behavioral ism

Upload: gabriela-lorena

Post on 06-Apr-2018

214 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    1/15

    BEHAVIORALISM:

    Origins of the Concept

    1. Behavioralism and the History of American Political

    Science

    In the short history of American academic political science, behavioralism has played an

    important role. Even most contemporary historians of the discipline have agreed with Waldo's

    statement above (e.g., Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 150; Farr 1995: 198). Behavioralism

    has, indeed, haunted the discipline for half of its existence now. And although behavioralism

    is a product of an American political science and must be understood in that context, the

    impact of behavioralism on political science may have been as big in some other countries asit was in the United States. (1) In that sense the 'story' should have relevance fo all political

    scientists.

    To write about behavioralism today is important at least for three reasons. First, the question

    is about the identity. Although the present state of the discipline is usually labeled as

    postbehavioralism, "the present postbehavioral era can be understood only with reference to

    behavioralism and that, even then, the behavioral revolution is open to different

    interpretations" (Farr 1995: 221). But the strong identity is also based on conflict, and

    although "political scientists have quarreled over many matters in the contemporary

    period...the most divisive issue by far has been behavioralism" (Somit and Tanenhaus 1982:

    173). Only conflicts reveal important issues.

    Secondly, behavioralism is one of the best research objects to understand the nature of

    political science and conceptual change within the discipline. The period following the

    Second World War was actually one of the two significant moments of academic reform in

    the United States, the first one being the rise of the research university after the Civil War

    (Bender 1997: 4). This academic reform touched also political science. The 1950s and the

    early 1960s were the golden days for the support of modern social science (Warren E. Miller

    in Baer 1991: 242). In fact, the prestige of social science has clearly declined in the United

    States since that time (Lindblom 1997: 227). And behavioralism brought passion for many. It

    has even be claimed that none of the contemporary tendencies "has caught the imagination of

    the discipline as whole and swept it along with the sense of a common and compelling

    purpose" (David Easton in Baer 1991: 213; cf. also Lindblom 1997: 230) the way

    behavioralism did. The reasons for passion were many, but passion there was.

    Thirdly, from time to time it is useful to look back at history to see, if there is something to

    learn from history. Social sciences are eager to adopt new ideas, research topics and

    approaches. Many times these new ideas may sweep important topics into the dustbin of

    history. Maybe it is time to save something important.

    2. An Intellectual Matrix of Political Science

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    2/15

    To analyse the history of political science it is useful to understand the development as a

    discursive practice. What is usually referred to as discursive practice (Berndtson 1983;

    Berndtson 1987; Gunnell 1993: 1) refers to a scholar's attempt to work intellectually within

    the scientific and social discourse in given society society. A scholar tries to answer problems

    which the society poses, but he does so through theoretical debate. A good example is

    conceptual change within a discipline. As James Farr points out: "Conceptual change is oneimaginative consequence of political actors criticizing and attempting to resolve the

    contradictions which they discover or generate in the complex web of their beliefs, actions,

    and practices as they try to understand and change the world around them" (Farr 1989: 25).

    To understand the nature and history of behavioralism I will use the following simple

    intellectual matrix of political science as a framework for discursive practice:

    An Intellectual Matrix of Political Science

    Political science is an endeavor between science and society. As a study of politics, political

    science lives off the social, and above all, political development. This is self-evident, butapparently one must remind of it once in a while (e.g., Lowi 1992; Ball 1995: 41-41). The

    discipline is always a part of politics, in three different senses. First, social development offers

    problems to study; secondly, it has a socializing effect; and thirdly, political scientists have to

    cope with society in order to pursue their interests, whether in obtaining resources for research

    or even in being allowed to do research.

    Scholars must deal with organizations. Governments, foundations and corporations are

    important financiers of research. There may be direct demands for research or at least indirect

    ones.

    Contacts with society usually lead into bureaucratic rhetorics within the discipline (Ball

    1995). Scholars have to convince influential outsiders about the relevance of their research.

    Bureaucratic rhetorics is always a part of a general metadiscourse of the discipline, other part

    being an internal criticism among scholars. In reality these two forms of metadiscourse often

    get mixed and it is hard to separate them.

    Goals of the discipline belong partly to a general metadiscourse of the discipline (bureaucratic

    rhetorics or internal criticism), but they are also part of scientific practice (discourse on

    methodology). In that sense they are an important link between metadiscourse and scientific

    practice itself. In regard to the latter it is useful to make a distinction between research areas,

    theories, organizing concepts and methodology (Berndtson 1983). In short: what to study,existing knowledge systems, perspectives and methods.

    The division of the focus of political science into research areas, theories, organizing concepts

    and methodology ahas an affinity with research programs (Lakatos) and with research

    traditions (Laudan) as they have been used in political science (Ball 1976; Dryzek 1986).

    Laudan, for instance, defines research traditions as "a set of general assumptions about the

    entities and processes in a domain of study, and about the appropriate methods to be used for

    investigating the problems and constructing the theories in that domain." (Laudan 1977: 81;

    Dryzek 1986: 305)

    Without going into a discussion about the usefulness of research programs or researchtraditions in the study of political science (see Dryzek 1986), I will use the term of a research

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    3/15

    tradition to refer to the web of research areas, theories, organizing concepts and methodology.

    As an example of research traditions one can take, for instance, rational choice theories,

    functionalism and Marxism (Ball 1976; although Ball calls them research programs). It is

    important to point out that in order to qualify as a research tradition research areas, theories,

    organizing concepts and methodology must form a logical system of thought.

    Political science organizations include universities, associations, think tanks, etc. In a given

    society these organizations reflect the general culture of that society. An important feature of

    these organizations is their degree of academic freedom, which, again, is very much

    dependent on the prevailing degree of democracy and freedom in society in general.

    Individual scholars may be divided into the elite, the mandarins, and the mass. The mandarins

    may belong to the elite or to the mass, but for the purposes of the present article, it is useful to

    understand them as a category of their own.

    A last dimension is the impact of other disciplines. Social sciences have always developed in

    close contact with each other. In the case of political science it has been common that thediscipline has received more impulses from other disciplines than the other way around. It is

    also important to notice that relations between academic disciplines are continuously

    changing. To study the history of political science is also to study relations between

    disciplines.

    3. Definitions of Behavioralism

    Most histories of political science agree on one thing: the concept of behavioralism has

    always been somewhat unclear. As Dwight Waldo stated while writing about the emergence

    of behavioralism, "what happened was...complicated - and somewhat obscure" (Waldo 1975:58). Almost all those trying to define behavioralism have confessed that "every man puts his

    own emphasis and thereby becomes his own behavioralist" (Easton 1962: 9) and "attempts at

    coming to any complete definition of behavioralism are probably futile given the diversity of

    those who followed its banner" (Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 151). And also David Truman

    has warned that it is a mistake to overstandardize the definition of behavioralism, because "it

    was a kind multifaceted expression of dissatisfaction with the constraints and formalities of

    the conventional political science" and "that impulse, was the only thing that was in common

    among really a quite diverse series of efforts" (David Truman in Baer, et al., eds. 1991). The

    problem in trying to interpret the meaning of behavioralism simply seems to be that we can

    always find "authorities to whom we can turn to press our interpretation" (Easton 1962: 9).

    This seems to indicate that there has been no behavioralism, but many behavioralisms.

    Accordingly, the first conclusion is that behavioralism is not a research tradition, but

    something else. To find out what, a short history of conceptual change is useful.

    Behavioralism as a concept dates from the mid-1950s. As far as I have been able to detect the

    first one to use it in writing was Dwight Waldo in his 1956 book "Political Science in the

    United States" (Waldo 1956: 24) which was an introductory text written mainly for foreign

    audiences under UNESCO auspices. The term may have been used earlier, especially at the

    University of Chicago (Somit and Tanenhaus 1982: 183), but it became into general use only

    after 1956 (e.g. Hacker 1959). Furthermore, the concept seems to have received a wider

    popularity only after the publication of "The Limits of Behavioralism in Political Science"

    (Charlesworth, ed. 1962). The first time the concept appeared in the pages of the American

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    4/15

    Political Science Review was in 1963 (Mendelson 1963: 593). Mendelson's article "The Neo-

    behavioral Approach to the Judicial Process: A Critique" was, as its name indicates, a critique

    of behavioralism. In the next issue of the Review the concept appeared again in Albert Somit's

    and Joseph Tanenhaus's survey of the trends in American political science, now in the form of

    a neutral research field (Somit and Tanenhaus 1963).

    In the beginning of the 1950s the concept of behavioralism was not used. Instead, the concept

    of political behavior was very common from the beginning of the 1940s having spread since

    Charles E. Merriam's call for its study in the 1920s. The next step, accordingly, was to

    identify those studying political behavior, behavioralists. This happened at the beginning of

    the 1950s (e.g. Easton 1953: 151), although, instead of behavioralists, many used the term

    'behaviorist'. It was above all David Easton, who stressed the importance of distinguishing

    behavioralists from behaviorists (Easton 1953: 151).

    The conceptual development seems to coincide with Albert Somit's and Joseph Tanenhaus's

    periodization of the history of emerging behavioralism (Somit and Tanenhaus 1982: 185): 1)

    from the end of the Second World War to 1949 there were only scattered signs of what wascoming, political behavior as a new research area began to be propagated, 2) from 1950 to the

    mid-1950s was the emerging period, and, 3) from the mid-1950s to the mid-1960s

    behavioralism began to claim hegemony within the discipline, at the same time when its

    opponents launched a determined counter-attack.

    This seems to indicate that behavioralism was used first either in a neutral introductory

    meaning (Waldo; Somit and Tanenhaus) or in a critical fashion (Mendelson). David Easton

    has also pointed out that:

    "behavioralism was not a clearly defined movement for those who were thought to be

    behavioralists. It was more clearly definable by those who were opposed to it, because they

    were describing it in terms of the things within the newer trends that they found objectionable.

    So some would define behavioralism as an attempt to apply the methods of natural sciences to

    human behavior. Others would define it as an excessive emphasis upon quantification. Others

    as individualistic reductionism. From the inside, the practioners were of different minds as

    what it was that constituted behavioralism...few of us were in agreement." (David Easton in

    Baer et al., eds. 1991: 207)

    It was no wonder that those identifying themselves as behavioralists were more apt to speak

    about the study of political behavior as an approach and used the concepts of revolution,

    mood, movement, persuasion or protest to describe what political behavior research indicated.From the beginning behavioralism was a political, not a scientific concept. However, when

    behavioralists rised to an hegemonic position within American political science at the

    beginning of the 1960s the concept became more general. Behavioralists accepted it (Easton

    1962) and it became even to designate the stage in the history of American political science

    (Easton 1985), while the critics continued to use it in a pejorative sense.

    Because behavioralism cannot be considered as a research tradition, but a political movement

    to advance something, definitions of behavioralism give an idea of what the behavioralists

    wanted. Most introductions to the subject stress methodology and goals of the discipline

    (value free research).

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    5/15

    One of the most "influential" definitions of behavioralism has been David Easton's list of its

    characteristics: 1) search for regularities, even with explanatory and predictive value, 2)

    verification with testable propositions, 3) self-conscious examination for rigorous techniques,

    4) quantification for precision when possible and relevant, 5) keeping values and empirical

    explanations analytically distinct, 6) systematization as an intertwining of theory and research,

    7) pure science preceding the application of knowledge, and 8) integration of the socialsciences (Easton 1962: 7-8; Easton 1965: 7).

    Other commentators have agreed. Somit and Tanenhaus present actually the same eight tenets

    of behavioralism (Somit and Tanenhaus 1982: 177-179) and many critics of behavioralism

    have also focused on methodology as a key element of behavioralism (e.g., Seidelman and

    Harpham 1985: 151-152.)

    But behavioralism has been understood also as dealing with something more than only

    methodology and goals of the discipline. James Farr has recently analysed behavioralism

    through three key problem areas: 1) a research focus on political behavior, 2) a

    methodological plea for science, and 3) a political message about liberal pluralism (Farr1995). Although a focus on political behavior is self-evident in behavioralism, it has been

    somehow forgotten by those who are more interested in techniques than in actual problems.

    Maybe one reason has also been that behavioralists have been eager to demonstrate that the

    behavioral study of politics can be applied to all kinds of research areas (Eulau 1962).

    Political message about liberal pluralism refers to a new theory of democracy that was

    developed by American political scientists after the Second World War. Especially radical

    critics of behavioralism have taken a pluralist theory of American politics as their target,

    claiming that it has accepted the social and political system uncritically (e.g., McCoy and

    Playford, eds. 1967). Locigally behavioralism and pluralism are two distinct phenomena, but,

    if behavioralism is a political concept or, if it would like to present itself as a research

    tradition, pluralism could be understood as a tenet of behavioralism.

    4. Explanations for the Rise of behavioralism

    In order to understand behavioralism better as an internally heterogenous movement, it is

    necessary to focus on different explanations about its birth. The nature of behavioralism has

    been a topic of many articles, but systematic research on its development has been rare. There

    are general explanatory descriptive studies (Somit and Tannehaus 1982; Waldo 1975; Ricci

    1984), historical interpretations of the period through some key scholars (Crick 1959;

    Seidelman and Harpham 1985), genealogical studies of the birth of research fields (Gunnell1993) and countless articles (Dahl 1961; Ball 1993; Farr 1995).

    Although many of these studies are very systematic and thorough in their own ways, they

    give, however, only a partial picture of the problem. No full scale attempt to outline factors

    behind the behavioral movement exists. Using the intellectual matrix of political science,

    given explanations thus far may be presented as follows:

    Society

    Social development. Deep social crises have made political scientists more keen to realism.

    Students of the history of the discipline have mainly referred to three "big things": The Great

    Depression of the 1930s and the New Deal (Ball 1993), the World War II (Dahl 1961: Waldo

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    6/15

    1975; Ball 1993; Farr 1995) and the Cold War (Ball 1993; Farr 1995). The socializing effect

    seems to have been most important in connection with the Great Depression, while it was

    Second World War that really forged a new relation between academia and politics. The Cold

    War marked the whole era of behavioralism and in that way its general effect on

    behavioralism was maybe more important than anything else. All three crisis led to a deep

    dissatisfaction with the "state of the discipline" (Somit and Tannehaus 1982: 184) and tobehavioralism as an answer.

    Organizations. One of the most given explanations for the rise of behavioralism has been a

    reference to the role of foundations (2), mainly the emergence of the Ford Foundation as an

    important provider of funds (Dahl 1961; Somit and Tanenhaus 1982; Seidelman and Harpham

    1985: 154). Many have even argued that the whole concept of behavioralism came into use

    only because of the policy of foundations (Geiger 1988: 329). And Bernard Berelson seems to

    agree:

    "What happened to give rise to the term? The key event was the development of a Ford

    Foundation program in this field. The program was initially designated 'individual behaviorand human relations' but it soon became known as the behavioral sciences program and,

    indeed, was officially called that within the foundation. It was the foundation's administrative

    action, then, that led directly to the term and to the concept of this particular field of study."

    (Berelson 1968: 42) (3)

    The foundation money created also a self-generating process which led to the recruitment of

    behavioralists. Because behavioralist projects were funded better than traditional ones, there

    were a larger supply of behavioralists up for recruitment than others (Hacker 1959: 39-40). It

    is no wonder that some of the key practioners of behavioralism have been willing to admit,

    that "it was almost single-handedly the Ford Foundation that did so much to legitimate

    empirical social science" (Warren E. Miller in Baer, et al., eds. 1991: 242).

    And David Easton has argued that "in its orgins it may well be that the concept can be

    considered an accident" (Easton 1965: 12). Easton explains this accident with the

    convergence of the founding of the Behavioral Sciences Division of the Ford Foundation and

    the story of some congressmen attacking social sciences as socialist sciences (Easton 1965:

    22; cf. Ball 1993).

    Foundations played a key role in financing research at the beginning of the 1950s, but the

    Ford Foundation terminated its behavioral program in 1957. One of the reasons was the attack

    towards foundations. There had already been the House of Representatives Select Committee(Cox Committee) investigating tax-exempt foundations in 1952, and the foundations were

    increasingly criticized as being too liberal (actually it was in the hearings of Cox Committee

    when social sciences were termed as socialist sciences).

    After the foundations began to diminish their financing of the behavioral sciences, the

    National Science Foundation stepped in. The original bill for the establishment of a National

    Science Foundation, which was given to the Congress in 1945, contained the establishment of

    a Social Science Division. Social Sciences came under attack from politicians, however,

    already then, because some congressmen saw them representing values foreign to

    Anmericans. Social scientists counterattacked with rhetorics stressing the values of science,

    neutral pursuance of truth, and distancing themselves from social reform. All the values that

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    7/15

    had helped to win the Second World War (Ball 1993). But to no avail. The National Science

    Foundation was established in 1950 without the Division of Social Sciences.

    The Foundation began to search for opportunies to finance the social sciences, however,

    already in 1953. In 1958 it founded the Office of Social Sciences, which was changed into the

    Division alredy a year later (Lyons 1969: 272). Social sciences were accepted by politicians atlast.

    As these examples show, political science was deeply dependent on the state of democracy in

    society. A general political climate had an impact also on individual scholars and universities

    as organizations.

    Political Science

    Scientific Culture. Scientific culture is tied to many ways to the general social, economic and

    political culture and development of a given country. Bernard Crick's thesis that American

    political science is based on a four-fold relationship between a common notion of science, theidea of a citizenhip training, the habits of democracy and a common belief in an inevitable

    progress (Crick 1959: xv) still merits attention.

    On the other hand, comparing the American and British political science, Andrew Hacker

    pointed out in the 1950s, how behavioralism was more natural for an American political

    scientist than for his/her British counterpart. British political scientists were at that time

    mainly library researchers. They could ignore the public, because they were judged by what

    they were rather than by what they did. On the contrary, in the United States there has always

    been a cultural requirement that the professor must "do" something. Although this is bound to

    lead to "productive scholarship" or as Benjamin Lippincott once remarked, to work which

    reminds "the compilation of a telephone directory" (Lippincott 1993: 157), the seeds for

    behavioral study of politics can be found in American culture.

    Organizations and Resources. Different universities played a different role in the rise of

    behavioralism. Usually one refers to the University of Chicago. The 'Chicago School of

    Political Science' led by Charles E. Merriam has been seen by many as a founder of the

    behavioralist movement in political science (Dahl 1961). Another kind of impact of the

    University of Chicago came after the World War II, when scholars from various disciplines

    joined together to develop an interdisciplinary behavioral science.

    Other forms of behavioral study of politics were developing elsewhere at the same time. TheUniversity of Michigan became a center for survey research. An important factor was the

    foundation the Survey Research Center in 1946, which became the Institute for Social

    Research in 1948 (Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 153). Later an event of utmost importance

    was the foundation of the Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research in

    1962 Michigan as its homebase. It is important to notice, however, that the development was

    very uneven in different places and the spreading of behavioralism as dominant ideology of

    research was a long political process.

    Other organizations than universities played a major role in this process. A special importance

    has been given to the Social Science Research Council and its Committee on Political

    Behavior (Dahl 1961; Farr 1995). The Committee was founded in 1949 V.O. Key as its firstchairman. The President of the Social Science Research Council at that time, Pendleton

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    8/15

    Herring, has simply stated later that there was a spectrum of changing attitudes about the role

    of political science and the group "had an opportunity to articulate ideas that were developing,

    and it had the means to encourage and reward people who chose to work along lines that the

    committee was concerned with" (Pendleton Herring in Baer et al., eds. 1991: 34).

    The American Political Science Association as a peak organization of the discipline did alsoplay an important role. Its impact was strengthened by the growth of the profession. In 1946

    APSA had a membership of 4 000 which had risen to 14 000 in 1966 (Seidelman and

    Harpham 1985: 154). This growth in itself transformed a learned society to a professional

    organization. The result was that political scientists were now able to concentrate more easily

    on their own problems leaving social problems outside the profession (Seidelman and

    Harpham 1985: 151; 185). A good example is the attendance at the annual meetings of APSA.

    In the 1920s the registrants ranged between 127 and 292 and it was only in 1939 when there

    were over 1000 participants.

    Academic freedom. McCarthyism had a severe effect on the moulding of behavioralism

    (Easton 1985: 139-140; Farr 1995: 211). Some political scientists referred to this already inthe 1950s, claiming that behavioralism provided a convenient escape from pressure from

    public appraisal and, because a behavioralist was "a liberal in his politics, but timid in his

    personality" he was ready to plunge into the behavioral stream, because he "who has not stuck

    his neck out cannot be attacked. And if he does question dominant values, he frequently does

    it in technical jargon and to a limited audience" (Hacker 1959: 40).

    These personal statements of scholars experiencing the everyday politics of the 1950s may

    also be corroborated by referring to studies on the impact of McCarthyism on academia. Paul

    F. Lazarsfeld's and Wagner Thielens, Jr.'s book "The Academic Mind: Social Scientists in a

    Time of Crisis" (1958) was a survey of over 2000 social scientists. Its results showed that

    "McCarthyism" really had an impact on academia. Many felt themselves under pressure (see

    also Diamond 1992).

    Individuals. The role of individuals is more complicated. Behavioralists have presented their

    own pedigree, which usually starts with Graham Wallas and Arthur F. Bentley, takes notice of

    Charles A. Beard and Walter Lippman, and then comes to Charles E. Merriam and the

    Chicago School of Political Science.

    However, there have also been conflicting arguments. The first one concerns the role of

    Charles E. Merriam and his younger colleagues Harold D. Lasswell and Harold F. Gosnell.

    For instance, Raymond Seidelman and Edward Harpham (1985) don't count Merriam andLasswell as behavioralists, but as representatives of reform political science which was

    criticized by behavioralists at the beginning of the behavioral era.

    Another case with conflicting interpretations concerns the role of the migr scholars during

    the Second World War. Dahl (1961) and Somit and Tanenhaus (1982) have claimed that they

    provided the theoretical background for behavioralism, while John G. Gunnell (1993) has

    recently argued for a much more complex relationship between the migr scholars and

    American political science. Many of those who escaped from Europe became leading critics

    of empirical science of politics.

    Other Disciplines

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    9/15

    The success of behavioralism would hardly have been possible without the development of

    survey methods, interviewing techniques and techniques of measurement (Truman 1955: 204-

    209; Dahl 1961; Somit and Tanenhaus 1982; Seidelman and Harpham 1985: 152). On the

    other hand, many American universities were organized so that political scientists had an easy

    access to representatives of other disciplines, sociologists, social psychologists, etc.

    Compared to situation in other countries these other social sciences were well organised andintellectually developed. It was no wonder that interdisciplinary work took root in American

    universities, at least to some degree (Hacker 1959).

    5. Explaining the Nature and Rise of Behavioralism

    After the brief survey of the meaning of behavioralism and of major explanations for its birth,

    the concept still seems elusive. It is also hard to determine the exact weight of different

    explanations. It seems reasonable to agree with David Easton, however, that the concept of

    behavioral sciences was due both to the policy of the Ford Foundation (3) and to the

    conservative climate suspicious of anything reminding of socialism. On the other hand, itmust be remembered that the concept of behavioralism was first used either in neutral or

    critical way, and it was only later that also behavioralists adopted it.

    Political climate shaped also the discourse on goals of the discipline. The debate on values

    became important when political scientists had to defend themselves (being liberal but

    neutral) against the threat both from the Right and from the Left (Gunnell 1993).

    But many of the tenets of behavioralism would have developed as well under some other label

    than behavioralism. The thirties and the New Deal, the Second World War and the Cold War

    had created the soscial context of American political science, behavioralist or not. And if we

    look at research areas, theories, organizing concepts and methodology of political science, allthese basic components of any research tradition, were already pointing towards what came to

    be called behavioralism.

    A focus on an individual as a basic unit of analysis as well as an interest in empirical study of

    observable facts are both goals deeply grounded in American culture. The growing

    individualism of American society has nurtured methodological individualism and research

    areas dealing with the political behavior.

    The scientific study of politics is also a part of American culture. Important forerunners of

    behavioralism were the national conferences on the science of politics already in the 1920s. It

    was only that the development of statistical techniques gave new ammunition to this endeavor(4).

    And, as was pointed out earlier, behavioralism really was only a loose collection of different

    research traditions which converged in a number of points in order to advance their own

    special interests (5). As Evron M. Kirkpatrick wrote: "the term served as a sort of umbrella,

    capacious enough to provide a temporary shelter for heterogenous group united only by

    dissatisfaction with traditional political science" (Kirkpatrick 1962: 13). It has even been

    claimed that it was often difficult to distinguish true card-carriers in the behavioral movement

    from fellow-travelers, tolerant sympathizers, occasional supporters, or ambivalent critics

    (Easton 1962: 5). And recently Heinz Eulau has argued that:

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    10/15

    "It seems to me that the practioners are less inclined than the bystanders to see this

    (behavioralism, E.B.) as a great divide in the discipline's history and tend to be more sensitive

    to the coexistence of novelties and continuities....I felt at the time, the historical, legal, or

    doctrinal approaches to the study of politics 'will persist....I have never believed that

    behavioralism occupied the hegemonic position attributed to it by some of its own advocates

    and by latter-day interpreters. The undue emphasis on behavioralism as 'revolution' has led toa biased neglect of theory and research that was not behavioral, though done in the 'behavioral

    era.'" (Eulau 1997: 585)

    It cannot be denied that in the 1950s and at the beginning of the 1960s the majority of

    American political scientists were doing something else than behavioral political science.

    International relations, American politics and government, comparative government, public

    administration and public law were all strong fields, and most of the scholars in those fields

    were not behavioralists.

    A good example is the Department of Political Science at the University of California

    (Berkeley), whose chairman from 1948 to 1956 was Peter Odegard. Odegard was a memberof the Ford Foundation Study Committee from 1948 to 1950, but Odegard's own department

    was very strong in comparative politics and even in political theory (Watson 1961: 315-343).

    Although it is good to remember that most of the money from Ford Foundation went actually

    to international relations and comparative politics.

    How can all this be accounted for? The obvious paradox may be explained by the fact that

    most political scientists in the 1950s and the early 1960s occupied a position somewhere in

    the middle between behavioralism and traditionalism, but they were intuitively drawn more

    towards behavioralism.

    Albert Somit's and Joseph Tanenhaus's survey of the profession at the beginning of the 1960s

    shows this well. Using factor analysis to study the attitudes among political scientists, the

    single most important factor dividing the discipline was "behavioralism". However, only 10

    percent of respondents identified themselves as behavioralists, although 22.6 percent felt that

    the most significant work within the discpline was being done by behavioralists. The other

    side of the coin was that there were 12.3 percent identifying themselves as political theorists,

    but only 9.9 percent felt political theory being a field of the most significant work.

    Furthermore, when asked which was the field of the least significant work, 7.8 percent said it

    was behavioral political science, but 32.4 percent thought that political theory had least

    significance in the discipline (Somit and Tanenhaus 1963: 939-942).

    The American political Science Review published also in 1956 a report on a Conference on

    Political Theory and the Study of Politics (Eckstein 1956), which indicated that there were a

    group of 'behaviorists' and 'anti-behaviorists' in the discipline, but a large majority were

    moderates between these two extreme groups. Much of the discussion in the conference dealt

    with a question of "how and why had the political 'philosophers' and the political 'scientists'

    managed to drift so far apart in their work when most of them were eager to concede that they

    had much to learn from one another?" and in the final analysis "our villain...was simply the

    'behaviorist' - 'theorist' dichotomy" (Eckstein 1956: 486-487).

    Of course, there were real differences of opinion concerning methods of political science

    (explanation vs. understanding), its social role (training vs. cultivating) and its ultimate goal(scientific discipline vs. learned wisdom), but the underlying problem in many cases seemed

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    11/15

    to be psychological and practical. People were interested in different problems and there was

    no real interest in the study of politics in totality. The problem was a political rather than an

    intellectual problem: "how to persuade the practioners in the field to develop a healthy interest

    and to acquire a healthy preparation in both political science and political philosophy." The

    'behaviorists' were too current-events-conscious and the 'theorists' were not genuinely

    interested in political behavior. It seemed to be difficult to reach a compromise "between thestudy of Plato and the study of local government in Illinois" (Eckstein 1956: 485).

    Anyone familiar with political scientists knows that this is a real problem. Partly it is an

    ontological and epistemological problem. There are political scientists who are convinced that

    there exists "immortal" questions of politics, such as, freedom, equality and welfare, which

    can be studied out of historical context. And there are political scientists who are more

    interested in the immediate practical issues of politics which they confront in the everyday

    life.

    But one must distinguish the elite and the mass. The mass of American political scientists

    were doing what they had done before. It is no wonder that Charles E. Lindblom has recentlynoted that in the 1950s there was an amazing discrepancy between accepted scientific ideals

    and actual practice (Lindblom 1997: 233). The elite was defining the discourse. But the elite

    was not unanimous. Behavioralism consisted of at least two (still internally divided) research

    traditions: empirical theory and general theory. Empirical theory could be divided into those

    focusing on individuals proper (voting, public opinion) and those adhering to group approach.

    Those adhering to general theory, on the other hand, could be divided into various forms of

    systems theory - general systems theory, cybernetics, systems analysis, functionalism.

    This internal division in the ranks of behavioralism has not always been understood by all

    those writing about it (see, however, Farr and Seidelman, eds. 1993: 203). The division can be

    personalized using David Truman and David Easton as examples. Easton spoke mainly for the

    general theorists who found the established political science wanting. David Truman, on the

    other hand, spoke for those more empirically oriented researchers who had been influenced by

    Charles E. Merriam (Eulau 1969: 5). At the end, it was Truman's side who took command of

    the behavioral research.

    This was due to two things. First, Truman was a representative of a true elite within the

    discipline during behavioral era. For a number of reasons this elite was able to rise in the

    ranks of the profession in the 1950s and especially at the beginning of the 1960s (Waldo

    1975: 61). Through their strategic positions, this key group of behavioralists was able to raise

    behavioralism into a legitimate and hegemonic position within the discipline at the beginningof the 1960s.

    Who should be counted as a member of this core group (elite), is a question which should be

    studied more carefully, but I would suggest that at least the following persons should be

    included: Pendleton Herring, Peter Odegard, V.O.Key, Jr., David Truman, Angus Cambell,

    Oliver Garceau, Alexander Heard, Avery Leiserson and Samuel J. Eldersveld. Many of them

    were members of the Committee on Political Behavior, while Herring and Odegard acted as

    key links to foundations. Herring was an executive associate of the Carnegie Corporation

    from 1846 to 1948 and Odegard was a member of the Ford Foundation Study Committee

    (1948-1950), which planned the Foundation's new activity for the social sciences. Both served

    also as President of the American Political Science Association (Odegard 1950-51, Herring1952-53). Herring was also President of the Social Science Research Council over twenty

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    12/15

    years (beginning in 1948). In many respects, however, the key person was V.O. Key, the first

    chairman of Social Science Research Council's Committee on Political Behavior. His good

    friends David B. Truman, Alexander Heard and Oliver Garceau still strengthened his position.

    It is good to point out two things. Most of these people were what is called empirical theorists

    and secondly, many of them had studied pressure groups (or parties). Another interestingthing is that those who wrote the most influencial writings about behavioralism (Robert A.

    Dahl, David Easton and Heinz Eulau) were somehow outside the core group (although Dahl

    was a close friend of Key). Maybe they were too much general theorists to fit in:

    "those who were particularly interested in quantification and the use of survey research were

    very critical of the work I was doing, which was very theoretical. They saw me as a person

    who was articulating a defense for them, but not as a practioner. And, although they accepted

    the importance of empirical theory, for them theory meant a much lower level of

    generalization than I was seeking. So those who criticized me as a behavioralist incarnate

    were driving me into the arms of the behavioralists, yet the behavioralists didn't have their

    arms wide open." (David Easton, in Baer et al., eds. 1991: 207)

    The division seems to have been also a question of different generations. Some of the oral

    histories of American political scientists (Baer, et. al., eds. 1991) point to this. Those born

    during the first decade of the 20th century were the first real generation of empirical students

    of politics (Charles Hyneman, Pendleton Herring, Belle Zeller, etc.). A generation born in the

    1910s became, however, more theoretically oriented (e.g., Gabriel Almond, Robert A. Dahl

    and David Easton). A common experience for them was the depression of the 1930s. The

    generation born in the 1920s was again more empirical (and conservative) than the previous

    generation (e.g., Austin Ranney and Warren E. Miller).

    But the second fact has to be taken into account, too. The reason Truman's side became the

    core of behavioralism was due to the attitudes and opinions of the mass. And with the growth

    of the discipline the mass has become important organizationally (Ricci 1984). Positive

    towards behavioralism, but doing very traditional political science, these ordinary political

    scientists felt more close to Key's and Truman's concerete studies on American politics than to

    Easton's theoretical analysis.

    If I would have to make a summary of my argument about the nature of behavioralism and

    about its rise into an hegemonic position within American political science, I would use an

    analogy of American party politics. As American party politics consists of two major parties

    which are loose coalitions of different interests, so American political science has tended tocreate two opposing parties, whether it is traditionalists vs. behavioralists or behavioralists vs.

    postbehavioralists does not matter. These parties have been as undefinable as their

    counterparts in real political life. But they have caught the imagination of American political

    scientists, because American culture is dialectical. They have also formed identities as well as

    they have been vehicles in pursuing material interests. To better understand the nature and

    history of political science, it might be better, however, to forget behavioralism and

    postbehavioralism and look at the development of the discipline through different research

    traditions competing with each other.

    6. The Legacy of Behavioralism

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    13/15

    Terence Ball has recently (1993: 220-221) argued that behavioralism succeeded in the short

    run, because of succesful self-promotion, but in the long run it failed, because promises were

    made that could not be met. But, if the analysis in the previous chapter is correct, it doesn't

    matter whether behavioralism succeeded or not. An interesting thing to look, however, is

    which aspects of behavioralism have survived in the postbehavioral era and which have been

    lost.

    A few years ago Theodore Lowi (1992) claimed that American political science was

    dominated by three subfields of the discipline, public opinion, public choice and public

    policy. Of these only public opinion represented the old behavioral study of politics. If Lowi

    is correct, the first conclusion is that it is the individualistic perspective inherent in

    behavioralism that has been one of the survivors. Although the early behavioralism

    understood the importance of studying governmental structures and understood also

    socialization as an important element in moulding a person's attitudes and behavior, the basic

    methodological starting point was methodological individualism, because it was assumed that

    "collectivities do not exist apart from the conduct of their individual members" and "political

    behavior analysis is pre-eminently interested in determining the consequences of individualpolitical behavior for the functioning of political institutions" (Eulau 1968: 205).

    A focus on individuals has also nurtured quantitative techniques. The early behavioralists

    were alraedy worried about this trend and, for example, V.O.Key used to warn that there is a

    danger that people stop asking good questions when methods are overemphasized (David

    Truman in Baer et al, eds., 1991: 148; cf. also David Easton in Baer et al., eds., 1991: 209).

    Both quantitative and qualitative analysis had their own place in research:

    "the approach cannot be limited to areas where the possibility of quantification is immediate.

    The student of political behavior cannot escape the obligation and must not deny himself the

    opportunity to ask important questions...simply because his answers must be more or less

    qualitative...he is obliged to perform his task in quantitative terms if he can and in qualitative

    terms if he must" (Truman 1951: 39).

    In regard to analyzing data with different nethods, American political science has really went

    into a wrong direction. Partly this may be due to the untheoretical nature of contemporary

    research. This untheoretical nature is tied to the major loss in behavioral legacy, forgetting the

    need for the integration of social knowledge. The idea has curiously disappeared. Here again

    the bureaucracy and special interests have been more powerful. The interdisciplinary idea

    never went through the ranks of ordinary political scientists (Geiger 1988: 332).

    At the beginning of the century there were also attempts to maintain close relations with all

    the social sciences, but already then the drift went away from this goal. As Albert Lepawsky

    has noted the new social science associations entered the twentieth century seeking to

    counteract their separateness. There were requests to a possible federation of associations, but

    "it was too late. The centrifugal forces in this phase of American life were stronger than the

    centripetal" (Lepawsky 1964: 52).

    And this has been the case ever since (the only success being the founding of the Social

    Science Research Council in 1924). This has galvanized also behavioralism. It is logical that

    the integration of the social sciences was not the major issue for the true behavioralist elite:

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    14/15

    "The student of political behavior is concerned with the methods and concepts in other

    disciplines only to the extent that such tools contribute directly to a more meaningful

    statement of the phenomena of politics. The ultimate goal of the student of political behavior

    is the development of a science of the political process, logically complete within itself. Given

    the tremendous range and complexity of political data, such specialization is a continuing

    need...Many of the concerns of the other behavioral sciences are not thus relevant" (Truman1951: 38-39).

    This attitude is completely different than David Easton's argument for the unity of behavioral

    sciences, which was, according to him, the real core of behavioralism. Arguing for the

    behavioral study of politics, Easton wrote that, "if all that behavioralists are arguing for is the

    introduction of scientific method and nothing more, why are we not content with calling a

    spade a spade?" (Easton 1965 :9)

    And Easton goes on to argue that the real meaning of behavioralism is (besides attention to

    empirical theory) "in locating stable units of analysis" (Easton 1965: 13) and "the key idea

    behind this approach has been the conviction that there are certain fundamental units ofanalysis relating to human behavior out of which generalizations can be formed and that these

    generalizations may provide a common sense on which the specialized sciences of man in

    society could be built" (Easton 1965: 14-15).

    Referring to attempts to find the most fruitful unit for a general social theory, Easton (1965:

    15-21) refers to concepts such as action, the decision, functions, systems, power and groups.

    Although noting that in his own work he has "been exploring the utility of the system as the

    major unit, focusing on political life as a system of behavior operating within and responding

    to its social environment as it makes binding allocations of values" (Easton 1965: 21), he still

    leaves a door open for the best unit of analysis. Easton's real concern is a search for unified

    social knowledge.

    Easton has not dropped the idea. In his 1969 APSA presidential address he argued again that

    "social problems do not come neatly packaged as economic, psychological, political and the

    like. Our crises arise out of troubles that involve all aspects of human behavior" (Easton 1969:

    1060). This time Easton proposed also the establishment of a Federation of Social Scientists

    to advance the integration of the social sciences. But no one seemed to notice this aspect of

    the new revolution in political science.

    The same has been the case with Easton's article on "The Political Science in the United

    States" in which Easton wrote:

    "in emphasizing the need to apply whatever knowledge we have to the solution of urgent

    social issues, we have already run into major difficulties in trying to reintegrate the various

    highly specialized disciplines....Application of knowledge to the social problems...requires the

    reassembly of the specialized knowledge of the various social sciences". (Easton 1985: 151)

    The need for integration of social sciences is a major legacy of behavioralism, but it has been

    forgotten as well by the majority of behavioralists as those criticizing it. The result has been

    the acceptance of the fragmentation of social knowledge as in the case of postmodernism. But

    the integration of social knowledge is as timely as it has always been. And this task doesn't

    require of finding any single concept that could unite the social sciences. It only requires thatpolitical, economic and social aspects of human behavior are theoretically linked together.

  • 8/3/2019 Behavioral Ism

    15/15

    Individualism, quantification and fragmentation are the three major problems of social

    sciences today. Some have even claimed that they are behind our social crisis today (Dimock

    1987; cf. also Bay 1965). To fight these tendencies of modern social science may be futile,

    but to be aware of these tendencies is the first requirement of forming ones's identity as a

    political scientist. To understand our identity we need a pluralist theory of scientific

    development.