adams, truth values & the value of truth [16 pgs]

Upload: gzalzalkovia

Post on 03-Apr-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    1/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    TRUTH VALUES AND THE VALUE OF TRUTH 207

    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 (2002) 207222 02790750/00/01000000

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd. Published by

    Blackwell Publishers, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and

    350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.

    207

    TRUTH VALUES AND

    THE VALUE OF TRUTH

    ERNEST ADAMS

    Abstract: This paper explores the ways in which truth is better than falsehood,

    and suggests that, among other things, it depends on the kinds of propositionto which these values are attached. Ordinary singular propositions like It is

    raining seem to fit best the bivalent scheme of classical logic, the general

    proposition It is always raining is more appropriately rated according to

    how often it rains, and a practically vague proposition like The lecture

    will start at 1 is appropriately rated according to its nearness to exactness.

    Implications for logic of this rating system are commented on.

    1. Introduction

    Pure reason, which is what most modern Logic is concerned with, gener-

    ally assumes that truth is bivalent: there are the true and the false,

    and Logic studies the laws to which bearers of these values conform, e.g.,

    the law of double negation. But it is not concerned with the values of

    these values, with why the true is better than the false, and why it should

    be the goal of scientific inquiry, as Frege and others have held.

    The reason for this neglect is perhaps not far to seek. There are too

    many and competing theories of truth semantic, correspondence, coher-

    ence, and all the varieties of pragmatism, which above all ought to teach

    us the value of truth. Better to leave the meaning of truth to the philo-

    sophers and study truth values independently of their value, just as science

    studies the motions of material bodies without overly concerning itself

    with the definitions of space, time, and matter.

    But recent developments, even in pure Logic, should make us wonder

    whether it can consistently maintain its olympian unconcern with the

    value of truth. Too many theories have recently been put forward thatcall bivalence and other dogmas of classical Logic into question, and in

    PAPQC01 pages: 16

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    2/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    208 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    consequence call for a re-examination of the very idea of truth. And to

    deal with the controversies to which these theories have inevitably given

    rise, I would argue that we must cross the threshold from pure to pract-

    ical reason, and ask ourselves: what makes the truth that is adopted byone theory better than the truth that is adopted by another? Failing to

    address this question, we are too apt to fall into empty formalism and

    simply assert, for instance, that vague statements have degrees of truth

    subject to these or those formal laws, or, mea culpa, that conditional

    statements have no truth values but only probabilities that are also sub-

    ject to certain seemingly arbitrary formal laws. And why not say that

    these probabilities are truth values?1

    But now we are going to examine an example that suggests a prag-

    matic diagram and a formula that reconciles all of the theories of truthmentioned above within a narrow domain, but which also suggest how

    they might be generalized outside of that domain to accommodate vague

    statements and other constructions whose laws shouldbe questioned, but

    which are often assumed without question.

    2. An example, a pragmatic diagram,

    and a pragmatic formula2

    The example is as follows: Sam, a student, is anxious to register for the

    same class that his girl friend, Jane, will take, and believing that she will

    take Logic, registers for Logic. This processfits thepractical syllogism

    pattern of practical reason, which can be diagrammed thus:

    Although this is a causal process, considered as a syllogism it appears

    to have two premisses, one a belief and the other a desire. However

    only what is believed, that Jane will take Logic, is an object of pure Logic

    that can be true or false. Neither what is desired, to take the same class as

    Jane takes, nor the conclusion, the action of taking Logic, is something

    that can enter into inferential processes of the kind that pure Logic deals

    Diagram 1: Practical Syllogism

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    3/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    TRUTH VALUES AND THE VALUE OF TRUTH 209

    with.3 But if we extend the picture and bring in not only the action but

    the results that follow from it, together with certain facts that determine

    whether these results are desired, we get a pragmatic diagram that has

    elements of concern to Logic:

    Diagram 2: Simple Pragmatic Diagram

    Note that now we have added another pair of causal arrows, leading

    from the action, 3, and the facts, 4, to the result, 5. We have also added

    two vertical arrows representing something like semantic relations, one

    between the belief, 1, and the facts, 4, and the other between the desire,

    2, and the results, 5. The first determines whether the beliefcorresponds

    to the facts and is true, and the second determines whether the desire cor-

    responds to the results and is satisfied. Details of these correspondences

    will be returned to, including whether they are properly called semantic,but first let us note that there is a correspondence between the correspond-

    ences that allows us to state simple pragmatic principles, or formulas:

    The results of actions based on beliefs correspond to what is desired if and only if the beliefs

    correspond to the facts.

    or more simply:

    Results satisfy desires if the actions that lead to them are based on true beliefs.

    Broadening the above diagrams and principles to add linguistic ele-

    ments to the picture would lead to an almost endless series of remarks

    tying it into classical, even ancient views on relations between thoughts,

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    4/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    210 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    words, and the world, but here we will confine ourselves largely to

    what might be called the pragmatic aspects of the picture. First and

    foremost, to the extent that these pragmatic principles are valid, they give

    truth a practical value and suggest a motive for seeking it i.e., forseeking to arrive at conclusions that are true.4 But even within these

    limits, which will be transgressed shortly, the principles do not define

    a pragmatic concept of truth. Obviously the first, more elaborate

    pragmatic principle is stated in terms of a correspondence between beliefs

    and facts, between something in the mind and something in the world,

    and therefore it can with equal right be held to embody a correspondence

    concept of truth.5 It also makes a possibly intriguing departure in involv-

    ing a parallel correspondence between a desire and a result, and therefore

    to embody a correspondence concept of satisfaction.Note too that if linguistic elements were added to the picture it could

    be regarded as embodying directly semantic concepts of both truth and

    desire. Thus, Sams belief that Jane will take logic is true if Jane takes

    logic, so essentially the same words are used to refer both to the belief

    and to the fact, and his desire to take the same class as Jane is described

    in essentially the same words as the result he aims for: to take the same

    class as Jane.6 Leaving these elements out of the picture leaves only the

    unstructured belief and desire as the bearers, respectively, of truth and

    satisfaction.In any case, the diagram and the principles are very limited, and two

    kinds of limitation will be discussed at some length in what follows. We

    will pass quickly over limitations like the following, cited by Nicholas

    Rescher (Rescher, 1977 and 1998), in which a person mistakenly believ-

    ing that an apple before him is a Gravenstein and wanting to eat an

    apple, satisfies his desire by eating the apple, even though the belief on

    which this action is based is mistaken. What this shows is that to make

    the principles or formulas work, there must also be a correspondence

    between the belief and the desire. One must be apposite to the other, sothat if the belief is that the apple is a Gravenstein then the desire must be

    for a Gravenstein apple.

    Much more serious are the personal and temporal limitations of our

    pragmatic principles. It is Sam who has the motive for seeking the truth

    about Janes plans, and he has that motive now. Not, say, a year from

    now. I regard it as important in developing a theory of practical reason

    to take limitations of this kind into account in a systematic way, since

    failing to do so we are too apt to regard the truth as an abstract good,

    of equal interest to all persons at all times.7 I would argue that even

    Science, which pretends to seek the truth for its own sake, doesnt

    really ignore human interests. However these are very complex matters,

    and the temporal limitation of our pragmatic principles will be returned

    to, relating to beliefs about the non-present, and the past and future.

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    5/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    TRUTH VALUES AND THE VALUE OF TRUTH 211

    But before turning to that, we will comment on less severe limitations

    that nevertheless show that the principles need to be revised significantly

    in application to beliefs of special kinds.

    3. The value of accuracy

    One limitation relates to statements of a kind that can said to be theoretic-

    ally precise, but practically vague. An example is The lecture will begin at

    1 pm. Trying to put that into the framework of Diagram 1 might lead to:

    The problem here is with the inference from 3 and 4b to 5b: Sam s

    arriving at 1 and the lectures not beginning at 1 do not entail that Sam

    will not arrive in time for the lecture. If the lecture started at 10 seconds

    after 1, then, taken literally, Sams belief that it would begin at 1 would

    be false. But even so his action of arriving at 1 would probably succeed.

    Therefore we couldnt say that

    The result of Sams action, based on the belief that the lecture would start at 1, will

    correspond to what he desires if and only if the belief corresponds to the facts.

    Rather, we might say that:

    The result of Sams action, based on the belief that the lecture would start at 1, will cor-

    respond to what he desires if and only if the belief corresponds closely enough to the facts.

    Diagram 3

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    6/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    212 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    This closely enough suggests accuracy and degrees of correspondence

    with the fact, perhaps as theorized about in Fuzzy Logic. One is even

    tempted to formulate a general pragmatic principle of fuzzy truth,

    thus:

    Results of actions based on beliefs correspond to what is desired if and only if the beliefs are

    sufficiently true.

    This formula still doesnt quite fit the facts of human action, since it

    seems to suggest that there is a sharp line of division between beliefs that

    are sufficiently true and those that are not. Is there an exact degree of

    truth such that Sam will arrive at the lecture on time if and only if the

    belief he acts on has that degree of truth? Fuzziness is not that sharp.Thus, our formula still doesnt correctly capture a practical value that

    might attach to beliefs that only correspond approximately or fuzzily

    to the facts. But these observations do bring out something.

    When we go beyond the values of beliefs like the one in the example

    of the class that Jane will take, and consider ones whose values only

    correspond to the facts roughly, or to a degree, the problem of char-

    acterizing an appropriate measure of this degree becomes acute. Nor is it

    one that we should leap to conclusions about, since all too often this

    leads to empty mathematical formalism. We may assume that these meas-ures should be componential, so that the degree of truth of a conjunc-

    tion is some precisely defined mathematical function of the degrees of

    truth of its conjuncts. Why? What is the value of these truth values; what

    evidence do we have that some practical advantage attaches to arriving at

    conclusions that score high on these measures? My view is that we would

    be better advised to give up this empty mathematizing, and look at the

    details of practical reasoning and acting on beliefs such as are expressed

    as The lecture will begin at 1. Further remarks on this will be made in

    section 6, but there are other domains to consider, including one in whichI have violated my own precepts in theorizing about degrees of truth.

    4. Approximate generalizations

    A belief that seems more like the kind that classical pragmatists like

    Pierce had in mind is typically expressed as a generalization, e.g., that

    dogs bark, or that red blackberries are unripe. These typically are less

    subject to temporal limitations than beliefs expressed by singular sent-

    ences, such as This dog barks, or Those red blackberries are unripe.

    One reason why the motive for seeking the truth about the generalization

    is less restricted than it is for seeking the truth about the singular state-

    ment is that the former may be acted upon repeatedly, and for this reason

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    7/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    TRUTH VALUES AND THE VALUE OF TRUTH 213

    a person may want to store it, much as she might put a tool in a

    toolbox against future uses that she only anticipates in a general way.

    The fact that one may act repeatedly on beliefs in generalizations

    also suggests that they do not conform to the same pragmatic prin-ciples as do beliefs in singular propositions. We cannot say that allsuch

    actions have desired results if and only if the beliefs acted on correspond

    to the facts. Thus, we cannot simply substitute Red blackberries are

    unripe for Jane will take Logic in Diagram 1 to arrive at something

    like:

    But replacing a belief about something particular, e.g., that these red

    blackberries are unripe, by a belief about agenerality (a general belief)

    demands corresponding changes in the other factors in the diagram, asfollows (numbering the changes to correspond to the entries in the dia-

    gram). (2) The desire should not be for ripe blackberries on a particular

    occasion, but then again, it should not be for ripe blackberries on all

    occasionswe cant suppose that Sam desires them all the time. (3) Nor

    do the general belief and desire influence a particular action, but rather

    something more like a policy for actionsay to refrain from eating red

    blackberries.8 (4) The possible facts as described in Diagram 4 are no

    longer exhaustive. The logical opposite ofred blackberries are unripe is

    not red blackberries are ripe, but something more like red blackber-

    ries are sometimes ripe. (5) One of the results given in Diagram 4 no

    longer corresponds to one of the facts, since if red blackberries are some-

    times ripe and Sam refrains from eating them he will sometimes not eat

    ripe blackberries. Incorporating the suggested changes leads to:

    Diagram 4

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    8/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    214 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    Diagram 5

    Crude as this diagram is, it nevertheless suggests a correspondence

    between the general belief that it involves and the facts, that is in

    some ways more like the one involved in the approximate, or fuzzy prag-

    matic formulas that correspond to Diagram 3 than it is like the simplesemantic correspondence that corresponds to Diagram 1. Thus, first

    approximations topragmatic principles for generalizations might go:

    The results of acting on in accord with policies based on general beliefs correspond to what

    is desired to the extent that the beliefs correspond to the facts.

    or more simply:

    The truer general beliefs are, the more desirable the results of acting in accord with them

    are.

    Let us briefly compare and contrast the principles stated above with

    those stated in section 2. Like the earlier principles, the present ones also

    suggest a practical motive for trying to arrive at beliefs that correspond

    to the facts, and therefore they are pragmatic. But while the motive for

    arriving at beliefs that correspond to the facts is less ephemeral than the

    one that applies, for instance, to the proposition that Jane will take Logic,

    it is less sharply defined. That is because in the present case the cor-

    respondence with the facts, rather than being all or none, is a matter of

    degree. Whatever this is, it is surely not bivalent. But like the degrees that

    enter into the pragmatic formulas that apply e.g., to the lecture will start

    at 1 p.m, they are what matter. What matters is significance, and an

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    9/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    TRUTH VALUES AND THE VALUE OF TRUTH 215

    exact degree oftruth ofred blackberries are unripe doesnt matter as

    long as it is significantwhich is related to the fact that satisfaction is no

    longer a matter of all or none, but rather of more or less.

    A final point about the degrees of correspondence of generalizationspertains to the way these degrees are measured in my theory of approximate

    generalizations (Adams, 1974, and elsewhere), which is as proportions.9

    E.g., the degree of correspondence of Red blackberries are unripe is

    the proportion of unripe berries among all red blackberries. Admittedly

    there is a good deal of arbitrariness in the choice of this measure, as is

    usually the case with numerical terms of art.10 But if it is agoodmeasure

    it contributes by refiningreasoning involving approximate generalizations.

    An example involves the syllogism Barbara though it doesnt involve

    blackberries.Barbara has traditionally been rendered in the form All As are Bs

    and all Bs are Cs; ergo all As are Cs.All As are Bs,All Bs are Cs,

    and All As are Cs are universal generalizations, but it is common to

    idealize and apply Barbara to generalizations that have exceptions,

    e.g., as in All Greeks are men and all Athenians are Greeks, therefore all

    Athenians are men.11 But these are really approximate generalizations,

    and proportionality analysis shows that when they are this kind of

    reasoning isnt always valid, and it brings counterexamples to light, e.g.,

    All penguins are birds and all birds fly, ergo all penguins fly. Evenmore importantly, we will see that this analysis tells us when approx-

    imate reasoning of the form of Barbara is valid. This will be returned to

    in the concluding section, but first we will comment very briefly on three

    kinds of propositions and possible associated pragmatic principles that

    are not among those covered so far.

    5. General themes, and pragmatic principles not yet covered

    The investigation on which we have embarked has barely begun, but

    already certain themes have already begun to emerge. One is that the

    correspondences that determine the values of different beliefs vary widely

    with the beliefs in question. Most importantly, what determines these

    values are pragmatic. They depend on how the beliefs influence actions

    or policies, and how much the results of these actions, or actions in

    accord with these policies, are desired. These things can only be ascer-

    tained by reference to the facts of human behavior, and no one or a few

    pragmatic principles should be expected to cover all cases.

    So far we have very cursorily considered three cases, no two of which

    conform to the same pragmatic principles: (1) beliefs expressed by simple

    singular statements, (2) beliefs expressed as singular quantitative state-

    ments, and (3) beliefs expressed as generalizations. The first might be

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    10/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    216 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    held to be the model assumed in current logical theory, since it involves

    a bivalent correspondence that in its semantic guise conforms to Conven-

    tion T. The second and third involve degrees of correspondence that are

    measured in different ways in the two cases. This will be returned tobelow, but first we must stress that our three cases are far exhausting all

    cases that are humanly important.

    Here are four more cases that are not included among the ones com-

    mented on above, which may be noted partly to show how limited the

    little that has been done so far is. These are: (1) propositions concerning

    the past and other remote things, (2) theoretical propositions, (3) moral

    claims, and (4) conditional propositions. My personal view is that what

    are often called the true or the right, pertaining to these propositions

    have important pragmatic dimensions. As to the past, clearly the truthabout it can be a matter of practical importance. The simple pragmatic

    formula often holds, since the correspondence between beliefs about the

    past and the facts often determines the desirability of the results of

    actions that are guided by these beliefs. For example, whether the action

    of looking for a coat in the closet, guided by the belief that the coat was

    hung in the closet, succeeds in finding the coat depends on whether the

    coat was hung in the closet. However, this success really depends on the

    coats remaining where it was hung. It is more immediately dependent on

    what ispresently the case, and where it was hung is only important as aguide to that. More generally, what matters, and what we aim to influ-

    ence, are the present or the future, and the past or otherwise remote only

    matters insofar as it bears on those. Therefore I am inclined to think that

    a pragmatic account of the truth about the past or the remote must

    bring in broadly inductive factors that lead from them to the present.12

    As to theories, all the brou-ha-ha and dispute over the rightness of

    theories, e.g., the theory of evolution, the labor theory of value, and so

    on, seems to me to show that the rightness or wrongness of claims about

    them makes very little practical difference. If anything, they become thefoci ofmovements or in the scientific case, ofparadigms that influ-

    ence programs of action or research whose long-term consequences may

    be important, but whose influence cannot be evaluated in the short term.13

    As to moral propositions, clearly hardly anything can be more pract-

    ically important. But we cannot say, e.g., that doing to others what one

    would have them do to oneself yields rewards in proportion to its degree

    of truth. My view is that such benefits as derive from holding true

    moral beliefs are societal and not individual. But that does not mean that

    it is not worthwhile to look at those benefits in detail, and to attempt to

    formulate principles that describe the relation between them and some

    sort ofrightness that pertains to the moral beliefs that guide them.

    Despite their formal similarities and even logical connections to gener-

    alizations, conditional propositions bring in a host of new pragmatic

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    11/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    TRUTH VALUES AND THE VALUE OF TRUTH 217

    issues at least, assuming with me that the practical aim of reasoning

    about them is not direct correspondence with the facts, i.e., truth, but

    rather probability.14 Although it is intuitively evident that persons often

    do aim, not just to arrive at true conclusions but also to arrive at prob-able ones, the question becomes: what is the practical value of success

    in this endeavor? What is the practical value of knowing that a coin

    that is about to be tossed has a 50% chance of coming down heads if

    in fact it is goingto come down tails? This question is examined in sec-

    tions 47 of Adams, 1998, and a pragmatic motive for being right

    in probability judgments is found, but the matter is too complicated

    to enter into here.15 The only lesson to be drawn here is that truth-as-

    correspondence, or closeness to it, is not the only pragmatically useful

    value that can attach to conclusions reached in reasoning. Probabilityis another one, and, at a still greater leap, it is the only one that attaches

    to conditionals.

    This ends our speculations on a pragmatic research program. Finally,

    we shall comment very briefly on another issue related to pragmatism,

    and to another kind of proposition.

    6. Addendum concerning truth and logic

    We must not take it for granted that the kind of pragmatic, utilitarian

    truth that we have been attempting to characterize has any simple con-

    nection with deductive logic. Now consider the syllogism Darii, which

    may be rendered as Some As are Bs and all Bs are Cs; therefore some

    As are Cs, and which, like Barbara, has exceptions when All Bs are

    Cs is only approximately true. Thus, it is just as invalid to reason Some

    penguins are birds and all birds fly; therefore some penguins fly as to

    reason All penguins are birds and all birds fly; therefore all penguins

    fly. But the following proportionality formula throws light both onthe validity of exact Darii and exact Barbara, and on when their

    approximate versions are valid. Letting P, B, and F symbolize is a

    penguin,is a bird, and flies, respectively, and letting p(P,B), P(B&P,F),

    and p(P,F) be the proportions of penguins that fly, of birds which are

    penguins that fly, and of penguins that fly, it is easily demonstrated that

    no matter what these proportions are, it is the case that:

    (P) p(P,F) p(P,B) p(B&P,F).

    The proportion of penguins that fly must be at least as great as the

    proportion of penguins that are birds, multiplied by the proportion of

    birds which are penguins that fly. This does not apply directly either to

    Barbara or Darii, since their common minor premise is All birds fly,

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    12/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    218 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    and (P) involves not the proportion of birds that fly, but rather the

    proportion of birds which are penguins that fly. But (P) relates to these

    syllogisms in two ways.

    Suppose first that All birds fly is exactly true. This would entail thatAll birds which are penguins fly is also exactly true: i.e., p(B&P,F) = 1.

    This together with (P) would entail that p(P,F) p(P,B): i.e., the propor-

    tion of penguins that fly must be at least as great as the proportion of

    penguins that are birds. This would validate both Barbara and Darii,

    since ifallpenguins are birds the proportion of penguins that are birds

    must equal 1 and so must the proportion of penguins that fly. And if only

    some penguins were birds, the proportion of penguins that flew would

    still have to be at least as great as the proportion that were birds, so at

    least some penguins would have to fly.16

    But the foregoing assumes that All birds fly is exactly true, whatever

    the truth of the other premise is, and the examples at hand show us that

    idealization is not always tenable. On the other hand, we do not want

    argue that we can never idealize Barbara and Darii when their com-

    mon universal premise is not exactly true. Thus, substituting parrot

    for penguin, it does not seem unreasonable to idealize and argue either

    All parrots are birds and all birds fly; therefore all parrots fly, or

    Some parrots are birds and all birds fly; therefore some parrots fly.

    Moreover the proportion p(B&P,F) in inequality (P) makes clear whatthe difference between these cases is. While a high proportion ofbirdsfly,

    and a high proportion of birds which areparrotsfly, a very low propor-

    tion of birds that are penguins fly. Inequality (P) is always valid, and

    Barbara and Darii are valid at least as idealizations when p(B&P,F) is

    high, but not when this proportion is not high.

    Now, Barbara and Darii only give us that all Bs are Fs, hence p(B,F)

    is high, but except in the ideal case in which p(B,F) = 1 they dont entail

    that p(B&P,F) is high. However, recent work of Donald Bamber, 2000,

    proves that when p(B,F) is close to 1, while it is not certain that p(B&P,F)is high, it is a statistical near certainty that it is high. Slightly more ex-

    actly, as p(B,F) approaches 1 the proportion of predicates, P, for which

    p(B&F,P) is arbitrarily high also approaches 1. Therefore it is a plaus-

    ible statistical default to assume, when almost all Bs are Fs, that almost

    all Bs which are Ps are also Fs, and therefore Barbara and Darii apply.

    Parrots are typical and penguins are rare and untypical in the birds

    and flying examples, which goes far towards explaining the acceptability

    of Barbara and Darii in most cases even when their universal premisses

    are not exactly true.

    The foregoing considerations will be developed further, and applied

    to more general syllogistic reasoning in a paper now in preparation, but

    let us conclude the present paper with some reflections on the method

    employed here in analyzing Barbara and Darii.

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    13/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    TRUTH VALUES AND THE VALUE OF TRUTH 219

    First, note that whereas inexact Barbara and Darii are vague and

    subject to exceptions, inequality (P) that is applied in analyzing them is

    exact and has no exceptions. Also, the analysis is more general than the

    syllogisms analyzed in that it explains not only why the syllogisms arevalid when their universal premisses are exactly true, but why and under

    what circumstances they can be idealized and applied when these

    premisses are only approximately true.

    Second, notice the way in which inequality (P) applies to particular

    premisses and conclusions of the form Some Ps are Bs and Some Ps

    are Fs that enter into applications of Darii. These correspond to the

    proportions p(P,B) and p(P,F) that enter into (P), but the proportions

    dont measure the degrees of truth ofSome Ps are Bs and Some Ps

    are Fs. They measure the proportions of Ps that are Bs and Ps that areFs, but the proportion, say, of parrots that fly is no more a measure of

    how trueSome parrots fly is than it is a measure of the degrees of

    truth either ofAll parrots fly or ofNo parrots fly. In other words,

    p(P,F) measures something that is common to a range propositional forms

    including All Ps are Fs,Some Ps are Fs, and No Ps are Fs, and so

    on, many of which are themselves vague. But p(P,F) cannot be regarded

    as measuring the degrees of truth of all of these forms simultaneously,

    which would be absurd, since this would entail that the alleged

    contradictories Some Ps are Fs and No Ps are Fs were equally true.At most section 4 of this paper suggests that p(P,F) might measure the

    degree to which it is desirable to believe and act on the approximate

    generalization Parrots fly a pragmatic degree of truth. But Some

    parrots fly is not a generalization, approximate or otherwise, nor is it

    an approximation of anything else. We may say that Some parrots

    fly is true, even that it has a degree of truth, but as yet we have no clear

    idea of what it is to act on this belief, hence no clear idea as to why it

    might be such actions should have beneficial consequences. And lack-

    ing that we have no justification for assuming that the proportion ofparrots that fly is a good measure of how good a policy it is to act on

    the belief that some parrots fly. But let us conclude with some general

    observations on the relation between inequality (P) and the syllogisms

    Barbara and Darii.

    The key fact is that (P) applies to Barbara and Darii not by formal-

    izingthem, but rather by explainingthem. That (P) doesnt formalize the

    syllogisms is clear from the fact that the syllogisms involve terms like

    all, some, and and therefore, while (P) involves three proportions,

    one of which is stated to be at least as great as the product of the other

    two. But (P) explains the syllogisms both by showing that they are always

    valid when their universal premisses are true without exception, and

    by showing that they are usually valid when these premisses have few

    exceptions.

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    14/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    220 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    Recall too the relation between the proportion p(P,F) and the con-

    clusions All Ps are Fs and Some Ps are Fs of Barbara and Darii. We

    have argued that in the former case is it plausible to take the proportion

    as a measure of the desirability of believing the conclusion, but lackinga pragmatic analysis of propositions of the form Some Ps are Fs,

    we have hesitated to suggest that the proportion might be a good meas-

    ure of the desirability of believing them. But given that (P) does not

    formalize inferences involving these propositions, that p(P,F) may not

    measure their degrees of truth does not militate against analyzing infer-

    ences involving them in terms of these proportions. In fact, this gives us

    a way of dealing with at least one kind of vague proposition, namely ones

    of the form Some Ps are Fs, without formalizing them or inferences

    involving them. Of course it is questionable how much light this mightthrow on vague propositions in general, but it is suggestive.

    A final point is that there is an analogy between our approach to the

    logic of practical syllogistic and the approach of Physics to informal

    reasoning about measurable quantities like weight, length, and tempera-

    ture. In ordinary language we say things like Mrs. Smith is light and

    Mr. Smith is heavy, but Physics or medicine would be more apt to

    say something like Mrs. Smith weighs 120 lbs. and Mr. Smith weighs

    220 lbs. That would not be regarded as a formalization or even a regime-

    ntation ofMrs. Smith is light and Mr. Smith is heavy, but it conveysall of the information in it and more besides. Similarly, in ordinary lan-

    guage we may say Some parrots fly, but though it would not formalize

    that statement, saying that at least 10% of parrots fly conveys at least this

    much information and more besides.

    If the foregoing approach has some validity it suggests that it may be

    possible to explain informal reasoning without formalizing it, by intro-

    ducing appropriate measures of logical quantities that are related to

    the propositions involved. But choosing appropriate measures is no

    easier in logic than it is in Physics (cf. Adams, 1966, and Adams andAdams, 1987), and while the degrees of truth that the Fuzzy Logicians

    theorize about might seem plausible a priori, it is less so in the case of

    statements of the Some Ps are Fs form that enter into syllogistic reason-

    ing than the proportions that are related to them.17

    Department of Philosophy

    University of California-Berkeley

    NOTES

    1 In fact, Brian Ellis did something very like this in an early work (Ellis, 1973), but only

    gave this up when David Lewis showed that his formal laws entailed that there could only

    be four possible probability values.

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    15/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    TRUTH VALUES AND THE VALUE OF TRUTH 221

    2 I apologize to readers familiar with my work for using the example, diagram, and

    formula to be discussed here elsewhere.3 Jeffreys logic decision (Jeffrey, 1983) does treat propositions as objects of desire, but

    we will ignore that here since it is not relevant to the developments to follow.

    4 This is a motive for seeking truth in our world, not truth in a world.5 Thus also, our simple pragmatic principles are far from William James pragmatism,

    e.g., as expressed as Principally, the truth of a state of mind means . . . a leading that is

    worthwhile (Pragmatism, 1907). Also, our principles have nothing to do with alleged feel

    good benefits of holding beliefs of one or another kind. Endnote 9 will comment briefly on

    a correspondence with a kind ofPeircian pragmatism.6 Bringing linguistic elements into the picture also adds elements to the world, since

    the Sams belief, described as that Jane will take Logic, involves the names Jane and

    Logic, and these are presumed to refer to things, objects, in the world.7 This suggests the distinction between practical and disinterested values of the

    information, discussed in Rosenkrantz, 1977.8 Changing the belief to something general, and changing what it influences from a

    particular action to general policy makes the picture more like Peirces The feeling of

    believing is a more or less sure indication of there being established in our nature some

    habit which will determine our actions (from The Fixation of Belief, 1877). Our picture

    thereby moves closer to Peircian pragmatism.9 Proportions suggest probabilities, since both obey the same formal laws. But the two

    ought not to be confused, since proportions are matters of fact while probabilities, at least

    of the sort that are relevant to reasoning, are matters of belief. The author s analysis of

    conditional propositions (Adams, 1975, and elsewhere) evaluates them in terms of probabil-

    ity, e.g., that a particular bird flies, not of the proportion of birds that fly. Sections 47 ofAdams, 1998, are concerned with probabilities, particularly of conditionals, and with for-

    mulating appropriate pragmatic principles that apply to judgments about them.10 Cf. my paper On the Nature and Purpose of Measurement (Adams, 1966) and my

    paper with William Y. Adams Purpose and Scientific Concept Formation, (Adams and

    Adams, 1989).11 Copi, 1972, p. 185. It might be argued that even though there are many non-Greek

    residents of Athens, All Athenians are Greeks is true without exception because these

    people could not be Athenian citizens. But if Barbara could only be applied to general-

    izations that are rendered universally true by definition, its practical usefulness would be

    limited in the extreme.12 It is in the details of this that I am inclined to see the practical importance of the

    coherence that sometimes figures in accounts of the nature of truth. We only have traces

    or records, and not direct sensory access to the past, and we often have to reconcile

    conflicts between these items of testimony. But I am inclined to think that going into

    detail concerning these matters will require us to confront the problem of time directly.13 It seems to me that the efforts of the praxis philosophers are directed primarily at

    the theoretical case. But if the present remarks are correct these efforts must be fruitless.

    There are no clear practical principles that apply to beliefs of this sort, and to demand that

    they should be discovered, formulated, or created is as pointless as to demand that the

    center of the universe should be discovered.14 Cf. my book The Logic of Conditionals, Adams, 1975.15 My ideas are largely inspired by very cryptic suggestions in parts (4) and (5) of Ramsey s

    great paper Truth and Probability (Ramsey, 1950). I think that even more than the earlier

    parts of this paper, upon which modern ideas of subjective probability are based, the last

    parts, which attempt to link that to a pragmatically useful concept of objective probability,

  • 7/28/2019 Adams, Truth Values & the Value of Truth [16 pgs]

    16/16

    2002 University of Southern California and Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    222 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY

    are the most profound ones in the paper. So far as I can see, to date these parts have hardly

    been commented on at all, and so we can say that Ramsey is still ahead of our time.16 Note that this would be somewhat stronger than the conclusion of Darii, which is only

    that some penguins must fly, and not that the proportion that fly must be at least as great

    as the proportion that are birds.17 It is particularly questionable to assume with Fuzzy Logic that the truth of Some

    parrots fly should equal 1 minus that ofNo parrots fly, assuming that that is the logical

    contradictory ofSome parrots fly (cf., Nguyen and Walker, 2000, p. 67).

    REFERENCES

    Adams, E. W. (1966). On the Nature and Purpose of Measurement, Synthese 16,

    pp. 225269.

    Adams, E. W. (1974). The Logic ofAlmost All , Journal of Philosophical Logic 3, pp. 3

    17.

    Adams, E. W. (1975). The Logic of Conditionals, Dordrecht, D. Reidel and Company.

    Adams, E. W. (1996). Four Probability-preserving Properties of Inferences, Journal of

    Philosophical Logic 25, pp. 124.

    Adams, E. W. (1998). The utility of truth and probability, in P. Weingartner, G. Schurz,

    and G. Dorn (eds.), The Role of Pragmatics in Contemporary Philosophy, Holder-Pichler-

    Tempsky, Vienna, pp. 1761994.

    Adams, E. W. and Adams, W. Y. (1987). Purpose and Scientific Concept Formation with

    W. Y. Adams, British Journal for Philosophy of Science 38, pp. 419440.

    Bamber, D. (2000). Entailment with near surety of scaled assertions of high probability,

    Journal of Philosophical Logic 29, pp. 174.

    Ellis, B. (1973). The logic of subjective probability,British Journal for the Philosophy of

    Science 24 (2), pp. 125152.

    James, W. (1907). Pragmatism, a New Name for Old Ways of Thinking, New York, Longmans,

    Green & Co.

    Jeffrey, R. (1983). The Logic of Decision, 2nd Edition, Chicago, the University of Chicago

    Press, 1983.

    Jevons, W. S. (1896). Studies in Deductive Logic, Third Edition, New York, The Macmillan

    Company, Limited.

    Nguyen, H. T., and Walker, E. A. (2000). A First Course In Fuzzy Logic, Second Edition,

    Boca Raton, Chapman and Hall/CRC.

    Peirce, C. S. (1877). The fixation of belief,Popular Science Monthly.

    Ramsey, F. (1950). Truth and Probability, in R.B. Braithwaite (ed.), The Foundations of

    Mathematics and Other Logical Essays, New York, The Humanities Press, pp. 156198.

    Rescher, N. (1977). Methodological Pragmatism, New York, New York University Press.

    Rescher, N. (1998). Pragmatism in crisis, in P. Weingartner, G. Schurz, and G. Dorn

    (eds.), The Role of Pragmatics in Contemporary Philosophy, Holder-Pichler-Tempsky,

    Vienna, pp. 2438.

    Rosenkrantz, R. D. 1977. Inference, Method and Decision, Dordrecht, D. Reidel Publishing

    Company.