nikolai lossky's reception and criticism of husserl

15
Nikolai Losskys Reception and Criticism of Husserl Frédéric Tremblay 1 Published online: 22 January 2016 © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016 Abstract Nikolai Lossky is key to the history of the Husserl-Rezeption in Russia. He was the first to publish a review of the Russian translation of Husserl’s first volume of the Logische Untersuchungen that appeared in 1909. He also published a presentation and criticism of Husserl’s transcendental idealism in 1939. An English translation of both of Lossky’s publications is offered in this volume for the first time. The present paper, which is intended as an introduction to these documents, situates Lossky within the Rezeptionsgeschichte of Husserl in Russia and explains why he is central to it. It also explains what Lossky principally found in Husserl: he saw in the latter’s critique of psychologism support for his own ontology, episte- mology, and axiology. Lossky characterizes his ontology as an ideal-realism. According to ideal-realism, both the realm of ideal beings (in Plato’s sense) and the realm of real beings (i.e., the world of becoming) are mind-independent. Per his epistemology, which he calls “intuitivism,” real beings are intuited by sensual intuition and ideal beings by intellectual intuition. The realm of ideal beings includes the subrealm of values, which is intuited by axiological intuition. This thoroughly realist conception contrasted sharply with the subjectivist tendencies of the time. So, when Lossky took cognizance of Husserl’s critique of psychologism, he thereupon found an ally in his battle against the various subjectivisms. But, when Husserl took the transcendental idealist turn, Lossky was at the forefront of the backlash against the new direction Husserl wanted to give to phenomenology. Nikolai Onufrievich Lossky is commonly held to be one of the first Russian philosophers to have played a key role in introducing Husserl to the Russian & Fre ´de ´ric Tremblay [email protected] 1 Institut Jean Nicod, UMR, 8129, Pavillon Jardin, Ecole Normale Supe ´rieure, 29 rue d’Ulm, 75005 Paris, France 123 Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163 DOI 10.1007/s10743-015-9181-5

Upload: uni-sofia

Post on 19-Nov-2023

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Nikolai Lossky’s Reception and Criticism of Husserl

Frédéric Tremblay1

Published online: 22 January 2016

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Abstract Nikolai Lossky is key to the history of the Husserl-Rezeption in Russia.

He was the first to publish a review of the Russian translation of Husserl’s first

volume of the Logische Untersuchungen that appeared in 1909. He also published a

presentation and criticism of Husserl’s transcendental idealism in 1939. An English

translation of both of Lossky’s publications is offered in this volume for the first

time. The present paper, which is intended as an introduction to these documents,

situates Lossky within the Rezeptionsgeschichte of Husserl in Russia and explains

why he is central to it. It also explains what Lossky principally found in Husserl: he

saw in the latter’s critique of psychologism support for his own ontology, episte-

mology, and axiology. Lossky characterizes his ontology as an ideal-realism.

According to ideal-realism, both the realm of ideal beings (in Plato’s sense) and the

realm of real beings (i.e., the world of becoming) are mind-independent. Per his

epistemology, which he calls “intuitivism,” real beings are intuited by sensual

intuition and ideal beings by intellectual intuition. The realm of ideal beings

includes the subrealm of values, which is intuited by axiological intuition. This

thoroughly realist conception contrasted sharply with the subjectivist tendencies of

the time. So, when Lossky took cognizance of Husserl’s critique of psychologism,

he thereupon found an ally in his battle against the various subjectivisms. But, when

Husserl took the transcendental idealist turn, Lossky was at the forefront of the

backlash against the new direction Husserl wanted to give to phenomenology.

Nikolai Onufrievich Lossky is commonly held to be one of the first Russian

philosophers to have played a key role in introducing Husserl to the Russian

& Frederic Tremblay

[email protected]

1 Institut Jean Nicod, UMR, 8129, Pavillon Jardin, Ecole Normale Superieure, 29 rue d’Ulm,

75005 Paris, France

123

Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163

DOI 10.1007/s10743-015-9181-5

intellectual community. In “Ed. Husserl und die russische Philosophie,” for

instance, Boris Jakowenko says that Lossky was “first among the Russian

philosophers who took an interest in Husserl’s groundbreaking ideas, and who

were partially influenced by them.”1 In The Phenomenological Movement, HerbertSpiegelberg says “It seems that the philosopher chiefly responsible for [the] early

interest in Husserl was Nikolai Lossky” (Spiegelberg, 1976, p. 609). And, more

recently, Maryse Dennes said that “the most outstanding reaction to Husserl’s

Logical Investigations was that of N. O. Lossky.”2

Lossky was not the very first to mention Husserl in print, however. David

Viktorov, who had been Husserl’s student, quotes the Logische Untersuchungen in

his “Philosophical Views of Ernst Mach” (Филocoфcкie взгляды Эpнcтa Maxa),

published in the May-June 1904 issue of the journal Questions of Philosophy andPsychology (Boпpocы филocoфiи и пcиxoлoгiи). Lossky only mentions Husserl in

print for the first time a year later, in the May-June issue of the same journal, in a

paper entitled “The Foundations of Mystical Empiricism” (Ocнoвaниeмиcтичecкoгo эмпиpизмa) (Lossky 1905, p. 176). In the latter article, Lossky

relies on Husserl’s definitions of similarity and identity when arguing against

nominalism and conceptualism in favor of the realism of universals (Lossky 1905,

pp. 205-206). He also finds support in Husserl’s distinction between specifischeEinzelheit and individuelle Einzelheit (Lossky 1905, p. 210). This article will

eventually become a chapter of The Foundations of Intuitivism (Oбocнoвaнieинтyитивизмa) (1906). Although Viktorov was chronologically prior, Lossky may

nevertheless have been prior in power of influence. Viktorov was five years younger

than Lossky, and, by 1905, he had three full-length articles and several book reviews

in Boпpocы филocoфiи и пcиxoлoгiи (the main organ for philosophical publications

in Russia at the time), whereas Lossky had already published about fifteen full-length

articles in the same journal and had a book published in German translation. It is hard

to say with any amount of certainty who between the two was most influential at the

time. But Lossky was certainly more en vue than Viktorov and, as such, may have

been more susceptible to exert an influence on the Russian intelligentsia.

Gustav Shpet eventually became the greatest ambassador of Husserl’s thought in

Russia. Shpet studied at the University of Gottingen, where he took Husserl’s

seminar “Natur und Geist,” which Roman Ingarden also attended, during the winter

semester of 1912-1913. Upon his return to Russia, he played an important role in

disseminating Husserl’s ideas. His Appearance and Sense (Явлeниe и cмыcл)published in 1914 initiated a distinctly — albeit short-lived — Russian

phenomenological movement. But Lossky preceded Shpet chronologically by many

years and contributed to the initial impetus to Husserlian studies in Russia. There is

also reasonable ground to suspect an influence of Lossky on Shpet, because,

according to Vladimir Zinchenko, Boris Pruzhinin, and Tat’iana Shchedrina,

“Lossky was one of the few Russian philosophers whose ideas came under the direct

1 “Als Erster unter den russischen Philosophen, der sich fur die bahnbrechenden Ideen Husserls

interessierte und sich teilweise durch dieselben beeinflussen ließ, muß N. O. Losskij bezeichnet werden”

(Jakowenko 1929/1930, p. 211). Otherwise noted, all translations are mine.2 “la reaction la plus marquante aux Recherches logiques de Husserl fut celle de N. O. Lossky.” (Dennes1997a, p. 156).

150 Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163

123

attention of Gustav Shpet” (Zinchenko, Pruzhinin, & Shchedrina 2011, p. 33). Shpet

seems to have had some esteem for Lossky,3 at least insofar as the non-religious

aspects of his work were concerned.4

We may thus agree that Lossky is central to the Rezeptionsgeschichte of Husserlin Russia. Let us now turn to Lossky’s philosophical background and program in

order to understand what he found in Husserl. Most historians of Russian

philosophy agree that Vladimir Solov’ev was the first great systematic Russian

philosopher.5 Solov’ev developed a syncretic system that we may describe —

although in a far too simplified way — as a sort of Christian Neo-Platonism, which

many believe to be characteristic of the Russian national way of thinking. This

philosophy implies a form of ontological realism. The most important philosophers

of the next generation, such as Nikolai Lossky and Semyon Frank, followed in

Solov’ev’s footsteps to varying extents. Given its realist inclination, Russian

philosophy remained relatively impervious to Kantianism and subjective idealism.

Russia had its fair share of Neo-Kantian philosophers, such as Alexander

Vvedensky.6 But, according to many historians, the Russian general philosophical

tendency was anti-Kantian. Frank, for instance, is of the opinion that “the

philosophical worldview of Vvedensky remains isolated in Russian philosophy.”7

Fichte had apparently almost no influence in Russia. Schelling and Hegel had an

immense influence, but what the Russian mind found typically attractive in them

3 We know that Shpet was a reader of Lossky. While in Gottingen in 1912, for instance, he wrote to his

wife, asking her if she could send him a copy of Lossky’s new book, Логика проф. Введенского (TheLogic of Prof. Vvedensky), in which Lossky criticizes Vvedensky’s Neo-Kantian account of the esselogicum (Shchedrina 2005, p. 53). We also know that in 1914 he recommended Lossky’s Основныяученiя психологiи (The Basic Teachings of Psychology) to Mikhail Gershenzon (Shchedrina 2005, p. 445).

Moreover, we know from Lossky’s correspondence with Shpet that in 1917 the latter was trying to get

Lossky to contribute articles to the journal Мысль и Слово (Thought and Word) of which he was the

editor (for Lossky’s letters to Shpet, see Shchedrina (2005, pp. 446-447)). Finally, the same year, Shpet

published a review of Lossky’s booklet Материя в системе органического мировоззрения (Matter andthe System of Organic Weltanschauung) (1916), which further suggests the importance of Lossky’s

thought for Shpet.4 Shpet’s review of Lossky’s Материя в системе органического мировоззрения was published under

the title “Нѣкоторыя черты изъ представленiя Н. О. Лосскаго о природѣ” (“Some Features of N.

O. Lossky’s Views on Nature”) in Мысль и слово in 1917. Shpet sent a copy to Lossky, who read it.

Lossky replied to Shpet: “I have read your article about me. The phrase ‘worldview that goes back to God

is a worldview going back to a whim’ was very upsetting to me, as to every man who believes in God and

who knows that He is; it gives the impression of something blasphemous” (Вашу статью обо мне ячитал. В ней фраза «миропонимание, которое восходит к Богу, есть мировоззрение, восходящее ккапризу» очень огорчило меня: на меня, как и на всякого человека, верующего в Бога и знающего,что Он есть, она производит впечатление чего-то кощунственного) (Shchedrina 2005, p. 446).5 E.g., “Soloviev evolved an original and independent system of philosophy. This happened in Russia for

the first time […] Soloviev was the first Russian truly original philosopher” (Lopatin 1916, p. 432) or,

again, Solov’ev is “arguably the first Russian philosopher worthy of that designation, certainly its first

systematic secular philosopher” (Nemeth 2014, p. ix).6 On Russian Neo-Kantianism and on Vvedensky in particular, see Nemeth (1998).7 “Wwedensky’s philosophische Weltanschauung steht in der russischen Philosophie ganz vereinzelt”

(Frank 1926a, p. 90).

Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163 151

123

was not so much their idealism as the organic character of their systems, Schelling’s

World Soul and his Ungrund, Hegel’s Absolute and his dialectics, etc.8

Whether they are biased or not, many historians of Russian philosophy describe

the Russian mind as having a penchant for ontologism. In Russische Philosophie(1925), for instance, Ernest Radlov says that “[o]bjectivism draws the Russian mind

toward the objective world, grounds him to the earth.”9 In Die russischeWeltanschauung (1926), Frank claims that one of the main tendencies among

Russian philosophers “is their leaning toward realism, or better said, toward

ontologism, the impossibility for them of being satisfied with any form of idealism

or subjectivism.”10 In History of Russian Philosophy (Иcтopия pyccкoйфилocoфии) (1948), Vasily Zenkovsky says that, “[e]xcept for a small group of

faithful Kantians, Russian philosophers are very prone to so-called ontologism in

resolving epistemological questions.”11 Lossky himself says in his own History ofRussian Philosophy (first published in English) that the “view that the external

world is knowable is widely prevalent in Russian philosophy, and indeed is often

stated in its extreme form, namely, as the doctrine of intuition or immediate

contemplation of objects as they are in themselves. A keen sense of reality, opposed

to regarding the contents of external perception as mental or subjective, seems to be

a characteristic feature of Russian philosophy” (Lossky 1952, p. 403).

At the beginning of the twentieth century, Lossky was — along with Frank —

one of the main flag-bearers of the Russian realist reaction against Kantianism and

German idealism. He characterizes his own metaphysical position as an “ideal-

realism,” which may mislead one to believe that his philosophy is an attempt to

somehow synthesize German idealism and external-world realism. But that is not

the case. The idealism Lossky has in mind here is rather the Platonic one according

to which there is an objective realm of ideal being. His position is thus a double-

edged realism: a realism about the Platonic realm of intelligible forms as well as

about the external world (i.e., the sensible world of events and processes). On this

view, truth is about something ontologically independent — a conception that is

averse to logical psychologism and relativism.

So, when the first volume of the Logische Untersuchungen appeared, Lossky

found in Husserl an ally in his fight against the subjectivist approaches then still

prevalent in Germany. When the first Russian translation appeared in 1909, Lossky

was the first to publish a review of it. His review reflects this newly discovered

alliance: “At first sight, it seems undeniable that judgment, reasoning, and all

8 On this, see also Ernest Radlov, who says that “Fichte has exercised almost no influence, and only the

philosophy of nature and the ethics of Schelling as well as some elements of the Hegelian theory have

made an impression” (“Fichte hat fast gar keinen Einfluß ausgeubt, und nur die Naturphilosophie und

Ethik Schellings und einige Elemente der Hegelschen Lehre haben Eindruck gemacht”) (Radlov 1925,

p. 11). See also Frank (1926b, p. 11).9 “Der Objektivismus zieht den russischen Geist zur gegenstandlichen Welt, schmiedet ihn an die Erde”

(Radlov 1925, p. 13).10 “ist ihr Hang zum Realismus oder, besser gesagt, zum Ontologismus, die Unmoglichkeit fur sie, sich

mit irgendeiner Form von Idealismus oder Subjektivismus zu befriedigen.” (Frank 1926b, p. 11).11 “За исключением небольшой группы правоверных кантианцев, русские философы оченьсклонны к так называемому онтологизму при разрешении вопросов теории познания.” (Zenkovsky

1948, p. 17).

152 Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163

123

thought processes in general are entirely of a psychic nature. That is why logic is

[considered to be] a science of psychic phenomena, is [considered to be] a ‘branch

of psychology’. No wonder, therefore, that psychologism is very common in logic.

The natural consequence of psychologism in logic must be the doctrine that teaches

that truth, as something determined by the human psychic organization, has only a

relative value (relativism).”12 What Lossky applauds here is above all Husserl’s

critique of psychologism and its anti-relativistic implications. He agrees with

Husserl that the liberation from psychologism must be achieved by clearly

distinguishing the act of judgment, which is a psychic process, from the meaning of

the judgment, which is not a psychic process but an ideal being that, to him, has an

independent existence in the Platonic sense.

Lossky developed a theory of knowledge that he calls “intuitivism,” which was

intended to be nothing less than “the overcoming of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reasonand justification of metaphysics as a science.”13 According to Losskyan intuitivism,

we have “immediate awareness of the externalworld.”14 Intuition can be of substances

as much as of properties, relations, causality, numbers, and so on. Real beings are

intuited via sensuous intuition, and ideal beings via intellectual intuition. Grounding

his own system of logic on intuitivism, Lossky claims that logic is concerned with the

realm of ideal being (i.e., superspatial and supertemporal being). On this view, “the

logical structure of judgments and inferences is at the same time the ontologicalstructure of reality” (Lossky 1930, p. 254). Lossky’s intuitivist logic is thus

“completely free from any tendency toward psychologism” (Lossky 1930, p. 254).

Some have seen in this theory an echo of Husserl’s theory of eidetic intuition

(see, e.g., Dennes 1997b, p. 49). But Lossky had probably already developed his

views on intuition before reading Husserl. In his Bocпoминaния (Memoirs), hewrites that in the summer of 1903 he still did not know who Husserl was,15 and that

he was already on his way to intuitivism in 1900.16 Lossky had already devoted a

section to the theory of intuition in “Fundamental Psychological Theories from the

Point of View of Voluntarism” (Основныя yчeнiя пcиxoлoгiи cъ тoчки зpѣнiявoлюнтapизмa) (1903a, b), and he had already published a series of articles on

intuitivism in Boпpocы филocoфiи и пcиxoлoгiи (1904-1905) before showing any

signs of being acquainted with Husserl.

12 “На первый взглядъ кажется несомнѣннымъ, что сужденіе, умозаключеніе, вообще процессымышленія цѣликомъ суть психическіе процессы, а потому логика есть наука о психическихъявленіяхъ, ест „вѣтвь психологіи“. Неудивительно поэтому, что психологизмъ широко распрос-траненъ въ логикѣ. Естественнымъ слѣдствіемъ психологизма въ логикѣ должно быть ученіе отомъ, что истина, какъ нѣчто обусловленное психическою организаціею человѣка, имѣетъ лишьотносительное значеніе (релативизмъ).” (Lossky 1909, p. 292).13 “преодоление «Критики чистого разума» Канта и оправдание метафизики, как науки.” (Lossky

1968, p. 121).14 “непосредственное сознаванiе внѣшняго мира” (Lossky 1904b, p. 325).15 “In the summer of 1903, I went on a trip to Gottingen […]. The philosopher Husserl was also in

Gottingen at this time, but I did not yet know his name” (На лето 1903 г. я получил командировку вГеттинген […]. Философ Э. Гуссерль был также в это время в Геттингене, но я не знал еще егоимени) (Lossky 1968, pp. 113-114).16 “в 1900 г. В то время я был уже на пути к своему интуитивизму.” (Lossky 1968, p. 97).

Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163 153

123

Lossky would more likely have developed his concept of intuition in contact with

Solov’ev’s philosophy. In Обоснованiе миcтичecкoгo эмпиpизмa (Foundations ofMystical Empirism), he credits Solov’ev, who, he says, “has put forward a doctrine

of intuition both in respect to finite things and in respect to God. In his view, the

knowledge of anything, even of any finite thing, involves three aspects — the

mystical, the rational, and the empirical.”17 And he goes on to quote at length on

this issue from Solov’ev’s Кpитикa oтвлeчeнныxъ нaчaлъ (Critique of AbstractPrinciples) (1880) — a book that he had to read early on for his magister exam.18

He also credits Sergei Trubetskoy for “valuable additions” made in this regard to the

teachings of Solov’ev (Lossky 1904c, p. 501), as well as Aleksei Kozlov, who was

one of his earliest philosophical influences (Lossky 1904c, p. 504).19 Other possible

early sources for his concept of intuition are the concepts of Anschauung of TheodorLipps,20 Schelling,21 and Schopenhauer,22 amongst others.

But Lossky nevertheless sought support in Husserl in the same way that he

sought support in Bergson’s theory of intuition (Lossky 1913, 1914). In 1910,

Lossky apparently prepared an article entitled “On Husserl’s Intentionalism in

Relation to Intuitivism” (Oб интeнциoнaлизмe Гyccepля в cвязи cинтyитивизмoм) for the second volume of the journal Logos (1910), but the

article was never published.23 In 1911, he gave a course on “Husserl’s Intention-

alism” (Интeнциoнaлизм Гyccepля) at St. Petersburg University, where he was

then privatdocent (Boris Lossky 1978, p. 13). He saw an analogy between his own

intuitivism and what he calls Husserl’s “intentionalism,” for intuitivism posits a

relation of coordination between subject and object that is not unlike that of

intentionality (see, e.g., Lossky 1928, p. 86). Lossky calls it the relation of

17 “В. С. Соловьевъ, развившiй ученiе о мистическомъ воспрiятiи и въ отношенiи конечныъ вещей,и въ отношенiи къ Боду. По его мнѣнiю, знанiе о всякой, даже конечной вещи складывается изътрехъ элементовъ—мистическаго, рацiональнаго и эмпирическаго.” (Lossky 1904c, p. 499).18 “Даже из трудов Вл. Соловьева мне были знакомы только «Критика отвлеченных начал»,входившая в программу магистерского экзамена” (Lossky 1968, p. 195).19 For the influence of Solov’ev and Kozlov in general on Lossky, see Zenkovsky, who says that “besides

Kozlov’s indisputable influence […] he undoubtedly felt that of Solov’ev” (кроме бесспорного влиянияКозлова […], Лосский испытал несомненно влияние Вл. Соловьева) (Zenkovsky 1950, p. 201).20 In 1902, Lossky translated Lipps’ Grundzüge der Logik (1893) (Теодор Липпс, Основы логики,1902) — a work in which Lipps speaks of different kinds of Anschauung. On Lipps’ possible influence onLossky, see Kurennoj (2005, pp. 272-273).21 Zenkovsky says that Solov’ev took his own concept of intuition from Schelling’s intellektuelleAnschauung (Zenkovsky 1950, p. 31). If this is true, Schelling could have been an indirect influence. But

it could also have been a direct influence, or both a direct and indirect one, because, in 1901, Lossky

translated volumes IV, VII, and VIII of Kuno Fischer’s series Geschichte der neuern Philosophie, theseventh volume of which was “Schellings Leben, Werke und Lehre” (1902) and in which Fischer presents

Schelling’s theory of Anschauung and intellectuelle Anschauung.22 In his Memoirs, Lossky says that in 1896 he “was fond of reading the major works of Schopenhauer”

(Lossky 1968, p. 98), for whom the concepts of Anschauung and intellectuelle Anschauung are central.23 For the assertion that he prepared an article titled “On Husserl’s Intentionalism in Relation to

Intuitivism,” I am relying solely on a claim by T. A. Dmitriev (1998, p. 180). But there is no unpublished

article bearing that title in the Lossky-archives at the Institut d’Etudes Slaves in Paris.

154 Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163

123

“epistemological coordination” (гнoceoлoгичecкoй кoopдинaциeй). That relationis not itself knowledge, for knowledge is something purely subjective, whereas the

relation of epistemological coordination extends beyond the subject.

Lossky also defends a realist axiology of Neo-Platonic inspiration. On this view,

positive values coincide with being, and values are grasped, as Max Scheler also

claimed, by way of axiological intuition. This theory of values implies the thesis of

the existence of a supernatural realm of values — a thesis that conflicts with the

tenets of naturalism understood as the belief that everything arises from natural (as

opposed to supernatural) causes. In his review of the Logische Untersuchungen,Lossky associates psychologism with naturalism: “along with psychologism and

relativism, in researches on logic takes root naturalism, i.e., the tendency to regard

thought processes, as bearing not on the norm, the ideal, but on the fact (on what is,not on what ought to be).”24 His concern is that grounding logic in psychic processesimplies a grounding of ideal being (thus, of what ought to be) as a whole in the

psychè, which in turn leads to naturalism and moral relativism. Naturalism (as

defined above) excludes all supernatural, spiritual, and — by implication — teleo-

logical explanation. It thus rules out the possibility of a supernatural ideal realm of

values, and thereby the postulation of a faculty of axiological intuition that would

give immediate access to such values. As a Neo-Platonist and a theist, Lossky

rejects the idea that nature contains all of what is. Moreover, his theory of values is

codependent with an eschatological view of the evolution of the universe, where

evolution is conceived as a gradual progress toward the Good. Any attempt to

naturalize the theory of values is thus, for him, not only deemed to fail, but also

dangerous to humanity. So, Lossky sees in Husserl’s early anti-psychologism a

rampart against moral relativism.25

Lossky repeatedly returned to Husserl’s ideas related to the main themes of the

Logische Untersuchungen afterwards. In Logic (Лoгикa) (1922-1923), he relies on

Husserl with regard to different issues, such as the latter’s critique of Mill’s

psychologism in the first volume of the Logische Untersuchungen. As he did earlier

in The Foundations of Intuitivism (Oбocнoвaнie интyитивизмa), Lossky also relies

here on Husserl for his theory of general concepts, for his argument against

nominalism, and for his concepts of similarity and identity. He also finds support in

Husserl’s supposed Platonism as well as in his theory of “ideating abstraction”

(ideierende Abstraktion). He furthermore discusses Husserl’s criterion of truth

(Wahrheitskriterium) or what Husserl also calls his “concept of evidence”

(Evidenzbegriff).

24 “вмѣстѣ съ психологизмомъ и релативизмомъ въ изслѣдованіяхъ по логикѣ долженъукорениться, т.-е. склонность разсматривать процессы мышленія, имѣя въ виду не норму, неидеалъ, а фактъ (то, что есть, а не то, что должо быть)” (Lossky 1909, p. 292). For Lossky, what “is”

and what “ought to be” are interdependent. This conception is characteristic of Russian religious

philosophy. It can also be found in Solov’ev, for whom “From the standpoint of genuine reality, it is more

fitting to speak of what ought to be, rather than of what is” (Съ точки зрѣнiя настоящей, наличнойдѣйствительности намъ приходится говорить болѣе о томъ, что должно быть и будетъ, нежели отомъ, что есть) (Solov’ev 1880, p. VIII).25 Lossky presents his theory of values in Цѣнность и бытiе (1931).

Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163 155

123

At the time when Lossky published his review, Husserl was better known as a

logician than as the founder of phenomenology. But Lossky also took great interest

in Husserlian phenomenology later on.26 For him, a theory of knowledge “must be

free from assumptions.”27 He conceived of his own ideal-realism as a position that

begins with neither the assumption of naive realism, nor with that of idealism. What

we must begin with, he thought, is the phenomenon — hence his attraction to

phenomenology. However, he thought of phenomenology as a method of access to

being. Ideal-realism was, after all, an ontology and intuitivism a theory of our

knowledge of being.In 1939, while in exile,28 Lossky published an article entitled

“Tpaнcцeндeнтaльнo-фeнoмeнoлoгичecкiй идeaлизм Гyccepля” (Husserl’s Tran-

scendental-Phenomenological Idealism) in the émigré journal Пyть (The Way),29 inwhich he presents and criticizes Husserl’s transcendental idealist turn. In this paper,

Lossky interprets Husserl as a Neo-Kantian idealist. Regardless of whether this

interpretation is correct or not, Lossky is certainly not alone in interpreting Husserl

in this way. We need only mention the likes of Nicolai Hartmann, Roman Ingarden,

and Theodor Celms. Lossky finds support for his own interpretation in passages

such as the following one from the Nachwort, where Husserl says that “the real

world […] has an essential character of relativity to transcendental subjectivity”30

and that “only transcendental subjectivity has the existential meaning of absolute

being.”31 He also quotes the Méditations cartésiennes, where Husserl says that

“objects exist only for us and their essence is that they exist only as objects of actual

or possible consciousness.”32 He also relies on Ludwig Landgrebe, who says, in his

“Husserls Phanomenologie und die Motive zu ihrer Umbildung,” that many

successors of the Gottingen phenomenological school saw that Husserl was moving

away from “a realist turn to the object” (einer realistischen „Wendung zum Objekt“)

26 I specify here that the phenomenology in question is “Husserlian,” because Lossky had already taken

interest in Alexander Pfander’s pre-Husserlian Phänomenologie des Wollens (1900), which he discusses in“The Voluntarist Theory of the Will” (Волюнтаристическое ученiе о волѣ) (1902). This discussion was

afterwards republished in the book Основныя ученія психологіи съ точки зрѣнія волютаризма (1903).27 “Теорiя знанiя должна быть свободною отъ предпосылокъ” (Lossky 1904a, p. 217). See also

Lossky’s Memoirs, where he says that, already as a student, “The ideal for me were philosophers like

Descartes and Hume, who start their systematic doctrines absolutely from scratch, trying not to rely on

any preconceived doctrines and assumptions, but certainly on the basis of reliable facts” (Идеалом дляменя были такие философы, как Декарт или Юм, которые начинают свою систему ученийабсолютно сначала, стремясь не опираться ни на какие предвзятые учения и предпосылки, ноисходя из несомненно достоверного факта) (Lossky 1968, p. 100).28 Lenin exiled Lossky from Russia in 1922 along with other judged “anti-Soviet” members of the

intelligentsia. For a chronicle of this exile, see Chamberlain (2006).29 For a study of the émigré journal Путь edited by Nikolai Berdyaev, see Arjakovsky (2013).30 “die reale Welt […] wesensmaßige Relativitat hat auf die transzendentale Subjektivitat” (Husserl

1930, p. 562).31 “nur die transzendentale Subjektivitat den Seinssinn des absoluten Seins hat” (Husserl 1930, p. 562).32 “Les objets n’existent pour nous et ne sont ce qu’ils sont que comme objets d’une conscience reelle ou

possible” (Husserl 1931, p. 55).

156 Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163

123

and was regressing to a theory that bore the “stamp of Neo-Kantian idealism”

(Idealismus neukantischer Prägung) (Landgrebe 1939, p. 301).

Among Lossky’s criticisms of Husserl is an accusation of inconsistency based on

Husserl’s very claim that his idealism is a transcendental one. Lossky says that

Husserl “claims that his system is a transcendental idealism, as opposed to a

psychological idealism, precisely because of the theory of transcendental intersub-

jectivity.”33 On Lossky’s interpretation, the only truly objective aspect in Husserl’s

transcendental idealism, if any, would be the community of transcendental egos. But

according to Lossky, Husserl is caught in a paradox because the transcendentality of

the other egos remains immanent to consciousness. Husserl himself speaks in terms

of “transcendental immanence” in the Méditations cartésiennes, and he himself

says: “From the phenomenological point of view, the other is a modification of ‘my’

I […]. In other words, another monad is constituted, by appresentation, in my

monad.”34 About Husserl’s self-characterization of his own brand of idealism as

“transcendental,” Lossky remarks that “It is clear that Husserl talks here, as

paradoxical as it may seem, about transcendence immanent to consciousness, just as

the one that Cohen talks about, reforming Kant’s notion of ‘thing in itself’.”35 For

Lossky, if whatever is transcendent is immanently transcendent, then this cannot be

transcendence in the proper sense of the term.

Lossky is sympathetic with Husserl’s use of Leibnizian terminology in calling

transcendental I’s “monads.” Nikolai Onufrievich adopted the Leibnizianism of his

mentor Alexei Kozlov.36 As he says in his Memoirs, Leibniz had become his

“favorite philosopher”37 and he was “deeply imbued with the tendency to

understand the universe as a system of monads in the spirit of Leibniz’s

metaphysics.”38 But Lossky is also critical of Leibniz. For Leibniz, monads do

not have “doors and windows.”39 Christian Wolff had criticized Leibniz on this

point; he argued that the possibility of causation and freewill requires that monads

33 “Онъ говоритъ, что его система есть трансцендентальный идеализмъ, отличный отъпсихологистическаго идеализма именно благодаря ученiю о трансцендентальнойинтерсубъективности” (Lossky 1939, p. 43).34 “Au point de vue phenomenologique, l’autre est une modification de « mon » moi […]. Autrement dit,

une autre monade se constitue, par appresentation, dans la mienne” (Husserl 1931, p. 97).35 “Ясно, что Гуссерль говоритъ здѣсь, какъ это ни парадоксально о трансцендентности,имманентной сознанію, подобно той, о которой говоритъ Когенъ, реформируя понятіе «вещи въсебѣ» Канта” (Lossky 1939, p. 41).36 For Kozlov’s influence on Lossky, see Lossky (1968, pp. 84-85). Kozlov was himself influenced by

Gustav Teichmuller’s Leibnizianism. On the intellectual lineage Teichmuller [ Kozlov [ Lossky, see

Ryzhkova (2013), and Schwenke (2013, esp. pp. 13-14). Of interest is also Kozlov’s article on

Teichmuller published in two installments (Kozlov 1894a, b, vols 24 and 25).37 “любимейший мною философ Лейбниц” (Lossky 1968, p. 110); “мой любимый философЛейбниц” (Lossky 1968, p. 193).38 “глубоко проникся склонностью понимать вселенную, как систему монад в духе метафизикиЛейбница” (Lossky 1968, p. 87).39 “Cela s’accorde avec nos principes, car naturellement rien ne nous entre dans l’esprit par dehors, et

c’est une mauvaise habitude que nous avons, de penser comme si nostre ame recevoit quelques especes

messageres et comme si elle avoit des portes et des fenestres” (Leibniz, Discours de métaphysique, §.XXVI).

Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163 157

123

have windows and doors. Kozlov had likewise admitted intermonadic causation.40

Lossky, who fully agrees with this criticism, reads Husserl’s theory of intersub-

jectivity on the model of Leibniz’s monadology. On this reading, Husserl’s

transcendental idealism is not only a return to Kantianism, but also a return to

Leibnizianism. When transplanted in the context of phenomenology, as Husserl

does in the Méditations cartésiennes, the thesis of the impossibility of intermonadic

relations leads to the conception that egos are cut off from each other. Thus, for

Lossky, Husserl is repeating the Leibnizian mistake of making intermonadic

relations impossible, which, in turn, makes moral progress unachievable. Therefore,

the only aspect of Husserl’s transcendental-idealist phenomenology that could have

saved it from being nothing more than a return to subjective idealism, namely the

recognition of the objective existence of transcendental egos, is really not the

recognition of something existing objectively, but of something immanent to the

subject.

This sort of reaction and criticism of Husserl appears to have been characteristic

of a troika of philosophers born in the Baltic region corresponding to present-day

Latvia. Lossky was born in the city of Kraslava, which was part of the Vitebsk

Governorate in the Russian Empire, now part of Latvia. Another philosopher to

criticize Husserl on these grounds was Theodor Celms, who was born in the

Governorate of Livonia, which is also now in Latvia. In Der PhänomenologischeIdealismus Husserls (1928), Celms interprets Husserl’s phenomenological mon-

adology as a pluralistic solipsism.41 According to Celms, Husserl fails to solve the

problem of intersubjectivity, because his monadology only replaces a monistic

solipsism with a pluralistic one. As Celms says: “It is only with the help of the

metaphysical assumption of pre-established harmony that Husserl obtains his

phenomenological monadology. But the latter is in the strict sense no overcoming ofsolipsism, but rather only an extension of ‘monistic solipsism’ into a ‘pluralisticsolipsism’.”42 We may thus consider the possibility of an influence of Celms on

Lossky.

But Celms was himself influenced by Nicolai Hartmann.43 Hartmann, who was

born in Riga (then part of the Governorate of Livonia) and who studied with Lossky

40 On Kozlov’s Leibnizianism, see Zenkovsky (1950, vol. 2, pp. 172-217). For the claim that he admits

of intermonadic causation, or what he calls “substantial interaction” (взаимодействии субстанций), see(ibib., p. 178).41 “phanomenologische Monadologie Husserls als » Pluralistischer Solipsismus«” (Celms, 1928, p. 402).42 “Nur mit Hilfe der metaphysischen Annahme einer prastabilierten Harmonie gewinnt Husserl seine

phanomenologische Monadologie. Diese ist aber im eigentlichen Sinne gar keine Überwindung desSolipsismus, sondern nur eine Erweiterung des »monistischen Solpsismus« zum »pluralistischen Solip-sismus«” (Celms 1928, p. 404).43 In Teodors Celms: fenomenoloģiskie meklējumi, Maija Kule, Lıva Muizniece, and Uldis Vegners say

that in his “Konigsberg lectures, he mostly focused on the ontology of Nicolai Hartmann, who, in his

opinion, is the greatest contemporary systematic philosopher” (lekcijas Kenigsberga vins pieversas

lielakoties Nikolaja Hartmana ontologijai, kas, vinaprat, ir tagadnes lielakais filosofs sistematikis) (Kule

et al. 2009, p. 65). They also say that while in the United States, Celms continued his reflections on topics

including “Hartmann’s questions about the objective and personal spirit, realist issues about how to avoid

solipsism” (Hartmana jautajumi par objektıvo un personalo garu, realistu jautajumi, ka nenonakt pie

solipsisma) (Kule et al. 2009, p. 239). Celms developed Hartmannian themes notably in his manuscripts

158 Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163

123

at St. Petersburg University, was also critical of Husserl.44 In his correspondence

with Raymond Vancourt, for instance, he says: “I have from the outset seen

phenomenology differently from most contemporaries. Its representatives, espe-

cially Husserl, developed a theory that was half-psychological, half-transcendental;

I have to reject this theory, together with the Husserlian concept of consciousness

and the constraints of the new method of act and act-phenomena. It seemed to me

that we could just as well describe the object-phenomena and thereby re-establish

the priority of the outside world — the same phenomena that Husserl had abrogated

by his bracketing of real cases.”45 Hartmann saw in Husserl’s philosophy — at least

in its third phase — a “regress into idealism.”46 And he claimed in 1921 that

idealism inevitably has solipsism for consequence.47 This, by implication, would

make Husserl a solipsist. So, if influence there was, it could also be, at least in its

general lines, from Lossky to Celms via Hartmann. At any rate, the part of Western

Russia that is now Latvia turns out to have been — fortuitously or not — a breeding

ground of realist phenomenologists in the style of the Munich-Gottingen School.

Lossky also criticizes Husserl for not being sufficiently radical in his abstention

from judgments about existence. On Lossky’s reading of Husserl, the latter would

have inferred without evidence the phenomenal character of the objects of

experience immanent to consciousness. He would have failed to realize that this

conclusion was itself an existential judgment — “he did not include it in his

‘abstention’ and, therefore, was caught in its net.”48 For Lossky, we have to

distinguish between “immanence to consciousness and immanence to the subject ofconsciousness, i.e., the individual I: an object can become immanent to my

consciousness yet remain transcendent to me, the subject of consciousness.”49

Moreover, Lossky defends the view that consciousness is not a mere sphere of

objects, but “is an activity that can take the I beyond its psychophysical

individuality. Consciousness, in the case of my observation of the external world,

Footnote 43 continued

Zum Problem des Nichtmystischen Irrationalismus and Matemātikas filosofija (Kule et al. 2009, pp. 250-253).44 For the claim that Hartmann studied with Lossky, see the unpublished interview with Lossky in which

Herbert Spiegelberg notes that the link “with Nicolai Hartmann, who studied under L[ossky] in St.

Petersburg, was strong” (Spiegelberg 1960).45 “habe ich von vornherein die Phanomenologie anders gesehen als die meisten Zeitgenossen. Ihre

Vertreter, vor allem Husserl selbst, entwickelteten eine Theorie, die halb psychologisch, halb

transcendental war; diese Theorie, zusammen mit dem Husserlschen Bewusstseins begriff musste ich

ablehnen, desgleichen die Beschrankung der neuen Methode auf Akte und Aktphanomene. Es schien mir,

man musste genau so gut Gegenstandsphanomene beschreiben konnen und dadurch das Gewicht der

Aussenwelt wieder herstellen, das Husserl durch seine Einklammerung der Realfalle aufgehoben hatte”

(Hartmann 1945, p. 8, note 1).46 “in Idealismus zuruckfallt (Husserl)” (Hartmann 1925, p. 113).47 “Aber daß der subjektive Idealismus ihn [i.e., Solipsismus] als Konsequenz gar nicht vermeiden kann,

ist evident” (Hartmann 1921, p. 107).48 “онъ не включилъ ее въ составъ своего « воздержанiя » и потому попалъ въ плѣнъ ея” (Lossky

1939, p. 53).49 “имманентность сознанiю и имманентность субъекту сознанiя, т. е. индивиду-альному я:предметъ можетъ стать имманентнымъ моему созна-нiю, но оставаться трансцендентнымъ мнѣ,субъекту сознанiя” (Lossky 1939, p. 54).

Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163 159

123

is a superindividual whole: the knowing subject and the cognizable portion of the

external world, united with it by the relation of coordination, form a unity.”50

Lossky’s insight here is that many psychic processes, such as awareness, attention,

differentiation, recognition, etc., are already transcendent to the subject as bearer of

consciousness. They act as relations of coordination between the subject of

consciousness and objects of the external world. As such, i.e., insofar as they extend

beyond, so to say, their bearer, they are themselves objective features of the world.

And if we are to be radical all the way in our abstention from judgment, and if

objects are given as external to the subject of consciousness—that is, if in the

epochè they appear as external to the I—then, to be consistent, we are forced to take

these objects as objective realities. Once we have recognized that there is a

multiplicity of acts of cognition that exist outside of the I, there is only one step to

make to infer that the objects that they are directed at exist outside of the I, too, and

are not projected, produced, formed, or framed by it.

Finally, Lossky adhered to what we might call an “epistemological primitivism”

according to which a civilized culture has sometimes more chance of being

embroiled in false artificial theories than a more primitive one. In “The Primitive

and the Civilized Mind” (1926), for instance, he says that “the comparison of

philosophical doctrines about the universe with the primitive man’s perception of

the world is particularly useful for making us realize what truths lie hidden in the

naive views of our younger brothers” (Lossky 1926, p. 152). Along the same lines

he says, in 1928, “Often intellectual culture brings with itself not only a liberation

from the primitive ‘naıvete’, but also a deplorable loss of its natural aspect that it

replaces by something artificial.”51 When the Weltanschauung of a civilized culture

has unfolded itself into an intellectual cul de sac, it is the role of other cultures to

show it the way back to a more primitive yet truer worldview. It is in this overall

spirit — quite congruent with Slavophilism and Russian messianism52 — that, in

1939, Lossky says that he has arrived at this “rehabilitation of naive realism by

means of its liberation from naivety and its formulation in the form of a theory of

intuitivism.”53 Lossky thus thought that he had completed the return to the things

that Husserl announced in the second part of the Logische Untersuchungen(“Einleitung,” § 2), but never achieved.

In 1962, i.e., three years before dying at 94 years old, the indefatigable Lossky

reused material published in “Husserl’s Transcendental-Phenomenological Ideal-

ism” for composing another paper on Husserl entitled “Two Ways of Refuting

50 “есть дѣятельность, могущая выво-дить я за предѣлы ею психо-физической индивидуальности.Сознанiе, въ случаѣ наблюденiя мною внѣшняго мiра, есть сверх-индивидуальное цѣлое: сознающiйсубъектъ и сознаваемый имъ отрѣзокъ внѣшняго мiра, спаянный съ нимъ отношенiемъ ко-ординацiи, образуютъ единство” (Lossky 1939, p. 54).51 “Souvent la culture de l’esprit apporte avec elle non seulement la liberation de la « naıvete » primitive,

mais aussi une perte deplorable de son cote naturel qu’elle remplace par un cote artificiel” (Lossky 1928,

p. 51).52 On Russian messianism, see, for instance, Solov’ev’s theory of the development of humanity and of

Russia’s mission presented in Three Forces (Три силы) (1877).53 “реабилитація наивнаго реализма путемъ освобожденія его отъ наивности и формулировки еговъ видѣ теоріи интуитивизма съ точно опредѣленными понятіями” (Lossky 1939, p. 54).

160 Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163

123

Solipsism: A Critique of Husserl’s Phenomenology” (Lossky 1962).54 In this paper,

published in English in the Bostonian journal The Philosophical Forum, Losskyreformulates his criticism of Husserl’s theory of the transcendental ego, to which he

opposes, again, his homegrown intuitivism and his Neo-Leibnizian personalistic

metaphysics. For Lossky, the intuitivist theory of the immediate apprehension of

external objects is by itself a refutation of solipsism. Moreover, for him all is

immanent in all. So monads, or what he calls substantival agents, are partially

consubstantial with one another and are epistemologically coordinated in a way that

renders solipsism impossible. This paper, along with the review of the LogischeUntersuchungen and the 1939 paper, constitute the sum of Lossky’s published work

on Husserl.55

Acknowledgments Thanks are due to Thomas Nemeth, Rodney Parker, Frederick Matern, Nikolaj

Plotnikov, Elena Serdyukova, and Uldis Vegners for valuable comments, as well as to Maria Avril (néeLossky), who oversees the archives of her grandfather’s works at the Institut d’Etudes Slaves, Paris. Part

of the research leading to this paper has received funding from the European Union’s Seventh Framework

Program (FP7/2007-2013 - MSCA-COFUND) under Grant agreement n°245743 - Post-doctoral program

Braudel-IFER-FMSH, in collaboration with the Institut Jean Nicod, Paris.

References

Arjakovsky, Antoine (2013), The Way: Religious Thinkers of the Russian Emigration in Paris and TheirJournal, 1925-1940, translated by Jerry Ryan, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

Celms, Theodor (1928), Der Phänomenologische Idealismus Husserls, Riga: Walters und Rapa.

Chamberlain, Lesley (2006), Lenin’s Private War: The Voyage of the Philosophy Steamer and the Exile ofthe Intelligentsia, New York: St. Martin’s Press.

Dennes, Maryse (1997a), “Husserl et l’ecole russe de phenomenologie,” Slavica occitania, Toulouse, vol.4, pp. 153–175.

Dennes, Maryse (1997b), “L’influence de Husserl en Russie au debut du XXeme siecle et son impact sur

les emigres russes de Prague,” Jakobson entre l’Est et l’Ouest, 1915-1939: Un épisode de l’histoirede la culture européenne, Lausanne: Cahiers de l’ILSL, n. 9, pp. 47–68.

Dmitriev, T. A. (1998), “Николай Онуфриевич Лосский,” И. М. Чубарова (ed.), Антологияфеноменологической философии в россии, Москва: Логос «гнозис» РФО, pp. 180–182.

Fischer, Kuno (1902), Geschichte der neuern Philosophie. Siebenter Band. Schellings Leben, Werke undLehre, Dritte Auflage, Heidelberg: Carl Winter’s Universitatsbuchhandlung.

Frank, Semyon Lyudvigovich (1926a), “Die russische Philosophie der letzten funfzehn Jahre,” Kant-Studien, vol. 31, pp. 89–104.

Frank, Semyon Lyudvigovich (1926b), Die russische Weltanschauung, Charlottenburg: Pan-Verlag Rolf

Heise.

Hartmann, Nicolai (1921), Grundzüge einer Metaphysik der Erkenntnis, erste Auflage, Berlin und

Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter & Co.

Hartmann, Nicolai (1925), Grundzüge einer Metaphysik der Erkenntnis, zweite Auflage, Berlin und

Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter & Co.

Hartmann, Nicolai (1945), Les principes d’une métaphysique de la connaissance, translated by Raymond

Vancourt, Paris: Aubier Montaigne, tome 1.

Husserl, Edmund (1901), Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Theil: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologieund Theorie der Erkenntnis, Halle (Saale): Max Niemeyer.

54 Typescript drafts of “Two Ways of Refuting Solipsism” exist in both the Russian and English version

in the Lossky-archives at the Institut d’Etudes Slaves, Paris. The Russian version bears the title:

“Субординационное преодоление солипсизма в философии Гуссерля и координационноепреодоление.”55 For further readings on Lossky and Husserl, see Molchanov (2010) and Schastlivceva (2010).

Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163 161

123

Husserl, Edmund (1930), “Nachwort zu meinen Ideen zu einer reinen Phanomenologischen Philosophie,”

Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, Halle (Saale): Max Niemeyer Verlag,

11. Band, pp. 549–570.

Husserl, Edmund (1931), Méditations cartésiennes, traduit par Emmanuel Levinas, Paris: Armand Colin.

Jakowenko, Boris (1929/1930), “Ed. Husserl und die russische Philosophie,” Der russische Gedanke:internationale Zeitschrift für russische Philosophie, Literaturwissenschaft und Kultur, vol. 2,

pp. 210–212.

Kozlov, Alexei A. (1894a), “Густавъ Тейхмюллеръ,” Вопросы философiи и психологiи, Книга 24,

pp. 523–536.

Kozlov, Alexei A. (1894b), “Густавъ Тейхмюллеръ (Окончанiе),” Вопросы философiи и психологiи,Книга 25, pp. 661–681.

Kule, Maija, Lıva Muizniece, & Uldis Vegners (2009), Teodors Celms: fenomenoloģiskie meklējumi,Latvia: Letonika.

Kurennoj, Vitalij (2005), “К вопросу о возникновении феноменологического движения,” Логос, 5(50), pp. 247–275.

Landgrebe, Ludwig (1939), “Husserls Phanomenologie und die Motive zu ihrer Umbildung,” RevueInternationale de Philosophie, vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 277–316.

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1907), Discours de métaphysique, Paris: Felix Alcan.

Lipps, Theodor (1893), Grundzüge der Logik, Hamburg und Leipzig: Verlag von Leopold Voss.

Lipps, Theodor (1902), Основы логики, русский перевод Лосского, СПб.Lopatin, Leo Mikhailovich (1916), “The Philosophy of Vladimir Soloviev,” translated by A. Bakshy,

Mind, vol. 25, n. 100, pp. 425–460.Lossky, Boris, & Nadejda Lossky (1978), Bibliographie des œuvres de Nicolas Lossky, Paris: Institut

d’Etudes Slaves.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1902), “Волюнтаристическое ученiе о волѣ,” Вопросы философiи ипсихологiи, Книга 62, pp. 667–709.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1903a), “Основныя ученiя психологiи съ точки зрѣнiя волюнтаризма,”Вопросы философiи и психологiи, Книга 66, pp. 1–42.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1903b), Основныя ученія психологіи съ точки зрѣнія волютаризма,Санкт-Петербург.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1904a), “Обоснованiе мистического эмпиризма. Глава II-III,” Вопросыфилософiи и психологiи, Книга 73, pp. 197–228.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1904b), “Обоснованiе мистического эмпиризма. Глава III-IV,” Вопросыфилософiи и психологiи, Книга 74, pp. 315–396.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1904c), “Обоснованiе мистического эмпиризма. Глава V,” Вопросыфилософiи и психологiи, Книга 75, pp. 451–507.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1905), “Обоснованiе мистического эмпиризма. Глава VII-VIII,”Вопросы философiи и психологiи, Книга 78, pp. 163–211.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1906), Обоснованiе интуитивизма: Пропедевтическая теорія знанія,Санкт-Петербург.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1909), “Э. Гуссерль, Логическія изслѣдованія, Часть первая.Пролегомены къ чистой логикѣ. Разрѣшенный авторомъ переводъ съ нѣмецкаго Э. А.Берштейнъ, подъ редакціею и съ предисловіемъ С. Л. Франка. Книгоиздательство „Образо-вание“. Спб., 1909, 224 г.” Русская мысль, книга XII, 1909, pp. 292–293.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1912), Логика проф. А. И. Введенскаго, Москва, Типо-литографiя Т-ваИ. Н. Кушнеревъ и Ко.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1913), “Недостатки гносеологiи Бергсона и влiянiе ихъ на егометафизику,” Вопросы философiи и психологiи, Книга 118, pp. 224–235.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1914), Интуитивная философия Бергсона, Москва: Изданiе Путь.Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1916), Матерiя въ системѣ органическаго мiровоззрѣнiя, Москва:

Изданiе Г. А. Лемана и С. И. Сахарова.Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1922–1923), Логика, Берлин: Обелиск, 2 vols.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1926), “The Primitive and the Civilized Mind,” Journal of PhilosophicalStudies, vol. 1, n. 2, pp. 145–158.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1928), “Esquisse d’une theorie intuitiviste de la connaissance,” RevuePhilosophique de la France et de l’Étranger, tome 105, pp. 50–87.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1930), “The Chief Characteristics of a System of Logic Based Upon

Intuitivism in Epistemology and Ideal-Realism in Metaphysics,” Gilbert Ryle (ed.), Proceedings of

162 Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163

123

the Seventh International Congress of Philosophy Held at Oxford, England, September 1-6, 1930,Oxford University Press, pp. 254–260.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1931), Цѣнность и бытiе: богъ и царство божiе какъ основацѣнностей, Paris: YMCA Press.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1939), “Трансцендентально-феноменологическiй идеализм Гуссерля,”Путь: Органъ русской религiозной мысли, n. 60, pp. 37–56.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1952), History of Russian Philosophy, London: Georg Allen and Unwin

Ltd.

Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1962), “Two Ways of Refuting Solipsism: A Critique of Husserl’s

Phenomenology,” The Philosophical Forum: An Annual Journal, vol. 19, pp. 41–55.Lossky, Nikolai Onufrievich (1968), Воспоминания: Жизнь и философский путь, herausgegeben von

B. N. Lossky, Munchen: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.

Molchanov, Victor (2010), “Позиции и предпосылки Теория знания Н. О. Лосского и феномено-логияp,” Логос, vol. 5, n. 78, pp. 22–42.

Nemeth, Thomas (1998), “The Rise of Russian Neo-Kantianism: Vvedenskij’s Early ‘Critical

Philosophy’,” Studies in East European Thought, vol. 50, n. 2, pp. 119–151.Nemeth, Thomas (2014), The Early Solov’ëv and His Quest for Metaphysics, Springer.Pfander, Alexander (1900), Phänomenologie des Wollens: eine psychologische Analyse, Leipzig: J.

A. Barth.

Radlov, Ernest L. (1925), Russische Philosophie, Breslau: Ferdinand Hirt.

Ryzhkova, Galina S. (2013), “Gustav Teichmuller, a German-born Founder of Russian Personalism,”

Journal of Siberian Federal University. Humanities & Social Sciences, vol. 2, n. 6, pp. 284–290.Schastlivceva, Elena Anatol’evna (2010), “Реалистическая феноменология Н. О. Лосского и

трансцендентальная феноменология Э. Гуссерля,” Вече: Журнал русской философии икультуры, vol. 21, pp. 71–82.

Schwenke, Heiner (2013), “‘A Star of the First Magnitude within the Philosophical World’: Introduction

to Life and Work of Gustav Teichmuller,” Studia Philosophica Estonica, February, pp. 1–21.Shchedrina, Tat’iana G. (ed.) (2005), Густав Шпет: жизнь в письмах: Эпистолярное наследие,

Москва: Российская политическая энциклопедия.Shpet, Gustav (1917), “Нѣкоторыя черты изъ представленiя Н. О. Лосскаго о природѣ,” Мысль и

слово, t. 1, Мoscow, pp. 368–374.

Shpet, Gustav (1991), Appearance and Sense: Phenomenology as the Fundamental Science and ItsProblems, translated by Thomas Nemeth, Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

Solov’ev, Vladimir Sergeyevich (1877), Три силы, Москва: Въ университетской типографiи.Solov’ev, Vladimir Sergeyevich (1880), Критика отвлеченныхъ началъ,Москва: Въ университетской

типографiи.Spiegelberg, Herbert (1960), “Notebook from Interviews with Philosophers 1922–1930; 1953–1960,”

Herbert Spiegelberg Papers, University Archives, Department of Special Collections, Washington

University Libraries, Box 2, Folder 9.

Spiegelberg, Herbert (1976), The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction, The Hague:

Nijhoff, vol. 2.

Viktorov, David V. (1904), “Философскiе взгляды Эрнста Маха,” Вопросы философiи и психологiи,vol. 73, n. 3, pp. 229–313.

Zenkovsky, Vasily Vasil’evich (1948), История русской философии, Париж: YMCA-Press, vol. 1.

Zenkovsky, Vasily Vasil’evich (1950), История русской философии, Париж: YMCA-Press, vol. 2.

Zinchenko, Vladimir, Boris Pruzhinin, and Tat’iana Shchedrina (2011), “ ‘Another Consciousness’ as the

Horizon of Cultural-Historical Psychology,” Journal of Russian and East European Psychology, vol.49, n. 4, pp. 31–46.

Husserl Stud (2016) 32:149–163 163

123