inductive inference and paradigms - langara college · 2016-11-25 · • an inductively strong...

54
Inductive Inference and Paradigms Which theory is best supported by the evidence? the evidence? 1

Upload: others

Post on 30-May-2020

3 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Inductive Inference and Paradigms

Which theory is best supported by the evidence?the evidence?

1

Page 2: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Inductive InferenceInductive Inference

• The basic format is:

H predicts E E‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐H

H h h i d l hH = some hypothesis, model, theoryE = some evidence, data, observation

2

Page 3: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• Of course more premises are needed to makeOf course more premises are needed to make the inference reasonable, things like:

– “H is a plausible theory”

“O h h i h di E i l ibl ”– “Other theories that predict E are implausible”

3

Page 4: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Induction and PredictionInduction and Prediction

• In general, induction is the reverse ofIn general, induction is the reverse of prediction.  We inductively infer a hypothesis from which the data can be predicted.

4

Page 5: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• E gE.g.

1 (This valley was formed by a glacier) predicts (This valley is U shaped)1. (This valley was formed by a glacier) predicts (This valley is U‐shaped)

2.  This valley is observed to be U‐shaped

‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐

This valley was formed by a glacier

5

Page 6: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

hypothesis

evidence

6

Page 7: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

H predicts E

E

‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐

H

Question:  Is this a valid inference?  

(I.e. is the conclusion guaranteed to be true, given the premises?)

7

Page 8: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• No.  It’s an invalid argument.  (Known to logicians as “affirming the consequent”.)

• In an inductive inference the conclusion isn’t guaranteed, or certain, even if all the premises are true.  It would be possible to have ppremises that are all true, and a false conclusion.  The data may be entirely correct, y y ,and yet the hypothesis is wrong.

8

Page 9: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• Maybe God carved that valley directly, thousands of years ago.  It’s U‐shaped because God happens to like the look of it.

• Or maybe it was formed by some bizarre physical process that no one has evenphysical process that no one has even imagined yet.

• Can we be sure something like this isn’t true?

9

Page 10: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Many possible causes• For any observed data, we can imagine many possible 

causes of it.• If (say) three hypothesis all predict the observed data, then 

which hypothesis do you (inductively) infer from the data?

10

Page 11: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Example: Why did the dinosaurs die out?

Data:  in Cretaceous rocks, there are dinosaur fossils.  In Tertiary rocks (the next layer up) there are no dinosaurTertiary rocks (the next layer up) there are no dinosaur fossils.

H th i 1 A t id i t l di t d t l d bl kiHypothesis 1:  Asteroid impact, leading to dust cloud blocking the sun, massive fireball reducing oxygen levels, etc.

11

Page 12: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Hypothesis 2:  Volcanic Activity.  The Deccan Traps formed at the end of the Cretaceous period, erupting for thousands of years, and releasing 

i th t l d th li tpoisonous gases that cooled the climate.

12

Page 13: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Hypothesis 3 …

13

Page 14: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• The fact that there are many possibleThe fact that there are many possible hypotheses, to explain a given set of data, doesn’t mean that they’re all equally gooddoesn t mean that they re all equally good.

S h h h k• Some hypotheses are strong, others weak, given the data available.

14

Page 15: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

“Inductively Strong”Inductively Strong

• An inductively strong argument is one whoseAn inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises.

• In other words, someone who believes the i ( i h i ) h b li hpremises (with certainty) ought to believe the 

conclusion to a high degree (though perhaps i h inot with certainty.

15

Page 16: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

“Deductively Valid”Deductively Valid

• The extreme case of an inductively strong argumentThe extreme case of an inductively strong argument is where the conclusion is certain, given the premises.  Such an argument is said to be “deductively valid”, or just “valid”.

• E.g.  All Canadian people are polite

Don Cherry is a Canadian person

‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐

Don Cherry is politey p

16

Page 17: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

ExamplesExamples

(i) Eric has been convicted of 4 separate(i) Eric has been convicted of 4 separate murders‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐Eric has killed someone.

(ii) Rob is a member of Canada’s armed forces‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐Rob has shot and killed someone.

17

Page 18: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

(iii) All metals conduct electricity but mercury(iii) All metals conduct electricity, but mercury doesn’t conduct electricity.  So mercury isn’t a metalisn t a metal.

(i ) Mik l d hi i h k i hi(iv) Mike leads his varsity hockey team in hits and penalty minutes, so he must be pretty 

htough. 

(v) Kim is good at presenting arguments, so she must be a lawyer.y

18

Page 19: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

“Background Knowledge”Background Knowledge

• Notice how in evaluating the strength of anNotice how, in evaluating the strength of an inductive inference, we have to use our background knowledgebackground knowledge.

Thi i id bl I hi k (C• This is pretty unavoidable, I think.  (Can you think of any exceptions?)

19

Page 20: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Michael Gershon, Columbia University, talking about the hypothesis that the MMR vaccine causes autismhypothesis that the MMR vaccine causes autism.

“From the point of view of the physiology of the bowel, blood circulation p p y gy ,and the brain, this theory of the link between MMR and autism is implausible. For the theory to be correct a series of miracles would have to occur.

The liver would have to forget to function as a filter. It normally removes foreign molecules from the blood. Autistic patients, however, are notforeign molecules from the blood. Autistic patients, however, are not jaundiced so there's no reason to suspect liver failure. The blood‐brain barrier, which is impermeable to large molecules, would have to part, like the Red Sea did for Moses and the Israelites, to let toxins from the bowel into the brain. Once there they'd have to do something to the human brain that they've never even been demonstrated to do in animals.”

20

Page 21: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

4. Jim offers the following argument that wearing a bike helmet reduces the likelihood of a fatal accident.reduces the likelihood of a fatal accident.

“In this city, we have found that 40% of cyclists wear helmets while riding their bikes. But, in all cases where cyclists have been killed while riding, only 10% of them were wearing helmets at the time So10% of them were wearing helmets at the time. So, clearly, wearing a helmet while riding a bike significantly reduces the chance of being killed.”

In evaluating the inductive strength of this argument, it is useful to imagine other hypotheses that would explain theuseful to imagine other hypotheses that would explain the same data.  Write down (one or two) alternative explanations of this evidence.

21

Page 22: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Hypothesis 1:  Wearing a bicycle helmet protects the head from injury, and so reduces the chance of being killed in a bike accident.

Hypothesis 2:  Some people are more cautious than th C ti l lik l tothers.  Cautious people are more likely to wear 

helmets, and also more likely to ride carefully, on less busy streets, obey traffic laws, etc., leading toless busy streets, obey traffic laws, etc., leading to a lower chance of death.

• In assessing which of these explanations is the best, what background ideas come into play?

22

Page 23: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Relevant background beliefsRelevant background beliefs

• Putting a layer of foam around the head ought to cushion it from impacts, reducing brain damage.

• Some people are more cautious than others.Some people are more cautious than others.

• Cautious people are more likely to wear helmets

• Cautious people are less likely to ride on busy streets.

• Serious accidents are more likely to occur on busy streets.

(Etc )(Etc.)

23

Page 24: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Example:  The Big Bang Theory

• In 1916 Albert Einstein published a theory of gravity called General Relativity (GR) In thisgravity called General Relativity (GR).  In this theory space‐time and matter are tied together into a single dynamical system.g y y

• The universe, according to GR, can be pictured as a balloon, with the skin of the balloon representing space itself.

24

Page 25: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

“The Cosmological Constant”The Cosmological Constant

• One puzzle for GR was why the whole universeOne puzzle for GR was why the whole universe doesn’t collapse in on itself, under its own gravity.

• In order to keep the universe in a steady stateIn order to keep the universe in a steady state, Einstein added a force of repulsion to his equations, known as the ‘cosmological constant’.equations, known as the  cosmological constant .

25

Page 26: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

The Big Bang Theoryg g y

• In 1927, however,, another solution to the problem was spotted by Georges Lemaître a physicist and Catholicspotted by Georges Lemaître, a physicist and Catholic priest.

L ît d th t th i idl• Lemaître proposed that the universe was rapidly expanding, so that its outward momentum prevented it from collapsing inwards.

• One obvious consequence of an expanding universe was that the universe must have been smaller and smaller the f th b k i ti At d fi it i t i thfurther back in time you go.  At some definite point in the past, all matter (and space itself) was compressed into a tiny volume.

26

Page 27: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Relevant background ideasRelevant background ideas

• Lemaître’s theory was scientific.  It was a e a t e s t eo y as sc e t c. t as amathematical solution to Einstein’s “field equations” of GR.  It made predictions (e.g. 

l h f f d l ) hconcerning Doppler shifts of distant galaxies) that were later observed.B t h i i t i iti ll l t t t• But some physicists were initially reluctant to accept the Big Bang model, on the grounds that it smelled of religion. The idea of a beginning tosmelled of religion.  The idea of a beginning to time itself suggested the need for something outside the physical universe to create it.

27

Page 28: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Relevant background ideasRelevant background ideas

• By the mid 1960s the Big Bang theory gainedBy the mid 1960s the Big Bang theory gained mainstream acceptance, thanks to a number of supporting observations.

• Prior to those observations, however, religiousPrior to those observations, however, religious scientists tended to find the theory more plausible than secular scientists did.  Secular scientists preferred to think that the universe was eternal, with no beginning.

28

Page 29: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

E gE.g.“While many of us may be OK with the idea of the big bang simply starting everything, physicists, including H ki t d t h f i iHawking, tend to shy away from cosmic genesis. 

“A point of creation would be a place where scienceA point of creation would be a place where science broke down. One would have to appeal to religion and the hand of God”,

Hawking told the meeting, at the University of Cambridge, in a pre‐recorded speech.”

(New Scientist, “Why physicists can’t avoid a creation event”, January 2012.)event , January 2012.)

29

Page 30: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Who’s the thief?Who s the thief?

30

Page 31: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

ParadigmsParadigms

• It looks like Hazel since she’s the only personIt looks like Hazel, since she s the only person who was present on every day when money went missing (On March 5 Hazel didn’t stealwent missing.  (On March 5 Hazel didn t steal, for some unknown reason.)

• But here we’re assuming that there’s just one hi f Wh if ( ) lthief.  What if two (or more) people are working together?  Any other hypotheses?

31

Page 32: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

ParadigmsParadigms

• If we assume that there are two thieves thenIf we assume that there are two thieves, then a decent hypothesis is that Jan and Dan are working together and (rather cleverly) tryingworking together, and (rather cleverly) trying to make it look as if Hazel is the thief!

• In general, a scientific hypothesis is grounded f k f iupon some framework of assumptions, or 

paradigm.

32

Page 33: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

The geocentric paradigmThe geocentric paradigm

• Suppose we try to construct a universe thatSuppose we try to construct a universe that explains the known facts of astronomy.  We need a paradigm to begin with Let’s supposeneed a paradigm to begin with.  Let s suppose that the earth is stationary, and that the planets are all orbiting the earth Supposeplanets are all orbiting the earth.  Suppose further that we order the planets by their apparent speedapparent speed.

• What kind of universe do we get?

33

Page 34: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• We get something like Ptolemy’s universe inWe get something like Ptolemy s universe, in its basic structure.  (Remember that Ptolemy’s actual model was quite complicated withactual model was quite complicated, with minor epicyles, eccentric orbits and equants.)

34

Page 35: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• We’ve seen that scientific inferences are inductive, in the sense that the premises (empirical data) do not guarantee that the ( p ) gconclusion is true.  More precisely, the conclusion offers one possible explanation of p pthe data, perhaps the best explanation, but not the only possible explanation.y p p

• Also, what one judges to the best explanation of the data depends on the paradigm that oneof the data depends on the paradigm that one is working in.

35

Page 36: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Inductive InferenceInductive Inference

• Hence inductive inference might beHence inductive inference might be represented as follows:

H predicts EEEParadigm‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐‐H

36

Page 37: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

What is a paradigm?What is a paradigm?

• The term is used rather loosely, with a variety of meanings y, y g(even by Kuhn himself).  The following give the basic idea. A paradigm provides: 

‐‐ a framework within which specific hypotheses can be constructed.

‐‐ a basic picture of the thing being investigated

‐‐ a set of methods and tools for the investigation

37

Page 38: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• A paradigm achieves these things largelyA paradigm achieves these things largely through a “canon” of accepted solutions to problems In trying to solve a new problemproblems.  In trying to solve a new problem (within a paradigm) researchers try to extend the methods that have been used successfullythe methods that have been used successfully in the past.

38

Page 39: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

ExamplesExamples

• The Ptolemaic paradigm for map‐making includedThe Ptolemaic paradigm for map making included the basic assumption of a spherical earth.  It also included methods for determining the longitude and latitude of a place.

• The paradigm of oxygen chemistry includes the basic picture that metals are elements, that metal ores are compounds of metals with oxygen, etc.  It includes the use of an accurate balance to weigh thethe use of an accurate balance to weigh the reactants and products of a reaction, and the use of a pneumatic trough.a pneumatic trough.

39

Page 40: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• The Copernican paradigm for astronomyThe Copernican paradigm for astronomy includes the idea that the sun is stationary, and the earth spins on its axis and orbits theand the earth spins on its axis and orbits the earth.

• The telescope became (in the hands of• The telescope became (in the hands of Galileo) a major tool.

40

Page 41: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

(Darwinian) evolution is a paradigm?(Darwinian) evolution is a paradigm?

• Olivia Judson New York Times July 15 2008:Olivia Judson, New York Times, July 15, 2008:

“I’d lik t b li h th i idi t D i i“I’d like to abolish the insidious terms Darwinism, Darwinist and Darwinian. They suggest a false narrowness to the field of modern evolutionarynarrowness to the field of modern evolutionary biology, as though it was the brainchild of a single person 150 years ago, rather than a vast, complex and p y g , , pevolving subject to which many other great figures have contributed.”

41

Page 42: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

“Although several of his ideas — natural andAlthough several of his ideas natural and sexual selection among them — remain cornerstones of modern evolutionary biology, y gythe field as a whole has been transformed.”

“For although natural selection is the only creative force in evolution — the only one that can produce complex structures such as wings and eyes — it is not the only force that affects

hi h ill d d hi h illwhich genes will spread, and which will vanish.”

42

Page 43: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• Judson is right that evolutionary biology has come aJudson is right that evolutionary biology has come a long way since Darwin.  Also, natural selection isn’t the only driver of evolutionary change.  (There is also drift, symbiogenesis, lateral gene transfer, etc.)

• But (unlike e.g. Newtonian physics) some of Darwin’s core ideas about evolution are still accepted by most biologists.

bi l i i i h• Moreover, some biologists are now questioning the importance of natural selection as a mechanism for evolution These biologists are not questioningevolution.  These biologists are not questioning ‘evolution’, so we need some separate term for what they’re questioning.y q g

43

Page 44: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

E.g James Shapiro’s “Third Way” groupE.g James Shapiro s  Third Way  group

44

Page 45: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• People are in fact using “Darwinism” to refer p gto any theory of evolution (contemporary or otherwise) whose main mechanism is natural )selection, operating on random variation.

• In particular “Darwinism” refers to the ideaIn particular,  Darwinism  refers to the idea that (among the mechanisms of evolution) natural selection is “creative” as Judson putsnatural selection is  creative , as Judson puts it.  “…natural selection is the only [force] that can produce complex structures such as wingscan produce complex structures such as wings and eyes”.  (Selection does not merely prune.)

45

Page 46: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• Used in this way, “Darwinism” is better seen y,as a paradigm rather than a hypothesis, as it is a “broad tent” that will include many different yspecific hypotheses.  It is a general approach to evolutionary biology, rather than a specific y gy, phypothesis.

• If at some point in the future naturalIf, at some point in the future, natural selection is seen as having only a minor role in evolution (e g as being conservative ratherevolution (e.g. as being conservative rather than creative) this would certainly count as a major “paradigm shift” in Kuhn’s sensemajor  paradigm shift , in Kuhn s sense.

46

Page 47: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

“Irrelevant Details”Irrelevant Details

• Notice how on the Duck paradigm the PCINotice how, on the Duck paradigm, the PCI was an irrelevant detail.  Asking “What is the PCI for?” is a mistake It’s a bad questionPCI for?  is a mistake.  It s a bad question.

• Today, “Why are there 8 planets?” is a bad question There’s no particular reason whyquestion.  There s no particular reason why there are 8 planets.  There just are.  It doesn’t “call for an explanation”call for an explanation .

47

Page 48: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• Problem for Kepler: How do you explain that h l l i h h bi l ithere are exactly 6 planets, with the orbital sizes they have?

48

Page 49: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Kepler’sexplanation!explanation!

A Platonic solid is a regular, convexpolyhedron withp ycongruent faces ofregular polygonsand the same number f f iof faces meeting 

at each vertex. There are only 5 of these.

49

Page 50: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Another irrelevant detail? Why do theAnother irrelevant detail?  Why do the planets all go the same way?

• Descartes considered this very significant, a vital clue to understanding themechanics of planetaryclue to understanding the mechanics of planetary motion.

• He explained it with his “vortex” theory, that each star (including the sun) drives the matter ( g )around it into a swirling vortex.  This vortex pushes the planets around their orbits.

50

Page 51: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Descartes’ Vortex TheoryDescartes  Vortex Theory

51

Page 52: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

• Descartes’ rival, Isaac Newton, had a differentDescartes  rival, Isaac Newton, had a different theory of why the planets move the way they do.  His theory held that the planets are moving through empty space, under the influence of the sun’s gravity.  There is no 

d h ’ h h lvortex, and there’s no reason why the planets all move in the same direction.  They just do.

• It doesn’t call for a mechanical explanation, b t hi t i l (It i f h thbut a historical one.  (It arises from how the solar system was formed.)

52

Page 53: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

The Problem of InductionThe Problem of Induction

• The reliance of inductive inferences on e e a ce o duct e e e ces obackground assumptions, or a “paradigm”, shows that there is no possibility of deriving a h h f d l lhypothesis from data, using pure logical inference.I th b f b k d ti l i• In the absence of background assumptions, logic won’t even tell us that a hypothesis is probablytrue, given the known data.true, given the known data.

• (E.g. Copernicus and Kepler assumed that the universe will be simple, rational, economical, etc.)p , , , )

53

Page 54: Inductive Inference and Paradigms - Langara College · 2016-11-25 · • An inductively strong argument is one whose conclusion is probable, given the premises. • In other words,

Empiricism and InductionEmpiricism and Induction

• Some philosophers (known as empiricists) believeSome philosophers (known as empiricists) believe that all our knowledge comes from experience.

• In that case it seems that Copernicus and KeplerIn that case, it seems that Copernicus and Keplercould not know that the universe will be simple, or that mathematical harmony is a guide to truth.or that mathematical harmony is a guide to truth.

• Hence (David Hume argued for example) the inferences of Copernicus and Kepler are notinferences of Copernicus and Kepler are not rationally justified!

54