justice: what money can buy - sites@duke |...

36
Primary Social Goods and the Rawlsian Difference Principle Joshua Chen-Yuan Teng, Joseph Tao-yi Wang and C. C. Yang 1 Abstract: While most economists view the relationship between equality and efficiency as a tradeoff or conflict, Rawls (1971) saw it differently according to his proposed difference principle: equality has priority over efficiency in essence. Previous experimental studies lend little support to the importance of the difference principle -- subjects whose social preferences obey the difference principle represent only a small minority in the sample. This paper finds a much stronger support -- a salient majority of subjects whose social preferences obey the difference principle. A key to our departure from previous studies lies in that allocating monetary payoffs between subjects in our experimental design embodies not simply choosing the distribution of payoffs but more importantly the distribution of Rawls's so-called “primary social goods,” which serve as instruments critical to the fulfillment of people's rational desire. 1 Teng: Department of Public Finance, National Taipei University (corresponding author, email: [email protected] ); Wang: Department of Economics, National Taiwan University (email: [email protected] ); Yang: Institute of Economics, Academia Sinica; Department of Public Finance, National Chengchi University; Department of Public Finance, Feng Chia University (email: [email protected] ). This research is supported by The National Science Council, Taiwan, grant 101-2410-H-305-002-. 1

Upload: dangkhanh

Post on 09-May-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

Primary Social Goods and the Rawlsian Difference Principle

Joshua Chen-Yuan Teng, Joseph Tao-yi Wang and C. C. Yang1

Abstract: While most economists view the relationship between equality and efficiency as a

tradeoff or conflict, Rawls (1971) saw it differently according to his proposed difference

principle: equality has priority over efficiency in essence. Previous experimental studies lend

little support to the importance of the difference principle -- subjects whose social

preferences obey the difference principle represent only a small minority in the sample. This

paper finds a much stronger support -- a salient majority of subjects whose social preferences

obey the difference principle. A key to our departure from previous studies lies in that

allocating monetary payoffs between subjects in our experimental design embodies not

simply choosing the distribution of payoffs but more importantly the distribution of Rawls's

so-called “primary social goods,” which serve as instruments critical to the fulfillment of

people's rational desire.

1Teng: Department of Public Finance, National Taipei University (corresponding author, email: [email protected]); Wang: Department of Economics, National Taiwan University (email: [email protected]); Yang: Institute of Economics, Academia Sinica; Department of Public Finance, National Chengchi University; Department of Public Finance, Feng Chia University (email: [email protected]). This research is supported by The National Science Council, Taiwan, grant 101-2410-H-305-002-.

1

Page 2: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

I. Introduction

A fundamental tradeoff in policy or institutional design in economics is between equality

and efficiency. On the one hand, we would like to have a pie produced as large as possible.

On the other hand, we would also like to divide the pie among individuals as equal as

possible. Unfortunately, an equal division of a pie will generally dull individual incentives to

work hard; as a result, the equality goal and the efficiency goal are often in conflict. A

tradeoff between these two goals seems inevitable, and the focus of policy or institutional

design is on the tradeoff. 

Rawls (1971) saw the relationship between equality and efficiency differently: equality

has priority over efficiency in essence. He proposed the difference principle (popularly

known as the maximin criterion), arguing that efficiency is desirable only if it is beneficial to

the least advantaged. Papers including Johannesson and Gerdtham (1995), Beckman et al.

(2002), Charness and Rabin (2002), Johansson-Stenman et al. (2002), Carlsson et al. (2003),

Engelmann and Strobel (2004), Traub et al. (2005) and Schildberg-Hörisch (2010), have

conducted experiments to test, among other things, the importance of the Rawlsian difference

principle. Overall, it receives little support -- subjects whose social preferences obey the

difference principle represent only a small minority in the sample. For example, this

proportion of subjects is found to be lower than 14% in Schildberg-Hörisch (2010), and 9%

in Traub et al. (2005), both are well below the majority.2

In this paper we re-conduct test on the difference principle and find a much stronger

support -- a salient majority of subjects whose social preferences obey the principle. A key to

the departure from previous studies is that our experimental design introduces the so-called

“primary social goods,” a critical concept emphasized by Rawls (1971) in his arguments for

2Besides incentivized experiments, Konow (2009) used a survey approach and found that people would apply divergent principles under various described circumstances. For example, the efficiency principle will be adopted in business administration, but people would allocate enough money to satisfy necessary means of students.

2

Page 3: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

the difference principle. 

Primary social goods

Rawls (1971) used a contractarian approach to develop his theory of justice. He

perceived that everyone would agree to construct principles of justice behind “the veil of

ignorance”, that is, no one knows “his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and

abilities, his intelligence, strength, and the like.” (p. 12) Then the “two principles of justices”

that would be agreed by everyone arise (p. 302):

1. First principle: “Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system

of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all.”

2. Second principle: “Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are

both: (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings

principle,3 and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair

equality of opportunity.”

The one that is subject to tests most frequently in economics is part (a) of the second

principle -- the difference principle. Below we often appeal to Rawls's (1971) original quotes

for the purpose of persuading readers that the category of primary social goods is the main

domain to which the difference principle is supposed to apply.

To motivate the difference principle, Rawls first discussed concepts of welfare.

Specifically, Rawls adopted Aristotle’s thought of welfare: “A person’s good is determined by

what is for him the most rational long-term plan of life given reasonably favorable

circumstances. A man is happy when he is more or less successfully in the way of carrying

out this plan. To put it briefly, the good is the satisfaction of rational desire.” (pp. 92-93)

Postulating that people have this concept of welfare, Rawls reasoned that they would “prefer

3The aim of the just saving principle is to realize justice between generations. Rawls believed that it can be formulated behind the veil of ignorance, that is, no one knows to which generations she belongs. For more details, see Rawls (1971, pp. )

3

Page 4: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

more primary social goods” (p. 142), which are defined as “Things that every rational man is

presumed to want. These goods normally have a use whatever a person’s rational plan of life.

For simplicity, assume that the chief primary goods at the disposition of society are rights,

liberties, and opportunities, and income and wealth.” (p. 62) In fact, Rawls explicitly wrote:

“The difference principle is a very special criterion: it applies primarily to the basic structure

of society via representative individuals whose expectations are to be estimated by an index

of primary goods.”4

Note that Rawls did not specify what kinds of expectations or plans in life people would

or should pursue. Instead, “Only the most general assumptions are made about the aims of

the parties, namely, that they take an interest in primary social goods …To suppose, then

that the parties want these goods, and to found a conception of justice on this presumption,

is not to tie it to a particular pattern of human interests as these might be generated by a

particular arrangement of institutions. The theory of justice does, indeed, presuppose a

theory of the good, but within wide limits this does not prejudge the choice of the sort of

persons that men want to be.” (p. 260)

Behind the veil of ignorance, one of the reasons for which people would adopt the

difference principle is that it is too risky to gamble on primary social goods: “…the person

choosing has a conception of the good such that he cares very little, if anything, for what he

might gain above the minimum stipend that he can, in fact, be sure of by following the

maximin rule. It is not worthwhile for him to take a chance for the sake of a further

advantage, especially when it may turn out that he loses much that is important to him.” (p.

4 See Rawls (1999, p. 72), the revised edition of A Theory of Justice. In this edition, Rawls disagreed with economists’ view of seeing the maximin preference as a result of extreme risk aversion, and argued that the difference principle is a fairness idea.

4

Page 5: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

154)5

To our understanding of these quotations, Rawls seemed to suggest that the difference

principle is applicable to the allocation of primary social goods, which serve as instruments

to fulfill “the most rational long-term plan of life”; indeed, “The difference principle ...

applies primarily to the basic structure of society via representative individuals whose

expectations are to be estimated by an index of primary goods.” Naturally, the difference

principle is not applicable to the distribution of final outcomes resulting from “the

satisfaction of rational desire” since the theory of justice “within wide limits ... does not

prejudge the choice of the sort of persons that men want to be.”

5 People may not even know the distribution of their social positions behind the veil of ignorance. This nature of uncertainty makes it very risky to choose principles other than the difference principle. Gerber et al. (2013) tested this by giving subjects full or partial or no information of their social positions (defined by differences in productivities). They found higher demand for redistribution under the no and partial information than under the full information.

5

Page 6: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

Previous experimental tests on the difference principle typically ask subjects to choose

the distribution of monetary payments, which designate as the distribution of final

outcomes. As such, these tests may fail to catch a critical point of the Rawlsian difference

principle, that is, it is the distribution of primary social goods (serving as instruments to

fulfill “the most rational long-term plan of life”) rather than the distribution of final

outcomes that really matters. This paper builds on and extends previous work, exploring

implications of this plausible thought on the Rawlsian difference principle.

The rest of the paper is organized as follows. Section II introduces our experimental

design. Section III reports the results and Section IV concludes.

II. Experimental Design

In Schildberg-Hörisch (2010), a subject in the “allocation stage” must choose one

distributional allocation from the 13 possible ones shown in Table 1. After decisions are

made, all subjects are randomly divided into groups of two, and roles (Player 1 or Player 2)

are then randomly assigned to each group member as “the veil of ignorance” would be. It is

clear from Table 1 that Alternative 1 is the most efficient allocation, from which Player 1’s

payoff equals the largest amount 240 (in terms of experimental standard currency, ESC)

whereas Player 2 receives nothing. The next distributional allocation, Alternative 2, yields

220 for Player 1 and 10 for Player 2, indicating an efficiency loss of 50% when transferring

20 ESC from Player 1 to Player 2. In fact, every time when we move to the next higher

numbered Alternative, Player 1’s payoff is reduced by 20 ESC but Player 2 will only gain

10 ESC. Put differently, there exists tradeoff or conflict between efficiency and equality in

choosing different distributional allocations in Table 1. Note that choosing Alternatives 10

to 13 is not rational, in that it sacrifices efficiency without gaining equality. No subject

chose any of these alternatives in our experiment. So, we confine our analysis to

Alternatives 1-9 for the rest of the paper.

6

Page 7: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

[Insert Table 1 about here]

As far as the allocation stage is concerned, we adopt the same setup represented by

Table 1 as in Schildberg-Hörisch (2010). Our innovation is to add a “real effort stage” right

after the allocation stage. In the real effort stage, subjects perform the slider task devised by

Gill and Prowse (2012). They earn 30 ESC for each successful task and, within 120

seconds, there are total 48 slider tasks to be completed by a subject. Each slider is initially

positioned at 0. To accomplish a task successfully, the subject has to use the mouse to

position the slider exactly at 50. There are two different working environments under which

subjects can carry out the task. The first is the environment in which the current position of

a slider is displayed with a numerical scale so that subjects can adjust the slider to the

correct position without errors; see Figure 1a. The second is the environment in which the

current position of a slider is displayed without any numerical scale so that subjects face

difficulty in adjusting the slider to the correct position; see Figure 1b.

[Insert Figure 1 about here]

To which environment a subject is applied, it hinges completely upon whether the

monetary payoff received by the subject in the allocation stage is no less than some

threshold or not. If the threshold criterion is met in the allocation stage, a subject will carry

out the task in the first environment with scales displayed; however, if the threshold

criterion is not met, a subject must carry out the task in the second environment without

scales displayed. To accomplish the task successfully, it is obvious that the display of

numerical scales for the current position of a slider serves as a critical instrument for

subjects. It is important to recognize that once the threshold is met, no subject is in a better

position than others in terms of advantage or disadvantage in carrying out the task in the

real effort stage. Subjects are “all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity” as Rawls

(1971, p. 266) would put it. By means of this experimental design, we tie the monetary

7

Page 8: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

payoffs received in the allocation stage tightly to the concept of primary social goods in the

real effort stage. More specifically, if a subject’s payoff received in the allocation stage is

below the threshold, the amount of primary social goods owned by the subject in the real

effort stage will be insufficient and, consequently, he or she has to implement the task in the

real effort stage in the absence of “reasonably favorable circumstances.” On the other hand,

all of those who meet the threshold will own sufficient primary social goods or means to

make money in the real effort stage, and all are under conditions of fair equality of

opportunity to realize “the most rational long-term plan of life”.

Allocating resources between subjects in the allocation stage in Schildberg-Hörisch

(2010) and other similar studies is to determine the distribution of final outcomes, which

directly dictate subjects' well-being. Allocating resources between subjects in the allocation

stage here is to mainly determine the distribution of social primary goods in the real effort

stage, which only indirectly dictate subjects' well-being. It is indirect because primary social

goods serve as instruments, not ends, in the real effort stage.

We conduct a between-subject experiment with three different thresholds in the

allocation stage: 75, 35 and 0. These three thresholds represent different critical levels of

redistribution in the allocation stage such that once the thresholds are met, the resulting

distributions of primary social goods will enable subjects to face “reasonably favorable

circumstances” and have “conditions of fair equality of opportunity” in the real effort stage.

The 0 threshold serves the benchmark or control. Because choices in the allocation stage

have no impact whatsoever on the real effort stage when the threshold is 0, the result of this

treatment is expected to be similar to that of Schildberg-Hörisch (2010).

When the critical level of redistribution in the allocation stage reaches 75 as required in

the 75-threshold treatment, Alternative 9 in Table 1 is the only distribution in the allocation

8

Page 9: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

stage that meets the threshold for both players.6 Subjects who choose Alternative 9 in the

allocation stage in this treatment reveal their maximin social preferences.

The critical level of redistribution in the 35-threshold treatment is located between the

two treatments above. Alternatives including 5 to 9 in Table 1 all meet the 35 threshold. 7 It

is interesting to know how subjects would trade off equality against efficiency in their

choices once the critical level is met. The results from the 35-threshold treatment serve the

purpose for this investigation.

In order to let subjects have some concrete idea about impacts of the two different

working environments in the real effort stage, we conduct a pilot with two rounds of the real

effort task before the allocation stage -- one in the environment with scales displayed while

the other in the environment without scales displayed. The order of the two rounds is

randomly assigned to each subject. To avoid the wealth effect, subjects are paid randomly

only in one of the two rounds. We also conduct the experiment as in Holt and Laury (2002)

to elicit subjects’ risk attitudes before the pilot. This elicitation is to control for subjects' risk

attitudes in our later analysis since they might play a role in the allocation stage. Again, to

avoid the wealth effect, subjects are paid only 50% of the time. Finally, according to their

choices and the number of tasks completed, subjects are always paid in the allocation stage

and the one round of the real effort stage.

Figure 2 illustrates the procedure of our experiment.

[Insert Figure 2 about here]

We conducted a total of 14 sessions of experiments in May and June, 2014. Each lasting

within an hour. A total of 202 National Taiwan University students were recruited via the

6We use 75 instead of 80 as the threshold so that subjects would not choose Alternative 9 (where both players receive 80) simply because 80 is mentioned so as to become the focal point.7 Remember that choosing Alternatives above 9 is not rational, and that none of subjects chosen Alternatives above 9 in our experiment.

9

Page 10: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

Taiwan Social Science Experimental Laboratory (TASSEL) online recruiting website.8 3 ESC

in the experiment is equal to one NT$. The average payment was NT$483 (approximate

US$16.32), ranging from NT$147 (US$ 4.97) to NT$925 (US$ 31.30).

A possible scenario

Here we provide a concrete scenario for our abstract experimental design.

Consider two families: one is rich (Player 1) while the other is poor (Player 2). The rich

leave some bequest to their children, whereas the poor leave none. How much bequest left by

the rich depends on how high the inheritance tax is imposed. The amount of the inheritance

tax collected will be transferred to children of the poor family. Table 1 documents all possible

distributions of outcomes. For example, if there is no inheritance tax, the amount of bequest

left will equal 240 (Alternative 1). However, if the inheritance tax imposed is high enough, the

amount of bequest left will equal 160, which is divided equally between rich and poor children

through transfer (Alternative 9). Previous studies elicit individual social preferences over the

imposed inheritance tax by sampling how subjects would make choices behind the veil of

ignorance when they face alternatives shown in Table 1.

Our experimental design does not elicit individual social preferences solely based on

Table 1 (the allocation stage). We further explore the plausible possibility that children

expectations of their life (the real effort stage) critically depend on the amount of initial capital

owned at the beginning of their career. Initial capital is called “income and wealth” in Rawls

(1971) and viewed by him as one of the chief primary social goods. It serves as an important

instrument for the fulfillment of the most rational long-term plan of children life. When the

distribution of primary social goods rather than simply the distribution of outcomes is

8 Two subjects’ data are dropped in our data analysis. A subject participates in this experiment twice. We drop the data of his second attendance, which is the session of the 75-threshold treatment. Another subject participating in the 35-threshold treatment uses right and left buttons on the keyboard to conduct slider tasks. We disable these buttons but he somehow enables them, and complete lots of tasks in both rounds. Since the primary social goods manipulation does not work for him, we drop his data.

10

Page 11: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

involved in Table 1, we elicit individual social preferences over the imposed inheritance tax

behind the veil of ignorance.

III. Results

We first compare results from treatments (35- and 75-threshold) with those from control

(0-threshold). We then consider an empirical model to investigate motivations underlying

subjects' choices

A. Treatments against control

The focus of our analysis is on the allocation stage, which involves the distribution of

primary social goods in the real effort stage. Table 2 reports the summary statistics of subjects'

choices, and Figure 3 plots the frequency distributions.

[Insert Table 2 and Figure 3 about here]

We first compare the results of the 75-threshold treatment with those of the 0-threshold

treatment, which serves as the benchmark or control. In order to meet the critical level of

resource allocation for both players, it is crucial to recognize that all distributional allocations

in Table 1 are satisfied in the 0 treatment, whereas only Alternative 9 is satisfied in the 75

treatment. When the threshold is 0, it is found that merely 14.29% (10/70) of subjects chose

Alternative 9. This percentage is not salient compared with many other chosen percentages, as

can be seen from Figure 3. Indeed, our result of 14.29% is comparable to the result of 13.7%

(18/131) in Schildberg-Hörisch (2010).

By contrast, the percentage of subjects who chose Alternative 9 jumps to 54.10% (33/61)

when the threshold is 75. This percentage represents the mode of the subject-choice

distribution and is clearly salient compared with any other chosen percentages, as can be

visibly seen from Figure 3. Table 3 reports that the rise in the percentage compared to the

control is statistically highly significant at p < 0.0001 (the p-value of one-tail test). Thus, a

11

Page 12: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

salient majority of subjects are significantly willing to sacrifice efficiency and act according to

the difference principle when: (i) monetary payoffs that they can obtain in the allocation stage

are tightly tied to the concept of primary social goods in the real effort stage (instruments for

future success in the subsequent slider task), and (ii) the maximin of resource allocation in the

allocation stage represents the critical level of redistribution of primary social goods needed

for meeting conditions of fair equality of opportunity in the real effort stage. Table 4 makes

comparison between the results of the two treatments using two standard tests: the Wilcoxon–

Mann–Whitney rank sum test yields Z = 3.53 (p<0.001), and the Epps-Singleton test gives

W2=34.33 (p<0.0001). The difference between the two treatments is highly significant. It is

interesting to note from Figure 4 that the frequency distribution of the 75 treatment

stochastically dominates that of the 0 treatment in the strict sense. This dominance implies that

subjects tend to choose more equally distributional allocations in the 75 treatment than the 0

treatment. There is no such dominance in the 35 treatment, as we show below.

[Insert Tables 3 and 4 about here]

[Insert Figure 4 about here]

We next compare the results of the 35-threshold treatment with those of the 0-threshold

treatment, which again serves as the benchmark or control. To meet the critical level of

resource allocation for both players in the 35 treatment, Alternatives equal to or above 5 in

Table 1 are all satisfied. Table 4 reports that both the Wilcoxon–Mann–Whitney test (Z = 0.39

and p=0.6940) and the Epps-Singleton test (W2=2.13 and p=0.7117) indicate no significant

difference in frequency distribution between the 35 treatment and the 0 treatment.

Nevertheless, careful examination of the data reveals some important information. Table 2

reports that while the proportion of subjects who chose Alternatives 1-4 is 32.86% in the 0

treatment, it reduces to 27.54% in the 35 treatment. Since the proportion of subjects who

chose Alternatives 7-9 is also decreased as noted below, this implies that, as the threshold level

12

Page 13: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

raises from 0 to 35, the decrease in the proportion of subjects who chose Alternatives 1-4 must

shift to contribute to the increase in the proportion of subjects who chose Alternative 5-6. This

result is consistent with our previous finding: subjects are more willing to sacrifice efficiency

when monetary payoffs that they can obtain in the allocation stage are associated with the

availability of “reasonably favorable” primary social goods in the real effort stage.

A new finding, which is absent previously, is that the proportion of subjects who chose

Alternatives 7-9 is decreased from 44.29% in the 0 treatment to 34.78% in the 35 treatment.

Since the proportion of subjects who chose Alternatives 1-4 is also decreased as noted above,

this implies that, as the threshold level raises from 0 to 35, the decrease in the proportion of

subjects who chose Alternatives 7-9 must shift to contribute to the increase in the proportion

of subjects who chose Alternative 5-6. This kind of shift in subjects' choices from Alternatives

7-9 to 5-6 can be ascribed to the plausible interpretation that once fair equality of opportunity

for future success is guaranteed, subjects become more willing to trade off equality for

efficiency.

Subjects who chose Alternatives 5-6 increase from 22.86% to 37.68% as the threshold

level raises from 0 to 35. Table 3 reports that this increase is significant with p=0.0286. It is of

no surprise to find that the 14.82 percentage-point increase for Alternatives 5-6 is almost equal

to the sum of the 5.32 percentage-point decrease for Alternatives 1-4 plus the 9.51 percentage-

point decrease for Alternatives 7-9. Suppose our samples are representative of the population.

Then, as the threshold level raises from 0 to 35, the overall picture revealed indicates that

those who used to emphasize efficiency in the absence of primary social goods (i.e., those who

chose Alternatives 1-4 in the 0 treatment) become more willing to place priority on equality,

while those who used to emphasize equality in the absence of primary social goods (i.e., those

who chose Alternatives 7-9 in the 0 treatment) become more willing to sacrifice equality for

efficiency. In fact, Figure 3 shows that Alternative 5, which is the least numbered alternative

13

Page 14: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

that meets the 35 threshold, becomes the focal point and is the mode in the 35-threshold

treatment.

To sum up, our experiment yields three main results:

1. When monetary payoffs that subjects can obtain in the allocation stage have little to do

with the availability of “reasonably favorable” primary social goods in the real effort stage

(the 0-threshold treatment), the proportion of subjects whose social preferences obey the

Rawlsian difference principle is not salient at all and lower than 15%. This result is

comparable with previous experimental findings in the absence of the role for primary social

goods

2. When (i) monetary payoffs that subjects can obtain in the allocation stage are tightly

tied to the concept of primary social goods in the real effort stage, and (ii) the maximin of

resource allocation in the allocation stage represents the critical level of redistribution of

primary social goods needed for meeting conditions of fair equality of opportunity in the real

effort stage (the 75-threshold treatment), a salient majority of subjects are significantly willing

to sacrifice efficiency and act in accordance with the Rawlsian difference principle.

3. Once the availability of “reasonably favorable” primary social goods or the equality of

opportunity for future success is guaranteed (the 35-threshold treatment), subjects place less

priority on distributional equality and are more willing to trade off equality for efficiency.

On the specialty of the 75-threshold

Our experimental design considers three thresholds, 0, 35 and 75 in the allocation stage.

Once the thresholds are met in our experiment, the distribution of primary social goods can

generate “reasonably favorable circumstances” and meet “conditions of fair equality of

opportunity” for subjects in the real effort stage. A question remains unanswered: which

threshold is more realistic? Consider our concrete scenario in which primal social goods are

identified with “income and wealth.” In this context, the distribution of monetary payoffs in

14

Page 15: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

the allocation stage can be viewed essentially the same as the distribution of primary social

goods in the real effort stage. As such, it seems that the 75-threshold is the only threshold out

of three that is really capable of generating “reasonably favorable circumstances” and meeting

“conditions of fair equality of opportunity” for subjects in the real effort stage. The assertion is

logical in view of Rawls's reasoning that every rational man would “prefer more primary

social goods” and that these goods “normally have a use whatever a person’s rational plan of

life.” This suggests the specialty of the 75-thredhold in our experiment, and explains why the

Ralwsian difference principle is uniquely associated with the maxmin criterion.

B. An empirical model

To better understand motivations underlying subjects' choices in the allocation stage, we

estimate a conditional logit model. Our estimation use separate data from different treatments,

not pooled data from all treatments. As will be seen, motivations underlying subjects' choices

differ qualitatively across treatments. The model is built on Engelmann and Strobel (2004)

with the important modification of: (i) incorporating the impact of primary social goods, and

(ii) focusing on the element of trading off between equality and efficiency as in our

experiment and so concerns other than this element such as inequality aversion in Fehr and

Schmidt (1999) and Bolton and Ockenfels (2000) are not considered.

Let

i: index of subjects;

j: Alternatives in the allocation stage with j∈{1,2,3 ,. . . ,9};

k: threshold levels with k∈ {0 , 35 ,75 };

V ij : utility representation of subject i's social preferences over Alternative j.

The conditional logit model specifies the probability of subject i's choosing Alternative j as

15

Page 16: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

pij=exp(V ij )

∑ j=1

9exp(V ij )

where V ij=β1⋅DPij+β2⋅EQij+β3⋅EFij+ β4⋅EU ij+uij , in which the right-hand-side

variables are defined as follows:

(1) DPij : subjects behave in the sense of respecting the threshold of resource allocation such

that

(i) when k=0, DPij=1 all the time;

(ii) when k=35, DPij=1 if j∈{5,6,7,8,9}; DPij=0 otherwise;

(iii) when k=75, DPij=1 if j=9 ; DPij=0 otherwise.

(2) EQij : subjects chose the most equal allocation such that

when k∈ {0 , 35}, EQij=1 if j=9 ; EQij=0 otherwise.

(3) EFij : a measure of efficiency with

EFij=P 1ij+P 2ij , where P 1ij and P 2ij are subject i's two equally likely payoffs in choosing

Alternative j in the allocation stage.

(4) EU ij : subjects behave according to the expected utility hypothesis, that is, maximizing

total payoffs from both the allocation stage and the real effort stage with

EU ij=0 .5⋅(P 1ij+30⋅Taskij )

1−γ i

1−γi+0 . 5⋅

( P 2ij+30⋅Task ij)1−γ i

1−γ i

16

Page 17: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

where γi is subject i's coefficient of relative risk aversion elicited in accordance with the

experiment of Holt and Laury (2002), Task ij is the number of tasks completed by subject i in

one of the first two rounds slider tasks, dependent on whether she/he will be able to see

numerical scales. Specifically, if DPij =1 (0) , Task ij is the number of tasks complete in the

round where numerical scales can (not) be seen. Recall that subjects earn 30 ESC for each

successful task.

[Insert Table 5 about here]

As in Engelmann and Strobel (2004), we estimate the preferences of an “average

subject.” Table 5 reports the results. When there is no threshold as in the 0 treatment, the

expected utility hypothesis features significantly in explaining subjects' choices as indicated

by the variable EU in Table 5. This implies that subjects behaved by trading off equality

against efficiency or vice versa according to the expected utility hypothesis when primary

social goods are not involved.

By contrast, the expected utility hypothesis represented by the variable EU in Table 5

does not have bites in explaining subjects’ choices in the 35- and 75-threshold treatments,

especially in the case of the 75-threshold treatment. On the other hand, the presence of

thresholds captured by the variable DP in Table 5 explains subjects' choices highly

significantly in both treatments. Moreover, in terms of odds ratio, DP exerts large positive

impact in both treatments, especially in the case of the 75-threshold treatment. The presence of

primary social goods altered subjects’ social preferences over the distribution of payoffs

qualitatively in a significant way.

The efficiency measure represented by the variable EF in Table 5 features significantly

in both the 0- and the 35-threshold treatments. This is in contrast to the finding that the

17

Page 18: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

efficiency measure is not a critical motive in the 75-threshold treatment. This result suggests

the priority of equality over efficiency as argued by Rawls (1971) when the critical level of

redistribution of primary social goods equals the maximin of distributional allocations as in

the 75-treshold treatment.

The variable EQ represents subjects who chose the most equal allocation, Alternative 9,

regardless of variations in the threshold. However, EQ in Table 5 does not feature importantly

in both the 0- and the 35-threshold treatment, especially in the case of the 0-thresold treatment.

This result is not surprising in view of the significance of the efficiency measure EF in both

treatments -- the significance of EF simply means that subjects would not behave according

to the equality criterion alone.

Overall, the results here complement our previous findings, in support of: (i) the presence

of primary social goods alters subjects' social preferences over the distribution of payoffs

qualitatively, and (ii) the priority of equality over efficiency features significantly in the 75-

threshold treatment.

IV. Conclusion

While most economists view the relationship between equality and efficiency as a

tradeoff or conflict, Rawls (1971) saw it differently according to his proposed difference

principle: equality has priority over efficiency in essence. Previous experimental studies lend

little support to the importance of the difference principle -- subjects whose social

preferences obey the difference principle represent only a small minority in the sample. This

paper finds a much stronger support -- a salient majority of subjects whose social preferences

obey the difference principle. A key to our departure from previous studies lies in that

allocating monetary payoffs between subjects in our experimental design embodies not

18

Page 19: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

simply choosing the distribution of payoffs but more importantly the distribution of Rawls's

so-called “primary social goods,” which serve as instruments critical to the fulfillment of

people's rational desire.

The other important finding of our experiment is that once access to primary social goods

is under “reasonably favorable circumstances,” subjects place less priority on distributional

equality and are more willing to trade off equality for efficiency.

References

Beckman, Steven, R., Formby, John, P., Smith, W., James and Buhong, Zheng. 2002. “Envy,

malice and Pareto efficiency: an experimental examination.” Social Choice and Welfare, 19

(2): 349–367.

Bolton, Gary E. and Axel Ockenfels. 2000. “ERC -- a theory of equity, reciprocity, and

competition.” American Economic Review, 90, 166-193.

Carlsson, Fredrik, Gupta, Gautam and Olof Johansson-Stenman. 2003. “Choosing from behind

a veil of ignorance in India.” Applied Economics Letters, 10: 825-827.

Charness, Gary and Matthew Rabin. 2002. “Understanding social preferences with simple

tests.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117(3): 817-869.

Engelmann, Dirk and Martin Strobel. 2004. “Inequality Aversion, Efficiency and Maximin

Preferences in Simple Distribution Experiments.” American Economic Review, 94: 857-

869.

Fehr, Ernst, and Klaus M. Schmidt. 1999. “A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation.

” Quarterly Journal of Economics 114, 817-868.

Gerber, Anke, Nicklisch, Andreas and Stefan Voigt. 2013. “Strategic choices for redistribution

and the veil of ignorance: theory and experimental evidence.” working paper.

Gill, David and Victoria Prowse. 2012. “A Structural Analysis of Disappointment Aversion in

a Real Effort Competition.” American Economic Review, 102(1): 469-503.

Holt, Charles A. and Susan K. Laury. 2002. “Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects.” American

19

Page 20: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

Economic Review, 92(5): 1644-1655.

Johannesson, Magnus and ULF-G Gerdtham. 1995. “A pilot test of using the veil of ignorance

approach to estimate a social welfare function for income.” Applied Economics Letters, 2:

400-402.

Johansson-Stenman, Olof, Carlsson, Fredrik and Dinky Daruvala. 2002. “Measuring future

grandparents’ preferences for equality and relative standing.” The Economic Journal, 112:

362-383.

Konow, James. 2009. “Is fairness in the eye of the beholder? An impartial spectator analysis of

justice.” Social Choice and Welfare, 33: 101-127.

Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press,

Cambridge, Massachusetts.

Schildberg-Hörisch, Hannah. 2010. “Is the veil of ignorance only a concept about risk? An

experiment.” Journal of Public Economics, 94: 1062-1066.

Traub, Stefan, Christian Seidl, Ulrich Schmidt and Maria V. Levati. 2005. “Friedman, Harsnyi,

Rawls, Boulding – or somebody else? An experimental investigation of distributive

justice.” Social Choice and Welfare, 24: 283-309.

20

Page 21: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

Table 1. Possible distributional allocations in the allocation stage

Alternatives 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13

Player 1 240 220 200 180 160 140 120 100 80 60 40 20 0

Player 2 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100 110 120

Table 2. Summary statistics of subjects' choices in the allocation stage

75-threshold treatment

Alternatives Frequency Percentage Accumulation12

92

14.753.28

14.7518.03

34

13

1.644.92

19.6724.59

56

14

1.646.56

26.2332.75

789

2633

3.289.8454.10

36.0745.09100.00

Total 61 100.00

0-threshold treatment

Alternatives Frequency Percentage Accumulation12

112

15.712.86

15.7118.57

34

28

2.8611.43

21.4332.86

56

88

11.4311.43

44.2955.71

789

13810

18.5711.4314.29

74.2985.71100.00

Total 70 100.00

21

Page 22: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

35-threshold treatment

Alternatives Frequency Percentage Accumulation12

102

14.492.90

14.4917.39

34

25

2.907.25

20.2927.54

56

1511

21.7415.94

49.2865.22

789

969

13.048.7013.04

78.2686.96100.00

Total 69 100.00

Table 3. Tests of the effect of primal social goods

Alternative 9 Alternatives 5-6

0 Treatment 10/70

(14.29%)16/70

(22.86%)35 Treatment 26/69

(37.68%)75 Treatment 33/61

(54.1%)

Tests of

differences

z = 4.84

p = 0.0000

z = 1.90

p = 0.0286

Table 4. Tests of differences in frequency distributions

Choice on average

0 Treatment 5.51 5.51

35 Treatment 5.46

75 Treatment 6.82

22

Page 23: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

Wilcoxon-Mann-Whitney Z = 3.53

p = 0.0004

Z = 0.39

p = 0.6940

Epps-Singleton W2=34.33

p = 0.0000

W2= 2.13

p = 0.7117

Table 5. Results for the conditional logit model

Treatment

75 0 35

Odds ratio p-value Odds ratio p-value Odds ratio p-value

11.31 <0.0017.36 <0.001

1.00 0.9601.02 0.012 1.00 0.275

1.01 0.4580.98 0.024 1.03 0.013

0.96 0.930 1.82 0.253

23

Page 24: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

24

Page 25: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

blank

Panel a. Scales displayed Panel b. No scales displayed

Figure 1. Two different working environments in the real effort stage

Figure 2. Experimental procedure

25

Elicit risk attitude(paid 50% of the time)

Two rounds of the pilot slider task (paid randomly one of two rounds)

Allocating stage (always paid)

One round of the slider task (always paid)

blank

Page 26: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

26

020

4060

Per

cent

1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9Distribution

75-threshold treatment (n=61)

020

4060

Per

cent

1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9Distribution

0-threshold treatment (n=70)

Page 27: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

Figure 3. Frequency distributions of subjects’ choices

Figure

4.

27

020

4060

Per

cent

1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9Distribution

35-threshold treatment (n=69)

Page 28: Justice: What Money Can Buy - Sites@Duke | …sites.duke.edu/2014bmp/files/2014/10/Teng_Wang_Yang.docx · Web viewHe proposed the difference principle (popularly known as the maximin

Cumulative distributions of subjects’ choices

28