beyond the brain - how body and environment shape animal and human minds - reviewed by mirko farina

8
LOUISE BARRETT Beyond the Brain: How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds. Louise Barrett, Beyond the Brain: How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds, Princeton U niversity Press, 2011. 270 pages, ISBN: 978-0- 691-12644-9, $28.61. Reviewed by Mirko Farina, ARC Cen tre of Exc ell ence in Cog nit ion and its Di sor der s (CCD) , Ins tit ute of Human Cog ni tio n and Br ain Sci ence (IHCBS), Macquarie University – Sydney, Australia. Beyond the Brain: How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds is an eye-opening and thought-provoking book that sets out a much-needed contribution to the study of the relationship between animals, cognition and the environment. The volume provides remarkable new insights into how to understand animal (including human) behavior, raises interesting ques tion s about the role of environmental affordances in the emergence of complex cognitive processes and provides the reader with a refreshing break from the wearisome excess of brain-cen tric literat ure that still pervades much of the debate sur rounding evolutionary psychology. In embracing the theor etical framework endorsed by proponents of embodied cognition, Barrett adopts an ecological approach to psychology that aims at challenging any attempt to descri be comp lex thinki ng and fl exible behavi or as mere by-pro ducts of  int ern al cog ni tiv e act ivity . Eco logic al app roaches in psy cho logy typ ica lly provide a powerful and coherent alternative to standard informatio n-processing paradigms [see Marr (1982); Poggio (1981) just to name a few], that postulate the exi stence of di sti nct and hi era rch ica l the ore tic al lev els to und erstand comp lex informat ion-p rocessin g tasks such as visual perce ptio n. [Rowlands (2006), p.8]. Ecological approaches resist these computational understandings of visual perception and rather explain perceiving as “ an achievement of the individual , not an appear ance in the theater of hi s consciousness; as a kee pin g-i n-t ouc h- with the world and exp eri encing of things rather than a having of experi ences; as an awa ren ess -of inste ad of jus t awarenes s”. Perceiving, they continue, may be awareness of something in the environment or some thin g in the observer or both at once, but there is no cont ent of  awareness independent of that of which one is aware ”. [Gibson (1979), p.239]. On these accounts, visual perception is not therefore the mere reception of st imul i fr om th e envi ronment fo ll owed by th e constr uc ti on of in tern al representations, but rather an active sampling of the optic array, driven by environmental affordances 1 , that allows an animal to discover the information present in the world. (p.106). In endorsing this “Gibsonian” perspective, Barr ett successfully merges and deeply interweaves different disciplines (ranging from ethology and ecological psychology to artificial intelligence, robotics and philosophy) to create an interdisciplinar y space for the study of the evolution of cognition that 1 Affordances are the terms in which perceptual information is made available.

Upload: mirko-farina

Post on 07-Apr-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

8/3/2019 Beyond the Brain - How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds - Reviewed by Mirko Farina

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/beyond-the-brain-how-body-and-environment-shape-animal-and-human-minds- 1/8

LOUISE BARRETT

Beyond the Brain: How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human

Minds.

Louise Barrett, Beyond the Brain: How Body and Environment Shape Animaland Human Minds, Princeton University Press, 2011. 270 pages, ISBN: 978-0-

691-12644-9, $28.61.

Reviewed by Mirko Farina, ARC Centre of Excellence in Cognition and its

Disorders (CCD), Institute of Human Cognition and Brain Science (IHCBS),

Macquarie University – Sydney, Australia.

Beyond the Brain: How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds

is an eye-opening and thought-provoking book that sets out a much-neededcontribution to the study of the relationship between animals, cognition andthe environment. The volume provides remarkable new insights into how tounderstand animal (including human) behavior, raises interesting questionsabout the role of environmental affordances in the emergence of complexcognitive processes and provides the reader with a refreshing break from thewearisome excess of brain-centric literature that still pervades much of thedebate surrounding evolutionary psychology. In embracing the theoreticalframework endorsed by proponents of embodied cognition, Barrett adopts anecological approach to psychology that aims at challenging any attempt todescribe complex thinking and flexible behavior as mere by-products of 

internal cognitive activity. Ecological approaches in psychology typicallyprovide a powerful and coherent alternative to standard information-processingparadigms [see Marr (1982); Poggio (1981) just to name a few], that postulatethe existence of distinct and hierarchical theoretical levels to understandcomplex information-processing tasks such as visual perception. [Rowlands(2006), p.8]. Ecological approaches resist these computational understandingsof visual perception and rather explain perceiving as “an achievement of theindividual, not an appearance in the theater of his consciousness; as akeeping-in-touch- with the world and experiencing of things rather than ahaving of experiences; as an awareness-of instead of just awareness”.Perceiving, they continue, may be awareness of something in the environment or something in the observer or both at once, but there is no content of awareness independent of that of which one is aware”. [Gibson (1979), p.239].On these accounts, visual perception is not therefore the mere reception of stimuli from the environment followed by the construction of internalrepresentations, but rather an active sampling of the optic array, driven byenvironmental affordances1, that allows an animal to discover the informationpresent in the world. (p.106).

In endorsing this “Gibsonian”  perspective, Barrett successfully merges anddeeply interweaves different disciplines (ranging from ethology and ecological

psychology to artificial intelligence, robotics and philosophy) to create aninterdisciplinary space for the study of the evolution of cognition that

1 Affordances are the terms in which perceptual information is made available.

8/3/2019 Beyond the Brain - How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds - Reviewed by Mirko Farina

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/beyond-the-brain-how-body-and-environment-shape-animal-and-human-minds- 2/8

ultimately calls into question any orthodox, brain-bounded, purelyintracranialist understanding of the nature of the human mind. Barrett’scriticism is essentially directed at those views that deny any possibility of body-brain integration. Such views, she notices, find both their communal ancestorand their theoretical justification in the conceptual palette provided by

Cartesianism2. Cartesianism is the idea, affecting much of modern psychology,that the mind is separated from the corporal body and entirely in control of it.In this book, Barrett powerfully questions Cartesianism by presenting acompelling bulk of empirical evidence that shows how heavily animals andhumans rely on their bodies and milieus to behave intelligently. The mainscope of the volume is therefore to demonstrate that: 1) the brain isn’t the solelocus of intelligence and 2) that there isn’t, properly speaking, such a thing asa “naked brain”- an isolated mental substance that dominates the physicalfrom above. A related goal of the book is also to prove that our knowledgecannot be entirely derived, through reason and thinking, from a set of constrained innate ideas but that it rather emerges in the interplay betweenbrain, body and the wider world. To the extent that the book unveils theseerroneous conceptions of the mental, it also encourages us to drop ouranthropomorphic stance by revealing that intelligent behavior is alwaysprofoundly influenced and directly governed by physical and socio-culturalcircumstances in a way that has lead both Paul Maclean (1949) and WilliamBlessing (1997) to talk of a “visceral brain”. For this reason, Barrett’s book canbe taken as a refreshing antidote for anyone who is troubled by old-fashionedtendencies that attempt to describe the human brain as a Swiss army knife,[Cosmides & Tooby (1992)]; a collection of highly modular, domain-specificcomputational tools. [Fodor (1975, 2008); Pinker (2003), Byrne & Bates

(2006) ]. In line with a long-established tradition of writings in phenomenology[see Heidegger (1927 trans. 1962) and Merleau Ponty for (1945 trans. 1962)for instance] and in agreement with more recent works in the cognitivesciences [such as Clark (1997, 2008), Menary (2007), Rowlands(2010), Sutton(2010),Wheeler (forthcoming)] that describe the brain as an integral andinseparable part of the complex loop that accompanies the formation of mentalstates; Beyond the Brain therefore contributes to further illustrate theimportance of the Umvelt – the wider world as it is experienced by a particularorganism [von Uexküll (1957)]- for the emergence of complex cognitivestrategies and successful adaptations.

 The volume is organized in eleven chapters centering, as we have seen above,around one main theme: the Gibsonian idea that environmental affordancesare crucial for the emergence of our cognitive functions. In the course of thisreview I have already presented standard ecological approaches and quicklyexplained how they follow Gibson in taking the environment to be the richestsource of information we can directly access through perception-action cycles.In what remains of this review I will now try to provide the reader with a full

2 John Sutton has written a fair bit about how Descartes did allow for this kind of body-brainintegration. In Sutton’s view; modern forms of Cartesianism must be intended as deviations

from the Magister’s Dictum because they have failed to keep abreast of the spirit of hisphilosophy. So, Cartesianism would interestingly be not true to the spirit of Descartes! Formore specific details see Sutton (1998) and Gaukroger, S., Schuster, J., & Sutton, J. (2000). Thanks to Julian Kiverstein for the hint.

8/3/2019 Beyond the Brain - How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds - Reviewed by Mirko Farina

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/beyond-the-brain-how-body-and-environment-shape-animal-and-human-minds- 3/8

sense of Barrett’s project by condensing, in a page or two, the most importantcontents of the volume.

In chapters 1 and 2 Barrett mounts a sustained attack on chauvinistic forms of anthropomorphism. Anthropomorphism is basically the attribution of human

characteristic to gods, animals, weather(in this case is called “pathetic fallacy”)or inanimate objects3.Through a series of compelling empirical examples(involving facial recognition in babies [Kanwisher et al. (1997); Gauthier et al.(2000)] and social intelligence in apes [Brothers et al. (1992); Perrett (1999);Barton (2006)], Barrett invites us to renounce our anthropomorphic perspectiveby demonstrating how, in investigating cognition, a strictly human-centeredperspective is not only undesirable but also wrong both theoretically andempirically. This kind of chauvinistic anthropomorphism should be abandoned,Barrett argues, because it “invites us to ask scientific questions that simply reflect our own concerns” (p.3) and therefore encourages us to think that“other creatures are interesting only to the extent that they resemble us” (p.5).In essence, in the first chapters of her book, Barrett attempts to resist the ideathat the whole of evolution was crafted to produce us as the most supremecreature and rather tries to establish the claim that anthropocentrism is ahazardous bias that considerably endangers scientific enquiry.

Chapters 3 ,4 5 are principally devoted to explore and appreciate how much asmall brain can achieve. The goal of these chapters is therefore to preventanother bias, what Barrett labels as the “big head bias” – the idea that a bigbrain can allow us for an assumption of superiority over creatures that possessvastly smaller and less developed brains than ours. Barrett calls into question

this idea and effectively demonstrates that there is no connection between thecomplexity of an observed behavior, and the complexity of the mechanism thatproduced it. As evidence for this claim, she adduces two interesting examples:1) the “fertile turtles” and 2) the behavior of Portia spiders, which shediscusses in ch.3 and 4 respectively. In the early ‘50s, in order to test the ideathat complexity of brain functions doesn’t necessarily arise from the number of neurons but rather emerges from the richness of their interconnections[Holland (2003)], neurophysiologist and robotics pioneer Grey Walter built twomotorized robots (Elsie and Elmer) that looked like tortoises. These tortoiseshad only two “brain cells”, which could produce one reflex response each; onefor the light, the other for touch. The sensor for detecting the light was a

photoelectric cell mounted on the front of the steering column of the robot, thetouch sensor was instead an electrical contact that was turned off wheneverthe shell of the tortoise encountered an obstacle. (p.43). These tortoises couldonly work in two modalities: 1) seeking light; 2) moving towards it. Despitetheir relatively simple architectures, these robots, once freed in theenvironment, were able to explore the surroundings by slowly moving in aseries of arches, detecting and hurrying towards sources of light and avoidingor pushing obstacles around. They were also reported, when placed in front of a mirror, to flicker, twitter and jig like clumsy Narcissuses [Grey Walter (1951,1953)], in a sort of mating dance that led many to attribute them what wouldhave normally been accepted, if observed in living animals, as evidence of self-

3 For a series of interesting studies see: Guthrie (1997); Datson & Mitman (2005); Horowitz(2007)]. For more popular treatments see also: [Patten (2006) and Myers (2008)].

8/3/2019 Beyond the Brain - How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds - Reviewed by Mirko Farina

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/beyond-the-brain-how-body-and-environment-shape-animal-and-human-minds- 4/8

awareness. Without any kind of internal, programmed knowledge or computer-like structure, these tortoises were able to exhibit remarkably complexbehaviors and these “emerged” as a direct result of their interaction with theenvironment. Barrett uses the tortoises’ example to show that sometimes thestructure of the environment and the physical shape of the animal’s body can

play a highly active role in forging and moulding adaptive strategies4.Analogous results are also observed in the animal kingdom. In chapter 4,Barrett takes us into a fascinating journey in the world of spiders and invites usto focus on the behavior of the Portia. Portia spiders are spiders that havebrains with the size of a pin, yet this doesn’t impede them to exhibit one of themost complex and flexible hunting behavior displayed in the animal kingdom.Portia spiders in fact, while chasing their prey, successfully engage in a seriesof intricate stalking strategies (including aggressive mimicry, detouring tobreak visual contact and smoked-screen behavior), that have led manyscientists to accept the idea that they behave intelligently, being capable of learning on the fly and of deploying complex hunting tactics. [Wilcox & Jackson(2002); Ross (2007)]. Again, Barrett uses the case of Portia spiders to furtherdemonstrate that articulated behavior isn’t necessarily tied to big brains butmay indeed be triggered by relatively simple internal mechanisms respondingto complex environments.

Chapters 6,7,8 and 9 are probably the most crucial in the book, as they areused to introduce, critically assess and ultimately endorse the case for theecological approach in psychology that Barrett wants to establish. Thoughcrucial, this isn’t however the only key-theme that span across these fourchapters. Additional topics worth a mention are those that relate to otherimportant aspects of embodied approaches to cognition [such as the critique of classical computationalism conducted through the analysis of the so-called“Watt governor metaphor” (Van Gelder 1995) and through the idea of soft-assembly. (Thelen & Smith (1994)]. The Watt governor metaphor is a metaphorused by Barrett to attack the “brain as a computer analogy”- the idea that ourbrains work in the same way as digital computers work by means of symbolicmanipulations carried out by dedicated mechanisms or pre-specified modules.  The Watt-governor was introduced by the Australian philosopher Tim vanGelder (1995) as an alternative metaphor better able to capture the dynamicinteractions between animal’s and the surrounding world. Cognition, in hisview, is described as a dynamical process arising when, “inputs, internal

 processes and outputs are tightly coupled like the spindle, angle arm, and throttle valve” in the centrifugal governor (p.129-130). Barrett takes dynamicalapproaches to be in competition with computational accounts of brain functionbut this opposition may well be more apparent than real. Clark (2008) andWheeler (2005) in fact both talk of dynamical computationalism. Dynamical

4 This seems to provide nice empirical evidence for what Mark Rowland (1999) has called the“barking dog principle”:“If it is necessary for an organism to be able to perform a givenadaptive task T, then it is differentially selectively disadvantageous for that organism todevelop internal mechanisms sufficient for the performance of T when it is possible for theorganism to perform T by way of a combination of internal mechanisms and manipulation of the external environment ” [Rowlands (1999), p.80]. This principle is very similar to the 007

principle formulated by Clark in 1989. It is important to note that the 007 principle has beenconsistently used, in the literature directed at the extended mind thesis, to endorse the case of cognitive extension. For an interesting analysis of the relationships between the two see[Shapiro (2010)].

8/3/2019 Beyond the Brain - How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds - Reviewed by Mirko Farina

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/beyond-the-brain-how-body-and-environment-shape-animal-and-human-minds- 5/8

computationalism, they argue, is a view that merges dynamical systems theorywith old-fashioned computationalism and asserts that in order to provide withthe right kinds of temporal coordination needed to trigger the temporally richadaptive behaviors typical of forms of higher cognition, the brain needs to spanthe body-world boundaries creating crossing architectures that encompass

these two realms.

 The other important point that Barrett tries to make in these central chaptersof her book is related with the idea that embodied systems are preferable toclassical computational systems because they can express more variability. Inorder to illustrate this point Barrett introduces the idea of soft-assembly. Softly-assembled systems are provisionally assembled units working in the service of successful phenotypic transmission. They are made up via temporary bio-ecological operations of assemblage that occur between neural and non-neuralresources and are characterized by operations that deal with specific problemsarising in the course of one’s experience. Softly-assembled systems are richly

variable systems that act as pacemakers and rhythm-setters [Wheeler (2005)]to couple an animal with its own world. These systems are systems in whichthere is no central controller and no planning and according to Thelen andSmith(1994), they should be taken as the defining feature of a dynamicalaccount of development. Barrett deploys the idea of soft-assembly in thecontext of human babies (ch.10), to show that 1) “our knowledge is tailored tothe specific environment we encounter ” (p.176), and 2) to demonstrate thatthe environment is an “equal partner” in producing cognitive behavior. [Clark(1997)]. The book ends (ch.11) with a final chapter in which Barrett discussesthe idea of the body schema and the incorporation of tools. In recalling a seriesof studies involving the plasticity of the body schema (Iriki et al. (1996),Maravita & Iriki (2004)], Barrett focuses on the negotiability of our own bodiesand tries to demonstrate that organism are “always mutually entangled withtheir environments and do not stand apart from them as some kind of hermetically sealed, disembodied cognisers”. (p.200). Although I am verysympathetic with this line of argument [see Kiverstein and Farina (inpreparation)], in this book Barrett fails to address and rule out alternative andcompeting approaches (such as the embedded view), that invites us todistinguish the “fairly acceptable” claim that incorporation yields new agent-world circuits, entangled and re-engineered bio-mechanical architectures; fromthe more radical assumption that buys the inference to extended cognition and

therefore envisages literal cognitive extension.

In particular, Rupert (2009,ch.8) grants the existence of the former but gives an embedded account of cases of incorporation on the grounds of his notion of brain-centred realisers of the body schema. Barrett surprisingly doesn’t discuss this objection.

  To conclude. The impressive sheer of wealth and breadth of informationpresented in this book combined with a charming and engaging prose, makesthis volume very enjoyable reading. Beyond the Brain is indeed an amusingand entertaining read, but one with an extraordinary analytical rigor andeloquence of argument. Very accessible, enticing and lucidly written it can beenjoyed both by professional academics and laypeople. Readers—be they

novice or seasoned—will certainly find the volume uplifting and inspirational,Barrett’s style brisk and delightful and her intellectual playfulness quitesolacing. An intriguing, illuminating, very ambitious and stylish book that will

8/3/2019 Beyond the Brain - How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds - Reviewed by Mirko Farina

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/beyond-the-brain-how-body-and-environment-shape-animal-and-human-minds- 6/8

8/3/2019 Beyond the Brain - How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds - Reviewed by Mirko Farina

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/beyond-the-brain-how-body-and-environment-shape-animal-and-human-minds- 7/8

Gauthier, I., Skudlaski, P., Gore, J.C., & Anderson, A.W. (2000). “Expertise for cars andbirds recruits brain areas involved in face recognition”. Nature Neuroscience, 3,pp.191-197.

Gibson, J.J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: HoughtonMifflin.

Grey Walter, W. (1951). “A machine that learns”. Scientific American, 185, pp.60-63.

Grey Walter, W. (1953). The Living Brain. W.W. Norton, New York.

Guthrie, S. E. (1997). “Anthropomorphism: A definition and a theory”. In Mitchell, R.W., Thompson, N.S., & Miles, H.L.(Eds.). Anthropomorphism, anecdotes, and animals. (pp.50-58). Albany, NY: State University New York Press.

Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and Time. London: SCM.

Holland, O. (2003). “The first biologically inspired robot”. Robotica, 21, pp. 351-363.

Horowitz, A. (2007). “Anthropomorphism”. In Bekoff, M. (Eds.). Encyclopedia of Human-Animal Relationships, (pp 60-66). Greenwood Publishing Group, Westport, CT.

Iriki, A., Tanaka, M., & Iwamura, Y. (1996). “Coding of Modified Body Schema during Tool use by Macaque Postcentral Neurones”. NeuroReport, 7, pp. 2325-2330.

Kanwisher, N. McDermott, J., & Chun, M. (1997). “The fusiform face area: a module inhuman extrastriate cortex specialised for the perception of faces”. Journal of Neuroscience, 17, pp. 4302-4311.

Kiverstein, J., & Farina, M. (in preparation). Integration and The Extended Mind Thesis

(Provisional Title).MacLean, P.D. (1949) “Psychosomatic disease and the ‘visceral brain’: recentdevelopments bearing on the Papez theory of emotion”. Psychosom Med., 11, pp. 338–353.

Maravita, A., & Iriki, A. (2004). “Tools for the Body (Schema)”. Trends in CognitiveSciences, 8, pp. 79-86.

Marr, D. C. (1982). Vision: A Computational Investigation into the HumanRepresentation and Processing of Visual Information. New York: Freeman.

Menary, R.(2007), Cognitive Integration: Mind and Cognition Unbounded , New York:Palgrave Macmillian.

Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of Perception. New York: Humanities Press,1962.

Myers, B. (10 June 2008). “Why we are all animal lovers”. The Guardian. Retrieved 6May 2010.

Patten, F. (2006). Furry! The World's Best Anthropomorphic Fiction. ibooks. pp. 427–436.

Perrett, D.I. (1999) “A cellular basis for reading minds from faces and actions”. InHauser, M., & Konishi, M. (Eds.), Behavioral and Neural Mechanisms of Communication. (pp.159-185). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

8/3/2019 Beyond the Brain - How Body and Environment Shape Animal and Human Minds - Reviewed by Mirko Farina

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/beyond-the-brain-how-body-and-environment-shape-animal-and-human-minds- 8/8

Pinker, S. (2003). How the Mind Works. Penguin, London.

Poggio, T. (1981). “Marr’s Computational Approach to Vision”. Trends inNeurosciences, 10, pp. 258-262.

Ross, P. (2007). Extraordinary Animals: An Encyclopedia of Curious and Unusual

 Animals. Greenwood Publishing Group, Westport, CT.

Rowlands, M. (2010), The new science of the mind: from extended mind to embodied  phenomenology , Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

Rowlands, M. (2006). “Against Methodological Solipsism: The Ecological Approach”.Philosophical Psychology, 8 (1), pp.5-20.

Rowlands, M. (1999), The body in mind: understanding cognitive processes,Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Rupert, R. (2009). Cognitive Systems and the Extended Mind . Oxford, UK: Oxford

University Press.

Shapiro, L. (2010). “James Bond and The Barking Dog: Evolution and ExtendedCognition”. Philosophy of Science, 77, pp. 400-418.

Sutton, J. (2010), “'Exograms and Interdisciplinarity: history, the extended mind, andthe civilizing process” , in Richard Menary (eds). The Extended Mind. (pp. 189-225). MITPress.

Sutton, J. (1998). Philosophy and Memory Traces: Descartes to Connectionism.Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

 Thelen, E., Smith, L.(1994). “A Dynamic Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action”. Cambridge, MA. MIT Press.

Van Gelder, T. (1995). “What might cognition be, if not computation?” Journal of Philosophy, 92, pp.435-381.

Von Uexküll, J. (1957). “A stroll through the worlds of animals and men”. In Shiller,C.H., & Lashley, K.S. (Eds.). Instinctive Behavior: The Development of a ModernConcept. (pp.5-82). International Universities Press, Madison, Conn. (Original workpublished in 1934).

Wheeler, M.(forthcoming). Extended X : Recarving the Biological and Cognitive Joints of Nature. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the Cognitive World: the Next Step. Cambridge,Mass: MIT Press.Wilcox, S., & Jackson, R. (2002). "Jumping Spider Tricksters". In Bekoff, M., Allen, C.,and Burghardt, G.M.. (Eds.). The Cognitive Animal: Empirical and TheoreticalPerspectives on Animal Cognition. (pp. 27-34). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.