. 1996); United States v. Cuff,

    37 F. Supp. 2d 279 (S.D.N.Y. 1999); State v. Bartylla, 755 N.W.2d 8 (Minn. 2008). See generally

    Peter Donnelly & Richard Friedman, DNA Database Searches and the Legal Consumption of

    Scientific Evidence, 97 Mich. L. Rev. 931 (1999).

    54McCormick on Evidence 185, at 640-41 (John W. Strong ed., 5

    thed., 1999). To the same

    effect, it is not to be supposed that every witness can make a home run. Judson F. Falknor,

    Extrinsic Policies Affecting Admissibility, 10 Rutgers L. Rev. 574 (1956).

    55On confusing admissibility with sufficiency generally, see Dale A. Nance, Conditional

    Relevance Reinterpreted, 70 B.U. L. Rev. 447, 449-59 (1990).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    22/40

    20

    standard for determining the admissibility of an individual piece of evidence.56

    Moreover, if we

    are using the evidence to show why a defendant should notgo to prison, then the level of

    reliability can be lower still, arguably much lower.57

    After all, we do not have a system in which

    a defendant goes to prison unless he can prove beyond a reasonable doubt that he is not guilty.

    Many of the same considerations apply to civil cases as well. The American legal system

    employs the standard of proof by a preponderance of the evidence in almost all civil cases

    because the system is committed to the view that failure to award damages, say, to an injured

    or otherwise wronged plaintiff is every bit as serious an error as is wrongly requiring a non-

    56

    See United States v. Glynn, 578 F. Supp. 2d 567, 574-75 (S.D.N.Y. 2008); In re Ephedra

    Products Liability Litigation, 393 F. Supp. 2d 181, 187-88 (S.D.N.Y. 2005).

    57For an extended argument about the advantages of asymmetry between prosecution and

    defense in the standards for admission of scientific evidence, see Christopher Slobogin, Proving

    the Unprovable: The Role of Law, Science, and Speculation in Adjudicating Culpability and

    Dangerousness 131-44 (2007). The strongest response to the argument for asymmetry is that

    the justifiable defendant-skewed epistemic goals of the criminal justice system are already

    incorporated in the presumption of innocence and the proof-beyond-a-reasonable-doubt

    burden of proof, and to overlay special evidentiary burdens on the prosecution (or special

    evidentiary benefits on the defense) would thus be a form of double-counting. See Larry

    Laudan, Truth, Error, and the Criminal Law: An Essay in Legal Epistemology 123-28, 144 (2006).

    But this argument rests on the assumption, perhaps a justified one but perhaps not, that the

    existing standard of proof achieves the socially proper distribution of errors of false acquittal

    and of false conviction. If it does not, then, given the historical provenance (and thus resistance

    to modification) of the beyond-a-reasonable-doubt-standard, adjusting the results of that

    standard (whether upwards or downwards) by the use of other evidentiary, substantive, or

    procedural devices seems hardly inappropriate. Nor is there any reason to believe that the best

    way to achieve the optimal distribution of error is with one burden of proof rule rather than a

    combination of multiple evidentiary and procedural rules. See Raphael M. Goldman & Alvin I.Goldman, Review ofTruth, Error and the Criminal Law: An Essay in Legal Epistemology, by

    Larry Laudan, 15 Legal Theory 55 (2009); Michael S. Pardo, On Misshapen Stones and Criminal

    Laws Epistemology86 Texas L. Rev. 347 (2007) (book review). Regardless of the outcome of

    the debate about asymmetry, however, the very existence of the debate, and the terms on

    which it is conducted, demonstrates the folly of trying to determine questions of the legal

    usability of evidence without taking account of legal goals and legal standards.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    23/40

    21

    culpable defendant to pay damages.58

    And once again, therefore, it is hardly clear that a party

    in a civil lawsuit seeking to bolster his assertions about facts should be precluded from doing so

    by use of a method whose reliability is nowhere near sufficient to send someone to jail.

    Awarding damages is less serious than imprisoning someone, or so our legal system believes,

    and as long as that is so then it is a mistake to assume that a uniform standard of reliability

    should govern all legal uses of a particular type of evidence.

    Although the foregoing is about reliability and not validity, the same analysis applies to

    questions of experimental validity as well. The experiments alleged to establish the reliability

    of fMRI lie-detection have been attacked as lacking in external and construct validity,59

    but, like

    questions of reliability, these issues of validity are also matters of degree,60

    and whether some

    degree is or is not good enough will again depend on the uses for which the experiment is being

    put. Consider first the question of external validity, the question whether laboratory results on

    58On the decision theoretic aspects of burdens of proof in civil cases in general, see James

    Brook, Inevitable Errors: The Preponderance of the Evidence Standard in Civil Litigation,18 TulsaL.J. 627 (1982); Bruce Hay & Kathryn Spier, Burdens of Proof in Civil Litigation: An Economic

    Perspective, 26 J. Legal Stud. 413 (1997); John Kaplan, Decision Theory and the Factfinding

    Process, 20 Stan. L. Rev. 1065 (1968); Dale A. Nance, Civility and the Burden of Proof, 17 Harv.

    J.L. & Pub. Pol. 647 (1994); Frederick Schauer & Richard Zeckhauser, On the Degree of

    Confidence for Adverse Decisions, 25 J. Legal Stud. 27 (1996). An important challenge to the

    conventional view about burdens of proof in civil cases is Ronald J. Allen, The Nature of Juridical

    Proof, 13 Cardozo L. Rev. 373 (1991); Ronald J. Allen, A Reconceptualization of Civil Trials, 66

    B.U. L. Rev. 401 (1986), arguing, correctly, that because the plaintiff must typically prove each

    of multiple elements of an offense by a preponderance of the evidence, then the actual burden

    on the plaintiff is substantially higher than the burden on the defendant.

    59See notes 27-37 and accompanying text, supra.

    60See Kenneth R. Foster & Peter W. Huber, Judging Science: Scientific Knowledge and the

    Federal Courts 17 (1999); Erica Beecher-Monas,A Ray of Light for Judges Blinded by Science:

    Triers of Science and Intellectual Due Process, 33 Ga. Rev. 1047, 1062 (1999); Nance, supra note

    41, at 200.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    24/40

    22

    a certain subject population can be employed to reach conclusions or make predictions about a

    different and non-laboratory subject population. The issue often arises in psychological

    experiments in which conclusions drawn from experiments using university undergraduates a

    common pool of experimental subjects can be applied to the behavior of non-undergraduates

    in non-laboratory settings. What makes the experimental research useful, however, is that

    there are other experiments that have demonstrated a substantial correlation for many kinds of

    studies between the results reached in the laboratory with experimental subjects and the

    results observed in non-laboratory settings.61

    These correlations are not perfect, of course, but

    they are positive to a substantial degree, and whether that substantial degree is good enough

    will depend on the uses to which the research is to be put. When the research is to be used to

    enact policy with negative consequences for some segment of the population, for example, we

    should demand a higher correlation between laboratory results and non-laboratory conclusions

    than we would if, for example, the population were merely being warned to be aware of a

    dangerous phenomenon that thus far had been demonstrated only in laboratory settings on

    subjects motivated differently from subjects in the external (non-laboratory) world.

    Although perhaps less obvious, the same considerations apply to construct validity as

    well. Suppose we wish to determine whether there is a relationship between eating a big

    breakfast and increased proficiency in performing mathematical tasks. And then suppose

    61See Craig J. Anderson, James J. Lindsay, & Brad J. Bushman, Research in the Psychological

    Laboratory: Truth or Triviality, 8 Current Directions in Psychological Sci. 3 (1999); Leonard

    Berkowitz & Edward Donnerstein, External Validity is More than Skin Deep: Some Answers to

    Criticisms of Laboratory Experimentation, 37 Amer. Psych. 245 (1982); Douglas J. Mook, In the

    Defense of External Invalidity, 38 Amer. Psych. 379 (1983).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    25/40

    23

    someone were to have conducted an experiment demonstrating a relationship between eating

    a big breakfast and an increased ability to avoid misspellings for the rest of that day. If this

    experiment were used to support a claim about breakfast and mathematical proficiency, it

    would be open to the charge of construct validity, because what the experiment measured

    spelling ability was not the same as what the experiment was being offered to show

    mathematical proficiency. But if there were to exist a demonstrated correlation between

    avoiding spelling mistakes and avoiding mathematical errors, then an experiment showing an

    effect on the former would provide some evidence that there would be an effect on the latter.

    It would not be conclusive evidence, but the deficiencies in construct validity would not render

    the experiment actually conducted totally spurious in terms of the ability to draw conclusions

    about a different but correlated effect.

    So too, perhaps, with the flaws in construct validity in many existing experiments about

    neuroscience-based lie-detection. Although there are important exceptions,62

    most of the

    experiments purportedly establishing the reliability of fMRI lie-detection are experiments in

    which subjects are told by the experimenter to lie or not to lie. When the experimenter is told

    to lie, it is argued, following that instruction is not lying at all, and thus an fMRI result

    demonstrating a certain kind of brain activity for following an instruction to lie tell us nothing

    about the kinds of brain activity involved in actual lying.63

    But even though this gap between

    the instructed lie and the real lie is a significant problem of construct validity, it would render

    62See especially Greene, supra note 20.

    63See Greely & Illes, supra note 27; Kanwisher, supra note 29.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    26/40

    24

    the experimental results totally useless only if there were no correlation at all between the

    brain activity involved in the real lie and that involved in the instructed lie. As yet we do not

    know whether such a correlation exists, but if there is some correlation, even if small, once

    again it would be incorrect to conclude that the existing studies condemn the use of fMRI-

    based lie-detection as completely without evidentiary value, as opposed to offering, say, only

    slight evidence.

    Although slight evidence ought not to be good enough for scientists,64

    it is a large part

    of the law. Not only do basic principles of evidence law (as well as human thinking) routinely

    allow the cumulation of weak but not spurious pieces of evidence, whether in holistic story-

    creation form,65

    or for the related purpose of prompting an inference to the best explanation,66

    or in Bayesian more linear fashion,67

    and not only might weak evidence be sufficient to allow a

    defendant to resist a prosecutions claim to have established his guilt beyond a reasonable

    doubt, but low standards of proof or persuasion pervade the legal system. A plaintiff in some

    states can resist a defendants motion for a directed verdict by offering only a scintilla o f

    64See David H. Kaye, Statistical Significance and the Burden of Persuasion, 46 Law & Contemp.

    Probs. 13 (1983). And see Raichle, supranote 30, at 5 (equating validity with high statistical

    quality).

    65See Inside the Juror (Reid Hastie ed., 1993); Reid Hastie, The Role of Stories In Civil Judgments,

    32 Univ. Mich. J.L. Ref. 1 (1999);Reid Hastie & Nancy Pennington,A Cognitive Theory of Juror

    Decision-Making: The Story Model, 13 Cardozo L. Ref. 519 (1991).

    66See Amalia Amaya, Inference to the Best Legal Explanation, in Legal Evidence and Proof:

    Statistics, Stories, Logic (H. Kapstein, H. Prakken, & B. Verheij, eds., forthcoming 2009); Ronald

    J. Allen & Michael S. Pardo,Juridical Proof and the Best Explanation, 27 L. & Phil. 223 (2008).

    67See Alvin Goldman, Quasi-Objective Bayesianism and Legal Evidence, 42 Jurimetrics 108

    (2002).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    27/40

    25

    evidence.68

    In many contexts, evidence that is substantial but less than a preponderance can

    generate legal results.69

    And the police may stop and frisk a person upon reasonable

    suspicion70

    and can obtain a search warrant by showing probable cause to believe that the

    search will yield usable evidence.71

    For all of these purposes, and many more, weak (and thus

    potentially flawed) evidence serves pervasive functions in the legal system, and to require that

    only compelling or conclusive or even highly reliable evidence, certified as such on the

    basis of highly valid scientific processes, would be to dramatically revamp the legal system as

    we know it.

    IV. JUDGES, JURIES, AND THE DANGERS OF MISUSEIn resisting much of the foregoing argument, it is sometimes said that juries are simply

    not very adept at distinguishing one piece of evidence from another, or at evaluating technical

    evidence critically, and that as a result superficially persuasive pseudo-scientific evidence will

    have more of an effect on deliberations than it should have.72

    In effect, the claim is that one

    brick will in fact constitute the entire wall for most jurors. Yet even apart from the diminishing

    68See, e.g., AALAR, Ltd. v. Francis, 716 So.2d 1141, 1147 (Ala. 1998).

    69See, e.g., De la Luente v. FDIC, 332 F.3d 1208, 1220 (9

    th

    Cir. 2003).70

    Terry v. Ohio, 392 U.S. 1 (1968).

    71U.S. Const. amend. IV.

    72See, for example, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Adina Roskies, Teneille Brown, & Emily Murphy,

    Brain Images as Legal Evidence, 5 Episteme 359 (2008).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    28/40

    26

    role that juries play in American litigation,73

    the state of the empirical evidence on jury over-

    valuation is decidedly mixed.74

    Indeed, were we (and the neuroscientists) to subject the

    common claims of jury over-valuation to the same scrutiny that we subject scientific evidence,

    we might well find that some of the scientific basis for excluding bad scientific evidence is itself

    an example of less than ideal science. A good example is the research purportedly showing

    specifically that people will take brain scan images as having more evidentiary value than such

    images, in some instances, actually have.75

    One of the studies,76

    however, compared the effect

    of textual neurobabble with that of accurate explanations, another compared brain scans to

    73Some of the data are reported in Frederick Schauer, On the Supposed Jury-Dependence of

    Evidence Law, 155 U. Penn. L. Rev. 165 (2006).

    74See Laudan, supra note 36, at 214-18. Good summaries of the existing primary research,

    much of which suggests that juries are not nearly as inept at evaluating scientific or expert

    evidence as is often supposed, can be found in, for example, Richard D. Friedman, Minimizing

    the Jury Over-Valuation Concern, 2003 Mich. St. L. Rev. 967 (2003); Michael S. Jacobs, Testing

    the Assumptions Underlying the Debate About Scientific Evidence: A Closer Look at Juror

    Incompetence and Scientific Objectivity,25 Conn. L. Rev. 1083, 1086-93 (1993); Daniel A.Krauss & Bruce D. Sales, The Effect of Clinical and Scientific Expert Testimony on Juror Decision

    Making in Capital Sentencing, 7 Psychology, Pub. Pol. & L. 267 (2001);Richard O. Lempert, Civil

    Juries and Complex Cases: Taking Stock After Twelve Years,in Verdict: Assessing the Civil Jury

    System 181, 235 (Robert E. Litan ed., 1993); Dale A. Nance & Scott B. Morris,Juror

    Understanding of DNA Evidence: An Empirical Assessment of Presentation Formats for Trace

    Evidence with a Relatively Large and Quantifiable Random-Match Probability, 42 Jurimetrics

    403 (2002); Neil Vidmar & Shari S. Diamond,Juries and Expert Evidence, 66 Brook. L. Rev. 1121

    (2001). Joseph Sanders, The Paternalistic Justification for Restrictions on the Admissibility of

    Expert Testimony, 33 Seton Hall L. Rev. 881, 937-38 (2003), endorses the jury over-valuation

    worry, but appears to based it more on problems of complexity of evidence rather than on jury

    mis-understanding of science or expertise in non-complex cases.

    75D.P. McCabe & A.D. Castel, Seeing is Believing: The Effect of Brain Images on Judgments of

    Scientific Reasoning, 107 Cognition 343 (2008); Deena Skolnick Weisberg et al., The Seductive

    Allure of Neuroscience Explanations, 20 J. Cognitive Neuroscience 470 (2008).

    76Weisberg et al., supra note 75.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    29/40

    27

    plain text and to black and white bar graphs,77

    and a third compared the effect of a neuroimage

    with testimony that was read aloud.78

    As a result of failure to exclude the potentially

    confounding variables of complexity and of photographic representation and color, however,

    we have no idea whether the allegedly distorting effect of brain scans is in fact an effect of

    brain scans or is instead the effect of any photographic image,79

    or an effect of any image (or

    even drawing) in color, or the effect of complex information presented without opposing

    explanations and without opportunity for cross-examination. And thus we lack evidence

    supporting the belief that judges and juries will overvalue brain scan evidence as such, although

    we do have general evidence indicating that jurors may understand more than we think they

    do.80

    Moreover, in practice if not in theory, the admissibility and use of some types of

    evidence, like the actual practice with respect to hearsay and many other exclusions, may vary

    with whether it is judge or jury who is serving as the trier of fact. Because juries make none of

    the decisions regarding reasonable suspicion to stop, probable cause to search, and other

    decisions as to which the credibility of (especially) a police officer is at issue, and because juries

    in fact make only a small percentage of the decisions in trials themselves, both criminal and

    77McCabe & Castel, supra note 70.

    78Jessica R. Gurley & David K. Marcus, The Effects of Neuroimaging and Brain Injury on Insanity

    Defenses, 326 Behavioral Sci. & L. 85 (2008).

    79See Adina L. Roskies,Are Neuroimages Like Photographs of the Brain, 74 Phil. Sci. 860 (2007);

    Sinnott-Armstrong et al., supra note 72, at 367-68. On the distorting effect of photographs

    generally, see David A. Bright & Jane Goodman-Delahunty, Gruesome Evidence and Emotion:

    Anger, Blame, and Jury Decision Making, 30 L. & Human Behavior 183 (2006). And on the

    distorting effect of colored images, see Aura Hanna & Roger Remington, The Representation of

    Color and Form in Long Term Memory, 24 Memory & Cognition 322 (1996).

    80See authorities cited in note 74, supra.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    30/40

    28

    civil, it may be a mistake to extrapolate what we know about jury decision-making or jury

    comprehension of scientific evidence to the legal system generally. Admittedly, there would be

    difficulties in designing an evidentiary system in which admissibility varied depending on

    whether the trier of fact was judge or jury, and formally if not informally the American legal

    system has rejected such an approach, but whether what we know about juries, even if the

    skepticism about juror comprehension of science is well-grounded, is the appropriate model for

    all of law is once again a determination that cannot be made without regard to the normative

    goals and varied tasks of the legal system.

    That the standards of sufficient reliability should vary with their legal uses remains

    subject to the concern about contamination across the different uses, leading ti inappropriate

    uses as well as appropriate ones.81

    There is a concern, for example, that allowing fMRI lie

    detection by a defendant as a way of supporting his claim of innocence might lead to allowance

    of the same technique by the prosecution as a way of sending a (possibly innocent) defendant

    to prison or by a plaintiff as a way of obtaining damages against a possibly non-culpable

    defendant in a civil case. And a related worry would be that allowing judges to hear fMRI lie

    detection evidence in evaluating the credibility of a police officer at a suppression hearing

    before a judge or magistrate might again lead, eventually, to allowing such evidence to be

    heard by juries in determining ultimate guilt or innocence. These worries may not be

    completely fanciful, but again the claims are empirical and causal ones about the effect of one

    action on another, and it is more than a bit ironic that those who are most insistent about

    81See D. Michael Risinger, Navigating Expert Reliability: Are Criminal Standards of Certainty

    Being Left on the Dock?, 64 Alb. L. Rev. 99 (2000).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    31/40

    29

    finding a sound scientific and empirical basis for the admission of various forms of evidence

    seem often to be comfortable abandoning the science in favor of their own hunches when the

    question is about the potential downstream dangers of allowing certain forms of evidence to be

    used for a particular purpose. Those dangers may well exist, but to date there is no scientific

    evidence to support them. For now, the empirical support for the view that allowing fMRI lie

    detection by a defendant in a criminal case will lead to allowing fMRI lie detection by the

    prosecution against an unwilling defendant appears to be weaker than the admittedly weak

    empirical support for the view that fMRI lie detection can actually distinguish liars from truth

    tellers.

    V. COMPARED TO WHAT?In law as well as in science, one of the most important questions is, compared to

    what? And the compared to what? question can usefully be applied to questions about the

    determination of witness veracity in courts of law. Traditionally, the task of assessing witness

    credibility and veracity has been left to the scientifically-unaided determination of the trier of

    fact often the jury but just what are the mechanisms that the trier of fact uses to make

    these determinations? We know that jurors often use characteristics other than the content of

    what a witness says to evaluate the truth of a witnesss claim, we know that these non-content

    characteristics include factors such as whether a witness looks up or down, fidgets, speaks

    slowly or quickly, and testifies with apparent confidence, and we know from serious research

    that these alleged indicators of veracity are at best highly unreliable, and at worst totally

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    32/40

    30

    random.82

    And this is why numerous studies of the ability of untrained people to determine

    truth-telling in others rarely rises above 60%, where 50% would be random.83

    Moreover, the

    problem of unreliable determination of veracity by judges and juries is exacerbated by the rules

    of evidence themselves, which presume on the basis of scarcely more than venerable

    superstition that those who have been convicted of serious crimes, even crimes not involving

    dishonest statements, are more likely to lie than those who have not,84

    which allow witnesses

    to offer testimony about whether other witnesses have a reputation in the community for lying

    or truth-telling,85

    and which allow witnesses to offer their personal opinions about the general

    credibility of other witnesses.86

    We can thus reframe the question. The question is not whether fMRI based lie

    detection is reliable enough in the abstract to be used in court. Rather, it is whether there are

    good reasons to prohibit the use of evidence of witness veracity that may well be better than

    the evidence of witness veracity that now dominates the litigation process, and at the very least

    is probably no worse. The choice is not between very good evidence of veracity and less good

    bad, if you will fMRI evidence. Rather it is between admittedly bad fMRI evidence and the

    82See authorities cited in note 13, supra.

    83See Charles F. Bond, Jr. & Bella M. DePaulo,Accuracy of Deception Judgments, 10 J.

    Personality & Soc. Psych. Rev. 214 (2006); Maureen OSullivan, Why Most People Parse Palters,

    Fibs, Lies, Whoppers, and Other Deceptions Poorly, in Deception, supra note 8, at 74; Aldert Vrij

    et al., Increasing Cognitive Load to Facilitate Lie Detection: The Benefit of Recalling an Event inReverse Order, 32 L. & Human Behavior 253, 253 (2008).

    84Fed. R. Evid. 609(a)(1).

    85Fed. R. Evid. 608(a).

    86Fed. R. Evid. 608(a).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    33/40

    31

    even worse evidence that is not only permitted, but in fact forms the core of the common law

    trial process.

    VI.ON THE USES AND LIMITATIONS OF SCIENCE: DOUBTING DAUBERT

    The tone of some of the foregoing notwithstanding, it is decidedly notmy purpose in

    this Essay to argue in favor of the admissibility of fMRI-based lie-detection evidence, whether in

    the courtroom itself or for related forensic purposes. Rather, it is to suggest that the reliability

    and validity standards for scientific evidence that the courts should use must be standards that

    come, ultimately, from the legal goals of the legal system and not from the scientific goals of

    the scientific system.87

    Science can tell us that a certain scientific process has, say, a 12% error

    rate, or some rate of false positives and some other rate of false negatives. And scientists must

    decide for scientific purposes whether such a rate is sufficient, for example, to assert that

    something is the case, to conclude that a finding is adequate for publication, or to find a

    research program promising enough for renewal of a research grant. But whether such an

    error rate is sufficient for a trier of fact to hear it, put someone in jail, keep someone out of jail,

    or support an injunction or an award of damages is not itself a scientific question.

    The same applies to the methods of inquiry. Science properly relies on peer-review,

    replication, and other indicia of sound methodology. But whether those indicia are the right

    ones for purposes of non-scientific action, including but not limited to courtroom verdicts, is

    87See Margaret A. Berger, Upsetting the Balance Between Adverse Interests: The Impact of the

    Supreme Courts Trilogy on Expert Testimony in Toxic Tort Litigation, 64 L. & Contemp. Prob.

    289, 300-02 (2001) (distinguishing legal and scientific standards of causation).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    34/40

    32

    not itself a scientific question,88

    and to think otherwise is to believe erroneously that one can

    derive a legal or policy ought from a scientific is.

    Evidence cognoscenti will detect in much of this a challenge to Daubertitself, and that

    may be so. Daubertand its successors, General Electric v. Joinerand Kumho Tire Co. v.

    Carmichael,89

    were directed primarily to the problem of products liability cases and mass tort

    verdicts that have been based on allegedly persuasive but seemingly unreliable junk science.90

    Indeed, no one who reads the description of the tire failure expert in Kumho Tire can fail to

    recognize that junk science really does exist.91

    And there is no doubt that the legal system

    must guard against a world in which experts in astrology, phrenology, and countless other

    bogus -ologies, some of which appear superficially more plausible than astrology and

    phrenology but have little more grounding in fact, have a place in the courtroom. Moreover,

    and as an important and very recent National Academy of Sciences study has documented in

    detail,92

    many of the traditionally-used methods of forensic identification methods bitemarks,

    88See David L. Faigman et al., Science in the Law: Standards, Statistics and Research Issues 1-

    3.5.1, at 43 (2002) (determining value of scientific expert opinion is a matter of policy, not

    science).

    89See note 16, supra.

    90See United States v. Starzepyzel, 880 F. Supp. 1027, 1036 (S.D.N.Y. 1995); Joseph Sanders,

    Benedictin on Trial: A Study of Mass Tort Litigation (1998).

    91On the junk science problem generally, see Peter W. Huber, Galileos Revenge: Junk Science in

    the Courtroom (1991).

    92National Research Council of the National Academies, Strengthening Forensic Science in the

    United States: A Path Forward (2009).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    35/40

    33

    shoe prints, handwriting analysis, ballistics, tool marks, and even fingerprints93

    may have less

    scientific backing than their proponents have claimed and than the legal system has historically

    accepted.94

    Identification of the problem is thus comparatively straightforward: prior to the

    Daubert revolution and its insistence on reliability and scientific validity,95

    American courts

    admitted into evidence experts and tests purporting to demonstrate defective manufacture,

    causation, or identification, but which were based on empirical findings that do not have a

    sound scientific basis as measured by the standards of science. Without Daubert, so the

    argument goes, this kind of scientific evidence will continue to be admitted and juries will be

    persuaded by it notwithstanding its scientific weakness, causing innocent defendants to be

    wrongfully identified and convicted, and non-culpable defendants in tort cases to be held liable.

    These steps to what we might call the Daubertconclusion are based on empirical claims

    as to which there is little empirical evidence. We do not know, for example, how often the

    admission of scientifically substandard evidence has produced an erroneous verdict. It would

    do so whenever the admission of substandard evidence was unaccompanied by better evidence

    93See United States v. Monteiro, 407 F. Supp. 2d 351, 355 (D. Mass. 2006) (excluding ballistics

    testimony); United States v. Green, 405 F.2d 104, 120-22 (D. Mass. 2005) (same). Cf. Robert

    Epstein, Fingerprints MeetDaubert: The Myth of Fingerprint Science is Revealed, 75 S. Cal. L.

    Rev. 605 (2002) (questioning scientific basis for fingerprint matching).

    94See Michael J. Saks, Explaining the Tension Between the Supreme Courts Embrace of Validity

    as the Touchstone of Admissibility of Expert Testimony and Lower Courts (Seeming) Rejection of

    Same, 5 Episteme 329 (2008); Michael J. Saks, Merlin and Solomon: Lessons from the Laws

    Formative Encounters with Forensic Identification Science, 49 Hastings L.J. 1069 (1998).

    95Daubert, 509 U.S. at 591 n.9.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    36/40

    34

    leading to the same conclusion, whenever the admission of the substandard evidence caused

    the trier of fact to find for the prosecution or plaintiff where without that evidence the verdict

    would have been otherwise, andwhenever the defendant was not in fact guilty or culpable. It

    is possible that there are many cases in which all three of these facts are present, but we do not

    know how many there are, or what proportion of all cases, verdicts, accidents, or crimes they

    constitute. So it is far from clear how much of a problem there is, and how effective Daubert

    has been in solving it. Nor is it clear that the problem of junk science is best solved at the point

    of admissibility, because solving it, or at least ameliorating it, by the vigorous use of summary

    judgment and dismissal could likely achieve the same result without mistakenly importing the

    all-things-considered determination of whether the plaintiff or prosecution should prevail into

    the determination of the admissibility of particular pieces of evidence.96

    But even ifDauberthas significantly reduced the number of erroneous verdicts actually

    caused by poor science, the compared to what question still looms. Bad science is worse

    than good science, but not necessarily worse than the non-science that lurks in the heads of

    judges and jurors. And flawed science may still be superior to the superstitions and urban

    legends that influence so much of public policymaking and legal decision-making. Daubert is

    based on the sound premise that manufacturers of products should not be held liable for

    damages unless there is a basis for believing that some negligent act of a manufacturer actually

    caused injury to the user of the product, but it is important to consider what occurs when bad

    science, measured by scientific standards, is excluded from litigation. We do not know with

    96See Richard D. Friedman, Squeezing Daubert Out of the Picture, 33 Seton Hall L. Rev. 1047

    (2003); Nance, supra note 33, at 252.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    37/40

    35

    certainty the answer to this question in all circumstances, but we do know that because

    scientific reliability and validity is not a prerequisite for the admission of all evidence, much

    non-scientific evidence might well fill the gap left by the excluded flawed scientific evidence.

    We do not, after all, have a civil litigation system in which we prohibit those who are injured in

    automobile accidents from recovering unless they can show with scientific reliability that the

    defendant was driving negligently, nor do we have a criminal litigation system in which we

    prohibit defendants from offering a wide variety of non-scientific evidence to keep them out of

    prison. Requiring that all legal determinations of guilt or innocence, liability or non-liability, be

    guided by science thus seems utopian in both the best and worst senses of that word.97

    Best in

    the sense that such a system might in fact achieve more justice than the one we now have. But

    worst in the sense that eliminating bad or flawed science from the courtroom, the legal system,

    and the rules of evidence would require such a dismantling of the entire edifice of common law

    adjudication that not only is it fanciful to think it might ever happen, but also that attempting to

    make the existing system more scientific by keeping out bad science while not doing anything

    about the non-science with which the entire system is infused may produce a system that is in

    fact less scientific and less reliable just because it keeps out somewhat poor science in favor of

    keeping in the really poor science that sneaks in the back door by not billing itself as science at

    all.

    97And perhaps that is why Kumho Tire made clear that although Dauberts broad concept of

    reliability would be applicable to all expert testimony, using the norms of science to evaluate

    reliability would be required only where the proposed evidence or testimony purported to be

    scientific. See Glynn and Ephedra, supra note 56.

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    38/40

    36

    At the heart of the controversy over the legal systems use of poor science may be the

    justified concern of scientists to keep theirscientific enterprise as free as possible from non-

    scientific taint. When science that is not yet ready for prime scientific time is commandeered

    for commercial gain, the enterprise of science suffers, which is exactly what has happened with

    the commercialization of fMRI-based lie detection. Encouraging the use of shoddy science for

    legal or policy purposes is worse for science, and in the long run may and this too is an

    empirical question hurt us all by making science and the use of it by the public and policy-

    makers worse. But the tension between the valuable goals of long-term scientific integrity and

    short-term uses of scientific output is hardly a new one and hardly unique to lie detection or to

    the law of evidence. When medical researchers performing placebo-controlled experiments

    reach a point at which they suspect but do not yet know with scientific confidence that a new

    drug will cure a fatal disease,98

    they face the moral dilemma a dilemma faced by Dr. Martin

    Arrowsmith in Sinclair Lewiss great novel99

    and by countless real research physicians before

    and since -- about whether to sacrifice science to immediate suffering, or instead to sacrifice

    peoples health and life to long-term scientific integrity. The stakes with respect to fMRI-based

    lie detection may be smaller, but the question is the same. If incomplete or shoddy or

    commercially-motivated science is usable in law, science will suffer. But if incomplete or

    shoddy or commercially-motivated science is barred from the law in the name of science, laws

    98See Robert J. Levine, The Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research (2

    nded., 1986); Sharona

    Hoffman, The Use of Placebos in Clinical Trials: Responsible Research or Unethical Practice,?33

    Conn. L. Rev. 449 (2001).

    99Sinclair Lewis, Arrowsmith (1932).

  • 8/22/2019 Can Bad Science Be Good Evidence

    39/40

    37

    own goals may suffer,100

    and the tension and necessary tradeoffs between the goals of law and

    the goals of science can never be completely eliminated.101

    The claim that evaluating science within the legal system must be based on

    characteristically legal standards and norms is in fact an example of a larger issue about the

    (partial) distinctiveness of legal thinking, legal analysis, and legal decision-making.102

    Judges

    routinely based their decisions on precedent and stare decisis, but every elementary textbook

    on informal logic treats an argument from past practice as a fallacy. Lawyers are expected to

    rely on authority, but thoughtful scientists recognize that reliance on scientific authority is in

    great tension with scientific method. When Blackstone observed that it is better that ten

    guilty persons escape, than that one innocent suffer,103

    he not only drew on ideas now

    100Especially important in this context is the obligation of law simply to reach a decision, and

    the ability to postpone a judgment until better evidence is available is rarely available to law.

    See Neil B. Cohen, The Gatekeeping Role in Civil Litigation and the Abdication of Legal Values in

    Favor of Scientific Values, 33 Seton Hall L. Rev. 943 (2003).

    101In suggesting that the decision about the use or non-use of neuroscience-based lie-detection

    for trial or forensic purposes must be made according to legal standards, I do not mean to

    suggest that the decision should be made solely by lawyers and judges. Committees or other

    decision-making processes on which both legal and scientific professionals are represented

    would be preferable to leaving the decision solely to legal professionals or solely to scientists,

    and my principal concern in this paper is only to argue against the view that only scientists