gillespie 2011 inquiry

Upload: makusu-amanah

Post on 04-Jun-2018

223 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    1/68

    INQUIRYCRITICALTHINKINGACROSSTHEDISCIPLINES

    Contents

    Robert H. Ennis Critical Thinking: Reection and Perspective Part I................ 4

    Michael A. Gillespie Assessing Critical Thinking about Values:A Quasi-Experimental Study.................................................. 19

    Articles from the Members of the Lone Star College CyFair Campus Critical Thinking Based

    Faculty Learning Community (CTB-FLC)

    Maria Sanders Embracing Critical Thinking as a Model forProfessional Development: Creating CTB-FLCsOn Your Campus..................................................................... 29

    Maria Sanders &Jason Moulenbelt Dening Critical Thinking: How Far Have We Come?.......... 38

    Frank Codispoti The Academic College Course is an Argument ..................... 47

    Idolina Hernandez Critical Thinking and Social Interaction in theOnline Environment............................................................... 55

    Heather Mong & Ben Clegg Review of David Levys Tools of Critical Thinking:Metathoughts for Psychology................................................. 62

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    2/68

    2 INQUIRY: CRITICAL THINKING ACROSS THE DISCIPLINES

    Copyright Permission and Disclaimer

    It is the policy of this journal to obtain and hold the copyrights for all articles published with

    the exception of those articles or parts of articles in the public domain. Authors are allowed to

    make copies of their articles for any scholarly purpose of their own. Other scholars are hereby

    given permission to make single or multiple copies of single articles for personal scholarly use

    without explicit written permission, providing that no such copies are sold or used for commercial

    purposes. It is the obligation of any user to acknowledge sources explicitly and to obtain permission

    from the journal if extensive use is to be made of materials or information contained in an article.

    Extensive use of copy privileges in such a way would be unethical. These policies will be followed

    until further notice.

    This journal is not responsible for the statements of any contributor. Statements or opinions

    expressed in the journal reect the views of the author(s) and not the Editor, the Editorial Advisory

    Board, or ad hoc reviewers. Publication should not be construed as endorsement.

    Frank Fair, Managing Editor

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    3/68

    3SPRING 2011, VOL. 26, NO. 1

    From the Editors DeskFrank Fair

    I am very pleased that in this issue ofINQUIRYwe continue the series of reection pieces that Gerald

    Nosich began so well in the previous issue. Now it is Bob Enniss turn, and his contribution is so rich, so

    replete with relevant detail, that it has been split into two parts. Critical Thinking: Reection and Perspec-

    tive Part I appears in this issue and covers Bobs initial involvement with the eld of critical thinking and

    the evolution of his conceptualization of critical thinking. Critical Thinking: Reection and Perspective

    Part II has equally meaty content, and it will appear in the next issue,INQUIRYVol. 26, No. 2 (Summer

    2011). It will cover Bobs perspective on issues involved in the assessment and teaching of critical thinking.

    Next comes a piece by Michael Gillespie Assessing Critical Thinking about Values: A Quasi-experi-

    mental Study that reports on a study of an innovative program at Bowling Green State University whose

    goal is to foster critical thinking in the context of considering values. Many universities have programs

    with similar intent, and Gillespies careful study provides a model for how one might assess such programs.Then we have a series of articles contributed by faculty members from the Cypress Fairbanks (CyFair)

    campus of the Lone Star College System. With an enrollment of 85,000 students on its several campuses,

    the Lone Star system is the largest institution of higher education in the Houston area and the fastest grow-

    ing community college system in Texas. A faculty member and administrator from Lone Star-CyFair, Maria

    Sanders, describes in Embracing Critical Thinking as a Model for Faculty Development how she and a

    number of other faculty members from diverse disciplines formed a CTB-FLC, a Critical Thinking Based

    Faculty Learning Community, in which critical thinking served as a focus for a low-cost, potentially high-

    impact faculty development effort. Then come three essays that are fruits of this effort. The rst essay by

    Maria Sanders and Jason Moulenbelt Dening Critical Thinking: How Far Have We Come? surveys

    the often bewildering variety of conceptions of critical thinking with a view toward noting difculties this

    variety poses for critical thinking assessments and for interdisciplinary collaborations. The second essay,

    The Academic College Course is an Argument, is a spirited defense by Frank Codispoti of the lecture as

    an instructional mode when done well and when approached with an emphasis on the same sort of critical

    thinking skills that students are supposed to bring to course reading matter. (Note: anyone interested in

    improving lectures might also look at the article on Successful Lecturing by Patricia deWinstanley and

    Robert Bjork in Applying the Science of Learning to University Teaching and Beyond,edited by Diane

    Halpern and Milton Hakel, a 2002 collection from Jossey-Bass.) Finally, Idolina Hernandezs essay Criti-

    cal Thinking and Social Interaction in the Online Environment considers how the use of discussion boards

    in the online course environment can foster critical thinking by encouraging the appropriate processes of

    social interaction.

    The last contribution is a review of David Levys Tools of Critical Thinking: Metathoughts for Psy-

    chology.Heather Mong and Ben Clegg give an informative account of the book and a generally favorable

    review, but they have a few caveats, mainly about what might be needed to avoid some of the thinkingpitfalls that the Levy discusses.

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    4/68

    4 INQUIRY: CRITICAL THINKING ACROSS THE DISCIPLINES

    It is an honor to have received Editor Frank Fairs

    request to write a personal historical report about the

    development of critical thinking education.1 My response

    emphasizes the period 1950-2010, but does reach further

    into the past, and is by no means a historians history of

    critical thinking. It is a personal view of the critical thinking

    movement and my involvement in it. Part I deals with how

    I became involved in the critical thinking movement and

    how my denition and conception of critical thinking have

    evolved. Part II will deal with efforts to assess and to teach

    critical thinking and with problems and future prospects.

    My Background: How I Arrived atCritical Thinking

    Although in my K-12 years I was exposed to an ex-

    cellent traditional education, I, like Gerald Nosich (2010),

    was quite ignorant and naive in making my early decisions.

    Because I did well in high school math and physics, and

    because of the encouragement of my teachers and parents, I

    went to MIT in 1945, right at the end of World War II, plan-

    ning to become an engineer. Although I did well for four

    semesters in the math, engineering, and science aspects of

    the curriculum, I developed some misgivings. For those

    and other personal reasons, I interrupted my studies andjoined the US Army, serving in the Army of Occupation

    in Japan in 1947. There I experienced a 19-year-old-type

    total revision of my goals and interests. The war-making

    technology and its effects (including what I saw in Hi-

    roshima during a visit there on the second anniversary

    of the bomb) convinced me that the world did not need

    engineers or more science and technology. It needed a

    population suffused with wisdom. At the time I thought

    that philosophy was the ultimate repository of wisdom, so I

    decided to obtain a bachelors degree in philosophy rather

    than engineering, having done no investigating about the

    nature of academic philosophy.

    MIT at that time had no philosophy courses, so I

    cautiously took a leave of absence, never to return. I

    transferred to the University of Wisconsin, Madison. There

    the contemporary philosophy to which I was exposed was

    logical positivism, but also some of John Deweys work.

    Neither satised me. Logical positivism seemed to be an

    interesting, challenging system, like chess, but without

    relevance to wisdom; and Deweys defense of his positions,

    as well as some of his positions, seemed weak. Further-

    more, even though his advocacy of reective thinking

    (Dewey, 1933) would later appeal to me, that was not part

    of what was presented to me as Deweys philosophy. Nor

    did I see relevance to wisdom in my history of philosophy

    courses. The content came too thick and fast for me to

    grapple with and to discuss what I now see as important

    ideas and issues. Grappling and discussing were not part

    of the total curriculum that I experienced, though they are

    what I now think are crucial elements in critical thinking

    instruction, though of course not in themselves sufcient.

    As a result of frustration in my search for wisdom,

    I instead considered a career in the theater because my

    extra-curricular experiences there were exciting and fun,and the theater actually is a way of promoting wisdom

    (e.g., Twelve Angry Men, a timeless play). But I rejected

    the theater, partly because I saw so many unemployed

    actors and dancers who were much more talented than I.

    There was a bit of critical thinking here: making observa-

    tions and using the information in considering and being

    open to alternatives (to some extent) when making deci-

    sions. But these practices were not part of my traditional

    education.

    Critical Thinking: Reection and PerspectivePart I

    Robert Ennis

    Abstract

    This is Part I of a two-part reection by Robert Ennis on his involvement in the critical thinkingmovement. Part I deals with how he got started in the movement and with the development of his

    inuential denition of critical thinking and his conception of what critical thinking involves. Part

    II of the reection will appear in the next issue ofINQUIRY, Vol. 26, No. 2 (Summer 2011), and it

    will cover topics concerned with assessing critical thinking, teaching critical thinking, and what the

    future may hold.

    Key words: critical thinking denition, rigor, criteria, logic, looseness, progressive education, Vietnam

    War protests, subject matter, critical thinking movement

    I am uneasy to think I decide concerning truth and falsehood, reason and folly, without

    knowing upon what principles I proceed.(David Hume)

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    5/68

    5SPRING 2011, VOL. 26, NO. 1

    In 1950 I managed to get a BA in philosophy without

    any knowledge of the ordinary-language philosophical

    developments associated with the later Wittgenstein. More

    ignorance. Then I heard about philosophy of education. It

    struck me (still naively, given what I believed about phi-

    losophy) that what I had learned and had not yet learned

    about philosophy could somehow help the eld of educa-tion. There was some equivocation going on in my head

    regarding philosophy, but I had not been sensitized to

    equivocation or ambiguity in my logic course, or any other

    courses. And I rightly believed that education could have an

    important role in developing a world population suffused

    with wisdom. I decided to go into philosophy of education.

    I then received some wise (though unrequested)

    advice: Learn rst-hand as a teacher what goes on in

    our education system before launching into a career in

    educational theory. Though I had not sought that advice,

    I followed it and became a high school physical science

    teacher, who also had to teach two sections of a combina-

    tion of English and social studies. It was called a coreor common learnings course in progressive education

    parlance, and it was a precursor to writing across the

    curriculum. In the process, I heard about critical thinking

    from the progressive-education movements advocacy of it,

    and realized that the promotion of critical thinking would

    be very important for our personal, vocational, and civic

    lives, and that the survival of a democratic way of life de-

    pended on the critical thinking of the voters. I still believe

    this, even more strongly, and am pleased that I have been

    able to spend as much time as I have on critical thinking,

    only wishing that I could have accomplished more.

    I tried to incorporate critical thinking in my teaching.

    But I had little notion of how to teach it or even of whatcritical thinking was other than propaganda analysis

    (Institute for Propaganda Analysis, 1938), which was

    heavily negative and oversimplied in its approach (as is

    commonly the case with the current fallacies approach to

    teaching critical thinking).

    After three years of high school teaching I became

    a graduate student at the University of Illinois, and en-

    rolled in a philosophy of education program with minors

    in philosophy and educational measurement. I was lucky

    to get an assistantship with the Illinois Project for the Im-

    provement of Thinking under the leadership of B. Othanel

    Smith and Kenneth Henderson. We tried to help three

    Chicago-area high schools embed critical thinking in their

    subject-matter instruction, physics being the area on which

    I focused. I also found myself immersed in, and fascinated

    by, the later-Wittgenstein movement in philosophy, which I

    saw and still see to be quite relevant to education, wisdom,

    and critical thinking, in spite of its excesses. I had nally

    found a home combining philosophy and education.

    The above-described background is, among other

    things, a generalizable argument-by-example in support of

    the supplementation of our subject-matter courses and oth-

    er courses with a heavy dose of critical thinking instruction.

    Notice that I said supplementation, not supplanting. A

    necessary condition for thinking critically about anything is

    being well informed, which includes subject-matter content

    where relevant. Unfortunately, aside from simple deduc-

    tion, principles of critical thinking were not included in thecontent that I encountered with two minor exceptions:

    In high school English I was taught to make classication

    (genus-differentia) denitions, and in college physics labs

    I was taught to make three measurements (instead of just

    one) and average the three in order to secure a more reliable

    measure of a quantity. In my undergraduate deductive logic

    course I was not shown thatstrictdeductive logic rarely

    applies to everyday reasoning (including that of scholars,

    voters, and Supreme Court Justices). However, imprecise

    derivation or qualied reasoning (Ennis, 1969a & 1969b,

    1981a, 1996a, 2004; discussed later in this essay) does

    apply to everyday reasoning. Fortunately, material impli-

    cation and its implausible cohorts were, as I remember it,not promoted in that logic course.

    The fact that I did receive advice from an experienced

    person about how to pursue my career is not to my credit.

    I did not know enough to seek it out. It was in effect im-

    posed on me by the father of a high school friend. In none

    of my courses was I told the critical thinking principle that

    one needs to make a special effort to get all the relevant

    information appropriate for a decision, and to seek, con-

    sider, and get informed about alternatives before making

    an important decision.

    In sum, in my K-12 and undergraduate education there

    was virtually no attention to the principles, procedures,

    and criteria for thinking critically in or out of the subjectsI studied. Basically I was engaged in acquiring, and was

    tested on, straight subject-matter knowledge only.

    The Critical Thinking Movement as I Saw Itand Associated with It:

    From Progressive Education and theLater Wittgenstein to the Present

    Early philosophical concerns about critical thinking

    can be found, among other places, in Socrates, Plato,

    Aristotle, Bacon, Hume, and especially John Stuart Mill,

    but John Dewey (Dewey, 1933, rst edition 1910) was the

    source of inspiration for the progressive-education K-12

    critical thinking movement of which the Illinois Project

    for the Improvement of Thinking was a part.

    The Progressive Education Movement

    The progressive-education movement, which was

    strong in the United States from the 1920s through the

    1950s, adopted and developed Deweys emphasis on

    reective thinking. Tests called Interpretation of Data,

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    6/68

    6 INQUIRY: CRITICAL THINKING ACROSS THE DISCIPLINES

    Application of Principles of Science, Application of Prin-

    ciples of Logical Reasoning, andNature of Proof(Smith

    and Tyler, 1942, pp. 35-156) were developed to appraise

    students in the Progressive Education Associations monu-

    mental Eight-Year Study, which took place in the 1930s.

    (See Aiken, 1942, for an overview.) In that study, the words

    critical thinking and clear thinking replaced reec-tive thinking (Smith & Tyler, pp. 35-37), and a 1942

    yearbook of the National Council for Social Studies used

    critical thinking in its title, Teaching Critical Thinking

    in the Social Studies(Anderson, 1942). My rst published

    article was about the teaching of critical thinking (Critical

    Thinking: More on Its Motivation, Ennis, 1956), and ap-

    peared in the journal,Progressive Education. I submitted to

    that journal because the progressive-education movement

    was the primary promoter of critical thinking at the time.

    In addition to my focus on the teaching of critical

    thinking, I became the statistician for the Illinois Project for

    the Improvement of Thinking, and produced conclusions

    from the data obtained with the tests we used and fromour observations in the classrooms. I saw the importance

    of having valid tests of critical thinking, and I realized the

    dependence of such tests on ones conception of critical

    thinking. As a result, my Ph.D. dissertation topic was The

    Development of a Critical Thinking Test (Ennis, 1959b).

    Given the state of critical thinking theory in use at the time,

    I believed that the development of a critical thinking test

    required the prior development and specication of a con-

    ception of critical thinking. So my dissertation combined

    the development of a conception with the development of

    a test. The conception leaned heavily on my philosophi-

    cal forbears, as well as this question: How do people go

    wrong in their thinking? Because of my assistantship andthesis work I was able at the time to contribute directly to

    the literature on the teaching of (Ennis, 1956), the nature

    of (Ennis, 1962, 1964b), and assessment of (Ennis, 1958,

    1959b) critical thinking. In particular, my 1962 article

    on the nature of critical thinking, A Concept of Critical

    Thinking, has received much attention. Michael Roth

    (Roth, 2010), in an article in the Chronicle of Higher

    Educationchallenging critical thinking, attributed critical

    thinkings becoming popular to this article. Harvey Seigel

    (Siegel, 1988) deemed the article highly inuential (p.

    5). John McPeck (McPeck, 1981), perhaps the critical

    thinking movements most vociferous critic, treated this

    article as presenting the prevailing view of the conception

    of critical thinking (pp. 39-57).

    From Progressive Education to Emphasizing Subject

    Matter

    Results of the Eight-Year Study were published in

    1942, when everyone was focused on World War II. I

    believe that the progressive-education movement disin-

    tegrated because of the overwhelming importance of the

    war (1941-1945 for the United States) when the Eight-Year

    Studys results appeared; the excesses that inevitably occur

    in any movement; the strong criticisms of the movement

    by academic subject-matter specialists (especially Arthur

    Bestor of the University of Illinois); and (the nal nail

    in the cofn) Russias beating the USA to having a suc-

    cessful satellite, Sputnik, in 1957. Sputniks appearingbefore the USAs rst satellite was blamed by many on

    the schools, which were still somewhat under the inu-

    ence of progressive education. I have a vivid recollection

    of the large front-page headline in the Chicago Tribune

    right after Sputnik, What went wrong with U.S. schools?

    According to popular insight, the schools had failed to

    teach science to their students. Progressive education

    was held by many to be the problem. As a result, straight

    subject-matter acquisition became very popular, and was

    the theme in former scientist and Harvard President James

    B. Conants inuential The American High School Today

    (Conant, 1959).

    In spite of the opposition to, and the disintegrationof, the progressive-education movement, there were con-

    tinuing expressions of interest in critical thinking in the

    1930s through the 1970s, mostly by philosophers. Cohen

    and NagelsIntroduction to Logic and Scientic Method

    (1934) introduced me as a graduate student to many aspects

    of critical thinking. Max Blacks Critical Thinking: An

    Introduction to Logic and Scientic Method(1946) and

    W. H. WerkmeistersAn Introduction to Critical Thinking

    (1948) were college textbooks that to my knowledge were

    the earliest college textbooks that used the words critical

    thinking in their titles. Another early text was Monroe

    BeardsleysPractical Logic(1950). All four of these early

    works were guides used by the staff of the Illinois Projectfor the Improvement of Thinking, of which I was a member

    from 1954 to 1957.

    Even Conant was a participant in the early promotion

    of critical thinking at the college level with his general

    editorship of the series,Harvard Case Histories in Experi-

    mental Science(Conant, 1950-1954), and his authorship of

    On Understanding Science(Conant, 1951). Using detailed

    cases from the history of science, his series and his book

    illustrated certain principles in the strategy and tactics of

    science (Conant, 1951, pp. 102-111). A principal theme of

    Conants in these works was opposition to a simple ve-

    step concept of the scientic method(promoted I believe

    by the progressive-education movement), which he felt

    vastly oversimplied how scientists think. I agreed with

    him in his emphasis on principles in scientic thinking

    (Ennis, 1974b, 1979, 1991a, 1991b), and his complaint

    about oversimplication.

    From Sputnik through the mid-1970s, I was part of the

    philosophically-oriented minority pressing for the incor-

    poration of critical thinking in K-12 and higher education.

    During this period (1959-1970), I authored 12 articles

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    7/68

    7SPRING 2011, VOL. 26, NO. 1

    and two books concerned with the nature, teaching, and

    assessment of critical thinking.

    The Vietnam War Protests

    From the mid-1960s to the mid-1970s, the Vietnam

    War and student-based concerns about relevance, authen-

    ticity, and the war itself overwhelmed the subject-matteremphasis of Conant and others. But it was not only students

    who challenged the academic establishment. I vividly re-

    member a scholarly professor in the English Department

    at Cornell University in 1968 expressing at a university

    faculty meeting his contempt for the academic establish-

    ment by gravely pronouncing, Were in bad trouble.

    Bad trouble is not the sort of expression I expected to

    hear from a scholar in the English Department at a Uni-

    versity Faculty meeting. It was protest language. To use it

    in those circumstances in 1968 was a powerful expression

    from within of a rejection of academia.

    In that context, critical thinking struggled along,

    but was not very popular because of its emphasis onrigor, reection,and, alternatives,as opposed to action

    now. For example, the activists of the period judged that

    neutrality by our educational institutions was impossible

    (generally, in that period, neutrality toward the Vietnam

    War, and in one instance, toward the administration in the

    late 1960s by some colleges and universities of a draft-

    exemption examination, an unpopular action in the eyes

    of most activists because it constituted what they felt was

    complicity in the war effort). Though I opposed the war,

    I disagreed with the judgment that neutrality for colleges

    and universities was impossible. I argued that neutrality

    on any specic issue (though not on every issue at once)

    was possible, unless the argument assumed from its begin-ning that its position and recommendation on the specic

    issue were correct, in which case the argument became

    essentially circular (Ennis, 1969d, an improvement on an

    early version, 1959a). My argument in this case involved

    an ordinary-language sensitivity to reported denition and

    equivocation, sub-aspects of the denition aspect of critical

    thinking to be considered later and listed in the appendix

    (Abilities 9b1 and 9d).

    Renewed Emphasis on Critical Thinking

    In the late 1970s, concern about critical thinking

    moved back into the foreground, I believe because of the

    excesses of the protest movement, because the war was

    over, and because the protestors emphasis on relevance

    had strong appeal. Howard Kahanes popular Logic and

    Contemporary Rhetoric(1971) contributed to the revival

    of attention to critical thinking at the time. It was written

    . . . in an attempt to raise the level of political argument

    and reasoning by acquainting students with the devices and

    ploys which drag that level down (Kahane, 1971, Pref-

    ace). But the renewed emphasis on critical thinking was

    not as part of a rejuvenation of the progressive-education

    movement. Critical thinking was advocated because it

    provided the rigor, reection, and reasonableness that both

    the anti- and pro-war forces had ignored, as evidenced by

    Howard Kahanes inuential efforts.

    Around 1980, interest in critical thinking suddenly ex-

    ploded. The First International Conference on Informal Log-ic was held at the University of Windsor in 1978. Canada,

    as I understand it, had not experienced the extreme reaction

    against academia that we had in the United States. Never-

    theless, there was some, and emphasis on critical thinking

    and informal logic was a step back to rigor and reection.

    Signicant establishment institutions contributed. The

    Commission on the Humanities (1980), sponsored by the

    Rockefeller Foundation, placed heavy emphasis on critical

    thinking, as did the Carnegie Foundations Ernest Boyer

    (Boyer, 1983). The College Board (College Board, 1983),

    which is responsible for the SAT test, specied reasoning

    as one of the six basic academic competencies in Aca-

    demic Preparation for College.In 1983, Executive Order# 338 in the California State University System required

    that in order to graduate from one of the State University

    units, a student must have had nine hours of instruction

    in communication and in critical thinking. At the Second

    International Conference on Informal Logic at Windsor

    in 1983, The Association for Informal Logic and Critical

    Thinking (AILACT) was established, the membership of

    which then consisted mostly of philosophers from Canada

    and the United States and it still does. The American

    Philosophical Associations Board of Ofcers (1985) urged

    philosophers to help with attempts to test for critical think-

    ing and attempts to include critical thinking in elementary

    and secondary curricula.This explosion of interest was neither a return to

    straight subject matter exclusively, nor to the progressive-

    education movement. It was a marriage of subject matter

    and one important feature of the progressive movement,

    critical thinking, a marriage that to this day we struggle to

    implement. In going beyond straight subject-matter acquisi-

    tion, The College Board exhibited this attempted marriage

    in its Academic Preparation for College: The learning

    outcomes described here [including reasoning] are rigorous

    as well as comprehensive (College Board, 1983, p. 3).

    The roots of three current, philosopher-led, criti-

    cal-thinking-promoting organizations developed in the

    1980s. One, led by Richard Paul (and currently also

    Linda Elder), developed at Sonoma State University,

    California, with large annual conferences of educators at

    the K-12 and university levels at which many of us in

    AILACT made presentations. Its current titles are Foun-

    dation for Critical Thinking, Center for Critical Think-

    ing, and The National Council for Excellence in Critical

    Thinking. A second, led by Robert Swartz, developed at

    the University of Massachusetts-Boston with a masters

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    8/68

    8 INQUIRY: CRITICAL THINKING ACROSS THE DISCIPLINES

    program in critical and creative thinking, and is currently

    titled the National Center for Teaching Thinking (NCTT).

    I have participated in some of its workshops. A third, led

    by Peter Facione, had its origins at Santa Clara Univer-

    sity, California, where Facione led an effort to arrive

    at an agreement by mail among forty-six specialists in

    critical thinking (of which I was one) on a fairly-detaileddispositions-and-abilities denition of critical thinking.

    Facione called the results The Delphi Report (Facione,

    1990). His organization operates under the title Insight

    Assessment. The rst two of these organizations focus on

    teaching, and the third focuses on a conception of and on

    the assessment of critical thinking, although all are con-

    cerned with all three elements. All three have extensive

    web sites. The rst and second claim national status,

    but I see no interaction or cooperation between them.

    AILACT, of which I am a member and past pres-

    ident, is open to new members on application, has elec-

    tions for its leaders, and is not publicized as well as the

    above three, though it is trying to catch up. On its web siteat http://ailact.mcmaster.ca, it provides material dealing

    with the nature of, teaching of, and assessment of criti-

    cal thinking and informal logic, lists available consultants

    from its membership, lists institutions providing advanced

    instruction in critical thinking, and will be listing avail-

    able critical thinking tests. AILACT also sponsors criti-

    cal thinking and informal logic sessions at annual APA

    meetings. More information about all four of these critical

    thinking organizations can be found on their web sites.

    Throughout the 1980s there was a large amount

    of activity in critical thinking: workshops, conferences,

    test development, new curricula, restatement of goals,

    books, articles, etc., accompanied by controversies aboutall aspects of the movement. These controversies live

    on, and include the basic nature of critical thinking; the

    details of the nature of critical thinking; the relationship

    between critical thinking and subject matter; promoting

    critical thinking in the different subjects as opposed to

    doing it in separate critical thinking courses (often unfor-

    tunately assumed to be mutually-exclusive alternatives);

    the role of metacognition (being aware of and thinking

    about ones own thinking) in critical thinking; the nature

    of the deduction involved in critical thinking; the role

    of persuasion in critical thinking; the relation between

    critical thinking and problem solving; the degree to which

    critical thinking is broader than argumentation and

    deduction, if at all; the possibility of assessing critical

    thinking; how to assess critical thinking on a large

    scale and on a small scale; the possibility of teaching

    critical thinking; the role of critical thinking principles

    in critical thinking instruction; whether to seek and how

    to achieve transfer of the learning of critical thinking to

    topics other than those used in instruction; and of course,

    the value of critical thinking.

    The multiplicity of critical-thinking-promoting activi-

    ties from 1980 through the present involved not only phi-

    losophers, but also people in all subject-matter areas. The

    principal academics with whom I interacted at workshops

    and conferences were philosophers, psychologists, and

    speech/communication experts, each with a somewhat dif-

    ferent emphasis. To oversimplify, the philosophers tendedto emphasize seeking the truth (or the rightness or correct-

    ness of a process or result), and using rational methods of

    doing so; psychologists tended to emphasize empirical

    relationships, such as what causes what, including such

    processes as metacognition, transfer of critical thinking

    learning to a new area of application, and problem solving.

    Speech/communication experts tended to emphasize effec-

    tive persuasion. But all three were generally interested at

    least to some extent in the others emphases. During this

    period I contributed to general critical thinking and criti-

    cal thinking in science, and authored some 41 articles and

    one book, as well as co-authoring two articles, one book,

    three published tests, and several unpublished tests, eachrelevant to at least one of the above-listed controversial

    areas in critical thinking.

    In the 1980s, the critical thinking movement em-

    phasized critical thinking in K-12, as well as at the un-

    dergraduate level. Extending into the 1990s and the rst

    decade of the twenty-rst century, emphasis on critical

    thinking increased in college and universities, at least

    in mission statements. This occurred partly at the behest

    of accrediting agencies and partly because people real-

    ized that critical thinking is important and that existing

    subject-matter acquisition generally did not adequately

    prepare people to think critically in their vocational, civic,

    and personal lives. All the controversies I have mentionedcontinue today, though progress has been made. Because

    critical thinking is so important, I have devoted much of

    my career to the task.

    My Contributions to the Content of theCritical Thinking Movement

    Because I am probably best known for my develop-

    ment of a conception of critical thinking, and because

    teaching and assessment both assume a conception of

    critical thinking, the nature of critical thinking is the rst

    topic to be addressed. It will be followed in Part II in the

    next issue of INQUIRYby discussions of assessment,

    teaching (including incorporation in a curriculum), and

    future prospects.

    The Nature of Critical Thinking

    Early on I developed a denitionand an associated

    elaborated conceptionof critical thinking (Ennis, 1962).

    I am here employing the distinction between concept

    and conception that John Rawls offered (Rawls, 1971,

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    9/68

    9SPRING 2011, VOL. 26, NO. 1

    p. 5), following H. L. A. Hart (Hart, 1961, pp. 155-159):

    A conceptis that which different, more detailed concep-

    tionsof a particular idea have in common. But I use the

    terms denition and conception instead of concept

    and conception in order to minimize confusion. In 1962

    I was not aware of the distinction and called the whole

    presentation a concept of critical thinking (Ennis, 1962,p. 81), though a more appropriate title might have been a

    denition and a conception of critical thinking.

    As a result not only of the intense discussions of the

    late 1970s and the early 1980s, but also further investiga-

    tion from 1962 to 1987 of a number of critical thinking

    aspects, my rst denition and conception of critical

    thinking developed into a new pair (Ennis 1987b, 1991c,

    1996a, 2002), which I shall call my second denition and

    conception. In this section, I shall present and discuss the

    features of the two pairs, the second conception having

    evolved from the rst, and the second denition being

    radically different from the rst, though they both treat

    critical thinking as a term of approbation. An unexempli-ed presentation of the total second denition/conception

    can be found in the appendix to this essay.

    My First Critical Thinking Denition and the

    Associated First Conception of Critical Thinking

    The critical thinking denition that was presented

    to me as a graduate student was the one advanced by B.

    Othanel Smith (Smith, 1953), my advisor, mentor, teacher,

    model, and supervisor in the Illinois Project for the Im-

    provement of Thinking. Smith held that critical thinking is

    both determining the meaning of statements and assessing

    these statements (p. 130).

    For my rst denition, I amended Smiths denitionby holding that critical thinking is the correct assessing

    of statements (Ennis, 1962, p. 83). The key change from

    Smiths denition was the addition of the word correct.

    I felt that the determining-the-meaning part was implicit,

    although I now would make it explicit because it is so

    important. I added correct because I believed and still

    do believe (somewhat under the ordinary-language inu-

    ence of the later Wittgenstein) that critical thinking, as

    used in the critical thinking movement, was not merely a

    descriptive term, but also a term of approbation.

    This approbation feature of the rst denition is one

    of several features of particular note in the 1962 deni-

    tion/conception. Three other features are (a) emphasis on

    detailed criteria, (b) emphasis on good judgment in an

    imprecise environment because criteria do not automati-

    cally yield critical thinking decisions, and (c) attention to

    credibility of sources. I shall elaborate.

    (a) Criteria

    One basic idea in both the rst and second of my

    conceptions of critical thinking came from my high school

    teaching experience. It is that in order to do critical think-

    ing, students need criteria for making decisions. These

    criteria would give them guidance that is as precise as is

    feasible in making decisions. That meant, for example, not

    just that students should learn or know that they should

    take into account the credibility of their sources, or that

    they should judge a hypothesis by looking at the evidence;but also that they should learn or know criteria (and ac-

    companying distinctions) for deciding whether a source is

    credible, or for judging whether the evidence supports the

    hypothesis. As a high school teacher I had no such criteria

    to promote with my students.

    (b) Good Judgment: Qualications, Tolerating Lack

    of Precision, and SEBKUS

    One cannot expect the application of these criteria

    to yield a result automatically, except in mathematics

    and deductive logic. And even deductive logic in real life

    applications usually has to deal with implicit or explicit

    qualifying words like ceteris paribus(other things be-ing equal), probably, tends to, roughly, etc., making

    the application of criteria not logically necessary in most

    cases (Ennis, 1969b); hence, in a way, imprecise or loose.

    So good judgment in applying the criteria is needed

    as well. Criteria used in making a good judgment are

    generally aided by Sensitivity, Experience, Background

    Knowledge, and Understanding of the Situation, that is,

    SEBKUS (an acronym I developed fairly recently (En-

    nis, 2004)).

    These emphases on criteria and good judgment (ex-

    pressed with varying degrees of qualication, and made

    with SEBKUS) have permeated all my work on critical

    thinking, even my work on operational denition (En-nis, 1964a), but the basic ideas started to develop when

    I was a graduate student involved in the Illinois Project

    for the Improvement of Thinking. They are key features

    of my 1962 concept article. Many of my articles since

    then have elaborated these emphases in different contexts

    and with respect to different aspects of critical thinking.

    If I am right about the need for good judgment (which

    often requires a tolerance of some lack of precision,

    that is, tolerance of some looseness), then I see no hope

    for computerizing critical thinking, though I admit that

    expert computer systems can probably ((!) See my

    paper Probably (Ennis, 2006) for a discussion of some

    details of imprecision.) do a better job in tight time limits

    than many professionals.

    The emphases on qualications, tolerance of impreci-

    sion, and SEBKUS are not original. For example, Aristotle

    suggested them in The Nichomachean Ethics (I, 3). I have

    attempted to implement them in numerous places (Ennis,

    1964a, 1969b Ch. 5, 1981a, 1987a, 1987b, 1991c, 1996a,

    2001, 2004, 2006, 2007). But although they seem obvious

    to me, they are controversial, both in and out of philosophy.

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    10/68

    10 INQUIRY: CRITICAL THINKING ACROSS THE DISCIPLINES

    (c) Credibility of Sources

    Another feature I introduced that was not original,

    but that to my knowledge was new to the philosophical

    critical thinking literature is the emphasis on judging the

    credibility of sources.I introduced it in my dissertation,

    leaning heavily on a legal source, John Henry Wigmore.

    (Wigmore, 1942) In the rst denition/conception article(1962), I discussed credibility of sources and later, at

    the time of challenges to President Nixons credibility,

    elaborated the imprecision of credibility criteria (Ennis,

    1974a). I also incorporated credibility of sources in my

    second conception of critical thinking (Ennis, 1980, 1981b,

    1987a, 1991c, 1996a, 2002).

    Credibility of sources is now fairly widely accepted

    as an aspect of critical thinking. I suspect that it was

    not mentioned in early philosophical works on critical

    thinking because of philosophers traditional emphasis

    on argument and reasoning (especially deductive logic).

    However, I do realize that there was some philosophical

    concern with this topic, for example in consideration offallacies, and in Francis Bacons idols, but criteria for

    judging credibility of a source (such as the desirability

    of a sources not having a conict of interest) were not at

    that time advanced in the philosophical literature (so far

    as I know). However, they are in both of my conceptions

    of critical thinking.

    My Second Critical Thinking Denition and

    Conception of Critical Thinking

    Going beyond the special features of the rst de-

    nition/conception, (criteria, judgment/imprecision, and

    credibility of sources) my second denition/conception

    has several additional special features. These are (a) thedenition itself, (b) explicit inclusion of critical thinking

    dispositions, (c) qualied deduction, (d) detailing of as-

    sumption ascription, (e) expansion of inference-to-best-

    explanation, (f) special emphasis on equivocation, and (g)

    inclusion of value judging. All of these except the rst and

    the last, were present in some form or were implicit in the

    rst conception. I shall discuss each in turn.

    (a) The Denition

    John Dewey provided two informative examples of

    critical thinking inHow We Think.The rst involves what

    to believe about the cause of bubbling coming from under

    hot, recently-washed glasses (which involved formulat-

    ing alternative hypotheses and checking predictions from

    them with observations). The second concerned selecting

    a subway train for a timely trip to his destination (involv-

    ing alternative possible decisions, exploring their prob-

    able consequences, and making one decision, which was

    implemented and found satisfactory). He thus exemplied

    the two main emphases (belief and action) in my second

    and current denition of critical thinking:

    Critical thinking is reasonable reective

    thinking focused on deciding what to believe

    or do.(Ennis, 1987a, 1987b, 1991a, 1996a,

    2002).

    During the early 1980s when I was developing this

    denition, Gerald Nosich urged me to add or do tobelieve, on the ground that decisions about actions (not

    only decisions about beliefs) are a type of decision that is

    ordinarily included in the concerns of people in the criti-

    cal thinking movement and incorporated in their use of

    the term. I appreciate his suggestion and did implement it.

    It is not a precise denition, which fact bets the gen-

    eral imprecision in the everyday use of the term critical

    thinking (thus illustrating the tolerance of imprecision as

    suits the circumstances, which was a topic in the previ-

    ous section). If the denition is a true though imprecise

    report of usage in the critical thinking movement, which

    is what I hold it to be, then it describes the current no-

    tion of critical thinking in that movement. But it is alsopositional in that in offering it I take the position that this

    denition represents something worth implementing in

    our education system and elsewhere. So I offer it also as

    a defensible positional denition (a denition that takes a

    position on some issue for which rational arguments can

    be offered). I hold this position because I think that reason-

    able and reective thinking focused on what to believe or

    do should be a very important part of our personal, civic,

    and vocational lives, and should receive attention in our

    education system.

    (b) Dispositions

    The rst conception has been criticized for omittingcritical thinking dispositions (e.g., Siegel, 1988, p. 6), such

    as the dispositions to be open-minded, to try to be well

    informed, to be alert for alternatives, and to exercise ones

    critical thinking abilities. Although I believe that critical

    thinking dispositions are implicit in my rst conception, I

    explicitly included them in the second conception because

    they are so important and might otherwise be neglected.

    Over the years, I have reorganized my presentation of

    critical thinking dispositions (Ennis, 1987a, 1991c, 1996a,

    1996b, 2002). See the latest version in the appendix. It is a

    brief list with no examples, containing I believe the most

    important ones.

    (c) Qualied Deduction

    The basic ideas of deduction are important in many

    aspects of thought, as I argued in A Conception of De-

    ductive Logic Competence (Ennis, 1981a), although

    logical necessity is too strict for many practical ap-

    plications (discussed under Good Judgment above),

    and although material implication and its cohorts make

    trouble and must be ignored in critical thinking (Lewis,

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    11/68

    11SPRING 2011, VOL. 26, NO. 1

    C. I., 1912 and Strawson, P. F., 1952). Criteria for useful

    deduction have not been specied in most versions of my

    second conception of critical thinking in order to save

    space, but can be found in a few places (Ennis, 1969a,

    1969b, 1981a, 1996a, with further application discussed

    in 2004).

    Deduction is usually included in attempts by phi-losophers to teach critical thinking. What is unique in

    my conception is my emphasis on qualifying deductive

    reasoning so as to accommodate the implicit and explicit

    use of words like probably and ceteris paribus.The

    explicit rejection of material implication and its cohorts is

    not unique, but is controversial. Keeping deduction simple

    is also a feature of my approach, but it is not unique in the

    eld of critical thinking.

    (d) Assumption Ascription

    This second conception goes more deeply into types

    of assumptions and criteria for ascribing assumptions than

    is widely advocated, perhaps because of the complexityof the topic. Ordinarily students are urged to identify their

    and others assumptions, but are not told how to do this.

    There are different sorts of assumptions, which need

    to be distinguished from each other because different

    criteria apply to each. Some are presuppositions, which

    must be true for another proposition to make sense (but

    see Donnellan, 1966,1968). Some are assumptions in the

    pejorative sense. Some are also needed assumptions (called

    assumptions of the argument by Hitchcock, 1985),

    which, however, are not logically necessary conditions

    for drawing the conclusion, as some people think. And

    some are used assumptions (called assumptions of the

    arguer by Hitchcock, 1985), that is, those that someonecognitively used, either explicitly or implicitly. Reason-

    able space limits preclude giving more details here, but the

    distinctions and criteria for ascribing assumptions can be

    found most completely in Identifying Implicit Assump-

    tions (Ennis, 1982c), and to a lesser extent also in Critical

    Thinking(Ennis, 1996a), Argument Appraisal Strategy

    (Ennis, 2001), and Applying Soundness Standards to

    Qualied Reasoning (Ennis, 2004).

    (e) Inference-to-best-explanation

    Although inference-to-best-explanation (IBE) is well

    known in the philosophical literature as exemplied by

    Gilbert Harman (Harman, 1965, 1973), a discussion by

    me of one feature of Harmans approach (Ennis, 1968)

    with a reply by him, and Peter Liptons book (Lipton,

    2004). But outside of my work (Ennis, 1996a), IBE is not

    generally advocated in the critical thinking literature. There

    are three features about IBE that I should mention: (1) the

    confusion that might be introduced by the name, (2) its

    widespread applicability in elds other than science, and

    (3) its relation to causality.

    First with regard to a confusion, IBE basically consists

    of an approach to evaluation of hypotheses that considers

    the explanatory power of the hypothesis and the inability

    of competitors to explain evidence or the outright incon-

    sistency of the alternatives with the evidence. There are

    details that are more controversial. But calling it infer-

    ence might misleadingly suggest that it is a set of rules forgenerating hypotheses, that is, of inferring the hypothesis

    directly from the evidence, which it is not. Rather IBE is an

    approach containing a set of rules or criteria for evaluating

    a hypothesis, and in many situations is the evaluation part

    of the exploratory process of rening and developing a nal

    hypothesis, which is also evaluated by IBE.

    However, IBE can also be used as a label for the

    intuitive leap from the known facts in a situation to a

    hypothesis which should then be judged for its adequacy

    by the rules or criteria of IBE. Thus IBE is both an intui-

    tive generation and an approach to evaluating the product

    resulting from this intuitive process. This dual meaning

    can be confusing.Second, as far as applicability is concerned, IBE ap-

    plies not only to scientic hypotheses, but also to historical

    claims about what happened, such as, Napoleon died of

    arsenic poisoning; interpretive claims in literature, such

    as the claim that in Othello,Desdemonas maid, Emelia,

    never dreamed he [Iago] was a villain. (Bradley, 1937,

    p. 213 an example suggested to me by Bruce Warner).

    It also applies to test validity claims, such as a claim I have

    made to the effect that a particular critical thinking test is

    a substantially valid test of college-level critical thinking

    ability under standard conditions (Ennis, 2009). I have

    discussed the Napoleon and Emelia examples elsewhere

    (Ennis, 1996a).Third, to consider IBE in relation to causality, as I

    see it, all explanatory hypotheses that account for an oc-

    currence or type of occurrence are implicitly or explicitly

    causal. There are some, including Bertrand Russell, who

    have urged abandoning causality in our disciplined think-

    ing, and there are various views about what it is and how

    we identify it. This is a controversial area. In the past, I

    have argued that we should not abandon causality (Ennis,

    1982a), and that being a necessary condition for an effect

    is not necessarily necessary (Ennis, 1982b), contrary to

    necessary-condition and counterfactual analyses of specic

    (singular) causal claims, e.g., the analyses of John Mackie

    (1974) and David Lewis (1973). I have also tried to sketch

    out a broad picture of causality (Ennis, 1973), especially

    specic causal claims like The bad decisions by BP caused

    the 2010 Gulf oil spill and Lack of adequate regulation

    caused the spill (two seemingly inconsistent claims),

    and am now working on a sufcient-condition speech-act

    interpretation of specic causal claims. However, I am

    convinced that causality itself is an irreducible notion.

    There is still much work to be done here.

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    12/68

    12 INQUIRY: CRITICAL THINKING ACROSS THE DISCIPLINES

    (f) Equivocation

    Although equivocation is a standard item in a list of

    fallacies, I treat it as deserving special mention because

    it is particularly insidious. In my rst conception I called

    it merely ambiguity, but actually it is more serious than

    ambiguity. It is often connected with denitions, and I

    usually mention it in association with denitions. As I usethe term, equivocation is the process of shifting between

    two meanings of a term in an argument, generally proving

    a proposition using one sense of the term and applying the

    proposition using a different sense.

    For example someone might charge that my concep-

    tion of critical thinking is biased because it takes a posi-

    tion on what makes for good thinking. In this example the

    denition of bias that is assumed is that a person is biased

    if he or she has a position on something. But the applica-

    tion of the term bias seems to be a charge of unfairness

    (unfairness not having been mentioned in the denition of

    bias, but a characteristic ordinarily associated with the

    use of the term bias). So it seems to follow that criticalthinking is unfair, ifone ignores the shift in meaning. But

    of course, it does not follow.

    Actually, blatant cases of equivocation (in which the

    arguer explicitly adopts two meanings, and deliberately

    exploits the shift between them) are rare. Most actual cases

    of equivocation are more subtle, and must be uncovered

    by probing. One of the subtleties is in what I have called

    impact equivocation (Ennis, 1980) which is found in

    arguments that have the impact of equivocation but in

    which the arguer does not explicitly adopt both of the

    meanings of the crucial term. Rather the arguer adopts a

    special meaning for a term that is at variance with ordinary

    use of the audience, makes a statement using the term inthat special meaning, which will be taken by the audience

    to assume the ordinary meaning of the term, and thus be

    misleading. This sometimes happens with the word bias,

    and with the word reliability, a psychometric term used

    in the discussion of tests. Concern with equivocation,

    including impact equivocation, is one of the good things

    that was part of the ordinary-language movement inspired

    by the later Wittgenstein.

    (g) Value judgments

    Value judgments were omitted in my rst conception,

    making it what I then called a truncated conception.

    Appraising value judgments is an aspect of the second

    conception, and some criteria are offered, such as getting

    the facts straight (including facts about the likely conse-

    quences of an action), prima facie application of acceptable

    principles, and attention to alternatives. But a heavy dose

    of good judgment is needed as well.

    Two Overall Summaries

    (a) The appendix

    The Nature of Critical Thinking: An Outline of

    Critical Thinking Dispositions and Abilities, which is the

    appendix to this paper and is in outline form, contains all

    of the above-described second-conception ideas, as well

    as additional features that are fairly standard in the criticalthinking literature. This outline, though unexemplied, is

    comprehensive and thorough enough to be used in plan-

    ning for an overall curriculum, or as a basis for a table

    of specications for a critical thinking test or test series.

    But it makes for difcult reading if read straight through,

    especially for beginners, and it contains more than can be

    incorporated in an introductory course in critical thinking.

    (b) A brief summary of the second conception

    Table 1 provides a very brief (super-streamlined)

    overall presentation with neither listings of criteria nor

    detailed listing of aspects of critical thinking. I call it

    super-streamlined to show that it is a streamlined ver-sion of A streamlined conception of critical thinking

    (Ennis, 1991c) and other article-length presentations of the

    second conception. It also merges critical thinking abilities

    and dispositions. But it can be useful as someones rst

    encounter with critical thinking, or as a rough checklist for

    a students paper or thesis, or for anyones act of deciding

    what to believe or do.

    Table 1

    A Super-Streamlined Conception of

    Critical Thinking

    Assuming that critical thinking is reasonable reective thinkingfocused on deciding what to believe or do, a critical thinker:

    1. Is open-mindedand mindful of alternatives

    2. Desires to be, and is, well-informed

    3. Judges well the credibilityof sources

    4. Identies conclusions, reasons,and assumptions

    5. Asks appropriate clarifying questions

    6. Judges well the quality of an argument,including its reasons,

    assumptions, evidence,and their degree of support for the

    conclusion

    7. Can well developand defend a reasonable position,doing

    justice to challenges

    8. Formulatesplausible hypotheses

    9. Plans and conducts experimentswell

    10. Defnes termsin a way appropriate for the context

    11. Draws conclusions when warranted but with caution

    12. Integratesall items in this list

    Incidentally I have argued (Ennis, 1981c) that another

    brief characterization of good thinking, Benjamin Blooms

    popular Taxonomy of Educational Objectives: Cognitive

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    13/68

    13SPRING 2011, VOL. 26, NO. 1

    Domain (Bloom, 1956) is inspiring, but not very helpful

    as guidance. Among other things, its six categories do

    not have useful criteria that can be applied across top-

    ics and subject-matter areas. For example, his category,

    analysis, covers a range of important activities that vary

    considerably from, for example, chemistry to literature,

    with not much in common that is worth teaching as criti-cal thinking or higher-order thinking (a term in use by

    Blooms followers). There is not much to teach in general

    about analysis, making Blooms taxonomy vulnerable to

    McPecks (1981, 1990a) complaints about the emptiness

    of attempts to teach general thinking. However, in provid-

    ing a list with a ve-to-one ratio of thinking categories to

    knowledge (Bloom behaviorally dened knowledge

    as recall, but most people have taken it in its ordinary

    sense), his taxonomy is an apparently persuasive counter to

    demands for exclusive attention to subject-matter knowl-

    edge, as opposed to higher-order thinking.

    Other TopicsRelated to the second conception, though not explic-

    itly mentioned in it, is the relationship between critical

    thinking and creativity. In agreement with Sharon Bailin

    (1985), I hold that they are somewhat interdependent

    (Ennis, 1985). Judgments that some act of thinking is

    creative generally assume a positive evaluation of the

    thinking (thus requiring critical thinking). Furthermore,

    creativity is needed in generating hypotheses, denitions,

    and alternatives, in planning experiments, and conceiving

    of counter-examples.

    Another so-far-undiscussed topic in this essay is the

    possibility of critical thinkings being gender or culturally

    biased (Wheary & Ennis, 1995; Ennis, 1998). My view isthat critical thinking is basically not gender or culturally

    biased, as can be seen in a point-by-point examination of

    the second conception in the Appendix.

    Later, in the section labeled Teaching Critical Think-

    ing in Part II, I will consider the question of whether

    critical thinking is subject-specic, and the question of

    the appropriate allocation of responsibility for teaching

    critical thinking among various teachers, subject-matter

    areas, and other units. Both questions are related to ones

    conception of critical thinking, but perhaps better consid-

    ered under teaching.

    [To be continued inINQUIRYVol. 26, No. 2 (Sum-

    mer 2011).]

    References

    Aiken, W. M. (1942). The story of the eight-year study.New

    York: Harper & Brothers.

    The American Philosophical Association (1985). Board of Of-

    cers statement on critical thinking. Proceedings of the

    American Philosophical Association, 58, 484.

    Anderson, H. R. (1942). Teaching critical thinking in the social

    studies.Washington: The National Council for the Social

    Studies.

    Bailin, S. (1985). Creativity and quality. In E. Robertson (Ed.),

    Philosophy of education 1984 (Proceedings of the fortieth

    annual meeting of the Philosophy of Education Society).

    Normal, IL: Philosophy of Education Society.

    Beardsley, M. (1950).Practical logic.New York: Prentice Hall.Black, M. (1946). Critical thinking.New York: Prentice Hall.

    Bloom, B. S. (Ed.), (1956). Taxonomy of educational objectives

    The classication of educational goals Handbook 1:

    The cognitive domain.New York: Longmans Green and Co.

    Boyer, E. (1983).High school.New York: Harper & Rowe.

    Bradley, A. C. (1937). Shakespearean tragedy.London: Mac-

    millan.

    Cohen, M. B., & Nagel, E. (1934).An introduction to logic and

    scientic method.New York: Harcourt Brace.

    College Board (1983).Academic preparation for college.New

    York College Entrance Examination Board.

    Commission on the Humanities (1980). The humanities in

    American life. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Conant, J. B. (1951). On understanding science.New York,Mentor.

    Conant, J. B. (Ed.) (1950-1954).Harvard case histories in experi-

    mental science, #1 through #8.Cambridge, MA: Harvard.

    Conant, J. B. (1959). The American high school today: A rst

    report to interested citizens.New York: McGraw-Hill Book

    Company.

    Dewey, J. (1933, rst edition 1910).How we think.Boston: D.

    C. Heath.

    Donnellan, K. S. (1966). Reference and denite descriptions.

    The Philosophical Review, 75, 281-304.

    Donnellan, K. S. (1968). Putting Humpty Dumpty together again.

    The Philosophical Review, 77, 203-315.

    Ennis, R. H. (May, 1956). Critical thinking: More on its motiva-

    tion.Progressive Education,75-78.Ennis, R. H. (1958). An appraisal of the Watson-Glaser critical

    thinking appraisal. Journal of Educational Research, 52,

    155-158.

    Ennis, R. H. (1959a). The impossibility of neutrality.Harvard

    Educational Review, 29, 128-136. Reprinted as Is it impos-

    sible for the schools to be neutral? (1961),Language and

    concepts in education,1961, B. O. Smith, & R. H. Ennis

    (Eds.), Chicago: Rand McNally and Company, pp. 102-111;

    and (1971) Es imposible que las escueles sean neutrales?

    in B. O. Smith, & R. H. Ennis (Eds.),Lenguaje y conceptos

    en la educacion,1971, Buenos Aires: Al Ateneo, 113-123.

    Ennis, R. H. (1959b). The development of a critical thinking test.

    Unpublished doctoral dissertation. Urbana-Champaign, IL:

    University of Illinois, University Microlms #59-00505.Ennis, R. H. (1961). Assumption-nding. In B. O. Smith, &

    R. H. Ennis (Eds.), Language and concepts in education.

    Chicago: Rand McNally and Company, pp. 161-178. Re-

    printed as La identicacion de supestos, in B. O. Smith, &

    R. H. Ennis (Eds.),Lenguaje y conceptos en la educacion,

    1971, Buenos Aires: El Ateneo, 177-194.

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    14/68

    14 INQUIRY: CRITICAL THINKING ACROSS THE DISCIPLINES

    Ennis, R. H. (1962). A concept of critical thinking. Harvard

    Educational Review, 32, pp. 81-111. Reprinted in B. P.

    Komisar, & C. J. B. Macmillan (Eds.), Psychological

    concepts in education,1967, Chicago: Rand McNally and

    Company, 114-148.

    Ennis, R. H. (1964a). Operational denitions.American Educa-

    tional Research Journal, 1, 183-201.

    Ennis, Robert H. (1964b). A denition of critical thinking. TheReading Teacher, 17(8), 599-612.

    Ennis, R. H. (1968). Enumerative induction and best explanation.

    The Journal of Philosophy, 65, 523-530.

    Ennis, R. H. (1969a).Logic in teaching.Englewood Cliffs, NJ:

    Prentice-Hall.

    Ennis, R. H. (1969b). Ordinary logic. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:

    Prentice-Hall.

    Ennis, R. H. (1969c). Operationism can and should be divorced

    from covering law assumptions (a reprint of Operational

    Denitions (1964). In L. I. Krimerman (Ed.), The nature

    and scope of social science: A critical anthology,1969, New

    York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 431-444.

    Ennis, R. H. (1969d). The possibility of neutrality. Journal of

    Educational Theory, 19, 347-356.Ennis, R. H. (1973). On causality. Educational Researcher,

    2(6), 4-11.

    Ennis, R. H. (1974a). The believability of people. Educational

    Forum, 38, 347-354.

    Ennis, R. H. (1974b). Denition in science teaching.Instructional

    Science, 3, 285-298.

    Ennis, R. H. (1979). Research in philosophy of science and

    science education. In P. Asquith, & H. Kyburg (Eds.), Cur-

    rent research in philosophy of science.East Lansing, MI:

    Philosophy of Science Association, 138-170.

    Ennis, R. H. (1980). Presidential address: A conception of rational

    thinking. In J. Coombs (Ed.),Philosophy of education 1979.

    Bloomington, IL: Philosophy of Education Society, 1-30.

    Ennis, R. H. (1981a). A conception of deductive logic compe-tence. Teaching Philosophy, 4, 337-385.

    Ennis, R. H. (1981b) Rational thinking and educational practice.

    In J. Soltis (Ed.),Philosophy of education 1981 (Eightieth

    yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Educa-

    tion, Part I). Chicago: The National Society for the Study

    of Education, 143-183.

    Ennis, R. H. (1981c). Eight fallacies in Blooms taxonomy. In

    C. J. B. Macmillan (Ed.), Philosophy of education 1980.

    Bloomington, IL: Philosophy of Education Society, 269-

    273.

    Ennis, R. H. (1982a). Abandon causality? Educational Re-

    searcher, 11(7), 25-27.

    Ennis, R. H. (1982b). Mackies singular causality and linked

    overdetermination. In P. D. Asquith, & T. Nickles (Eds.),PSA 1982. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science As-

    sociation, 55-64.

    Ennis, R. H. (1982c). Identifying implicit assumptions. Synthese,

    51, 61-86.

    Ennis, R. H. (1985). Quality and creativity. In E. Robertson (Ed.),

    Philosophy of education, 1984(pp. 323-328). Bloomington,

    IL: Philosophy of Education Society.

    Ennis, R. H. (1987a). A taxonomy of critical thinking dispositions

    and abilities. In J. Baron & R. Sternberg (Eds.), Teaching

    thinking skills: Theory and practice.New York: W. H.

    Freeman, 9-26.

    Ennis, R. H. (1987b). A conception of critical thinking With

    some curriculum suggestions.APA Newsletter on Teaching

    Philosophy, Summer, 1-5.

    Ennis, R. H. (1991a). The State of Illinois goals and sample learn-ing objectives for scientic thinking and methods: Strengths,

    weaknesses and suggestions. Spectrum, 17(1), 10-16.

    Ennis, R. H. (1991b). An elaboration of a cardinal goal of science

    instruction: Scientic thinking.Educational Philosophy and

    Theory, 23(1), 31-45.

    Ennis, R. H. (1991c). Critical thinking: A streamlined conception.

    Teaching Philosophy, 14(1), 5-25.

    Ennis, R. H. (1996a) Critical thinking.Upper Saddle River, NJ:

    Prentice-Hall.

    Ennis, R. H. (1996b). Critical thinking dispositions: Their nature

    and assessability.Informal Logic, 18(2 & 3), 165-182 .

    Ennis, R. H. (March, 1998). Is critical thinking culturally biased?

    Teaching Philosophy, 21(1), 15-33.

    Ennis, R. H. (2001). Argument appraisal strategy: A comprehen-sive approach.Informal Logic, 21(2), 97-140.

    Ennis, Robert H. (2002). Goals for a critical thinking curriculum

    and its assessment. In A. L. Costa (Ed.),Developing minds

    (3rd Edition).Alexandria, VA: ASCD, 44-46.

    Ennis, R. H. (2004). Applying soundness standards to qualied

    reasoning.Informal Logic, 24(1), 23-39.

    Ennis, R. H. (2006). Probably. In D. Hitchcock, & B. Verheij

    (Eds.),Arguing on the Toulmin model.Dordrecht, Nether-

    lands: Springer, 145-164.

    Ennis, R. H. (2007). Probable and its equivalents. In H. V.

    Hansen & R. C. Pinto (Eds.), Reason reclaimed:Essays in

    honor of J. Anthony Blair and Ralph H. Johnson.Newport

    News, VA: Vale Press, 243-256.

    Ennis, R. H. (2009). Investigating and assessing multiple-choicecritical thinking tests. In J. Sobocan, & L. Groarke (Eds.),

    Critical thinking education and assessment: Can higher

    order thinking be tested?London, Ontario, CA: Althouse,

    75-97.

    Ennis, R. H. (in process). Situational test validity.

    Facione, P. A. (1990). Critical thinking: A statement of expert

    consensus for purposes of educational assessment and

    instruction (Executive summary of The Delphi Report)

    Millbrae, CA: California Academic Press.

    Harman, G. (1965). The inference to the best explanation.Philo-

    sophical Review, 74(1), 88-95.

    Harman, G. (1968). Enumerative induction as inference to the

    best explanation.Journal of Philosophy, 65(18), 529-533.

    Harman, G. (1973). Thought.Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer-sity Press.

    Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The concept of law.Oxford: The Claren-

    don Press.

    Hitchcock, D. (1985). Enthymematic arguments.Informal Logic,

    7(2 & 3), 83-97.

    Institute for Propaganda Analysis (1938).Propaganda analysis.

    New York: Columbia University Press.

    Kahane, H. (1971).Logic and contemporary rhetoric.Belmont,

    CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company.

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    15/68

    15SPRING 2011, VOL. 26, NO. 1

    Lewis, C. I. (1912). Implication and the algebra of logic.Mind,

    522-531.

    Lewis, D. (1973). Causation.Journal of Philosophy, 70, 556567.

    Lipton, P. (2004).Inference to best explanation.London: Rout-

    ledge.

    Mackie, J. L. (1974). The cement of the universe.Oxford: Clar-

    endon Press.

    McPeck, J. (1981). Critical thinking and education.New York:St. Martins Press.

    McPeck, J. (1990a). Teaching critical thinking. New York:

    Routledge.

    McPeck, J. (1990b). Critical thinking and subject specicity:

    A reply to Ennis.Educational Researcher, 19(4), 10-12.

    Nosich, G. (2010). From argument and philosophy to critical

    thinking across the curriculum.INQUIRY: Critical Thinking

    Across the Disciplines, 25(3), 4-13.

    Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice.Cambridge, MA: The

    Belknap Press.

    Roth, M. (2010). Beyond critical thinking. The Chronicle of

    Higher Education, January 3.

    Siegel, H. (1988).Educating reason.New York: Routledge.

    Smith, B. O. (March, 1953). The improvement of critical think-ing.Progressive Education, 30(5), 130.

    Smith E. R., & Tyler, R. W. (1942). Appraising and recording

    student progress.New York: Harper & Brothers.

    Strawson, P. F. (1952).Introduction to logical theory.London:

    Methuen & Co.

    Werkmeister, W. H. (1948).An introduction to critical thinking,

    2nd Edition.Lincoln, NE: Johnsen Publishing Co.

    Wheary, J., & Ennis, R. H. (1995). Gender bias in critical think-

    ing: continuing the dialogue. Educational Theory, 45(2),

    213-224.

    Wigmore, J. H. (1942). Wigmores code of the rules of evidence

    in trials at law, 3rd Edition. Boston: Little Brown and Co,

    Web sites

    AILACT Web Site: ailact.mcmaster.ca/

    Ennis, Robert H. Academic Web Site: faculty.ed.uiuc.edu/rhennis

    Ennis, Robert H. Critical Thinking Web Site: www.criticalth-

    inking.net

    Appendix

    The Nature of Critical Thinking: An Outline of

    Critical Thinking Dispositions and Abilities3

    Critical thinking is reasonable and reective think-

    ing focused on deciding what to believe or do.Thisdenition I believe captures the core of the way the term

    is used in the critical thinking movement. In deciding what

    to believe or do, one is helped by the employment of a set

    of critical thinking dispositions and abilities that I shall

    outline. These can serve as a set of comprehensive goals

    for a critical thinking curriculum and its assessment. Use-

    fulness in curriculum decisions, teaching, and assessment,

    not elegance or mutual exclusiveness, is the purpose of this

    outline. For the sake of brevity, clarication in the form of

    examples, qualications, and more detail, including more

    criteria, are omitted, but can be found in sources listed

    below, but most fully in my Critical Thinking(1996a).

    This outline is the encapsulation of many years of

    work in the elaboration of the simple denition of critical

    thinking given above, and it distinguishes between criticalthinking dispositions and abilities.

    It is only a critical thinking contentoutline. It does not

    specify grade level, curriculum sequence, emphasis, teach-

    ing approach, or type of subject-matter content involved

    (standard subject-matter content, general knowledge

    content, streetwise-knowledge content, special knowledge

    content, etc.). For assessment purposes it can only provide

    a basis for developing a table of specications and the

    preparation of assessment rubrics.

    Critical Thinking Dispositions

    Ideal critical thinkers are disposed to

    1. Care that their beliefs be true,4and that their decisions

    be justied; that is, care to get it right to the extent

    possible; including to

    a. Seek alternative hypotheses, explanations, conclu-

    sions, plans, sources, etc.; and be open to them

    b. Consider seriously other points of view than their

    own

    c. Try to be well informed

    d. Endorse a position to the extent that, but only to the

    extent that, it is justied by the information that is

    available

    e. Use their critical thinking abilities

    2. Care to understand and present a position honestly

    and clearly, theirs as well as others; including to

    a. Discover and listen to others view and reasons

    b. Be clear about the intended meaning of what is

    said, written, or otherwise communicated, seeking

    as much precision as the situation requires

    c. Determine, and maintain focus on, the conclusion

    or question

    d. Seek and offer reasons

    e. Take into account the total situation

    f. Be reectively aware of their own basic beliefs

    3. Care about every person. (This one is an auxiliary,

    not constitutive, disposition. Although this concern

    for people is not constitutive, critical thinking can be

    dangerous without it.) Caring critical thinkers

    a. Avoid intimidating or confusing others with their

    critical thinking prowess, taking into account others

    feelings and level of understanding

    b. Are concerned about others welfare

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    16/68

    16 INQUIRY: CRITICAL THINKING ACROSS THE DISCIPLINES

    Critical Thinking Abilities

    The following abilities numbered 1 to 3 involve basic

    clarication; 4 and 5, the bases for a decision; 6 to 8,

    inference; 9 and 10, advanced clarication; and 11 and

    12, supposition and integration. Abilities 13 to 15 are

    auxiliary abilities, not constitutive of critical thinking,but very helpful.

    Ideal critical thinkers have the ability to:

    (Basic Clarication, 1 to 3)

    1. Focuson a question:

    a. Identify or formulate a question

    b. Identify or formulate criteria for judging possible

    answers

    c. Keep the question and situation in mind

    2. Analyze arguments:

    a. Identify conclusions

    b. Identify reasons or premises c. Ascribe or identify simple assumptions (see also

    ability 10)

    c. Identify and handle irrelevance

    d. See the structure of an argument

    e. Summarize

    3. Ask and answer clarication and/or challenge ques-

    tions, such as:

    a. Why?

    b. What is your main point?

    c. What do you mean by______________________?

    d. What would be an example?

    e. What would not be an example (though close tobeing one)?

    f. How does that apply to this case (describe a case,

    which appears to be a counterexample)?

    g. What difference does it make?

    h. What are the facts?

    i. Is this what you are saying:__________________?

    j. Would you say more about that?

    (Two Bases for a Decision: 4 and 5)

    4. Judge the credibilityof a source. Major criteria(but

    not necessary conditions):

    a. Expertise

    b. Lack of conict of interest

    c. Agreement with other sources

    d. Reputation

    e. Use of established procedures

    f. Known risk to reputation (the sources knowing of

    a risk to reputation, if wrong)

    g. Ability to give reasons

    h. Careful habits

    5. Observe, and judge observation reports. Major

    criteria (but not necessary conditions, except for

    the rst):

    a. Minimal inferring involved

    b. Short time interval between observation and report

    c. Report by the observer, rather than someone else

    (that is, the report is not hearsay)d. Provision of records

    e. Corroboration

    f. Possibility of corroboration

    g. Good access

    h. Competent employment of technology, if technol-

    ogy applies

    i. Satisfaction by observer (and reporter, if a differ-

    ent person) of the credibility criteria in Ability # 4

    above (Note: A third basis is your own established

    conclusions.)

    (Inference, 6 to 8)

    6. Deduce, and judge deduction:a. Class logic

    b. Conditional logic

    c. Interpretation of logical terminology, including

    i. Negation and double negation

    ii. Necessary and sufcient condition language

    iii. Such words as only, if and only if, or,

    some, unless, and not both

    d. Qualied deductive reasoning (a loosening for

    practical purposes)

    7. Make material inferences(roughly induction):

    a. To generalizations. Broad considerations:

    i. Typicality of data, including valid samplingwhere appropriate

    ii. Volume of instances

    iii. Conformity of instances to generalization

    iv. Having a principled way of dealing with outliers

    b. To explanatory hypotheses (IBE: inference-to-

    best-explanation):

    i. Major types of explanatory conclusions and

    hypotheses:

    a.Specic and general causal claims

    b.Claims about the beliefs and attitudes of

    people

    c.Interpretation of authors intended meanings

    d.Historical claims that certain things happened

    (including criminal accusations)

    e.Reported denitions

    f.Claims that some proposition is an unstated,

    but used, reason

    ii. Characteristic investigative activities

    a.Designing experiments, including planning

    to control variables

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    17/68

    17SPRING 2011, VOL. 26, NO. 1

    b.Seeking evidence and counterevidence, in-

    cluding statistical signicance

    c.Seeking other possible explanations

    iii. Criteria, the rst four being essential, the fth

    being desirable

    a.The proposed conclusion would explain or

    help explain the evidenceb.The proposed conclusion is consistent with

    all known facts

    c.Competitive alternative explanations are

    inconsistent with facts

    d.A competent sincere effort has been made

    to nd supporting and opposing data, and

    alternative hypotheses

    e.The proposed conclusion seems plausible and

    simple, tting into the broader picture

    8. Make and judge value judgments

    Important factors:

    a. Background factsb. Consequences of accepting or rejecting the judg-

    ment

    c. Prima facie application of acceptable principles

    d. Alternatives

    e. Balancing, weighing, deciding

    (Advanced Clarication, 9 and 10)

    9. Dene terms and judge denitions, using appropriate

    criteria

    Three basic dimensions are form, function (act),

    and content. A fourth, more advanced dimension is

    handling equivocation.

    a. Denition form. For criteria for 1 through 4 and6, see Ennis (1996, Ch 12 & 13). For #5 see Ennis

    (1964, 1969c).

    i. Synonym

    ii. Classication

    iii. Range

    iv. Equivalent-expression

    v. Operational

    vi. Example and non-example

    b. Denitional functions (acts)

    i. Report a meaning (criteria: the ve for an ex-

    planatory hypothesis)

    ii. Stipulate a meaning (criteria: convenience,

    consistency, avoidance of impact equivocation)

    iii. Express a position on an issue (positional deni-

    tions, including programmatic and persua-

    sive denitions) Criteria: those for a position

    (Ennis 2001)

    c. Content of the denition

    d. Identifying and handling equivocation (Ennis 1996)

    10. Attribute unstated assumptions(an ability that belongs

    under both basic clarication(2b) and inference(7bif)

    a. Pejorative avor (dubiousness or falsity): com-

    monly but not always associated to some degree

    with the different types. Criteria: See #8 above.

    b. Types:

    i. Presuppositions (required for a proposition tomake sense)

    ii. Needed assumptions (needed by the reasoning

    to be at its strongest, but not logically necessary

    (Ennis 1982)), (called assumptions of the argu-

    ment by Hitchcock (1985))

    iii. Used assumptions (judged by hypothesis-testing

    criteria, Ennis 1982), called assumptions of the

    arguer by Hitchcock (1985)

    (Supposition and Integration, 11 and 12)

    11. Consider and reason from premises, reasons, assump-

    tions, positions, and other propositions with which

    they disagree or about which they are in doubt, withoutletting the disagreement or doubt interfere with their

    thinking (suppositional thinking)

    12. Integrate the dispositions and other abilities in making

    and defending a decision

    (Auxiliary abilities,13 to 15)

    13. Proceed in an orderly manner appropriate to the situ-

    ation:

    a. Follow problem solvingsteps

    b. Monitor their own thinking (that is, engage in

    metacognition)

    c. Employ a reasonable critical thinking checklist

    14. Be sensitiveto the feelings, level of knowledge, and

    degree of sophistication of others

    15. Employ appropriate rhetoricalstrategies in discussion

    and presentation (oral and written), including employ-

    ing and reacting to fallacylabels in an appropriate

    manner. Examples of fallacy labels are circularity,

    bandwagon, post hoc, equivocation, non se-

    quitur, and straw person

    Summary and Comments

    In brief, the ideal critical thinker is disposed to try to

    get it right, to present a position honestly and clearly, and

    to care about others (this last being auxiliary, not constitu-

    tive); furthermore the ideal critical thinker has the ability

    to clarify, to seek and judge well the basis for a view, to

    infer wisely from the basis, to imaginatively suppose and

    integrate, and to do these things with dispatch, sensitivity,

    and rhetorical skill.

  • 8/13/2019 Gillespie 2011 Inquiry

    18/68

    18 INQUIRY: CRITICAL THINKING ACROSS THE DISCIPLINES

    In presenting this outline of critical thinking disposi-

    tions and abilities, I have only attempted to depict, rather

    than defend, them. The defense would require much more

    space than is available, but would follow two general paths:

    1) examining the traditions of good thinking in existing

    successful disciplines of inquiry, and 2) seeing how we go

    wrong when we attempt to decide what to believe or do.In any teaching situation for which critical thinking

    is a goal, whether it be a separate critical thinking course

    or module, or one in which the critical thinking content

    is infused in (making critical thinking principles explicit)

    or immersed in (not making critical thinking principles

    explicit) standard subject-matter content, or some mixture

    of these; all of the dispositions, as well as the suppositional

    and integrational abilities (# 11 and #12) and auxiliary

    abilities (#13 through #15) are applicable all the time and

    should permeate the instruction to the extent that time and

    student ability permit.

    I have only attempted to outline a usable and de-

    fensible set of critical thinking goals, including criteriafor making judgments