ct jf 07.ppt - university of torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/ct_jf_07.pdf · categorical...

52
Deduction Deductive arguments, deduction, deductive logic all means the same thing. They are different ways of referring to the same style of reasoning Deduction is just one mode of reasoning, but it is a formidable form of reasoning. Deductive reasoning is common in the ‘imperial disciplines. Deductive reasoning is prized because deductive arguments have the highest standards of cogency. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises Recall: we reserve the term sound to describe good deductive arguments.

Upload: others

Post on 23-Apr-2020

5 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Deduction

• Deductive arguments, deduction, deductive logic all means thesame thing.– They are different ways of referring to the same style of

reasoning• Deduction is just one mode of reasoning, but it is a formidable form

of reasoning. Deductive reasoning is common in the ‘imperialdisciplines.

• Deductive reasoning is prized because deductive arguments havethe highest standards of cogency.

– Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongestrelationship between the premises

• Recall: we reserve the term sound to describe good deductivearguments.

Page 2: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Recall: Validity

• In day-to-day life, we talk about a valid driver’s license, or the validation of software serial number.

• Validity is a technical term in deductive logic.• If an argument has an appropriate deductive form, then we say

that the argument is valid.• Recall: deductive logic is just one mode of reasoning, though it is

a very powerful form of reasoning.

• A deductive argument is either “valid” or “invalid”. • When we say that an argument is invalid we mean that we are rejecting

the argument because it doesn’t have the right deductive form.• When we say this, we don’t care about the content of the premises.

• That is, we don’t care what the premises are about.

Page 3: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Recall: Validity (more)

• If an argument has a valid form and the premises are true, then the conclusion of the argument must be true.– The conclusion is deductively entailed.

• But, an argument may be valid (have the right form or structure) but not be true. It’s premises could be false.

• Important: Committing to the validity of an argument, does not necessarily commit you to the truth conclusion.– Likewise, asserting the invalidity of an argument, does not necessarily

commit you to rejecting the conclusion. (You might accept the conclusion, but reject the form of the argument given for the conclusion.)

Page 4: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Validity IllustratedP1: If it’s whirly-gig then smack-gurgle.P2: This is a whirly-gig.C1: This is also a smack-gurgle.

• This is a valid argument. We recognize the form as being valid. Allarguments of this form are valid:

P1: If P then Q.P2: PC1: Therefore, Q

• But, not all arguments of this form necessarily produce true conclusions. Inthis case, we don’t know if the premises are true or false.• We only know that argument is valid. We know nothing about its truth!

Page 5: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

An example of validity• Premise: All apples are fruit.• Premise: All fruit contain antioxidants.• Conclusion: All apples contain antioxidants.

• Premise: All aardvarks have long noses.• Premise: Anything with a long nose has an acute sense of smell.• Conclusion: All aardvarks have an acute sense of smell.

• Logical form:• All As are Bs.• All Bs are Cs.• Therefore, all As are Cs.

Page 6: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

A Valid But Untrue SyllogismConsider this syllogism again:

P1: All men are purple.P2: Socrates is a man.C1: Socrates is purple.

This syllogism also has the form:P1: All S are PP2: M is SC1: M is P

Recall: Truth and Validity are different things. Validity guarantees (and only guarantees) that if the premises are true the conclusion will be true.

In this case, P1 is false. So, the conclusion is false. Nonetheless, the form of the syllogism is valid.

Page 7: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Important!Validity and Truth are Different.

Example 1:P1: All men are mortal.P2: Socrates is a man.C1: Socrates is mortal.(Valid and True)

Example 2:P1: All men are purple.P2: Socrates is a man.C1: Socrates is purple.(Valid but false)

Common Form:All S are PM is an S.Therefore, M is P

Note: Example 1 and Example 2 have exactly the same form or structure of argument. This is one valid form of deductive argument.

Page 8: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Valid Deductive Arguments are Truth Preserving

Look at Example 2 again:P1: All men are purple.P2: Socrates is a man.C1: Socrates is purple.(Valid but false)

• What went wrong? Clearly, P1 is false. It is not true that “All men are purple.”

• Hypothetically, if P1 were true, then C1 would be true too!

• Valid deductive arguments are truth preserving.– That’s a fancy way of saying that: in valid deductive arguments are machines the

gobble up true premises and split out true conclusions.

Page 9: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Why we ♥ deduction …• In deductive arguments, the premises entail the

conclusion.

• This is because valid deductive arguments are truth preserving.

• And so, it is not possible for the premises of a deductive argument to be true and the conclusion false.

• In more detail:If (1) the premises are true,And (2) the form of the deductive argument is valid,Then (3) the conclusion must be true

… always and forever which is why ‘imperial disciplines’ love deduction!

Page 10: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Deductive Logic• Often when people say “logic” they mean “deductive logic”

– There are other logics, notably, inductive logic.

• Deductive logic is studies the valid forms of deductive argument.– It looks at the forms of argument that preserve truth.– It looks at ways of testing arguments to see if they are valid (truth

preserving).

• Important: Form NOT Content!– Deductive logic is concerned purely with forms of argument, not

the content.– It is not concerned with truth. It is only concerned with figuring

out the arguments that preserve truth.

Page 11: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Scope of Course Concern

• There are many types of deductive logic.– We will be looking briefly at one: categorical logic– The aim is to understand what deductive arguments look likes so

you know when you are dealing with a situation involving deductive entailment.

• Shameless advertisement: If you want deductive logic, take PHIL2210 and then PHIL3110.

Page 12: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Categorical Logic

• Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good arguments have common shapes, forms or patterns.

• Aristotle thought of logic as a tool or organon for inquiry.

• We call Aristotle’s tool categorical logic, or syllogistic logic, or simply syllogism.

Page 13: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Four Categorical Statements

1) Universal Affirmative – All S is P“All men are mortal”“Every man is an island”

2) Universal Negative – No S is P“No conservatives are fiscally responsible.”“No penguins are flying birds.

3) Particular Affirmative – Some S is P“Some guinea pigs have long hair.”“Some Tories are good people”

4) Particular Negative – Some S is not P“Some people are not generous”“Some rocks are not sedimentary.”

Page 14: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Variables

• The four forms of the syllogism are: All S are P; No S are P; Some S are P; Some S are not P.

• We use ‘S’ and ‘P’ to stand for the specific content of the statements. – We do this because we are only interested in the form of the

statements.– The use of variables helps us achieve generality.

• We say that ‘S’ and ‘P’ are variables.– The specific content of S and P may change or vary.

Page 15: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Categories

• We use ‘S’ to stand for the subject of the statement (what the statement is about) and ‘P’ to stand for the predicate of the statement (what is begin said about the subject.)– The choice of ‘S’ and ‘P’ as variables is entirely

conventional. We could use any letter or other symbol

• Categorical logic is the logic of categories.– The subject and predicate will always be categories.

• Any category can include only one thing, five things, or everything. Likewise, a category can exclude only one thing, five things, or everything.

Page 16: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Examples

• All robins are birds. – Every thing in the category robin is a member of the category

birds.

• No elephants are reptiles.– Everything in the category elephant is not a member of the

category reptile.

• Some mammals are marsupials.– Some of the things in the category of mammals are members of

the category or marsuplials.

• Some animals are not viviparous.– Some of the things that are animals are not things that are

viviparous.

Page 17: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Categorical Form

• We make many assertions about categories, but most of the time the sentences that we utter are not exactly in categorical form.

• Nevertheless, it is still plausible to represent their content in the categorical form. – That is, we can translate many different kinds of

sentences into sentences with one of the four categorical forms.

Page 18: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Everyday sentences can be translated into categorical sentences and categorical sentences can be translated into standard form …

• Every robin is a bird.All robins are birds.All S are P

• Every elephant is not a reptile.No elephants are reptiles. No S are P

• There are a few mammals that are marsupialsSome mammals are marsupials. Some S are P

• You can find animals that are not viviparous.Some animals are not viviparous. Some S are not P

Page 19: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Translation into Categorical Form

(1) Stylistic variants: many different sentences can assert exactly the same categorical relation. – “All Texans are ornery”, “Every single Texan is ornery”, “Any

Texan is ornery”, “There is no Texan who is not ornery.”

(2) ‘A’ and ‘The’ are ambiguous between a particular and a universal (or generic) sense.

– “A lion is a mammal” makes a different claim that “A lion just escaped from the zoo”

(3) ‘Any’ is generally universal, but is particular when inside the scope of a ‘not’.

– Compare ‘Amy can solve any problem’ and ‘Amy cannot solve any problem’.

(4) ‘Only’: Like ‘all’, ‘only’ asserts a universal affirmative, but it asserts the opposite inclusion relation.

– ‘Only Ss are P’ translates into Categorical form as ‘All Ps are S’.

Page 20: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Syllogism

• Syllogisms are a basic form of argument.• Syllogisms have three lines; two premises and one

conclusion.

• You see lots of syllogisms. Here are two you have seen in the course:

P1: All men are mortal.P2: Socrates is a man.C1: Socrates is mortal.

P1: All three-sided figures are triangles.P2: This figure has three sides.C1: This figure is a triangle.

Page 21: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Anatomy of a Syllogism• A syllogism consists of three sentences. Two premises and one

conclusion.• Each sentence is made up of two terms.

– Every term occurs twice in a syllogism.

• Count the terms in the following syllogismP1: All S are MP2: No M are PC1: No S are P

• Each unique term that makes up the syllogism has a particular name.– The predicate, P, of the conclusion is the major term.– The subject, S, of the conclusion is the minor term.– The term that appears in both premises but not the conclusion is

the middle term.

Page 22: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Translating Syllogisms into Categorical Form

P1: All men are mortal.P2: Socrates is a man.C1: Socrates is mortal.

P1: All three-sided figures are triangles.P2: This figure has three sides.C1: This figure is a triangle.

P1: All S are PP2: M is SC1: M is P

P1: All S are PP2: M is SC1: M is P

• These syllogisms have different contents but the same logical form! They are valid for the same reason.

Page 23: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Translate Syllogism into Categorical Form

“No lawyers are golfers, but some golfers are doctors. Therefore, no lawyers are doctors.”

No L are G.Some G are D.Therefore, no L are D.

Page 24: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Translation“Only doctors are golfers, and any golfer has good turf shoes. So, all doctors have good turf shoes.”

All G are D.All G are S.Therefore, all D are S.

Page 25: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Venn Diagrams

• In Symbolic Logic (1881), English mathematician John Venn (1834-1923) invented a way to pictorially represent categorical statements, and to test syllogisms for validity.

• Every category is represented by a circle. We overlap the circles, so that we can represent inclusion and exclusion relations between categories.

Page 26: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

One Category

Page 27: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

One Category

Page 28: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Two Categories

Lawyers Golfers

Page 29: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Two Categories

Lawyers Golfers

Lawyers who are also golfers.

Golfersonly

Lawyers only

Page 30: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Picturing Categorical Statements

• We can use Venn diagrams to picture categorical statements and syllogisms.

• We use Venn diagrams to picture logical space.

• “[In Venn diagrams] logical space is represented in circles and parts of circles. To indicate that there is nothing in an area of logical space, we shade in the area. To indicate that there is something, we put an x in the space.” [216]

Page 31: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Universal Affirmative

“All lawyers are golfers.”“All S are P.”

P“golfers”

S“lawyers”

Page 32: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Universal Negative

“No lawyers are golfers.”“No S are P.”

P“golfers”

S“lawyers”

Page 33: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Particular Affirmative

“Some lawyers are golfers.”“Some S are P.”

X

P“golfers”

S“lawyers”

Page 34: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Particular Negative

X

“Some lawyers are not golfers.”“Some S are not P.”

S“lawyers”

P“golfers”

Page 35: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Venn Diagrams and Syllogisms• We can use Venn diagrams to picture syllogisms, AND

to check whether or not the syllogism is valid or invalid.

• Consider the syllogism:All S are PNo P is MTherefore, no S is M.

• Every categorical statement has two terms, and so we pictured categorical statements with two circles, one for each term.

• Since a syllogism has three terms, we will need three circles to picture the syllogism, again one for each term.

Page 36: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Venn Diagram for a Syllogism

M

PS

Page 37: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

An Example

• Consider the syllogism:– All liberals are Keynesians.– No Keynesians are monetarists.– Therefore, no liberal is a monetarist.

• The syllogism has the form:All S are MNo M are PTherefore, no S are P.

• We can picture this syllogism in a Venn diagram.

Page 38: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

P1: All S are MP2: No M are PC1: No S are P

S P

M

Page 39: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

** P1: All S are M **P2: No M are PC1: No S are P

S P

M

Page 40: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

** P1: All S are M **P2: No M are PC1: No S are P

S P

M

Page 41: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

P1: All S are M** P2: No M is P **

C1: No S is P

S P

M

Page 42: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Validity and Invalidity

• In valid deductions, the conclusion states no more information than has already been stated in the premises.– This is why valid deductive arguments are truth preserving.

They simply preserve whatever truth happens to have been stated in the premises.

• If the conclusion states more than has been stated in the premises, then the conclusion is invalid.

• To see if a conclusion is valid or invalid, we simply check to see if the information in the conclusion is already pictured in the Venn diagram.

– If the information is already on the diagram, then the syllogism is valid.– If the information is not already on the diagram – if something new has been

stated in the conclusion – then the syllogism is invalid.

Page 43: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

P1: All S are MP2: No M is P

** C1: No S is P **

S P

M

Valid! The area in green picturing “No S is P” was already shaded black and red. So, all the information in the conclusion is information already in the premises.

Page 44: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Another Example

P1: Some people who smoke also drink.P2: Some people who drink take risks.C1: Some people who smoke take risks.

P1: Some S are MP2: Some M are PC1: Some S are P

Page 45: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

** P1: Some S are M **P2: Some M are PC1: Some S are P

S P

M

X

Page 46: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

** P1: Some S are M **P2: Some M are PC1: Some S are P

S P

M

XX

Page 47: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

P1: Some S are M ** P2: Some M are P **

C1: Some S are P

S P

M

XX X

Page 48: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

P1: Some S are MP2: Some M are P

** C1: Some S are P **

S P

M

XX X

X (!)

Invalid! Note that the X marked with an exclamation point was not information included in either of the premises.

Page 49: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Like forms have like properties of validity and invalidity

• We began with examples that included content. We replaced the content with variables.– This allows us to achieve generality.– The specific content of an argument does not affect its validity or

invalidity.• From the first example, all syllogisms are valid if they have the form:

P1: All S are MP2: No M are PP3: No S are P.

• From the second example, all syllogisms are invalid if they have the form:P1: Some S are MP2: Some M are PC1: Some S are P

• Keep in mind, these are just specific examples. There are, of course, many other valid syllogism forms. We will need to test each to see if it is a valid or invalid form.

Page 50: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Last Example

P1: All fuzzies are dolittles.P2: Some dolittles are mugwumps.C1: No fuzzies are mugwumps.

P1: All S are MP2: Some M are PC1: No S are P

• We are going to do this example in a single diagram.

Page 51: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

P1: All S are MP2: Some M are PC1: No S are P

S P

M

XX

Invalid! Note the shading and the X in the very center section indicates a contradiction.

Page 52: CT JF 07.ppt - University of Torontohomes.chass.utoronto.ca/~jfoster/CT_JF_07.pdf · Categorical Logic • Aristotle (384-322BCE), an Ancient Greek philosopher, showed that some good

Summary of Some Key Points

• All categorical statements have one of four forms. Each has a unique Venn diagram with two circles.

• We can use a Venn diagram with three circles to represent a syllogism and test whether the syllogism is valid or invalid.

• Remember that validity and invalidity has nothing to do with truth and falsity.

• Valid arguments preserve truth. In a valid argument, if the premises are true, then the conclusion will be true.

• Valid deductive arguments provide the strongest relationship between premises and conclusion. Such arguments are sound; i.e., possess the highest standard of cogency.