expected utility and risk aversionluca/econ2100/2018class/lecture_12.pdf · unlike risk aversion,...

121
Expected Utility And Risk Aversion Econ 2100 Fall 2018 Lecture 12, October 8 Outline 1 Risk Aversion 2 Certainty Equivalent 3 Risk Premium 4 Relative Risk Aversion 5 Stochastic Dominance

Upload: others

Post on 25-Sep-2020

4 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Expected Utility And Risk Aversion

Econ 2100 Fall 2018

Lecture 12, October 8

Outline

1 Risk Aversion2 Certainty Equivalent3 Risk Premium4 Relative Risk Aversion5 Stochastic Dominance

Page 2: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Notation From Last Class

A cumulative distribution function (cdf) is a function F : R→ [0, 1] which isnondecreasing, right continuous, and goes from 0 to 1.

µF denotes the mean (expected value) of F , i.e. µF =∫x dF (x).

δx is the degenerate distribution function at x ; i.e. δx yields x with certainty:

δx (z) =

{0 if z < x1 if z ≥ x

.

Given some F , δµF =

{0 if z <µF1 if z ≥µF

is a probability distribution that yields the

expected value of F for sure.

Preferences are over cumulative distributions.

Page 3: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion

DefinitionsThe preference relation % is

risk averse if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

δµF % F .risk loving if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

F % δµF .

risk neutral if it is both risk averse and risk loving (δµF ∼ F ).

DM is risk averse if she always prefers the expected value µF for sure to theuncertain distribution F .

This definition does not depend on the expected utility representation (or anyother).

Risk attitudes are defined directly from preferences.

Page 4: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion

DefinitionsThe preference relation % is

risk averse if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

δµF % F .risk loving if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

F % δµF .

risk neutral if it is both risk averse and risk loving (δµF ∼ F ).

DM is risk averse if she always prefers the expected value µF for sure to theuncertain distribution F .

This definition does not depend on the expected utility representation (or anyother).

Risk attitudes are defined directly from preferences.

Page 5: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion

DefinitionsThe preference relation % is

risk averse if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

δµF % F .risk loving if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

F % δµF .

risk neutral if it is both risk averse and risk loving (δµF ∼ F ).

DM is risk averse if she always prefers the expected value µF for sure to theuncertain distribution F .

This definition does not depend on the expected utility representation (or anyother).

Risk attitudes are defined directly from preferences.

Page 6: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion

DefinitionsThe preference relation % is

risk averse if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

δµF % F .risk loving if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

F % δµF .

risk neutral if it is both risk averse and risk loving (δµF ∼ F ).

DM is risk averse if she always prefers the expected value µF for sure to theuncertain distribution F .

This definition does not depend on the expected utility representation (or anyother).

Risk attitudes are defined directly from preferences.

Page 7: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion

DefinitionsThe preference relation % is

risk averse if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

δµF % F .risk loving if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

F % δµF .

risk neutral if it is both risk averse and risk loving (δµF ∼ F ).

DM is risk averse if she always prefers the expected value µF for sure to theuncertain distribution F .

This definition does not depend on the expected utility representation (or anyother).

Risk attitudes are defined directly from preferences.

Page 8: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion

DefinitionsThe preference relation % is

risk averse if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

δµF % F .risk loving if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

F % δµF .

risk neutral if it is both risk averse and risk loving (δµF ∼ F ).

DM is risk averse if she always prefers the expected value µF for sure to theuncertain distribution F .

This definition does not depend on the expected utility representation (or anyother).

Risk attitudes are defined directly from preferences.

Page 9: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion

DefinitionsThe preference relation % is

risk averse if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

δµF % F .risk loving if, for all cumulative distribution functions F ,

F % δµF .

risk neutral if it is both risk averse and risk loving (δµF ∼ F ).

DM is risk averse if she always prefers the expected value µF for sure to theuncertain distribution F .

This definition does not depend on the expected utility representation (or anyother).

Risk attitudes are defined directly from preferences.

Page 10: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion: An example

ExerciseLet % be a preference relation on the space of all cumulative distribution functionsrepresented by the following utility function:

U(F ) =

{x if F = δx for some x ∈ R0 otherwise

True of false: % is risk averse.False: If µF < 0, then F � µF .

Page 11: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion: An example

ExerciseLet % be a preference relation on the space of all cumulative distribution functionsrepresented by the following utility function:

U(F ) =

{x if F = δx for some x ∈ R0 otherwise

True of false: % is risk averse.False: If µF < 0, then F � µF .

Page 12: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion: An example

ExerciseLet % be a preference relation on the space of all cumulative distribution functionsrepresented by the following utility function:

U(F ) =

{x if F = δx for some x ∈ R0 otherwise

True of false: % is risk averse.False: If µF < 0, then F � µF .

Page 13: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Certainty Equivalent

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the certaintyequivalent (CE) of F , denoted c(F , v), is defined by

v(c(F , v)) =

∫v (·) dF .

By definition, the certainty equivalent of F is the amount of wealth c(·) suchthat c(·) ∼ F .

DM is indifferent between a distribution and the certainty equivalent of thatdistribution.The certainty equivalent is constructed to satisfy this indifference.

One can compare two lotteries by comparing their certainty equivalents.

Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent definition assumes a givenpreference representation (needs some utility function that representspreferences).

The value of the certainty equivalent is related to risk aversion.

Page 14: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Certainty Equivalent

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the certaintyequivalent (CE) of F , denoted c(F , v), is defined by

v(c(F , v)) =

∫v (·) dF .

By definition, the certainty equivalent of F is the amount of wealth c(·) suchthat c(·) ∼ F .

DM is indifferent between a distribution and the certainty equivalent of thatdistribution.The certainty equivalent is constructed to satisfy this indifference.

One can compare two lotteries by comparing their certainty equivalents.

Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent definition assumes a givenpreference representation (needs some utility function that representspreferences).

The value of the certainty equivalent is related to risk aversion.

Page 15: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Certainty Equivalent

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the certaintyequivalent (CE) of F , denoted c(F , v), is defined by

v(c(F , v)) =

∫v (·) dF .

By definition, the certainty equivalent of F is the amount of wealth c(·) suchthat c(·) ∼ F .

DM is indifferent between a distribution and the certainty equivalent of thatdistribution.The certainty equivalent is constructed to satisfy this indifference.

One can compare two lotteries by comparing their certainty equivalents.

Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent definition assumes a givenpreference representation (needs some utility function that representspreferences).

The value of the certainty equivalent is related to risk aversion.

Page 16: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Certainty Equivalent

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the certaintyequivalent (CE) of F , denoted c(F , v), is defined by

v(c(F , v)) =

∫v (·) dF .

By definition, the certainty equivalent of F is the amount of wealth c(·) suchthat c(·) ∼ F .

DM is indifferent between a distribution and the certainty equivalent of thatdistribution.The certainty equivalent is constructed to satisfy this indifference.

One can compare two lotteries by comparing their certainty equivalents.

Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent definition assumes a givenpreference representation (needs some utility function that representspreferences).

The value of the certainty equivalent is related to risk aversion.

Page 17: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Certainty Equivalent

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the certaintyequivalent (CE) of F , denoted c(F , v), is defined by

v(c(F , v)) =

∫v (·) dF .

By definition, the certainty equivalent of F is the amount of wealth c(·) suchthat c(·) ∼ F .

DM is indifferent between a distribution and the certainty equivalent of thatdistribution.The certainty equivalent is constructed to satisfy this indifference.

One can compare two lotteries by comparing their certainty equivalents.

Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent definition assumes a givenpreference representation (needs some utility function that representspreferences).

The value of the certainty equivalent is related to risk aversion.

Page 18: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Certainty Equivalent

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the certaintyequivalent (CE) of F , denoted c(F , v), is defined by

v(c(F , v)) =

∫v (·) dF .

By definition, the certainty equivalent of F is the amount of wealth c(·) suchthat c(·) ∼ F .

DM is indifferent between a distribution and the certainty equivalent of thatdistribution.The certainty equivalent is constructed to satisfy this indifference.

One can compare two lotteries by comparing their certainty equivalents.

Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent definition assumes a givenpreference representation (needs some utility function that representspreferences).

The value of the certainty equivalent is related to risk aversion.

Page 19: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Certainty Equivalent

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the certaintyequivalent (CE) of F , denoted c(F , v), is defined by

v(c(F , v)) =

∫v (·) dF .

By definition, the certainty equivalent of F is the amount of wealth c(·) suchthat c(·) ∼ F .

DM is indifferent between a distribution and the certainty equivalent of thatdistribution.The certainty equivalent is constructed to satisfy this indifference.

One can compare two lotteries by comparing their certainty equivalents.

Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent definition assumes a givenpreference representation (needs some utility function that representspreferences).

The value of the certainty equivalent is related to risk aversion.

Page 20: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Premium

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the riskpremium of F , denoted r(F , v) is defined by

r(F , v) = µF − c(F , v).

This measures the difference between the expected value of a particulardistribution and its certainty equivalent.

The definition of risk premium also assumes a given preference representation.

This is related to risk aversion.

Page 21: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Premium

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the riskpremium of F , denoted r(F , v) is defined by

r(F , v) = µF − c(F , v).

This measures the difference between the expected value of a particulardistribution and its certainty equivalent.

The definition of risk premium also assumes a given preference representation.

This is related to risk aversion.

Page 22: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Premium

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the riskpremium of F , denoted r(F , v) is defined by

r(F , v) = µF − c(F , v).

This measures the difference between the expected value of a particulardistribution and its certainty equivalent.

The definition of risk premium also assumes a given preference representation.

This is related to risk aversion.

Page 23: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Premium

DefinitionGiven a strictly increasing and continuous vNM index v over wealth, the riskpremium of F , denoted r(F , v) is defined by

r(F , v) = µF − c(F , v).

This measures the difference between the expected value of a particulardistribution and its certainty equivalent.

The definition of risk premium also assumes a given preference representation.

This is related to risk aversion.

Page 24: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, Certainty Equivalent, and RiskPremium

If preferences satisfy the vNM axioms, risk aversion is completely characterizedby concavity of the utility index and a non-negative risk-premium.

Proposition

Suppose % has an expected utility representation and v is the corresponding vonNeumann and Morgestern utility index over money.The following are equivalent:

1 % is risk averse;2 v is concave;3 r(F , v) ≥ 0;

The proof uses Jensen’s inequality.

Page 25: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, Certainty Equivalent, and RiskPremium

If preferences satisfy the vNM axioms, risk aversion is completely characterizedby concavity of the utility index and a non-negative risk-premium.

Proposition

Suppose % has an expected utility representation and v is the corresponding vonNeumann and Morgestern utility index over money.The following are equivalent:

1 % is risk averse;2 v is concave;3 r(F , v) ≥ 0;

The proof uses Jensen’s inequality.

Page 26: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, Certainty Equivalent, and RiskPremium

If preferences satisfy the vNM axioms, risk aversion is completely characterizedby concavity of the utility index and a non-negative risk-premium.

Proposition

Suppose % has an expected utility representation and v is the corresponding vonNeumann and Morgestern utility index over money.The following are equivalent:

1 % is risk averse;2 v is concave;3 r(F , v) ≥ 0;

The proof uses Jensen’s inequality.

Page 27: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, Certainty Equivalent, and RiskPremium

If preferences satisfy the vNM axioms, risk aversion is completely characterizedby concavity of the utility index and a non-negative risk-premium.

Proposition

Suppose % has an expected utility representation and v is the corresponding vonNeumann and Morgestern utility index over money.The following are equivalent:

1 % is risk averse;2 v is concave;3 r(F , v) ≥ 0;

The proof uses Jensen’s inequality.

Page 28: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, Certainty Equivalent, and RiskPremium

If preferences satisfy the vNM axioms, risk aversion is completely characterizedby concavity of the utility index and a non-negative risk-premium.

Proposition

Suppose % has an expected utility representation and v is the corresponding vonNeumann and Morgestern utility index over money.The following are equivalent:

1 % is risk averse;2 v is concave;3 r(F , v) ≥ 0;

The proof uses Jensen’s inequality.

Page 29: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Jensen’s InequalityJensen’s inequalityA function g is concave if and only if∫

g (x) dF ≤ g(∫

xdF)

This saysg(E(X )) ≥ E(g(X ))

Consequences of Jensen’s inequality

Hence, v(·) is concave if and only if∫vdF︸ ︷︷ ︸

expected utility of F

≤ v(∫

dF)

︸ ︷︷ ︸utility of the expected value of F

Since v is non decreasing,

c(F , v) ≤∫vdF is equivalent to v (c(F , v)) ≤ v

(∫vdF

)or ∫

v dF ≤ v(∫

vdF)

Page 30: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Jensen’s InequalityJensen’s inequalityA function g is concave if and only if∫

g (x) dF ≤ g(∫

xdF)

This saysg(E(X )) ≥ E(g(X ))

Consequences of Jensen’s inequality

Hence, v(·) is concave if and only if∫vdF︸ ︷︷ ︸

expected utility of F

≤ v(∫

dF)

︸ ︷︷ ︸utility of the expected value of F

Since v is non decreasing,

c(F , v) ≤∫vdF is equivalent to v (c(F , v)) ≤ v

(∫vdF

)or ∫

v dF ≤ v(∫

vdF)

Page 31: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Jensen’s InequalityJensen’s inequalityA function g is concave if and only if∫

g (x) dF ≤ g(∫

xdF)

This saysg(E(X )) ≥ E(g(X ))

Consequences of Jensen’s inequality

Hence, v(·) is concave if and only if∫vdF︸ ︷︷ ︸

expected utility of F

≤ v(∫

dF)

︸ ︷︷ ︸utility of the expected value of F

Since v is non decreasing,

c(F , v) ≤∫vdF is equivalent to v (c(F , v)) ≤ v

(∫vdF

)or ∫

v dF ≤ v(∫

vdF)

Page 32: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Jensen’s InequalityJensen’s inequalityA function g is concave if and only if∫

g (x) dF ≤ g(∫

xdF)

This saysg(E(X )) ≥ E(g(X ))

Consequences of Jensen’s inequality

Hence, v(·) is concave if and only if∫vdF︸ ︷︷ ︸

expected utility of F

≤ v(∫

dF)

︸ ︷︷ ︸utility of the expected value of F

Since v is non decreasing,

c(F , v) ≤∫vdF is equivalent to v (c(F , v)) ≤ v

(∫vdF

)or ∫

v dF ≤ v(∫

vdF)

Page 33: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Jensen’s InequalityJensen’s inequalityA function g is concave if and only if∫

g (x) dF ≤ g(∫

xdF)

This saysg(E(X )) ≥ E(g(X ))

Consequences of Jensen’s inequality

Hence, v(·) is concave if and only if∫vdF︸ ︷︷ ︸

expected utility of F

≤ v(∫

dF)

︸ ︷︷ ︸utility of the expected value of F

Since v is non decreasing,

c(F , v) ≤∫vdF is equivalent to v (c(F , v)) ≤ v

(∫vdF

)or ∫

v dF ≤ v(∫

vdF)

Page 34: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

We prove (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1). Start with (1)⇒ (2).

Proof.% is risk averse, hence δµF % F for all F ∈ ∆R.

For any x , y ∈ R and α ∈ [0, 1], let the discrete random variable X be suchthat P(X = x) = α and P(X = y) = 1− α. Let Fαx ,y be the associatedcumulative distribution.

By risk aversion we have:

v(µFαx,y ) ≥∫v(z)dFαx ,y (z)

⇒v(αx + (1− α)y) ≥

∑z

v(z)P(X = z) = αv(x) + (1− α)v(y)

Thus v is concave.

Page 35: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

We prove (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1). Start with (1)⇒ (2).

Proof.% is risk averse, hence δµF % F for all F ∈ ∆R.

For any x , y ∈ R and α ∈ [0, 1], let the discrete random variable X be suchthat P(X = x) = α and P(X = y) = 1− α. Let Fαx ,y be the associatedcumulative distribution.

By risk aversion we have:

v(µFαx,y ) ≥∫v(z)dFαx ,y (z)

⇒v(αx + (1− α)y) ≥

∑z

v(z)P(X = z) = αv(x) + (1− α)v(y)

Thus v is concave.

Page 36: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

We prove (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1). Start with (1)⇒ (2).

Proof.% is risk averse, hence δµF % F for all F ∈ ∆R.

For any x , y ∈ R and α ∈ [0, 1], let the discrete random variable X be suchthat P(X = x) = α and P(X = y) = 1− α. Let Fαx ,y be the associatedcumulative distribution.

By risk aversion we have:

v(µFαx,y ) ≥∫v(z)dFαx ,y (z)

⇒v(αx + (1− α)y) ≥

∑z

v(z)P(X = z) = αv(x) + (1− α)v(y)

Thus v is concave.

Page 37: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

We prove (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1). Start with (1)⇒ (2).

Proof.% is risk averse, hence δµF % F for all F ∈ ∆R.

For any x , y ∈ R and α ∈ [0, 1], let the discrete random variable X be suchthat P(X = x) = α and P(X = y) = 1− α. Let Fαx ,y be the associatedcumulative distribution.

By risk aversion we have:

v(µFαx,y ) ≥∫v(z)dFαx ,y (z)

⇒v(αx + (1− α)y) ≥

∑z

v(z)P(X = z) = αv(x) + (1− α)v(y)

Thus v is concave.

Page 38: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

We prove (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1). Start with (1)⇒ (2).

Proof.% is risk averse, hence δµF % F for all F ∈ ∆R.

For any x , y ∈ R and α ∈ [0, 1], let the discrete random variable X be suchthat P(X = x) = α and P(X = y) = 1− α. Let Fαx ,y be the associatedcumulative distribution.

By risk aversion we have:

v(µFαx,y ) ≥∫v(z)dFαx ,y (z)

⇒v(αx + (1− α)y) ≥

∑z

v(z)P(X = z) = αv(x) + (1− α)v(y)

Thus v is concave.

Page 39: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

We prove (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1). Start with (1)⇒ (2).

Proof.% is risk averse, hence δµF % F for all F ∈ ∆R.

For any x , y ∈ R and α ∈ [0, 1], let the discrete random variable X be suchthat P(X = x) = α and P(X = y) = 1− α. Let Fαx ,y be the associatedcumulative distribution.

By risk aversion we have:

v(µFαx,y ) ≥∫v(z)dFαx ,y (z)

⇒v(αx + (1− α)y) ≥

∑z

v(z)P(X = z) = αv(x) + (1− α)v(y)

Thus v is concave.

Page 40: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

We prove (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1). Start with (1)⇒ (2).

Proof.% is risk averse, hence δµF % F for all F ∈ ∆R.

For any x , y ∈ R and α ∈ [0, 1], let the discrete random variable X be suchthat P(X = x) = α and P(X = y) = 1− α. Let Fαx ,y be the associatedcumulative distribution.

By risk aversion we have:

v(µFαx,y ) ≥∫v(z)dFαx ,y (z)

⇒v(αx + (1− α)y) ≥

∑z

v(z)P(X = z) = αv(x) + (1− α)v(y)

Thus v is concave.

Page 41: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

Now prove that (2)⇒ (3)

Proof.Let v be concave, and X be a random variable with cdf F .

By Jensen’s inequality:v(E(X )) ≥ E(v(X ))

or

v(µF ) ≥∫v(x)dF (x) = v(c(F , v))

Since v is an increasing function, we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)Thus

µF − c(F , v) = r(F , v) ≥ 0

Page 42: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

Now prove that (2)⇒ (3)

Proof.Let v be concave, and X be a random variable with cdf F .

By Jensen’s inequality:v(E(X )) ≥ E(v(X ))

or

v(µF ) ≥∫v(x)dF (x) = v(c(F , v))

Since v is an increasing function, we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)Thus

µF − c(F , v) = r(F , v) ≥ 0

Page 43: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

Now prove that (2)⇒ (3)

Proof.Let v be concave, and X be a random variable with cdf F .

By Jensen’s inequality:v(E(X )) ≥ E(v(X ))

or

v(µF ) ≥∫v(x)dF (x) = v(c(F , v))

Since v is an increasing function, we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)Thus

µF − c(F , v) = r(F , v) ≥ 0

Page 44: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

Now prove that (2)⇒ (3)

Proof.Let v be concave, and X be a random variable with cdf F .

By Jensen’s inequality:v(E(X )) ≥ E(v(X ))

or

v(µF ) ≥∫v(x)dF (x) = v(c(F , v))

Since v is an increasing function, we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)Thus

µF − c(F , v) = r(F , v) ≥ 0

Page 45: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

Now prove that (2)⇒ (3)

Proof.Let v be concave, and X be a random variable with cdf F .

By Jensen’s inequality:v(E(X )) ≥ E(v(X ))

or

v(µF ) ≥∫v(x)dF (x) = v(c(F , v))

Since v is an increasing function, we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)Thus

µF − c(F , v) = r(F , v) ≥ 0

Page 46: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

Now prove that (2)⇒ (3)

Proof.Let v be concave, and X be a random variable with cdf F .

By Jensen’s inequality:v(E(X )) ≥ E(v(X ))

or

v(µF ) ≥∫v(x)dF (x) = v(c(F , v))

Since v is an increasing function, we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)Thus

µF − c(F , v) = r(F , v) ≥ 0

Page 47: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

Now prove that (2)⇒ (3)

Proof.Let v be concave, and X be a random variable with cdf F .

By Jensen’s inequality:v(E(X )) ≥ E(v(X ))

or

v(µF ) ≥∫v(x)dF (x) = v(c(F , v))

Since v is an increasing function, we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)Thus

µF − c(F , v) = r(F , v) ≥ 0

Page 48: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

(3)⇒ (1)

Proof.

Let r(F , v) ≥ 0 for all cdfs F .Then we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)

which in turn implies that

v(µF ) ≥ v(c(F , v)) =

∫v(x)dF (x)

Hence δµF % F for all F ; therefore % is risk averse.

We have shown that (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1), thus the proof is complete.

Page 49: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

(3)⇒ (1)

Proof.

Let r(F , v) ≥ 0 for all cdfs F .Then we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)

which in turn implies that

v(µF ) ≥ v(c(F , v)) =

∫v(x)dF (x)

Hence δµF % F for all F ; therefore % is risk averse.

We have shown that (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1), thus the proof is complete.

Page 50: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

(3)⇒ (1)

Proof.

Let r(F , v) ≥ 0 for all cdfs F .Then we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)

which in turn implies that

v(µF ) ≥ v(c(F , v)) =

∫v(x)dF (x)

Hence δµF % F for all F ; therefore % is risk averse.

We have shown that (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1), thus the proof is complete.

Page 51: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

(3)⇒ (1)

Proof.

Let r(F , v) ≥ 0 for all cdfs F .Then we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)

which in turn implies that

v(µF ) ≥ v(c(F , v)) =

∫v(x)dF (x)

Hence δµF % F for all F ; therefore % is risk averse.

We have shown that (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1), thus the proof is complete.

Page 52: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

(3)⇒ (1)

Proof.

Let r(F , v) ≥ 0 for all cdfs F .Then we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)

which in turn implies that

v(µF ) ≥ v(c(F , v)) =

∫v(x)dF (x)

Hence δµF % F for all F ; therefore % is risk averse.

We have shown that (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1), thus the proof is complete.

Page 53: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

(3)⇒ (1)

Proof.

Let r(F , v) ≥ 0 for all cdfs F .Then we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)

which in turn implies that

v(µF ) ≥ v(c(F , v)) =

∫v(x)dF (x)

Hence δµF % F for all F ; therefore % is risk averse.

We have shown that (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1), thus the proof is complete.

Page 54: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Risk Aversion, CE, and Risk Premium

% is risk averse︸ ︷︷ ︸(1)

⇔ v is concave︸ ︷︷ ︸(2)

⇔ r(F , v) ≥ 0︸ ︷︷ ︸(3)

(3)⇒ (1)

Proof.

Let r(F , v) ≥ 0 for all cdfs F .Then we have

µF ≥ c(F , v)

which in turn implies that

v(µF ) ≥ v(c(F , v)) =

∫v(x)dF (x)

Hence δµF % F for all F ; therefore % is risk averse.

We have shown that (1)⇒ (2)⇒ (3)⇒ (1), thus the proof is complete.

Page 55: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

When can we say that one decision maker is more risk averse than another?

Relative risk aversion answers this question in a preference-based way.

DefinitionGiven two preference relations, %1 is more risk averse than %2 if and only if

F %1 δx ⇒ F %2 δxfor all F and x .

If DM1 prefers the lottery F to the sure payout x , then anyone who is less riskaverse than DM1 also prefers the lottery F to δx .

Conversely, if DM2 prefers the sure payout x to the lottery F , then anyone whois more risk averse than DM2 also prefers the sure payout δx to the lottery F .

Again, this definition does not assume anything about preferences.

When both preferences satisfy expected utility, we have extra implications.

Page 56: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

When can we say that one decision maker is more risk averse than another?

Relative risk aversion answers this question in a preference-based way.

DefinitionGiven two preference relations, %1 is more risk averse than %2 if and only if

F %1 δx ⇒ F %2 δxfor all F and x .

If DM1 prefers the lottery F to the sure payout x , then anyone who is less riskaverse than DM1 also prefers the lottery F to δx .

Conversely, if DM2 prefers the sure payout x to the lottery F , then anyone whois more risk averse than DM2 also prefers the sure payout δx to the lottery F .

Again, this definition does not assume anything about preferences.

When both preferences satisfy expected utility, we have extra implications.

Page 57: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

When can we say that one decision maker is more risk averse than another?

Relative risk aversion answers this question in a preference-based way.

DefinitionGiven two preference relations, %1 is more risk averse than %2 if and only if

F %1 δx ⇒ F %2 δxfor all F and x .

If DM1 prefers the lottery F to the sure payout x , then anyone who is less riskaverse than DM1 also prefers the lottery F to δx .

Conversely, if DM2 prefers the sure payout x to the lottery F , then anyone whois more risk averse than DM2 also prefers the sure payout δx to the lottery F .

Again, this definition does not assume anything about preferences.

When both preferences satisfy expected utility, we have extra implications.

Page 58: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

When can we say that one decision maker is more risk averse than another?

Relative risk aversion answers this question in a preference-based way.

DefinitionGiven two preference relations, %1 is more risk averse than %2 if and only if

F %1 δx ⇒ F %2 δxfor all F and x .

If DM1 prefers the lottery F to the sure payout x , then anyone who is less riskaverse than DM1 also prefers the lottery F to δx .

Conversely, if DM2 prefers the sure payout x to the lottery F , then anyone whois more risk averse than DM2 also prefers the sure payout δx to the lottery F .

Again, this definition does not assume anything about preferences.

When both preferences satisfy expected utility, we have extra implications.

Page 59: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

When can we say that one decision maker is more risk averse than another?

Relative risk aversion answers this question in a preference-based way.

DefinitionGiven two preference relations, %1 is more risk averse than %2 if and only if

F %1 δx ⇒ F %2 δxfor all F and x .

If DM1 prefers the lottery F to the sure payout x , then anyone who is less riskaverse than DM1 also prefers the lottery F to δx .

Conversely, if DM2 prefers the sure payout x to the lottery F , then anyone whois more risk averse than DM2 also prefers the sure payout δx to the lottery F .

Again, this definition does not assume anything about preferences.

When both preferences satisfy expected utility, we have extra implications.

Page 60: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

When can we say that one decision maker is more risk averse than another?

Relative risk aversion answers this question in a preference-based way.

DefinitionGiven two preference relations, %1 is more risk averse than %2 if and only if

F %1 δx ⇒ F %2 δxfor all F and x .

If DM1 prefers the lottery F to the sure payout x , then anyone who is less riskaverse than DM1 also prefers the lottery F to δx .

Conversely, if DM2 prefers the sure payout x to the lottery F , then anyone whois more risk averse than DM2 also prefers the sure payout δx to the lottery F .

Again, this definition does not assume anything about preferences.

When both preferences satisfy expected utility, we have extra implications.

Page 61: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

Relative risk aversion is equivalent to: “more concavity”of the utility index, asmaller certainty equivalent, and a larger risk premium.

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the vNM indices v1 andv2. The following are equivalent:

1 %1 is more risk averse than %2;2 v1 = φ ◦ v2 for some strictly increasing concave φ : R→ R;3 c(F , v1) ≤ c(F , v2), for all F ;4 r(F , v1) ≥ r(F , v2), for all F .

Proof.Question 5 in Problem Set 6

Page 62: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

Relative risk aversion is equivalent to: “more concavity”of the utility index, asmaller certainty equivalent, and a larger risk premium.

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the vNM indices v1 andv2. The following are equivalent:

1 %1 is more risk averse than %2;2 v1 = φ ◦ v2 for some strictly increasing concave φ : R→ R;3 c(F , v1) ≤ c(F , v2), for all F ;4 r(F , v1) ≥ r(F , v2), for all F .

Proof.Question 5 in Problem Set 6

Page 63: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

Relative risk aversion is equivalent to: “more concavity”of the utility index, asmaller certainty equivalent, and a larger risk premium.

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the vNM indices v1 andv2. The following are equivalent:

1 %1 is more risk averse than %2;2 v1 = φ ◦ v2 for some strictly increasing concave φ : R→ R;3 c(F , v1) ≤ c(F , v2), for all F ;4 r(F , v1) ≥ r(F , v2), for all F .

Proof.Question 5 in Problem Set 6

Page 64: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

Relative risk aversion is equivalent to: “more concavity”of the utility index, asmaller certainty equivalent, and a larger risk premium.

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the vNM indices v1 andv2. The following are equivalent:

1 %1 is more risk averse than %2;2 v1 = φ ◦ v2 for some strictly increasing concave φ : R→ R;3 c(F , v1) ≤ c(F , v2), for all F ;4 r(F , v1) ≥ r(F , v2), for all F .

Proof.Question 5 in Problem Set 6

Page 65: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

Relative risk aversion is equivalent to: “more concavity”of the utility index, asmaller certainty equivalent, and a larger risk premium.

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the vNM indices v1 andv2. The following are equivalent:

1 %1 is more risk averse than %2;2 v1 = φ ◦ v2 for some strictly increasing concave φ : R→ R;3 c(F , v1) ≤ c(F , v2), for all F ;4 r(F , v1) ≥ r(F , v2), for all F .

Proof.Question 5 in Problem Set 6

Page 66: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

Relative risk aversion is equivalent to: “more concavity”of the utility index, asmaller certainty equivalent, and a larger risk premium.

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the vNM indices v1 andv2. The following are equivalent:

1 %1 is more risk averse than %2;2 v1 = φ ◦ v2 for some strictly increasing concave φ : R→ R;3 c(F , v1) ≤ c(F , v2), for all F ;4 r(F , v1) ≥ r(F , v2), for all F .

Proof.Question 5 in Problem Set 6

Page 67: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Relative Risk Aversion

Relative risk aversion is equivalent to: “more concavity”of the utility index, asmaller certainty equivalent, and a larger risk premium.

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the vNM indices v1 andv2. The following are equivalent:

1 %1 is more risk averse than %2;2 v1 = φ ◦ v2 for some strictly increasing concave φ : R→ R;3 c(F , v1) ≤ c(F , v2), for all F ;4 r(F , v1) ≥ r(F , v2), for all F .

Proof.Question 5 in Problem Set 6

Page 68: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Another Application: Asset DemandAn asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future.

Asset Demand

An agent has initial wealth w ; she can invest it in a safe asset that returns $1per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested.

The general version has N assets each yielding a return zn per unit invested.

The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume∫z dF > 1.

Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively.Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β.

The agent solves max∫v(αz + β) dF s. t. α, β ≥ 0 and α + β = w

The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is∫(z − 1)v ′(α(z − 1) + w) dF = 0

If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) becauseof the concavity of v .

One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 thenher optimal α1 is smaller than the corresponding α2: the more risk averseconsumer invests less in the risky asset.

Page 69: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Another Application: Asset DemandAn asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future.

Asset Demand

An agent has initial wealth w ; she can invest it in a safe asset that returns $1per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested.

The general version has N assets each yielding a return zn per unit invested.

The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume∫z dF > 1.

Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively.Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β.

The agent solves max∫v(αz + β) dF s. t. α, β ≥ 0 and α + β = w

The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is∫(z − 1)v ′(α(z − 1) + w) dF = 0

If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) becauseof the concavity of v .

One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 thenher optimal α1 is smaller than the corresponding α2: the more risk averseconsumer invests less in the risky asset.

Page 70: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Another Application: Asset DemandAn asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future.

Asset Demand

An agent has initial wealth w ; she can invest it in a safe asset that returns $1per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested.

The general version has N assets each yielding a return zn per unit invested.

The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume∫z dF > 1.

Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively.Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β.

The agent solves max∫v(αz + β) dF s. t. α, β ≥ 0 and α + β = w

The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is∫(z − 1)v ′(α(z − 1) + w) dF = 0

If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) becauseof the concavity of v .

One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 thenher optimal α1 is smaller than the corresponding α2: the more risk averseconsumer invests less in the risky asset.

Page 71: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Another Application: Asset DemandAn asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future.

Asset Demand

An agent has initial wealth w ; she can invest it in a safe asset that returns $1per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested.

The general version has N assets each yielding a return zn per unit invested.

The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume∫z dF > 1.

Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively.Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β.

The agent solves max∫v(αz + β) dF s. t. α, β ≥ 0 and α + β = w

The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is∫(z − 1)v ′(α(z − 1) + w) dF = 0

If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) becauseof the concavity of v .

One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 thenher optimal α1 is smaller than the corresponding α2: the more risk averseconsumer invests less in the risky asset.

Page 72: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Another Application: Asset DemandAn asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future.

Asset Demand

An agent has initial wealth w ; she can invest it in a safe asset that returns $1per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested.

The general version has N assets each yielding a return zn per unit invested.

The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume∫z dF > 1.

Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively.Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β.

The agent solves max∫v(αz + β) dF s. t. α, β ≥ 0 and α + β = w

The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is∫(z − 1)v ′(α(z − 1) + w) dF = 0

If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) becauseof the concavity of v .

One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 thenher optimal α1 is smaller than the corresponding α2: the more risk averseconsumer invests less in the risky asset.

Page 73: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Another Application: Asset DemandAn asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future.

Asset Demand

An agent has initial wealth w ; she can invest it in a safe asset that returns $1per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested.

The general version has N assets each yielding a return zn per unit invested.

The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume∫z dF > 1.

Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively.Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β.

The agent solves max∫v(αz + β) dF s. t. α, β ≥ 0 and α + β = w

The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is∫(z − 1)v ′(α(z − 1) + w) dF = 0

If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) becauseof the concavity of v .

One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 thenher optimal α1 is smaller than the corresponding α2: the more risk averseconsumer invests less in the risky asset.

Page 74: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Another Application: Asset DemandAn asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future.

Asset Demand

An agent has initial wealth w ; she can invest it in a safe asset that returns $1per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested.

The general version has N assets each yielding a return zn per unit invested.

The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume∫z dF > 1.

Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively.Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β.

The agent solves max∫v(αz + β) dF s. t. α, β ≥ 0 and α + β = w

The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is∫(z − 1)v ′(α(z − 1) + w) dF = 0

If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) becauseof the concavity of v .

One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 thenher optimal α1 is smaller than the corresponding α2: the more risk averseconsumer invests less in the risky asset.

Page 75: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Another Application: Asset DemandAn asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future.

Asset Demand

An agent has initial wealth w ; she can invest it in a safe asset that returns $1per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested.

The general version has N assets each yielding a return zn per unit invested.

The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume∫z dF > 1.

Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively.Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β.

The agent solves max∫v(αz + β) dF s. t. α, β ≥ 0 and α + β = w

The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is∫(z − 1)v ′(α(z − 1) + w) dF = 0

If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) becauseof the concavity of v .

One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 thenher optimal α1 is smaller than the corresponding α2: the more risk averseconsumer invests less in the risky asset.

Page 76: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Another Application: Asset DemandAn asset is a divisible claim to a financial return in the future.

Asset Demand

An agent has initial wealth w ; she can invest it in a safe asset that returns $1per dollar invested, or in a risky asset that returns $z per dollar invested.

The general version has N assets each yielding a return zn per unit invested.

The risky return has cdf F (z), and assume∫z dF > 1.

Let α and β be the amounts invested in the risky and safe asset respectively.Then, one can think of (α, β) as a portfolio allocation that pays αz + β.

The agent solves max∫v(αz + β) dF s. t. α, β ≥ 0 and α + β = w

The first oder conditions for this optimal portfolio problem is∫(z − 1)v ′(α(z − 1) + w) dF = 0

If the decision maker is risk averse, this expression is decreasing (in α) becauseof the concavity of v .

One can use this fact to verify that if DM1 is more risk averse than DM2 thenher optimal α1 is smaller than the corresponding α2: the more risk averseconsumer invests less in the risky asset.

Page 77: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

How to Measure Risk Aversion

Since concavity of v reflects risk aversion, v ′′ is a natural candidate measureof risk aversion.

Unfortunately, v ′′ is not appropriate since it is not robust to strictly increasinglinear transformations.

DefinitionSuppose % is a preference relation represented by the twice differentiable vNMindex v : R→ R. The Arrow—Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion λ : R→ R isdefined by

λ(x) = −v′′(x)

v ′(x).

The second derivative is normalized to measure risk aversion properly.

Notice that by integrating λ(x) twice one could recover the utility function.

How about the constants of integration?

Page 78: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

How to Measure Risk Aversion

Since concavity of v reflects risk aversion, v ′′ is a natural candidate measureof risk aversion.

Unfortunately, v ′′ is not appropriate since it is not robust to strictly increasinglinear transformations.

DefinitionSuppose % is a preference relation represented by the twice differentiable vNMindex v : R→ R. The Arrow—Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion λ : R→ R isdefined by

λ(x) = −v′′(x)

v ′(x).

The second derivative is normalized to measure risk aversion properly.

Notice that by integrating λ(x) twice one could recover the utility function.

How about the constants of integration?

Page 79: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

How to Measure Risk Aversion

Since concavity of v reflects risk aversion, v ′′ is a natural candidate measureof risk aversion.

Unfortunately, v ′′ is not appropriate since it is not robust to strictly increasinglinear transformations.

DefinitionSuppose % is a preference relation represented by the twice differentiable vNMindex v : R→ R. The Arrow—Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion λ : R→ R isdefined by

λ(x) = −v′′(x)

v ′(x).

The second derivative is normalized to measure risk aversion properly.

Notice that by integrating λ(x) twice one could recover the utility function.

How about the constants of integration?

Page 80: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

How to Measure Risk Aversion

Since concavity of v reflects risk aversion, v ′′ is a natural candidate measureof risk aversion.

Unfortunately, v ′′ is not appropriate since it is not robust to strictly increasinglinear transformations.

DefinitionSuppose % is a preference relation represented by the twice differentiable vNMindex v : R→ R. The Arrow—Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion λ : R→ R isdefined by

λ(x) = −v′′(x)

v ′(x).

The second derivative is normalized to measure risk aversion properly.

Notice that by integrating λ(x) twice one could recover the utility function.

How about the constants of integration?

Page 81: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

How to Measure Risk Aversion

Since concavity of v reflects risk aversion, v ′′ is a natural candidate measureof risk aversion.

Unfortunately, v ′′ is not appropriate since it is not robust to strictly increasinglinear transformations.

DefinitionSuppose % is a preference relation represented by the twice differentiable vNMindex v : R→ R. The Arrow—Pratt measure of absolute risk aversion λ : R→ R isdefined by

λ(x) = −v′′(x)

v ′(x).

The second derivative is normalized to measure risk aversion properly.

Notice that by integrating λ(x) twice one could recover the utility function.

How about the constants of integration?

Page 82: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Absolute Risk Aversion

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the twice differentiablevNM indices v1 and v2. Then

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

This confirms that the Arrow-Pratt coeffi cient is the correct measure ofincreasing absolute risk aversion.

One can add this to the characterizations of ‘more risk averse than’that youhave to prove in the homework...

but I decided to do this in class instead.

Page 83: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Absolute Risk Aversion

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the twice differentiablevNM indices v1 and v2. Then

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

This confirms that the Arrow-Pratt coeffi cient is the correct measure ofincreasing absolute risk aversion.

One can add this to the characterizations of ‘more risk averse than’that youhave to prove in the homework...

but I decided to do this in class instead.

Page 84: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Absolute Risk Aversion

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the twice differentiablevNM indices v1 and v2. Then

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

This confirms that the Arrow-Pratt coeffi cient is the correct measure ofincreasing absolute risk aversion.

One can add this to the characterizations of ‘more risk averse than’that youhave to prove in the homework...

but I decided to do this in class instead.

Page 85: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Absolute Risk Aversion

Proposition

Suppose %1 and %2 are preference relations represented by the twice differentiablevNM indices v1 and v2. Then

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

This confirms that the Arrow-Pratt coeffi cient is the correct measure ofincreasing absolute risk aversion.

One can add this to the characterizations of ‘more risk averse than’that youhave to prove in the homework...

but I decided to do this in class instead.

Page 86: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

Proof.

We know v1 = φ(v2) for some strictly increasing φ (by the homework).

Differentiating

v ′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x) and v ′′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x) + φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

Dividing v ′′1 by v′1 > 0 we have

v ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

Subsitute the first equationv ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=v ′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)or

−v′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)= −v

′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)− φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

using the definition of Arrow-Pratt:

λ1(x) = λ2(x) + something

since φ is concave and v is increasing.

Page 87: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

Proof.

We know v1 = φ(v2) for some strictly increasing φ (by the homework).

Differentiating

v ′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x) and v ′′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x) + φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

Dividing v ′′1 by v′1 > 0 we have

v ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

Subsitute the first equationv ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=v ′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)or

−v′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)= −v

′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)− φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

using the definition of Arrow-Pratt:

λ1(x) = λ2(x) + something

since φ is concave and v is increasing.

Page 88: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

Proof.

We know v1 = φ(v2) for some strictly increasing φ (by the homework).

Differentiating

v ′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x) and v ′′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x) + φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

Dividing v ′′1 by v′1 > 0 we have

v ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

Subsitute the first equationv ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=v ′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)or

−v′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)= −v

′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)− φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

using the definition of Arrow-Pratt:

λ1(x) = λ2(x) + something

since φ is concave and v is increasing.

Page 89: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

Proof.

We know v1 = φ(v2) for some strictly increasing φ (by the homework).

Differentiating

v ′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x) and v ′′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x) + φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

Dividing v ′′1 by v′1 > 0 we have

v ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

Subsitute the first equationv ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=v ′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)or

−v′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)= −v

′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)− φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

using the definition of Arrow-Pratt:

λ1(x) = λ2(x) + something

since φ is concave and v is increasing.

Page 90: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

Proof.

We know v1 = φ(v2) for some strictly increasing φ (by the homework).

Differentiating

v ′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x) and v ′′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x) + φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

Dividing v ′′1 by v′1 > 0 we have

v ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

Subsitute the first equationv ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=v ′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)or

−v′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)= −v

′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)− φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

using the definition of Arrow-Pratt:

λ1(x) = λ2(x) + something

since φ is concave and v is increasing.

Page 91: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

Proof.

We know v1 = φ(v2) for some strictly increasing φ (by the homework).

Differentiating

v ′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x) and v ′′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x) + φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

Dividing v ′′1 by v′1 > 0 we have

v ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

Subsitute the first equationv ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=v ′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)or

−v′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)= −v

′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)− φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

using the definition of Arrow-Pratt:

λ1(x) = λ2(x) + something

since φ is concave and v is increasing.

Page 92: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

%1 is more risk averse than %2 ⇔ λ1(x) ≥ λ2(x) for all x ∈ R

Proof.

We know v1 = φ(v2) for some strictly increasing φ (by the homework).

Differentiating

v ′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x) and v ′′1 (x) = φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x) + φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

Dividing v ′′1 by v′1 > 0 we have

v ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=φ′(v2 (x))v ′′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

Subsitute the first equationv ′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)=v ′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)+φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)or

−v′′1 (x)

v ′1 (x)= −v

′′2 (x)

v ′2 (x)− φ′′(v2 (x))v ′2 (x)

v ′1 (x)

using the definition of Arrow-Pratt:

λ1(x) = λ2(x) + something

since φ is concave and v is increasing.

Page 93: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD)What kind of relationship must exist between lotteries F and G to ensure thatanyone, regardless of her attitude to risk, will prefer F to G so long as shelikes more wealth than less?In general, if a consumer’s utility of wealth is increasing, but its functionalform unknown, we do not have enough information to know her rankingsamong all distributions...but we know how she ranks some pairs; namely, thosecomparable with respect to the following transitive, but incomplete, binaryrelation.

DefinitionF first-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �FOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing function v : R→ R.

If F �FOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less prefers F to G .This follows because F % G ⇔ U(F ) =

∫v dF ≥

∫v dG = U(G ).

Proposition

F �FOSD G if and only if F (x) ≤ G (x) for all x ∈ R.

Page 94: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD)What kind of relationship must exist between lotteries F and G to ensure thatanyone, regardless of her attitude to risk, will prefer F to G so long as shelikes more wealth than less?In general, if a consumer’s utility of wealth is increasing, but its functionalform unknown, we do not have enough information to know her rankingsamong all distributions...but we know how she ranks some pairs; namely, thosecomparable with respect to the following transitive, but incomplete, binaryrelation.

DefinitionF first-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �FOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing function v : R→ R.

If F �FOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less prefers F to G .This follows because F % G ⇔ U(F ) =

∫v dF ≥

∫v dG = U(G ).

Proposition

F �FOSD G if and only if F (x) ≤ G (x) for all x ∈ R.

Page 95: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD)What kind of relationship must exist between lotteries F and G to ensure thatanyone, regardless of her attitude to risk, will prefer F to G so long as shelikes more wealth than less?In general, if a consumer’s utility of wealth is increasing, but its functionalform unknown, we do not have enough information to know her rankingsamong all distributions...but we know how she ranks some pairs; namely, thosecomparable with respect to the following transitive, but incomplete, binaryrelation.

DefinitionF first-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �FOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing function v : R→ R.

If F �FOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less prefers F to G .This follows because F % G ⇔ U(F ) =

∫v dF ≥

∫v dG = U(G ).

Proposition

F �FOSD G if and only if F (x) ≤ G (x) for all x ∈ R.

Page 96: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD)What kind of relationship must exist between lotteries F and G to ensure thatanyone, regardless of her attitude to risk, will prefer F to G so long as shelikes more wealth than less?In general, if a consumer’s utility of wealth is increasing, but its functionalform unknown, we do not have enough information to know her rankingsamong all distributions...but we know how she ranks some pairs; namely, thosecomparable with respect to the following transitive, but incomplete, binaryrelation.

DefinitionF first-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �FOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing function v : R→ R.

If F �FOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less prefers F to G .This follows because F % G ⇔ U(F ) =

∫v dF ≥

∫v dG = U(G ).

Proposition

F �FOSD G if and only if F (x) ≤ G (x) for all x ∈ R.

Page 97: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD)What kind of relationship must exist between lotteries F and G to ensure thatanyone, regardless of her attitude to risk, will prefer F to G so long as shelikes more wealth than less?In general, if a consumer’s utility of wealth is increasing, but its functionalform unknown, we do not have enough information to know her rankingsamong all distributions...but we know how she ranks some pairs; namely, thosecomparable with respect to the following transitive, but incomplete, binaryrelation.

DefinitionF first-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �FOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing function v : R→ R.

If F �FOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less prefers F to G .This follows because F % G ⇔ U(F ) =

∫v dF ≥

∫v dG = U(G ).

Proposition

F �FOSD G if and only if F (x) ≤ G (x) for all x ∈ R.

Page 98: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD)F �FOSD G , if

∫v dF ≥

∫v dG , for every nondecreasing function v : R→ R.

FOSD is characterized by only looking at distribution functions.

Proposition

F �FOSD G if and only if F (x) ≤ G (x) for all x ∈ R.

This follows from “integration by parts”∫ b

av (x) f (x) dx = v (x)F (x)|ba −

∫ b

av ′ (x)F (x) dx

= v (b)× 1− v (0)× 0−∫ b

av ′ (x)F (x) dx

= v (b)−∫ b

av ′ (x)F (x) dx

Thus ∫ b

av dF −

∫ b

av dG =

∫ b

av ′ (x) [G (x)− F (x)] dx

and you can fill in the blanks for a formal proof.

Page 99: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD)F �FOSD G , if

∫v dF ≥

∫v dG , for every nondecreasing function v : R→ R.

FOSD is characterized by only looking at distribution functions.

Proposition

F �FOSD G if and only if F (x) ≤ G (x) for all x ∈ R.

This follows from “integration by parts”∫ b

av (x) f (x) dx = v (x)F (x)|ba −

∫ b

av ′ (x)F (x) dx

= v (b)× 1− v (0)× 0−∫ b

av ′ (x)F (x) dx

= v (b)−∫ b

av ′ (x)F (x) dx

Thus ∫ b

av dF −

∫ b

av dG =

∫ b

av ′ (x) [G (x)− F (x)] dx

and you can fill in the blanks for a formal proof.

Page 100: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

First Order Stochastic Dominance (FOSD)F �FOSD G , if

∫v dF ≥

∫v dG , for every nondecreasing function v : R→ R.

FOSD is characterized by only looking at distribution functions.

Proposition

F �FOSD G if and only if F (x) ≤ G (x) for all x ∈ R.

This follows from “integration by parts”∫ b

av (x) f (x) dx = v (x)F (x)|ba −

∫ b

av ′ (x)F (x) dx

= v (b)× 1− v (0)× 0−∫ b

av ′ (x)F (x) dx

= v (b)−∫ b

av ′ (x)F (x) dx

Thus ∫ b

av dF −

∫ b

av dG =

∫ b

av ′ (x) [G (x)− F (x)] dx

and you can fill in the blanks for a formal proof.

Page 101: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD)If one also knows that the decision maker is risk averse (her utility index for wealthis concave), we know how she ranks more pairs.

DefinitionF second-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �SOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing concave function v : R→ R.

If F �SOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less and is risk averseprefers F to G .By construction, the set of distributions ranked by FOSD is a subset of thoseranked by SOSD

F �FOSD G implies F �SOSD G .

Proposition

F �SOSD G if and only if∫ x−∞ F (t) dt ≤

∫ x−∞ G (t) dt for all x ∈ R.

SOSD is also characterized by looking at distribution functions.What if F �SOSD G an DM chooses G? Is this a ‘reasonable’choice?

Page 102: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD)If one also knows that the decision maker is risk averse (her utility index for wealthis concave), we know how she ranks more pairs.

DefinitionF second-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �SOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing concave function v : R→ R.

If F �SOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less and is risk averseprefers F to G .By construction, the set of distributions ranked by FOSD is a subset of thoseranked by SOSD

F �FOSD G implies F �SOSD G .

Proposition

F �SOSD G if and only if∫ x−∞ F (t) dt ≤

∫ x−∞ G (t) dt for all x ∈ R.

SOSD is also characterized by looking at distribution functions.What if F �SOSD G an DM chooses G? Is this a ‘reasonable’choice?

Page 103: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD)If one also knows that the decision maker is risk averse (her utility index for wealthis concave), we know how she ranks more pairs.

DefinitionF second-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �SOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing concave function v : R→ R.

If F �SOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less and is risk averseprefers F to G .By construction, the set of distributions ranked by FOSD is a subset of thoseranked by SOSD

F �FOSD G implies F �SOSD G .

Proposition

F �SOSD G if and only if∫ x−∞ F (t) dt ≤

∫ x−∞ G (t) dt for all x ∈ R.

SOSD is also characterized by looking at distribution functions.What if F �SOSD G an DM chooses G? Is this a ‘reasonable’choice?

Page 104: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD)If one also knows that the decision maker is risk averse (her utility index for wealthis concave), we know how she ranks more pairs.

DefinitionF second-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �SOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing concave function v : R→ R.

If F �SOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less and is risk averseprefers F to G .By construction, the set of distributions ranked by FOSD is a subset of thoseranked by SOSD

F �FOSD G implies F �SOSD G .

Proposition

F �SOSD G if and only if∫ x−∞ F (t) dt ≤

∫ x−∞ G (t) dt for all x ∈ R.

SOSD is also characterized by looking at distribution functions.What if F �SOSD G an DM chooses G? Is this a ‘reasonable’choice?

Page 105: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD)If one also knows that the decision maker is risk averse (her utility index for wealthis concave), we know how she ranks more pairs.

DefinitionF second-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �SOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing concave function v : R→ R.

If F �SOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less and is risk averseprefers F to G .By construction, the set of distributions ranked by FOSD is a subset of thoseranked by SOSD

F �FOSD G implies F �SOSD G .

Proposition

F �SOSD G if and only if∫ x−∞ F (t) dt ≤

∫ x−∞ G (t) dt for all x ∈ R.

SOSD is also characterized by looking at distribution functions.What if F �SOSD G an DM chooses G? Is this a ‘reasonable’choice?

Page 106: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD)If one also knows that the decision maker is risk averse (her utility index for wealthis concave), we know how she ranks more pairs.

DefinitionF second-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �SOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing concave function v : R→ R.

If F �SOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less and is risk averseprefers F to G .By construction, the set of distributions ranked by FOSD is a subset of thoseranked by SOSD

F �FOSD G implies F �SOSD G .

Proposition

F �SOSD G if and only if∫ x−∞ F (t) dt ≤

∫ x−∞ G (t) dt for all x ∈ R.

SOSD is also characterized by looking at distribution functions.What if F �SOSD G an DM chooses G? Is this a ‘reasonable’choice?

Page 107: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Second Order Stochastic Dominance (SOSD)If one also knows that the decision maker is risk averse (her utility index for wealthis concave), we know how she ranks more pairs.

DefinitionF second-order stochastically dominates G , denoted F �SOSD G , if∫

v dF ≥∫v dG ,

for every nondecreasing concave function v : R→ R.

If F �SOSD G , then anyone who prefers more money to less and is risk averseprefers F to G .By construction, the set of distributions ranked by FOSD is a subset of thoseranked by SOSD

F �FOSD G implies F �SOSD G .

Proposition

F �SOSD G if and only if∫ x−∞ F (t) dt ≤

∫ x−∞ G (t) dt for all x ∈ R.

SOSD is also characterized by looking at distribution functions.What if F �SOSD G an DM chooses G? Is this a ‘reasonable’choice?

Page 108: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 109: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 110: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 111: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 112: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 113: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 114: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 115: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 116: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 117: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 118: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 119: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Preferences and Lotteries Over MoneySo far, we have looked at expected utility preferences over sums of money.Dollar bills cannot be eaten, so where do these preferences come from?There are N commodities and % ranks lotteries on X = RN+.The expected utility axioms hold: the consumer is an expected utilitymaximzer, and U is her expected utility function.One can also think of U (·) as a utility function in the sense of consumertheory. Let the corresponding indirect utility function be v (p,w).Suppose all uncertainty is resolved so that the consumer learns how muchmoney she has before she goes to the markets to buy x .Fix prices p ∈ RN++; let w ∈ [0,∞) be income, and x∗ (p,w) the Walrasiandemand. Clearly, v (p,w) = U (x) for x ∈ x∗ (p,w).

How does the consumer rank lotteries over income?

A lottery over income π (w) is a probability distributions on [0,∞).

The expected utility of π is∑

y∈support(π) π (w) v (p,w); and

π % ρ⇔∑

y∈support(π)

π (w) v (p,w) ≥∑

y∈support(π)

ρ (w) v (p,w)

The indirect utility function v (·) is the utility of income.How do properties of % transfer to v (·)? Think about the answer.

Page 120: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Next Class

MIDTERM75 minutes long,covers everything so far:

includes Today’s classincludes Problem Set 6, due Wednesday;

you can consult the class handouts (in printed form), and any notes you mayhave written,but there is no access to any other materials (no books, computers, etc).Past midterm exams with Yunyun... but the content of the course has changedover the years.

I will hold extra offi ce hours tomorrow from 12:30pm to 2pm.

Page 121: Expected Utility And Risk Aversionluca/ECON2100/2018Class/lecture_12.pdf · Unlike risk aversion, the certainty equivalent de–nition assumes a given preference representation (needs

Next Class

MIDTERM75 minutes long,covers everything so far:

includes Today’s classincludes Problem Set 6, due Wednesday;

you can consult the class handouts (in printed form), and any notes you mayhave written,but there is no access to any other materials (no books, computers, etc).Past midterm exams with Yunyun... but the content of the course has changedover the years.

I will hold extra offi ce hours tomorrow from 12:30pm to 2pm.