i is for idea maimon, kant, and deleuze’s ontology of difference

Upload: roman-ruiz

Post on 04-Jun-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    1/11

    1

    I is for Idea: Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    Beth Lord [email protected]

    Draft conference paper. Please do not cite or circulate without authors permission.

    In chapter 4 of Difference and Repetition , Deleuze says that the fundamental

    reformulation of Kants Critique, and the overcoming of the Kantian duality

    between concept and intuition, are accomplished by the post-Kantian philosopher

    Solomon Maimon. 1 In order to understand Deleuzes complex relation to Kant, we

    must look at how Deleuze draws on Maimon. I will argue that Deleuzes

    transcendental empiricism, in attempting to overcome the failure of transcendental

    idealism to account for the genesis of beings, draws extensively on Maimon.

    However, Deleuze finds insufficient resources in Maimon to account for the

    generation of beings from difference . Curiously, it is in Kant that Deleuze finds these

    resources, and finds a source for an ontology of difference.

    Maimon was an outsider to Enlightenment circles, a self-taught philosopher

    without academic or social credentials. An eastern European Jew from an

    impoverished background, he read Spinoza, Hume, and Kant, and, against enormous

    odds, became a respected contributor to philosophical debates. His major work, the

    Versuch ber Transcendentalphilosophie , he sent to Kant in 1789, whereupon Kant

    declared that Maimon was his best and most profound critic. Maimons Versuch is a

    long and obscure criticism of Kants Critique of Pure Reason . Among other things,

    Maimon argues that given Kants strict separation of understanding from sensibility,

    the conceptual products of understanding cannot be directly applied to passively

    received intuitions. The understanding, trapped amongst its concepts, accesses only

    the object in general which it itself constructs, while the material that is given to

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    2/11

    2

    intuition is produced mysteriously. So on Kants account, there are two forces

    producing being one stemming from understanding, the other mysteriously

    emanating from nature that can find no way of meeting. Maimon concludes that a

    Kantian cannot account for real being. The only solution, on Maimons view, is to

    merge these two streams of production, such that the productivity of understanding is

    identical with the productivity of the given. In other words, given objects are not just

    received by the subject, but actively produced by it.

    Maimon is an idealist in a much stronger sense than Kant is. But Maimon also

    claims to be a transcendental philosopher in a stronger sense than Kant, because of his

    concern to go beyond conditions of possible experience to get at the conditions of

    the being of intuitions. Maimon finds these conditions in the human understanding,

    which he takes to be a finite mode of an infinite understanding. Briefly, Maimon

    accounts for the generation of objects of intuition by positing that the infinite

    understanding contains rules for the generation of qualities. These rules are

    differentials: the relations of difference that a specific qualitative tendency has to all

    the others. So the rule for producing this specific redness is its differential relation

    to every other quality. The finite understanding integrates, or generates, qualities

    from differentials, not as objects, but as intensities that exist as ideas of

    understanding. That is, ideas of understanding are spun out from differentials, as

    infinitely flowing intensities that cannot be experienced or conceptually thought. It is

    up to the imagination to delimit and fix these intensities, and to represent them in

    sensibility. In sensibility we have a partial view of the intensities of the idea, of which

    sensible intuitions are contractions. This is how sensible intuitions are generated

    from differentials. Maimon accuses Kant of ignoring the question of the generation of

    the sensible, and looking only at how sensible objects can be related to concepts that

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    3/11

    3

    are entirely external to them. Where Kant accounts only for what can be represented

    in the sensible, Maimon accounts for the being of the sensible. 2

    Deleuzes transcendental empiricism draws on Maimons genetic account of

    being. Like Maimon, Deleuze holds that if transcendental philosophy concerns itself

    with the conditions of possible experience, it remains on the level of conceptual

    representation and does not reach real being. Kant cuts his investigations off from the

    conditions of being, since those conditions are not objects of possible experience. In

    seeking the real being that gives rise to experience, Deleuze wants to recover a

    noumenon that does not have an external, transcendent relation to phenomena. He

    seeks the noumenon closest to the phenomenon which is internal to it and produces

    it immanently. 3 This is not the indeterminate thought of an intelligible ground, but the

    being of the sensible which can only be sensed. The distinction between the sensible

    and that which can only be sensed is between the recognizable given, and something

    that can only be encountered, that by which the given is given. 4 This transcendental

    condition is insensible in terms of representation, and unthinkable in terms of

    concepts, but it is internal to thought and must be thought.

    The question of the genesis of the given is closely related to the question of its

    determination. For Kant, determination takes place externally to the given, between

    the concepts of understanding and the object of intuition. External determination

    yields objects in general that differ in degree, the mass of possible experience.

    Deleuze, like Maimon, wants to find the internally -determining conditions that

    produce real experience (i.e. encounters that differ in kind). Deleuzes transcendental

    empiricism looks into the depth, interior, or being of experience. Transcendental

    empiricism is not concerned with the empirically real, but with the real immanent to

    the empirical; it is not concerned with the transcendentally ideal, but with what is

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    4/11

    4

    transcendental in the Idea. The real transcendental conditions of the given are in the

    Idea.

    Kant, too, locates the conditions of the given in ideas: the ideas of soul,

    cosmos and God are conditions that cannot be experienced, but force themselves upon

    our thought. But Kants ideas are legitimately conceived only as the conditions of our

    thinking of the genesis of being, insofar as they regulate conceptual thinking, not as its

    real conditions. Kants transcendental ideas are important but frustrating for Deleuze:

    they are undetermined problems concerning the genesis of being, but they are

    solved only in relation to representations and concepts. The constitutive power of

    the idea to determine and even generate being is distrusted and suppressed, leaving it

    only a regulative power to determine thinking. The model for an idea with genetic

    power, Deleuze finds in Maimon.

    Deleuze follows Maimon in arguing that the being of the sensible is in the

    Idea, and that intuition is produced from differentials. Chapter 4 of Difference and

    Repetition is, broadly, a Maimonian theory of onto-hetero-genesis, 5 in which a basic

    distinction is posited between productivity from differences in kind in the Idea, and

    produced, sensible things that differ in degree. But these realms are not external to

    one another: virtual differential productivity is immanent to its actual product, and the

    sensible is the surface contraction of the flows and intensities of the idea. Deleuzes

    Idea is far more Maimonian than it is Kantian: it is an unfinished, unfixed process

    of actualizing and expressing the differential relations that constitute it.

    Deleuze draws on Maimon in his criticism of Kants account of determination.

    For Kant, the determinant concept is applied to the determinable given from the

    outside, such that the transcendental moment is one of conditioning rather than

    genesis. The question of the internal constructability of the given is suppressed in his

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    5/11

    5

    focus on the surface construction of the object of experience. For Kant, therefore,

    difference is spoken of only in terms of this surface: the object in general is a

    blanket identity that is the basis for mere empirical diversity. For Maimon, on the

    other hand, determination is between determinant and determinable elements in the

    idea. The relation is not one of conditioning the intuition with a concept, but of

    generating the object from within. Determination is conceived not in terms of a one-

    way conditioning from the outside, but as reciprocal determination within the idea. 6

    For Maimon, determination takes place within the idea, according to

    reciprocal determination rather than negative determination. 7 For Maimon, a real

    object is determined by its differential positively generating its predicates. The

    predicates of a thing are new, and different in kind from others, because they are

    generated specifically with it. There is no sum-total of pre-existing possible predicates

    (greenness, blueness, etc) that a red thing is negatively determined to be. Instead, a

    red thing is reciprocally determined to be this instance of red: its differential

    determines its relation to all other qualities, and at the same time gains its own

    determination from its relation to all other qualities. This is what Deleuze, following

    Martial Gueroult, calls reciprocal determination as the reason for the emergence of

    qualities. When the differential is thought through all its relations of difference, both

    sides become determined: the differential becomes a determinate instance of redness,

    and all reality becomes more determined in its differential relations to that redness.

    This basic structure of the Idea Deleuze adapts from Maimon. Ideas appear

    [as ] a system of differential relations between reciprocally determined genetic

    elements. 8 The Idea produces determinate objects from differences, because of an

    ideal synthesis of differentials that gives determination to intensities and to the whole

    of the virtual. But Deleuze finds Maimon lacking in an important respect. For

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    6/11

    6

    Maimon, the differential is a fixed relation between qualities. For Deleuze, the

    differential relation varies, so that what is integrated from it is not a fixed quality, but

    rather the qualitys continuous multiplicity . Maimons differential is a rule for

    producing a fixed quality of variable size, but the rule itself does not vary. In this,

    Deleuze suggests, Maimon makes the same mistake as Leibniz: he fixes the

    differential relation such that it corresponds to the discrete multiplicity of a self-

    identical quality. 9 Deleuze sees this as a kind of atomism in which the differential is a

    fixed essence that resembles the objects generated from it. For Deleuze, the

    differential is not a fixed formula that produces a number of shades of red, but pure

    and varying difference from which flows a continuity of reds that cannot be divided

    into identifiable elements.

    So, even Maimon retains the image of thought through which the production

    of reality is taken to rest on the resemblance of the actual to the possible. Maimon

    ultimately grounds differential production in the identity of rules and qualities.

    Surprisingly, Deleuze finds a more profound thinking of difference in Kant. He refers

    to a precise moment within Kantianism, a furtive and explosive moment which is not

    even continued by Kant, much less by post-Kantianism. 10 The moment in question is

    one that makes the spontaneous self an other to itself in section 25 of the

    Transcendental Deduction (B). 11 Kants thinking of the determination of the I is

    crucial for Deleuzes ontology of difference in the Idea.

    Briefly, the I think, in determining its own being, cannot determine its own

    thinking activity, which can only be represented to it as an other. A gap therefore

    opens within the self, between its being and its thinking, or between the I am and

    the I think. While my existence is already given with the I think that determines

    it, my existence cannot be immediately determined. For the mode in which I am to

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    7/11

    7

    determine my existence that is, the manifold to be combined by the I think is not

    immediately given. It must be intuited in time, which makes my indeterminate

    existence determinable. But the I think thereby determines something different from

    itself: it determines its existence as it is given in time . Thus I cannot determine my

    existence as that of a self-active being; all that I can do is to represent to myself the

    spontaneity of my thought, that is, of the determination. 12

    The I think, in the act of determining its existence, prevents the

    determination of its own activity. The determination of my existence is a movement

    of self-differing. Determination is not here a matter of subsuming some given being in

    general under an external concept that would determine it as my being, but of

    producing my being by internally differentiating it from my thinking. This is a

    moment of Maimonian onto-hetero-genesis: the I think generates itself from its own

    differential relation to itself. The difference means there is no possibility of

    adequately thinking my spontaneity; it can only be represented insofar as receptivity

    experiences the spontaneity of my thought being exercised upon it, as if from outside

    it. The self cannot enact or be its own thinking activity. For this reason, Deleuze

    characterizes this moment with Rimbauds phrase I is an other. 13 Here, Deleuze

    finds, Kant adopts transcendental empiricism and discovers the pure difference

    internal to the relation of determination.

    It amounts to the discovery of Difference no longer in the form of an

    empirical difference between two determinations, but in the form of a

    transcendental Difference between the Determination as such as what

    it determines; no longer in the form of an external difference which

    separates, but in the form of an internal Difference which establishes

    an a priori relation between thought and being.14

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    8/11

    8

    Kants fractured I has three moments of determinable being, determinant

    thinking, and time as the form of determination. This is important for Deleuze for

    several reasons. It indicates the priority of time as a genetic condition for experience;

    it indicates that the self is generated from its own differential; and it grounds

    determination in an original difference of being and thinking. These factors make

    Kants fractured I the prototype of Deleuzes Idea, with the same problematic unity.

    The Idea performs like the I in that in determining its own being, its own activity

    must remain undetermined. As the Idea determines its actual solutions in the realm of

    the sensible, its virtual object, the problem, must be represented without being able

    to be directly determined. 15 The problem becomes determined by analogy with the

    objects of experience it relates to. So the Idea is its differing from itself. It produces

    itself as the determinate solutions (singularities and events) that make its problematic

    being fundamentally undeterminable and thinkable only in terms of representation. As

    a result, problems can indeed be represented in terms of experience and concepts, but

    their true being cannot be thought in this way. The true, problematic being of the Idea

    is fundamentally undetermined and unrepresentable. It is the being of the sensible

    that can only be sensed; the unthinkable that must be thought. Kants passive self

    receives the activity of [its] own thought as an other, and Deleuzes actualized Idea

    receives the activity of the problem as an other; this powerful other must be sensed

    and must be thought. 16

    Kants fractured I is therefore closely bound up with the discovery of the

    problematic and the Idea. Structurally, the Idea repeats its relation of determination

    and the difference internal to being and thought. Ideas are exactly the thoughts of the

    fractured Cogito 17 because they enact the activity of thinking determining its own

    being as the unfolding of time. Time is not simply the form of intuition, or the form of

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    9/11

    9

    actualized solutions, but the form of the determinability of being by thought. For

    Kant, it is the form internal to the I that continually produces the I as differing from

    itself. For Deleuze, time is internal to the Idea: its unfolding is the activity of the Idea

    determining itself and preserving its own indeterminacy. It is not that thinking

    determines being in time as a container. Rather, time is the difference internal to the

    fractured I and the Idea: thought determining being is the unfolding of time and the

    operation of difference. This indicates an original and irreducible relation that does

    not merely condition but generates experience: the relation of the difference of

    thinking and being that can be formulated thinking-time-being or determinant-

    determinable-undetermined. Ideas contain [these] dismembered moments as an

    internal problematic objective unity. 18

    The thinking and being that we speak of here does not refer to a determinative

    judgment between a concept and an actual being, but to an ontological relation that

    forms the internal structure of Kants transcendental unity of apperception, and of

    Deleuzes virtual, pre-individual Idea. This is the original relation of the

    determination and genesis of the actual. It is the relation of being and thinking

    differentiated by time. Deleuze thinks that Kant is mistaken to locate this differential

    relation in a subject, for this difference and its generative power too easily become

    covered over. The fracture in the I is quickly filled by a new form of identity and an

    external difference between spontaneity and receptivity. 19 Kant is too empirical in

    holding thinking and being in external opposition, whereas the post-Kantians are too

    dogmatic in filling the gap between them. But in this moment of the Transcendental

    Deduction, Kant discovers pure difference. For a brief moment we enter into that

    schizophrenia in principle which characterises the highest power of thought, and

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    10/11

    10

    opens Being directly onto difference, despite all the mediations, all the

    reconciliations, of the concept. 20

    The fractured, self-differing I is therefore the essence of Kants Copernican

    revolution and constitutes the discovery of the transcendental. 21 Kant discovers the

    genetic conditions of real experience in the pure difference of being and thinking.

    Without the difference of being and thinking internal to the fractured I, experience

    and determination are inevitably founded in identity: the identity of a finite or infinite

    self for whom there is no being that cannot be thought . In this kind of system, actual

    experience will be nothing more than a copy of a possible reality determined in

    advance. This is ultimately the problem with Maimon. Where experience is grounded

    in the difference between being and thinking, however (in Kants fractured I, in

    Deleuzes Idea, or paradigmatically, in Spinozas substance), the sensible is

    determined as it is generated . Differentials produce experience as surprising and

    unforeseeable, the encounters that shock us into thinking.

    1 Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition , trans. Paul Patton (London: Athlone, 1994), 173. HereafterDR.2 DR 56-7.3 DR 222.4 DR 139-40.5 Miguel de Beistegui, Truth and Genesis: Philosophy as Differential Ontology (Indianapolis: IndianaUniversity Press, 2004).6 DR 173.7 Martial Guroult, La philosophie transcendentale de Salomon Maimon (Paris: Librairie Flix Alcan,1929), 54, 76.8 DR 173-4.9 DR 172.10 DR 58.11 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1929),B157-9. Hereafter CPR.12 CPR B158n..13 Gilles Deleuze, Kants Critical Philosophy , trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam(London: Athlone, 1995) viii.14 DR 86.15 DR 169.16 Gilles Deleuze, On Four Poetic Formulas that might Summarize the Kantian Philosophy, EssaysCritical and Clinical , trans. Daniel W. Smith and Michael A. Grew (London: Verso, 1998), 30; DR199-200.

  • 8/13/2019 I is for Idea Maimon, Kant, and Deleuzes ontology of difference

    11/11

    11

    17 DR 169.18 DR 170.19 DR 87.20 DR 58.21 DR 86.