when truth is at stake - the case of contemporary legends

Upload: carlos-renato-lopes

Post on 04-Jun-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    1/16

    When Truth Is at Stake: The Case of Contemporary Legends

    Carlos Renato Lopes

    Federal University of So Paulo (UNIFESP), Brazil

    Introduction

    Unsuspicious moviegoers and pay phone users are being stung by HIV-tainted needles

    strategically planted as a means of revenge or out of sheer cruelty. Club scene habitus

    are getting doped at parties and waking up the next morning immersed in a bathtub

    surrounded by ice just to find that their kidneys have been snatched by the international

    traffic of body parts. Innocent fast food diners are being exposed to the risk of

    contamination from all sorts of unthinkable ingredients deliberately added to their

    happy meals. School kids are terrified of going to the school bathroom alone in case

    they bump into the ghost of the bloody bathroom blonde (in Brazil, the loira do

    banheiro): an ex-student whose unrequited love for a teacher led her to suicide on the

    school premises. All-too-frequent cell phone users are suddenly fearing for their brains,

    which might be exposed to the risk of long-term damage, or even cancer. Are any of

    these stories commonly passed on mouth-mouth or via the internet true? Are we

    justified in dreading them?

    A bunch of myths, some might say. Another series of contemporary legends, or more

    popularly named, urban legends1: these unverified reports of unknown origin, told in

    multiple versions as having actually occurred in a social context whose fears and

    aspirations they express symbolically (Renard 2006). A not so modern form of

    mythology which does little but recycle, in the form of narrative, the same old fears and

    apprehensions involving contamination, violence, death But is that all there is to it?

    Are contemporary legends simply a matter of believe it if you will?

    1The terms urban and contemporary are both commonly used in folklore bibliography. But they bothpresent problems. The former has become popular partly due to the American scholar Jan HaroldBrunvands collections and encyclopedias published since the early 1980s. Some authors, however, rejectthe term claiming that the stories are not restricted to an urban context. In turn, contemporary, the termpreferred by authors such as Bill Ellis and Gillian Bennett and ratified by the International Society forContemporary Legend Research which was created in the early 1990s (Fine 1992:1) , could lead tothe false impression that the stories are always recent, when actually many of them are rooted in long-

    lasting traditions. Still, in favor of this latter term there is the idea that any narrative is perceived ascontemporary in the time it circulates (Ellis 2001: xiii). I use both alternatives along this article but Iprivilege the latter, despite its limitations.

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    2/16

    In this article I wish to argue that such accounts are texts just as worth bringing into the

    language class as the semi-fictional, semi-factual narratives that have become staple

    didactic genres. My experience as a Brazilian teacher of English as a foreign language

    to Brazilian students particularly those with a greater familiarity with Internet pop

    culture shows that these narratives elicit a great deal of controversy and debate.

    However, these tend to take place in a rather uncritical manner, since the discussion

    often gets polarized into a dispute of whether the facts do or do not actually occur.

    Not being able to move beyond this polarization, both students and teachers would end

    up disqualifying the accounts, disregarding them as manipulative lies with nothing

    about them worth learning, at best something to be entertained by.

    It is my belief that a Critical Literacy perspective has a lot to contribute to these

    discussions in the sense that it provides teachers and students with a practice through

    which they are able to question their own naturalized conceptions of culture and truth. It

    can help readers to think through the power relations, discourses, and identities being

    constructed and reinforced through these texts (Shor 1999). And it may eventually lead

    to reading those texts as embedded in broader meaning-making practices in which the

    fear of Others in our social relations can take on many forms of which contemporary

    legends could be one whereby received interpretations and stereotypes of alterity are

    enacted. We might then be able to recognize that since texts are constructed

    representations of reality and of identities, we as critical readers have a greater

    opportunity to take a more powerful position with respect to these texts to reject them

    or construct them in ways that are more consistent with [our] own experiences in the

    world (Cervetti et al. 2001: 8).

    In order to shed a light on and begin to question the assumptions that underlie thecommonplace discussions on contemporary legends such as I have been able to observe

    in my own teaching practice in Brazil, I draw here upon some philosophical and critical

    theory engaging the problem of truth that should allow us to understand why such a

    debate is so pervasive. It is my hypothesis that by critically looking into this moving

    force of the debate we may be able to better understand how and why such stories in

    contemporary culture keep being reinvented, then spread and re-transmitted, over and

    over, whether or not they are perceived as having actually taken place somewhere

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    3/16

    specific, at some point in time. My focus will be, then, on this powerful if elusive

    thing called truth.

    When one looks at contemporary legends, one cannot actually avoid the issue of truth

    that hovers over them. It may appear explicitly in the very proposition of the narrative,

    in which the narrator claims she will tell something that really happened not to

    herself, but typically, to someone known to someone else she knows. It may also be

    read into the reactions of listeners or readers of such narratives in the form of

    incredulity, doubt or perhaps just straightforward belief. And, to be sure, it may be

    detected in the struggle of commentators who aim at establishing the scientifically,

    technically attested falsity or at least, implausibility of such reports, no matter how

    plausible these might seem.

    I would join Foucault (1971/1996; 1976/1999) in the claim that every discursive

    practice has the capacity to generate effects of truth which are more or less potent and

    enduring. Such a possibility of the creation of truth effects in and through discourse

    occurs due to an inescapable element that affects the subjects of discourse: the will to

    truth. It would seem that the question of whether contemporary legends are true or false

    cannot be answered adequately or at least not beyond a mere factual investigation in

    terms of this one actually took place versus this one actually did not unless we

    consider the fact that legends are transmitted within socially and historically situated

    discourse practices in which certainprograms of truthare at stake.

    Speaking of programs of truth implies letting go of a traditional conception of truth

    according to which a conscious, knowing subject, free from power relations, can accede

    to a truth that is rational and universally validated. In the history of philosophy, one cantrace that belief in its most rationalized form back to Enlightenment with Descartes at

    the forefront. It is only in the late 18 th century that this view began to be seriously

    questioned; and later with Nietzsche, and throughout the 20th century, it was

    systematically challenged. A short genealogy of this reviewed approach to truth in

    philosophy is what I set out to do in the following sections. For that purpose, and to

    back my claim on the relevance of reading contemporary legends, I turn to two major

    currents of critical thinking themselves discontinuous regimes of (philosophical) truth which share the aim of deconstructing the belief that truth is one, unique and

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    4/16

    transparent. Firstly, I examine Nietzsches and Foucaults views of truth as will to

    power (and hence will to truth), and the pragmatist conception of truth as a language

    tool, proposed more recently by Rorty. Secondly, I relate these two currents to the

    concept of programs of truth employed by Veyne in connection to his analysis of the

    different approaches towards myth.

    Nietzsche and Foucault: Truth as Will

    One of the hallmarks of Nietzsches philosophy is the idea that there is no truth as

    transparent knowledge of the world as it is. He was opposed to the idea of a possible

    apprehension of reality by means of language, since there is no single pre-existing (i.e

    prior to language) universe of things to know. In fact, the German philosopher

    proposed that we abandon once and for all any attempt of knowing the truth. For him,

    we should give up on the idea that language is capable of covering and representing the

    whole of reality a reality that is supposedly determinable and determinate and

    whose truth we could unveil or reveal.

    How does knowledge work, then? Nietzsche says knowledge is mans invention, that is,

    it is not something which is absolutely inscribed and inherent in human nature just

    waiting to be revealed. At its root, knowledge is the fruit of a will to power which

    mines its object and seeks to annihilate it in all its menacing potential. It is as if one

    needed first to reject the object only then to bring it back to ones domain, already

    tamed, already molded. This implies that each and every form of knowledge, including

    science and technology, becomes necessarily perspective, partial and oblique.

    Thus, if knowledge, which is the outcome of a historical will, leads to what we call

    truth, truth is, according to this reasoning, nothing more than the result of contingenthuman relations to which we seek to ascribe universal status by means of a willto truth.

    Nietzsches classical definition, proposed in the essay On Truth and Lie in an Extra-

    Moral Sense, perfectly synthesizes this thought:

    What then is truth? A mobile army of metaphors, metonyms, and

    anthropomorphisms -- in short, a sum of human relations, which have

    been enhanced, transposed, and embellished poetically and rhetorically,

    and which after long use seem firm, canonical, and obligatory to a

    people: truths are illusions about which one has forgotten that is whatthey are; metaphors which are worn out and without sensuous power;

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    5/16

    coins which have lost their pictures and now matter only as metal, no

    longer as coins.(Nietzsche 1873/1977: 46-7)

    For Nietzsche, then, truth is interested knowledge, the brainchild of a will which creates

    its own opposition between true and false: its own effect of truth. It appears in thefashion of arbitrary metaphors, which are nonetheless made to become literal, taking on a

    conventional and naturalized form throughout history. The original intuitive metaphors

    are therefore taken for the things themselves.

    But man forgets it. He forgets that he has created his own truths, since he has built

    himself and things within a paradigm of rationality. He believes that he builds up from

    an essence and that language serves merely as a transparent conduit for that essence. He

    believes that he can look into the real from the outside. And that is what allows him to

    think of science and philosophy in terms of discovery of truths. As Arrojo observes, the

    perspective proposed by Nietzsche points to the conclusion that man does not discover

    truths independently from his will to power or his survival instinct; he rather produces

    meanings and hence knowledge which is established through the conventions that

    discipline man in social groups (Arrojo 1992: 54, my translation).

    The production of solid and naturalized meanings, however, does not take place on a

    rational dimension only; it also occurs in mans relation with mythand art. Man allows

    himself to be tricked by the illusion of finding an ever-reinvented, particular form of

    relating to the world of dreams. As long as it does not cause him any visible harm, he

    will be charmed when he listens to epic tales being told as true, when he sees an actor

    play a king more regally than the king himself and, why not say it adding an example

    to the ones Nietzsche proposes , when receiving and transmitting urban legends over

    the Internet.

    The Nietzschean notion that truth does not exist as a pre-existing absolute fact of reality,

    but that it may exist as an effect even if necessarily illusory points to the utilitarian

    nature of truth. Nietzsche claims that knowledge, inasmuch as it presents itself as a set of

    truthful and reliable beliefs, may serve certain purposes, but not others, and that certain

    things can be described as useful to certain kinds of people but not to others. This only

    reinforces the authors refusal of the idea of truth as correspondence. Rather than

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    6/16

    corresponding to a factual reality existing outside language and independent of human

    beings, truth as conceived by Nietzsche is a cultural construction, a way of meeting

    human desires, needs and uncertainties. As such, it is a value.

    If for Nietzsche every form of knowledge and, consequently, every form of truth is

    necessarily a perspective, it becomes impossible to aspire to an absolute and final

    apprehension of reality. As Mos summarizes: by affirming that truth is a value,

    Nietzsche wishes to desacralize this evaluative principle, revealing its condition as a

    human invention: truth is an idea, a construct of thought, it has a history (Mos 2005:

    31). It is, therefore, inescapablypartial.

    Directly influenced by Nietzsche, Foucault finds here the inspiration for one of his most

    fundamental themes: the relation of interdependence between power and knowledge.

    According to Foucault (1971/1996: 13-21), truth is an important external exclusionary

    procedure in the order of discourse which operates by means of the true/false opposition.

    When one looks into a discourse, at the level of the sentence or proposition, such an

    opposition is neither arbitrary nor violent. It does not vary, either: the proposition is

    always true or always false. But when it comes to identifying what has been, historically,

    the will to truththat pervades our discourses and what sort of separation rules them, then

    truth presents itself as a historical and institutionally sustained system of exclusion.

    Major transformations which our societies have undergone over the centuries, including

    scientific discoveries, can, to a certain extent, be interpreted as being the result of always

    new wills to truth which were gradually imposed on a number of institutional practices,

    such as pedagogy, empirical research, or the exploitation of technological resources.

    But something peculiar occurs with discourses of truth: by presenting themselves asfreed from desire and power, they simply cannot recognize the will to truth that pervades

    them; that is, in order to establish themselves as true, these discourses cannot help but

    hide the fact that they are products of the will to truth. Thus, what we are allowed to see

    is a truth that is rich and fertile, a sweet and insidiously universal force, and not the

    prodigious machinery designed to exclude all those who, time after time in our history,

    have tried to evade that will to truth and to question it against truth (Foucault

    1971/1996: 20, my translation).

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    7/16

    Truth is not produced as an autonomous error-free entity, hovering above human

    errancy, independent from the institutional mechanisms of social action and control, or

    from human desire. Truth is inextricably attached to those mechanisms and, therefore, to

    power. Foucault reminds us that in any society the multiple power relations which

    characterize the social body cannot be established or function outside a regime of truth,

    that is, without being sustained by discourses of truth. In the authors words:

    There is no exerting of power without a certain economy of discourses of

    truth which function in, from, and through that power. We are subjected

    by power to the production of truth, and we can only exert power by

    producing truth. (...) After all, we are judged, condemned, classified,

    obliged to duties, destined to a certain way of living or to a certain way of

    dying as a result of discourses of truth that carry with them specific power

    effects, truth effects.(Foucault 1976/1999: 28-9, my translation)

    Foucault concludes that the will to truth, originated from the historically constructed

    division between right and wrong, or true and false, is nothing more than the

    exclusionary will to power. True discourse is no more than a necessary illusion on the

    basis of which social subjects struggle for power. And it is important to understand that

    this struggle takes place from inside the very discursive practice: we cannot reach the

    truth, for we are always-alreadyassignedacircumscribedsubjectposition themoment

    weenterdiscourse, the moment we are assigned a social position in our communities.

    The author proposes that in order to analyze the will to power (and knowledge) in

    discourse we must gradually build and define our analytical tools in a practice he calls

    genealogical. This is done in keeping with demands and possibilities designed by

    concrete, contextualized studies (Foucault 1997). Bringing our object of study into this

    perspective, I believe we ought to better investigate and understand how the discursive

    practices around contemporary legends point to the issue of the truthfulness versus

    falsehood of the stories as being the key to those legends as if the narratives depended

    exclusively on scientific-objective verdicts in order for validation. Such an

    investigation would imply the analysis of the discursive practices which produce these

    narratives in their localknowledgedimension.

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    8/16

    On Internet discussion lists dedicated to the transmission and discussion of

    contemporary legends2, a great number of posts refer specifically to the issue of truth

    in/of/around the legends. Different interlocutors often struggle, by means of

    argumentation and supposedly legitimate scientific references, to debunk the rumors or

    proto-legends and re-establish the factual order as soon as these narratives hit their e-

    mail boxes. It is as if to prove the stories false were the very raison dtre of such

    narrative practices: the moving force of the debate. Indeed, one must carefully

    examine how those narratives build on the tension between the local, discontinuous(in

    Foucaults terms) and unverified knowledge, on the one hand, and the hierarchical force

    of trueknowledgeon the other true knowledge which, once available to all by means

    of the rational-logical apparatus of science, is taken as something revealed or

    explained by the discourse of those select few who possess it.

    One must not lose track, however, of Foucaults reminder that there does not exist a

    simple division between accepted and excluded discourses, or between dominant and

    dominated discourses. There is no discourse of power on the one hand, and discourse

    against power on the other. Rather, in a given discursive practice, we often observe a

    co-relation of forces, a multiplicity of different power/knowledge strategies that co-

    exist. And it is this distribution of forces which is to be detected in the analysis: the play

    between the things that are said and those that are unsaid or banned from discourse; the

    variables and distinct effects depend on who speaks, when, from which

    subjective/power position, and within which institutional context.

    Rorty and the Pragmatist Approach to Truth

    For pragmatists knowledge is a tool, an instrument that must be put to the service of the

    conditions of experience. One of the basic principles of pragmatism shared by its

    major representatives, from William James to Richard Rorty, with John Dewey and

    Donald Davidson in between is anti-representationalism : the idea that there is nota

    world out there, a reality independent from thought which might be represented by

    language in a relation of correspondence or correctness. An idea which was already

    present in Nietzsche.

    2I am considering here, in particular, the discussion forum hosted by the site www.snopes.com, whichprovided most of the corpus of my doctoral thesis on contemporary legends (unpublished).

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    9/16

    The same holds for the notion of truth, which, already with the first pragmatists, appears

    as dissociated from the idea of the representation of things in reality. The focus here is

    on experience, the way people relate to reality. According to this line of thought, truth

    cannot be mere correspondence to reality, but rather the contingent product of relations

    that humans establish with each other through usage or, in Wittgensteinian terms,

    language games. In other words, being true is not a property which is external to

    language, a predicate of things in the world out there, but rather a fundamentally

    linguistic device, a predicate of phrases, sentences or propositions, produced by

    members of social communities through their interactions and inter-relations.

    Richard Rorty, arguably the most outstanding name in current pragmatist philosophy,

    formulates the questions in the following terms:

    To say that truth is not out there is simply to say that where there are no

    sentences, there is no truth, that sentences are elements of human

    languages, and that human languages are human creations. Truth cannot

    be out there cannot exist independently of the human mind because

    sentences cannot so exist, or be out there. The world is out there, but

    descriptions of the world are not. Only descriptions of the world can be

    true or false. The world on its own unaided by the describing activities

    of human beings cannot. (Rorty 1989:5)

    This reflection leads Rorty to wonder whether truth even deserves philosophical inquiry

    as a relevant and unquestionable concept in itself. He questions the utility for human

    society of insisting on formulating a theory of truth, a consistent body of thought that

    might account for a concept which, after all, pervades all the transcendental-

    metaphysical-epistemological problematic, from Plato to Heidegger, and which

    continues to confound and obscure philosophers. Instead, Rorty claims, philosophical

    thought should set out to describe the conditions in which the true presents itself inlinguistic behaviors, that is, in contingent practices where people do things with

    language.

    What Rorty values the most in the pragmatist tradition is his precursors vocation

    notwithstanding their differences and divergences to shift the focus away from

    questions like What in the world is true to questions like How is the word true

    used? (Rorty 1991: 132) or, simply, to consider the issue of truth in language inperformativeterms,highlightingthenecessarilypublicandhencesocialnatureof language.

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    10/16

    In a sort of radical minimalism, what Rorty claims that everything that can be said

    about X is what X is, there not being to X an occult or intrinsic side which eludes

    the relational apprehension of X through language. For Rorty, truth cannot be

    discovered, for that would be admitting that truth depends on what the world is like

    in the sense of causal relations rather than descriptive acts.

    Broadening this view towards a more specifically political formulation, Rorty argues

    that, in an ideally liberal and democratic society, the notion of truth as correspondence

    to reality should be replaced by an idea of truth as what one comes to believe over free

    and open encounters. For the American philosopher, truth appears as a historical

    contingency, and not as a convergence or a rational and universally valid (even if

    uncoerced) communicative consensus, such as defended by the likes of Habermas (Hoy

    1994). But does that mean one should take Rortys view as reducing truth to a mere

    pact, a fragile and capricious agreement between language players?

    The Polish sociologist Zygmunt Bauman could be called on into this debate. He aligns

    himself with the pragmatist view whereby truth, rather than symbolizing the relation

    between what is said and a determined non-verbal reality, stands in our usage for a

    certain attitude we take, but above all wish or expect others to take, to what is said or

    believed (Bauman 1997: 112). Still, according to Bauman, there is no sense in

    speaking of truth if not in a situation of dissent. Truth only comes up as an issue when

    different people hold on to different beliefs, making it the object of dispute on who is

    right and who is wrong. Truth comes up when one claims the right to speak with

    authority, or when it becomes particularly important for an adversary to prove that the

    other sideof the dispute is wrong. The struggle for truth represents, then, the strugglefor establishing certain beliefs as systematically superior, under the excuse that they

    have been reached at through a reliable procedure, or one that is vouched for by the

    kind of people who may be trusted to follow it (Bauman op. cit.: 113).

    The way I read him, Rorty would put this issue in other, maybe less ideological,

    terms. By explaining the relation between truth and justification related to the

    cautionary use of truth discussed above the philosopher claims that the need to justifyour beliefs and desires to others and to ourselves subjects us to certain norms, the

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    11/16

    obedience to which produces a behavioral pattern which we must detect in others

    before we can confidentlyattribute beliefs to them(Rorty1998: 26).

    In other words, we enter the language game of the communities to which we belong

    with certain beliefs, and we know that those we play with possess, on their side, their

    own beliefs. But we must attest to the existence of those beliefs performatively, from

    within the linguistic exchanges, and not take them as givens. What Rorty does not

    believe, perhaps unlike Bauman, is that the rules of the linguistic game necessarily

    imply obeying an additional norm the commandment to seek a [final] truth (Rorty

    op. cit.:op. cit.).

    Reading Legends, Reading Myths: The Lessons Theory Teaches Us

    Bringing our contemporary legends back into focus, we could but only begin, in a

    tentative exercise of critical reading, to reassess the issue of truth as it manifests itself

    in the practice of transmitting and commenting on these narratives. Rather than taking

    to the facile opposition between truthfulness versus falsehood, which would imply a

    view of truth as correspondence to a self-sustaining order of reality (i.e. the facts, the

    truth out there), we would do better by using the lessons our philosophers have

    offered and applying them in our language classes in an attempt to reassess our

    common sense interpretations and view the discursive practice with different, critical,

    eyes.

    We could certainly retain Foucaults critique of truth, particularly as it is formulated in

    the following passage by Barry Allen, one of his commentators: [f]or truth-value (and

    associated values like reference, translation, relevance, implication, identity, and

    objectivity) to be determinate in any case depends on the effectiveness of historically

    contingent practices of evaluation, and on nothing else (Allen 1995: 110-1). This

    amounts to claiming that the difference between true and false cannot be established by

    external, context-free parameters. It does not exist apart from a (contingent) local

    practice, in which these values are produced and evaluated, and statements circulate as

    true, presenting themselves in the form of facts, news, legends (legenda, i.e. what is

    to be read). Allen continues: Only here have statements currency, the capacity to

    circulate, to penetrate practical reasoning, to be taken seriously, to passfor the truth.

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    12/16

    These practical conditions situate truth amid all the major asymmetries of social power,

    undermining its status as a common good (Allen op. cit.: 4). Truth then is not common

    good. Rather, it is a space for potential dissent, in which power relations will battle

    their way towards either debunking or reaffirming the different stakes in the game.

    Contemporary legends, more particularly the practical conditions in which they are

    produced and perpetuated, function as the stage where a number of partial truths gain

    their currency. In other words, they are the space where different regimes, or programs

    of truth, are enacted. Believing or not in certain narratives in this or that version of a

    specific contemporary legend implies more than a single-minded pursuit of factual

    truth. It more likely involves a permanent shift between modes of belief a shift that is

    not unlike the one Paul Veyne (1983) identifies in the complex relation the Greeks held

    with their myths.

    Belonging to a time long gone, in all its wonders, its narratives of gods and men

    and fantastic creatures that one does not come across walking on the streets, at least not

    in the present , myth offered itself to the Greeks as an integrally truthful reality,

    one that transmitted collective memories which could not have been simply invented

    lies. As Veyne points out, believing in that body of narrative as a plausible one means

    still being within the true, but in analogical terms. Myth is inherited information. It is

    an accepted tradition. And it is respected. Once the story is over, we can shift to another

    mode of truth that of real life and then back and forth, in an analogical operation.

    One may criticize myth from within a historians program of truth rejecting the

    chronological incoherence and the improbable cause-and-effect propositions but one

    may also be compelled to read allegorical truths into it. To the rationalistcondemnation of the imaginary as false, the apologetic of the imaginary replies that it

    conforms to a hidden reason. For it is not possible to lie (Veyne 1983: 62). By

    claiming that truth and interest which I equate with (ever-partial) interpretation are

    inseparable concepts, Veyne echoes Foucault. Both would agree that in the process of

    attempting to fix the meanings of a discourse practice in a regime/program of truth,

    contingency (as situatedness)becomes a necessity that keeps justifying itself. And, as

    we have seen with Rorty, justifying is one more language game one plays with truth.

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    13/16

    In that sense, could contemporary legends be some sort of modern-day myth? I would

    argue that just as it is impossible to lie about myth, it may be impossible to lie about

    urban legends. The force that a legend may acquire in a certain interpretive community

    tends to be greater than the evidence that contests its veracity. Whether or not the

    narrative is trustworthy does not affect the impact that the force of its message may

    cause. As Whatley and Henken point out:

    [T]he evidence countering the veracity of a legend rarely carries the

    weight that the legend does. (...) The impact a legend has on those telling

    or hearing it may have little to do with whether the story is believed. ()

    What may be more important is the truth that folklore conveys about the

    attitudes, fears, and beliefs of a group, which in turn shape and maintain

    the identity of that group. (Whatley and Henken 2001: 4-5)

    Thus, our students may not believe, for example, that someone could have really

    planted an HIV-infected needle on their theater seats, but this will not necessarily stop

    them from double-checking before sitting. Equally, they may not believe that the long-

    lasting use of their cell phones may pose any risk of explosion, but still they will turn

    off their devices when pulling into a service station. That is, the most relevant aspect of

    this kind of narrative may not be its objectively attested implausibility, but rather the

    truth it reveals about the beliefs and values of the communities in which it circulates.

    Finally, we could stick with a lesson that Veyne indirectly teaches about the myths of

    our present time, and that somehow paves the way toward a more critical

    understanding of our object in point. What he says about myth serves just as well for

    contemporary legends: in order to engage with those narratives we would do well to

    sort through the heterogeneous programs of truth that constitute our imagination

    programs that tell us what we, in our communities, are or are not allowed to believe

    at different moments in history; programs that intersect or even contradict each other in

    our everyday, ever-shifting contingent practices of being in the true. And so, at each

    moment, nothing exists or acts outside these [space-defining] palaces of the

    imagination... They are the only space available (Veyne 1983: 121).

    This Elusive Thing Called Truth

    Agents and advocates of Critical Literacy will have identified in all these discussions

    one of the tenets of their own belief system, thus summarized by Cervetti et al. (2001:

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    14/16

    10): Reality cannot be known definitely, and cannot be captured by language;

    decisions about truth, therefore, cannot be based on a theory of correspondence with

    reality, but must instead be made locally. Locally in the different interpretive

    communities we claim membership to; locally in our classrooms, as we and our

    students learn to rethink the often deeply ingrained assumptions we hold on to as truth,

    and on what can or cannot be true about the stories we are told.

    In view of our theoretical grounding the search for the truth of/in contemporary legends

    leads us along the routes of two intersecting tracks. The first one shows that we cannot

    possibly learn all the facts and hence all the truth narrated in these stories. That

    is, we cannot know with absolute certainty what is a technically, scientifically attested

    (or even plausible) fact and what is merely a persistent rumor or piece of

    misinformation and I think here particularly of the abundant narratives surrounding

    the mysterious powers of not so new technologies, or the risks of yet uncontrollable

    diseases. We simply err;we cling to our most essential and mundane truths: that

    we are all exposed to too-close-to-home risks, and that someday we will all die. The

    second track teaches us that, albeit incomplete, controversial or merely plausible, facts

    only make sense insofar as they belong to an itinerary of truth. They are mediated by

    a regime of discursive practices that see narrative as a privileged form of manifestation

    narratives of a particular type, dispersed and mutable, such as contemporary legends,

    but also other narratives of a particular type, those claimed by the legitimized

    institutions of power/knowledge that go by the name of science, politics, education, the

    media, etc. Ultimately, narratives of this sort are the stuff that makes up the fabric of our

    everyday engagements with reality.

    So as to make the most out of these reflections in a critical stance towards contemporarylegends, we could perhaps draw the map of those two tracks in the form of a dialectic

    sway: one by which the will to truth in legends simultaneously constitutes on the one

    hand, a form of social regulation of, and on the other hand, afictional reinvention of, the

    fears and anxieties of daily life, through narrative. Positioning ourselves as teachers and

    learners who can perceive and critically engage with this dialectic will have been the

    result of a critical practice:a continual, ever-transitory but not a bit elusive exercise

    in critical literacy. An exercise which I believe, from my experience, could take placethe moment the agents involved in the language classroom practice venture beyond the

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    15/16

    predictable, consensus-aspiring discussion on the falsehood of legends and begin to

    think possibly different truths.

    REFERENCES:

    ALLEN, Barry (1995) Truth in Philosophy. Cambridge and London: HarvardUniversity Press.

    ARROJO, Rosemary (1992) A desconstruo do signo e a iluso da trama, in:ARROJO, Rosemary (org.) O Signo Desconstrudo. Campinas:Pontes.

    BAUMAN, Zygmunt (1997) Postmodernity and Its Discontents. Cambridge andOxford: Polity Press.

    CERVETTI, Gina; PARDALES, Michael J.; DAMICO, James S. (2001) A Tale ofDifferences: Comparing the Traditions, Perspectives, and Educational Goals ofCritical Reading and Critical Literacy, in:Reading Online, 4(9).http://www.readingonline.org/articles/art_index.asp?HREF=/articles/cervetti/

    ELLIS, Bill (2001)Aliens, Ghosts, and Rituals Legends We Live. Jackson: UniversityPress of Mississsippi.

    FINE, Gary Alan (1992)Manufacturing Tales Sex and Money in ContemporaryLegends. Knoxville:The University of Tennessee Press.

    FOUCAULT, Michel (1971/1996)A Ordem do Discurso. So Paulo:Loyola.

    _________________ (1976/1999)Em Defesa da Sociedade. So Paulo: Martins Fontes.

    _________________ (1997)Resumo dos Cursos do Collge de France (1970-1982).Rio de Janeiro:Jorge Zahar Editor.

    HOY, David Couzens (1994) The Contingency of Universality:Critical Theory asGenealogical Hermeneutics, in:HOY, David Couzens and McCARTHY,Thomas. Critical Theory. Oxford and Cambridge: Blackwell.

    MOS, Viviane (2005)Nietzsche e a Grande Poltica da Linguagem. Rio de Janeiro:Civilizao Brasileira.

    NIETZSCHE, Friedrich (1873/1977) On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense, in :The Portable Nietzsche. London:Penguin Books.

    RENARD, J.-B.Rumeurs et Lgendes Urbaines. Paris:PUF, 3e dition, 2006.

    RORTY, Richard (1989) Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.

    _______________ (1991) Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press.

  • 8/14/2019 When Truth is at Stake - The Case of Contemporary Legends

    16/16

    ________________(1998) Truth and Progress. Cambridge:Cambridge University

    Press.

    SHOR, Ira (1999) What is Critical Literacy?, in:Journal for Pedagogy, Pluralism &

    Practice, issue 4, vol. 1, http://www.lesley.edu/journals/jppp/4/shor.html.

    VEYNE, Paul (1983)Did the Greeks Believe in Their Myths? An Essay on theConstitutive Imagination, translated by Paula Wissing. Chicago and London:The University of Chicago Press.

    WHATLEY, Mariamne H. and HENKEN, Elissa R. (2000)Did you Hear About theGirl Who...? Contemporary Legends, Folklore, and Human Sexuality. NewYork & London:New York University Press.