ruth solomons mres thesis: in the context of precarity in contemporary uk art practice: how can...

63
Ruth Solomons August 2013 This thesis is submitted for the MRes Arts Practice degree at the University of the Arts London In the Context of Precarity in Contemporary UK Art Practice: How Can Artists’ Strategies Be Made Evident? Wordcount: 9,820 Not including cover page, acknowledgements, contents and figures tables, captions, bibliography and appendices

Upload: birkbeck

Post on 26-Feb-2023

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Ruth Solomons

August 2013

This thesis is submitted for the MRes Arts Practice

degree at the University of the Arts London

In the Context of Precarity in Contemporary UK Art

Practice: How Can Artists’ Strategies Be Made

Evident?

Wordcount: 9,820

Not including cover page, acknowledgements,

contents and figures tables, captions, bibliography

and appendices

2

Acknowledgements

For their invaluable assistance while I have been studying the MRes Arts

Practice, and while writing this thesis, I would like to thank the following

people:

Dr Paul Ryan, Dr Eleanor Bowen, Dr Jo Melvin, Gustavo Grandal Montero, Dr

Linda Sandino, Alison Goodyear, Dr Kirsten Forkert, Mikey Cuddihy, Phil

Schryber, David Solomons, Rebecca Waterworth, Emma Robertson, Enfys

Jones, Rab Harling, Ben Walker, Lisa McKendrick, Ollie Harrop, and all my

co-students on the MRes course.

3

Table of Contents

1 Abstract.............................................................................................. 4

2 Introduction & Question...................................................................... 5

2.1 Aims & Objectives ....................................................................... 6

2.2 Methodology................................................................................ 7

3 Historical Context: Post-studio theory................................................. 8

4 Contemporary Context: Precarity ..................................................... 12

5 Ethics and Judgements.................................................................... 14

5.1 Atkinson & Baldwin: Deontic Statements................................... 15

5.2 Hytten: The Universalisability Criterion ...................................... 18

5.3 Sidgwick: Concomitant Influence and Implied Duty ................... 19

6 Work Ethic and Studiowork .............................................................. 23

6.1 Molesworth’s Curation of Work Ethic ......................................... 24

6.2 Fer’s Curation of Studiowork ..................................................... 26

7 Gillick: The Good of Work ................................................................ 32

8 My practice....................................................................................... 37

9 Conclusion ....................................................................................... 42

10 Bibliography ..................................................................................... 45

11 Table of Figures ............................................................................... 48

12 Appendices ...................................................................................... 49

Appendix 1 Glossary............................................................................. 50

Appendix 2 Critical Reading Form......................................................... 54

Appendix 3 Conversation: Split brains................................................... 55

Appendix 4 Hasty Drawings and Scribbled Thoughts............................ 58

Appendix 5 Portfolio.............................................................................. 59

4

1 Abstract

This thesis uses Terry Atkinson and Michael Baldwin’s artists’ book Theories

of Ethics (1970-71) as a theoretical springboard from which to discover ways

in which artists’ strategies can be made evident. Other ethics theorists that are

cited include C. D. Broad, Eyvind Hytten, Stig Kanger and Henry Sidgwick.

Two key examples of curation are analysed: Helen Molesworth’s Work Ethic

(2003) and Briony Fer’s Studiowork: Eva Hesse (2009).

The historical context is formed of Lucy Lippard and John Chandler’s essay

The Dematerialization of Art (1968), and Daniel Buren’s The Function of the

Studio (1979), in order to situate the studio in contemporary art practice.

Concepts of work in relation to art practice are expanded into concepts of

immaterial labour (Lazzarato, 1996). The context of precarity is connected to

artists’ strategies through treatment of my own art practice as a case study,

and through analysis of Liam Gillick’s essay The Good of Work (2012). I also

define the term precarity myself, in order to explain its pertinence to my

research.

Methods of making strategies evident are offered through analysis of deontic

statements, passive concomitant judgements and active duty judgements. The

conclusion details ways in which such analysis could be further developed

through practice, and in relation to Daniel Buren’s essay.

5

2 Introduction & Question

Question

In the context of precarity in contemporary UK art practice: how can artists’

strategies be made evident?

In his essay The Good of Work (2012), Liam Gillick describes how precarity

acts as a challenge to practice, and how judgements that result from

ignorance of its influence cause anxiety for artists. My research aims to find a

way to make its influence evident, through examination of artists’ strategies,

and the ways in which practice is enabled by them.

The term precarity is difficult to define in relation to artists, as it is more

generally used to describe the precarious balance of workers’ income

(resources) with living costs (economic pressure). Practice becomes a third

element in this equation, meaning that the variables become more complex. I

propose that these three elements are connected by the following equation:

Resources – Economic Pressures = Practice

Further, I propose that for practice to be sustained, a critical threshold is

required at which resources exceed economic pressures. Situations in which

this threshold is constantly being threatened cause the equation to become

precarious. Thus precarity for artists can be defined as the precarious balance

between resources and economic pressures at which practice becomes

difficult to sustain.

The equation illustrates that an increased state of precarity occurs either by a

decrease in resources, or an increase in economic pressures. ‘Resources’

describes the time, space and materials with which practice can be sustained.

‘Economic pressures’ describes the conditions in which practice occurs: in this

thesis, the conditions being considered are that of the UK, which now, at the

time of writing this, is slowly emerging from a recession in which the Arts were,

and remain, deeply affected.

6

In conditions of increased economic pressures, and reduced resources in

terms of time, space and materials, artists sustain practice through strategic

means, whereby resources become maximised in different ways than before.

Therefore the current context of precarity in UK art practice causes strategy to

become an integral part of practice. In her doctoral thesis The Strategic

Studio: How to Access and Assess Decision-Making in Visual Art Practice

(2009), Johanna Bosch describes strategy in art practice as ‘ tactical

adaptation, resulting from a combination of experiences and artistic, personal

and financial urgency, and ‘gut feeling’’. She asserts the day-to-day nature of

artists’ strategic decisions (Bosch, 2009: 37), which makes strategic art

practice all the more interconnected to precarity.

Over the years I have developed strategies that circumvent the practical

barriers to making work, in order to sustain my practice. Such strategies have

become embedded in the hidden processes of the studio, and decreasingly

prominent in the ways I re-present works in documentation and for display.

Therefore, my perception of the influence of precarity on art practice leads me

to take a first-person position in writing this thesis. I aim to demonstrate how

others have perceived it too, and through analysis of such examples,

formulate ways in which to make artists’ strategies evident.

2.1 Aims & Objectives

Aims

I aim to make explicit the different activities pertaining to work in art practice,

in order to make artists’ strategies evident.

I aim to demonstrate the context of precarity in contemporary UK art practice.

I aim to devise a method1 by which the influence of precarity on art practice

can be made evident.

1 This may need more time than is available in the context of this MRes thesis. In myconclusion, I will explain any limitations and formulate suggestions for further research either bymyself or others, to build on what I am able to achieve here.

7

Objectives

My explication of the different activities pertaining to work in art practice will

take in a broad range of references including curation of the exhibitions Work

Ethic (Molesworth, 2003) and Studiowork2 (Fer, 2009).

In order to demonstrate the context of precarity, I will analyse Liam Gillick’s

essay The Good of Work (2012), and I will also observe the influence of

precarity in my own practice.

I will apply theories from the field of ethics in order to devise a method by

which the influence of precarity can be made evident. My process for testing

these theories will take in a range of references, including the two

aforementioned exhibitions, Gillick’s essay, and my own practice.

2.2 Methodology

Using Terry Atkinson & Michael Baldwin’s artists’ book Theories of Ethics

(1970-71) as my starting point, my methodology will be to interweave ethics

with two examples of curation: Molesworth’s Work Ethic (2003) and Fer’s

Studiowork (2009). I will extract their respective curatorial motives in terms of

implied and anticipated judgements.

Different methods of applying ethics theory will be tested in turn, with my

question as a guiding premise for the tests.

The context of precarity in contemporary UK art practice will be interwoven

through analysis of Gillick’s essay The Good of Work (2012), and by using my

practice as a case study.

I will use examples from my practice to demonstrate my findings relating to

ethics and Gillick’s essay, and to create a visual response to my research

question.

2 I refer to this exhibition throughout my essay as Studiowork. However, the full title isStudiowork: Eva Hesse. I will expand on the pertinence of the term ‘studiowork’ in relation toEva Hesse, the subject of the exhibition, later in this thesis.

8

3 Historical Context: Post-studio theory

Post-studio theory engages with an expanded idea of what a studio can be

understood to be, in the aftermath of 1960s conceptual art, and Daniel Buren’s

1979 essay The Function of the Studio . It is a key context to my thesis due to

the central argument of whether a studio is critically important for

contemporary practice. This rejection, or redefinition of the studio, is further

complicated by the practical barriers to sustaining practice experienced by

contemporary artists.

Evidence of precarity in contemporary UK art practice can be observed in

closely knit constellations of practice such as those brought together by artists’

communities and studio groups. This is the context within which I am working,

and as such has contributed to my motivation to engage with the question

posed by this thesis.

Figure 1 Members of the BAT Pack, photograph by Ollie Harrop, 2011. Formalphotograph shot on medium format black and white film, of Bow Arts Trust artists whoexhibited together at the Mile End Art Pavilion, 2011, set against a backdrop ofLeopold Estate buildings where some of the artists had their live/work studios. (I am inthe front row, second from left). Image courtesy of Ollie Harrop.

9

The collective nature of artists’ communities and studio groups enables the

conceptual rejection of the studio to become reconciled with the practical

needs of individual artists. Such reconciliation is enabled both through

collective and individual strategies. As such, it could be said that strategies

evolved due to the precarity of contemporary art practice, cast new light on the

concepts behind post-studio theory: practical considerations override

theoretical ones.

John Milner describes how the ‘symbiosis’ of artist with city (whether by living

in it, or maintaining strong contacts while working outside it) was at one time

crucial to their prospects of success (Milner, 2009: 66). This absorption of ‘the

whole apparatus of recognition’ (Milner, 2009: 68) into a single collective

effort, is still evident in artists’ communities and studio groups throughout the

UK, such as Bow Arts Trust 3 which I am myself involved in, and artist-run

studios and galleries such as Rogue Artists 4 in Manchester, and Bayart5 in

Cardiff.

Kirsten Forkert asserts the sociological importance of the city for artists in her

doctoral thesis Artistic lives: a two-city study (2010):

These places foster collaboration between cultural producers, link

them to audiences, and operate within ‘networks of exchange’

(Castells, 1989, cited in Lloyd, 2010, p.166) … One’s proximity or

distance from cultural centres such as London can thus affect access

to opportunities - which are often secured through informal networks

and so require face-to-face contact (Forkert, 2010: 67).

3 Originally an artist-run studio building on Bow Road, with the Nunnery Gallery on the samesite, and a considerable-sized outreach programme in local schools, Bow Arts Trust has nowexpanded onto two additional sites in Bow and Bermondsey, as well as at one point managingover 100 live/work spaces in local council housing blocks (the majority of these flats are nowdue to be vacated within the next 6 months).4 Rogue Artists is an independent studio and gallery in Manchester which sustains strong linkswith London galleries. I corresponded with them about proposing an exhibition there, anddiscovered their links with Transition Gallery which had accepted the same proposal for anexhibition in London.5 Bayart is based in the Butetown docks area of Cardiff, and comprises of an artist run galleryand studios. My proposal for the exhibition Needle’s Eye (2012) was accepted for arts councilfunding there, which I curated and hung myself, and was therefore able to find out about thestudios and artists’ community connected to the gallery. Bayart also shows the JerwoodDrawing, Painting and Fellowship exhibitions.

10

Both collective and individual strategies are therefore evident in the networks

of opportunities and shared resources fostered by artists’ communities and

studio groups.

Daniel Buren’s essay The Function of the Studio (1979) contrasts the studio

against museum, as a place of production, a contrived space for visitors, a

rooted, physical site, developed due to the apparent expectation for artists to

make portable, commercial objects: ‘… the unspeakable compromise of the

portable artwork’ (Buren, 1979: 54).

As more and more work is designed in the studio but executed

elsewhere by professional craftsmen, as the object becomes merely

the end product, a number of artists are losing interest in the physical

evolution of the work of art (Lippard & Chandler, 1968: 46).

Lucy Lippard and John Chandler’s 1968 text The Dematerialization of Art

critiqued ways that art has tended towards ‘nothing’, in terms of not having or

perhaps never being able to achieve a state of ‘nothing’, and the subsequent

implications for practice (Lippard & Chandler, 1968: 50). For Lippard &

Chandler this tendency towards ‘nothing’ predicts a corresponding rejection of

studio practice, in terms of ‘the physical evolution of the work of art’ (Lippard &

Chandler, 1968: 46). I interpret their warning as pointing to anxiety about the

studio becoming merely an outsourced facility or production line, in which

practice solely results in art commodities.

11

Figure 2 Daniel Buren, From and Off the Windows, 1974. (Photo-souvenirs: DanielBuren). Image from <http://www.jstor.org/stable/778375>, (Crimp, 1981: 70).

Buren’s essay spoke broadly to artists working in any medium, emphasising

the importance of site. In his essay “My studio is the place where I am

(working)” Daniel Buren, Davidts explains the contradictory nature of Buren’s

wishes, and the consequences of the developments that happened in the

wider movement of which Buren was symptomatic. Buren asserts that the

studio is the ‘first frame’ (Buren, 1979: 53). His essay amounts to a

condemnation of studios as being an acceptance by artists of production-line

art practice (Davidts, 2009: 70). However, globalisation has since proven that

production-line art is present in practices that are not studio-based as well.

Therefore Lippard & Chandler’s warning rings true: the artist must guard

against loss of the studio, whether as a physical site, or any other method of

coordinating the ‘physical evolution of the work of art’ (Lippard & Chandler,

1968: 46). I aim to challenge Buren’s instinct about the studio being

fundamentally constrictive, while engaging with the idea of the site of an

artwork’s making being necessarily integral to practice. Similarly I will respond

to Lippard & Chandler’s warning that ‘the artist is losing interest in the

evolution of the work of art’, by making explicit the different activities pertaining

to work, methods and strategies, in the context of contemporary art practice.

12

4 Contemporary Context: Precarity

The term precarity describes the precarious state workers find themselves in

when income barely matches living costs. In relation to artists, precarity arises

more specifically due to a tight balance between making art, and paying living

costs, caused by variables including public and private funding, lack of time

caused by the need for an additional part-time job, or simply the nature of

income from art being affected by external economic pressures. This tight

balance is particularly prevalent among artists working within the current UK

economic situation. For artists like me, an increase in living costs directly

affects the time available for practice. Avenues where resources could be

increased, such as through part-time job pay-rises and sales of artworks, are

closed until the UK fully recovers from the recent recession, which could take

several years. Therefore this tight balance is likely to continue for the

foreseeable future.

Precariousness, hyperexploitation, mobility, and hierarchy are the

most obvious characteristics of metropolitan immaterial labor… It is

worth noting that in this kind of working existence it becomes

increasingly difficult to distinguish leisure time from work time. In a

sense, life becomes inseparable from work (Lazzarato, 1996: 137-8).

This kind of ‘working existence’ rings true for me, and as such was a key

prompt for my research. Working part-time and fitting studio time around that,

on top of many other practicalities, is indeed becoming ‘increasingly difficult’.

‘Life’ intrudes. I have already begun to observe how time pressures affect the

way I am working, through notebooks recording my thoughts, in and away

from the studio.

Immaterial labour refers to work that does not result in production in terms of

exchange or use value in the Marxist sense. 6 Maurizio Lazzarato describes

the subjective nature of immaterial labour in terms of creative exchange

between worker and consumer (Lazzarato, 1996: 147). He emphasises the

6 I am aware that the larger discourse of immaterial labour in a social context would divert mythesis away from the processes of art practice itself, into an area that would not answer myquestion. I mention it here as a preface to Gillick’s essay, in which he infers that practice ofartists and ‘knowledge workers’ are a form of immaterial labour, but aside from that I will leavethe larger discourse of immaterial labour in art practice to other researchers.

13

importance of the consumer’s role and as such appears to dismiss a Marxist

approach to labour as having exchange value. Rather he believes it is a

people-based subject shift: ‘a “silent revolution” taking place within the

anthropological realities of work’, formed of individual relationships, in all the

incidents of mutual exchange between workers and consumers (Lazzarato,

1996: 140).

Liam Gillick’s The Good of Work (2012) echoes Lazzarato’s call for a people-

based subject shift, with specific reference to art practice. As such, I will

examine Gillick’s essay closely, in terms of how the assertions of his text

respond to implied or anticipated judgements. Such assertions include the title

itself: the notion behind the word ‘good’ denotes ethics, and as such implies

judgement; the word ‘work’, thus described by this notion of ‘good’, also then

implies judgement. Gillick himself demonstrates the ethical problems of such

an assertion by posing the question: ‘what is the good of this work?’ at the

outset of the essay (Gillick, 2012: 61). Through his interpretation of art practice

as immaterial labour, Gillick focuses on the reasons why artists persist in the

face of (apparently) little or no reward for such work. He presents us with a

precise, universally applicable description of the awareness artists now have,

about ‘theories of immaterial labor’ which ‘have exerted a profound influence

on the starting point of current artists’ (Gillick, 2012: 62). Gillick’s essay is of

key interest to my thesis, in terms of how he describes this ‘awareness’

influencing practice, and how strategies become formulated to overcome it.

14

5 Ethics and Judgements

My question’s emphasis on the strategic elements of studio practice, and how

they can be made evident, implies the presence of judgements. Decisions

made in the process of an artwork’s representation (or re-presentation), be it

through exhibition, documentation or archiving, all have their root in

judgements. As I explored my chosen examples of curation and writing, and

became more self-reflexive in my development of the research in my practice,

I began to notice the presence of certain statements and questions which

betrayed a sense of judgements being made. As such, ethics became a firm

theoretical component in my research.

My route into the area of ethics was an artists’ book by Atkinson & Baldwin,

founding members of British Art Collective Art & Language, titled Theories of

Ethics (1970-71). Atkinson & Baldwin’s text begins with a ‘declaration device’

format, followed by Hytten’s criteria, after which they explore a wider field of

ethics theory in a formal academic style. It is essentially an artists’ book about

ethics which crosses over between art-thinking and ethics-thinking. As such I

was very intrigued. Their understanding of the importance of ethics in art

resided specifically in the way they used language.

I sought out Hytten, the theorist quoted by Atkinson and Baldwin, but not

referenced in any footnote or bibliography. He emerged to be a Swedish

scholar, and the source I found was his 1959 doctoral thesis: The concept of

morality and the criteria of legitimate argumentation: An examination of some

recent definitions. I soon realised that this was not available in the UK.

Eventually I became the grateful recipient of an interlibrary loan, from which

point I began to uncover how Hytten’s ethics of language had inspired

Atkinson & Baldwin. Atkinson & Baldwin became the springboard for my

journey through a wider field of ethics, including writers such as C. D. Broad,

Eyvind Hytten, Stig Kanger and Henry Sidgwick, but I always returned back to

their original book as my gateway between art and ethics.

Hytten explains the threatening nature of judgements: ‘I do not threat [sic] you

with my fists, but with the things I may think and say about you if you do not

comply’ (Hytten, 1959: 1). Words need not be written or said: the sense that

15

they are even being thought can comprise such a ‘threat’. Like Gillick, I

perceive that artists are working in circumstances in which judgements are

implied or anticipated, judgements which are not explicitly spoken, but

nevertheless exert influence. To ascertain the effect of such implied or

anticipated judgements, I will use ethics theories raised by Atkinson & Baldwin

in Theories of Ethics (1970-71) to formulate my own methods of analysis.

Gillick provides a useful example of an implied judgement in his essay The

Good of Work. As mentioned in the previous chapter, he formulates the

question: ‘What is the good of this work?’ (Gillick, 2012: 61), the judgements

implied in which are expanded as follows:

The accusation inherent in the question is that artists are at best the

ultimate freelance knowledge workers and at worst barely capable of

distinguishing themselves from the consuming desire to work at all

times... (Gillick, 2012: 61)

The objective of such a question might be to find out what may result from

such work. However, the formulation of the question conveys a threat of

approval/disapproval, as per Hytten’s quote above. Gillick uses the terms

‘best’ and ‘worst’ to convey the sense of impending judgement that artists

experience as a result.

5.1 Atkinson & Baldwin: Deontic Statements

The ‘declaration device’, as used in Atkinson & Baldwin’s Theories of Ethics

(1970-71) does not simply expand a statement through a sequence of

‘declarations’: it also proposes itself as a method for practice (Art & Language,

1969: 4). This echoes text which I have written myself in the course of my

practice, an example of which can be seen in figure 3. I propose that these too

might be ‘declarations’, and as such complicit in the method of my own

practice.

Atkinson & Baldwin’s Theories of Ethics (1970-71) opened up possibilities for

analysis of language in the context of art practice. In ethics, words such as

ought, with a notion of judgement behind them, are commonly understood to

16

imply judgement. Later, I will describe the implications of the word ought with

reference to Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics (1962, originally

published 1874). First, I wish to focus on deontic statements, which also imply

judgements. These are statements where ‘the assertor’ might ‘deny that he

has (or refuse to give) “reasons”, in contexts in which we are “entitled to infer”

that he has and is “willing to give reasons” ’ (Atkinson & Baldwin, 1970-71:

41).

Figure 3 Ruth Solomons, Takeaway tin lid, 2012.

Therefore an ethical analysis of just one of the statements on my work

Takeaway Tin Lid (figure 3, above), could reveal several implied judgements

despite absence of my ‘reasons’ for the statement, for example:

You have to put on a lot of paint to keep it looking light 7

7 This statement is in fact back to front, in the more general understanding of how to keeplightness in a painting: traditionally, adding paint with a light touch is understood to allow therefraction of daylight through its surface, and thus give a light feel to the painterly quality. Bysaying instead that ‘you have to put on a lot of paint’ I was being deliberately converse. Thechallenge implicit in such statements help me think about the limits of paint’s capabilities, in thesame way that holding up a mirror helps me to look at the composition in reverse.

17

Here, ‘you have to’ carries the same notion as ought. Such implied

judgements could include:

The painting’s finished quality ought to be light

Paintings ought to sustain a light quality during the course of their making

You ought to put on a lot of paint

In the words of Atkinson & Baldwin, we are ‘entitled to infer’ such reasons, in

the case of identifying a deontic statement. As per the above analysis, my

statements could be seen as declarations that ‘propose… a method for

practice’ (Art & Language, 1969: 4), and could affect, for example, the quantity

of paint I am using.

Figure 4 Ruth Solomons, Untitled, 2012: detail of an unfinished painting. This detaildemonstrates different thicknesses and intensities of paint (and different qualities oflight).

Atkinson & Baldwin’s approach enables me to begin to answer my question of

how artists' strategies can be made evident, and to argue that the agent of a

judgement is ‘willing to give reasons’, and the addressee (artist) is ‘entitled to

infer’ reasons. Statements, such as depicted in figure 3, help me carry

thought-threads between studio days, through their assertions of my

18

strategies. I will return to this aspect of my practice later, as an indicator of

how my practice responds to judgements, as well as finding strategies that

enable my practice to be sustained within available resources.

5.2 Hytten: The Universalisability Criterion

Atkinson & Baldwin quoted ‘Hytten’s Criteria’ in their text, followed by a

questioning of whether these criteria are necessary, whether any one of them

would be sufficient to ensure a moral judgement, or even if they are all

necessary. I felt the third of these, ‘the universalisability criterion’, could be of

help to my research, which was described by Atkinson & Baldwin as follows:

(iii) The ‘universalizability’ criterion. A moral judgement must be as

‘universalizable’ as possible, i.e. a person who makes a moral

judgement at t must be willing, at t, to ‘universalize’ his judgement at

least to some extent (Atkinson & Baldwin, 1970-1: 31).

I sought further insight through examination of Hytten’s own writings. He

describes three main senses in which ‘the ‘universalizability’ criterion’ can be

applied. This provided me with a much broader concept of universalisability

than that conveyed by Atkinson & Baldwin. At the risk of losing some of the

complexity of Hytten’s analysis, I will shorten the three senses as follows:

1: Universalisability of attitude to different sets of people or circumstances

2: Universalisability of emotive notions about observable qualities

3: Universalisability as a rational prerequisite based on facts

I will now return to the example of Gillick’s question ‘What is the good of this

work?’ (Gillick, 2012: 61).

These three senses of universalisability enable me to point to the ethical

problems of Gillick’s question as follows:

19

1: The question betrays an attitude specific to ‘this work’. The word ‘this’

seems to apply only to contemporary artists working with little or no chance

of economic reward: the object of Gillick’s essay.

2: The emotive notion behind the term ‘good’ is not universalised to all

comparable objects, actions or individuals with the same observable

qualities.

3: The emotive notion behind the term ‘good’ itself undermines the factual

basis of the question, so in the third sense we discover a further un-

universalised aspect.

In short, the pointing to certain people or circumstances by the emphasis on

‘this’ in ‘this work’ is problematic, in addition to the notion behind the term

‘good’, which denotes an emotive sense of right or wrong hanging in the

balance.

5.3 Sidgwick: Concomitant Influence and Implied Duty

A deontic statement, as described by Atkinson & Baldwin earlier in this

chapter, implies judgement, without containing obviously judgemental

language or terms (Atkinson & Baldwin, 1970-71: 41). Kanger describes the

need for ‘some occurrence of “ought”’ in order for a statement to be described

as ‘deontic’ (Kanger, 1971: 101). This concurs with Atkinson & Baldwin’s

differentiation between deontic statements and imperatives: ‘ought’ pertains to

judgements, whereas imperatives merely instruct (Atkinson & Baldwin, 1970-

71: 41).

In the third chapter of Henry Sidgwick’sThe Methods of Ethics , originally

published in 1874, he describes the notion of ought

8

as having two senses:

8

From this point onwards, I will use bold type for the words ought, concomitant and duty, to

emphasise their occurrence in statements, and in my related analysis. Where I use the word

concomitant, I will tend to combine it with the word ‘influence’, to denote its passive sense:

concomitant influence. I will both indicate and temper duty’s active sense by pairing it with

‘implied’: implied duty. This use of the bold type and pairings is to assist readability in the

statements which I will formulate, and to consistently maintain the passive/active senses of

ought statements.

20

Concomitant: a collective influence originating from an implied audience

Duty: implying punishment, exclusion, or ‘dislike’ of the addressee

The concomitant sense relies on assumptions about moral behaviour, such

as the moral obligation not to cause harm. The sense in which duty is implied

relies more on the addressee’s fear of punishment (Sidgwick, 1962: 28-9). The

ethical implications of each are quite different: in the first case, a danger lies in

the ignorance of the person expressing the judgement; in the second, the

effect can be to distort the addressee’s subsequent action. Sidgwick’s two

senses, concomitant and implying duty, both imply a sense of ought buried

beneath several layers of social assumptions.

Figure 5 ‘Tracey Emin in her Spitalfields studio’ (original caption) , 2013. Image from:

<http://www.dailymail.co.uk/home/you/article-2311050/Tracey-Emin-opens-intimate-

photo-memoir-tells-Liz-Jones-past-shaped-lifes-work.html> (Jones, 2013).

21

‘Does she work all the time? “I can sit here and sew while talking to

you, but that’s not work, it’s production…” ‘ (Jones, 2013)

9

Amusingly, Emin answers the above question literally, interpreting ‘all the time’

as meaning even now, ‘while talking to you’. I perceive her response as being

defensive against the question’s implied judgement. The context in which the

question is asked has a history of social assumptions, including mistrust of

contemporary art, and knowledge of Emin’s fame and privileged position as a

Young British Artist. Therefore it acts as a deontic statement. Below I have

expanded this fragment of dialogue to demonstrate the presence of such

social assumptions in the interviewer’s question:

Does Tracey Emin, a rich, famous artist who makes conceptual art, which

is not popularly understood to require skill and application, work all the

time?

A concomitant judgement about the collective voice of The Mail on Sunday ’s

readership lies at the base of the interviewer’s question, and a corresponding

duty is demanded of Emin. She ought to be able to justify her practice in

terms of how much ‘work’ she does. Social assumptions about the article’s

readership’s ignorance about contemporary art practice demand this, and as

such Emin’s duty is to demonstrate that despite her (now) privileged position,

she is (still) hard-working.

The above analysis demonstrates how a combination of both the

concomitant sense and that in which duty is implied, are both evident in the

deontic statement: social assumptions can be found to have many layers,

obscuring our perception of judgements. By emphasising the importance of

‘work’ in Emin’s practice, the article distorts both the way her practice is

presented, and the readership’s resulting perception of an artist such as Emin.

The dual sense of ought as comprising of concomitant influence and implied

duty enabled me to analyse the fragment of dialogue from the interview with

Emin, with awareness of her practice in mind. This builds on the sense of

9

This quote is taken from an interview between Liz Jones and Tracey Emin in You Magazine, in

The Mail on Sunday, 21 April 2013. Available at: <http://www.dailymail.co.uk/home/you/article-

2311050/Tracey-Emin-opens-intimate-photo-memoir-tells-Liz-Jones-past-shaped-lifes-

work.html>

22

judgement which I began to uncover using Hytten’s three senses of

universalisability, as described earlier. However, the method using Sidgwick’s

two senses of ought now seems better suited to answer my research

question: to analyse deontic statements by extracting the concomitant and

duty aspects of judgements that are implied. Therefore I will continue to apply

this method in the following chapter.

23

6 Work Ethic and Studiowork

The term work is commonly used in art. We talk of a work of art, an artwork, or

simply a work. Yet the idea of artists being workers seems at odds with the

nature of art practice, as it is generally understood.

The exhibition Studiowork by Briony Fer (2009) combines the place of work

with the activity of work into a single term. The subject of the show’s curation

was not the works themselves, but the slippage that occurs between resolved

works, and evidence of work processes. Despite using the word ‘studiowork’,

with its glancingly Marxist connotations, Fer was not simply trying to define the

idea of art as labour: she aimed to elucidate activities of making.

The exhibition Work Ethic by Helen Molesworth (2003) applied a pre-set

structure of ‘professional’ roles to an exhibition of primarily conceptual

artworks, in a conscious attempt to describe thresholds of art practice in

relation to work. The exhibition’s curation compared these thresholds with

professional roles, that would not usually be associated with artists and art

practice.

Fer’s and Molesworth’s curatorial methodologies both offer ways to make

artists’ strategies evident. As such, I am led to question their motivations in

curating these two exhibitions, which both seem, to a certain extent, to

address my question.

‘Work Ethic is an art-historical hypothesis writ large in the galleries of

the museum’ (Molesworth, 2003: 20)

‘It is obvious that this is hard to generalise for all artists, but it is surely

worth seizing the chance to describe some aspects of the drive to

make art. The studiowork is work without making a work, which may

end up as something to look at, or may not.’ (Fer, 2007: 24)

The above statements signal that their respective curatorial methodologies

could be universalised to a wider set of artworks. Fer’s neologism ‘studiowork’

is introduced sensitively, echoing the way Hesse herself conferred status upon

24

her smaller ‘test’ pieces by gestures such as giving them as gifts to friends.

Fer negotiates a concept of how all artists ‘make’ work, aside from concepts of

‘production’. In contrast, Molesworth’s proposal resembles a manifesto for all

artworks which elude a more general understanding of art as profession. In

her implication of an art-historical re-write, Molesworth proves beyond doubt

her intention to universalise. By analysing these two curatorial methodologies,

I hope to uncover a range of ways that such curation responds to implied or

anticipated judgements. I think it is pertinent that these exhibitions both apply

ideas of work in retrospect, in an archival reappraisal of works from decades

earlier. Work as a context for practice is emerging even more strongly now, in

the current UK economic situation.

6.1 Molesworth’s Curation of Work Ethic

Figure 6 Roxy Paine, Paint Dipper, 1997. Installation at Work Ethic (2003) at TheBaltimore Museum of Art. Photograph by Howard Korn. Courtesy of The BaltimoreMuseum of Art.

25

Roxy Paine’s Paint Dipper (figure 6) demonstrates a humorous transference of

the traditional role of artist to a machine, which repeatedly applies the canvas

to paint, rather than the usual application of paint to canvas. ‘The Artist as

Manager and Worker’, ‘The Artist as Manager’, ‘The Artist as Experience

Maker’ and ‘Quitting Time’ comprise the four categories used to subdivide

Work Ethic (2003). They attempt to portray the role of the artist in their

process of making, in a way that can be more accessibly understood by the

public. But does Molesworth’s parallel serve the artist? Roxy Paine employs a

system, or the services of a machine, in order to make art, but are his

strategies made evident by Molesworth’s analogy?

The exhibition … hopes to transform the tone of the audience’s

questioning from bewildered accusation to curiosity and engagement

(Molesworth, 2003: 17).

In the above deontic statement, Molesworth states her intention to address the

anticipated judgements of ‘the audience’. She aims to shift their focus from

expectation of ‘traditional artistic skills’ to a ‘larger sociocultural and economic

context’ (Molesworth, 2003: 17). Such anticipated ‘questioning’ is perceived

rather than voiced. As such the above statement presents its intentions as

being in response to anticipated ‘accusation’, therefore the exhibition responds

to a passive, concomitant influence. I could further analyse the word

‘bewildered’ to describe Molesworth’s perception of the ‘accusation’ arising

from ignorance. This echoes the concept of anticipated ignorance of the

collective readership of The Mail on Sunday , discussed previously.

However, the formal position of Molesworth as a curator of contemporary art is

far removed from the informal nature of a tabloid interview. Molesworth begins

her introduction for the Work Ethic catalogue by describing how ‘museums

with collections of modern and contemporary art are haunted by the often

unanswered questions of their visitors’ (Molesworth, 2003: 17). This leads me

to understand that an active duty lies with museums to respond to such

‘questioning’. Molesworth’s aim to ‘transform the tone of the audience’s

questioning’ thus speaks both of the concomitant influence of audiences

(passive) and the implied duty of museums (active).

26

The museum’s implied duty could be stated:

The exhibition ought to engage audiences

The audience’s concomitant influence could be stated:

Exhibitions ought to be engaging.

Therefore, the moment at which the exhibition Work Ethic engages a visitor, it

both fulfils its duty, and recognises the concomitant influence of the

audience. However, I propose that this then distorts the practices of those

artists, in terms of how their practices are portrayed, and how they are

perceived by audiences. In the earlier example of the Daily Mail interview,

Emin’s compulsion was to assert the nature of work in her own practice.

However, her response was also symptomatic of how all artists might respond

to such a deontic judgement, and thus reflects the same concomitant

influence and implied duty as Work Ethic’s curation.

As a contemporary artist in the context of the UK’s current economic situation,

I also perceive the concomitant influence and implied duty addressed by

Molesworth and Emin. My concern is that, consequently, such judgements

affect and distort my practice, in the same way that Work Ethic over-

emphasises an analogy of art practice with professional roles, and The Mail on

Sunday allocates a significant proportion of interview inches to Emin’s

assertions about art practice as work.

6.2 Fer’s Curation of Studiowork

It is hard not to name things. Even nothing is a name of sorts, but it is

not a proper name and that makes a difference … In order to try to get

as near to nothing as possible, I shall rename all the diverse little

experimental things and the so-called test-pieces, ‘studiowork’ … (Fer,

2009: 19)

A neologism, the term ‘studiowork’ was devised to convey the uncategorisable

nature of works by Eva Hesse that struggle to fully separate themselves from

the studio, and that defy assertion of the status of being a finished artwork

27

(Fer, 2009: 24). As such, studiowork becomes a universal term for such works

within the art practices of all artists.

Figure 7 Eva Hesse, Studioworks, installed at Fruitmarket Gallery, Edinburgh, 2009.Photograph courtesy of Fruitmarket Gallery.

In the housekeeping of death, they were carefully packed up and

stored (Fer, 2009: 14).

The process of archiving demands that the curator reflect on legacy: how will

this object, artist, oeuvre, be seen in the future, in light of the archive they are

creating now? In the case of the studioworks, this process was much delayed.

At the point when Fer was beginning to devise her curatorial concept, the

studioworks remained uncategorised. However, I propose that the artist also

reflects on legacy: an archival process that begins in the suspended moment

of their working activities. In practice, works are also ‘carefully packed up and

stored’ in an intuitive process akin to archiving. The following analysis

demonstrates how Fer’s concept of the studiowork enables a parallel to be

seen between archivist and artist.

28

If everybody can accept that artists ‘fool around’

10

with materials, it

may be less plausible to think it worthwhile to track a history of that

very basic sediment of activity within art-making. It might seem too

huge a subject while at the same time seeming too marginal to be

worth the trouble: a history of an impulse to make (Fer, 2009: 24).

This quote demonstrates how Fer is answering implied or anticipated

judgements. Fer attends both to the artist (in terms of their working methods)

and the museum (in terms of engaging the audience). I will analyse the above

two sentences in terms of concomitant influence and implied duty, as

explored previously in relation to Molesworth’s Work Ethic.

The concomitant influence of the audience sits within a range defined at one

end by ‘if everybody can accept’ and at the other by ‘less plausible to think it

worthwhile’. This range implies an increase towards being ‘worthwhile’. By

applying Molesworth’s sense of the audience’s expectation for the museum to

be engaging, I interpret that there are two concomitant influences upon Fer’s

curation. The first refers simply to artists’ methods, and the second is once

removed, referring to Fer’s method for describing artists’ methods:

The way artists use materials ought to be acceptable.

Fer’s method of describing the way artists use materials ought to be

plausible.

Fer asserts the museum’s duty as sitting within a range defined by ‘too huge a

subject’ at one end, and ‘too marginal to be worth the trouble’ at the other. I

interpret that Fer perceives judgement at both ends of this range, both apart

and co-existing at the same time. Following the same process as above, this

time in terms of Molesworth’s sense of the duty of the museum, two

statements can also be formed. However, now Fer’s opposing poles are

describing what the museum ought not to do:

10

The phrase ‘fool around’ refers to comments made by Sol Lewitt about uncategorisable works

by Eva Hesse in the Berkley Art Museum archive, ranging between the seemingly flippant ‘“I

think in the beginning she was just fooling around”’ and the more measured ‘“studio

leavings/experimental/little pieces/molds to make pieces out of/unresolved - unfinished pieces”’.

These quotes were taken from a transcript of a meeting between Sol Lewitt, Carol Androccio,

Connie Lewallen and Elise Goldstein at Berkeley Art Museum, CA, 17 November 1981 (in Fer,

2009, pp.14-15).

29

The museum ought not to tackle a subject that is too huge.

The museum ought not to bother with a marginal subject.

Fer’s response to the former concomitant judgements can be found in her

assertion of the studiowork being the ‘very basic sediment of activity within art-

making’. The duty judgements are answered in her articulation of how

Studiowork (2009) elicits ‘a history of an impulse to make’. The ‘studiowork’

thus signals archival awareness in both the artist and the museum.

The two sentences of Fer’s quote also echo each other in their repetition of

the words ‘worth’ and ‘history’. Here I detect Fer’s aim to align these two

concepts through her archival approach. The pedestal on which Fer’s concept

of studiowork placed previously unapplauded works was highlighted by many

observers of this exhibition, as is evident in the following quote from a review

of the exhibition:

Because these objects haven’t been shown in public – most were

given to the Berkley Art Museum by Hesse’s sister – we see them as

somehow lesser … their status as artworks is far from secure

(Darwent, 2009).

Darwent draws attention to the fact that these works had been ‘given’, later

describing that ‘status’ as being at odds with the ‘act of museologising’

associated with artists of such ‘greatness’ (Darwent, 2009). In Studiowork,

Hesse’s ‘greatness’ is asserted by the archival function of the museum, rather

than by the financial system of the art market, which also influences museums’

motives for exhibitions. Fer intends the worth of the studioworks to be

recorded in terms of new knowledge and legacy (history). It is this sense of

archival worth that Fer wishes to convey: worth that extends beyond the

market value of artworks, beyond Hesse’s legacy alone, into the unfolding

future archive of all such works, and the broader field of making and art

practice within which such works function. This ‘very basic sediment of activity

within art-making’ becomes an integral part of the newly asserted ‘history of an

impulse to make’, in the broadest possible way.

30

Fer’s sense of archival worth relates both to the artist and the museum, as

both are able to discover new knowledge and legacy within artworks through

the studiowork lens. Thus, Studiowork bridges the gap between the curatorial

drive of Molesworth’s Work Ethic, and an individual artist’s approach to art

practice.

This relates to the equation which I formulated in my introduction, which I will

re-state here:

Resources – Economic Pressures = Practice

Figure 8 Ruth Solomons, Various works in the studio , 2013

In the above image my work is displayed both framed and unframed; some

are wall-mounted, and some are leaning on the floor in ways that suggest

decision-making processes. The framed works are drawings on backs of

envelopes, quick annotated sketches on a material that would usually be

thrown away. However the contrast in their seeming material worth, to the

more traditional-seeming charcoal drawings on cartridge paper (to the left),

and to the bubble-wrapped paintings on canvas and board (to the right, behind

the wall), seems relevant here. This image displays examples of different

31

types of archiving by artists, and so demonstrates awareness of perceived

worth and status of artworks as beginning in the studio.

In the context of precarity, I would then state that distribution of resources

within practice reflects the archival decisions of the artist, within their available

means. The relationship between distributions of resources and their resulting

archived practices, can be demonstrated using the above equation, adapted

as follows:

Distribution of resources – Economic Pressures = Archived practice

Earlier, I qualified the former equation by stating that for practice to be

sustained, a critical threshold is required at which resources exceed economic

pressures. Here, a situation where the equation becomes precarious, could

result in an ‘archived practice’ that does not display the expected ‘distribution

of resources’, such as framing, or working with traditional artists’ materials. In

figure 8, I have mismatched the two, by investing a sense of archival worth

(through framing) into works made with less formal materials, within the

context of my practice. The strategies by which artists’ archival intentions are

implemented may be difficult to interpret by a museum curator, archivist, or

other agent of documentation. Fer’s concept of the studiowork contributes a

more nuanced insight to this field of the archived practice, and as such I

consider it a useful tool with which to describe artists’ strategies, particularly

with reference to the current context of precarity in contemporary UK art

practice.

32

7 Gillick: The Good of Work

The Good of Work by Liam Gillick (2012) describes the nature and possible

causes of artists’ anxiety about working without reward, with particular

reference to the ways this anxiety affects art practice. Gillick explores the ‘why’

version of my question: why do artists undertake practical strategies? I on the

other hand am looking at what strategies they evolve, and how they can be

made evident.

Artists exist in the professional realm (as they require income), yet they are

also ‘knowledge workers’ (Gillick, 2012: 62). The idea of knowledge exchange,

a form of immaterial labour, is readily accepted in an academic context.

However, translated to the professional realm, such exchanges are less

readily accepted as ‘work’. This echoes my own experience of contemporary

UK art practice, and draws attention to precarity as a key current context.

Gillick formulates the following question, as an example of the implied

judgements which artists perceive:

What is the good of this work? (Gillick, 2012: 61)

By articulating the response of artists in terms of ‘anxiety’, Gillick describes the

emotive impact resulting from this sort of ‘work’ being challenged, or even

simply not accepted. The following list describes a network of identities for

practice, by which Gillick aims to respond to the judgements implied in such

questions:

‘Leisure’ is not simply a counter-activity to work: for the artist it may be

‘adopted … to openly counter notions of labor as sites of dignity and

innovation …’ (Gillick, 2012: 63).

‘Self-enforced isolation’ is a key response by many contemporary artists,

and can take the form of co-opting other working models, or withdrawing

from production altogether (Gillick, 2012: 64).

‘Creation of one’s own deadlines’ to present an acceptable structure of

working practice is a mask devised to deflect accusations of not working

(Gillick, 2012: 66).

33

Art is a ‘lived experience, for the artist as much as for the viewer’: work is

one of many layers of activity in art practice (Gillick, 2012: 71).

‘Working alone but in a group’ entails collaboration of individuals, but does

not have to imply an artist’s consensus with a majority (Gillick, 2012: 72-

73).

By applying the ethical notion of ‘good’ alongside analysis of Gillick’s network

of identities, I aim to articulate the nature of artists’ strategies in relation to

‘work’.

Sidgwick devotes a whole chapter to ‘good’, positioning it as an ethical

concept in itself, as a notion equable to ‘desire’. He differentiates between

ideas of ‘what ought to be desired’, and ‘what would be desired’ (Sidgwick,

1962: 110-111). ‘Good’ is proposed to be a variable concept, with a passive

sense which I connect here with the concomitant sense of we, discussed

previously in relation to concepts of the audience’s expectations. In the

context of Gillick’s essay, ‘good’ could be articulated as follows:

The good is what we would desire in work.

Broad critiques Sidgwick’s concept of ‘good’, contradicting his assertion that

what we would desire is necessarily good. Term such as ‘ right, wrong, ought,

good, bad’ are all their own lowest denominators (Broad, 1930: 145). This

leads him to examine the relationship between the terms good and right, 11 as

absolute notions in themselves.

It is surely possible that both “good” and “right” are indefinable, as

both “shape” and “size” are, and yet that there is a synthetic,

necessary, and mutual relation between them, as there is between

shape and size. (Broad, 1930: 176-7)

I also made the connection between good and right in my earlier chapter

about universalisability; the term good denoting an emotive sense of right or

11

For this section of the thesis, I will use bold type for the words good and right. This

is to emphasise their occurrence in statements that I develop through my analysis.

34

wrong hanging in the balance. This emotive sense relates to Sidgwick’s

concept of good as concomitant desire. I will now develop the relationship

between good and right by offering another version of Gillick’s question:

Is it right to work like this?

If good is to be equated with ‘shape’, and right with ‘size’, then by abduction I

would propose that good is a variable concept, whereas right is an absolute.

The emotive sense of good in the concomitant sense of desire is what

makes it variable. Therefore ‘right’ is perhaps non-emotive, non-negotiable,

and this is where the sense of judgement hanging in the balance really

resides. In the above question, right could be interpreted to mean:

It is right to work in the way that we would desire.

Figure 9 Ruth Solomons, Back of Envelope Drawing 14 , 2013. Pen on back of

envelope.

In my painting practice, shape is a variable within my decision-making

processes, as demonstrated in Back of Envelope Drawing 14 , above. Shapes

can be moved between paintings through various methods of transposition:

tracing, projecting, copying across. Size however is often pre-defined by the

boundaries of the painting surface, the tracing paper, the distance of the

projector away from the wall. Yet the two are inextricably connected. The act

35

of taping a fixed-size piece of tracing paper onto a painting to try out a new

positioning of a shape, helps me visualise the connection Broad makes

between good and right.

I attempted to visualise some of Gillick’s network of artistic identities in relation

to my back of envelope drawing:

Figure 10 Diagram over Back of Envelope Drawing 14

What is the lived experience of visualising these shapes?

Is the tracing paper the right size to enable visualisation?

I developed the above questions to demonstrate the range of query that I

perceive in Gillick’s question. Gillick’s response to the implied accusation in

‘what is the good of this work?’ (Gillick, 2012: 61), is to demonstrate the

network of identities an artist exists within, and how ‘work’ fits into all the

branches of that network. Therefore a possible way of answering my research

question, of how to make strategies evident, is through articulation of networks

of artists’ identities. The above process leads me to conclude that the

following judgement is anticipated by my practice:

You ought to use the right size tracing paper.

36

The lived experience of visualising shapes in my practice is thus reduced to a

perceived judgement about the way in which I’m working. The comparison of

the two relationships, between good and right, and shape and size, is

demonstrated through the process by which I developed the above judgement.

By basing this process on a visual method, the relationships can perhaps be

perceived visually. However, I don’t think it’s a coincidence that it is my instinct

to connect the terms good and shape to practice, and right and size to

judgements about artworks. This process has many layers of implication for

practice, and for making artists’ strategies evident. I feel that it would be fruitful

to test more rigorously the relationship between these term at a future date.

Therefore this application of ethics in relation to emotive notions behind terms,

in relation to their more judgemental counterparts, such as between good and

right, could evolve into a method for discovering the effect of judgements on

artists’ practices.

Gillick’s sense of ‘lived experience’ (Gillick, 2012: 71) particularly resonates

with my sense of artists’ strategies relating to resources as well as practice.

Therefore I feel that Gillick’s identities for practice go some way to answering

my research question. These are key examples of the range of ways in which

art practice can be portrayed, when attempts are made to make artists’

strategies evident.

37

8 My practice

The changeable nature of the studio and the materials I’m working with mean

that it is not a self-contained site of activity: in the context of precarity my

practice becomes a more ‘lived experience’ (Gillick, 2012: 71). I began a

notebook as a conduit for thoughts had both in and away from the studio, to

create a record of the ways that thought-threads were sustained. The format

of the notebook was as a series of anecdotal thought-occurrences.

Figure 11 Ruth Solomons, Notebook 18/4/13, 2013. Page from notebook.

In entries made away from the studio, I recalled details that I had previously

thought reconciled in my decision-making processes. A simple method for

constructing wooden panels, revealed imperfections once they were glued

together (as described in figure 11). In the studio, I had been able to visually

reconcile these ‘mis-matched’ edges through my intentions for the painting

process that would follow. However, away from the studio, I lacked this visual

method of measuring and judging details. Such mis-remembering, or anxiety

38

from not having these objects visually present while my thought process

continues, becomes linked to my developing intentions for activities I will

undertake upon my return to the studio. Language begins to fill the gaps: the

gaps in my memory of the painting I am working on, and the gaps in time

between days in the studio.

The conclusion I reach, that I will ‘explore a range of possibilities’, could refer

to several of the activities described in this entry, including: planing, priming,

assertion of errors, and the painting processes I plan to undertake on the

panels’ surfaces. As with earlier observations about repeated statements in

my piece Takeaway Tin Lid (figure 3), such ‘possibilities’ do not simply lie in

the realm of language. Thought is visual as well as linguistic. Georgia Holz

describes this visual/linguistic overlap in relation to Eva Hesse’s notebooks

and diaries: ‘For Hesse, the artistic use of language and writing remained

inseparably tied to the visual and material aspects of art’ (Holz, 2004: 39).

Figure 12 Mikey Cuddihy, Slide, 2002: detail. Xerox, acrylic, gesso and paper on canvas. Photograph by Stephen White. Courtesy of Mikey Cuddihy.

Cuddihy's paintings speak frankly of the mundanity of the artist's life.

(Peer, 2003)

39

Mikey Cuddihy’s paintings have at their source doodles and scribbled notes

from telephone conversations, referring to day to day lived experience. Her

transformation of these doodles into paintings leaves a trail of transparent

process, behind which the original pages of the notepad remain visible,

untouched apart from their repetition through photocopying, visible in the detail

shown in figure 12.

Returning to images of Cuddihy’s work from her 2003 exhibition James in

Limbo, in the midst of writing this thesis, reminds me of the origin of my

research inclination to make strategies evident, and processes visible.

Through the display of Cuddihy’s paintings, and the accompanying press

release, essay and catalogue, the exhibition served to make evident the

strategies which were inherent to Cuddihy’s practice.

Figure 13 Ruth Solomons, Mobius, 2013. Oil on board: section of the reverse while painting was in progress.

A few weeks into working on them, I cut up the panels of my painting Mobius

(2013) with a jigsaw, in such a way that they could be reconfigured back into

rectangular panels. Having glued and taped the backs together, I continued

working on the fronts. When I presented some of these panels to co-students

40

on the MRes course, I was struck by their reactions, which I recorded as

follows:

Aware that they were seeing fragments separate from the whole work, my

co-students were curious to see the sides, the backs, to handle each panel

themselves. Hands held edges gingerly, tipping the panels away to see the

inside edges of jigsawed cuts through the surface, bare wood just visible in

cross-section. Minimal intervention of glue and gumstrip used to reconnect

sawn parts in their different configurations, became a pattern on the backs:

evidence of the artist’s eye and hand, echoing painterly reconfiguration on

the front. It became apparent the panels now had two fronts. The handling

was one symptom, the visual examination another. The first served to

discover the material reality of the panels, the second to understand the

methods and thought processes evident in these objects, which now

contained both two and three dimensional evidence of making.

The ‘two fronts’ both displayed ‘evidence of making’, but what my co-students

specifically observed was my ‘impulse to make’, as described by Fer in

Studiowork (Fer, 2009: 24). My notebook records ‘making’ in all my processes.

Yet intervention with a jigsaw was considered ‘making’, by my co-students,

whereas the original construction of the panels was not observed in the same

way. This leads me to conclude that these are perceived as different types of

‘making’, even though for me they are both integral to my practice. The

response of my co-students implied that if artists have the resources with

which to work, then they are making art. However this precludes the strategies

undertaken to attain such resources. In the context of precarity, the threshold

at which resources are available is in fact much lower, therefore activities

whereby resources are attained, or adapted, become integral to practice.

I finished the previous chapter describing how Gillick answers the question

‘what is the good of this work?’ in terms of practice being a network of

activities amongst which work resides (Gillick, 2012). The panels of my

painting also represent a network of activities, all of which are integral to my

practice. Even the methods by which I display errors, and methods of both

construction and re-construction, become integral (such as depicted in figure

13).

41

Figure 14 Mel Bochner, Wrap: Portrait of Eva Hesse, 1966

The network of activities that describe an art practice can be made evident

through language, for example in Mel Bochner’s word-image Wrap: Portrait of

Eva Hesse (1966). However, I would also argue that Bochner’s process was

first to perceive Hesse’s strategies visually, and then to express them in

language. Gillick’s sense of the network of activities also connects to Eva

Hesse, whose practice involved handling of all the parts: she interrogated pre-

fabrication through her making processes. All such activities were recorded in

her diaries, drawings, notebooks, and in documented conversations. Thus the

‘mundanity of the artist’s life’ (Peer, 2003) is made integral to practice through

the artist’s own decisions to make their strategies evident, a first stage in the

curating, archiving and documenting of artworks.

42

9 Conclusion

The strategies evolved by artists in the context of precarity are subject to

judgements made by a public still adapting to these conditions themselves.

The concomitant influence of audiences and readerships is felt by artists as

accusations, such as articulated by Gillick: ‘the accusation as framed by

doubts that form the base of art’s work’ (Gillick, 2012: 62), and Molesworth’s

‘bewildered accusation’ of the ‘audience’s questioning’ (Molesworth, 2003:

17). A duty also lies with the artist, however, one that I found relates to

practice as an archive: the artist in parallel to the museum. Fer sensitively

picked up Hesse’s thread in describing the nature of the ‘studiowork’, towards

the formulation of a new branch of history: ‘a history of an impulse to make’

(Fer, 2009: 24). I demonstrated my own ‘impulse to make’ in the jigsawed

panels which I presented to co-students.

I found that universalisability became a method with which to apply judgement

to judgements. Whereas, Sidgwick’s senses of concomitant influence and

implied duty in a passive/active dynamic evident in statements, enabled me to

interweave ethics with art practice discourse. As I want to simply make artists’

strategies evident, the latter method of gently opening up ethical notions within

statements, and analysis of passive/active judgements implied within them,

proved a more measured way to answer my research question.

My own practice demonstrated the critical nature of statements arising from

practice itself, in an echo of the declaration device employed by Atkinson &

Baldwin in their artists’ book Theories of Ethics (1970-71). This became a

circular referring back to my original impetus behind my foray into ethics.

Another concept I returned to was of resources. The reduction in resources

brought about by, and in comparison to, increased economic pressures, led

me to observe the role strategies play in maximising the availability of

resources. Such strategies included the construction of materials and

utilisation of time when I am away from the studio.

My assertion of the position the studio holds in contemporary art practice

included collectives and studio groups, and as such situated it as an important

base for art practice, where life outside ceases to intrude. I do not preclude life

experience as a studio in itself however, and this is where I agree with Buren.

43

Practice is key, and resources, such as a physical studio, are in service to it.

Lippard & Chandler also pitch this angle on practice: they describe how a

focus on applying concepts directly to artworks poses a danger that practice

gets bypassed. Hesse proved a great example as an artist who stayed true to

her conceptual integrity without sacrificing practice, as demonstrated through

Fer’s curation of Studiowork (2009).

Molesworth gave voice to the unconventional practices of conceptual artists,

whose resources do not lie in the expected realm of physical studio and

traditional art materials (Bolger, 2003: 17). Contrasting as they may be,

Molesworth’s and Fer’s approaches both serve to respond to implied

judgements: those of the concomitant audience, and of the duty of

museum/artist. Thus, I find that they succeed in making artists’ strategies

evident.

To take this research further a possible path could be to join the dots between

Buren’s essay and Molesworth’s curation, with an aim of casting light on

Buren’s sense of the implied duty of the artist. I would anticipate finding a

contrast between this and Molesworth’s sense of the museum’s duty, which

led her to form her curatorial methodology for Work Ethic (2003). I would like

to analyse the resulting excess in duty that the museum is required to fulfil,

above that of the artist, in relation to Buren’s essay, and the broader field of

post-studio theory. There is also scope to further explore the parallel between

artist and archive in terms of Fer’s ‘history of the impulse to make’ (Fer, 2009:

24). My analysis of Gillick’s network of identities through Broad’s comparison

of the relationships between good and right, and shape and size (Broad,

1930: 176-7), similarly holds potential for further testing, both theoretically and

through practice.

In terms of limitations, I experienced a great deficit in resources during the

period in which I undertook this MRes course and wrote this resulting thesis,

due to being self-funded, and working part-time throughout. This put further

pressure on my studio time on top of the existing economic pressures

described in this thesis. Ironically, I felt the context of precarity especially

keenly during this time and my practice suffered as a consequence. Despite

having made work that I am satisfied will support and has aided in developing

my theoretical research, I regret not being able to make more work in this vein.

44

The artworks I am including in this thesis: statements, notebook entries, back

of envelope drawings, details of painting surfaces, jigsawed painting panels,

and work displayed in my studio, were all made during the MRes Arts Practice

course. I also include a portfolio in the appendix section.

I present the following research questions as findings from this thesis, and to

demonstrate my commitment to pursuing threads of this thesis at a future

date:

How does Daniel Buren’s essay The Function of the Studio aim to relieve

artists of their duty to the viewers and audiences of art?

How does the distribution of resources within an art practice reflect the

archival intentions of the artist?

Can the effect of judgements on artists’ practices be discovered through

identifying parameters, or counterpart-terms (such as good and right),

which denote ethics?

I am leaving this thesis open-ended in terms of my own duty to pursue

channels arising from it, through future practice and research; and in terms of

the reader’s own concomitant influence, which is ever-changing as time

passes, and as economic conditions in the UK change.

45

10 Bibliography

Art & Language. (1969) Introduction. In: Art-Language, pp.1-10. Vol.1 No.1May 1969. Banbury, Oxfordshire: Art & Language Press

Atkinson, T & Baldwin, M. (1970-1). Theories of ethics. New York: Art &Language Press

Barlow, P. (initiated by) (2007-2010) What do artists do?: April 2008. [Internet].Available from: <http://whatdoartistsdo.blogspot.com> [Accessed 7 August2013]

Barry, R. (2003) Some places to which we can come: Robert Barry works1963-1975. Bielefeld: Kerber Verlag

Bolger, D. (2003) Foreword. In: Molesworth, H. Work ethic. Baltimore:Pennsylvania State University Press

Bosch, J. (2009) The strategic studio: how to access and assess decision-making in visual art practice . PhD thesis, University of Northumbria

Broad, C. D. (1930) Five types of ethical theory . London: Routledge & KeganPaul Ltd

Bryan-Wilson, J. (2009) Art workers: radical practice in the Vietnam war era .California, London: University of California Press

Buren, D. (1979) The function of the studio. In: October. pp.51-58 [Internet]Vol.10 Autumn 1979. Translated from the French by Thomas Repensek.Available from: <http://www.jstor.org.arts.idm.oclc.org/stable/778628>[Accessed 7 August 2013]

Crimp, D. (1981) The end of painting. In: October. pp.69-86 [Internet] Vol.16Spring 1981. Available from: <http://www.jstor.org/stable/778375> [Accessed7 August 2013]

Cuddihy, M. (2003) James in limbo. Recent Paintings. London: PEER

Cuddihy, M. (2003) James in limbo. London: PEER 21 June - 27 July 2003

Darwent, C. (2009) Eva Hesse: Studiowork, Fruitmarket Gallery, Edinburgh.In: The Independent on Sunday [Internet] 16 August 2009. Available from:<http://www.independent.co.uk/arts-entertainment/art/reviews/eva-hesse-studiowork-fruitmarket-gallery-edinburgh-1772701.html> [Accessed 7 August2013]

Davidts, W & Paice, K. (2009) The fall of the studio: artists at work.Amsterdam: Valiz

Fer, B. (2009) Eva Hesse: studiowork. New Haven: Yale University Press,Edinburgh Fruitmarket Gallery

46

Fer, B. (2009) Eva Hesse studioworks (a keynote lecture) . [Internet]. Availablefrom: <http://fruitmarket.co.uk/learning/resources/eva-hesse-recordings/>[Accessed 7 August 2013]

Forkert, K. (2011) Artistic lives: a two-city study . Unpublished PhD thesis.Goldsmiths College (University of London)

Gillick, L. (2012) The Good of work. In: E-flux Journal, Are you working toomuch? Post-Fordism, Precarity, and the Labor of Art . USA: Sternberg Press

Hesse, E. (2013) Eva Hesse 1965. London: Hauser & Wirth. 30 January - 9March 2013

Hesse, E. (2009) Studiowork: Eva Hesse . London: Camden Arts Centre. 11December 2009 - 7 March 2010

Hodge, S. (2012) Why your five year old could not have done that: modern artexplained. London: Thames & Hudson

Holz, G. (2004) “Thoughts made visible” Eva Hesse’s language use, inherentin her works. In: Hesse, E. Transformations: the sojourn in Germany 1964/65 .Wien: Kunsthalle

Hytten, E. (1959) The concept of morality and the criteria of legitimateargumentation. An examination of some recent definitions. Stockholm:Filosofiska Studier

Jones, C. (1996) Machine in the studio: constructing the postwar Americanartist. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press

Jones, L (2013) A life more Eminent: Tracey Emin opens up her intimatephoto memoir - and tells Liz Jones why her 'not always palatable' past hasshaped her life's work [Internet]. 21 April 2013 Available from:<http://www.dailymail.co.uk/home/you/article-2311050/Tracey-Emin-opens-intimate-photo-memoir-tells-Liz-Jones-past-shaped-lifes-work.html> [Accessed7 August 2013]

Kanger, S. (2001) New foundations for ethical theory. In: Hintikka, J. (ed.)Collected papers of Stig Kanger with essays on his life and work vol. 1 .Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Kluwer Academic

Lazzarato, M. (1996) Immaterial labor. In: Virno, P & Hardt, M. (1996). Radicalthought in Italy. Minneapolis, US: University of Minnesota Press

Lippard, L, Chandler, J. (1999) The dematerialization of art (1968). In: Alberro,A., Stimpson, B., eds. Conceptual art: a critical anthology . Massachusetts:Massachusetts Institute of Technology

MacLeod, K. & Holdridge, L. (eds.) (2006) Thinking through art: reflections onart as research. Oxfordshire, USA, Canada: Routledge

McLean-Ferris, L. (2011) ArtReview discusses Eva Hesse: studioworks withBriony Fer [Internet]. Available at:<http://www.artreview.com/forum/topic/show?id=1474022:Topic:847555>[Accessed 7 August 2013]

47

McLellan, D. (1980) The thought of Karl Marx, 2nd ed. London: MacmillanPress Ltd

Milner, J. (2009) Locating the studio. In: Waterfield, G. ed. The artist’s studio,UK: Hogarth Art, Compton Verney

Molesworth, H. (2003) Work ethic. Baltimore: Pennsylvania State UniversityPress

PEER. (2003) Mikey Cuddihy - James in limbo , [Internet]. Available at:<http://www.peeruk.org/projects/cuddihy/mikey-cuddihy.html> [Accessed 7August 2013]

Ryan, P. (2009) Peirce's Semeiotic and the implications for aesthetics in thevisual arts : a study of the sketchbook and its positions in the hierarchies ofmaking, collecting and exhibiting . Unpublished PhD thesis, University of theArts London

Sennett, R. (2008) The craftsman. New Haven, London: Yale UniversityPress, New Haven

Sidgwick, H. (1962). Chapter III Ethical Judgements. In: Sidgwick, H. (1962)The methods of ethics , 2nd ed. London: Macmillan and Company Limited

Smith, Terry (2003) Production. In: Schiff, R, Nelson, R. (2003) Critical termsfor art history . Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press (pp.361-381)

Work ethic (2004) [Internet]. Available from:<http://www.artbma.org/exhibitions/special/work_ethic/index.htm> [Accessed 5May 2013]

48

11 Table of Figures

Figure 1 Members of the BAT Pack , photograph by Ollie Harrop,2011

8

Figure 2 Daniel Buren, From and Off the Windows, 1974 11

Figure 3 Ruth Solomons, Takeaway tin lid, 2012 16

Figure 4 Ruth Solomons, Untitled, 2012 17

Figure 5 ‘Tracey Emin in her Spitalfields studio’ (original caption) ,2013

20

Figure 6 Roxy Paine, Paint Dipper, 1997 24

Figure 7 Eva Hesse, Studioworks, installed at Fruitmarket Gallery,Edinburgh, 2009

27

Figure 8 Ruth Solomons, Various works in the studio , 2013 30

Figure 9 Ruth Solomons, Back of Envelope Drawing 14 , 2013 34

Figure 10 Diagram over Back of Envelope Drawing 14 35

Figure 11 Ruth Solomons, Notebook 18/4/13, 2013 37

Figure 12 Mikey Cuddihy, Slide, 2002 38

Figure 13 Ruth Solomons, Mobius, 2013 39

Figure 14 Mel Bochner, Wrap: Portrait of Eva Hesse , 1966 41

49

12 Appendices

Appendix 1 Glossary 50

Appendix 2 Critical Reading Form 54

Appendix 3 Conversation: Split brains 55

Appendix 4 Hasty drawings and scribbled thoughts 58

Appendix 5 Portfolio 59

50

Appendix 1 Glossary

The following terms, listed alphabetically, are used in this thesis with particular

meanings. In most cases I have explained these meanings within the text, and

I merely repeat them here, so they can be referred to while reading. The few

which I have not defined within the text, are listed here so as to provide

supplementary detail to their implied contexts in the thesis.

I use bold type for these terms where they occur in the glossary, so that their

interconnections can be visually perceived. However in the main body of the

thesis, I use bold only to emphasise specific uses of these terms, particularly

the terms concomitant and duty.

Where Americanisms occur in titles and quotes, I have left their spellings as

found (e.g. dematerialized). If I repeat such words within my own writing, I

have used the equivalent English spellings (e.g. dematerialised). I chose to

include both in this way, as a commitment to transcribing quotes exactly as

found, while also making sure my own writing remained consistent.

Concomitant. One of two senses of the notion behind ought: a collective

influence originating from an implied audience (Sidgwick, 1962: 28-9). (The

other sense is duty, a more commonly understood word which does not need

to be explained in this glossary).

Contemporary, current artist. Liam Gillick prefers the term ‘current artist’,arguing that ‘contemporary art no longer accounts for what is being made –

that is connected more to what we have all become than what we might

propose, represent, or fail to achieve’ (Gillick, 2012: 61). I have still, however,

used the term contemporary, which I feel is generally understood to mean

artists working now, but could also be perceived in a broader sense to simply

mean recent, in an unspecified time period spanning back perhaps a couple of

decades, as well as ‘what we have all become’ now. Therefore I use words

such as ‘working now’ in conjunction with contemporary to emphasise which

sense I am referring to.

Declaration device . This refers to artworks and art writing which extrapolate

elements through a ‘necessary form of development in pointing out the

51

possibilities of a theoretical analysis as a method for (possibly) making art’

(Atkinson, 1969, p.4). Robert Barry produced works in this vein. A useful

example here is All the Things I know but of which I am not at the Moment

thinking – 1:36 p.m., June 15 (1969), written/stencilled in pencil onto a wall:

knowledge which has the potential to become thought, and in turn the

potential to become art.

Dematerialised, dematerialisation . This was a process of stripping down, or

tending towards nothing, specifically of 1960s conceptual artworks, such as

Robert Barry’s work described above. In my thesis, these terms are used in

relation to Lucy Lippard and John Chandler’s essay The Dematerialization of

Art (1968).

Deontic. Statements which imply judgement without use of an imperative

form. The term deontic describes statements where ‘the assertor’ might ‘deny

that he has (or refuse to give) “reasons”’ (Atkinson & Baldwin, 1970-71: 41).

Ethics. A normative science, taking in a broad field of philosophy stretching

back to Spinoza and Kant. For the purpose of this thesis, I have taken

Atkinson & Baldwin’s artists’ book Theories of Ethics (1970-71) as a

springboard from which to find theories pertaining to ethics of language, that

help me to answer my research question.

Immaterial labour. This refers to work that does not result in production in the

terms of exchange or use value in the Marxist sense. Maurizio Lazzarato

describes immaterial labour as having ‘creative content’: a creative exchange

occurs between worker and consumer (Lazzarato, 1996: 147). Liam Gillick

also refers to immaterial labour, knowledge exchange, and the anxiety of

working without reward (Gillick, 2012: 65).

Judgement. I refer to judgements as notions that carry threats of disapproval

or punishment. Many of the judgements described in this thesis are

perceived, implied or anticipated. I have extracted these judgements through

ethics analysis.

Marxist. I refer glancingly to Marxist philosophy relating to work, and his

theories of use and exchange value, and how they might relate to art practice.

52

However, my thesis shifts emphasis from practice as work in the Marxist

sense, into practice as process and making. This sense is more in the vein of

immaterial labour, and artist as knowledge worker, as described above.

Museum. I use the term museum to describe a general idea of a public

institution which safeguards and displays artworks. When applied to galleries,

I am referring to this aspect of their function.

Notion. This term is used a great deal in ethics. It serves to describe the

intentions behind terms (and statements). A notion becomes easier to convey

once separated from the linguistic weight of terms such as good, right and

ought.

Ought. This term is also used a great deal in ethics. The notion behind

ought is the same as for should, have to, must. Even if such words are not

used in themselves, a notion of ought can be said to be perceived.

Post-studio. Daniel Buren’s essay The Function of the Studio (1979) is widely

cited as the source of post-studio debate. Post-studio describes a historical

rejection of the studio that paralleled and developed from movements which

rejected the museum.

Precarity. The term precarity describes the precarious position workers find

themselves in when income barely matches living costs.

Representation, re-presentation . Here I refer to ways in which art practice

and artworks are re-presented outside the studio. This could include ways of

talking about, writing about, documenting, archiving and displaying art

practice/artworks.

Strategies. I refer to strategies rather than processes, to draw attention to

the crossover between art practice and life. Johanna Bosch defines strategies

as ‘tactical adaptation’, and as having a day-to day nature (Bosch, 2009: 37).

Studio. The origin of the term studio is as a study, rather than a workshop,

and as such the term ‘embodies the gradual blurring of the distinction between

artistic reflection or 'studious activity' that permeates contemporary artistic

53

ways of making’ (Davidts & Pace, eds., 2009: 9). In the thesis I refer to

physical studio sites, such as my own studio, but I also allude to a sense of

studio which does not have to be attached to a physical site, and exists more

in an attitude to work, or the resources with which practice is enabled.

Universalisability. My basic understanding of universalisability stems from

Atkinson & Baldwin’s definition in Theories of Ethics (1970-71): a person who

makes a moral judgement at t must be willing, at t, to ‘universalize’ his

judgement at least to some extent (Atkinson & Baldwin, 1970-1: 31).

Work (verb and noun). In this thesis, I have considered the mutability of work

between its verb and noun forms as being a key characteristic of its meaning.

The verb to work implies work being made. The noun work implies work

being done. Therefore in Liam Gillick’s question ‘what is the good of this

work?’ (Gillick, 2012: 61) and Briony Fer’s neologism ‘studio work’ (Fer,

2009), both senses are present.

54

Appendix 2 Critical Reading Form

I developed the following critical reading form as a result of recommendations

made by Eleanor Bowen in the Academic Writing module of the MRes. It

helped me to skip quickly to the critical aspects of texts I was reading while

everything was still fresh in my mind, and was also an invaluable method for

collecting bibliographical data.

55

Appendix 3 Conversation: Split brains

The following dialogue with Kataryna Leach will appear in the catalogue for

Mise-en-Scene, an exhibition instigated by Cullinan Richards, at Bermondsey

Project Space, 20 September to 5 October 2013.

56

57

58

Appendix 4 Hasty Drawings and Scribbled Thoughts

This short written work and the accompanying image was submitted for the

second issue of JAWS (2013), the Journal of Art Writing by Students, which

was instigated by Francesca Peschier, one of my co-students on the MRes. I

was part of the editing team for JAWS, so I wanted to contribute something

which demonstrated how initial research ideas, subject to peer-review, can

develop into more complex critical analysis, as is now evident in my thesis.

59

Appendix 5 Portfolio

My portfolio consists of work made during or immediately preceding the MRes

course, which supports, develops or is related to my research.

Back of Envelope Drawing 3, 2013: pen on back of envelope, 18x24cm.

60

Mobius, 2013: detail showing back of panels, gumstrip on wood.

61

Mobius, 2013: detail showing the panels being handled, oil on board.

62

Mobius, 2013: painting in progress in the studio, oil on board, approx dimensions 100x150cm.

63

Untitled, 2012-2013. Oil on board, 180x300cm: unfinished painting in progress. A detail of this painting is shown in figure 4.