art bulletin vol 21 no 4_ornament_coomaraswamy

8
ORNAMENT By ANANDA K. COOMARASWAMY A S remarked by Clement of Alexandria, the scriptural style is parabolic, but it is not for the sake of elegance of diction that prophecy makes use of figures of jspeech. On the other hand, "The sensible forms [of artifacts], in which there was at first a polar balance of physical and metaphysical, have been more and more voided of content on their way down to us: so we say, 'This is an ornament' . . . an 'art form' ... [Is the symbol] therefore dead, because its living meaning had been lost, because it was denied that it was the image of a spiritual truth? I think not" (Andrae, Die ionische Sdiule, Bauform oder Symbol, 1933, Schlusswort). And as I have so often said myself, a divorce of utility and meaning, concepts which are united in the one Sanskrit word artha, would have been inconceivable to early man or in any traditional culture. In the present article we are not concerned with beauty, which is traditionally propor- tionate to the perfection of the artifact itself, and is the attractive power of this perfection, and being thus objective is dependent upon truth and not upon opinion: our concern is rather with the aesthetic view of art, and the decorative values of art, which depend on taste and liking rather than on judgment. We should distinguish accordingly between the beautiful on the one hand and the lovely, i.e., loveable or likeable, on the other,' bearing in mind that "the beautiful is not just what we like, for there are some who like deformities" (St. Augustine, De Musica, VI, 38). What we have in view is to support by the analysis of certain familiar terms and categories the proposition that our modern preoccupation with the "decorative" and "aesthetic" aspects of art represents an aberration that has little or nothing to do with the original purposes of art; to demonstrate from the side of semantics the position that has been stated by Maes with special reference to Negro art that "Vouloir separer l'objet de sa signification sociale, son r8le ethnique, pour n'y voir, n'y admirer et n'y chercher que le c6t6 esthetique, c'est enlever a ces souvenirs de l'art negre leur sens, leur significance et leur raison-d'etre! Ne cherchons point a effacer l'id6e que l'indigene a incrust6e dans l'ensemble comme dans chacun des details d'execution de l'objet sans significance, raison-d'etre, ou vie. Efforgons nous au contraire de comprendre la psychologie de l'art negre et nous finirons par en p6n6trer toute la beaut6 et toute la vie" (IPEK, 1926, p. 283), and that, as remarked by Karsten, "the ornaments of savage peoples can only be properly studied in connection with a study of their agical and religious beliefs" (ib., p. 164); emphasizing, however, that the application of these considerations is not merely to negro, "savage," and folk art but to all traditional arts, those for example of the Middle Ages and of India.2 I. Cf. the distinction of the "honest" from the "pleas- ant," the one desired for its own sake by the rational appetite and an intelligible good, the other desired for its own sake by the sensible appetite and a sensible good: that which is honest (admirable) is naturally pleasing, but not all that is pleasing is honest (St. Thomas Aquinas, Sum. Theol., II-II, 145, 3, cf. I-II, 30, I); and that of freyas from preyas, the glorious or beautiful from the merely delectable, in Katha Up., II, 2. 2. As remarked by Th. W. Danzel, in a primitive culture -by "primitive" the anthropologist often means no more than "not quite up to (our) date"-"sind auch die Kultur- gebiete Kunst, Religion, Wirthschaft usw. noch nicht als selbstandige, gesonderte, geschlossene Betitungsbereiche vorhanden" (Kultur und Religion des primitiven 1924, P. This is, incidentally a devastating criticism of such societies as are not "primitive" and in which the various functions of life and branches of knowledge are treated as specialities, "gesondert und geschlossen" from any unifying principle.

Upload: kosti7

Post on 02-Apr-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

7/27/2019 Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/art-bulletin-vol-21-no-4ornamentcoomaraswamy 1/8

ORNAMENT

By ANANDA K. COOMARASWAMY

A S remarked by Clement of Alexandria, the scriptural style is parabolic, but it

is not for the sake of elegance of diction that prophecy makes use of figures of

jspeech. On the other hand, "The sensible forms [of artifacts], in which there

was at first a polar balance of physical and metaphysical, have been more and

more voided of content on their way down to us: so we say, 'This is an ornament' . . . an

'art form' ... [Is the symbol] therefore dead, because its living meaning had been lost,

because it was denied that it was the image of a spiritual truth? I think not" (Andrae,

Die ionische Sdiule,Bauform oder Symbol, 1933, Schlusswort). And as I have so often said

myself, a divorce of utility and meaning, concepts which are united in the one Sanskrit

word artha, would have been inconceivable to early man or in any traditional culture.

In the present article we are not concerned with beauty, which is traditionally propor-tionate to the perfection of the artifact itself, and is the attractive power of this perfection,and being thus objective is dependent upon truth and not upon opinion: our concern is

rather with the aesthetic view of art, and the decorative values of art, which depend on

taste and liking rather than on judgment. We should distinguish accordingly between the

beautiful on the one hand and the lovely, i.e., loveable or likeable, on the other,' bearingin mind that "the beautiful is not just what we like, for there are somewho like deformities"

(St. Augustine, De Musica, VI, 38). What we have in view is to support by the analysis of

certain familiar terms and categories the proposition that our modern preoccupation with

the "decorative" and "aesthetic"aspects

of art represents an aberration that has little or

nothing to do with the original purposes of art; to demonstrate from the side of semantics

the position that has been stated by Maes with special reference to Negro art that "Vouloir

separer l'objet de sa signification sociale, son r8le ethnique, pour n'y voir, n'y admirer et

n'y chercher que le c6t6 esthetique, c'est enlever a ces souvenirs de l'art negre leur sens,leur significance et leur raison-d'etre! Ne cherchons point a effacer l'id6e que l'indigenea incrust6e dans l'ensemble comme dans chacun des details d'execution de l'objet sans

significance, raison-d'etre, ou vie. Efforgonsnous au contraire de comprendre la psychologiede l'art negre et nous finirons par en p6n6trer toute la beaut6 et toute la vie" (IPEK,

1926, p. 283), and that, as remarked by Karsten, "the ornaments of savage peoples can onlybe properly studied in connection with a study of their magical and religious beliefs" (ib.,

p. 164); emphasizing, however,that the

applicationof these considerations is not

merelyto negro, "savage," and folk art but to all traditional arts, those for example of the Middle

Ages and of India.2

I. Cf. the distinction of the "honest" from the "pleas-ant," the one desired for its own sake by the rational

appetite and an intelligible good, the other desired for itsown sake by the sensible appetite and a sensible good: thatwhich is honest (admirable) is naturally pleasing, but not

all that is pleasing is honest (St. Thomas Aquinas, Sum.

Theol., II-II, 145, 3, cf. I-II, 30, I); and that of freyas from

preyas, the glorious or beautiful from the merely delectable,in Katha Up., II, 2.

2. As remarked by Th. W. Danzel, in a primitive culture

-by "primitive" the anthropologist often means no morethan "not quite up to (our) date"-"sind auch die Kultur-

gebiete Kunst, Religion, Wirthschaft usw. noch nicht als

selbstandige, gesonderte, geschlossene Betitungsbereichevorhanden" (Kultur und Religion des primitiven Menschen,1924, P. 7). This is, incidentally a devastating criticism ofsuch societies as are not "primitive" and in which thevarious functions of life and branches of knowledge aretreated as specialities, "gesondert und geschlossen" from

any unifying principle.

Page 2: Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

7/27/2019 Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/art-bulletin-vol-21-no-4ornamentcoomaraswamy 2/8

376 THE ART BULLETIN

Let us consider now the history of various words that have been used to express the

notion of an ornamentation or decoration and which in modern usage for the most part

import an aesthetic value added to things of which the said "decoration" is not an essential

or necessary part. It will be found that most of these words which imply for us the notion

of something adventitious and luxurious, added to utilities but not essential to their ef-ficacy, originally implied a completion or fulfilment of the artifact or other object in ques-

tion; that to "decorate" an object or person originally meant to endow the object or personwith its or his "necessary accidents," with a view to "proper" operation; and that the

aesthetic senses of the words are secondary to their practical connotation; whatever was

originally necessary to the completion of anything, and thus proper to it, naturally giving

pleasure to the user; until still later what had once been essential to the nature of the

object came to be regarded as an "ornament" that could be added to it or omitted at will;

until, in other words, the art by which the thing itself had been made whole began to mean

only a sort of millinery or upholstery that covered over a body that had not been made

by "art" but rather by "labor"-a point of view bound up with our peculiar distinction of

a fine or useless from an applied or useful art, and of the artist from the workman, and withour substitution of ceremonies for rites.

A related example of a degeneration of meaning can be cited in our words "artifice,"

meaning "trick," but originally artificium, "thing made by art," "work of art," and our

"artificial," meaning "false," but originally artificialis, "of or for work."

The Sanskrit word alatkadra3s usually rendered by "ornament," with reference either

to the rhetorical use of "ornaments" (figures of speech, assonances, kennings, etc.), or to

jewelry or trappings. The Indian category ofalatkarra-~astra,

the "Science of Poetic

Ornament," corresponds, however, to the medieval category of Rhetoric or Art of Oratory,

in which eloquence is thought of not as an end in itself or art for art's sake, or to display the

artist's skill, but as the art of effective communication. There exists, indeed, a mass of

medieval Indian poetry that is "sophistic" in Augustine's sense ("A speech seeking verbalornament beyond the bounds of responsibility to its burden (gravitas) is called 'sophistic',"

De doc. christ., II, 31). At a time when "poetry" (kavya)4had to some extent become an

end in itself, a discussion arose as to whether or not "ornaments" (alatkara) represent the

essence of poetry; the consensus being that, so far from this, poetry is distinguishable from

prose (i.e., the poetic from the prosaic, not verse from prose) by its "sapidity" or "flavor"

(rasa, vyafjana, corresponding to the sap- in Lat. sapientia, wisdom, "scientia cumsapore").

Sound and meaning are thought of as indissolubly wedded; just as in all the other arts of

whatever kind there was originally a radical and natural connection between form and sig-

nificance, without divorce of function and meaning.

If we analyse now the word alatikara and consider the many other than merely aesthetic

senses in which the verb alat-kr is employed, we shall find that the word is composed of

alam, "sufficient," or "enough," and kr to "make." It must be mentioned for the sake of

what follows that Sanskrit I and r are often interchangeable, and that alam is represented

3. The present article was suggested by, and makes con-

siderable use of, J. Gonda, The meaningof the word"alarh-kara"in the Volume of Eastern and Indian studiespresentedto F. W. Thomas, Bombay, 1939, PP. 97-114; the same

author's The meaning of Vedicbhifsati,Wageningen, 1939;

and "Abharana"in the New Indian Antiquary, May, 1939.

4. Derivative of kavi, "poet." The reference of these

words to "poetry" and "poet" in the modern sense is late:

in Vedic contexts, kavi is primarily an epithet of the highest

Gods with reference to their utterance of words of creative

power, kavya and kavitva the corresponding quality of wis-

dom-Vedic kavi being therefore rather an "enchanter"

than a "charmer" in the later sense of one who merely

pleases us by his sweet words.In much the same way Greek 2rotios originally meant a

"making," so that as Plato says "The productions of all

arts are kinds of poetry and their craftsmen are all poets"

(Symposium, 205, C).

Page 3: Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

7/27/2019 Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/art-bulletin-vol-21-no-4ornamentcoomaraswamy 3/8

ORNAMENT 377

by aram in the older literature. Analogous to the transitive arath-krare the intransitive

arambha, to become able, fit for and ara*t-gam,to serve or suffice for. The root of aram

may be the same as that of Greek apapto, to fit together, equip or furnish. Aram with

kror bha occurs in Vedic texts in phrases meaning preparedness, ability, suitability, fitness,

hence also that of "satisfying" (a word that renders ala t-kr very literally, satis corre-sponding to aram and facere to kr), as in RV, VII, 29, 3 "What satisfaction (aradtkrti)is

there for thee, Indra, by means of our hymns?" A/la*-kr in the Atharva Veda (XVIII, 2)

and in the Satapatha Brahmaitais employed with reference to the due ordering of the sacri-

fice, rather than to its adornment, the sacrifice indeed being much less a ceremony than a

rite; but already in the Ramayana, a "poetical" work, the word has usually the meaning to

"adorn."

Without going into further detail, it can easily be seen what was once the meaning of

an "adornment," viz., the furnishing of anything essential to the validity of whatever is

"adorned," or enhances its effect, empowering it.

In just the same way bhaisa.a and

bhas.,

words that mean in Classical Sanskrit "orna-

ment," respectively as noun and as verb, do not have this value in Vedic Sanskrit, where(like alatzkara etc.) they refer to the provision of whatever properties or means increase

the efficacy of the thing or person with reference to which or whom they are employed:5the hymns, for example, with which the deity is said to be "adorned," are an affirmation

of and therefore a confirmation and magnification of the divine power to act on the singers'behalf. Whatever is in this sense "ornamented" is thereby made the more in act, and more

in being. That this should be so corresponds to the root meaning of the verb, which is an

extension of bha, to "become," but with a causative nuance, so that, as pointed out by

Gonda, bhMsatidyan in RV, X, I i, 7 does not mean "ornaments his days," but "lengthenshis life," "makes more his life," cf. Skr. bhiayas, "becoming in a greater degree" (Pdnini),

"abundantly furnished with," and "more." Bhias has thus the value of vrdh, to increase

(trans.), Macdonell rendering the gerundives abhasenya and vavrdhenyaboth alike by "tobe glorified" (Vedic Grammar, 580): an identical connection of ideas survives in Eng-

lish, where to "glorify" is also to "magnify" the Lord, and certain chants are"Magnificats."

Vedic bhas in the sense "increase" or "strengthen," and synonymous with vrdh, corre-

sponds to the later causative bhav(from bha), as can be clearly seen if we compare RV, IX,

Io4, I, where Soma is to be "adorned," or rather "magnified" (pari bhasata) by sacrifices,

"as it were a child" (Sisuu na) with Ait. Ar., II, 5, where the mother "nourishes"

(bhavayati)the unborn child, and the father is said to "support" (bhavayati)it both before

and after birth; bearing also in mind that in RV, IX, 103, I the hymns addressed to Soma

are actually compared to "food" (bhrti) from bhr,to "bear," "bring," "support," and that

in the Ait. Ar. context the mother "nourishes... and bears the child" (bhavayati...

garbhambibharti). And insofar as abharanaand bhaisaa in other contexts are often "jew-

elry" or other decoration of the person or thing referred to, it may be observed that the

values of jewelry were not originally those of "vain adornment" in any culture, but rather

metaphysical or "magical."6 To some extent this can be recognized even at the present

day: if, for example, the judge is only a judge in act when wearing his robes, if the mayor

5. The two values of bhasana are found side by side in

Visnudharmottara,III, 41, 10 where outline, shading (therepresentation of) jewelry (bhsya.sam), and color are col-

lectively "the ornaments (bhasanam) of painting," and it

is clear that these "ornaments" are not a needless elabora-

tion of the art, but much rather the essentials or character-istics of painting, by which it is recognized as such.

6. As in AV, VI, 133, where the girdle is worn "for lengthof life" and invoked to endow the wearer with insight,understanding, fervor, and virility.

Page 4: Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

7/27/2019 Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/art-bulletin-vol-21-no-4ornamentcoomaraswamy 4/8

378 THE ART BULLETIN

is empowered by his chain, and the king by his crown, if the pope is only infallible and

verily pontiff when he speaks ex cathedra,"from the throne," none of these things are mere

ornaments; but much rather an equipment by which the man himself is "mored" (bhfyas-

krta),just as in AV, X, 6, 6 Brhaspati wears a jewel, or let us say a talisman, "in order to

power" (ojase). Even today the conferring of an order is a "decoration" in the same sense:and it is only to the extent that we have learned to think of knighthood, for example, as

an "empty honor" that the "decoration" takes on the purely aesthetic values that we nowa-

days asociate with the word.

The mention of bhr,above, leads us to consider also the word abharanta,n which the

root is combined with a self-referent a, "towards." Abharatta s generally rendered by "or-

nament," but is more literally "assumption" or "attribute." In this sense the characteristic

weapons or other objects held by a deity, or worn, are his proper attributes, abharaeam,

by which his mode of operation is denoted iconographically. In what sense a bracelet of

conch (Saiikha),7worn for long life, etc., is an "abharatam" can be seen in AV, IV, Io,where the "sea-born" shell is "fetched (abhrtab) from the waters." In the same way

dharya,from hr, to "bring," with a as before, means in the first place that which is "to beeaten," i.e., "nourishment," and secondly the costume and jewels of an actor, regardedas one of the four factors of dramatic expression; in the latter sense the sun and moon are

called theaharya

of Siva when he manifests himself on the world stage (Abhinaya Darpanta,

invocatory introduction).

Returning now to alakadra as "rhetorical ornament," Gonda very properly asks, "Have

they always been nothing but embellishments?," pointing out that very many of these so-

called embellishments appear already in the Vedic texts, which, for all that, are not in-

cluded in the category of poetry (kavya), i.e., are not regarded as belonging to "belles

lettres." Ydska, for example, discusses upama, "simile" or "parable" in Vedic contexts,

and we may remark that such similes or parables are repeatedly employed in the Pali

Buddhist canon, which is by no means sympathetic to any kind of artistry that can be

thought of as an ornamentation for the sake of ornamentation. Gonda goes on to point out,

and it is incontrovertibly true, that what we should now call ornaments (when we study"the Bible as literature") are stylistic phenomena in the sense that "the scriptural style is

parabolic" by an inherent necessity, the burden of scripture being one that can be expressed

only by analogies: so this style had another function in the Vedic contexts "than to be noth-

ing but ornaments. Here, as in the literature of several other peoples, we have a sacred or

ritual 'Sondersprache' . . . different from the colloquial speech." At the same time, "These

peculiarities of the sacral language may also have an aesthetic side ... Then they become

figures of speech and when applied in excess they become 'Spielerei'." Alaskrta, in other

words, having meant originally "made adequate," came finally to mean "embellished."

In the case of another Sanskrit word subha, of which the later meaning is "lovely,"

there may be cited the expression subha, silpin from the Ramayava, where the reference is

certainly not to a craftsman personally "handsome," but to a "fine craftsman," and like-

wise the well-known benediction subham astu, "May it be well," where subham is rather

the "good" then the beautiful as such. In RV we have such expressions as "I furnish

(sumbhami) Agni with prayers" (VIII, 24, 26), where for sumbhamimight just as well have

been said alatkaromi (not "I adornhim," but "I fit him out"); and sumbhanto(I, I30, 6),

7. The commentators here, and on RV, I, 35, 4; I, 126,

4; and X, 68, 11 (where krgana=suvarta, golden, or

suvaram Jbharaiam, golden ornament) offer no support

whatever for the rendering of krtana by "pearl-." It is,moreover, amulets of conch, and not of pearl oyster shell

that have been worn in India from time immemorial.

Page 5: Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

7/27/2019 Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/art-bulletin-vol-21-no-4ornamentcoomaraswamy 5/8

ORNAMENT 379

not "adorning"but "harnessing"a horse; in J.V, 129 alamhkatais "fully equipped"(in

coat of mail and turban,and with bow and arrowsand sword). In I, 130, 6, it is Indra

that is "harnessed" ike a steed that is to race and win a prize, and it is obvious that in

such a case the aptituderatherthan the beauty of the gearmust have been the primary

consideration,and that althoughthe charioteermust have enjoyed at the same time the"pleasurethat perfects the operation,"this pleasuremust have been ratherin the thingwell made for its purpose,than in its mere appearance; t wouldbe only under the more-

unrealconditionsof a parade hat the mereappearancemight becomean end in itself, and

it is thus, in fact, that over-ornamentedhings aremadeonly for show. This is a develop-ment that we are very familiarwith in the history of armor(anothersort of "harness"),of which the original ife-savingpurposewas pre-eminentlypractical,howeverelegant the

resultant formsmay have been in fact, but whichin the end servedno otherpurposethan

that of display.To avoidconfusion, t mustbepointedout that whatwehavereferredo as the "utility"

of a harness,or any otherartifact,had neverbeen, traditionally,a matter of merelyfunc-

tional adaptation;8 on the contrary, in every work of traditional art we can recognizeAndrae's "polar balance of physical and metaphysical,"the simultaneous satis-faction

(alati-karata) of practical and spiritualrequirements. So the harness is originallypro-vided (ratherthan "decorated")with solarsymbols, as if to say that the racingsteed is

the Sun(-horse) n alikeness,andthe race tselfanimitationof "whatwasdoneby the Gods

in the beginning."A good exampleof the use of an "ornament"not as "millinery"but forits significance

can be cited in SB. III. 5. 1. I9-20 where,because n the primordial acrifice he Ailgiraseshad acceptedfromthe Adityasthe Sun as their sacrificial ee, so now a white horse is the

fee for the performance f the corresponding adyahkriSoma-sacrifice.This white horse

is made to wear "a gold-ornament ruikma),wherebyit is made to be of the formof, or

symbol (rapam)of the Sun." This ornamentmust have been like the golden disk withtwenty-onepoints or rays which is also wornby the sacrificerhimselfand afterwards aid

downon the altar to represent he Sun (SB. VI. 7. 1.1-2, VII. 1.2. 10, VII. 4. 1.10). It is

familiar that horses are even now sometimes"decorated"with ornamentsof brass(a sub-

stitute forgold, the regular ymbolof Truth, Sun,Light, Immortality,SB.VI. 7. 1.2, etc.)of which, the significance s manifestly solar; it is precisely such forms as these solar

symbols that, when the contexts of life have been secularised,and meaninghas been for-

gotten, surviveas "superstitions"'and are regardedonly as "art forms"or "ornaments,"to be judged as good or bad in accordance,not with their truth, but with our likes or

dislikes. If children have always been apt to play with useful things or miniature copies

of useful things for example carts, as toys, we ought perhaps to regard our own aestheti-

cism as symptomatic of a second childhood; we do not grow up.

8. "Honesty"having been identifiedwith"spiritual orintelligible)beauty," St. ThomasAquinas remarks hat

"Nothing ncompatiblewith honesty can be simplyand

truly useful,since it follows that it is contraryto man'slast end"(Sum.Theol., I-II, 145,3 ad 3). It is the intel-

ligible aspectof the workof art that has to do with man'slast end,its unintelligible spectthat serveshis immediateneeds; the "merelyfunctional"artifactcorrespondingo"bread alone." In other words,an object devoid of all

symbolicornament, rof whichthe form tselfis meaning-less and thereforeunintelligible,s not "simplyand trulyuseful,"butonlyphysically erviceable, s is the trough othepig. Perhapswe mean thiswhenwe thinkof mereutili-

ties as "uninteresting," nd fly for refugeto the fine or

materiallyuselessarts; t is nevertheless he measure f ourunawarenesshat we consent o anenvironmentonsistingchieflyof in-significant rtifacts.

9. "Superstition... a symbol which has continued nuse after ts originalmeaninghas been forgotten... Thebest cure for that, is not misapplied nvection againstidolatry,but an expositionof the meaningof the symbol,so that menmay againuse it intelligently" MarcoPallis,Peaksand Lamas, 1939,P. 379). Ourcontemporaryul-

ture,from the pointof viewof this definition,s preimi-nently "superstitious"nd "unintelligent."

Page 6: Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

7/27/2019 Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/art-bulletin-vol-21-no-4ornamentcoomaraswamy 6/8

380 THE ART BULLETIN

Enoughof Sanskrit. The Greekword K&.LgOSs primarily"order"(Skr. rta), whether

with reference o the dueorderor arrangement f things,or to the world-order"themost

beautifulordergiven to thingsby God,"St. ThomasAquinas,Sum. Theol.,I, 25, 6 ad3)-;

andsecondarily"ornament,"whetherofhorses,women,men,orspeech. The corresponding

verb KO1EW is toorderor arrange,and secondarily o equip,adorn,ordress,or finallywithreference o the embellishmentof oratory. K6awrtas an ornamentor decoration,usuallyof dress.

Koaorr7LK6sis skilled in ordering, OQO1qTEKi'he art of dressand ornament,

KO00r/lTt6v"cosmetic,"10KoaoUr.lTjpLovdressing-room. Koaouoroin71ss architectural

ornament;henceour designationof the Doric etc. "orders." Againwe see the connection

between an original"order"and a later "ornament." In connection with "cosmetic" t

may be remarked hat we cannot understandthe originalintention of bodily ornaments

(unguents, tattooing,jewelry, etc.) from our modernand aesthetic point of view. The

Hindu woman feels herself undressedand disorderlywithout her jewels which, however

muchshemay be fondof them fromotherand"aesthetic"pointsof view, she regardsas a

necessaryequipment,withoutwhich she cannot functionas a woman(fromManu, III, 55

"it appearsthat there existed a connectionbetweenthe properadornmentof womenandtheprosperityof theirmalerelatives,"Gonda,Bhasati,p. 7).11To be seenwithout hergearwould be more than a mere absenceof decoration, t would be inauspicious, ndecorous,and disrespectful,as if one shouldbe presentat some function in "undress,"or have for-

gottenone'stie: it isonly asawidow,andas such"inauspicious,"hat thewomanabandons

her ornaments. In ancient India or Egypt, in the same way, the use of cosmeticswas

assuredlynot a matterof merevanity, but muchratherone of propriety. We can see this

moreeasily, perhaps, n connectionwith hair-dressing Koo~ut6,.Atsndalsoone of the senses

of ornare); he putting of one'shair in order s primarilya matter of decorum,and there-

fore pleasing, not primarilyor merely for the sake of pleasing Kooa-ew."clean" and

Ka4ur7povbroom"recall the semanticsof Chineseshih (9907) primarily o wipe or clean

orbesuitablydressed the ideograms composedof signsfor"man"+ "clothes"),and moregenerallyto be decorated;cf. hsiu (4661),a combinationof shihwith san= "paint-brush,"and meaningto put in order,prepare,regulateand cultivate.

The words"decoration" nd"ornament,"whetherwith reference o the embellishment

of personsor of things,can be considered imultaneouslyn Latin andin English. Ornare

is primarilyto "fit out, furnish,providewith necessaries" Harper)and only secondarilyto "embellish,"etc. Ornamentums primary"apparatus,accoutrement, quipment,trap-

pings"12ndsecondarily mbellishment,ewel, trinket,'3 tc., as well as rhetoricalornament

(Skr. alakara); the word is used by Pliny to render KAbtOs."Ornament" is primarily "any

adjunct or accessory (primarily for use... )" (Webster): so Cooper (sixteenth century)

speaks of the "tackling or ornaments of a ship," and Malory of the "ornementys of an

o0. Cf. Skr. an-j, to anoint, to shine, to be beautiful;

aijana, ointment, cosmetic, embellishment.

i1. Cf. such terms asrakjgbhj2an.a,

"apotropaic amu-

let," Sugruta, I, 54, 13; manigaldlarhkrta, Wearing auspi-cious ornaments," Kalidasa, Malavikdgnimitra, I, 14; and

similarly matngalamdtrabh1astaa,Vikramorvagi, III, 12,cited by Gonda. The bow and the sword which areRMma's

equipment, and in this sense "ornaments" in the originalsense of the word "are not for the sake of mere ornamenta-

tion or only to be worn" (na ...bhisanya...

na...

Jbandhandrthdya,Rdmdyan.a,II, 23, 30).12. "Trappings," from the same root as "drape," and

drapeau,"flag,"was originally a cloth spread over the back

or saddle of a horse or other beast of burden, but has ac-

quiredthe inferiormeaningof superficial r unnecessaryornament.

13. "Trinket," by which we always understand ome

insignificant rnament,was originallya little knife, latercarriedas a mere ornamentandso disparaged. We oftenrefer o a trinketas a "charm," orgetting he connectionsof this word with carmen nd "chant." The "charm" m-

plied originallyan enchantment:our words "charming"and "enchanting" ave acquired heir trivial and purelyaesthetic values by a developmentparallelto that whichhas been discussed hroughouthe presentarticle. It maybe addedthat an "insignificant"rnament s literallyonewithouta meaning; t is preciselyn this sense that orna-ments werenotoriginally nsignificant.

Page 7: Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

7/27/2019 Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/art-bulletin-vol-21-no-4ornamentcoomaraswamy 7/8

ORNAMENT 381

aulter."14 Even now "The term 'ornaments' in Ecclesiastical law is not confined, as by

modern usage, to articles of decoration or embellishment, but it is used in the larger sense

of the word 'ornamentum' " (Privy Council Decision, 1857). Adornment is used by Burke

with reference to the furnishing of the mind. Decor, "what is seemly . . . ornament . . . per-

sonal comeliness" (Harper) is already "ornament" (i.e. embellishment) as well as "adapta-tion" in the Middle Ages. But observe that "decor" as "that which serves to decorate;

ornamental disposition of accessories" (Webster) is the near relative of "decorous" or

"decent," meaning "suitable to a character or time, place and occasion" and to "decorum,"i.e. "what is befitting . . propriety" (Webster), just as Kb6aola is of KOb~trL6rs.

The law of art in the matter of decoration could hardly have been better stated than bySt. Augustine, who says that an ornamentation exceeding the bounds of responsibility to

the content of the work is sophistry, i.e. an extravagance or superfluity. If this is an artistic

sin, it is also a moral sin: "Even the shoemakers' and clothiers' arts stand in need of re-

straint, for they have lent their art to luxury, corrupting its necessity and artfully debasingart" (St. Chrysostom, Super Matth. hom. So, a med.). Accordingly, "Since women may

lawfully adorn themselves, whether to manifest what becomes (decentiam) their estate, oreven by adding something thereto, in order to please their husbands, it follows that those

who make such ornaments do not sin in the practice of their art, except in so far as they

may perhaps contrive what is superfluous and fantastic" (St. Thomas Aquinas, Sum. Theol.,

II-II, 169, 2 ad 4). It need hardly be said that whatever applies to the ornamentation of

persons also applies to the ornamentation of things, all of which aredecorations, in the origi-nal sense of an equipment, of the person to whom they pertain. The condemnation is of an

excess, and not of a richness of ornament. That "nothing can be useful unless it be honest"

(Tully and Ambrose, endorsed by St. Thomas) rules out all pretentious art. The concur-

rence here of the laws of art with those of morals, despite their logical distinction, is re-

markable.

We have said enough to suggest that it may be universally true that terms which now

imply an ornamentation of persons or things for aesthetic reasons alone originally impliedtheir proper equipment in the sense of a completion, without which satis-faction (alai-

karana) neither persons nor things could have been thought of as efficient or "simply and

truly useful," just as, apart from his at-tributes

(a-bharan.a),Deity could not be thought

of as functioning.15To have thought of art as an essentially aesthetic value is a very modern

development, and a provincial view of art, born of a confusion between the (objective)

14. "Whatever makes a thing befitting (decentem) is

called 'decoration' (decor), whether it be in the thing or ex-

ternally adapted to it, as ornaments of clothing and jewelsand the like. Hence 'decoration' is common to the beautiful

and to the apt" (Ulrich of Strassburg, De Pulchro, seeTHE ART BULLETIN, XVII, p. 44): as in the case of "theiron style that is made by the smith on the one hand thatwe may write with it, and on the other that we may take

pleasure in it; and in its kind is at the same time beautifuland adapted to our use" (St. Augustine, Lib. de ver. rel.,

39), between which ends there is no conflict; cf. the style il-

lustrated in my Mediaeval SinhaleseArt, fig. I29.I5. The analogy is far reaching. Whatever is unorna-

mented is said to be "naked." God, "taken naked of all

ornament" is "unconditioned" or "unqualified" (nirguna):one, but inconceivable. Ornamented, He is endowed with

qualities (saguna), which are manifold in their relationsand intelligible. And however insignificant this qualifica-tion and this adaptation to finite effects may be when con-

trasted with His unity and infinity, the latter would be in-

complete without them. In the same way a person or thingapart from its appropriate ornaments ("in the subject or

externally adapted to it") is valid as an idea, but not as

species. Ornament is related to its subject as individualnature to essence: to abstract is to denature. Ornament is

adjectival; and in the absence of any adjective, nothing re-ferred to by any noun could have an individual existence,however it might be in principle. If, on the other hand, the

subject is inappropriately or over-ornamented, so far from

completing it, this restricts its efficiency, and thereforeits

beauty, sinoe the extent to which it is in act is the extent ofits existence and the measure of its perfection as such andsuch a specified subject. Appropriate ornament is, then,essential to utility and beauty: in saying this, however, itmust be remembered that ornament may be "in the sub-

ject" itself, or if not, must be something added to the

subject in order that it may fulfil a given function.

Page 8: Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

7/27/2019 Art Bulletin Vol 21 No 4_Ornament_Coomaraswamy

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/art-bulletin-vol-21-no-4ornamentcoomaraswamy 8/8

382 THE ART BULLETIN

beauty of order and the (subjectively) pleasant, and fathered by a preoccupation with

pleasure. We certainly do not mean to say that man may not always have taken a sensitive

pleasure in work and the products of work; so far from this, "pleasure perfects the opera-tion." We do mean to say that in asserting that "beauty has to do with cognition," Scho-

lastic philosophy is affirmingwhat has always and everywhere been true, however we mayhave ignored or may wish to ignore the truth-we, who like other animals know what we

like, rather than like what we know. We do say that to explain the nature of primitive or

folk art, or, to speak more accurately, of any traditional art, by an assumption of "decora-

tive instincts" or "aesthetic purposes" is a pathetic fallacy, a deceptive projection of our

own mentality upon another ground; that the traditional artist no more regarded his work

with our romantic eyes than he was "fond of nature" in our sentimental way. We say that

we have divorced the "satis-faction" of the artifact from the artifact itself, and made it

seem to be the whole of art; that we no longer respect or feel our responsibility towards the

burden (gravitas)of the work, but prostitute its thesis to an aisthesis; and that this is the

sin of luxury.' We appeal to the historian of art, and especially to the historian of orna-

ment and the teacher of the "appreciation of art," to approach their material more objec-

tively; and suggest to the "designer" that if all good ornament had in its beginning a neces-

sary sense, it may be rather from a sense to be communicated than from an intention to

please that he should proceed.

i6. It may be remarked that in the animal world an ex-

cessive development of ornament usually preludes extinc-

tion ("The wages of sin is death"; sin, as always, beingdefined as "any departure from the order to the end").

In the preceding text, the following abbreviations have

been employed: RV., RgvedaSaiihit,;

TS., Taittiriya

Saihiti; AV., Atharva Veda Safahit&: SB., gitapatha

BrAhmaina;Ait.Ar., Aitareya Araiyaka; J., J.taka.