exemplars and scientific change author(s): david l. hullsource: psa: proceedings of the biennial...

Upload: abuabdur-razzaqal-misri

Post on 02-Jun-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    1/26

    Exemplars and Scientific ChangeAuthor(s): David L. Hull

    Source: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association,Vol. 1982, Volume Two: Symposia and Invited Papers (1982), pp. 479-503Published by: The University of Chicago Presson behalf of the Philosophy of Science AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/192438.

    Accessed: 21/07/2014 16:41

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    The University of Chicago Pressand Philosophy of Science Associationare collaborating with JSTOR to

    digitize, preserve and extend access to PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of ScienceAssociation.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll bj t t JSTOR T d C diti

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpresshttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=psahttp://www.jstor.org/stable/192438?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/192438?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=psahttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    2/26

    Exemplars and

    Scientific

    Change'

    David L. Hull

    The

    University of

    Wisconsin-Milwaukee

    A

    recurrent

    theme

    in

    the "new

    philosophy

    of science"

    is the

    impor-

    tance

    of

    temporally

    extended

    conceptual

    entities termed

    variously

    dis-

    ciplinary

    matrixes

    (Kuhn

    1970),

    research

    programs (Lakatos

    1970),

    scientific

    disciplines

    (Toulmin

    1972),

    theories

    (McMullin

    1976), and

    research traditions (Laudan 1977). Each of these macro-conceptual en-

    tities contains a

    rich

    heterogeneity

    of constituent

    elements. For ex-

    ample, Kuhn's

    (1970, pp.

    183-187)

    disciplinary

    matrixes

    ("paradigm"

    in

    his

    global

    sense)

    include

    symbolic

    generalizations,

    metaphysical

    views,

    models,

    values,

    and

    exemplars as concrete

    problem

    solutions

    ("paradigm"

    in the

    narrow

    sense).

    All

    of the

    conceptual

    entities

    listed above are

    "historical entities"

    or

    "continuants",

    the

    sorts of

    things

    that

    can

    change

    through time. Toulmin

    (1972)

    and Laudan

    (1977)

    permit

    total

    changeover

    in

    elements

    just

    so

    long

    as

    the transformation

    is

    gradual

    and

    the system

    remains cohesive in

    the

    process.

    Others,

    such

    as

    Lakatos

    (1970),

    insist on

    the retention

    of a "hard

    core" of some

    kind.

    Numerous problems

    have

    arisen with

    respect

    to

    the notion of

    concep-

    tual

    historical entities. In

    this

    paper,

    I

    am

    concerned

    with

    only

    two--

    how

    they

    are

    to be

    individuated and

    named.

    If

    such

    conceptual

    systems

    as

    "Darwinism"

    are

    internally quite

    heterogeneous,

    if

    different

    concep-

    tual

    systems contain

    instances of

    many

    of

    the "same"

    concepts,

    if

    a

    conceptual

    system

    can

    undergo a total

    transformation of

    its

    elements

    while

    remaining the

    "same"

    conceptual

    system, how are

    we to

    tell

    whether

    we have

    one

    conceptual

    system

    or two,

    either at any

    one

    time or

    through

    time? How

    can we

    name

    such

    slippery entities and

    continue

    to

    apply the

    same

    name to

    the same

    entity

    through time?

    When

    disagreements

    arise,

    how are

    we to

    reconcile them?

    In

    this

    paper

    I

    propose

    to answer

    the

    preceding

    questions by

    extend-

    ing

    Mayr's

    (1982) notion

    of

    "population

    thinking" to

    thinking itself

    (Ghiselin

    1981).

    As

    Mayr (1982)

    continues to

    emphasize, anyone

    who

    thinks

    that

    the

    populations that

    function

    in the

    evolutionary process

    are

    populations of

    similar

    organisms

    has

    misunderstood the

    fundamentals

    PSA

    1982,

    V lume

    2,

    pp.

    479-503

    Copyright

    (9

    1983

    by the

    Philosophy of

    Science

    Association

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    3/26

    480

    of population

    thinking.

    The reason

    that the notion of "identity by

    de-

    scent"

    is so important

    in

    biological

    evolution is

    that the

    only

    similar-

    ities

    and

    differences that

    matter in the

    evolutionary process

    are

    those

    that

    exhibit this sort

    of

    "identity"

    or lack of it.

    If

    populationthink-

    ing is to be extended to thinking, conceptual populations must be treat-

    ed

    in the same way.

    Biological species

    are

    internally quite

    heterogEne-

    ous. They too can change

    through

    time, regularly turning

    over their

    constituent

    organisms,

    possibly

    modifying every

    trait that might

    be con-

    sidered

    defining. Rarely do two species

    share the same "elements"

    in

    the

    sense of the

    same

    organisms,but

    the members

    of two or more species

    are frequently

    characterized by

    instances

    of the same trait. The

    hood-

    ed

    and

    the

    carrion

    crow both have

    black feathers.

    Although

    evolving

    species

    are

    just

    as

    slippery

    as

    evolving

    conceptual

    systems, biologists

    have worked

    out ways

    of

    individuating

    and

    naming them,

    i.e.,

    the

    type

    specimen method.

    In the first

    two sections

    of

    this paper,

    I explain

    how

    this method arose in the context of theories of special creation and was

    then modified

    in

    response

    to the acceptance

    of evolutionary theory.

    I

    then show how

    this

    method can be extended

    to handle

    social

    groups (such

    as the Darwinians)

    and

    conceptual

    systems (such

    as Darwinism).

    1. Species as

    Natural Kinds

    During the belle epogue

    of natural

    history

    in

    the

    18th and

    19th cen-

    turies, systematics

    included

    a

    greater

    element

    of

    philately

    than

    pres-

    ent-day systematists

    like to recall. During

    this period,

    the

    most wide-

    ly held view on

    the origin of species

    was

    some form of special

    creation.

    According

    to some creationists,

    the

    first

    members

    of every species

    were

    created in the beginning, and the resulting species remained unchanged

    thereafter.

    According

    to other creationists, species

    were

    introduced

    sequentially

    in

    time,

    either

    in

    huge

    masses

    or

    a

    few at a time, as other

    species

    went

    extinct.

    Many

    naturalists believed that

    both origins and

    extinctions

    are

    miraculous

    events;

    others that origins

    are

    miraculous

    while

    extinctions are natural;

    still others that

    both processes

    are

    equally

    natural.

    One

    implication

    of all versions

    of creationism

    is that

    a finite number of species

    exist at any

    one

    time

    in

    human history.

    Hence,

    the

    discovery of previously

    unknown

    species had a

    certain urgen-

    cy

    to it. The

    explorers

    who

    crawled the

    surface of the earth felt

    that

    they

    had best

    hurry

    and find

    their species

    before they

    were all taken.

    Like stamp collectors, the keepers of various "cabinets" had as their

    task to obtain

    for their collections

    at least one

    good specimen

    of

    every

    species.

    The

    special

    creationist

    view of

    species

    was usually

    coupled

    with the

    philosophical

    view that species

    are

    natural

    kinds. Like other

    natural

    kinds,

    species

    were held to be eternal,

    immutable,and

    discrete.

    Quite

    obviously,

    creationists could not

    very well believe

    that all

    species are

    extensionally eternal;

    i.e., that

    throughout all

    time there

    existed rep-

    resentatives of every species.

    Instead, they held

    that species

    are

    somehow built

    into the fabric of

    the universe.

    Species exist

    even

    when

    they

    are not exemplified.

    The sense

    in

    which species that

    are not

    ex-

    emplified

    could continue to exist varied

    extensively.

    At least one

    nat-

    uralist can be found advocating

    every metaphysical

    position on the

    sub-

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    4/26

    481

    ject.

    In

    any case,

    a

    common

    belief

    among

    creationists

    was that

    species

    could cease to be

    exemplified

    every

    once in a

    while and then become

    re-

    exemplified

    later. Naturalists also

    thought

    that

    organisms

    on

    occasion

    could change their species, but an organism changing its species was

    not

    the

    same

    thing

    as

    species

    themselves

    changing.

    It was akin to

    an

    alchemist

    transmuting

    a base metal into

    gold.

    However, by

    the 19th

    cen-

    tury,

    most naturalists

    thought

    that

    species'

    boundaries

    were

    largely in-

    violate.

    The characteristic

    of

    species

    as

    natural kinds

    that roused the

    great-

    est amount of discussion was not their

    immutability

    but the

    discretEness

    of their

    boundaries

    in

    conceptual space.

    On

    the traditional

    "essential-

    ist"

    view,

    all

    genuinely

    meaningful

    terms must

    be defined

    by

    means of

    characteristics

    that

    are

    severally

    necessary

    and

    jointly

    sufficient for

    membership. Either

    a

    geometric

    figure

    is

    a

    triangle,

    or

    it

    is not.

    No

    borderline cases can possibly exist. Naturalists at the time were ob-

    viously aware

    of

    variation

    both within

    species and between

    them. Not

    all

    members of a

    particular

    species

    were

    identical

    to

    each

    other,

    and

    at time

    borderline

    cases existed.

    However,

    they

    took

    it

    as

    their

    task

    to

    see

    through

    all

    this

    accidental variation to

    the

    essential

    nature

    of

    each

    species

    and to

    capture

    its

    essence

    in

    a

    definition

    or

    "diagnosis"

    (to

    use

    the taxonomic

    term).

    Given a

    correct

    definition

    of

    a

    particu-

    lar

    species,

    nearly

    all

    organisms

    belonging

    to

    that

    species

    should

    pos-

    sess

    all

    its essential

    characters.

    Any variation

    that

    might occur

    was

    thought

    to

    be merely a

    function of

    the limitations of

    nature,

    the

    fail-

    ure of a

    principle.

    Numerous

    present-day authors

    have

    claimed

    that no

    one from

    Aristotle

    to the

    present

    ever held the

    preceding view

    of

    species.

    Certainly no

    philosopher or

    naturalist

    held

    precisely

    the view

    described

    above, but

    views

    of

    this

    sort were

    just as

    surely

    common

    during the

    period

    under

    discussion. For

    example,

    the

    importance of the

    discreteness of

    spe-

    cies'

    boundaries can

    be

    seen in a

    dispute

    between

    William

    Whewell

    (1847,

    1853) on one

    side

    and John

    Stuart

    Mill (1843,

    1872)

    and W. S.

    Jevons

    (1892)

    on

    the other.

    According to

    Whewell (1847,

    vol. 1,

    p.494),

    natural

    kinds in

    mathematics

    and

    certain

    areas of

    physics

    are

    absolute-

    ly

    discrete,

    while in other

    areas such as

    biology, equally

    sharp

    bound-

    aries

    had

    yet

    to

    be

    discerned.

    Hence, the

    traditional

    Method of

    Defi-

    nition could be used for the former

    sort of

    natural

    kinds, but

    for the

    latter, Whewell

    devised what he

    termed the Type

    Method.

    According to

    this

    method,

    a

    typical

    representative

    of each

    species

    is chosen

    as its

    "type"

    and

    other

    members of the

    species are

    included in the

    species by

    means

    of

    their

    relation to

    it.

    Whewell

    (1847, vol. 2,

    p. 12)

    was aware

    that

    zoologists

    defined the

    species

    category

    in terms

    of

    "individuals

    which have,

    or

    may have,

    sprung

    from

    the same

    parents."

    However,

    the relation

    that

    another or-

    ganism in

    a

    species must

    have to

    its type

    was

    not

    genealogical

    but a

    certain

    degree

    of

    similarity.

    Whewell

    justified

    replacing

    genealogy

    with similarity by noting that "individuals so related resemble each

    other more than

    those which

    are

    excluded

    from such

    a

    definition."

    The

    only

    unusual

    thing

    about Whewell's

    Type

    Method

    was that

    the

    conceptual

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    5/26

    482

    boundaries between

    species

    need not be

    absolutely

    sharp.

    For

    Whewell

    species

    formed a

    "cluster",

    some

    organisms

    being

    more central

    than

    oth-

    ers. Even

    so,

    he

    thought

    that these

    fuzzy

    boundaries

    were real.

    They

    no more

    changed

    through

    time

    than

    did

    the

    absolutely

    discrete

    boundar-

    ies of more traditional typologists. Nor did Whewell believe that the

    distributions of actual

    organisms

    in

    conceptual

    space

    were ever

    per-

    fectly

    continuous.

    Although every point

    in

    character

    space might

    be

    occupied by an organism,

    the numbers varied

    significantly.

    Most

    organ-

    isms in

    a

    species tended to cluster

    around the

    type.

    And

    in most cases

    large expanses of

    character space

    between

    species

    were

    unoccupied.

    If

    "essentialism"

    is merely

    an

    invention of later

    evolutionists such

    as

    Mayr

    (1982),

    as some

    authors have

    claimed, then Whewell's

    minor

    modification

    should hardly have

    elicited much of a

    response.

    After

    all,

    for

    Whewell, species

    remained eternal and immutable.

    They

    simply

    were

    not absolutely discrete. Whewell (1847, vol. 1, p. 493) himself sus-

    pected that

    his

    views on

    the subject were "so

    contrary

    to

    many

    of the

    received

    opinions

    respecting the

    use of definitions and

    the nature of

    scientific

    propositions, that

    they

    will

    probably appear to

    many

    persons

    highly

    illogical and

    unphilosophical." He

    was right.

    Both Mill (1872,

    p.

    472)and Jevons

    (1892, p. 723)

    rejected

    Whewell's

    Type Method.

    They

    argued that either it reduced to

    the traditional

    Method

    of

    Definition

    or it

    was not an

    acceptable method of

    classification; for

    further

    dis-

    cussion see Ruse

    (1979,

    pp. 125-126)

    and Hull

    (1981,

    vol.

    2, pp. 133-

    137).

    On

    the

    "typological" or "essentialistic" view

    of

    species,

    collecting

    was relatively easy. An occasional mutilation or monster to one side,

    any specimen

    could

    equally

    well

    serve as a

    representative

    of

    its

    spe-

    cies.

    Any

    trait that was

    truly

    variable could

    not

    possibly

    be

    part

    of

    a

    species' essence. A

    naturalist

    might

    sample

    his

    species

    widely but

    not for the

    purpose

    of

    reflecting

    any

    variation

    he

    might

    find in

    his

    diagnosis.

    To

    the

    contrary, the

    purpose

    of

    studying variation

    was to

    eliminate it. On

    this

    view,

    definitions

    (or

    diagnoses)

    are the

    goal of

    systematics,

    and after

    sufficient

    study,

    competent

    observers must

    nec-

    essarily agree

    about

    appropriate

    definitions. For

    example,

    two natu-

    ralists

    collecting

    on

    opposite sides

    of

    Australia

    might stumble

    upon

    organisms

    belonging

    to

    the same

    species.

    If

    these

    collectors are com-

    petent naturalists, they must produce precisely the same definitions.

    In

    actual fact, the

    state

    of

    taxonomy

    was

    just the

    opposite

    of what

    the

    typological

    species concept would

    lead one to

    expect. The

    more ex-

    tensively

    a

    group

    was

    studied,

    frequently the more difficult it

    became

    to delimit

    its boundaries. At a

    single

    location, species are

    easy

    enough

    to

    distinguish

    from

    each

    other,

    but if

    species

    are

    studied

    across

    their

    ranges, their definitional

    boundaries

    become

    increasingly

    diffi-

    cult

    to discern.

    Attempting

    to

    integrate fossil species

    with extant

    forms

    only complicates matters

    further. As a result,

    systematists work-

    ed and

    reworked their

    groups

    as

    regularly as

    stock

    brokers churn their

    accounts

    and

    with much

    the same effect. Of

    greater

    significance, the

    diagnoses so carefully constructed by systematists should have been the

    key

    to

    resolving

    difficult

    cases.

    Time

    and

    again, the

    specimens

    were

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    6/26

    483

    what helped.

    Time and

    again,

    later workers

    could

    not tell from the

    pub-

    lished

    diagnoses

    which

    species

    the

    systematist

    had

    studied,

    but

    an

    ex-

    amination of his

    specimens

    often

    helped

    bring

    some order

    to the

    chaos.

    Darwin and his famous finches

    is an excellent case in

    point.

    According

    to

    the

    traditional

    legend,

    Darwin was led

    to

    speculate

    on

    the

    origin

    of

    species

    because

    of the

    distribution

    of the finches

    which

    he observed on the various islands

    of

    the

    Galapagos

    Archipelago

    and

    later used

    these

    observations to

    support

    his

    theory

    of

    evolution.

    As

    Sulloway(1982)

    has shown

    in

    some

    detail,

    the historical evidence

    does

    not

    support

    this

    legend;

    see also

    (Herbert

    1980).

    While at

    the

    Gala-

    pagos

    Islands,

    Darwin

    gives

    no hint

    that he had

    any

    doubts

    about

    the

    immutability of

    species.

    Not until nine months

    later,

    in

    1836,

    does

    he

    record

    any doubts

    on

    the

    subject

    (Sulloway

    1982, p. 12).

    Nor

    was Dar-

    win,

    on his return to

    England,

    able to use his

    Galapagos

    collection to

    support the theory of evolution because his collecting had been too hap-

    hazard.

    In

    particular,

    he

    did not

    always

    record

    the location at

    which

    the

    specimen

    was

    obtained,

    precisely

    the

    biogeographic

    information need-

    ed

    to test his views on

    speciation.

    As

    Sulloway

    (1982, p.

    18)

    points

    out,

    locale

    is not all

    that

    impor-

    tant

    for

    a

    creationist,

    certainly

    not as

    important

    as

    it is for

    anyone

    who

    believed,

    as

    Wallace

    (1855, p.

    186)

    did,

    that

    every

    "species

    has

    come into

    existence coincident both in

    space

    and

    time

    with

    a

    pre-ex-

    isting

    closely allied

    species."

    Wallace

    had a

    decided

    advantage over

    Darwin.

    He went

    on his

    voyage intent on

    testing

    his

    evolutionary hy-

    pothesis. He

    could

    keep

    his

    eye

    out

    for

    the relevant data. Darwin had

    to

    do

    everything

    in

    retrospect, and too

    often he had

    not

    made or

    record-

    ed

    the relevant

    observations.

    Legend

    notwithstanding, Darwin

    did

    not

    use

    his finches

    as a

    paradigm

    example

    of

    the

    evolution of

    species

    by

    means of

    natural

    selection in

    the

    Origin

    (1859)

    because

    he did not

    have

    the

    necessary

    information.

    Upon

    returning

    to

    England,

    Darwin

    sought the aid

    of

    a

    variety of

    specialists

    in

    curating

    his

    collections.

    Chief

    among

    these

    was the

    ornithologist

    John

    Gould

    (1804-1881). As it

    turned out,

    Darwin's ini-

    tial

    guesses about

    the

    relations

    of his

    birds,

    including the

    Galapagos

    finches, were

    mistaken. For

    example, many

    of

    Darwin's

    varieties,

    Gould

    claimed were distinct species. With the aid of the collections of oth-

    er

    members of

    the

    crew of

    the

    Beagle,

    Darwin

    produced what

    has

    been

    termed

    a

    "taxonomic

    nightmare".

    Some

    order has

    been

    brought

    to

    Darwin's

    finches by

    subsequent

    workers

    but not

    because

    of

    Darwin's

    published des-

    criptions. It

    was

    his

    specimens

    and

    those of

    his

    shipmates

    that

    were of

    the

    greatest

    help.

    If

    these

    specimens had

    not

    been

    preserved, later

    systematists

    would

    have been

    at a

    loss to

    work

    out the

    actual

    identities

    and

    relations

    of

    Darwin's finches.

    Not until

    Lack's

    (1947)

    work

    did the

    myth of

    Darwin's

    finches

    become a

    reality.

    2.

    The

    Type

    Specimen

    Method

    The

    acceptance of

    evolutionary

    theory

    transmuted

    numerous

    curiosities,

    such as

    Wallace's

    1855 law,

    into

    solved

    problems

    (Laudan

    1977). It

    also

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    7/26

    484

    changed

    the relation between organisms

    and their species. As before,

    organisms

    are

    part

    of their

    genealogical

    nexus,

    but no

    longer

    could

    one

    assume,

    as Whewell had,

    that

    genealogical

    relations

    must

    universally

    coincide

    with

    similarity

    relations.

    Although

    the point

    was extremely

    slow in making itself felt, similarities encapsulated in definitions

    had been

    displaced by organisms as

    nodes

    in

    the

    genealogical nexus.

    If

    species evolve

    gradually through

    time,

    one changing into another or

    one

    species splitting slowly into two,

    then

    the search

    for

    "typical"

    mem-

    bers of a species

    is

    questionable

    at best. For

    example,

    upon reading

    Whewell's

    (1853) discussion

    of his Type Method,

    Darwin responded,

    "On

    my theory

    an

    'Exemplar'

    is

    no

    more wanted than to account

    for the like-

    ness

    of members

    of one Family." (Ospovat 1981,

    p. 260). Although

    this

    comment

    is

    more

    than a little cryptic,

    Darwin

    rejected

    the abstract

    ar-

    chetypes

    of idealist

    philosophers

    and

    replaced

    them with

    actual ances-

    tors,organisms

    that

    need

    not

    in

    every

    case be

    typical.

    For

    Darwin spe-

    cies became segments

    of the phylogenetic tree,

    as historical

    as

    the Ba-

    roque period. Just as

    the Baroque

    period

    will

    never return,

    extinct

    species

    cannot

    re-evolve.

    Because

    of the terminological

    confusion

    of

    the

    sort described above,

    systematists

    gradually evolved systems

    of rules

    and

    regulations

    formal-

    ized in various

    codes

    of nomenclature. As these

    codes were

    developed,

    a

    very

    strange notion

    began to

    emer?e

    and become

    central to taxonomic

    practice--the

    type specimen

    method.

    As

    the

    name indicates, initially

    systematists

    strove to designate as the type

    specimen for

    a species a

    typical

    member.

    If

    later workers came to think that

    a

    particular

    type

    specimen

    was

    not as

    typical

    as it

    might be,

    they replaced

    it

    with

    an-

    other specimen. The resulting confusion, rapidly led systematists to

    put

    an end to this practice

    and to rule that once a specimen

    had been

    designated

    as a type specimen,

    it could not be replaced except

    in cases

    of

    duplication.

    The sole function

    of

    the

    type

    specimen

    is to be the

    name bearer for

    its

    species.

    No

    matter in which

    species

    the

    type speci-

    men

    is

    placed,

    its name

    goes

    with

    it. The crucial decision made

    by sys-

    tematists

    was to

    disentangle

    two different

    functions for

    specimens,

    that

    of

    typifying

    their

    species

    and that

    of

    designating

    them rigidly.

    For

    those species

    that

    form unimodal distributions,

    the notion of a

    "typi-

    cal"

    member

    has some

    point,

    but

    given

    the wide

    variety

    of

    character

    distributions

    exhibited

    by

    actual

    species

    in

    nature,

    too often it does

    not.

    Instead an

    array

    of

    specimens

    is

    necessary.

    As

    Mayr

    (1969, p.

    369) has expressed

    this

    position,

    "Species

    consist of variable

    popula-

    tions,

    and no

    single

    specimen

    can

    represent

    this

    variability.

    No

    single

    specimen

    can be

    typical

    in

    the Aristotelian

    sense."

    In

    cases

    in

    which species

    cannot be characterized

    in

    terms

    of simple,

    coincident

    unimodal

    distributions of

    characters,

    no

    specimen,

    including

    the

    type specimen,

    could

    possibly

    be

    "typical"

    of its

    species.

    However,

    even

    in

    those

    special

    cases that fit our common

    sense

    intuitions

    about

    species,

    there

    is still

    ample justification

    for

    keeping

    the

    naming

    func-

    tion

    separate

    from

    description.

    With the rarest

    of

    exception,

    any org-

    anism chosen at random

    must

    belong

    to

    a

    species,

    one

    species

    and

    one

    species only. Our ideas of character distributions, however, can be

    mistaken.

    A

    systematist

    may think that he has

    collected a

    variety of

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    8/26

    485

    specimens

    from

    a

    single

    species,

    when later workers decide

    that

    his

    "single"

    species

    actually consisted of two

    or more

    sibling

    species.

    Hence,

    even

    in

    those cases

    in

    which the selection of

    a

    "typical"

    spec-

    imen

    is

    feasible,

    the likelihood

    that increased

    knowledge

    will

    lead

    systematists

    to

    change

    their minds

    about character distributions

    is

    sufficiently

    high to warrant

    excluding

    the

    name

    bearing specimen

    from

    these exercises.

    No matter how

    typical

    or aberrant

    systematists

    may

    take

    a

    type specimen

    to

    be at

    any

    one

    point

    in

    time,

    it can serve

    just

    as well as the name bearer

    for its

    species.

    As

    Simpson

    (1940, p. 413)

    put

    the

    point

    in

    his seminal

    paper,

    "items

    called

    'types'

    have

    been used

    in

    taxonomy

    in three

    ways:

    as bases

    for

    definitions,

    as standards of

    comparison,

    and as fixed

    points

    to

    which

    names are attached. The modern

    conception

    of

    taxonomy

    as

    involving

    the

    inference of

    population

    characters

    from

    samples

    makes

    it

    impossible

    for

    the same items properly to serve all three of these purposes." Simpson

    accordingly recommends

    reserving

    the

    term"type"

    for

    the

    last

    function,

    as

    a

    fixed

    point

    for

    attaching

    a taxonomic name to a taxon

    (see

    also

    Williams 1940). Later

    Simpson

    (1945, p.

    29) expressed

    his

    position

    on

    type

    specimens even more

    forcefully.

    "It is

    a natural but

    mistaken as-

    sumption

    that

    types

    are somehow

    typical,

    that

    is,

    characteristic,

    of

    the

    groups

    in

    which

    they

    are

    placed.

    It

    is,

    of

    course,

    desirable

    that

    they should be

    typical because then

    they

    are

    less

    likely

    to be shifted

    about from

    group

    to

    group,

    carrying

    their names

    with them and

    upsetting

    nomenclature,

    but there is no

    requirement that a

    type be

    typical, and

    it

    frequently

    happens that it is

    quite aberrant."

    Whether Simpson

    was enunciating

    a new but

    compelling

    position or only

    putting

    into words a

    conviction

    that had

    already

    been

    widespread for

    some

    time is

    difficult to

    decide. But

    with

    surprising

    rapidity, the

    role of

    the

    type specimen as

    a

    name bearer

    became

    standard

    taxonomic

    practice.

    For

    example,

    in

    the

    first modern

    textbook

    on

    biological sys-

    tematics, Mayr,

    Linsley

    and

    Usinger

    (1953, p. 236)

    state, "It

    is very

    difficult to

    characterize or to

    define a

    taxonomic

    entity

    solely by

    means of

    words. As a

    result, many of

    the

    Linnaean and

    early

    post-Lin-

    naean

    species,

    particularly

    among

    the

    invertebrates,

    are

    unidentifiable

    on

    the

    basis of

    the

    description

    alone. It is

    obvious

    that more

    secure

    standards are

    needed

    to tie

    scientific

    names

    unequivocally to

    objective

    taxonomic entities. These standards are the types, and the method of

    using types to

    eliminate

    ambiguity is

    called

    the type

    method."

    On

    one

    interpretation, all

    the type

    specimen

    method does

    is to

    free

    the

    type

    specimen from

    participating in the

    inevitable

    disagreements

    that

    go on

    continually in

    biological

    systematics

    about splitting,

    lump-

    ing

    and

    shifting

    boundaries.

    Once a

    systematist has

    decided on

    his spe-

    cies

    and their

    limits,

    he

    can then check

    where the

    specimens designated

    as

    types happen

    to

    fall and assign

    names

    accordingly.

    If

    he recognizes

    a new

    species

    for

    which there is

    no type

    specimen, he

    must

    designate a

    particular

    specimen as such.

    If

    two specimens

    previously

    designated as

    the

    type specimens for different species end up in a single species,the

    temporally prior

    type

    specimen

    becomes

    the name

    bearer for

    his newly

    combined

    species and

    the other

    type

    specimen is

    demoted.

    As might be

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    9/26

    486

    expected,

    the

    type specimen

    method

    is not without its difficulties.

    For

    example,

    Randall and

    Nelson

    (1979) point

    out a case in which the

    same

    specimen of a

    parrotfish

    was

    designated

    as the

    type specimen

    for

    three

    different species

    belonging to two different genera

    Periodic

    congresses

    are held to resolve such problems.

    Nor does the type specimen method eliminate

    entirely

    a

    role

    for the

    study of character distributions

    in

    systematics.

    On a

    conservative in-

    terpretation of this

    method,

    the

    diagnoses

    published by systematists

    define the designated

    species.

    In

    each case, though

    the

    type specimen

    may be aberrant, it

    must at least

    fall

    within the range of variation

    established

    by

    the

    systematist (Heise

    and Starr

    1968).

    On

    a

    more radi-

    cal

    interpretation, the interpretation

    I

    favor,

    character distributicns

    are

    secondary

    to the

    genealogical

    nexus. The

    type specimen,

    like

    all

    organisms,

    is

    merely one node

    in

    this

    nexus.

    The

    type specimen

    method

    works by tying down a name to one chunk of the genealogical nexus via

    a

    single node

    in

    that nexus.

    No

    matter how the boundaries

    are

    reas-

    sessed, whatever species

    includes a

    particular

    type specimen

    must be

    called

    by the name

    associated with that specimen. Characters

    are3still

    important but only as

    an aid to inferring the genealogical nexus.

    3. Scientific Communities

    In

    recent years

    an

    increasing number of authors have been

    paying at-

    tention to the social structure of

    science, especially

    the

    social

    groups into which scientists

    organize themselves.

    Philosophers

    tend to

    be extremely suspicious

    of

    such

    concerns, fearing

    that some sort of

    social

    relativism lies

    behind them.

    However,

    I

    think that scientific

    communities

    play

    several

    important roles in science,

    roles that have

    little

    to

    do with

    such epistemological concerns. For

    example, much of

    the coherence and

    continuity

    that is so characteristic of

    conceptual

    development

    in

    science results from

    the coherence

    and

    continuity of

    the

    groups

    of

    scientists

    developing

    these views.

    Similarly, unless at-

    tention is paid to cooperating and

    competing factions

    in

    science, many

    of

    the

    positions

    that

    scientists take on

    particular issues are

    all

    but

    inexplicable.

    Frequently, a relatively minor tenet in

    an emerging re-

    search

    program

    becomes elevated in

    importance

    because of the incessant

    attacks

    on

    this tenet

    by the opponents

    of

    the

    program.

    One

    of the

    most common

    and intuitive

    ways

    of

    dividing scientists in-

    to

    groups

    is

    by

    means of

    intellectual

    agreement.

    "A

    paradigm is what

    the members

    of

    a scientific

    community

    share, and, conversely,

    a

    scien-

    tific

    community consists

    of

    men

    who share

    a

    paradigm."

    (Kuhn 1970, p.

    176). Unfortunately, this position

    simply will not do. If

    by "para-

    digm"

    Kuhn means disciplinary matrix,

    rarely do any two

    scientists a-

    gree

    totally on every element of their

    common matrix.

    If

    by "para-

    digm" Kuhn means

    exemplar, differences

    of

    opinion

    still

    remain. Cer-

    tainly much more agreement

    exists

    among the members of a scientific com-

    munity about the value of their

    concrete puzzle

    solutions, but in every

    community

    I

    have

    studied, the

    agreement is never total. As Palter

    (1974, p. 314) pointed out some time

    ago in reaction to

    the writings of

    Kuhn

    and

    Lakatos,

    any concensus that might exist on a

    given scientific

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    10/26

    487

    topic is

    generally

    incomplete.

    Just

    as

    biologists

    were forced

    to

    aban-

    don

    definitions in terms

    of

    statistical

    covariation,

    philosophers

    might

    well

    relax

    the

    requirement

    of

    total

    agreement

    for

    scientists'

    belonging

    to

    the same scientific

    community.

    All

    they

    have to

    do is

    agree

    on

    e-

    nough of the more important issues. But even this more reasonable po-

    sition

    is too

    stringent.

    Whether one deals

    with such massive and

    rela-

    tively

    insignificant

    groupings

    as

    "physicists"

    or

    with

    such small

    ephem-

    eral

    research

    groups

    as

    the Cold

    Spring

    Harbor

    group,

    disagreements

    can

    be

    found

    among

    their

    members even on

    fundamentals.

    Although

    the

    scien-

    tists

    involved

    go

    to

    great

    lengths

    to

    emphasize

    their areas of

    agree-

    ment,

    one

    extremely

    important

    feature

    of

    science

    (and

    possibly

    other

    endeavors

    as

    well)

    is

    that scientists

    can

    cooperate

    with each other

    even

    when

    they

    disagree.

    The

    appropriate relation

    for

    "defining"

    the

    groups

    of

    scientists

    that

    function in

    the

    ongoing

    process

    of

    science is

    cooper-

    ation

    and not

    agreement.4

    For

    example,

    if

    one

    attempts

    to

    define the

    Darwinians in the

    first

    decade

    after

    the

    publication of

    the

    Origin

    in

    terms of

    basic

    agreement,

    one

    gets an

    extremely

    motley

    group.

    In

    the

    early

    years,

    J.D.

    Hooker,

    T. H.

    Huxley, and

    Charles

    Lyell were

    important Darwinians. A.

    R.

    Wal-

    lace and

    J. S.

    Henslow

    might be

    included

    as

    welL Adam

    Sedgwick, Richard

    Owen,

    William

    Hopkins and

    St.

    George Jackson

    Mivart

    were

    important

    anti-

    Darwinians.

    No

    weighting of

    substantive

    beliefs

    about

    science

    or

    bio-

    logical

    species

    produces

    anything like

    this

    division.

    In

    1859

    neither

    Henslow

    nor

    Lyell

    believed

    in

    the

    evolution

    of

    species.

    Henslow

    died

    unconvinced, while

    Lyell came out

    openly

    for

    evolution

    only

    in

    1868 and

    then

    grudgingly

    with

    reservations.

    Conversely,

    both

    Owen and

    Mivart ad-

    vocated evolution, just not "Darwinian" evolution, but the same

    can

    be

    said

    for

    Huxley and

    Wallace.

    Huxley

    agreed

    with Darwin

    about

    the

    import-

    ance

    of

    natural

    selection

    but

    thought

    that

    speciation

    might be

    more sal-

    tative

    than did

    Darwin,

    while

    Wallace

    disagreed

    with

    Darwin

    on

    a

    variety

    of

    counts

    (Kottler

    1980).

    Although

    I

    think

    that

    there

    are

    excellent

    reasons

    for

    paying

    atten-

    tion

    to

    areas

    of

    agreement

    and

    disagreement

    between

    scientists,

    I

    think

    it

    would

    be

    a

    serious

    mistake

    to

    delimit

    scientific

    communities

    in

    this

    way.

    Instead

    the

    variety of

    ways

    in

    which

    scientists

    cooperate

    with

    each

    other

    in

    their

    research

    are

    much

    more

    appropriate

    relations

    to in-

    tegrate scientists into groups. Among these relations are co-authoring

    papers,

    recommending for

    positions

    and

    honors,

    citing

    areas

    of

    agree-

    ment in

    published

    papers

    while

    reserving

    disagreements

    for

    private

    cor-

    respondence,

    and

    so

    on.

    If

    these

    measures are

    used for

    the

    Darwinians

    during

    the

    early

    years,

    a

    single

    community

    materializes

    quite

    forceful-

    ly. Of

    course,

    there

    is

    a

    sense

    in

    which

    anyone who

    pledged

    allegiance

    to

    "Darwinism"

    counts

    as a

    "Darwinian",

    but

    I

    do not

    think

    that

    the

    Dar-

    winians in

    this

    broad

    sense

    can

    possibly

    be

    said

    to

    form a

    "community"

    or

    a

    "group".

    Discerning

    genuine

    scientific

    communities

    is

    a

    difficult

    undertaking,

    as

    difficult

    as

    delineating

    biological

    species,

    so

    difficult

    that one

    is tempted to take the easy

    way out.

    Just

    as

    it is

    easier to

    define

    bi-

    ological

    species in

    terms

    of

    characters than

    to

    individuate

    them

    by

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    11/26

    488

    means of their

    genealogical

    relations,

    it is easier to delimit

    scientif-

    ic communities

    in terms

    of shared beliefs than

    by

    means

    of

    the

    profes-

    sional

    relationships

    of

    their members.

    However,

    the

    easy

    way

    out

    dis-

    torts our

    understanding

    of

    science

    beyond

    all

    recognition.

    If

    we are

    to

    understand the ongoing process of science, genuine scientific communi-

    ties must

    be discerned. Sometimes the boundaries between

    communities

    are not

    sharp, they

    frequently

    change through time,

    sometimes

    one com-

    munity splits into

    two,

    somewhat more

    rarely

    two

    communities

    merge

    into

    one. All

    these complex relations are

    certainly difficult to

    discern,

    but

    they are not

    only

    important

    in

    their own

    right,

    they

    are crucial

    for our

    understanding of

    what is

    going on

    at

    the

    conceptual

    level.

    The

    similarities

    between

    scientific communities

    and

    evolving species

    might

    lead

    one

    to

    suspect that

    something

    like the type specimen

    method

    might be

    usefully extended to aid

    in the

    individuation of

    groups of

    scientists. All one needs to do is to pick a member of a particular

    community, any

    member, and

    attach a name to that

    group by means of

    this

    member.

    One

    advantage

    of

    this

    method is

    that

    it

    can be used

    prior

    to

    knowing

    very much about

    the group as

    a

    group.

    It

    helps

    if

    one

    picks

    a

    central

    member,

    but

    such

    estimations before

    the

    fact

    tend to be

    faulty,

    and

    the status

    of the members of a

    group

    can

    change through time.

    A

    scientist who was

    very

    important

    initially

    can

    drop

    out

    and

    a

    marginal

    member

    become

    central.

    Because organisms

    rarely

    change

    their

    species--

    for

    all

    intents and

    purposes never--no

    temporal index need be

    applied

    to the

    biological

    type

    specimen. However,

    scientists do

    join

    and

    leave

    groups. Hence the

    sociological

    type

    specimen must have a

    tempor-

    al index

    appended

    to

    it,

    e.g.,

    Hooker in 1859.

    In the

    history of

    science,

    sociologically central

    members of a

    scien-

    tific

    community

    also tend to

    be

    conceptually

    exemplary.

    In

    spite

    of his

    relative

    isolation in

    Down, Darwin was still

    sociologically

    a

    fairly cen-

    tral

    Darwinian.

    Needless

    to

    say,

    he

    also made

    significant contributions

    to

    Darwinism,

    but even

    if

    he

    had

    not,

    he would

    still

    have to be

    counted

    a Darwinian.

    Any

    member of

    the

    group

    who was

    genuinely

    a member

    of the

    group

    can function

    as a

    type specimen

    (a

    name bearer) for

    the group.

    Hooker,

    Huxley,

    and

    Lyell

    would all

    serve

    equally well.

    Because

    of

    his

    isolation in

    the United

    States,

    Asa

    Gray

    would

    serve less

    well,

    while

    Henslow was so

    peripheral,

    he

    might

    not

    even be

    counted

    a

    member.

    No-

    tice, however: if Henslow is excluded from the Darwinians, it is not

    because of his

    conceptual

    reservations

    but because

    he

    had

    ceased to

    have

    sufficient

    contact with the

    Darwinians

    by

    1859 and died

    soon thereafter.

    Because

    communities of

    scientists

    are sometimes

    named by means of the

    name

    of

    a

    particular

    scientist,

    care

    must be

    taken

    not to confuse

    social

    type specimens

    with

    eponyms.

    When

    the

    group

    is

    named after a

    patron

    saint,

    the

    distinction

    is

    easy

    enough

    to

    keep

    in

    mind.

    Mendel was clea-

    ly

    not

    sociologically

    a

    Mendelian. He

    had been

    long

    dead

    when Bateson

    picked him as a

    patron saint and

    eponym for the

    Mendelians. All

    sorts

    of

    considerations

    go

    into

    naming

    scientific

    groups.

    sometimes

    they are

    named

    after particular scientists (the Newtonians, Darwinians and Men-

    delians),

    sometimes

    after

    places

    (the Cold Spring

    Harbor

    group, the

    Columbia

    Drosophila

    group, the

    Texas

    group), and sometimes

    after

    views

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    12/26

    489

    they

    hold or are believed

    to hold

    (phrenologists,

    uniformitarians,

    atom-

    ists).

    The first

    two

    ways

    of

    naming

    scientific

    communities

    pin

    them

    down

    appropriately

    to

    particular times and

    place;

    the

    latter

    does

    not

    unless

    "ideas" are

    made

    particular

    in

    a

    way

    that

    conflicts

    strongly

    with

    traditional usage (see later discussion). In any case, the choice of a

    particular

    scientist

    as the

    type

    specimen

    for

    a

    particular

    group

    is

    in-

    dependent

    of the

    name chosen for the

    group.

    The

    scientist who

    serves

    to

    pin

    down

    the name

    "Darwinians" to the

    Darwinians

    need

    not be

    Darwin.

    Any

    member of

    the

    group

    would do as

    well.

    As

    I

    have been

    using

    the

    term"Darwinian"

    thus

    far,

    it refers

    to

    a

    small

    group

    of

    scientists that formed a

    tightly

    knit

    group

    during

    the

    first

    decade or so

    after the

    publication

    of

    the

    Origin.

    The

    fate

    of

    this

    group

    can be

    described in

    two

    ways:

    either it

    petered

    out

    as

    its

    members

    died

    or lost

    interest,

    or it

    expanded

    to

    include almost

    every-

    one working in evolutionary biology. I prefer the first alternative

    because

    the

    "Darwinians" in

    the second

    sense

    was

    not

    much of a

    social

    group

    (for

    a

    classic

    example

    of

    a

    groups

    of

    scientists

    gradually

    dis-

    integrating, see

    MacLeod

    1970).

    However,

    in

    the

    last

    decade

    of

    the

    century,

    something peculiar

    happened.

    A

    new

    group

    of

    scientists e-

    merged

    who came to

    be called

    the

    "neo-Darwinians".

    The

    old

    guard Dar-

    winians

    did not

    evolve into

    this

    group;

    most

    opposed what

    they

    took to

    be

    the

    excessive

    emphasis

    placed

    by

    the

    neo-Darwinians

    on

    selection.

    In-

    stead,

    young scientists

    who

    were

    "Darwinians"

    in

    only

    the

    broadest

    sense of

    the

    term

    organized

    themselves into a

    new

    scientific

    research

    group

    in

    reaction

    to

    the

    work

    of

    August

    Weismann

    (Churchill

    1968,

    1978).

    Once

    again,

    this

    group can

    be

    individuated

    by

    selecting one of

    its

    mem-

    bers as the type specimen and tracing his professional

    relations to oth-

    er

    members of

    the

    group.

    As

    should

    be

    clear

    by

    now, the

    designation

    of

    one

    member of

    a

    group

    to be

    the

    type

    specimen for

    a

    group

    is not

    something

    that

    the

    members

    of

    that

    group do

    but is a

    device

    employed

    by

    others

    studying

    the

    group.

    Because

    more

    than

    one

    scholar

    is

    likely to

    study the

    same

    group

    or

    groups,

    disagreements

    are

    sure

    to

    arise.

    As

    long

    as

    everyone

    keeps

    in

    mind

    that

    the

    designation of

    a

    particular

    member of a

    group

    as

    the

    so-

    cial

    type

    specimen

    for that

    group

    does not

    imply

    anything

    about

    the

    con-

    tributions

    of

    this

    scientist,

    one

    important

    source

    for

    scholarly

    squab-

    bling is eliminated. Because the choice of a social type specimen is

    arbitrary

    with

    respect

    to

    contributions,

    considerations

    of

    priority

    are

    good

    enough

    to

    settle

    disputes

    over

    who is or

    is

    not

    the

    type

    specimen

    for a

    given

    group.

    I

    am

    not

    saying

    that there

    will

    not be

    disagreement

    about the

    "proper"

    name

    for

    a

    group,

    but

    such

    disputes

    to

    one

    side,

    whatever

    name

    is

    settled

    on

    can

    be

    attached

    unequivocally

    to

    that

    group

    by the

    social

    type

    specimen.

    The

    one

    implication of

    the

    type

    specimen

    method

    when

    extended to

    apply

    to

    social

    groups

    that

    I

    find

    disquieting is

    the

    inflexible

    tying

    of

    a

    name

    to

    the

    type

    specimen.

    For

    example,

    consider

    a

    hypothetical

    situa-

    tion

    in

    which

    the

    first

    scholar

    studying

    the

    neo-Darwinians

    thinks thatC. J. Romanes

    (1848-1894) was

    a

    neo-Darwinian

    and

    uses him

    as the

    type

    specimen

    for

    the

    neo-Darwinians.

    Very

    little

    research

    would be

    requimd

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    13/26

    490

    to uncover the

    mistake.

    Nevertheless,

    a

    rigid

    application

    of the

    type

    specimen

    method would

    require

    that

    the

    name

    "neo-Darwinian" be

    applied

    to Romanes

    and his scientific

    circle,

    not to

    such workers

    as

    Thiselton-

    Dyer,E.

    R.

    Lankester,

    and

    E. B. Poulton.

    Although

    such mistakes are

    liable to be very rare in intellectual history, the imposition of such

    non-standard

    terminology by

    commentators on science is sure to be re-

    sisted and

    justifiably

    so. It must be admitted that cases in

    which

    blanket application

    of

    the

    rules of

    nomenclature would

    require

    the

    abandonment of a familiar name

    are

    not unknown

    in

    biological systemat-

    ics.

    More time is

    spent

    at the

    periodic meetings

    of

    the nomenclatural

    congresses

    hearing appeals

    on

    such issues

    than

    on

    just

    about

    any

    other

    matter.

    4.

    Conceptual

    Systems

    Commenting on the reaction to his The Structure of Scientific Revo-

    lutions, Kuhn

    (1970, p. 187)

    remarks

    that the "paradigm as shared ex-

    ample

    is

    the

    central element

    of

    what

    I

    now

    take

    to

    be the most novel

    and

    least

    understood

    aspect

    of this book." One

    of

    the

    problems

    raised

    by

    Kuhn's book has come to be known as

    the

    problem

    of

    incommensurabili-

    ty.

    If

    scientific theories are

    tightly-knit

    inferential

    systems,

    if

    even observation

    statements

    are

    theory-laden,

    and if

    the

    only

    rational

    way to choose between

    competing theories is

    to derive contradictory

    observation statements

    from

    each,

    then

    theory

    choice

    in

    science

    would

    seem to be

    necessarily

    a nonrational

    process.

    As

    Kuhn sees

    it, the

    chief

    misunderstanding

    of

    his

    views

    is

    the conclusion that scientific

    change

    is

    fundamentally

    irrational.

    Part

    of the

    problem

    is Kuhn's

    habit of equating inference with deductive inference, deductive infer-

    ence with

    logical,

    and

    logical

    with rational.

    Hence, any inference

    that is not

    deductive

    is

    neither

    logical nor rational.

    Certainly

    scientific

    change

    is not

    exclusively

    a

    matter of deductive

    inference.

    It

    is not,

    thereby, nonrational, let alone irrational. Rationality is

    a much broader notion

    than deductive inference.

    The novel feature of Kuhn's

    system is the

    way

    he intends to circum-

    vent

    the problem of

    incommensurability by reference to exemplars.

    An

    exemplar

    not

    only

    solves

    the

    problems

    for

    which

    it

    was formulated but

    also serves as a model

    or

    example

    to

    "replace

    explicit

    rules as a

    basis

    for the solution of the remaining puzzles of normal science." (Kuhn

    1970, p. 175).

    People

    have the

    ability

    to

    extrapolate

    from

    one puzzle

    solution to

    another

    without

    being

    able to formulate

    any rules that they

    might

    be

    using

    to make

    these extrapolations.

    Kuhn (1977, p. 472) ex-

    plicates this

    ability

    in terms

    of a "learned similarity relation". The

    example

    Kuhn

    uses

    to

    illustrate

    this notion

    is,

    for our

    purposes,

    un-

    fortunate.

    It is a

    father

    teaching

    his child

    the differences between

    swans, geese

    and ducks as

    they

    stroll

    through

    a

    park. As epistemolog-

    ically important

    as

    the similarity relation

    may be for inferring gene-

    alogy,

    I

    agree with biologists such as Mayr

    and Simpson that theoreti-

    cally genealogy is

    prior

    to

    similarity. In spite of this disagreement,

    Kuhn's

    main

    thesis

    remains unaffected.

    From

    the

    point

    of view

    of

    evading the problem of incommensurability,

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    14/26

    491

    the

    important

    issue is the

    nature

    of this

    similarity

    relation.

    If

    it

    can

    be

    expressed

    linguistically,

    then

    Kuhn is

    right

    back

    where

    he

    started. The words

    used

    to

    express

    the

    similarity

    relation

    that

    ob-

    tains between an

    exemplar

    and its

    exemplifications

    are as liable

    to

    be

    as theory-laden as any others. If this relation cannot be expressed

    linguistically,

    then

    its

    status

    remains

    problematic.

    It is

    one

    thing

    to

    argue

    that a

    particular

    way

    of

    reasoning

    is not

    adequately captured

    by

    current formal

    analyses

    of inference.

    It

    is

    quite

    another

    to

    argue

    that it is

    ineluctably

    ineffable. If

    biological

    species

    really

    were

    classes

    of similar

    organisms

    (ancestor-descendant

    relations

    be

    damned),

    current methods of

    multivariate

    analysis

    can

    capture

    these

    correlations

    well

    enough. There

    is

    nothing

    ineffable here.

    Problems arise

    chiefly

    when

    one

    attempts

    to

    combine

    genealogy

    with

    similarity.

    I

    am not sure

    that Kuhnian

    exemplars

    can be used to

    avoid

    the

    prob-

    lem of

    incommensurability (Suppe 1977). I propose to present quite a

    different

    use for

    exemplars--as

    type

    specimens

    for the

    individuation

    of

    conceptual

    systems.

    To

    perform

    the function

    assigned

    them

    by

    Kuhn,

    exemplars

    must

    be both

    exemplary

    and

    similar

    to

    their

    exemplifications.

    For

    example,

    a

    good

    case

    can

    be made that

    Mendel's

    way

    of

    structuring

    breeding

    experiments served as a

    Kuhnian

    exemplar

    for

    modern

    genetics.

    Most of

    the

    early

    progress

    in

    genetics was the

    result

    of

    geneticists

    milking Mendel's

    exemplar

    for

    all it

    was worth.

    However,

    problems

    arise.

    This

    same

    exemplar can be found in

    the works of

    other

    geneticists

    before

    anyone heard of

    Mendel.

    In

    many

    instances,

    it

    was

    these

    characteriza-

    tions

    that

    served

    as

    Kuhnian

    exemplars.

    As it

    turns

    out,

    legends

    such

    as

    Darwin's

    finches

    are often

    effective

    Kuhnian

    exemplars,

    as

    effective

    as more historically accurate examples. To complicate matters further,

    later

    applications of

    an

    examplar

    may

    have

    very

    little

    in

    common

    with

    earlier

    applications.

    To

    serve as a

    conceptual

    type

    specimen,

    as a

    fixed

    reference point

    by

    which

    a

    name can

    be

    attached

    to a

    conceptual

    system, an

    exemplar

    need

    not be

    especially

    exemplary, nor

    need

    it be

    in

    any

    sense

    similar

    to

    other

    elements in

    its

    conceptual

    system.

    However,

    it

    must be

    a

    good

    deal

    more

    concrete than

    KuhnI's

    puzzle

    solutions. I

    am

    not

    sure

    whether

    those

    philosophers who

    have

    suggested

    treating

    conceptual

    systems

    as

    historical

    entities

    are

    completely aware of

    the

    magnitude of

    the

    change

    that they are suggesting. I suspect, as in the case of biology, rem-

    nants

    of

    the

    traditional view

    remain.

    Concepts are

    commonly

    treated as

    atemporal

    similarity

    classes,

    as

    expression

    types.

    Two

    instances

    of a

    particular

    concept

    (two

    expression

    tokens)

    are

    instances of

    the

    same

    concept

    if,

    and

    only

    if

    in

    some

    sense,

    they

    mean

    the same

    thing.

    A

    decade or

    so

    ago,

    Kripke

    (1972)

    and

    Putnam

    (1973,

    1975)

    caused

    quite

    a

    stir

    by

    suggesting

    that

    singular

    terms

    (in

    particular

    proper

    names) and

    some

    substance

    and

    kind

    terms

    might

    best be

    interpreted

    as

    rigid

    designators. In

    rigid

    designation, a

    name

    is

    conferred in

    an

    initial

    baptismal

    act

    (possibly

    fictitious)

    and

    thereafter

    passed

    on in

    a

    link-to-link

    reference

    preserving

    chain.

    Regardless

    of the

    appro-

    priateness of the Kripke-Putnam analysis in general, it accurately de-

    picts

    the

    way in

    which

    systematists

    introduce

    the

    names of

    biological

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    15/26

    492

    taxa. The baptismal

    act

    in

    systematics

    is not identical in

    every respect

    to that practiced by

    Judeo-Christians

    (e.g.,

    no water is

    involved),

    but

    it is easily as ritualized and never fictitious.

    Both also

    require

    ref-

    erence preservation. The respective terms

    cannot

    change

    their

    reference,

    although we can find out that we are mistaken about what we thought

    their reference was.

    The interesting thing about the Kripke-Putnam

    analysis is that it is

    applied

    to

    certain

    general

    terms

    (such

    as

    'tiger')

    as well as

    traditicn-

    al proper names (such

    as

    'Moses').

    If

    Iwere

    arguing

    that the names of

    particular species

    are

    general

    terms and species themselves kinds of

    some

    sort,

    the

    coincidence of taxonomic

    practice

    with the

    procedures

    postulated by Kripke

    and Putnam

    might

    serve as

    indirect

    support

    for

    their

    views.

    However,

    because

    my

    main

    contention

    is that

    species

    are

    not

    kinds

    and their names not

    general,

    the position

    I

    am

    arguing has,

    in

    this connection, no implications

    for

    the Kripke-Putnam

    analysis of rigid

    designation. The names of particular species, as are the names of all

    spatiotemporally localized individuals, proper.

    That

    proper

    names are

    rigid designators should surprise no one.

    The interesting feature of

    the

    Kripke-Putnam analysis

    for our

    purposes

    is

    that the link-to-link

    reference preserving

    chains are themselves historical entities tied

    down

    to a particular time and place. No use of

    a

    term not causally connected

    to the original baptismal act can be part of

    this chain.

    The

    main

    weakness

    of the

    Kripke-Putnam

    analysis

    for

    my purpose is

    that

    it

    must be reference

    preserving. Species

    do

    evolve even

    if

    the

    link-to-link reference preserving

    chains do

    not.

    However,

    I

    see no

    reason not to let these chains themselves "evolve". Kitcher (1978) sets

    out a

    way

    in

    which it

    is

    "possible

    for

    scientists

    to

    use different

    to-

    kens

    of

    the same expression-type

    to

    refer

    to different entities."

    (Kitcher 1978, p. 536).

    He does so

    by

    means of postulating a community-

    based reference

    potential

    for

    each

    expression-type.

    The reference

    po-

    tential of

    an

    expression-type

    for a

    particular

    community is the "set of

    events such

    that

    production

    of

    tokens

    of that

    type by

    members of the

    community are normally instituted by

    an

    event

    in

    the associated set."

    (Kitcher 1978, p. 540).

    Because

    socially

    defined

    communities of

    scien-

    tists

    are to some extent heterogeneous,

    the reference potential of an

    expression-type

    is also liable to be somewhat variable

    at

    any

    one

    point

    in

    time. Because the

    make-up

    of scientific

    communities changes through

    time,

    the referential

    potential

    for

    particular

    expression-types

    is

    also

    likely

    to

    change through

    time.

    I

    think that what is needed

    in

    addition

    to

    a semantic analysis of

    reference such as the one presented by Kitcher, is

    a

    general analysis of

    conceptual systems that is

    not

    designed

    to solve traditional semantic

    problems such as meaning change

    but

    merely provides

    criteria

    for

    indi-

    viduating conceptual systems

    as historical entities. The purpose of

    this

    section is

    to

    present just such

    an

    analysis.

    On

    the basis

    of

    the

    biological analog,

    four conditions seem necessary:

    (1) descent is necessary: conceptual replication sequences and the

    systems

    which

    they

    form

    must be historical

    entities;

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    16/26

    493

    (2)

    local retention of information

    content

    in

    replication

    sequences

    is

    necessary,

    but

    global

    change

    must also

    be

    possible;

    (3) different

    replication

    sequences

    must co-exist

    in the same

    con-

    ceptual

    system;

    (4)

    the relations

    that

    integrate

    the elements

    of a

    conceptual

    system

    into a

    system

    include but cannot

    be limited

    just

    to inferential

    rela-

    tions.

    I do not intend to

    deny

    that there

    is some

    point

    in

    recognizing

    to-

    tally unrestricted reference

    types, e.g.,

    3 to

    1

    ratios in

    hereditary

    patterns.

    Literally

    hundreds of

    investigators

    can

    be found

    who

    stumbled

    upon

    such

    3 to

    1

    ratios

    (including

    Darwin).

    The lists of

    precursors

    that historians can

    produce

    for

    any

    "unit

    idea" or "theme" in

    science

    are

    fascinating'.

    These lists are sometimes

    disparaged

    because some of

    the

    items on a

    particular

    list are

    really

    not similar

    enough

    to

    count as

    being the same idea. This is not my complaint at all. My complaint is

    that

    concepts

    in

    this

    sense

    do not

    function

    in

    conceptual

    systems

    as

    historical

    entities.

    Paying

    attention

    to

    the filiation of

    ideas is not

    just good

    historiography--which

    it is--it

    is

    necessary

    if

    conceptual

    change

    is to

    be

    interpreted

    as a

    matter of the

    replication,

    competition,

    and

    selective retention of

    ideas.

    All

    three of

    these notions

    apply

    only

    to concrete

    exemplifications--tokens--and not

    types.

    To

    put

    it meta-

    phorically, there is no

    replication

    at a

    distance.

    Conceptual

    tokens

    must be

    organized

    into

    more

    inclusive

    entities,

    but

    these

    entities are

    not

    those

    of

    traditional

    semantic

    categories. Instead

    they

    are

    replica-

    tion

    sequences.

    One

    might well

    argue that

    Lamarck's notion

    of

    the

    transmutation of

    species was

    replicated

    in

    Darwin's

    theory

    of

    evolution

    because Darwin

    was at

    least aware of

    Lamarck's

    views as

    Lyell

    presented

    them

    in

    his

    Principles

    of

    Geology

    (1830-3),

    but

    one cannot

    claim

    that

    Darwin

    was

    replicating

    the

    transmutationist views of

    Pierre-Jean

    Cabanis

    (1757-

    1808)

    if no

    chain of

    influence can be

    traced from

    Cabanis

    to

    Darwin

    (Richards

    1982).

    Local

    retention of

    assertive

    content is

    necessary for

    tokens

    to

    be

    part

    of

    the

    same

    replication

    sequence, but it

    is

    far from

    sufficient.

    Matthew's

    (1831) statement of

    natural

    selection

    was

    nearly

    identical to

    that of

    Darwin, but

    it

    does not

    belong in

    Darwinism

    as an

    historical

    entity

    because no

    one seems

    to

    have noticed

    it

    or have

    been

    influenced by it. The point is not assigning credit for originality

    but

    gauging effect.

    Truly

    unappreciated

    precursors do

    not

    count.

    Matthew was not

    sociologically a

    Darwinian.

    Matthew's

    views, as

    similar

    as

    they

    might

    have

    been to

    those

    of

    Darwin,

    also do

    not

    belong in Dar-

    winism.

    If

    tokens of

    a

    particular idea

    are

    to build up

    differentially

    in a

    conceptual

    system,

    local

    similarity is

    necessary.

    Ideas

    must be

    trans-

    mitted

    with

    some

    fidelity.

    However,

    long

    term change

    must

    also be

    pos-

    sible.

    For

    example, all

    but

    one

    of

    the

    "laws" usually

    associated

    with

    Mendel's name

    at

    the turn of

    the

    century

    underwent rapid

    and

    signifi-

    cant change, butthey belong in the same replication sequence because

    they

    are

    modifications

    of previous

    tokens.

    Conversely,

    Goldschmidt's

    This content downloaded from 142.51.1.212 on Mon, 21 Jul 2014 16:41:41 PMAll use subject toJSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Exemplars and Scientific Change Author(s): David L. HullSource: PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the P

    17/26

    494

    (1940) systemic

    mutations

    do not

    belong

    in

    Darwinism even

    though quite

    similar ideas introduced

    thirty years

    later

    may (Gould 1982).

    Local similarity

    is relevant

    only

    for

    conceptual replication

    se-

    quences.

    Numerous

    ideas

    coexist

    in

    the

    same

    conceptual system

    even

    if

    they are quite different. For

    example,

    Darwin's views on evolution

    were quite

    different from

    his

    views on heredity.

    In

    his

    own

    version

    of

    Darwinism, they

    coexisted.

    In

    other

    versions they

    did not.

    Pangenesis

    was only one

    very

    minor

    strain

    in

    the larger

    conceptual system.

    One

    is

    tempted to

    interpret

    the

    relations between

    the several elements

    in

    a

    conceptual system

    in

    terms of

    inference,

    and

    inferences

    do

    play

    a role

    in

    integrating

    some

    of the

    elements of a conceptual system into a single

    system.

    As Toulmin

    (1972) puts it, there are at least "pockets

    of

    sys-

    tematicity"

    in

    scientific

    disciplines.

    However, the only inferential

    relations

    that

    belong

    in a

    system are the ones

    actually

    made at the time.

    Unnoticed though perfectly valid conclusions do not. Similarly, a well

    known property of contradictions

    is

    that

    they imply any proposition

    whatsoever. Time and

    again,

    later workers have uncovered contradictions

    in

    early formulations of particular scientific

    theories,

    but as

    long

    as

    these contradictions were not exploited, no

    damage

    was

    done.

    The

    only

    inferences