wolz, henry g. - plato's doctrine of truth - orthótes or alétheia

Upload: anacconzatti

Post on 24-Feb-2018

226 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    1/27

    International Phenomenological Societyis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy and

    Phenomenological Research.

    http://www.jstor.org

    nternational Phenomenological Society

    Plato's Doctrine of Truth: Orthtes or Altheia?Author(s): Henry G. WolzSource: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 27, No. 2 (Dec., 1966), pp. 157-182Published by: International Phenomenological SocietyStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2105357

    Accessed: 21-08-2015 13:16 UTC

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ipshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2105357http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2105357http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ipshttp://www.jstor.org/
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    2/27

    PLATO'S

    DOCTRINE

    OF

    TRUTH:

    ORTHOTES

    OR

    AL]tTHEIA?

    The

    stagewhich

    the

    interpretation

    f

    the Platonic

    writings

    has

    reached

    is very

    odd

    indeed. If

    we divide

    the

    dialogues

    roughly nto

    three

    groups,

    then

    we

    find that

    the

    early dialogues,

    with their

    emphasis

    on

    search,

    are generally

    said

    to

    be

    animated

    by the liberal spirit

    of the

    living

    Socrates.'

    But the

    very attempt

    to find a

    definition

    for such

    terms

    as

    courage, self-mastery, r virtue tself, suggestsa belief in the possi-

    bility

    of rigid

    standards

    or the

    conduct

    of life

    which

    belies that

    spirit.

    The

    dialoguesof

    the second

    group

    are

    ascribed o

    the

    period of

    Plato's

    supreme excellence

    as a dramatist.

    Here

    one

    would expect

    to find

    the playwright's

    eachingby

    indirection,

    he stimnulation

    f thought

    which

    is usually

    associated

    with

    the

    Socratic method.

    Instead

    the

    dramatic

    elements

    are completelyneglected

    by the

    commentatorsor

    relegated

    to

    the byplay,

    and the main

    purpose

    of the

    dialogues

    s

    seen in

    the presen-

    tation

    of such

    Platonic

    doctrines

    as

    the theory

    of ideas

    in the

    Phaedo

    which serves

    as the basis for a rigorousdemonstrationof the immor-

    tality

    of the

    soul, and

    the rule

    of the

    philosopher-kings

    n the Republic,

    whose insight

    into the

    ultimate

    meaning

    of the world

    enables

    them

    to

    judge

    with

    infallibility

    in matters

    both

    private

    and

    public.

    The

    late

    dialogues

    which

    are

    characterized

    by

    a marked

    decline

    of

    dramatic

    power

    one

    would

    associate

    with

    a more

    straightforward

    xposition

    and perhaps

    a

    more dogmatic

    attitude.

    This anticipation

    would

    be in

    keeping

    with the

    reason

    which

    is customarilygiven

    for the

    more

    rigid

    outlook of the second group as againstthe first. For if this change is

    rightly

    attributed o

    the decline

    of

    the memory

    of Socrates

    in

    the

    mind

    of

    Plato,

    then the

    last

    group

    would

    be

    likely

    to continue

    this

    trend.

    Curiously

    enough

    it has of

    late

    become

    fashionable

    to

    see much

    of

    the

    Socratic

    method

    and

    spirit

    in

    the late

    dialogues.

    Cornford's

    om-

    mentary

    on

    the Parmenides,

    or

    instance,

    is

    replete

    with remarks

    such

    1

    E. A.

    Taylor

    refers

    to them

    as

    Socratic

    dialogues.

    (Plato,

    The Man

    and

    His

    Work.

    Sixth

    Edition.

    London:

    1949,

    p.

    XI.)

    Hermann Gauss

    calls

    them

    Friih-

    dialoge and distinguishesthem from the Dialoge der literarischenMeisterschaft

    and

    the

    Spidialoge.

    (Philosophischer

    Handkommentar

    zu

    den

    Dialogen

    Platos.

    Bern:

    1961.)

    2

    E.

    A.

    Taylor,

    op. cit.,

    p. 20.

    3

    Ibid., p.

    19.

    157

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    3/27

    158 PHILOSOPHY

    NDPHENOMENOLOGICAL

    ESEARCH

    as these: Faithful

    o Socrates,

    he would

    rathermake

    us think for our-

    selves than tell

    us what

    to think. We

    are ... to

    draw for ourselves

    the necessary

    nferences. Cornford

    goes,so far as, to say that at

    times

    Plato'spurpose is to puzzle the reader by apparent contradictions

    or

    that differentmeanings,

    of the supposition

    have

    been disguised

    and that he leaves

    it to

    us to

    discover

    the

    relevant sense or aspect.

    Hermann

    Gauss, in his

    six-volume

    Handkommentar

    nterprets

    Philebus

    65a

    to mean

    that Plato no longer

    regards.

    he supreme,

    Good

    as

    directly

    accessible.9

    He finds that

    in the-Laws

    Plato has become

    much

    more

    liberal

    as

    compared

    with

    the Republic where

    he advocated

    state

    control of the

    arts,'0 and that he

    now

    holds

    that the founder of

    a

    new

    state cannot simply look to the ideal but must have

    regard for various

    aspects of the

    specific

    situation, such as

    the geographical

    onditions

    of

    the site he has

    chosen,

    as well as the historical

    tradition

    n which

    the

    prospective

    colonists have

    been raised.

    In fact Gauss

    attempts

    o

    trace

    a process,of

    maturation

    and liberalization

    of Plato's

    philosophy,which

    finds its consummation

    n the dialogues

    written

    toward the end

    of

    his

    life:

    It seems that when

    Plato

    wrote the Sophist

    he

    had not

    yet

    altogether

    freed

    himself from the illusion

    that a

    kind of permanent

    knowledge

    might

    after

    all

    be accessible to us. He has not yet reached the height which he will reach

    in

    the

    Timaeus where all our

    assertions

    about

    reality

    are

    regarded

    as no more

    than

    eik6tes

    mythoi,

    that is as tentative and

    merely probable

    assertions,

    which

    in principle

    can be

    overthrown and of

    which,

    in the

    name

    of

    philosophy,

    we

    must

    hope

    that

    sooner

    or

    later they

    will

    in

    fact be

    overthrown

    and

    surpassed.12

    It

    was,

    difficult

    enough

    to

    accept the

    old

    view

    which

    maintained

    hat

    one and the

    same author who

    so successfully portrayed

    the

    spirit

    of

    Socrates

    n

    the

    early

    dialogues

    had become

    so

    utterly

    inflexiblein

    later

    life. But the new

    one,

    which would have

    us

    believe

    that

    the wine

    turned

    4

    F.

    MacDonald

    Cornford,

    Plato

    and

    Parmenides.

    New York, 1951,

    p.

    111.

    5

    Ibid.,

    p. 107.

    6

    Ibid.,

    p. 163.

    7

    Ibid., p. 217.

    8

    Ibid., p. 154

    Note

    also:

    They

    (the

    students

    of the

    Academy)

    are

    expected

    to

    compare

    the

    arguments

    of each

    Hypothesis

    with

    those

    of the

    others and

    to

    find

    out

    for

    them-

    selves

    the

    distinctions

    that

    must

    be drawn.

    (Ibid., p.

    130.)

    9

    Zuerst

    werden

    wir

    darueber

    nicht

    erstaunt

    sein,

    wenn es

    von

    diesem

    obersten

    'Guten' heisst, dass wir zu ihm keinen direkten Zugang haben. Das ist, was

    wir

    beim

    spaten

    Plato seit

    dem

    Parmenides

    ohnehin

    erwarten.

    (Hermann

    Gauss,

    Handkommentar

    zu

    den

    Dialogen

    Platos. 3. Teil. Zweite

    Haelfte.

    Bern,

    1961,

    p.

    43.)

    10

    Ibid.,

    p. 70.

    11

    Ibid.

    12

    Op. cit.,

    3.

    Teil.,

    Erste

    Haelfte, p.

    223.

    My

    own

    translation.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    4/27

    PLATO'S

    DOCTRINE

    OF TRUTH: ORTHOTES

    OR

    ALEiTHEIA?

    159

    sour had miraculously egained

    ts

    sweetness,

    places

    an unbearable

    train

    on

    our

    credulity.

    A

    field

    of inquiry

    which has reached

    such

    a state

    of

    confusion

    calls for

    a

    radically

    new

    approach.

    To many interpretersof Plato, Heidegger's essay entitled Platons

    Lehre von

    der

    Wahrheit

    3

    seemed

    to open

    the

    way toward a radical

    reappraisal

    of

    the dialogues.

    For

    when

    coming to

    terms

    with the great

    thinkers

    of

    the Western

    tradition,

    Heidegger

    does

    not rest content

    with

    surface

    meanings,

    but penetrates

    o the very

    foundation,

    o the

    usually

    unexpressed round

    upon which

    the philosophy

    under consideration

    ests:

    Die Lehre eines

    Denkers

    ist das in

    seinem

    Sagen Ungesagte,

    dem der

    Mensch

    ausgesetzt

    wird, auf dass

    er

    daffir sich verschwende.

    Damit wir

    das

    Ungesagte

    eines Denkers, welcher

    Art es

    auch sei,

    erfahren und

    inskiinftig

    wissen k6nnen, miissen

    wir sein Gesagtes

    Bedenken.'4

    In

    his essay

    Heidegger

    sets

    out

    to show that

    the

    unheralded

    but fateful

    event

    in

    the dialogues

    ies

    in the transition

    o a new conception

    of truth,

    a

    conception

    which

    has controlled

    philosophic

    hinking

    o this

    very day.

    Truth as

    aletheia

    (unhiddenness),

    according

    to

    Heidegger, is

    the older

    and more basic

    notion.

    It is

    situation-directed

    nd hence

    requires

    a

    flexible

    mind,

    sensitive to

    the flux

    of things.

    Truth

    as orthotes

    (correct-

    ness) presupposes

    fixed standards

    of

    judgment

    and

    is therefore

    likely

    to foster a certainrigidityof outlook.'5 Heideggerfurtherclaims that

    13

    Martin Heidegger,

    Platons Lehre

    von der

    Wahrheit. Zweite

    Auflage,

    Bern,

    1954.

    14

    Ibid., p. 5.

    The 'doctrine'

    of a thinker

    is that which

    is left unsaid in

    what

    he says,

    to which man is

    exposed in

    order to expend himself

    upon it. In order

    to

    learn and henceforth

    know what a thinker

    has left unsaid,

    whatever

    it

    may be,

    it

    is necessary

    to consider

    what he has

    said.

    (Transl.

    by John Barlow in Philosophy

    in the

    Twentieth Century ed. by William Barrett and Henry D. Aiken.

    New

    York,

    1962, p. 251.) Translations

    cannot adequately

    reflect the power

    and

    suggestiveness

    of Heidegger's language. It seemed therefore justified to cite the original German

    in the

    text of this paper and

    add the

    translation in the

    footnotes

    as an aid to the

    reader.

    '5

    It should be

    noted that

    Heidegger does

    not simply

    substitute one conception

    of truth for another.

    Instead

    he tries to show

    that truth

    as orth6tes or correctness

    is merely

    part

    of or derivative from

    a more

    integral -phenomenon,

    namely,

    truth

    as

    aletheia.

    Consider,

    he

    suggests in Sein

    und Zeit (Sechste

    Auflage.

    Tfibingen,

    1949,

    p. 217) a man with

    his back

    turned toward the

    wall making

    the assertion:

    The picture

    on the wall does

    not hang

    straight. The assertion

    is found

    to be true

    if, upon

    facing

    the wall, the man discovers

    the

    picture in the condition

    described.

    The assertion -does not refer to representations or images, but to the concrete

    situation

    and

    nothing else:

    Jede Interpretation,

    die hier

    etwas anderes einschiebt,

    das im

    nur

    vorstellendenAussagen

    soil gemeint

    sein, verfilscht den

    phenomenalen

    Tatbestand

    dessen,

    worilber ausgesagt

    wird.

    (Ibid., pp. 217-218.)

    The

    assertion

    may

    be merely thought;

    or

    it

    may

    be expressed in

    a

    sentence

    which

    allows another

    to

    share

    in

    the view of reality

    to

    which

    the assertion leads.

    The

    sentence may be

    passed

    on

    from

    person to person,

    without a

    renewal of the contact

    with

    reality.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    5/27

    160

    PHILOSOPHY

    NDPHENOMENOLOGICAL

    ESEARCH

    becauseof

    the decline

    of aletheia

    and the simultaneous

    ise of

    orthotes

    there

    is in Plato's

    writings

    a persistent ambiguity.'6 Now if

    Heidegger's

    findings should prove

    correct,

    then one

    would

    expect the confusion

    in

    the conceptionof truth to be reflectedin Plato's attitudeof mind, and

    we

    would

    then be able to

    put our

    finger on the

    cause of the

    perplexing

    fluctuation

    between

    a liberal and

    a dogmatic

    spirit which seems to

    run

    through

    all the dialogues.

    The subtlety

    of Heidegger's

    analysis

    and the

    suggestiveness

    and rich-

    ness

    of his

    thought sorely

    tempt

    the reader simply

    to

    accept his con-

    clusions. But were

    he to

    do so, he would

    overlook

    the fact

    that

    the

    Allegory

    of

    the Cave, a

    small and

    relatively

    unimportant

    portion of

    a

    single dialogue, forms the main basis of Heidegger's argument. In order

    to do justice

    to his

    claim, Heidegger,

    as

    he himself admits,

    would have

    to

    examine

    all the dialogues.'7

    So quite apart

    from

    the light which

    all

    of Heidegger's discussions

    of other thinkers

    shed

    on

    his

    own

    thought,

    the

    'essay on Plato

    can be

    considered

    as no

    more than a

    Hinweis,

    an

    indication

    as to a possible

    fresh

    approach

    to Plato.

    And of these

    Hinweise Heidegger

    himself

    has said in

    another

    connection hat

    they

    are

    too

    often unthinkingly

    passed on

    as the opinions

    of

    their

    author when

    they

    should serve as

    Weisung

    ... sich selber

    auf den Weg

    zu

    machen,

    um der gewiesenenSache selbst nachzudenken directions or the road

    of

    independent

    reflection on

    the

    matter

    pointed

    out which

    each

    must

    travel for

    himself.)

    18

    What militates

    most

    strongly,

    however, against

    an uncritical

    accept-

    ance

    of the

    result of

    Heidegger's

    investigation,

    is the

    fact

    that

    he

    approaches

    Plato as

    he

    had

    previously

    approached

    Aristotle,

    Descartes,

    and

    Kant. These thinkers

    make

    an effort

    to

    give

    a

    clear

    account of

    their

    position,

    and so

    it

    is

    proper

    for

    Heidegger

    to

    start with

    their

    explicit

    utterancesand then attempt to penetrate

    to, the

    implied, unexpressed

    ground.

    Plato, by

    contrast,

    not

    unlike

    the

    great

    tragedians,

    eaches

    by

    While

    it still

    refers

    to

    things,

    to

    concrete situations,

    these

    are no

    longer

    experienced

    by the

    one

    hearing

    or

    seeing

    the sentence.

    The assertion

    now

    hardens

    into

    some

    sort

    of

    independent

    reality,

    and

    in

    that independent

    state

    it

    may

    be

    said

    either

    to

    conform

    or

    not to

    conform

    to

    things.

    Only

    in that secondary

    sense can

    it be

    said

    that

    truth

    lies

    in the

    assertion.

    But to regard

    truth

    of the

    assertion

    as the

    only

    truth

    is to

    lose

    sight

    of the original

    heuristic

    and

    apophantic

    function

    of

    the

    asser-

    tion:

    Die

    Aussage

    ist wahr,

    bedeutet:

    sie

    entdeckt

    das

    Seiende

    an

    ihm

    selbst.

    Sie

    sagt aus, sie zeigt auf, sie 'Thsstsehen' (apophansis) das Seiende in seiner Ent-

    decktheit.

    Wahrsein

    (Wahrheit)

    der

    Aussage

    muss

    verstanden

    werden

    als ent-

    deckendsein.

    (Ibid.,

    p.

    218.)

    16

    Heidegger,

    Platons

    Lehre Von

    Der Wahrheit,

    p.

    42.

    17

    Ibid., p.

    5.

    18

    Heidegger's

    Preface

    to:

    William

    J.

    Richardson,

    S.

    J.,

    Heidegger:

    Through

    Phenomenology

    to Thought.

    The

    Hague,

    1963,

    pp.

    viii-ix.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    6/27

    PLATO'S DOCTRINE OF TRUTH: ORTHOTES OR ALETHEIA?

    161

    indirection.

    As

    a result he usually does

    not immediately eveal his posi-

    tion, for

    he is concerned more with

    the stimulation

    and subsequent

    direction

    of thought rather

    than with the advocacy

    of specific

    doctrines.

    And so the insight which Plato is tryingto convey is somethingwhich

    must happen

    in the

    mind of the reader, as the result

    of a clash

    of ideas

    which

    occurs in the dialogue.'9

    It is doubtful whether

    the dramatic

    aspects of Plato's dialogues

    can

    be ignored

    with impunity.

    We propose, therefore,

    to test

    Heidegger's

    theory

    of a change in

    the conceptionof truth in

    the light of

    an inter-

    pretation

    which attempts to allow

    full sway to

    the dramatic elements

    of

    the

    dialogues.And

    if we take as our point of

    departure

    a

    view which

    emerges from the dialectical interplay of opposing positions, we are

    likely to

    reach conclusions

    which are quite different

    from those

    which

    Heidegger derives from

    a literal

    reading.

    In

    fact it might well

    be

    that

    Plato

    and Heideggerare then found

    to be allies

    rather than adversaries

    in the

    struggle to

    attain to

    a

    satisfactory

    conception of

    truth. Since

    a

    considerationof

    all

    the dialogues

    is

    impossible,

    we

    shall

    try

    to do

    the

    next best thing, namely

    to discuss

    those dialogueswhich

    most

    obviously

    seem to confirm Heidegger's

    contention.

    But

    first, merely

    by way

    of

    reminder,

    a few words about Heidegger's

    analysis

    of the Allegory of

    the

    Cave.

    The

    very locale

    of the allegory,

    as

    Heidegger

    points out,

    suggests,

    ruth

    as unhiddenness:

    he

    dark cave, the sunlit world

    outside,

    various

    levels

    of

    light

    and darkness between

    the two.

    Each

    stage

    in the

    paideia

    of

    the inhabitants

    of the

    cave has

    its own

    truth,

    its own

    revela-

    tion of

    reality. The

    shadows which

    the

    chained

    prisoners

    see on

    the wall

    are not simply nothing.

    These

    shadows

    offer

    themselves

    or their

    reality

    to

    the

    understanding

    f

    the

    prisoners.

    The latter

    perceive

    19This

    is clearly

    enough

    stated in the Seventh

    Letter,

    which

    is

    generally

    regarded

    as

    authentic:

    ....

    in regard

    to ...

    the subjects to which

    I

    devote

    myself

    -...

    I

    certainly

    have composed

    no

    work

    in

    regard

    to

    it,

    nor

    shall

    I ever

    do

    so in

    the

    future,

    for there

    is no way of putting

    it in

    words

    like other

    studies.

    Acquaintance

    with

    it comes

    after

    a long

    period

    of attendance

    on instruction

    in the

    subject

    itself

    and

    of close

    companionship,

    when,

    suddenly,

    like

    a

    blaze

    kindled

    by

    a

    leaping

    spark,

    it is

    generated

    in

    the soul

    and at

    once

    becomes

    self-sustaining.

    (Seventh

    Letter,

    par.

    341c-d. Translated

    by L. A. Post.

    The Collected

    Dialogues

    of

    Plato.

    Including

    the

    Letters,

    edited

    by Edith

    Hamilton

    and

    Huntington

    Cairns.

    Bollingen

    Series LXXI, New York, 1961, pp. 1588-1589.) Italics added.

    Note

    also the

    remarks

    on

    the

    indirect

    method

    of

    teaching

    in

    Republic,

    Book

    VII,

    par. 518;

    Vol. I,

    p.

    777;

    Apology

    par.

    31,

    Vol. I, p. 414;

    Theatetus

    par.

    149,

    Vol.

    II,

    p. 150.

    The Dialogues of Plato,

    translated

    by

    B.

    Jowett,

    in two

    volumes.

    New

    York,

    1937.

    Unless

    otherwise

    indicated,

    all

    quotations

    from

    Plato's

    dialogues

    refer to

    this

    edition.

    20

    Platons

    Lehre

    von

    der

    Wahrheit,

    p. 33.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    7/27

    162

    PHILOSOPHYAND PHENOMENOLOGICALESEARCH

    them, but do not or cannot inquire into the

    ground of their

    being,

    that

    is, the fire and the objects which make them

    mere shadows. The cave

    dweller who is released from his, chains,but

    confused by the brightness

    of the fire in the,cave does not at once experience

    a higherkind of truth

    or

    reality;

    in fact he considers. he shadows

    which he saw before his

    release as more true and more real than what confronts and

    bedazzles

    him now. It is only when he gets outside the cave and becomes accus-

    tomed to the sun in whose light real things present themselvesthat he

    is face to face with genuine truth and reality.

    After he has reentered

    the cave and overcome the first few moments

    of confusion, he sees the

    shadows again,

    but

    now he knows them as shadows, with merely

    a

    borrowedkind of reality.

    There

    is, however, also the fire, the

    things outside the cave which

    stand

    for the ideas and the sun which represents

    he

    idea

    of

    ideas,

    the

    source of intelligibility and reality for all

    things. The ideas are

    the

    standardson a higher level to which beings

    on a lower level

    must

    con-

    form. And

    according o Heidegger he emphasis

    s being placed,

    not on

    the levels of truth, but on the ideas:

    Die

    Unverborgenheit wird zwar

    in

    ihren verschiedenen Stufen genannt, aber

    sie wird nur daraufhin bedacht, wie sie das Erscheinende

    in seinem Aussehen

    (eidos) zugiinglich und dieses Sichzeigende (idea) sichtbar macht. Die eigent-

    liche

    Besinnung geht

    auf das in der Helle

    des Scheins gewiihrte Erscheinen

    des Aussehens. Dieses gibt die Aussicht auf

    das, als was jegliches Seiende

    anwest. Die eigentliche Besinnung gilt der idea.21

    A

    more

    shift of

    emphasis

    alone

    would,

    of course,

    not

    be

    very

    con-

    vincing,

    and

    so

    Heidegger

    points

    to the well-known

    heory

    of

    ideas,

    and

    especially

    to

    a

    passage

    from Book VI

    of the

    Republic

    which

    seems

    to

    eliminate

    all

    doubt.

    There

    the

    philosopher-kings

    re,

    described

    as

    men

    who have

    in their soul a clear

    pattern

    of

    perfect truth,

    which

    they

    might study

    in

    every

    detail

    and

    constantly

    refer

    to,

    as a

    painter

    looks

    to his model, before they proceed to embody

    notions of justice, honour,

    and

    goodness

    in

    earthly

    institutions.

    2

    The paideia

    is now

    understood

    to consist

    in

    turning oward

    and

    steadfastly

    adhering

    o

    the

    ideas,which

    21

    Ibid., p. 34.

    To be sure unhiddenness

    is named in

    its

    various stages,

    but one can only

    con-

    sider it in

    the way it makes

    the

    phenomenal

    accessible

    in its outward appearance

    (eidos) and

    the way

    it makes this

    emerging

    (idea) visible.

    Consciousness,

    properly

    speaking,

    has to do with

    the

    way outward

    appearance

    manifests itself

    and is

    preserved

    in the brightness

    of

    its steady appearance. Through

    this

    one can

    view

    whatever each being

    is present

    as. Consciousness,

    properly

    speaking,

    applies

    to

    the

    idea.

    (Transl.

    John

    Barlow, in

    Barrett

    and Aiken,

    op. cit.,

    p. 261.

    22

    The

    Republic

    of Plato. Trans. by F. M. Cornford.

    New

    York, 1945,

    Book

    VI,

    par.

    484, p.

    190.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    8/27

    PLATO'S DOCTRINE OF TRUTH: ORTHOTESOR

    ALETHEIA?

    163

    serve as a standard

    n the light of which

    all

    human activity

    is to be

    evaluated:

    Die Befreiung

    ergibt sich

    nicht schon aus der

    Losldsung

    der

    Fesseln

    und

    besteht nicht in der Zuigellosigkeit,sondern beginnt erst als die stetige Ein-

    gewdhnungin das Festmachen

    des Blickes auf

    die festen Grenzen der in

    ihrem

    Aussehen feststehenden Dinge.

    Die

    eigentliche

    Befreiung ist die Stetigkeit der

    Zuwendungzu dem, was in

    einem

    Aussehen

    erscheint und in diesem Erschei-

    nen das Unverborgenste ist.23

    The notion

    of truth inherent in the theory

    of ideas, together with its

    corresponding

    attitude of

    mind, seems in fact to be the very

    opposite

    of aletheia. Instead of turning

    to things,

    to'

    the concrete,

    ituation, the

    inquirerturns.

    o the

    ideas;

    instead of flexibility

    and malleability,

    here

    is now rigid adherenceto set standards.Heidegger'sconclusion seems

    inescapable:

    Indem Platon von

    der idea sagt, sie sei

    die Herrin, die Unverborgenheit

    zulasse,

    verweist

    er in

    ein Ungesagtes,

    dass namlich

    fortan sich das Wesen

    der Wahrheit

    nicht als das Wesen der Unverborgenheit aus

    eigener Wesen-

    fiulle

    entfaltet,

    sondern sich auf

    das

    Wesen

    der

    idea

    verlagert.

    Das

    Wesen

    der

    Wahrheit

    gibt

    den

    Grundzug

    der

    Unverborgenheit preis....

    Wahrheit

    wird

    zur

    orthotes,

    zu

    Richtigkeit

    des Vernehmens

    und

    Aussagens.24

    The

    theory of ideas is generally regarded

    as established

    Platonic

    doctrine,so that a contention,such as Heidegger's,which is implied by

    it, should

    have no difficulty

    in

    finding

    acceptance.

    But what happens

    if

    we

    tear ourselves oose

    from

    the accustomed iteral

    reading

    of the

    text

    and hold ourselves

    open

    and

    receptive

    to

    the

    possible

    effects of the

    dialectical

    nterplay

    of idea?

    The

    Euthyphro

    seems

    particularly

    uitable

    for

    making

    the

    experiment;

    it contains

    strong

    evidence in favor of

    Heidegger's thesis

    and

    at the same

    time

    is not

    lacking

    in dramatic

    elements.

    The dialogueshows us Socratesengagedin the search for the defini-

    23

    Platons

    Lehre

    von

    der Wahrheit,

    p.

    30. Italics

    added.

    Liberation

    does

    not take

    place

    in

    the mere act

    of getting

    free from

    the

    chains

    and

    does

    not consist

    merely

    in being

    untrammeled,

    but

    begins

    first

    as

    the

    steady

    orienting

    of

    oneself

    so

    that

    one's

    gaze

    is made

    fast to the

    firm

    limits

    of the

    things

    standing

    fast

    in

    their

    outward

    appearance.

    Actual

    liberation

    lies

    in the

    steadiness

    with

    which

    one turns

    towards

    what manifests

    itself

    in its outward

    appearance

    and

    is in

    this

    manifesting

    the

    most unhidden.

    (Transl.

    by

    Barlow,

    in

    Barrett

    and

    Aiken,

    op. cit.,

    p.

    259.)

    24

    Platons Lehre von der Wahrheit,pp.

    41-42.

    When

    Plato

    says

    that

    the

    idea is

    the master permitting

    unhiddenness

    he

    banishes

    to something

    left

    unsaid the

    fact

    that

    henceforth

    the

    essence

    of

    truth

    does

    not

    unfold

    out

    of

    its own

    essential

    fullness-as

    the

    essence

    of

    unhiddenness,

    but

    shifts

    its abode

    to the

    essence

    of

    the idea.

    The essence

    of

    truth

    relinquishes

    the.

    basic

    feature

    of

    unhiddenness....

    Truth

    becomes

    orth6tes,

    correctness

    of the

    ability

    to

    perceive

    and to

    declare something.

    (Tr.

    Barrett

    and

    Aiken,

    p.

    265.)

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    9/27

    164

    PHILOSOPHY

    NDPHENOMENOLOGICAL

    ESEARCH

    tion

    of

    a

    virtue,

    namely

    piety. Euthyphro,

    who

    is not very bright,

    needs

    to

    be

    told

    what

    a definition

    is:

    Is not piety in every

    action

    always

    the same? And

    impiety,

    again

    -

    is it

    not

    always

    the

    opposite

    of

    piety,

    and

    also

    the

    same with

    itself, having,

    as

    impiety,

    one

    notion

    which

    includes

    whatever

    is

    impious.25

    And

    then Socrates

    describes

    the

    function

    of

    a

    definition,

    which

    when

    found

    would

    make

    moral judgments

    so simple

    and so

    reliable:

    Tell me

    what is

    the

    nature

    of this

    idea,

    and

    then

    I shall have

    a

    standard

    to

    which

    I

    may look,

    and

    by

    which

    I

    may

    measure

    actions,

    whether

    yours

    or

    those

    of any

    one

    else,

    and then

    I shall

    be able

    to say

    that such

    and

    such

    an

    action

    is

    pious,

    such

    another

    impious.26

    The enquiryhas beenoccasionedby a concretemoralproblem.Euthyphro

    is

    about

    to institute

    proceedings

    against

    his father

    for causing

    the

    death

    of

    a

    serf

    through

    gross

    negligence.

    To

    the

    objections

    of

    his family

    that

    a

    son

    is impious

    who

    prosecutes

    his

    father,

    he replies

    with

    an

    appeal

    to

    the behavior

    of the

    gods.

    Do

    not

    men,

    he

    argues,

    regard

    Zeus

    as

    the

    best

    and

    most

    righteous

    of

    the gods?

    -

    And

    yet they

    admit

    that

    he

    bound

    his

    father (Cronos)

    because

    he

    wickedly

    devoured

    his

    sons,

    and

    that

    he

    too

    had

    punished

    his

    own

    father

    (Uranus)

    or

    a similar

    reason.

    7

    Through

    his

    insistence

    on a

    definition

    as a

    norm

    of

    judgment,

    Socrates

    extricatesthe problemfrom the realm of religion and mythology and

    raises

    the

    discussion

    to

    the

    level

    of

    rational

    inquiry.

    And

    what

    if

    Euthyphro

    does

    prove

    to me,

    he

    asks,

    that

    all the gods

    regard

    the

    death

    of the

    serf

    as

    unjust,

    how

    do

    I

    know

    anything

    more

    of

    the

    nature

    of

    piety

    and

    impiety?

    28

    From

    Mythos

    to

    Logos

    one

    might

    be

    inclined

    to name

    the

    theme

    of

    this

    brief

    dialogue.

    Of course,

    a definition

    is not actually

    found,

    but

    this

    is usually

    thought

    to be

    attributable

    to the Socratic

    method:

    Socrates

    meansus to find the definitionfor ourselves.As againstthe doctrinaire

    position

    of

    Euthyphro,

    Socrates'

    call

    for a definition

    is very

    alluring.

    Leaving

    dark superstition

    ar

    behind,

    one

    feels transported

    nto the

    clear

    light

    of

    reason.

    The

    fact,

    however,

    that we

    have

    left behind

    not

    only

    superstition

    but the

    concrete

    situation

    as well should

    give

    us

    pause.

    Just

    how,

    we

    might

    ask,

    would

    the

    definition

    of a moral excellence

    function

    in

    the

    kaleidoscopic

    lux of

    human

    relationships?

    Would

    it tell

    us

    that

    such

    and

    such

    an

    act is

    good

    or

    bad and therefore

    ought

    to

    be

    pursued

    or

    shunned regardless

    of

    the

    consequences?

    What

    would

    happen

    to

    human responsibility?Could we simply say that our task is to adhere

    25

    Euthyphro,

    par. 5,

    op.

    cit.,

    Vol.

    I,

    p.

    386.

    26

    Ibid., par.

    6, p.

    387.

    Italics

    added.

    27

    Ibid., par.

    5-6,

    pp.

    386-387.

    28

    Ibid.,

    par.

    9,

    p.

    390.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    10/27

    PLATO'S

    DOCTRINE

    OF

    TRUTH:

    ORTHOTES

    OR ALETHEIA?

    165

    to

    the

    definition

    or rule, and

    that

    the

    consequences

    are

    not our

    concern?

    Does

    not the

    successful

    use

    of a fixed definition

    presuppose

    a

    stable,

    unchangeable

    world,

    that

    is,

    one

    in which

    we clearly do

    not live?

    More

    often than not we must choose not betweengood and evil, but between

    the

    greater

    of two

    goods

    or

    the lesser

    of two evils.

    But just

    what

    will

    turn

    out to

    be

    the

    greater

    good

    or lesser

    evil only

    the given

    circum-

    stances

    will reveal.

    Unless,

    he

    whole

    history

    of the

    world

    is spread

    out

    before

    us,

    we

    can

    never

    say

    once

    and for

    all that

    such and such

    an

    evil

    will

    never

    be outdone

    by

    a greater

    evil and therefore

    must be

    shunned

    always

    and

    no matter

    what the

    circumstances.

    Let

    him know

    how

    to

    choose

    the mean

    and

    avoid the extremes

    on

    either side, as far as possible,

    9

    Socrates warns

    at the end

    of

    the

    Republic.

    But in

    the

    Euthyphro

    he

    himself

    proposes

    an

    extreme.

    Shall

    we

    say that

    when

    Plato

    wrote

    this dialogue

    he

    had

    not

    yet

    attained

    to

    the wisdom

    shown

    in

    the

    Republic?

    Or would it

    be more reasonable

    o

    assume

    that he

    had

    Socrates

    play

    the

    devil's

    advocate?

    Then

    the

    Socratic

    method would

    not be

    directed

    at

    Euthyphro,

    who

    evidently

    learns

    nothing

    from

    his

    encounter

    with

    Socrates,

    nor would

    it consist

    simply

    in the question

    and

    answer

    method.

    It would

    rather

    seem

    that

    by

    pitting

    one

    extreme

    against

    the

    other,

    Plato

    is trying

    to make

    the

    attentive

    readersee that it is not enoughto abjuresuperstitionand have recourse

    to

    reason.

    For

    the appeal

    to

    a

    rule

    divorced

    from

    life

    can

    spring

    from

    as

    ruthless

    an attitude

    as that

    inspired

    by

    superstition.

    And

    just

    as

    Euthyphro's

    unshakeable

    onviction

    s

    unjustified

    ince it implies

    famili-

    arity

    with

    the will

    of the gods,

    so

    intellectual

    certainty

    n moral

    matters

    presupposes

    a

    definition

    which

    the

    world

    in which

    we live

    does

    not

    allow.30

    Toward

    the end

    of

    the

    dialogue,

    Socrates

    suggests

    that piety

    be

    defined

    as

    a kind of

    justice

    or

    ministration

    with reference

    to

    the

    gods.

    But what

    benefits can possibly accrue to the gods from the,deeds of

    men?

    Is

    there

    anything

    which only

    men

    can do? Tell

    me,

    oh

    tell

    me,

    Socrates

    urges,

    what

    is

    that

    fair work which

    the

    gods

    do by

    the

    help

    of

    our

    ministrations ?

    1

    Euthyphro,

    of course,

    does

    not know

    the

    answer,

    and

    Socrates

    refuses

    to

    give

    it.

    It seems

    plausible,

    however,

    that

    this

    task

    has

    something

    to do with

    bringing

    order into one's,

    own

    life

    and

    helping

    in the

    establishment

    and maintenance

    of order

    in the

    com-

    munity.

    For

    neither

    the individual's

    ife nor the life

    of the

    community

    29

    Republic,

    Book

    X,

    par.

    619,

    p.

    876.

    30

    Plato

    says

    as

    much

    explicitly

    in

    a

    later

    dialogue:

    The

    difference

    of

    men

    and

    actions,

    and

    the endless

    irregular

    movements

    of

    human

    things,

    do

    not

    admit

    of

    any

    universal

    and simple

    rule.

    And

    no

    art

    whatsoever

    can

    lay

    down

    a

    rule

    which

    will

    last

    for

    all

    time.

    Statesman,

    par.

    294,

    Vol.

    II,

    p.

    322.

    81

    Euthyphro,

    par.

    13,

    p.

    396.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    11/27

    166 PHILOSOPHYNDPHENOMENOLOGICALESEARCH

    is provided n a ready-made orm. And how

    can there be free

    men in

    a free society, unless they are accountable

    or their own way

    of life? It

    is as if the, gods

    who are responsiblefor

    the order in the world, had

    stopped short of humanaffairs and imposedupon men the task of com-

    pleting the ordering

    process..

    To bring about

    and preserve proper relations,among men

    is a con-

    tinuous,never-ending

    ask. Neither cherished raditions, or deeply rooted

    desires are

    a

    reliable

    guide. We must tear

    ourselves, oose from habitual

    modes

    of

    behavior

    and from the immediateneeds arisingout

    of the con-

    crete

    situation n order to gain

    a

    wider

    perspective or successfulaction.

    But neither can we expect to discoverfinal

    answers in an abstract

    realm

    of ideas. Only the kind of reflection which allows for the intricate

    interplayof idea and situation offers any

    hope for the establishment

    of

    satisfactoryhuman

    relations.

    If we are willing to accept this, nterpretationhen we identify Plato's

    position with neither

    of the two adopted

    by the participants o

    the

    dis-

    cussion. We would

    rather see it midway between the blind

    superstition

    and traditionalism

    f Euthyphroand the rigid rationalismwhich

    in this

    dialogue Plato chooses to place into

    the mouth of Socrates.

    And then

    the Euthyphro would

    not confirm the, findings

    of

    Heidegger

    in the

    Allegory of the Cave. For while Heidegger there sees aletheia under the

    yoke

    of the

    idea,32

    it now

    appears

    hat the idea stands in the

    service of

    aletheia, helping the

    truth of things to

    shine forth in its own light.

    While

    the

    Euthyphro,

    on a literal

    reading,

    would

    place

    moral

    behavior

    under the

    control of

    a

    definition,

    the

    Crito

    would subject

    the

    individual

    to the rule of law.

    Socrates

    s,

    usually

    thought to have

    died rather

    than

    break

    the law which

    condemnedhim to death

    in

    spite

    of

    his

    innocence,

    and this

    view

    can

    be amply supported

    by

    references o

    the text. Socrates

    stresses

    the

    importance

    of

    the

    laws

    for

    the welfare

    of the citizens.

    They

    regulate the

    marriage aws

    and

    provide

    for the education

    of the child.

    Well

    then,

    since

    you

    were

    brought

    into the world

    and nurtured

    and

    educated

    by us, Socrates

    has

    the laws

    say,

    can

    you deny

    in the

    first

    place

    that

    you are

    our child and slave,

    as

    your

    fathers,

    were

    before

    you?

    And if this is true

    you

    are

    not

    on

    equal

    terms

    with

    us;

    nor

    can

    you

    think

    that you have

    a

    right to do to us what

    we are doing

    to

    you

    ...

    Has

    a

    philosopher

    ike you failed to

    discover

    that our

    country

    is more to

    be

    valued and

    higher

    and holier

    far than

    mother or

    father or

    any

    ances-

    32

    Indem

    Platon

    von

    der

    idea

    sagt,

    sie

    sei

    die

    Herrin

    die

    Unverborgenheit

    zulasse,

    verweist

    er

    in

    ein

    Ungesagtes,

    dass

    niinlich

    fortan

    sich

    das

    Wesen

    der

    Wahrheit

    nicht als

    das

    Wesen

    der

    Unverborgenheit

    aus

    eigener Wesensfillie

    ent-

    faltet, sondern

    sich

    auf

    das Wesen

    der idea verlagert.

    Das Wesen

    der

    Wahrheit

    gibt den Grundzug

    der Unverborgenheit

    preis.

    Platons

    Lehre

    von

    der Wahrheit,

    p.

    41.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    12/27

    PLATO'S DOCTRINE

    OF TRUTH:

    ORTHOTES

    OR ALEfTHEIA?

    167

    tor...

    . 33 The

    modem reader

    might

    stir uneasily

    at this

    point, for

    he

    is wary

    about too

    submissive

    an

    attitude

    toward

    the state. But

    the

    next

    few

    lines are

    bound to make

    him cry out in

    dissent:

    And

    when we

    are

    punished

    by

    her, whether

    with

    imprisonment

    or stripes,

    the

    punishment

    is

    to be

    endured

    in silence;

    and if she leads

    us to wounds

    or

    death

    in battle,

    thither

    we

    follow

    as

    is right;

    neither

    may any

    one yield

    or

    retreat

    or

    leave

    his

    rank,

    but whether

    in battle

    or in

    a

    court

    of law,

    or in any

    other

    place,

    he must do what his

    city

    and his country

    order

    him.34

    Such

    a

    principle

    could

    have

    exonerated

    he worst of

    the war

    criminals

    after

    the

    last war,

    aside

    from

    the

    dictator

    himself.

    It is true that

    the

    imaginary

    aws

    try

    to

    mitigate

    the

    harshness

    of their

    demand

    by

    pro-

    claimingto any Athenian

    by

    the

    liberty

    which

    we allow

    him, that if

    he

    does

    not

    like

    us

    when

    he

    has become

    of

    age

    and has

    seen

    the ways

    of

    the

    city,

    and

    made

    our

    acquaintance,

    he

    may go

    where

    he pleases

    and

    take

    his goods

    with

    him.

    35

    But

    even

    with

    the best

    of laws

    it

    can

    come

    about

    that

    strict

    application

    of the

    law

    would

    work

    an

    injustice

    so

    severe

    as

    to

    make

    disobedience

    a

    moral

    obligation.

    Nor can

    it be

    rightly

    claimed,

    as the

    laws

    do,

    that

    he

    who has

    experience

    of the

    manner

    in

    which

    we

    order justice

    and administer

    he

    state,

    and still

    remains,

    has

    entered

    nto

    an

    implied

    contract

    hat he

    will

    do

    as

    we command

    him.

    36

    A citizen can never, without forfeitinghis freedom and responsibility,

    give

    such

    a blank

    pledge

    of

    obedience

    in

    complete

    disregard

    of

    existing

    circumstances.

    Even

    more

    embarrassing

    o

    a literal

    interpretation

    s

    the

    fact

    that

    at

    the

    beginning

    of

    the

    dialogue,

    just

    before

    the discussion

    with

    Crito gets

    under way,

    Socrates

    adopts

    a

    position

    which

    is the very

    op-

    posite

    of

    an

    unquestioning

    ubmission

    o law:

    And

    therefore

    we

    ought

    to

    consider

    whether

    I shall

    or shall

    not do

    as

    you

    say.

    For I

    am

    and

    always

    have

    been

    one

    of those

    natures

    who must

    be

    guided

    by

    reason,

    whatever

    the

    reason may

    be which

    upon

    reflection

    appears

    to me to be the best.37

    And just

    as

    the Eichmanns,

    if

    unquestioning

    submission

    to

    the

    law

    is

    made

    a

    virtue,

    can

    shift

    responsibility

    o,

    higher

    authority,

    so

    the

    Oswalds,

    if

    individual

    reason reigns

    supreme,

    can

    justify

    their

    misdeed

    by

    appealing

    o

    the

    outcome

    of

    their own

    reflections.

    In the

    Crito,

    even

    more

    so

    than

    in the

    Euthyphro,

    he

    two

    extremes

    are clearly

    stated.

    It

    is

    reasonable'

    o assume

    that they serve

    Plato

    to

    bring

    home

    the

    paradoxical

    nature

    of civic

    virtue.For

    a

    good

    citizen

    at

    33

    Crito,

    par.

    50-51,

    pp.

    434-435.

    34

    Ibid.,

    par.

    51,

    p.

    435.

    Italics

    added.

    35

    Ibid.

    36 Ibid.

    37

    Ibid.,

    par.

    46,

    p.

    430.

    Italics

    added.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    13/27

    168

    PHILOSOPHY

    NDPHENOMENOLOGICAL

    ESEARCH

    one

    and the

    same time must

    be

    obedient

    and yet hold himself

    responsible

    for the

    consequences

    of his

    acts. If

    we ask

    how this

    is

    possible,

    we

    will

    find no

    direct

    answer in the

    dialogue.

    We might,

    however, discover

    a

    hint, such as the one containedin the followingremarkmade by the

    laws:

    We

    do

    not

    impose

    (our

    commands)

    rudely, but give

    him

    the alternative

    of

    obeying

    or convincing us ... that

    our

    commands

    are

    unjust.38

    To convince

    the ideal

    laws, which

    Plato

    elsewhere

    identifies

    with

    reason,39 can

    only mean

    that

    we must

    show

    disobedience

    to constitute

    the lesser

    evil.

    Vital

    as the

    laws

    may be

    to

    the maintenance

    of order

    and hence

    to the

    existence

    of

    the state,

    there

    may be

    occasions

    when

    the harm which comes from the disregardor suspensionof the, law is

    outweighed

    by

    the evil

    consequences

    which would

    follow upon

    enforce-

    ment of

    the

    law. So laws

    have

    no absolute

    power.

    And now

    in order

    not to

    give reason

    unrestricted

    ontrol

    we must

    add

    that the

    sheer

    fact

    that a law exists

    ought

    to weigh

    heavily

    in

    the

    determination

    of the

    greater

    good

    or the lesser

    evil. So both

    law and reason

    must control

    our

    actions

    but

    in such

    a

    way

    as to make

    one

    restrain

    he

    other. However,

    as we

    have seen

    in

    the Euthyphro,

    he greater

    good

    or the

    lesser

    evil

    are not

    discovered

    by looking

    to

    a

    definition

    or idea.

    They

    arise

    out of

    the

    interrelations

    of

    the

    various

    goods,

    and

    evils

    which are present or

    likely

    to occur

    under given

    circumstances.

    And

    so

    by trying

    to resolve

    the

    paradox

    presented

    n

    the

    dialogue,

    and following

    the

    suggestion

    of

    Socrates to

    their

    natural

    conclusion,

    we

    are led back

    to the

    concrete

    situation.

    But

    this

    means

    that Plato's

    thought

    takes,

    a

    direction

    which

    is

    the very

    opposite

    of

    the one

    it is

    said

    to

    take

    in the

    opinion

    of Martin

    Heidegger.

    So

    far

    we

    have

    dealt

    only

    with

    two

    of the earlier

    dialogues,

    n

    which

    the liberalspiritof Socrates s said to be still alive. In the later dialogues,

    the

    more

    dogmatic

    character

    of

    Plato's own

    philosophy

    is,

    alleged

    to

    come to the

    fore. So

    it

    may

    well

    be

    that we have not as

    yet

    come

    to

    grips with

    Plato's doctrine

    of truth. Since

    the theory

    of ideas forms

    a

    prominent

    part

    of

    Heidegger's

    argument,40

    a

    brief examination

    of

    it,

    especially

    as

    it

    appears

    n the

    Phaedo,

    becomes

    unavoidable.

    A

    full

    discussion

    of the Phaedo

    is,

    of

    course,

    not

    possible.

    But

    the

    theory

    of

    ideas,

    which

    has

    traditionally

    been

    regarded

    as its main

    philo-

    sophic

    yield,

    should

    at

    least

    be

    placed

    into

    its immediatecontext.

    The

    38

    Ibid.,

    par.

    52,

    p.

    436.

    39

    We

    must

    ...

    regulate

    our

    cities

    and

    houses

    according

    to

    law, meaning

    by

    the very

    term

    'law'

    the distribution

    of mind.

    Laws,

    Book IV,

    par.

    713,

    Vol.

    II,

    p.

    485.

    40

    Platons

    Lehre

    von

    der

    Wahrheit,

    esp.

    pp.

    20

    ff.

    and

    pp.

    38 ff.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    14/27

    PLATO'S DOCTRINE OF TRUTH: ORTHOTES OR

    ALUTHEIA?

    169

    theoryoccurs

    in Socrates'discussionof his method of inquiry.He relates

    how

    in

    his

    youth he was taken in by

    the nature

    philosophers who

    sought

    for principlesof explanationamong.physical

    hings.

    Is the blood

    the element with which we think, or the air, or the

    fire?

    41

    these are

    questions of the kind which

    Socrates

    said agitated him. But instead

    of

    seeing more

    clearly he

    became more confused; or rather,

    becoming

    aware of

    the distinction between factual

    juxtaposition

    and causal or

    necessary

    connections,

    he

    recognized hat

    what he took

    to be all expla-

    nation was no explanation

    at all:

    For I was fascinated by

    them to such

    a degree that my eyes grew blind

    to

    things

    which

    I

    had seemed to myself,

    and also to others, to know quite

    well;

    I forgot what I had before thought self-evident truths;e.g. such a fact as that

    the growth of man is

    the result of eating

    and drinking; for when

    by the

    digestion

    of food flesh is added to flesh

    and bone

    to bone, and whenever

    there

    is an aggregationof congenial elements,

    the lesser

    bulk becomes larger

    and the small man great.42

    While

    necessary

    connections cannot be

    observed

    between

    things,

    they

    can be detected

    between ideas:

    I was afraid that

    my

    soul

    might

    be blinded

    altogether

    if I looked at things

    with my eyes

    or tried to

    apprehend

    them

    by

    the

    help

    of the senses. And I

    thought

    that I had

    better

    have recourse

    to the

    world of mind and seek there

    the truth of existence.4s

    But this appeal to ideas,

    as he soon

    found

    out,

    was

    not without

    serious

    limitations. The

    ideal would

    be

    to, discover

    an

    ultimate

    principle

    of

    explanation,

    which would

    assign

    to

    each

    thing

    its

    proper place

    in the

    total scheme.

    To such

    a

    principle

    he had

    hoped

    to

    be

    introduced

    by

    Anaxagoas who had

    said that

    mind

    was

    the

    disposer

    and cause

    of

    all.

    44

    But

    Anaxagoras

    disappointed

    him

    because

    he had

    recourse o

    air, and ether,

    and

    water,

    and

    other

    eccentricities.

    5

    Having

    to

    fall

    back on his own resources,Socratescould do no better than assume

    some likely

    principles of

    explanation

    and

    test them

    by

    means

    of their

    synthesizingpower:

    I

    first assumed

    some

    principle

    which

    I

    judged

    to be

    strongest,

    and

    then

    I

    affirmed

    as true whatever

    seemed

    to

    agree

    with

    this,

    whether

    relating

    to

    the

    cause

    or to

    anything

    else;

    and

    that

    which

    disagreed

    I

    regarded

    as

    untrue.46

    41

    Phaedo, par. 96,

    Vol. I, p. 481.

    42 Ibid.

    43

    Ibid., par. 99-100, p. 484.

    44

    Ibid.,

    par. 97, p.

    482.

    Anaxagoras,

    Socrates

    thought,

    would

    give

    him a

    per-

    fect explanation,

    that

    is,

    he would

    tell

    him,

    for

    instance,

    whether the earth

    is

    flat

    or round,

    and then

    he would

    explain

    why

    it is necessarily

    so and

    why

    it is

    best

    that it should

    be

    so.

    45

    Ibid.,

    par. 98, p.

    482.

    46

    Ibid.,

    par. 100, p.

    484.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    15/27

    170

    PHILOSOPHY

    NDPHENOMENOLOGICAL

    ESEARCH

    This

    second

    best mode

    of

    inquiry as

    Socrates

    calls

    it, cannot

    lay

    claim

    to certainty,

    since

    it is not

    in

    possession of the ultimate

    principle

    nor

    even of principles

    or ideas

    necessarily

    reflecting

    the essence

    or

    nature

    of things.Someof them mightperhapsbe derived rom a higheror more

    comprehensive

    principle,

    but the

    test

    would always

    be in reference

    to

    experienced

    eality:

    If anyone assails

    you

    there (i.e.,

    questions

    your

    principle),

    you would

    not

    mind

    him or answer

    him until you

    had

    seen whether

    the

    consequences

    which

    follow

    agree

    with one

    another or

    not, and when

    you

    are further required

    to give

    an

    explanation

    of this

    principle,

    you would

    go

    on

    to

    assume

    a higher principle,

    and a

    higher,

    until you found

    a resting-placein the

    best

    of the

    higher.47

    It would appear,therefore,that if the strictlyphilosophicalpart of

    the

    Phaedo

    were

    to

    end with the

    exposition

    of Socrates'

    second-best

    method of

    inquiry,the

    dialogue

    could

    hardly

    be called

    upon to support

    Heidegger's

    contention.

    For the

    ideas

    to which

    Socrates

    here refers

    cannot

    be said

    to contain

    the truth of

    things.

    They

    are

    merely postulates

    which are

    somehow

    derived

    from experience

    and

    whose

    function

    it

    is

    to help us

    discover some

    orderly

    relationship

    between the

    elements

    of

    experience.

    Heidegger

    could,

    however,

    appeal

    to the

    argument

    which

    follows

    and to which

    the

    exposition

    of

    the method

    appears

    as

    a

    prelude.

    For oddly enough the argumentproceeds as if the second-best were

    the ideal method,

    as if

    the

    postulates

    were

    the essences

    of

    things. Only

    if

    Socrates

    could

    claim

    to

    possess

    insight

    into the very

    nature

    of

    the

    human

    soul

    would

    it make

    any

    sense

    for

    him

    to

    maintain

    that

    death-

    lessness

    is one

    of

    its

    necessary

    attributes.

    The

    difficulty

    can

    not be

    eliminatedsimply

    by

    saying

    that Plato

    was

    unaware

    of the

    implications

    of

    Socrates'

    second-best

    method.48

    For in

    the brief

    interval

    between

    the

    exposition

    and

    the

    final

    argument,

    Socrates

    uses

    the

    method

    as if

    he

    had a

    proper

    understanding

    f it.

    When

    Simias

    raises

    an

    objection against

    Socrates'

    irst set of

    arguments

    by

    offering

    a

    rival hypothesis,

    namely

    the harmony theory,

    which

    would

    imply

    the

    mortality

    of

    the soul,

    Socrates

    refutes

    it

    precisely

    as

    one

    would a

    mere

    postulate.

    He shows

    that

    it lacks

    consistency,

    that its

    consequences

    do

    not

    agree

    with

    the

    observed

    facts,

    that

    it is

    in

    conflict

    with

    other

    postu-

    lates

    which

    Simlias

    has accepted.49

    47

    Ibid.,

    par.

    101,

    p.

    485.

    48

    Note for instance: His hypothetical method, if our analysis of the Phaedo

    has

    been correct,

    can never

    attain to

    absolute

    knowledge

    ...

    but, when

    we

    recall

    that

    (Plato)

    believed

    in the

    possibility

    of absolute

    knowledge

    ...

    we must

    certainly

    wonder

    why he

    devoted

    so

    much

    space to

    its elaboration

    ...

    (Richard

    Robinson,

    Plato's

    Earlier

    Dialectic.

    Second Edition,

    Oxford, 1953,

    p.

    146.)

    49

    Socrates'

    refutation

    can

    be

    summarized briefly

    as follows:

    The

    harmony

    theory leads

    to absurd

    consequences

    since

    it would

    make

    us

    say

    that

    the soul

    as

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    16/27

    PLATO'S

    DOCTRINE

    OF TRUTH:

    ORTHOTES

    OR

    ALETHEIA?

    171

    Before

    we come

    to grips

    with the problem

    which

    arises

    out of

    the

    discrepancy

    between

    Socrates'

    exposition

    of

    his method

    and its, use

    in

    the final argument

    of the

    Phaedo,

    we

    may perhaps

    be allowed

    a

    brief

    reference o the Protagoras.For this dialogueoffers a furtherexcellent

    illustration

    of

    the proper

    use of the method.

    There Socrates

    challenges

    Protagoras'

    claim

    of

    being

    able to

    teach political

    virtue to

    the

    young

    men

    of the city,

    on

    the

    ground

    that

    virtue

    is

    incapable

    of

    being

    taught.

    It

    is significant

    hat

    Socrates.

    does

    not

    turn

    to

    the idea

    of virtue

    in

    an

    attempt

    to show

    that

    teachability

    s

    incompatible

    with

    it.

    Instead

    he

    examines

    the

    social

    situation,

    or,

    more

    specifically,

    the

    behavior

    of

    the

    Athenians

    in

    the

    Assembly

    and

    the attitude

    of

    the great

    statesmen

    toward

    their

    offspring.

    The

    latter,

    observes

    Socrates,

    gave

    (their

    sons)

    excellent

    instruction

    n all

    that

    could

    be learned

    from

    masters,

    but in

    their own

    department

    of

    politics

    neither

    taught

    them,

    nor

    gave

    them

    teachers.

    0

    The

    former

    accept

    advice

    in

    technical

    matters

    only

    from

    experts,

    such

    as

    architects

    and shipwrights,

    but

    when

    the

    question

    is

    an

    affair

    of

    state,

    says Socrates,

    everybody

    s

    free

    to

    have

    a

    say

    -

    carpenter,

    tinker,

    cobbler,

    sailor,

    passenger;

    rich

    and

    poor,

    high

    and

    low

    -

    any

    one

    who

    likes

    gets

    up,

    and

    no one reproaches

    him,

    as in

    the

    former

    case,

    with

    not

    having

    learned,

    and

    having

    no teacher,

    and yet

    giving advice.

    1

    The reason for this unconcernabout instructionand

    training

    n

    political

    virtue

    must,

    according

    o Socrates,

    be

    sought

    in

    the

    fact

    that this

    virtue

    cannot

    be

    taught.

    All

    that

    Socrates

    does

    and all

    that

    he

    legitimately

    can

    do is

    to

    show

    that

    on

    the

    assumption

    hat

    virtue

    cannot be

    taught,

    the

    behavior

    of

    the

    members

    of the Assembly

    and

    of

    the

    great

    statesmen

    which

    first appeared

    very

    odd

    indeed,

    now

    makes

    better

    sense.

    Protagoras

    n turn refutes,

    Socrates

    by appealing

    ikewise

    to

    the social

    situation,

    although he

    refers

    not

    to the

    behavior

    of

    the

    Athenians

    alone

    but to

    intelligent

    men

    in

    general.

    He claims

    that

    virtue

    is innatein all men,52at least as a capacity,andthat it requires eachers

    to realize

    that capacity.

    To Socrates'

    objection

    that there are

    no

    special

    teachers

    as in

    the other

    arts,

    he

    replies

    that

    all the citizens

    help

    in

    the

    a

    harmony

    contains

    within

    itself a

    discord

    or a

    harmony,

    according

    as

    it

    is

    vicious

    or

    not;

    its

    implications

    are

    contrary

    to

    known

    phenomena,

    inasmuch

    as

    the

    soul

    to

    some

    extent

    leads

    and controls

    the

    body,

    while

    a

    harmony

    is

    dependent

    on

    the

    instrument;

    it is

    incompatible

    with

    the

    theory

    of recollection

    accepted

    by

    Simmias,

    according

    to

    which

    the

    soul

    exists prior

    to

    its

    entry

    into

    the

    body,

    while

    a

    har-

    mony appears after the

    instrument

    has

    come

    into

    existence.

    (Cf.

    Phaedo,

    par.

    91-95;

    pp.

    476-479).

    50

    Protagoras,

    par.

    320,

    Vol.

    I,

    p.

    91.

    51

    Ibid.,

    par.

    319,

    p.

    91.

    52

    For

    the

    manner

    in

    which

    Protagoras

    arrives

    at

    the

    innateness

    of

    virtue,

    see

    H. Wolz

    The

    Protagoras

    Myth

    and

    the

    Philosopher-Kings,

    The

    Review of

    Metaphysics,

    Vol.

    XVII,

    No.

    2,

    December,

    1963,

    pp.

    219ff.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    17/27

    172 PHILOSOPHY

    NDPHENOMENOLOGICAL

    ESEARCH

    education

    of

    the young;

    and

    therefore

    it

    is difficult

    to find a teacher

    such as Protagoraswho has the skill to add the finishing

    ouches to what

    the others have done.

    And

    if everybodypossesses political

    virtue, every-

    body should be allowed to speak on political mattersin the Assembly.

    Thus the view of Protagoras

    also casts a measureof reasonableness ver

    the behavior of the Athenians.

    But the theory of

    Protagoras

    surpasses

    that of Socrates n synthesizing

    power, for it can accountfor phenomena

    which

    Socrates,

    from his position, must leave unexplained.

    Why, for

    instance, do we not chastize

    or instruct he ugly, or the diminutive,or

    the feeble, asks Protagoras,

    but hold men responsible for political

    virtue, except

    under the assumption that the latter are capable of

    improvement by study and exercise and teaching,

    3

    Why do people

    not blame a man when

    he admits a lack of skill in

    any particularart,

    but when he lacks honesty

    ..

    or some other political

    virtue

    54

    and

    publicly tells

    the

    truth

    about himself, they think he

    must be out

    of

    his

    mind. For

    they

    consider

    his virtue as so essential o

    community

    ife that

    not even the wickedarewhollydevoid

    of it. And finallyProtagoras ppeals

    to the theory of punishment

    which, he says, is held by all reasonable

    people.

    For he

    who desires to

    inflict

    rational

    punishment

    does

    not

    retaliate for

    a

    past wrong

    which cannot be undone,

    (but)

    has

    regard

    to

    the future, and is desirous that the man who is punished,and he who

    sees him punished, may be deterred from doing

    wrong again

    ...

    thereby

    clearly implyingthat virtue

    is capable of being

    taught.

    5

    Thus Protagorashas won the

    first

    roundof

    the

    argument

    with

    Socrates

    not by showing that he is right and his opponent

    wrong in the

    light

    of

    some set standard,but

    by leading his audienceto

    a

    point of view

    from

    which

    they discover

    a

    higher degree

    of

    intelligibility

    over

    a

    wider

    range

    of

    human

    experience

    than was obtainablewith

    the

    theory

    of Socrates.

    Both attack and defense show

    a

    keen awarenessof

    the

    interplay

    of

    fact

    and

    idea.

    The

    idea does not impose

    a

    structureupon

    reality,

    but

    merely

    aids

    in the

    discovery

    of whatever structure he

    concrete situation

    may

    exhibit.

    The digression o

    the

    Protagoras

    seemed

    necessary

    n order to direct

    the spotlight of attention on

    the

    conception

    of

    truth which

    is

    implied

    by Socrates'

    so-called second-best

    method of

    inquiry.

    For those

    who

    see the

    Phaedo

    mainly as the

    source

    of

    the

    theory

    of ideas

    usually

    over-

    look

    or

    minimize

    the

    importance

    of this

    conception,

    and

    consider

    only

    or at least place the main stress on the other conception which is

    implied by

    the final argument

    for the

    immortality

    of the

    soul. These

    53

    Protagoras,

    par.

    323,

    p.

    94.

    54

    Ibid.

    55

    Ibid.,

    par.

    324, p.

    95.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    18/27

    PLATO'S DOCTRINE

    OF TRUTH: ORTHOTES

    OR ALUTHEIA?

    173

    two conceptionsare not

    intermingled o that

    one could seek a way out

    of

    the difficultyby

    maintainingPlato

    confusedthem. In fact the change

    from one to

    other is so abrupt56 that one

    can hardly

    help seeing in

    this juxtapositionof incompatibleviews an analogue to the juxtaposi-

    tion of

    traditionalismand

    rationalism n the Euthyphro

    or of radical

    freedom and

    responsibilityas against

    unquestioning

    obedience to

    law

    in the Crito. The present

    problem is

    complicated,however, by the fact

    that we are

    confrontednot

    with two extremeswhich of

    themselves sug-

    gest

    a

    mean,

    but with an authentic and

    an

    unauthenticconception

    of

    truth.

    We

    should

    now

    be willing

    to

    face

    both aspects of the

    paradox which

    Plato creates

    by having Socrates

    expound

    a

    method operating with

    postulates and having him

    use it in an

    argument which presupposes

    insight into

    essences. And

    with the fuller understanding f

    the problem

    at hand, we

    should now also have a better

    chance of

    finding a satis-

    factory

    solution.

    When

    Socrates,

    after his

    disappointmentwith the nature

    philosophers

    and expecially with

    Anaxagoras,had

    decided that he had better have

    recourseto the world of

    mind and

    seek there the truth,of

    existence,

    7

    he

    might have

    done so for one of two

    reasons:He might

    have expected

    to find in the ideas the true reality or the essence of things, and truth

    would then

    have

    become

    the

    conformity

    of the

    mind

    to

    the ideas.

    In

    Heidegger's

    erminology, ruth would have

    become correctness

    Richtig-

    keit,

    orthotes).

    By contrast

    he might have seen the ideas.

    as devices, as

    instruments

    which, though

    rooted in reality, have as their

    primary

    unc-

    tion

    to stimulate

    and

    direct

    thought, so that

    it

    places itself

    in

    the

    proper

    perspective

    and

    thus

    discovers

    he truth shining forth from

    things.

    Then

    the ideas would be in

    the

    service

    of

    truth,

    and

    the truth

    thus conceived

    would be

    Heidegger's

    ale'theia

    r unhiddenness.

    In spite of the seeminglyradicaldifferencebetweenthe two views of

    truth, they are not

    unrelated.

    History

    has in fact

    shown

    that

    one

    can

    easily

    lead

    to

    the

    other. Scientific

    postulates,

    for

    instance, may.

    at

    a

    given period

    and in

    regard

    to specific aspects

    of nature

    appear

    so suc-

    cessful that

    the

    inquirer

    s

    temptedto, regard

    hem

    as

    revealing

    he

    very

    essence of

    things. This temptationmay

    prove irresistible

    when coupled

    with the common

    tendency of

    the

    scientist to allow

    as real

    only

    that

    5

    In this connection note: It is well that we should be reminded that the

    doctrine of Forms as

    causes is put forward by Socrates as a second-best doctrine

    relative.

    to that which

    he had hoped to build on the principle

    suggested by

    Anaxagoras. Nevertheless

    Plato seems, in our

    present section, and indeed through-

    out the rest of the argument which gives his

    final proof of immortality,

    to have

    forgotten

    this.

    (R.

    Hackforth, Plato's Phaedo.

    Cambridge, 1955, p. 146.)

    57

    Phaedo, par. 99-100,

    p. 484.

    This content downloaded from 200.130.19.143 on Fri, 21 Aug 2015 13:16:54 UTC

    All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/24/2019 WOLZ, Henry G. - Plato's Doctrine of Truth - Orthtes or Altheia

    19/27

    174 PHILOSOPHY

    ND

    PHENOMENOLOGICAL

    ESEARCH

    which

    falls within the range

    of his method and conforms

    to his

    postu-

    lates,

    and

    to regard

    as

    'mere' appearance

    that

    which does not.58

    To

    those

    who

    believed themselves

    n the

    possession

    of definitive

    ruth

    about

    the cosmos, Galileo was a dangerousheretic;and many of those who

    felt

    comfortably

    at home

    in the

    world of Newton must have looked

    upon

    Einstein

    as a subversive

    ntruder

    and a disturberof the scientific

    peace.

    Now

    it is

    hardly necessary

    to point

    out

    that Socrates

    devoted

    his

    life

    to the

    task

    of ferreting

    out

    and exposing

    the, false pretenders

    to,

    wisdom.

    But it

    is perhaps,

    ess

    readily

    recognized

    hat at

    least

    the first

    half

    and

    probably

    the

    whole

    of the

    Phaedo

    concerns

    itself

    in

    the main

    with

    the

    flaw

    of overconfidence

    based

    on the

    wrong

    conception

    of

    truth

    and the

    baneful effects it may have on inquiry.This will not become,evident,

    however,

    unless we

    are willing

    to call into

    play

    the usually

    neglected

    dramaticelements

    of the

    dialogue.

    Far

    from

    promising

    a

    compelling

    demonstration

    or the

    immortality

    of the soul,

    Socrates

    at

    the,

    outset had

    merely

    wanted

    to converse

    a

    little

    of the

    probabilities

    of these

    things.

    59

    One

    of his

    two

    young

    Pythagorean

    riends

    warned

    that

    it

    requires

    a

    great

    deal of

    argument

    and

    many proofs

    to

    show that

    when

    the

    man is dead

    his soul

    yet

    exists,

    and has any

    force

    or intelligence.

    0

    And

    after

    the first set of proofs

    the otherremarkson howhard or ratherimpossible s the attainment

    of any

    certainty

    abou