sociology: an analytical core

42
Sociology: An Analytical Core Herbert Gintis Santa Fe Institute July 2013

Upload: anneke

Post on 11-Feb-2016

34 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Sociology: An Analytical Core. Herbert Gintis Santa Fe Institute July 2013. Summary. Economics and biology each has a common core of analytical theory that all practitioners learn as a common basis for discourse, testing, and revision. Sociology lacks such a common core. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Sociology: An Analytical Core

Herbert GintisSanta Fe Institute

July 2013

Page 2: Sociology: An Analytical Core

SummaryEconomics and biology each has a common

core of analytical theory that all practitioners learn as a common basis for discourse, testing, and revision.

Sociology lacks such a common core. Rather, every sociological theorist develops a grand intellectual structure that rejects rather than building on past theoretical successes.

For this reason, sociological theory is widely ignored by the other behavioral disciplines,leading to the exclusion of sociology from the current move towards the unification of the behavioral sciences.

Page 3: Sociology: An Analytical Core

SummaryWe must build an analytical core to

sociological theory.What follows is my concept of what such a

core should include.

Page 4: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Summary1. Sociobiology:

The place of humans in the array of social speciesThe Major Transitions in Evolution: Cumulative Increase in the Complexity of Social Interaction

Every major transition involved a solution to a complex social dilemmaGene-Culture Coevolution in Humans

2. Rational Choice:The Role of Morality and Prosociality in Rational ChoiceNetworked Minds and Distributed CognitionSelf-regard, other-regard, and character virtues

Page 5: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Summary3. Social Structure

Social Actor and Social Role The Articulation of Social Roles

Social Frames4. Integration of Social Actor and Social

StructureSocial Production of Common PriorsThe Socio-psychological Theory of NormsGame Theory: The Correlated Equilibrium and the Choreographer

Social norms are correlated equilibria

Page 6: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Sociobiology ofDictyostelium Discoideum

Dictyostelium Discoideum is a cellular slime mold.

When food is readily available it lives as an individual amoeba, feeding and dividing normally.

When food is exhausted, individuals aggregate to form a multicellular assembly, called a slug.

The slug forms a fruiting body with a stalk supporting a ball of spores.

These spores remain dormant until food is available.

The stalk is composed of individual amoebae which die during stalk formation.

Page 7: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Dictyostelium Discoideum

Page 8: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Dictyostelium DiscoideumDictyostelium Discoideum is a beautiful

example of a social dilemma.The future of the group depends on

cooperating in forming the stalk and choosing some individuals to live as sporeswhile the rest die as members of the stalk.

How cheating is limited in Discoideum and other such species is complex and only partially understood.

Page 9: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Major Transitions in Evolution

Prokaryote EukaryoteUnion of previously independently-living prokaryotes into a complex cooperative unity.

Clones Sexual reproductionMendelian (fair) segregation is the product of gene regulatory networks that prevent cheating.Tensions remain; e.g., mitochondria have their own non-Mendelian (maternal) inheritance system.

Page 10: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Major Transitions in Evolution

Single-cell protists Multicellular organismsWhich cells get to reproduce?How to avoid cheaters who benefit from the cellular division of labor without contributing?

Solitary individuals Societies of interaction individualsHow to prevent defectors from reducing fitness.How to promote non-reproductive castes, such as workers and soldiers in an insect colony.

Genetic control of behavior Gene-culture coevolutionHow to control defectors in a totipotent species (i.e., where all individuals reproduce).

Page 11: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Genetic Contribution to Behavior

Genes

Environment Behavior

Culture

Genes predispose individuals to behave in certain ways, and provide them with the capacity to do so.

For instance, human infants are predisposed to share, and have a sophisticated theory of mind.

Page 12: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Central Problem of Sociobiology in Humans

Human sociobiology is the study of the interaction among utterly selfish genes, the human core genome, which promotes cooperation through the action of regulatory gene networks, and culture/institutions.

Page 13: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Selfish GeneDawkins interpreted the fact that genes are

utterly selfish as implying that all creatures must be behaviorally selfish:Let us try to teach generosity and altruism, because we are born selfish. Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (1976)

This conclusion is at odds with the evidence we have on human behavior, coming fromdevelopmental psychologylaboratory and field studies.

Page 14: Sociology: An Analytical Core

A Cooperative Species

with Samuel BowlesPrinceton University

Press 2010

Page 15: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Other Cooperative Species

Studies show that non-human primates also exhibit extensive prosocial behaviors if, like humans in the hunter-gatherer stage of evolution,they engage in collective child-rearing.

The centrality of collective child-rearing in other species suggest that human sociology should stress the structure of child care very carefully.

Page 16: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Gene-culture CoevolutionIndividual fitness in humans depends on the

structure of social life. Human cognitive, affective, and moral

capacities are the product of an evolutionary dynamic involving the interaction of genes and culture.

For a more complete analysis and extensive references, see Herbert Gintis, "Gene-culture Coevolution and the Nature of Human Sociality", Proceedings of the Royal Society B 366 (2011).

Page 17: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Gene-culture CoevolutionIn this dynamic, humans transform culture,

and the new cultural environment alters the nature of fitness-enhancing genes.

Thus, genes are the product of culture just as culture is the product of genes.

Page 18: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Gene-culture CoevolutionI will give a dramatic example of gene-culture

coevolution: the evolution of the physiology of speech and facial communication.

The increased social importance of speech in our hominin ancestors rewards genetic changes that facilitate speech.

Regions in the motor cortex expanded in early humans to facilitate speech production.

Concurrently, nerves and muscles to the mouth, larynx, and tongue became more numerous to handle the complexities of speech.

Page 19: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Gene-culture CoevolutionAdult modern humans have a larynx low in the

throat, a position that allows the throat to serve as a resonating chamber capable of a great number of sounds .

In addition, the production of consonants requires a short oral cavity, whereas our nearest primate relatives have much too long an oral cavity for this purpose.

Page 20: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Gene-culture CoevolutionAnother indication that the tongue has

evolved in hominids to facilitate speech is the size of the hypoglossal canal, an aperture that permits the hypoglossal nerve to reach the tongue muscles.

This aperture is much larger in Neanderthals and humans than in early hominids and non-human primates (Campbell 2000).

Human facial nerves and musculature have also evolved to facilitate communication.

Page 21: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Gene-culture CoevolutionI have illustrated gene-culture coevolution by

the evolution of communication physiology.But gene-culture coevolution applies to the

emergence of unique human emotional capacities (e.g., shame, guilt, pride, empathy, jealousy, and a taste for retribution).

This coevolutionary process has endowed us with preferences that go beyond the self-regarding concerns emphasized in traditional economic and biological theory

Page 22: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Gene-culture CoevolutionGene-culture coevolution explains why we

have a social epistemology facilitating the sharing of intentionality across minds, as well as why we have such non-self-regarding values as a taste for cooperation, fairness, and retribution, for the capacity to empathize, and for the ability to value character virtues (e.g., honesty)

Page 23: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Rational Actor ModelBehavioral game theory, like much of

economic theory, is built on the rational actor model, which treats choice as taking the most preferred among a set of alternatives.

This model is extremely general, requiring only consistency of preferences.

It applies to the heuristics described by Gigerenzer when the issue is choice rather than problem solving.

The model applies to bacteria just as well as to humans.

When choice is over risky alternatives, the theory implies that agents have subjective priors: probability distributions over the various outcomes.

Rational agents maximize expected utility subject to their subjective priors.

Page 24: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Rational Actor ModelThe rational actor model is widely criticized

outside of economics and biology, but these critiques are generally based on attributing to the theory assertions that are in fact not part of the theoryor desirata that are easily incorporated in the theory.

The results of Kahneman, Tversky et al. are often cited as violations of the rational actor model, but in fact they generally are not (Gintis, Bounds of Reason, 2009).

Indeed, prospect theory, for which Kahneman was awarded the Nobel prize in Economics, is based on the rational actor model.

Behavioral game theory without the rational actor model has no coherence.

Page 25: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Rational Actor ModelThere is, however, one deep problem with the

rational actor model: it assumes that agents choose in isolation from other agents.

In fact, human have networked minds supporting distributed cognition.

Sociology should aim towards characterizing the structure and dynamics of networked minds and how cognition is shared across minds.

I have explored this using agent-based models where networks of individuals control the replicator dynamic.

Page 26: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Defending Rational ChoiceRational choice theory does not require that

the choices people make be welfare-improving.

In fact, people are often slaves to such passions assmoking cigarettes, eating junk food, and engaging in unsafe sex. These behaviors do not violate preference consistency, and hence are rational, according to the rational choice model’s “thin” conception of rationality.

Page 27: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Defending Rational ChoiceRational choice does not require that rational

actors be good problem-solvers.If humans cannot solve complicated problems,

like evaluating the expected value of a lottery, they may simply not know how.

Assuming that rational actors can solve complex problems is a failure of social theory, not the rationality assumption.

Page 28: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Defending Rational ChoiceMost important, rational choice does not imply

self-interested choice. It is rational to care for others, believe in

fairness, or sacrifice for a social ideal.Indeed, Andreoni and Miller (2002) have

shown that people obey all the usual principles of rational choice in the case of contributions to charity.

Page 29: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Character VirtuesCharacter virtues are ethically desirable

behaviors that individuals value for their own sake.

The character virtues include honesty, loyalty, trustworthiness, fairness, considerateness, etc.

These character virtues operate without concern for the individuals with whom one interacts: one is honest because it is the right way to behave.

Character virtues are not absolutes. If the cost of honesty is sufficiently high, most individuals will behave dishonestly (Gneezy 2005).

Page 30: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Sociological ActorThe individual is a rational actor with a

preference function that includes self-regarding and other-regarding objects of desire, as well as valuing virtuous behavior.

The belief system of the actor is constituted from the position of the individual in one or more distributed networks of minds,and depends on the distribution of information across these networks.

Page 31: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Social Structure: Role-based Social Division of

LaborThe social division of labor consists of actors filling social roles (George Herbert Mead, Ralph Linton).

Attached to a social role is a content, consisting of a set of rights, duties, expectations, material and symbolic rewards, and behavioral norms.

In social equilibrium, the content of social roles is common knowledge; i.e., all know and agree on the content of social roles.

Ascriptive states (e.g., man, woman, Korean, accident victim, prisoner) are not social roles.

Page 32: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Social Structure: Role-based Social Division of

LaborAn actor’s behavior in a social role can be modeled as the maximization of his objective function subject to the content of the role.

Few social roles can be productively filled without drawing on the moral commitment of role-occupants.

Page 33: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Social Structure: Role-based Social Division of

LaborEconomic theory has attempted to model role performance as motivated by pure self-regard,but this has failed because complete contracts are unfeasibly costly to enforce, and because principals (government, supervisors) have incomplete information concerning performance in complex economic roles.

Contracts based on a strong element of trust are superior to complete (but unenforceable) contracts.See, for instance, Brown, Falk, and Fehr, Econometrica 2004.

Page 34: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Social Structure: Role-based Social Division of

LaborWhen social roles are not strongly legitimated,role-performance will deteriorate.

Often this is called corruption.Similarly, if unethical role-performance is not

appropriately socially sanctioned,social cooperation will generally unravel, leading to widespread non-compliance.

Page 35: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Social Structure: Social Frames

How does an actor know what role he currently occupies?

Every social situation has a social frame that supplies the sensory cues as to the social situation in which the individual is situated, and the particular social role the individual occupies in this social situation.

In equilibrium, the set of social frames is common knowledge.

Definition: A state s is common knowledge if all actors know s, all actors know that all actors know s, all actors know that all actors know that s, and so on, to whatever depth of recursive knowledge is required.

Page 36: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Common Knowledge is Durkheim’s

Collective RepresentationsCommon knowledge is Durkheim’s notion of collective representations,shorn of its possible metaphysical dimensions.

“Collective representations exist outside of individual consciences…they derive not from individuals taken one by one, but from their interaction.” Émile Durkheim

Sociologie et Philosophie

Page 37: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Common Knowledge is Durkheim’s

Collective RepresentationsA central unifying task of social institutions is to turn private information into common knowledgeas a basis for an efficient social division of labor.

Page 38: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Epistemic Game Theory

The concept of common knowledge comes from epistemic game theory.

See: The Bounds of Reason

(Princeton 2009).

Page 39: Sociology: An Analytical Core

Example: The Role of VoterIn Liberal Democracy

The electoral process in a liberal democracy is perhaps the grandest example of a social dilemma.

The legitimacy of liberal democracy depends on a high level of electoral participation.

However, individual voters have no self-regarding interest in votingbecause one vote makes no difference in a large election.

No voter has a self-regarding interest in voting his self-interest.

Therefore the electorate has no self-regarding interest in being politically informed.

The electoral process is a vast morality play.

Page 40: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Socio-psychological Theory of Norms

The socio-psychological theory of norms relates social morality to individual morality.

Social norms are commonly seen as devices that choose among the Nash equilibria of an underlying social role-playing game.

In fact, social norms are better explained as correlating devices for an underlying stage game.

Page 41: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Socio-psychological

Theory of NormsSocial norms are an emergent property of human society,

In particular, social norms are predicated upon a social epistemology, instantiated in the neural structure of the human brain, that is the product of individual ontogeny (personal development) and our common species phylogeny (natural selection and adaptation).

Page 42: Sociology: An Analytical Core

The Socio-psychological

Theory of NormsThis social epistemology fosters the

interpersonal sharing of mental concepts, and justifies the assumption of common priors upon which the identification of Bayesian rationality with correlated equilibrium rests.