virginia journal of criminal law v 1 2013 novirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · luke...

156
i VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW VOL. 1 2013 NO. 3 CONTENTS ARTICLES Judicial Fundamentalism, the Fourth Amendment, and Ashcroft v. al- Kidd ....................................................................................................446 Ofer Raban The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age ...............................481 Ricardo J. Bascuas Unbinding Binding Arbitration of Police Discipline: The Public Policy Exception ...........................................................................................540 Mark Iris, Ph.D.

Upload: others

Post on 26-May-2020

2 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

i

VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAWVOL. 1 2013 NO. 3

CONTENTS ARTICLES Judicial Fundamentalism, the Fourth Amendment, and Ashcroft v. al-

Kidd ....................................................................................................446 Ofer Raban The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age ...............................481 Ricardo J. Bascuas Unbinding Binding Arbitration of Police Discipline: The Public Policy

Exception ...........................................................................................540 Mark Iris, Ph.D.

Page 2: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

ii

The Virginia Journal of Criminal Law gratefully acknowledges the support of the University of Virginia Law School Foundation and the University of Virginia Student Activities Fund, with special thanks to the Margaret Bennett Cullum Charitable Lead Unitrust for its generosity. All donations to the Journal are tax deductible and must be made through the University of Virginia Law School Foundation. Please contact the Journal at the address below for more information on donations.

Virginia Journal of Criminal Law University of Virginia

School of Law 580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA 22903-1789 [email protected] ISSN: 2329-0404

The Virginia Journal of Criminal Law publishes two times per year. The subscription rate for a complete volume, which consists of two issues per year, is $60.00 domestic. Individual issues from the current or previous volumes can be obtained for $35.00 domestic. Please send all correspondence regarding subscriptions, including address changes, to the Journal at either the above mailing address or [email protected]. If notice of termination is not received by the Journal before the expiration of a subscription, that subscription will be automatically renewed. The Journal is not an official publication of the University of Virginia, and the views expressed in the Journal do not necessarily reflect the policies or opinions of the Journal, its editors and staff, or its Executive Advisory Board. The Journal welcomes the submission of articles for publication. Authors who wish to publish with the Journal should send a copy of their manuscript, resume, and cover letter to [email protected].

Copyright © 2013 Virginia Criminal Law Association

iii

VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAWVOL. 1 2013 NO. 3 EXECUTIVE MANAGING BOARD

2012-2013

EDITOR-IN-CHIEF Gregory Schneider

DEVELOPMENT EDITOR

Julian RadzinschiSENIOR ARTICLES

EDITOR Tiffany Parrot

FINANCE EDITOR Jonathan Williams

SYMPOSIUM EDITOR

Greg Gellert

ARTICLES EDITORS

Kate Naseef Eleanor Winn

Meaghan Mapes

PRODUCTION EDITOR Melissa Reilly-Diakun

SENIOR EDITORIAL BOARD

Sirisah Bendapudi Jaylum Chen Jeff George

Jonathan Guynn

Sung Jae Lim Sarah Santos Chris Santoli

William Stoddard

Jasmine Wade Jonathan Yung Xinyi Zhang

Meghann Morrill

JUNIOR EDITORIAL BOARDEmmanuel Brown

Julia Boyer Scott Burton

Michelle Carmon Catherine Fata

Salvatore Favuzza

Alexander Foster Sharif Gray

Kieran Hartley Daniel Kaplan Luke Leichty

Grant McCarthur Yakov Medinets

Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo

Catharine Richmond Brad Thompson Ruth Windberg John Williams Jesse Wright

Page 3: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

ii

The Virginia Journal of Criminal Law gratefully acknowledges the support of the University of Virginia Law School Foundation and the University of Virginia Student Activities Fund, with special thanks to the Margaret Bennett Cullum Charitable Lead Unitrust for its generosity. All donations to the Journal are tax deductible and must be made through the University of Virginia Law School Foundation. Please contact the Journal at the address below for more information on donations.

Virginia Journal of Criminal Law University of Virginia

School of Law 580 Massie Road

Charlottesville, VA 22903-1789 [email protected] ISSN: 2329-0404

The Virginia Journal of Criminal Law publishes two times per year. The subscription rate for a complete volume, which consists of two issues per year, is $60.00 domestic. Individual issues from the current or previous volumes can be obtained for $35.00 domestic. Please send all correspondence regarding subscriptions, including address changes, to the Journal at either the above mailing address or [email protected]. If notice of termination is not received by the Journal before the expiration of a subscription, that subscription will be automatically renewed. The Journal is not an official publication of the University of Virginia, and the views expressed in the Journal do not necessarily reflect the policies or opinions of the Journal, its editors and staff, or its Executive Advisory Board. The Journal welcomes the submission of articles for publication. Authors who wish to publish with the Journal should send a copy of their manuscript, resume, and cover letter to [email protected].

Copyright © 2013 Virginia Criminal Law Association

iii

VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAWVOL. 1 2013 NO. 3 EXECUTIVE MANAGING BOARD

2012-2013

EDITOR-IN-CHIEF Gregory Schneider

DEVELOPMENT EDITOR

Julian RadzinschiSENIOR ARTICLES

EDITOR Tiffany Parrot

FINANCE EDITOR Jonathan Williams

SYMPOSIUM EDITOR

Greg Gellert

ARTICLES EDITORS

Kate Naseef Eleanor Winn

Meaghan Mapes

PRODUCTION EDITOR Melissa Reilly-Diakun

SENIOR EDITORIAL BOARD

Sirisah Bendapudi Jaylum Chen Jeff George

Jonathan Guynn

Sung Jae Lim Sarah Santos Chris Santoli

William Stoddard

Jasmine Wade Jonathan Yung Xinyi Zhang

Meghann Morrill

JUNIOR EDITORIAL BOARDEmmanuel Brown

Julia Boyer Scott Burton

Michelle Carmon Catherine Fata

Salvatore Favuzza

Alexander Foster Sharif Gray

Kieran Hartley Daniel Kaplan Luke Leichty

Grant McCarthur Yakov Medinets

Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo

Catharine Richmond Brad Thompson Ruth Windberg John Williams Jesse Wright

Page 4: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

iv

We would like to thank the incoming board for their help in finalizing this publication.

EXECUTIVE MANAGING BOARD 2013–2014

EDITOR-IN-CHIEF

Melissa Reilly-Diakun

MANAGING EDITOR Meaghan Mapes

EXECUTIVE

EDITOR Catharine Richmond

SENIOR ARTICLES EDITOR

Eleanor Winn

ARTICLES DEVELOPMENT EDITOR

Kate Naseef

FINANCE EDITOR Julia Boyer

SYMPOSIUM DIRECTOR Sean Mulligan

PRODUCTION EDITOR Sean Welsh

ARTICLES EDITORS

Sharif Gray Daniel Kaplan

ASSISTANT MANAGING BOARD

ASSISTANT MANAGING EDITORS ASSISTANT DEVELOPMENT EDITORS

Joseph Fairbank Kathleen Robeson

Hadeel Abouhasira Daniel Wallmuth

John Williams

SENIOR EDITORIAL BOARD Scott Burton

Michelle Carmon Catherine Fata

Salvatore Favuzza Alyssa Fong-Kwan

Kieran Hartley Luke Leichty

M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets

Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo

Brandon Smith Brad Thompson Ruth Windberg

Jesse Wright Jessica Wright

JUNIOR EDITORIAL BOARD

Chris Arakaky Sarah Brigham

Jared Krejci Matthew Morgan

Mario Peia Reuven Roslyn Wesley Russ

Lauren Schnyer

Paige Taylor Samuel Thomas

Christopher White Jamie Whittenburg

VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW VOL. 1 2013 NO. 3

JUDICIAL FUNDAMENTALISM, THE FOURTH AMENDMENT, AND ASHCROFT V. AL-KIDD

Ofer Raban

ABSTRACT

The Supreme Court's opinion in Ashcroft v. al-Kidd is a classic

of judicial fundamentalism.1 The decision held that the former U.S. Attorney General was immune from a lawsuit alleging he misused the Material Witness Statute as a pretext for detaining individuals suspected of terrorist activities. The article argues that the decision is based on an untenable interpretation of precedent, and is rooted in a fundamentalist judicial philosophy long advocated by Justice Antonin Scalia, who wrote the opinion. The article then surveys the potential impact of the decision on Fourth Amendment protections, and concludes with brief remarks on the intellectual foundations of Scalia’s judicial philosophy.

Ofer Raban, Associate Professor of Law and Elmer Sahlstrom Senior Fellow, University of Oregon. I would like to thank Lee Goldman, Carrie Leonetti, and Alexander Tsesis for their helpful comments. An early version of this article was presented at the Loyola University Chicago School of Law University of Constitutional Law Colloquium.

1 Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011).

Page 5: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

iv

We would like to thank the incoming board for their help in finalizing this publication.

EXECUTIVE MANAGING BOARD 2013–2014

EDITOR-IN-CHIEF

Melissa Reilly-Diakun

MANAGING EDITOR Meaghan Mapes

EXECUTIVE

EDITOR Catharine Richmond

SENIOR ARTICLES EDITOR

Eleanor Winn

ARTICLES DEVELOPMENT EDITOR

Kate Naseef

FINANCE EDITOR Julia Boyer

SYMPOSIUM DIRECTOR Sean Mulligan

PRODUCTION EDITOR Sean Welsh

ARTICLES EDITORS

Sharif Gray Daniel Kaplan

ASSISTANT MANAGING BOARD

ASSISTANT MANAGING EDITORS ASSISTANT DEVELOPMENT EDITORS

Joseph Fairbank Kathleen Robeson

Hadeel Abouhasira Daniel Wallmuth

John Williams

SENIOR EDITORIAL BOARD Scott Burton

Michelle Carmon Catherine Fata

Salvatore Favuzza Alyssa Fong-Kwan

Kieran Hartley Luke Leichty

M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets

Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo

Brandon Smith Brad Thompson Ruth Windberg

Jesse Wright Jessica Wright

JUNIOR EDITORIAL BOARD

Chris Arakaky Sarah Brigham

Jared Krejci Matthew Morgan

Mario Peia Reuven Roslyn Wesley Russ

Lauren Schnyer

Paige Taylor Samuel Thomas

Christopher White Jamie Whittenburg

VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW VOL. 1 2013 NO. 3

JUDICIAL FUNDAMENTALISM, THE FOURTH AMENDMENT, AND ASHCROFT V. AL-KIDD

Ofer Raban

ABSTRACT

The Supreme Court's opinion in Ashcroft v. al-Kidd is a classic

of judicial fundamentalism.1 The decision held that the former U.S. Attorney General was immune from a lawsuit alleging he misused the Material Witness Statute as a pretext for detaining individuals suspected of terrorist activities. The article argues that the decision is based on an untenable interpretation of precedent, and is rooted in a fundamentalist judicial philosophy long advocated by Justice Antonin Scalia, who wrote the opinion. The article then surveys the potential impact of the decision on Fourth Amendment protections, and concludes with brief remarks on the intellectual foundations of Scalia’s judicial philosophy.

Ofer Raban, Associate Professor of Law and Elmer Sahlstrom Senior Fellow, University of Oregon. I would like to thank Lee Goldman, Carrie Leonetti, and Alexander Tsesis for their helpful comments. An early version of this article was presented at the Loyola University Chicago School of Law University of Constitutional Law Colloquium.

1 Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011).

Page 6: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

447 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

JUDICIAL FUNDAMENTALISM, THE FOURTH AMENDMENT, AND ASHCROFT V. AL-KIDD

Ofer Raban

TABLE OF CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION .............................................................................. 448 I. ASHCROFT V. AL-KIDD .............................................................. 449 II. PRETEXTUAL ARRESTS ............................................................ 453 III. WHREN VERSUS SPECIAL NEEDS AND ADMINISTRATIVE

SEARCHES ................................................................................ 455 IV. STATUTORY INTERPRETATION ................................................ 462 V. THE JURISPRUDENTIAL DEBATE ............................................. 468 VI. EMASCULATING FOURTH AMENDMENT PROTECTIONS ......... 473 CONCLUSION .................................................................................. 477

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 448

INTRODUCTION

undamentalism—whether found in religion (where the term originated),2 politics,3 economics,4 or law5—is a form of extremism

whose essence is a belief in a small, “fundamental” set of principles that are supposed to yield all the answers to complex social or political questions. Fundamentalism is quintessentially a belief in a reductive form of decision-making process: fundamentalists answer complicated social or political questions by relying on a few purportedly simple and rigid considerations—notwithstanding the occasional impractical or seemingly unreasonable solutions these yield. Fundamentalism is therefore a form of willful narrow-mindedness, combined with a hardheaded willingness to live with the consequences whatever they be. Understood against this definition, Justice Antonin Scalia’s textualist philosophy is a paradigm of judicial fundamentalism. Scalia has long claimed that statutory text should be given virtually exclusive weight in statutory interpretation, to the exclusion of all other considerations—including such time-honored factors as statutory purpose, legislative history, changed conditions, equity, morality, or coherence.6 And he often

2 The term “fundamentalism” originated as a form of self-description among American Protestants in the 19th century. See MALISE RUTHVEN, FUNDAMENTALISM: THE SEARCH FOR MEANING (2004) at 10–11.

3 See, e.g., Kelly O’Connell, Leftists Want to Ban Believers From Office—But Who Are the Real Fundamentalists? Political Fundamentalists—A Grave Threat to World Liberty, CANADA FREE PRESS, (Nov. 27, 2011), available at http://www.canadafreepress.com/index.php/article/42739.

4 See, e.g., Joseph Stiglitz, Globalization and Its Discontents 14, 58, 102 (2002). 5 See, e.g., CASS R. SUNSTEIN, RADICALS IN ROBES: WHY EXTREME RIGHT-

WING COURTS ARE WRONG FOR AMERICA (2005); Morton J. Horwitz, Foreword, The Constitution of Change: Legal Fundamentality Without Fundamentalism, 107 HARV. L. REV. 30, 43 (1993).

6 See generally, ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997). His most recent iteration of this philosophy appeared in a recent 500-page tome, where Scalia writes that judges should “look for meaning in the governing text, ascribe to that text the meaning that it has borne from its inception, and reject judicial speculation about both the drafters’ extratextually derived purposes and the desirability of the fair reading’s anticipated consequences.” ANTONIN SCALIA & BRYAN A. GARNER, READING LAW: THE INTERPRETATION OF LEGAL TEXTS (2012) at xxvii.

F

Page 7: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

447 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

JUDICIAL FUNDAMENTALISM, THE FOURTH AMENDMENT, AND ASHCROFT V. AL-KIDD

Ofer Raban

TABLE OF CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION .............................................................................. 448 I. ASHCROFT V. AL-KIDD .............................................................. 449 II. PRETEXTUAL ARRESTS ............................................................ 453 III. WHREN VERSUS SPECIAL NEEDS AND ADMINISTRATIVE

SEARCHES ................................................................................ 455 IV. STATUTORY INTERPRETATION ................................................ 462 V. THE JURISPRUDENTIAL DEBATE ............................................. 468 VI. EMASCULATING FOURTH AMENDMENT PROTECTIONS ......... 473 CONCLUSION .................................................................................. 477

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 448

INTRODUCTION

undamentalism—whether found in religion (where the term originated),2 politics,3 economics,4 or law5—is a form of extremism

whose essence is a belief in a small, “fundamental” set of principles that are supposed to yield all the answers to complex social or political questions. Fundamentalism is quintessentially a belief in a reductive form of decision-making process: fundamentalists answer complicated social or political questions by relying on a few purportedly simple and rigid considerations—notwithstanding the occasional impractical or seemingly unreasonable solutions these yield. Fundamentalism is therefore a form of willful narrow-mindedness, combined with a hardheaded willingness to live with the consequences whatever they be. Understood against this definition, Justice Antonin Scalia’s textualist philosophy is a paradigm of judicial fundamentalism. Scalia has long claimed that statutory text should be given virtually exclusive weight in statutory interpretation, to the exclusion of all other considerations—including such time-honored factors as statutory purpose, legislative history, changed conditions, equity, morality, or coherence.6 And he often

2 The term “fundamentalism” originated as a form of self-description among American Protestants in the 19th century. See MALISE RUTHVEN, FUNDAMENTALISM: THE SEARCH FOR MEANING (2004) at 10–11.

3 See, e.g., Kelly O’Connell, Leftists Want to Ban Believers From Office—But Who Are the Real Fundamentalists? Political Fundamentalists—A Grave Threat to World Liberty, CANADA FREE PRESS, (Nov. 27, 2011), available at http://www.canadafreepress.com/index.php/article/42739.

4 See, e.g., Joseph Stiglitz, Globalization and Its Discontents 14, 58, 102 (2002). 5 See, e.g., CASS R. SUNSTEIN, RADICALS IN ROBES: WHY EXTREME RIGHT-

WING COURTS ARE WRONG FOR AMERICA (2005); Morton J. Horwitz, Foreword, The Constitution of Change: Legal Fundamentality Without Fundamentalism, 107 HARV. L. REV. 30, 43 (1993).

6 See generally, ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997). His most recent iteration of this philosophy appeared in a recent 500-page tome, where Scalia writes that judges should “look for meaning in the governing text, ascribe to that text the meaning that it has borne from its inception, and reject judicial speculation about both the drafters’ extratextually derived purposes and the desirability of the fair reading’s anticipated consequences.” ANTONIN SCALIA & BRYAN A. GARNER, READING LAW: THE INTERPRETATION OF LEGAL TEXTS (2012) at xxvii.

F

Page 8: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

449 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

adheres to textualist resolutions no matter how absurd or unreasonable they may be.7 I will later return to this issue of judicial fundamentalism, but will start with the occasion for this discussion—the Supreme Court’s 2010 decision Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, where Scalia’s fundamentalism was on full display.8

I. ASHCROFT V. AL-KIDD

Abdullah al-Kidd, born Lavoni T. Kidd, is an American-born, former college football player who converted to Islam.9 He was arrested by FBI agents in March 2003,10 when he was about to board a flight to Saudi Arabia in order to study at a Saudi university.11 His arrest warrant was issued under the federal Material Witness Statute,12 which authorizes the detention of individuals not themselves suspected of criminal wrongdoing if their testimony is “material in a criminal proceeding”13 and if it may “become impracticable to secure the presence of the person by subpoena.”14 The warrant application declared that al-Kidd’s testimony was “crucial” to the prosecution of one Sami Omar al-Hussayen for visa fraud.15 The application contained some false allegations (for example, that al-Kidd was flying on a one-way ticket),16 omitted important information (for example, that al-Kidd was an American citizen and that he had previously cooperated with the FBI),17 and did not specify what

7 See infra notes 124–40 and accompanying text. 8 Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011). 9 Al-Kidd v. Ashcroft, 580 F.3d 949, 952 (9th Cir. 2009), rev’d, 131 S. Ct. 2074

(2011). 10 Id. at 952–53. 11 Id. at 952. 12 See id. at 952. 13 18 U.S.C. § 3144 (2012). 14 Id. 15 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 953. 16 Id. 17 Id.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 450

material information al-Kidd possessed.18 Nevertheless the warrant was issued and al-Kidd was arrested.19 Al-Kidd was interrogated (mostly about his involvement with Islam) before being transferred to a high-security facility, where he remained for sixteen days.20 He was held in harsh conditions: his legs, wrists, and waist were shackled whenever he was moved;21 he was allowed out of his cell only one to two hours each day;22 and his cell was kept lit twenty-four hours a day.23 When he was finally released, it was on the conditions that he limit his travels, live with his wife at his in-laws’ home, report regularly to a probation officer, and consent to home visits.24 These conditions lasted over a year, during which al-Kidd separated from his wife (I guess that’s what happens when you live with the in-laws).25 Al-Kidd was never asked to testify in any criminal proceeding.26 In fact, according to his lawsuit, al-Kidd’s detention was never meant to secure his testimony at any criminal trial:27 he was arrested for investigative purposes.28 Indeed when FBI Director Robert Mueller testified before Congress in 2003, he listed al-Kidd’s arrest as one of five major successes in the FBI’s efforts to dismantle terrorist networks in the United States.29 As we now know, that was utter nonsense: the FBI never had a shred of evidence implicating al-Kidd in any terrorist activity.30

18 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2088 n.2. 19 See al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 953. 20 Id. at 951. 21 Id. 22 Id. at 953. 23 Id. Prisoners detained in the facility for actually committing serious crimes

were treated less harshly, id. at 978. 24 Id. at 953. 25 Id. at 953–54. 26 Id. at 954. 27 See id. at 960. 28 See id. 29 Id. at 964. 30 Id. at 952.

Page 9: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

449 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

adheres to textualist resolutions no matter how absurd or unreasonable they may be.7 I will later return to this issue of judicial fundamentalism, but will start with the occasion for this discussion—the Supreme Court’s 2010 decision Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, where Scalia’s fundamentalism was on full display.8

I. ASHCROFT V. AL-KIDD

Abdullah al-Kidd, born Lavoni T. Kidd, is an American-born, former college football player who converted to Islam.9 He was arrested by FBI agents in March 2003,10 when he was about to board a flight to Saudi Arabia in order to study at a Saudi university.11 His arrest warrant was issued under the federal Material Witness Statute,12 which authorizes the detention of individuals not themselves suspected of criminal wrongdoing if their testimony is “material in a criminal proceeding”13 and if it may “become impracticable to secure the presence of the person by subpoena.”14 The warrant application declared that al-Kidd’s testimony was “crucial” to the prosecution of one Sami Omar al-Hussayen for visa fraud.15 The application contained some false allegations (for example, that al-Kidd was flying on a one-way ticket),16 omitted important information (for example, that al-Kidd was an American citizen and that he had previously cooperated with the FBI),17 and did not specify what

7 See infra notes 124–40 and accompanying text. 8 Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011). 9 Al-Kidd v. Ashcroft, 580 F.3d 949, 952 (9th Cir. 2009), rev’d, 131 S. Ct. 2074

(2011). 10 Id. at 952–53. 11 Id. at 952. 12 See id. at 952. 13 18 U.S.C. § 3144 (2012). 14 Id. 15 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 953. 16 Id. 17 Id.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 450

material information al-Kidd possessed.18 Nevertheless the warrant was issued and al-Kidd was arrested.19 Al-Kidd was interrogated (mostly about his involvement with Islam) before being transferred to a high-security facility, where he remained for sixteen days.20 He was held in harsh conditions: his legs, wrists, and waist were shackled whenever he was moved;21 he was allowed out of his cell only one to two hours each day;22 and his cell was kept lit twenty-four hours a day.23 When he was finally released, it was on the conditions that he limit his travels, live with his wife at his in-laws’ home, report regularly to a probation officer, and consent to home visits.24 These conditions lasted over a year, during which al-Kidd separated from his wife (I guess that’s what happens when you live with the in-laws).25 Al-Kidd was never asked to testify in any criminal proceeding.26 In fact, according to his lawsuit, al-Kidd’s detention was never meant to secure his testimony at any criminal trial:27 he was arrested for investigative purposes.28 Indeed when FBI Director Robert Mueller testified before Congress in 2003, he listed al-Kidd’s arrest as one of five major successes in the FBI’s efforts to dismantle terrorist networks in the United States.29 As we now know, that was utter nonsense: the FBI never had a shred of evidence implicating al-Kidd in any terrorist activity.30

18 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2088 n.2. 19 See al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 953. 20 Id. at 951. 21 Id. 22 Id. at 953. 23 Id. Prisoners detained in the facility for actually committing serious crimes

were treated less harshly, id. at 978. 24 Id. at 953. 25 Id. at 953–54. 26 Id. at 954. 27 See id. at 960. 28 See id. 29 Id. at 964. 30 Id. at 952.

Page 10: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

451 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Al-Kidd’s lawsuit alleged that John Ashcroft, the U.S. Attorney General at the time, implemented a policy authorizing the arrest and detention of people suspected of having ties to terrorism, often on the flimsiest of grounds (and certainly without any probable cause) under the pretext that they were material witnesses.31 Many dozens were apparently arrested and detained pursuant to that policy.32 The allegation was supported by statistical data (many individuals arrested as material witnesses post-9/11 were never asked to testify in any criminal proceeding), and by official statements and affidavits of DOJ officials—including Ashcroft’s own public statement that the Material Witness Statute was an important tool in “taking suspected terrorists off the street.”33 The lawsuit claimed that this pretextual use of the Material Witness Statute violated the Statute, as well as the Fourth and Fifth Amendments to the U.S. Constitution (the latter because of unlawful conditions of confinement).34 In fact, John Ashcroft has a history of such off-label uses of statutes: in 2001, Ashcroft issued a directive claiming that the federal Drug Abuse Prevention and Control Act, whose stated purpose is the prevention of drug abuse and addiction, made it a criminal offense for Oregon doctors to help terminally ill patients die, as authorized by

31 See id. at 954. 32 Naftali Bendavid, Material Witness Arrests Under Fire, CHI. TRIB., Dec. 24,

2001, at N1. 33 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 954. Other statements included those of Alberto

Gonzales, White House Counsel at the time; Michael Chertoff, the head of the Department of Justice’s Criminal Division, who stated publicly that the Material Witness Statute was “an important investigative tool in the war on terrorism,” id. at 962 (emphasis added); and then-FBI Director Robert Mueller, who said in a 2002 speech that “a number of suspects were detained . . . on material witness warrants,” Brief for Respondent in Opposition at 16, Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (No. 10-98). The Office of Inspector General of the Department of Justice is working on a report “reviewing the Department’s use of the material witness warrant statute, 18 U.S.C. 3144 [and] investigating whether the Department’s post-September 11th use of the statute in national security cases violated civil rights and civil liberties.” U.S. Department of Justice, Office of the Inspector General, Semiannual Report to Congress October 1, 2011 – March 31, 2012, at 17, available at http://www.justice.gov/oig/semiannual/1205/index.pdf.

34 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 955–56.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 452

Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act.35 The Supreme Court declared that directive unlawful in 2006. (Justice Scalia filed a dissenting opinion36).37 Ashcroft sought to dismiss al-Kidd’s lawsuit by claiming that even if the allegations were true and he did implement a policy of pretextual arrests under the Material Witness Statute, he was nevertheless immune because he acted in his capacity as Attorney General.38 The Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals first rejected Ashcroft’s claim of absolute immunity,39 and then turned to examine his claim of qualified immunity—to which he was entitled only if he did not violate al-Kidd’s constitutional rights, or, if he did, did so without violating a clearly established law.40 The Ninth Circuit then rejected Ashcroft’s claim of qualified immunity as well. The appellate court first held that “[t]o use a material witness statute pretextually, in order to investigate or preemptively detain suspects without probable cause, is to violate the Fourth Amendment.”41 It then determined that this was a violation of a “clearly established law”—if only because such misuse of the Material Witness Statute “gutt[ed] the substantive protections of the Fourth Amendment’s ‘probable cause’ requirement [by] giving the state the power to arrest upon the executive’s mere suspicion.”42 If al-Kidd’s allegations were true, Ashcroft made a deliberate end run around the Fourth Amendment’s probable cause requirement: could there be a clearer violation of established law?43 The Supreme Court reversed on both issues. First, the five conservative Justices (Chief Justice Robert, and Justices Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas, and Alito) joined in an opinion holding that al-Kidd’s Fourth

35 Gonzales v. Oregon, 546 U.S. 243, 253–54 (2006). 36 Id. at 275–99 (Scalia, J., dissenting). 37 Id. at 275. 38 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 952. 39 Id. 40 Id. at 964. 41 Id. at 970. 42 Id. at 972. 43 Id. at 980–81.

Page 11: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

451 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Al-Kidd’s lawsuit alleged that John Ashcroft, the U.S. Attorney General at the time, implemented a policy authorizing the arrest and detention of people suspected of having ties to terrorism, often on the flimsiest of grounds (and certainly without any probable cause) under the pretext that they were material witnesses.31 Many dozens were apparently arrested and detained pursuant to that policy.32 The allegation was supported by statistical data (many individuals arrested as material witnesses post-9/11 were never asked to testify in any criminal proceeding), and by official statements and affidavits of DOJ officials—including Ashcroft’s own public statement that the Material Witness Statute was an important tool in “taking suspected terrorists off the street.”33 The lawsuit claimed that this pretextual use of the Material Witness Statute violated the Statute, as well as the Fourth and Fifth Amendments to the U.S. Constitution (the latter because of unlawful conditions of confinement).34 In fact, John Ashcroft has a history of such off-label uses of statutes: in 2001, Ashcroft issued a directive claiming that the federal Drug Abuse Prevention and Control Act, whose stated purpose is the prevention of drug abuse and addiction, made it a criminal offense for Oregon doctors to help terminally ill patients die, as authorized by

31 See id. at 954. 32 Naftali Bendavid, Material Witness Arrests Under Fire, CHI. TRIB., Dec. 24,

2001, at N1. 33 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 954. Other statements included those of Alberto

Gonzales, White House Counsel at the time; Michael Chertoff, the head of the Department of Justice’s Criminal Division, who stated publicly that the Material Witness Statute was “an important investigative tool in the war on terrorism,” id. at 962 (emphasis added); and then-FBI Director Robert Mueller, who said in a 2002 speech that “a number of suspects were detained . . . on material witness warrants,” Brief for Respondent in Opposition at 16, Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (No. 10-98). The Office of Inspector General of the Department of Justice is working on a report “reviewing the Department’s use of the material witness warrant statute, 18 U.S.C. 3144 [and] investigating whether the Department’s post-September 11th use of the statute in national security cases violated civil rights and civil liberties.” U.S. Department of Justice, Office of the Inspector General, Semiannual Report to Congress October 1, 2011 – March 31, 2012, at 17, available at http://www.justice.gov/oig/semiannual/1205/index.pdf.

34 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 955–56.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 452

Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act.35 The Supreme Court declared that directive unlawful in 2006. (Justice Scalia filed a dissenting opinion36).37 Ashcroft sought to dismiss al-Kidd’s lawsuit by claiming that even if the allegations were true and he did implement a policy of pretextual arrests under the Material Witness Statute, he was nevertheless immune because he acted in his capacity as Attorney General.38 The Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals first rejected Ashcroft’s claim of absolute immunity,39 and then turned to examine his claim of qualified immunity—to which he was entitled only if he did not violate al-Kidd’s constitutional rights, or, if he did, did so without violating a clearly established law.40 The Ninth Circuit then rejected Ashcroft’s claim of qualified immunity as well. The appellate court first held that “[t]o use a material witness statute pretextually, in order to investigate or preemptively detain suspects without probable cause, is to violate the Fourth Amendment.”41 It then determined that this was a violation of a “clearly established law”—if only because such misuse of the Material Witness Statute “gutt[ed] the substantive protections of the Fourth Amendment’s ‘probable cause’ requirement [by] giving the state the power to arrest upon the executive’s mere suspicion.”42 If al-Kidd’s allegations were true, Ashcroft made a deliberate end run around the Fourth Amendment’s probable cause requirement: could there be a clearer violation of established law?43 The Supreme Court reversed on both issues. First, the five conservative Justices (Chief Justice Robert, and Justices Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas, and Alito) joined in an opinion holding that al-Kidd’s Fourth

35 Gonzales v. Oregon, 546 U.S. 243, 253–54 (2006). 36 Id. at 275–99 (Scalia, J., dissenting). 37 Id. at 275. 38 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 952. 39 Id. 40 Id. at 964. 41 Id. at 970. 42 Id. at 972. 43 Id. at 980–81.

Page 12: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

453 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Amendment rights were not violated.44 Second, in a part joined by all eight Justices participating in the decision (Justice Kagan recused herself from the case because of her involvement in it as solicitor general), the Court also found that Ashcroft, in any case, did not violate a clearly established law.45 That is to say, even if al-Kidd’s constitutional rights were violated, those rights were not clearly established and therefore Ashcroft could not be sued for violating them: “Ashcroft deserves . . . qualified immunity even assuming—contrafactually [sic]—that his alleged detention policy violated the Fourth Amendment.”46 Thus, not one Justice thought that arresting al-Kidd and holding him as a material witness without any intention of using him as a witness was a clear violation of the U.S. Constitution. The three participating liberal justices—Breyer, Ginsburg, and Sotomayor—claimed that the Court should not have reached the Fourth Amendment issue, since it was not necessary for the decision.47 But the conservative justices were unwilling to relinquish that part. This was unsurprising: weakening Fourth Amendment protections has long been on the agenda of the Roberts court.48 However, for Justice Scalia there was an additional reason: the Fourth Amendment ruling was squarely based on his judicial dogma.

II. PRETEXTUAL ARRESTS

The question before the Supreme Court was whether arresting an individual as a material witness when there was no intention of using him as a witness violated the Fourth Amendment.49 The Court determined that it didn’t by relying on a line of cases that refused to examine police

44 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2083. Justice Kennedy also penned a concurring opinion.

45 See id at 2085. 46 Id. 47 Id. at 2088. 48 Perhaps the most prominent example of this assault is the weakening of the

Fourth Amendment’s exclusionary rule in Herring v. United States, 555 U.S. 135 (2009). See Section VI for a discussion of additional decisions.

49 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2079.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 454

officers’ purpose or intent when deciding whether a Fourth Amendment violation occurred.50 The principal precedent was Whren v. United States51—another Scalia opinion—where officers wishing to investigate a vehicle stopped it for a minor traffic violation.52 The car’s occupants claimed that the officers violated their Fourth Amendment rights on the theory that investigatory stops, even if supported by probable cause to believe that some minor traffic violation had occurred, were unreasonable unless they would have been made absent the investigatory motive.53 After all, they claimed, “the use of automobiles is so heavily and minutely regulated that . . . a police officer will almost invariably be able to catch any given motorist in a technical violation” (or just claim that he did54).55 A unanimous Supreme Court rejected the claim. In an opinion written by Justice Scalia, the Court held that it did not matter whether the police officers who made the traffic stop did so in order to investigate the vehicle and its occupants: if there was probable cause for a traffic violation, the stop was constitutional.56 The reason for this, said the Court, was not so much the difficulty of discovering police officers’ subjective intent, but the fact that “the Fourth Amendment’s concern with ‘reasonableness’ allows certain actions to be taken in certain circumstances, whatever the subjective intent.”57 The officers’ subjective intent was simply irrelevant to the constitutionality of their actions. The al-Kidd Court found that this principle also applied to al-Kidd’s arrest: just as police officers’ investigatory motivation was

50 See id. at 2080–81. 51 Whren v. United States, 517 U.S. 806 (1996). 52 Id. at 808. 53 Id. at 809. 54 Id. at 810. Research shows that police officers lie on the stand when

questioned about possible Fourth Amendment violations, and that judges collude in such perjuries. See, e.g., Myron W. Orfield, Jr., Deterrence, Perjury, and the Heater Factor: An Exclusionary Rule in the Chicago Criminal Courts, 63 U. COLO. L. REV. 75 (1992). And minor traffic violations—like crossing a solid white line or failing to signal—are exceedingly easy to fabricate.

55 Whren, 517 U.S. at 810. 56 Id. at 806. 57 Id. at 807.

Page 13: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

453 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Amendment rights were not violated.44 Second, in a part joined by all eight Justices participating in the decision (Justice Kagan recused herself from the case because of her involvement in it as solicitor general), the Court also found that Ashcroft, in any case, did not violate a clearly established law.45 That is to say, even if al-Kidd’s constitutional rights were violated, those rights were not clearly established and therefore Ashcroft could not be sued for violating them: “Ashcroft deserves . . . qualified immunity even assuming—contrafactually [sic]—that his alleged detention policy violated the Fourth Amendment.”46 Thus, not one Justice thought that arresting al-Kidd and holding him as a material witness without any intention of using him as a witness was a clear violation of the U.S. Constitution. The three participating liberal justices—Breyer, Ginsburg, and Sotomayor—claimed that the Court should not have reached the Fourth Amendment issue, since it was not necessary for the decision.47 But the conservative justices were unwilling to relinquish that part. This was unsurprising: weakening Fourth Amendment protections has long been on the agenda of the Roberts court.48 However, for Justice Scalia there was an additional reason: the Fourth Amendment ruling was squarely based on his judicial dogma.

II. PRETEXTUAL ARRESTS

The question before the Supreme Court was whether arresting an individual as a material witness when there was no intention of using him as a witness violated the Fourth Amendment.49 The Court determined that it didn’t by relying on a line of cases that refused to examine police

44 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2083. Justice Kennedy also penned a concurring opinion.

45 See id at 2085. 46 Id. 47 Id. at 2088. 48 Perhaps the most prominent example of this assault is the weakening of the

Fourth Amendment’s exclusionary rule in Herring v. United States, 555 U.S. 135 (2009). See Section VI for a discussion of additional decisions.

49 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2079.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 454

officers’ purpose or intent when deciding whether a Fourth Amendment violation occurred.50 The principal precedent was Whren v. United States51—another Scalia opinion—where officers wishing to investigate a vehicle stopped it for a minor traffic violation.52 The car’s occupants claimed that the officers violated their Fourth Amendment rights on the theory that investigatory stops, even if supported by probable cause to believe that some minor traffic violation had occurred, were unreasonable unless they would have been made absent the investigatory motive.53 After all, they claimed, “the use of automobiles is so heavily and minutely regulated that . . . a police officer will almost invariably be able to catch any given motorist in a technical violation” (or just claim that he did54).55 A unanimous Supreme Court rejected the claim. In an opinion written by Justice Scalia, the Court held that it did not matter whether the police officers who made the traffic stop did so in order to investigate the vehicle and its occupants: if there was probable cause for a traffic violation, the stop was constitutional.56 The reason for this, said the Court, was not so much the difficulty of discovering police officers’ subjective intent, but the fact that “the Fourth Amendment’s concern with ‘reasonableness’ allows certain actions to be taken in certain circumstances, whatever the subjective intent.”57 The officers’ subjective intent was simply irrelevant to the constitutionality of their actions. The al-Kidd Court found that this principle also applied to al-Kidd’s arrest: just as police officers’ investigatory motivation was

50 See id. at 2080–81. 51 Whren v. United States, 517 U.S. 806 (1996). 52 Id. at 808. 53 Id. at 809. 54 Id. at 810. Research shows that police officers lie on the stand when

questioned about possible Fourth Amendment violations, and that judges collude in such perjuries. See, e.g., Myron W. Orfield, Jr., Deterrence, Perjury, and the Heater Factor: An Exclusionary Rule in the Chicago Criminal Courts, 63 U. COLO. L. REV. 75 (1992). And minor traffic violations—like crossing a solid white line or failing to signal—are exceedingly easy to fabricate.

55 Whren, 517 U.S. at 810. 56 Id. at 806. 57 Id. at 807.

Page 14: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

455 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

irrelevant to the constitutionality of their traffic stops, so was Ashcroft’s investigatory motivation for arresting al-Kidd irrelevant to the constitutionality of the arrest.58 Thus, assuming that the facts supported a determination that al-Kidd was a material witness, it was irrelevant—so far as the Fourth Amendment was concerned—that he was arrested for investigative purposes. To sum up: the Fourth Amendment is not violated when people are arrested and detained under the Material Witness Statute even if there is no intention to secure their testimony and their arrest and detention are done for investigative purposes, so long as the statute’s requirements of “materiality” and “impracticability” are satisfied.59 That—said the al-Kidd decision—is the teaching of Whren.

III. WHREN VERSUS SPECIAL NEEDS AND ADMINISTRATIVE SEARCHES

The Ninth Circuit, by contrast, thought that Whren was beside the point.60 In Whren there was probable cause to believe that the seized individuals committed a crime.61 If there was such suspicion of criminal wrongdoing, the officers’ subjective intent did not matter: why should we care about police officers’ intent if they act on probable cause of criminal activity? Where there is probable cause to believe a person committed a crime, that person can be constitutionally detained no matter whether the arresting officer does so for the purpose of investigating another crime.

58 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2081–82. 59 The Court explicitly refused to address the constitutionality of the Material

Witness Statute itself. See id. at 2084–85 (“It might be argued, perhaps, that when, in response to the English abuses, the Fourth Amendment said that warrants could only issue ‘on probable cause,’ it meant only probable cause to suspect a violation of law, and not probable cause to believe that the individual named in the warrant was a material witness. But that would make all arrests pursuant to material-witness warrants unconstitutional, whether pretextual or not—and that is not the position taken by al-Kidd in this case.”). But see, al-Kidd v. Ashcroft, 598 F.3d 1129, 1139 (9th Cir. 2010) (noting that the federal Material Witness Statute has existed since 1789, Bacon v. United States, 449 F.2d 933, 938 (9th Cir. 1971), every state has adopted a version of the statute, id. at 939, and (at least until now), “[t]he constitutionality of th[e] statute apparently has never been doubted,” Barry v. United States ex rel. Cunningham, 279 U.S. 597 (1929)).

60 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 968. 61 Whren, 517 U.S. 806.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 456

But in al-Kidd there was no probable cause to believe al-Kidd engaged in any criminal wrongdoing.62 Al-Kidd was detained as a material witness, not as a criminal suspect.63 Thus, said the Ninth Circuit, the governing precedent is not Whren but the line of cases dealing with searches and seizures conducted without suspicion of criminal wrongdoing—the so-called “special needs” and “administrative searches” cases.64 Such searches and seizures include, among others, routine drug testing of railroad employees,65 drug testing of school pupils,66 and stops of vehicles near the Mexican border in search of illegal immigrants67—all targeting individuals not suspected of any criminal wrongdoing. In contrast to the Whren decision, in these cases Supreme Court precedents found that the purpose, or “subjective intent,” behind the search or the seizure did matter for its constitutionality under the Fourth Amendment. Specifically, the Court conditioned their constitutionality on that purpose being something other than investigating crime. Thus, the Court affirmed the constitutionality of suspicionless drug testing of railroad employees on the ground that they were aimed at railroad safety.68 It found suspicionless vehicle stops and questioning within 100 miles of the Mexican border constitutional because they were aimed at intercepting illegal border-crossers.69 And it found suspicionless drug testing in schools constitutional because the aim was to deter drug use in schools.70 These searches and seizures were constitutional because they were not aimed at investigating and prosecuting crime but at some other legitimate purpose.71

62 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2079. 63 Id. 64 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 968–69. 65 Skinner v. Ry. Labor Execs. Ass’n, 489 U.S. 602 (1989). 66 Bd. of Educ. v. Earls, 536 U.S. 822 (2002). 67 United States v. Flores-Montano, 541 U.S. 149, 152 (2004). 68 Skinner, 489 U.S. at 620. 69 United States v. Martinez-Fuerte, 428 U.S. 543, 560–62, 562 n.15 (1976). 70 Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v. Acton, 515 U.S. 646, 653 (1995); Earls, 536 U.S.

822, at 836–37. 71 See, e.g., id. at 833.

Page 15: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

455 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

irrelevant to the constitutionality of their traffic stops, so was Ashcroft’s investigatory motivation for arresting al-Kidd irrelevant to the constitutionality of the arrest.58 Thus, assuming that the facts supported a determination that al-Kidd was a material witness, it was irrelevant—so far as the Fourth Amendment was concerned—that he was arrested for investigative purposes. To sum up: the Fourth Amendment is not violated when people are arrested and detained under the Material Witness Statute even if there is no intention to secure their testimony and their arrest and detention are done for investigative purposes, so long as the statute’s requirements of “materiality” and “impracticability” are satisfied.59 That—said the al-Kidd decision—is the teaching of Whren.

III. WHREN VERSUS SPECIAL NEEDS AND ADMINISTRATIVE SEARCHES

The Ninth Circuit, by contrast, thought that Whren was beside the point.60 In Whren there was probable cause to believe that the seized individuals committed a crime.61 If there was such suspicion of criminal wrongdoing, the officers’ subjective intent did not matter: why should we care about police officers’ intent if they act on probable cause of criminal activity? Where there is probable cause to believe a person committed a crime, that person can be constitutionally detained no matter whether the arresting officer does so for the purpose of investigating another crime.

58 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2081–82. 59 The Court explicitly refused to address the constitutionality of the Material

Witness Statute itself. See id. at 2084–85 (“It might be argued, perhaps, that when, in response to the English abuses, the Fourth Amendment said that warrants could only issue ‘on probable cause,’ it meant only probable cause to suspect a violation of law, and not probable cause to believe that the individual named in the warrant was a material witness. But that would make all arrests pursuant to material-witness warrants unconstitutional, whether pretextual or not—and that is not the position taken by al-Kidd in this case.”). But see, al-Kidd v. Ashcroft, 598 F.3d 1129, 1139 (9th Cir. 2010) (noting that the federal Material Witness Statute has existed since 1789, Bacon v. United States, 449 F.2d 933, 938 (9th Cir. 1971), every state has adopted a version of the statute, id. at 939, and (at least until now), “[t]he constitutionality of th[e] statute apparently has never been doubted,” Barry v. United States ex rel. Cunningham, 279 U.S. 597 (1929)).

60 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 968. 61 Whren, 517 U.S. 806.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 456

But in al-Kidd there was no probable cause to believe al-Kidd engaged in any criminal wrongdoing.62 Al-Kidd was detained as a material witness, not as a criminal suspect.63 Thus, said the Ninth Circuit, the governing precedent is not Whren but the line of cases dealing with searches and seizures conducted without suspicion of criminal wrongdoing—the so-called “special needs” and “administrative searches” cases.64 Such searches and seizures include, among others, routine drug testing of railroad employees,65 drug testing of school pupils,66 and stops of vehicles near the Mexican border in search of illegal immigrants67—all targeting individuals not suspected of any criminal wrongdoing. In contrast to the Whren decision, in these cases Supreme Court precedents found that the purpose, or “subjective intent,” behind the search or the seizure did matter for its constitutionality under the Fourth Amendment. Specifically, the Court conditioned their constitutionality on that purpose being something other than investigating crime. Thus, the Court affirmed the constitutionality of suspicionless drug testing of railroad employees on the ground that they were aimed at railroad safety.68 It found suspicionless vehicle stops and questioning within 100 miles of the Mexican border constitutional because they were aimed at intercepting illegal border-crossers.69 And it found suspicionless drug testing in schools constitutional because the aim was to deter drug use in schools.70 These searches and seizures were constitutional because they were not aimed at investigating and prosecuting crime but at some other legitimate purpose.71

62 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2079. 63 Id. 64 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 968–69. 65 Skinner v. Ry. Labor Execs. Ass’n, 489 U.S. 602 (1989). 66 Bd. of Educ. v. Earls, 536 U.S. 822 (2002). 67 United States v. Flores-Montano, 541 U.S. 149, 152 (2004). 68 Skinner, 489 U.S. at 620. 69 United States v. Martinez-Fuerte, 428 U.S. 543, 560–62, 562 n.15 (1976). 70 Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v. Acton, 515 U.S. 646, 653 (1995); Earls, 536 U.S.

822, at 836–37. 71 See, e.g., id. at 833.

Page 16: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

457 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Thus, the Supreme Court clearly relied on the purpose or motive behind a search or a seizure in the “special needs” and “administrative searches” contexts: if the purpose or motive was criminal investigation (and there was no criminal suspicion to justify a search or a seizure), these searches or seizures were unconstitutional. Accordingly, in Ferguson v. City of Charleston the Supreme Court held unconstitutional a program of mandatory drug testing of maternity patients in public hospitals because “the immediate objective of the searches was to generate evidence for law enforcement purposes”;72 and in City of Indianapolis v. Edmond the Court struck down motor vehicle checkpoints set up “to interdict unlawful drugs” because their purpose was, similarly, investigatory, while the stopped drivers were not individually suspected of any wrongdoing.73 These cases, according to the Ninth Circuit, stand for the proposition that without sufficient suspicion of criminal wrongdoing, it is a Fourth Amendment violation to conduct searches or seizures with an investigatory purpose in mind.74 And since in al-Kidd there was no probable cause justifying al-Kidd’s arrest, arresting al-Kidd solely for investigatory purposes was unconstitutional. But the Supreme Court rejected that argument by claiming that the Ninth Circuit misunderstood the cases.75 The “special needs” and “administrative searches” cases made the officers’ purpose relevant not because these searches or seizures were conducted in the absence of any suspicion of criminal wrongdoing, but because they were conducted without any “individualized suspicion”—whether criminal or not.76 Where there is no “individualized suspicion” of the target of the search or the seizure—some evidence pointing to that particular individual as a proper target—the search or the seizure is constitutional only if done for some legitimate non-investigative purpose (and the purpose or intent of the officers is relevant). But purpose inquiries are irrelevant where there is such “individualized suspicion,” as in al-Kidd:

72 Ferguson v. City of Charleston, 532 U.S. 67, 83 (2001). 73 City of Indianapolis v. Edmond, 531 U.S. 32, 35 (2000). 74 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 968–69. 75 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2082–83. 76 See id. at 2081 (emphasis added).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 458

[T]he affidavit accompanying the warrant application . . . gave individualized reasons to believe that [al-Kidd] was a material witness and that he would soon disappear. The existence of a judicial warrant based on individualized suspicion takes this case outside the domain of . . . our special-needs and administrative-search cases . . .77

To summarize: what distinguished the cases where purpose or motive was relevant from those where it was not, was whether the search or seizure was based on “individualized suspicion.” And the term “individualized suspicion” was not limited to the suspicion of criminal wrongdoing (as the Ninth Circuit would have it),78 but to the “suspicion” that the person is the proper subject of any constitutional search or seizure, whether based on criminal wrongdoing or not. (The term “suspicion,” said the Court, is often used in relation to perfectly innocuous activities, as in “I have a suspicion she is throwing me a surprise birthday party”).79 And since al-Kidd was the subject of such “individualized suspicion” (a magistrate judge found that he qualified for arrest as a material witness), his case fell outside the scope of the “special needs” and “administrative searches” cases, and the actual purpose or motive of executive officials was irrelevant to the constitutionality of his arrest. This reading of the cases (which was lifted from the government’s brief) is absurd: the distinction between cases where purpose or intent inquiries are essential (“special needs” and “administrative searches”) and those where they are not (Whren) cannot possibly revolve around the presence or absence of “individualized suspicion” as the al-Kidd Court understood that term—that is, as a finding of individualized eligibility for a search or a seizure whether based on criminal suspicion or not.80 If that were the case it would mean, for example, that under Skinner v. Railway Labor Executives’ Association (approving drug testing of railroad employees because it was aimed at railroad safety rather than at investigating crime), a determination that a particular individual was in fact a railroad employee would have made the purpose inquiry irrelevant

77 Id. at 2082. 78 See also id. at 2088. (Ginsburg, J., dissenting in part and concurring in part). 79 Id. at 2082. 80 See id. at 2082.

Page 17: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

457 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Thus, the Supreme Court clearly relied on the purpose or motive behind a search or a seizure in the “special needs” and “administrative searches” contexts: if the purpose or motive was criminal investigation (and there was no criminal suspicion to justify a search or a seizure), these searches or seizures were unconstitutional. Accordingly, in Ferguson v. City of Charleston the Supreme Court held unconstitutional a program of mandatory drug testing of maternity patients in public hospitals because “the immediate objective of the searches was to generate evidence for law enforcement purposes”;72 and in City of Indianapolis v. Edmond the Court struck down motor vehicle checkpoints set up “to interdict unlawful drugs” because their purpose was, similarly, investigatory, while the stopped drivers were not individually suspected of any wrongdoing.73 These cases, according to the Ninth Circuit, stand for the proposition that without sufficient suspicion of criminal wrongdoing, it is a Fourth Amendment violation to conduct searches or seizures with an investigatory purpose in mind.74 And since in al-Kidd there was no probable cause justifying al-Kidd’s arrest, arresting al-Kidd solely for investigatory purposes was unconstitutional. But the Supreme Court rejected that argument by claiming that the Ninth Circuit misunderstood the cases.75 The “special needs” and “administrative searches” cases made the officers’ purpose relevant not because these searches or seizures were conducted in the absence of any suspicion of criminal wrongdoing, but because they were conducted without any “individualized suspicion”—whether criminal or not.76 Where there is no “individualized suspicion” of the target of the search or the seizure—some evidence pointing to that particular individual as a proper target—the search or the seizure is constitutional only if done for some legitimate non-investigative purpose (and the purpose or intent of the officers is relevant). But purpose inquiries are irrelevant where there is such “individualized suspicion,” as in al-Kidd:

72 Ferguson v. City of Charleston, 532 U.S. 67, 83 (2001). 73 City of Indianapolis v. Edmond, 531 U.S. 32, 35 (2000). 74 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 968–69. 75 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2082–83. 76 See id. at 2081 (emphasis added).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 458

[T]he affidavit accompanying the warrant application . . . gave individualized reasons to believe that [al-Kidd] was a material witness and that he would soon disappear. The existence of a judicial warrant based on individualized suspicion takes this case outside the domain of . . . our special-needs and administrative-search cases . . .77

To summarize: what distinguished the cases where purpose or motive was relevant from those where it was not, was whether the search or seizure was based on “individualized suspicion.” And the term “individualized suspicion” was not limited to the suspicion of criminal wrongdoing (as the Ninth Circuit would have it),78 but to the “suspicion” that the person is the proper subject of any constitutional search or seizure, whether based on criminal wrongdoing or not. (The term “suspicion,” said the Court, is often used in relation to perfectly innocuous activities, as in “I have a suspicion she is throwing me a surprise birthday party”).79 And since al-Kidd was the subject of such “individualized suspicion” (a magistrate judge found that he qualified for arrest as a material witness), his case fell outside the scope of the “special needs” and “administrative searches” cases, and the actual purpose or motive of executive officials was irrelevant to the constitutionality of his arrest. This reading of the cases (which was lifted from the government’s brief) is absurd: the distinction between cases where purpose or intent inquiries are essential (“special needs” and “administrative searches”) and those where they are not (Whren) cannot possibly revolve around the presence or absence of “individualized suspicion” as the al-Kidd Court understood that term—that is, as a finding of individualized eligibility for a search or a seizure whether based on criminal suspicion or not.80 If that were the case it would mean, for example, that under Skinner v. Railway Labor Executives’ Association (approving drug testing of railroad employees because it was aimed at railroad safety rather than at investigating crime), a determination that a particular individual was in fact a railroad employee would have made the purpose inquiry irrelevant

77 Id. at 2082. 78 See also id. at 2088. (Ginsburg, J., dissenting in part and concurring in part). 79 Id. at 2082. 80 See id. at 2082.

Page 18: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

459 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

to the constitutionality of the ensuing blood test.81 (After all, employment status was the “suspicion” that made the subject eligible for the search.) Or it would mean that under United States v. Martinez-Fuerte (approving seizures of vehicles located within 100 miles of the Mexican border because they were aimed at intercepting illegal border-crossers), a determination that a person’s vehicle was located within 100 miles of the Mexican border would make the purpose of that vehicular seizure constitutionally irrelevant.82 That, to repeat, is an absurd reading of the cases. These decisions considered it important to inquire into the actual purpose of the search or the seizure not because the search or the seizure lacked the safeguard of an individualized determination of employment or location (it was simply assumed that the targets were indeed railroad employees or located within 100 miles of the Mexican border), but because the sole reason these searches were constitutional was that they were not aimed at investigating crime—and therefore did not require probable cause of criminal wrongdoing (or any other level of criminal suspicion justifying an investigatory search or seizure).83 Indeed in Skinner (blood tests for railroad employees) the Court commented that it would be silly to even consider the safeguard of a warrant and its determination of individualized suspicion because “a warrant would do little”84 to further the traditional aims of the warrant requirement, and “there are virtually no facts for a neutral magistrate to evaluate.”85 Again: these cases were concerned with motive or purpose not because these searches or seizures were not supported by a warrant or an individualized determination of eligibility (such eligibility was simply presumed), but because the argument for why these searches or seizures were constitutional was that they were not

81 See Skinner, 489 U.S. at 602. 82 See Martinez-Fuerte, 428 U.S. at 543. 83 “The policies behind the warrant requirement are not implicated in an

inventory search, nor is the related concept of probable cause[,] . . . particularly when no claim is made that the protective procedures are a subterfuge for criminal investigations. . . . [I]nventory procedures serve to protect an owner’s property while it is in the custody of the police, to insure against claims of lost, stolen, or vandalized property, and to guard the police from danger,” Colorado v. Bertine, 479 U.S. 367, 371–72 (1987).

84 Skinner, 489 U.S. at 622. 85 Id.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 460

concerned with investigating crime and therefore did not have to be based on the suspicion that their targets committed a crime. The “special needs” and “administrative searches” cases clearly meant by “individualized suspicion” what the Ninth Circuit opinion meant by it: individualized suspicion of criminal activity. In the absence of individualized suspicion that the person committed or was about to commit a crime, these searches and seizures were constitutional only if they were not aimed at investigating crime but at some other legitimate purpose (ensuring railroad safety, deterring drug use in school, nabbing illegal border-crossers) and were not investigating crime under a pretext (the Court explicitly mentioned the absence of a claim of pretext when upholding special needs programs).86 Indeed if these cases meant by “individualized suspicion” what the al-Kidd majority claimed they did, so that an investigatory purpose would be irrelevant to the constitutionality of a search or seizure whenever there was a determination that an individual was the proper subject of a search—be it because of criminal suspicion or because she is a material witness or a railroad employee or a school pupil or within 100 miles of the Mexican border—these programs could become an easy means of subverting regular Fourth Amendment requirements: detentions and searches of criminal suspects could take place without probable cause simply because the target was somehow eligible for some other constitutional search or seizure aimed at some non-investigatory purpose.87 The proper interpretation of the special needs precedents is the one proffered by the Ninth Circuit: if suspicion of criminal wrongdoing is the basis for the intrusion, motive inquiries are irrelevant to its constitutionality; but if a purpose other than investigating crime is the basis for the intrusion, the intrusion is constitutional only if that purpose is in fact the real basis for the search or the seizure and not a sham meant to cover for criminal investigations. Al-Kidd’s lawyers and the Ninth Circuit

86 See, e.g., id. at 621 (“Absent a persuasive showing that the [Federal Railroad

Administration's] testing program is pretextual, we assess the FRA’s scheme in light of its obvious administrative purpose.”). See also Colorado v. Bertine, 479 U.S. 367, 371 (1987) (“The . . . concept of probable cause [is not implicated] . . . when no claim is made that the protective procedures are a subterfuge for criminal investigations.” ).

87 See also al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 980–81.

Page 19: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

459 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

to the constitutionality of the ensuing blood test.81 (After all, employment status was the “suspicion” that made the subject eligible for the search.) Or it would mean that under United States v. Martinez-Fuerte (approving seizures of vehicles located within 100 miles of the Mexican border because they were aimed at intercepting illegal border-crossers), a determination that a person’s vehicle was located within 100 miles of the Mexican border would make the purpose of that vehicular seizure constitutionally irrelevant.82 That, to repeat, is an absurd reading of the cases. These decisions considered it important to inquire into the actual purpose of the search or the seizure not because the search or the seizure lacked the safeguard of an individualized determination of employment or location (it was simply assumed that the targets were indeed railroad employees or located within 100 miles of the Mexican border), but because the sole reason these searches were constitutional was that they were not aimed at investigating crime—and therefore did not require probable cause of criminal wrongdoing (or any other level of criminal suspicion justifying an investigatory search or seizure).83 Indeed in Skinner (blood tests for railroad employees) the Court commented that it would be silly to even consider the safeguard of a warrant and its determination of individualized suspicion because “a warrant would do little”84 to further the traditional aims of the warrant requirement, and “there are virtually no facts for a neutral magistrate to evaluate.”85 Again: these cases were concerned with motive or purpose not because these searches or seizures were not supported by a warrant or an individualized determination of eligibility (such eligibility was simply presumed), but because the argument for why these searches or seizures were constitutional was that they were not

81 See Skinner, 489 U.S. at 602. 82 See Martinez-Fuerte, 428 U.S. at 543. 83 “The policies behind the warrant requirement are not implicated in an

inventory search, nor is the related concept of probable cause[,] . . . particularly when no claim is made that the protective procedures are a subterfuge for criminal investigations. . . . [I]nventory procedures serve to protect an owner’s property while it is in the custody of the police, to insure against claims of lost, stolen, or vandalized property, and to guard the police from danger,” Colorado v. Bertine, 479 U.S. 367, 371–72 (1987).

84 Skinner, 489 U.S. at 622. 85 Id.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 460

concerned with investigating crime and therefore did not have to be based on the suspicion that their targets committed a crime. The “special needs” and “administrative searches” cases clearly meant by “individualized suspicion” what the Ninth Circuit opinion meant by it: individualized suspicion of criminal activity. In the absence of individualized suspicion that the person committed or was about to commit a crime, these searches and seizures were constitutional only if they were not aimed at investigating crime but at some other legitimate purpose (ensuring railroad safety, deterring drug use in school, nabbing illegal border-crossers) and were not investigating crime under a pretext (the Court explicitly mentioned the absence of a claim of pretext when upholding special needs programs).86 Indeed if these cases meant by “individualized suspicion” what the al-Kidd majority claimed they did, so that an investigatory purpose would be irrelevant to the constitutionality of a search or seizure whenever there was a determination that an individual was the proper subject of a search—be it because of criminal suspicion or because she is a material witness or a railroad employee or a school pupil or within 100 miles of the Mexican border—these programs could become an easy means of subverting regular Fourth Amendment requirements: detentions and searches of criminal suspects could take place without probable cause simply because the target was somehow eligible for some other constitutional search or seizure aimed at some non-investigatory purpose.87 The proper interpretation of the special needs precedents is the one proffered by the Ninth Circuit: if suspicion of criminal wrongdoing is the basis for the intrusion, motive inquiries are irrelevant to its constitutionality; but if a purpose other than investigating crime is the basis for the intrusion, the intrusion is constitutional only if that purpose is in fact the real basis for the search or the seizure and not a sham meant to cover for criminal investigations. Al-Kidd’s lawyers and the Ninth Circuit

86 See, e.g., id. at 621 (“Absent a persuasive showing that the [Federal Railroad

Administration's] testing program is pretextual, we assess the FRA’s scheme in light of its obvious administrative purpose.”). See also Colorado v. Bertine, 479 U.S. 367, 371 (1987) (“The . . . concept of probable cause [is not implicated] . . . when no claim is made that the protective procedures are a subterfuge for criminal investigations.” ).

87 See also al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 980–81.

Page 20: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

461 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

got it right—notwithstanding Scalia’s preposterous declaration that “only an undiscerning reader” could read the precedents differently than him.88 There are additional good reasons as to why Whren should not govern al-Kidd, above and beyond proper reading of precedents. First, while rejecting motive inquiries may make sense in the context of low-ranking police officers, al-Kidd dealt with policy-making at the highest level. This meant not only that the alleged misconduct impacted multitudes of searches and seizures (rather than a single one), but also that, unlike in Whren, there was no need to “probe [the] subjective intent” of any individual.89 Policy-making is not a matter of subjective thought but of explicit directives.90 As the Ninth Circuit put it, “we are not probing into the minds of individual officers at the scene; instead, we are inquiring into the programmatic purpose of a general policy”91—a general policy that must be manifested in explicit written or oral directives. True, Whren did not rest merely on the difficulty of establishing subjective intent; indeed, Whren insisted that the more important factor in rejecting the motive inquiry was the fact that motive was simply irrelevant to the constitutional inquiry (“the Fourth Amendment’s concern with reasonableness allows certain actions to be taken . . . whatever the subjective intent”).92 And since it was irrelevant whether a police officer detaining a suspect pursuant to a traffic violation did so solely with an investigatory purpose in mind, it was equally irrelevant—so went the claim—whether the U.S. Attorney General instituted a policy that detained individuals pursuant to the Material Witnesses Statute for the sole purpose of investigating them.

88 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2082. 89 Id. at 2077. 90 The Court noted that al-Kidd’s complaint must demonstrate not only that

Ashcroft implemented the policy which al-Kidd claimed he did, but also that his particular arrest was a result of that policy, id. at 2083 n.4—a determination that may also necessitate the “subjective” inquiry that was blocked in Whren. But if al-Kidd could prove that an official unlawful policy was applied at the time, it seems reasonable to place the burden of proof on the government that his arrest was not conducted pursuant to that unlawful policy. In any case, it would be absurd to block al-Kidd’s claim on the ground that even if his constitutional rights were violated, proving it may involve a “subjective” inquiry.

91 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 969. 92 Whren, 517 U.S. at 814.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 462

But the analogy fails for the following fundamental reason: when police officers detain individuals pursuant to probable cause to believe they committed a traffic violation, they are properly enforcing the traffic laws that authorize the detention, even if they do so solely for an investigatory purpose; but when they detain someone pursuant to the Material Witness Statute solely for an investigatory purpose, they do not properly enforce the Material Witness Statute, and the detention is not authorized by the statute. The issue is one of first principle: can the Material Witness Statute authorize the detention of individuals in cases where there is no intent to use them as witnesses? How do we determine when a statute properly applies, and therefore what it authorizes or requires? That question lay at the heart of al-Kidd’s argument before the Supreme Court.

IV. STATUTORY INTERPRETATION

Al-Kidd’s lawyers argued that if al-Kidd was arrested without the intent to secure his testimony, his arrest could not have been authorized by the Material Witness Statute. The statute, they claimed, allows the government to detain people for the purpose of securing their testimony in criminal proceedings; it does not and cannot authorize the detention of people for investigatory or preventive purposes, even when—in theory—they could qualify as material witnesses under the statute. If the government has no interest in securing a person’s testimony, the statute does not apply. In 2005, a federal district court agreed with this rather commonsensical proposition—albeit in dicta.93 The claim was the centerpiece of al-Kidd’s Fourth Amendment argument before the Supreme Court: “[T]he statute itself authorizes arrests only for the limited purpose of securing testimony,” read the brief, “[i]t does not permit material witness arrests to detain and investigate suspects whom the government lacks probable cause to arrest for a crime.”94 And this meant, in turn, that al-Kidd’s arrest violated the Fourth Amendment:

93 See United States v. Awadallah, 349 F.3d 42, 59 (2003) (dictum) (“it would

be improper for the government to use § 3144 for other ends, such as the detention of persons suspected of criminal activity for which probable cause has not yet been established”).

94 Brief for Respondent at 12, Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (No. 10-98).

Page 21: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

461 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

got it right—notwithstanding Scalia’s preposterous declaration that “only an undiscerning reader” could read the precedents differently than him.88 There are additional good reasons as to why Whren should not govern al-Kidd, above and beyond proper reading of precedents. First, while rejecting motive inquiries may make sense in the context of low-ranking police officers, al-Kidd dealt with policy-making at the highest level. This meant not only that the alleged misconduct impacted multitudes of searches and seizures (rather than a single one), but also that, unlike in Whren, there was no need to “probe [the] subjective intent” of any individual.89 Policy-making is not a matter of subjective thought but of explicit directives.90 As the Ninth Circuit put it, “we are not probing into the minds of individual officers at the scene; instead, we are inquiring into the programmatic purpose of a general policy”91—a general policy that must be manifested in explicit written or oral directives. True, Whren did not rest merely on the difficulty of establishing subjective intent; indeed, Whren insisted that the more important factor in rejecting the motive inquiry was the fact that motive was simply irrelevant to the constitutional inquiry (“the Fourth Amendment’s concern with reasonableness allows certain actions to be taken . . . whatever the subjective intent”).92 And since it was irrelevant whether a police officer detaining a suspect pursuant to a traffic violation did so solely with an investigatory purpose in mind, it was equally irrelevant—so went the claim—whether the U.S. Attorney General instituted a policy that detained individuals pursuant to the Material Witnesses Statute for the sole purpose of investigating them.

88 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2082. 89 Id. at 2077. 90 The Court noted that al-Kidd’s complaint must demonstrate not only that

Ashcroft implemented the policy which al-Kidd claimed he did, but also that his particular arrest was a result of that policy, id. at 2083 n.4—a determination that may also necessitate the “subjective” inquiry that was blocked in Whren. But if al-Kidd could prove that an official unlawful policy was applied at the time, it seems reasonable to place the burden of proof on the government that his arrest was not conducted pursuant to that unlawful policy. In any case, it would be absurd to block al-Kidd’s claim on the ground that even if his constitutional rights were violated, proving it may involve a “subjective” inquiry.

91 Al-Kidd, 580 F.3d at 969. 92 Whren, 517 U.S. at 814.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 462

But the analogy fails for the following fundamental reason: when police officers detain individuals pursuant to probable cause to believe they committed a traffic violation, they are properly enforcing the traffic laws that authorize the detention, even if they do so solely for an investigatory purpose; but when they detain someone pursuant to the Material Witness Statute solely for an investigatory purpose, they do not properly enforce the Material Witness Statute, and the detention is not authorized by the statute. The issue is one of first principle: can the Material Witness Statute authorize the detention of individuals in cases where there is no intent to use them as witnesses? How do we determine when a statute properly applies, and therefore what it authorizes or requires? That question lay at the heart of al-Kidd’s argument before the Supreme Court.

IV. STATUTORY INTERPRETATION

Al-Kidd’s lawyers argued that if al-Kidd was arrested without the intent to secure his testimony, his arrest could not have been authorized by the Material Witness Statute. The statute, they claimed, allows the government to detain people for the purpose of securing their testimony in criminal proceedings; it does not and cannot authorize the detention of people for investigatory or preventive purposes, even when—in theory—they could qualify as material witnesses under the statute. If the government has no interest in securing a person’s testimony, the statute does not apply. In 2005, a federal district court agreed with this rather commonsensical proposition—albeit in dicta.93 The claim was the centerpiece of al-Kidd’s Fourth Amendment argument before the Supreme Court: “[T]he statute itself authorizes arrests only for the limited purpose of securing testimony,” read the brief, “[i]t does not permit material witness arrests to detain and investigate suspects whom the government lacks probable cause to arrest for a crime.”94 And this meant, in turn, that al-Kidd’s arrest violated the Fourth Amendment:

93 See United States v. Awadallah, 349 F.3d 42, 59 (2003) (dictum) (“it would

be improper for the government to use § 3144 for other ends, such as the detention of persons suspected of criminal activity for which probable cause has not yet been established”).

94 Brief for Respondent at 12, Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (No. 10-98).

Page 22: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

463 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

“[A] demonstrated purpose to misuse the statute . . . is directly relevant to the Fourth Amendment analysis.”95 If the warrant was not authorized by the statute, there could be no constitutional basis for al-Kidd’s arrest.

The material witness statute is designed for a singular purpose—to secure testimony. As a matter of both the Fourth Amendment and statutory construction, the government must therefore adhere to that purpose. Otherwise, the government could circumvent the traditional rule barring custodial investigative arrests in the absence of probable cause of wrongdoing.96

The government, in response, dedicated much of its brief to the claim that “the statute . . . permits a witness to be detained, regardless of the prosecutor's motive in seeking detention.”97 Thus, whether the Material Witness Statute could be read to authorize the detention of individuals never intended to be used as material witnesses was a question that lay at the heart of the arguments submitted to the Court (and was indeed the opening point in al-Kidd’s oral argument).98 It was therefore surprising that the opinion issued in May 2011 appeared to be silent on this issue: nowhere was it stated in any explicit manner whether the statute did or did not authorize pretextual arrest warrants. And yet, there is little doubt but that the Court squarely decided it did. The opinion repeatedly relied on the assumption that al-Kidd was detained pursuant to a valid warrant issued under the authority of the Material Witness Statute. The validity of the warrant was even presumed in the Court’s framing of the issue before it.99 The warrant’s validity was

95 Id. at 11–12. 96 Id. at 42–43. 97 Reply Brief for Petitioner at 16, Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (No. 10-98). 98 See Transcript of Oral Argument at 21, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074

(2011) (No. 10-98), available at http://www.supremecourt.gov/oral_arguments/argument_ transcripts/10-98.pdf.

99 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2079 (“We decide whether a former Attorney General enjoys immunity from suit for allegedly authorizing federal prosecutors to obtain valid material-witness warrants.”). This was a very different formulation than the one appearing in the grant of certiorari (see cert. granted, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (Oct. 18, 2010) (No. 10-98)).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 464

also central, as we saw, to the way in which the Court distinguished away the “special-needs” and “administrative-searches” cases100 (the warrant supplied the determination of individualized “suspicion”), and also figured prominently in the Court’s summation of its holding.101 The Court never as much as hinted that the warrant may not have been properly issued under the statute, and in fact expressed explicit disapproval of the view that the Material Witness Statute could not authorize pretextual arrests (a view appearing in the above-mentioned 2005 federal district court opinion).102 Indeed it is hard to see how the Court could have concluded that the Fourth Amendment was not violated by al-Kidd’s arrest if the arrest warrant was not authorized by the Material Witness Statute.103 Nevertheless, a footnote in the opinion did claim that, contrary to an assertion made in Justice Ginsburg’s concurrence, the “validity” of the warrant was in fact not decided by the Court:

The validity of the warrant is not our “opening assumption” post, at 2088 (Ginsburg, J., concurring in judgment); it is the premise of al-Kidd’s argument. Al-Kidd does not claim that Ashcroft is liable because the FBI agents failed to obtain a valid warrant. He takes the validity of the warrant

100 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2081 (“The Government seeks to justify the present

arrest on the basis of a properly issued judicial warrant—so that the special-needs and administrative-inspection cases cannot be the basis for a purpose inquiry here.”).

101 Id. at 2085 (“We hold that an objectively reasonable arrest and detention of a material witness pursuant to a validly obtained warrant cannot be challenged as unconstitutional on the basis of allegations that the arresting authority had an improper motive.”).

102 Id. at 2083–84 (“A district-court opinion had suggested, in a footnoted dictum devoid of supporting citation, that using such a warrant for preventive detention of suspects ‘is an illegitimate use of the statute’—implying (we accept for the sake of argument) that the detention would therefore be unconstitutional.” (emphasis added)). Also note that the Court “accept[ed] for the sake of the argument” the claim that if the statute did not authorize the warrant, the arrest would be unconstitutional. The Supreme Court, of course, ended up deciding that the detention was constitutional.

103 The fact that the statute did not authorize the warrant does not automatically mean, of course, that the arrest was unconstitutional. But if the statute did not authorize the arrest, it is hard to think of a constitutional basis for it, given that there was no probable cause to suspect al-Kidd of criminal wrongdoing, and no intent to use him as a witness in any criminal proceeding (according to the allegations of fact which the Court had to accept in this motion to dismiss). See also supra note 102.

Page 23: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

463 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

“[A] demonstrated purpose to misuse the statute . . . is directly relevant to the Fourth Amendment analysis.”95 If the warrant was not authorized by the statute, there could be no constitutional basis for al-Kidd’s arrest.

The material witness statute is designed for a singular purpose—to secure testimony. As a matter of both the Fourth Amendment and statutory construction, the government must therefore adhere to that purpose. Otherwise, the government could circumvent the traditional rule barring custodial investigative arrests in the absence of probable cause of wrongdoing.96

The government, in response, dedicated much of its brief to the claim that “the statute . . . permits a witness to be detained, regardless of the prosecutor's motive in seeking detention.”97 Thus, whether the Material Witness Statute could be read to authorize the detention of individuals never intended to be used as material witnesses was a question that lay at the heart of the arguments submitted to the Court (and was indeed the opening point in al-Kidd’s oral argument).98 It was therefore surprising that the opinion issued in May 2011 appeared to be silent on this issue: nowhere was it stated in any explicit manner whether the statute did or did not authorize pretextual arrest warrants. And yet, there is little doubt but that the Court squarely decided it did. The opinion repeatedly relied on the assumption that al-Kidd was detained pursuant to a valid warrant issued under the authority of the Material Witness Statute. The validity of the warrant was even presumed in the Court’s framing of the issue before it.99 The warrant’s validity was

95 Id. at 11–12. 96 Id. at 42–43. 97 Reply Brief for Petitioner at 16, Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (No. 10-98). 98 See Transcript of Oral Argument at 21, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074

(2011) (No. 10-98), available at http://www.supremecourt.gov/oral_arguments/argument_ transcripts/10-98.pdf.

99 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2079 (“We decide whether a former Attorney General enjoys immunity from suit for allegedly authorizing federal prosecutors to obtain valid material-witness warrants.”). This was a very different formulation than the one appearing in the grant of certiorari (see cert. granted, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (Oct. 18, 2010) (No. 10-98)).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 464

also central, as we saw, to the way in which the Court distinguished away the “special-needs” and “administrative-searches” cases100 (the warrant supplied the determination of individualized “suspicion”), and also figured prominently in the Court’s summation of its holding.101 The Court never as much as hinted that the warrant may not have been properly issued under the statute, and in fact expressed explicit disapproval of the view that the Material Witness Statute could not authorize pretextual arrests (a view appearing in the above-mentioned 2005 federal district court opinion).102 Indeed it is hard to see how the Court could have concluded that the Fourth Amendment was not violated by al-Kidd’s arrest if the arrest warrant was not authorized by the Material Witness Statute.103 Nevertheless, a footnote in the opinion did claim that, contrary to an assertion made in Justice Ginsburg’s concurrence, the “validity” of the warrant was in fact not decided by the Court:

The validity of the warrant is not our “opening assumption” post, at 2088 (Ginsburg, J., concurring in judgment); it is the premise of al-Kidd’s argument. Al-Kidd does not claim that Ashcroft is liable because the FBI agents failed to obtain a valid warrant. He takes the validity of the warrant

100 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2081 (“The Government seeks to justify the present

arrest on the basis of a properly issued judicial warrant—so that the special-needs and administrative-inspection cases cannot be the basis for a purpose inquiry here.”).

101 Id. at 2085 (“We hold that an objectively reasonable arrest and detention of a material witness pursuant to a validly obtained warrant cannot be challenged as unconstitutional on the basis of allegations that the arresting authority had an improper motive.”).

102 Id. at 2083–84 (“A district-court opinion had suggested, in a footnoted dictum devoid of supporting citation, that using such a warrant for preventive detention of suspects ‘is an illegitimate use of the statute’—implying (we accept for the sake of argument) that the detention would therefore be unconstitutional.” (emphasis added)). Also note that the Court “accept[ed] for the sake of the argument” the claim that if the statute did not authorize the warrant, the arrest would be unconstitutional. The Supreme Court, of course, ended up deciding that the detention was constitutional.

103 The fact that the statute did not authorize the warrant does not automatically mean, of course, that the arrest was unconstitutional. But if the statute did not authorize the arrest, it is hard to think of a constitutional basis for it, given that there was no probable cause to suspect al-Kidd of criminal wrongdoing, and no intent to use him as a witness in any criminal proceeding (according to the allegations of fact which the Court had to accept in this motion to dismiss). See also supra note 102.

Page 24: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

465 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

as a given, and argues that his arrest nevertheless violated the Constitution because it was motivated by an illegitimate purpose.104

What are we to make of this disclaimer? After all, as we saw, al-Kidd strenuously objected to the validity of the warrant, claiming that the statute did not authorize it.105 Indeed in his reply to the government’s brief—where the same preposterous claim was made—al-Kidd stated unequivocally:

[R]espondent does not concede that the warrant was “valid.” Even assuming that the material witness statute's materiality and impracticability requirements were met (18 U.S.C. 3144), the position of respondent (and the Ninth Circuit) is that both the Fourth Amendment and the statute itself prohibit a material witness arrest for the purpose of investigating a suspect, rather than for securing testimony.106

How could the Court then claim that “[h]e takes the validity of the warrant as a given?”107 The key to understanding that claim is to distinguish between what the Court meant by the warrant’s “validity,” and the question of whether the Material Witness Statute authorized pretextual arrests. Al-Kidd

104 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2083 n.3. 105 See Brief for Respondent at 29–30, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd 131 S. Ct. 2074

(2011) (No. 10-98) (“The statute's text provides that a warrant may issue only where ‘the testimony of a person is material in a criminal proceeding’ and it may become ‘impracticable to secure the presence of the person by subpoena’ in that criminal proceeding, 18 U.S.C. § 3144 (emphasis added). These textual requirements belie petitioner's contention that the government need not intend actually to secure testimony for a criminal proceeding and can simply be seeking to investigate the witness himself. Indeed, if petitioner's reading of the materiality and impracticability requirements were correct, then the government could inform a magistrate judge, under oath, that it believed it would be impracticable to secure the witness's “‘presence’ at the proceeding—even if the government had no intention to call the witness at any such proceeding. That is not a commonsense interpretation of the statute's materiality and impracticability requirements.”).

106 Brief in Opposition at i, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011) (No. 10-98), 2010 WL 3777221, at i.

107 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2083 n.3.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 466

obviously never conceded the latter, but he did concede—for purposes of the question before the Supreme Court—that the falsities and omissions in the warrant application did not invalidate the warrant. (To be precise, al-Kidd did not concede that point either, but that aspect of his claim was not accepted for review by the Supreme Court.) Thus, when the Court claimed that al-Kidd “takes the validity of the warrant as a given” it did not mean that al-Kidd conceded that the Statute could authorize pretextual warrants: that claim was simply rejected on the merit. A similar (unwitting) obfuscation occurred in Justice Kennedy’s opinion.108 Kennedy joined the majority opinion in full, but also wrote a concurring opinion where he stated:

The Court’s holding is limited to the arguments presented by the parties and leaves unresolved whether the Government’s use of the Material Witness Statute in this case was lawful. See ante, at 2083 (noting that al-Kidd “does not assert that his arrest would have been unconstitutional absent the alleged pretextual use of the warrant”). . . . [T]he Court is correct to address only the legal theory put before it, without further exploring when material witness arrests might be consistent with statutory and constitutional requirements.109

That statement—like the majority’s own—does not refer to the claim that there is no statutory authority for a pretextual warrant.110 Indeed Kennedy

108 Though note that Justice Kennedy’s concurrence was joined by all the justices who refused to join the Fourth Amendment ruling and by none of the justices who did join it.

109 Id. at 2085–86 (Kennedy, J., concurring). 110 Id. The opinion continued: “The scope of the statute’s lawful authorization is

uncertain. For example, a law-abiding citizen might observe a crime during the days or weeks before a scheduled flight abroad. It is unclear whether those facts alone might allow police to obtain a material witness warrant on the ground that it ‘may become impracticable’ to secure the person’s presence by subpoena. The question becomes more difficult if one further assumes the traveler would be willing to testify if asked; and more difficult still if one supposes that authorities delay obtaining or executing the warrant until the traveler has arrived at the airport. . . . The typical arrest warrant is based on probable cause that the arrestee has committed a crime; but that is not the standard for the issuance of warrants under the Material Witness Statute. . . . If material witness warrants do not qualify as ‘Warrants’ under the Fourth Amendment, then material witness arrests might still be governed by the Fourth Amendment’s separate reasonableness requirement

Page 25: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

465 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

as a given, and argues that his arrest nevertheless violated the Constitution because it was motivated by an illegitimate purpose.104

What are we to make of this disclaimer? After all, as we saw, al-Kidd strenuously objected to the validity of the warrant, claiming that the statute did not authorize it.105 Indeed in his reply to the government’s brief—where the same preposterous claim was made—al-Kidd stated unequivocally:

[R]espondent does not concede that the warrant was “valid.” Even assuming that the material witness statute's materiality and impracticability requirements were met (18 U.S.C. 3144), the position of respondent (and the Ninth Circuit) is that both the Fourth Amendment and the statute itself prohibit a material witness arrest for the purpose of investigating a suspect, rather than for securing testimony.106

How could the Court then claim that “[h]e takes the validity of the warrant as a given?”107 The key to understanding that claim is to distinguish between what the Court meant by the warrant’s “validity,” and the question of whether the Material Witness Statute authorized pretextual arrests. Al-Kidd

104 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2083 n.3. 105 See Brief for Respondent at 29–30, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd 131 S. Ct. 2074

(2011) (No. 10-98) (“The statute's text provides that a warrant may issue only where ‘the testimony of a person is material in a criminal proceeding’ and it may become ‘impracticable to secure the presence of the person by subpoena’ in that criminal proceeding, 18 U.S.C. § 3144 (emphasis added). These textual requirements belie petitioner's contention that the government need not intend actually to secure testimony for a criminal proceeding and can simply be seeking to investigate the witness himself. Indeed, if petitioner's reading of the materiality and impracticability requirements were correct, then the government could inform a magistrate judge, under oath, that it believed it would be impracticable to secure the witness's “‘presence’ at the proceeding—even if the government had no intention to call the witness at any such proceeding. That is not a commonsense interpretation of the statute's materiality and impracticability requirements.”).

106 Brief in Opposition at i, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011) (No. 10-98), 2010 WL 3777221, at i.

107 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2083 n.3.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 466

obviously never conceded the latter, but he did concede—for purposes of the question before the Supreme Court—that the falsities and omissions in the warrant application did not invalidate the warrant. (To be precise, al-Kidd did not concede that point either, but that aspect of his claim was not accepted for review by the Supreme Court.) Thus, when the Court claimed that al-Kidd “takes the validity of the warrant as a given” it did not mean that al-Kidd conceded that the Statute could authorize pretextual warrants: that claim was simply rejected on the merit. A similar (unwitting) obfuscation occurred in Justice Kennedy’s opinion.108 Kennedy joined the majority opinion in full, but also wrote a concurring opinion where he stated:

The Court’s holding is limited to the arguments presented by the parties and leaves unresolved whether the Government’s use of the Material Witness Statute in this case was lawful. See ante, at 2083 (noting that al-Kidd “does not assert that his arrest would have been unconstitutional absent the alleged pretextual use of the warrant”). . . . [T]he Court is correct to address only the legal theory put before it, without further exploring when material witness arrests might be consistent with statutory and constitutional requirements.109

That statement—like the majority’s own—does not refer to the claim that there is no statutory authority for a pretextual warrant.110 Indeed Kennedy

108 Though note that Justice Kennedy’s concurrence was joined by all the justices who refused to join the Fourth Amendment ruling and by none of the justices who did join it.

109 Id. at 2085–86 (Kennedy, J., concurring). 110 Id. The opinion continued: “The scope of the statute’s lawful authorization is

uncertain. For example, a law-abiding citizen might observe a crime during the days or weeks before a scheduled flight abroad. It is unclear whether those facts alone might allow police to obtain a material witness warrant on the ground that it ‘may become impracticable’ to secure the person’s presence by subpoena. The question becomes more difficult if one further assumes the traveler would be willing to testify if asked; and more difficult still if one supposes that authorities delay obtaining or executing the warrant until the traveler has arrived at the airport. . . . The typical arrest warrant is based on probable cause that the arrestee has committed a crime; but that is not the standard for the issuance of warrants under the Material Witness Statute. . . . If material witness warrants do not qualify as ‘Warrants’ under the Fourth Amendment, then material witness arrests might still be governed by the Fourth Amendment’s separate reasonableness requirement

Page 26: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

467 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

clearly believed that the decision addressed the “legal theory put before it,” and the claim that there was no statutory authority for the warrant was, of course, a central part of al-Kidd’s theory. In short, notwithstanding some confusing statements to the contrary, a careful reading of the opinion shows that the Court rejected al-Kidd’s argument that the Material Witness Statute could not have authorized a pretextual arrest warrant. Unfortunately that point was apparently lost on the three liberal Justices. The three joined two concurring opinions, by Justices Ginsburg and Sotomayor, which criticized the majority for simply assuming (but not deciding) that the statute could authorize an arrest warrant in the absence of any intent to use al-Kidd as a witness.111 Indeed Justice Ginsburg went so far as to accuse the Court of making that assumption under the false pretense that al-Kidd conceded that point (“[n]owhere in al-Kidd’s complaint is there any concession that the warrant gained by the FBI agents was validly obtained. But cf. ante, at 2083, n.3 (majority opinion)” 112). Justice Ginsburg is of course correct that al-Kidd never conceded the validity of the warrant so far as statutory authority was concerned; but

for seizures of the person. See United States v. Watson, 423 U.S. 411 (1976). Given the difficulty of these issues, the Court is correct to address only the legal theory put before it, without further exploring when material witness arrests might be consistent with statutory and constitutional requirements.” Id.

111 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2090 (Sotomayor, J., concurring) (“The majority assumes away these factual difficulties . . .”); id. at 2087 (Ginsberg, J., concurring) (“In addressing al-Kidd’s Fourth Amendment claim against Ashcroft, the Court assumes at the outset the existence of a validly obtained material witness warrant”). The two concurring opinions by Justices Ginsburg and Sotomayor raised explicit doubts about the possibility that the Material Witness Statute could authorize arrests in the absence of intent to use the arrestee as a witness. Justice Sotomayor wrote it was “unclear” whether “the affidavit supporting the warrant was sufficient” because, among other things, “its failure to disclose that the Government had no intention of using al-Kidd as a witness at trial may very well have rendered the affidavit deliberately false and misleading. Cf. Franks v. Delaware, 438 U. S. 154, 155–156 (1978).” Id. at 2090 (Sotomayor, J., concurring). Justice Ginsburg similarly questioned whether a warrant was “‘validly obtained’ when the affidavit on which it is based fails to inform the issuing Magistrate Judge that ‘the Government has no intention of using [al-Kidd as a witness]’ . . . .” Id. at 2087 (Ginsberg, J., concurring) (brackets in original). This somewhat contrived way of putting things amounts in practice to the same thing—namely, doubts that the Material Witness Statute could authorize the arrest of people not intended to be used as witnesses.

112 Id. at 2087 n.1 (Ginsberg, J., concurring).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 468

contra to her assertion, the Court actually decided that issue (albeit without defending it explicitly). Indeed to claim otherwise is to accuse the Court of momentous judicial misconduct: our entire adversarial system is based on accurate representation of litigants’ claims. If Justice Ginsburg is right and the majority simply lied about al-Kidd’s argument to the Court, then Ginsburg’s allusion to this matter—which appeared in a footnote—is itself a disgrace for making a mere passing comment on such a major breach of judicial duty. No, the better interpretation is not to attribute dishonesty to the Court but to realize that the opinion decided, rather than assumed, that the Material Witness Statute could authorize the arrest of individuals not intended as witnesses (so long as its materiality and unavailability requirements were met). This interpretation is superior not only because it does not rely on a claim of judicial dissimulation, but also because it coheres very well with the judicial philosophy of the opinion’s author. Indeed the important question of statutory construction underlying the case may have eluded a number of Justices, but it could not have eluded Justice Scalia—whose fundamentalist judicial philosophy naturally leads to the conclusion that the Material Witness Statute could authorize pretextual arrests.

V. THE JURISPRUDENTIAL DEBATE

The question of statutory construction involved in the case is a familiar one.113 It is a variation of the debate pitting those who regard statutory purpose or legislative intent as an indispensable factor in statutory interpretation114 against those who think that analyzing statutory purpose or legislative intent allows for too much judicial discretion (indeed manipulation), and should therefore be virtually eliminated as a judicial consideration.115 As an alternative to the use of legislative purpose

113 One of its most famous manifestations is the Hart-Fuller debate in the

Harvard Law Review. Compare H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 (1958) with Lon Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630 (1958).

114 See generally, e.g., Fuller, supra note 113; William N. Eskridge, Jr., The New Textualism, 37 UCLA L. REV. 621 (1990).

115 See generally, e.g., Frank H. Easterbrook, Statutes’ Domains, 50 U. CHI. L.

Page 27: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

467 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

clearly believed that the decision addressed the “legal theory put before it,” and the claim that there was no statutory authority for the warrant was, of course, a central part of al-Kidd’s theory. In short, notwithstanding some confusing statements to the contrary, a careful reading of the opinion shows that the Court rejected al-Kidd’s argument that the Material Witness Statute could not have authorized a pretextual arrest warrant. Unfortunately that point was apparently lost on the three liberal Justices. The three joined two concurring opinions, by Justices Ginsburg and Sotomayor, which criticized the majority for simply assuming (but not deciding) that the statute could authorize an arrest warrant in the absence of any intent to use al-Kidd as a witness.111 Indeed Justice Ginsburg went so far as to accuse the Court of making that assumption under the false pretense that al-Kidd conceded that point (“[n]owhere in al-Kidd’s complaint is there any concession that the warrant gained by the FBI agents was validly obtained. But cf. ante, at 2083, n.3 (majority opinion)” 112). Justice Ginsburg is of course correct that al-Kidd never conceded the validity of the warrant so far as statutory authority was concerned; but

for seizures of the person. See United States v. Watson, 423 U.S. 411 (1976). Given the difficulty of these issues, the Court is correct to address only the legal theory put before it, without further exploring when material witness arrests might be consistent with statutory and constitutional requirements.” Id.

111 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2090 (Sotomayor, J., concurring) (“The majority assumes away these factual difficulties . . .”); id. at 2087 (Ginsberg, J., concurring) (“In addressing al-Kidd’s Fourth Amendment claim against Ashcroft, the Court assumes at the outset the existence of a validly obtained material witness warrant”). The two concurring opinions by Justices Ginsburg and Sotomayor raised explicit doubts about the possibility that the Material Witness Statute could authorize arrests in the absence of intent to use the arrestee as a witness. Justice Sotomayor wrote it was “unclear” whether “the affidavit supporting the warrant was sufficient” because, among other things, “its failure to disclose that the Government had no intention of using al-Kidd as a witness at trial may very well have rendered the affidavit deliberately false and misleading. Cf. Franks v. Delaware, 438 U. S. 154, 155–156 (1978).” Id. at 2090 (Sotomayor, J., concurring). Justice Ginsburg similarly questioned whether a warrant was “‘validly obtained’ when the affidavit on which it is based fails to inform the issuing Magistrate Judge that ‘the Government has no intention of using [al-Kidd as a witness]’ . . . .” Id. at 2087 (Ginsberg, J., concurring) (brackets in original). This somewhat contrived way of putting things amounts in practice to the same thing—namely, doubts that the Material Witness Statute could authorize the arrest of people not intended to be used as witnesses.

112 Id. at 2087 n.1 (Ginsberg, J., concurring).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 468

contra to her assertion, the Court actually decided that issue (albeit without defending it explicitly). Indeed to claim otherwise is to accuse the Court of momentous judicial misconduct: our entire adversarial system is based on accurate representation of litigants’ claims. If Justice Ginsburg is right and the majority simply lied about al-Kidd’s argument to the Court, then Ginsburg’s allusion to this matter—which appeared in a footnote—is itself a disgrace for making a mere passing comment on such a major breach of judicial duty. No, the better interpretation is not to attribute dishonesty to the Court but to realize that the opinion decided, rather than assumed, that the Material Witness Statute could authorize the arrest of individuals not intended as witnesses (so long as its materiality and unavailability requirements were met). This interpretation is superior not only because it does not rely on a claim of judicial dissimulation, but also because it coheres very well with the judicial philosophy of the opinion’s author. Indeed the important question of statutory construction underlying the case may have eluded a number of Justices, but it could not have eluded Justice Scalia—whose fundamentalist judicial philosophy naturally leads to the conclusion that the Material Witness Statute could authorize pretextual arrests.

V. THE JURISPRUDENTIAL DEBATE

The question of statutory construction involved in the case is a familiar one.113 It is a variation of the debate pitting those who regard statutory purpose or legislative intent as an indispensable factor in statutory interpretation114 against those who think that analyzing statutory purpose or legislative intent allows for too much judicial discretion (indeed manipulation), and should therefore be virtually eliminated as a judicial consideration.115 As an alternative to the use of legislative purpose

113 One of its most famous manifestations is the Hart-Fuller debate in the

Harvard Law Review. Compare H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593 (1958) with Lon Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630 (1958).

114 See generally, e.g., Fuller, supra note 113; William N. Eskridge, Jr., The New Textualism, 37 UCLA L. REV. 621 (1990).

115 See generally, e.g., Frank H. Easterbrook, Statutes’ Domains, 50 U. CHI. L.

Page 28: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

469 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

they propose textualism: forget about purpose or intent (or anything else, for that matter) and concentrate exclusively on the literal text.116 This methodology—so goes the claim—allows for a more objective, less discretionary and therefore less politicized form of legal interpretation, thus reducing the ability of judges to impose their ideological preferences on the legal materials.117 Justice Scalia is, as we know, a leading proponent of this approach. His advocacy of clear textual commands as the only relevant consideration appears regularly in his scholarly works118 and in his judicial output.119 The claim that the Material Witness Statute can authorize pretextual arrests is in lockstep with this textualist approach. Simply put, just as legislative purpose should be irrelevant to the application of statutes, so should executive purpose be irrelevant. Indeed the government, well aware of Justice Scalia’s position, made that very point in its Supreme Court brief in al-Kidd:

Respondent . . . contends (Br. 24-31) that Section 3144 precludes the use of a material-witness warrant for the subjective purpose of investigation . . . . Respondent arrives at his reading of the statute with little discussion of the

REV. 533 (1983); ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997); John F. Manning, The Absurdity Doctrine, 116 HARV. L. REV. 2387 (2003).

116 See generally, supra note 6. 117 Id. 118 See, e.g., SCALIA, supra note 115, at 24 (“words do have a limited range of

meaning, and no interpretation that goes beyond that range is permissible”). 119 See, e.g., MCI Telecomms. Corp. v. AT&T Co., 512 U.S. 218, 231 n.4

(1994) (Scalia, J.) (judges “are bound, not only by the ultimate purposes Congress has selected, but by the means it has deemed appropriate, and prescribed, for the pursuit of those purposes”); Pa. Dep't of Corr. v. Yeskey, 524 U.S. 206, 212 (1998) (Scalia, J.) (“[A]ssuming . . . that Congress did not ‘envisio[n] that the [Americans with Disabilities Act] would be applied to state prisoners,’ in the context of an unambiguous statutory text that is irrelevant.” (second alteration in original) (citation omitted)); W. Va. Univ. Hosps., Inc. v. Casey, 499 U.S. 83, 98–99 (1991) (Scalia, J.) (“[T]he purpose of a statute includes not only what it sets out to change, but also what it resolves to leave alone. The best evidence of that purpose is the statutory text adopted by both Houses of Congress and submitted to the President.” (citation omitted) (final disposition later superseded by statute)).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 470

statutory language, which contains two requirements: that the testimony be material and that securing the presence of the witness be impracticable. 18 U.S.C. 3144. Those are objective criteria, and nothing in the statute calls for an inquiry into the motive or purpose of the prosecutor who seeks the warrant. Rather than focus on the text of the statute, respondent attempts to demonstrate (Br. 27) that Congress did not intend “to turn the law into a detention and investigation tool.” Congress provided an objective standard for obtaining a material-witness warrant, however, and that standard, on its face, does not turn upon the prosecutor's alleged motive. Cf. Oncale v. Sundowner Offshore Servs., Inc., 523 U.S. 75, 79 (1998) (“[I]t is ultimately the provisions of our laws rather than the principal concerns of our legislators by which we are governed.” [opinion by Justice Scalia]).120

The claim sounds absurd: the Material Witness Statute, claimed the government, authorizes the arrest of people who are not intended to serve as witnesses. Al-Kidd’s brief underlined that absurdity by asking what judge would sign a Material Witness Warrant that disclosed such circumstances.121 But the Supreme Court accepted it. Indeed notwithstanding his repetitive claim to the contrary,122 over the years Justice Scalia has repeatedly embraced unreasonable legal solutions (as have many of his fellow textualists).123 Here are two prime

120 Reply Brief of Petitioner at 15, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011)

(No. 10-98) (brackets added). 121 Brief for Respondent at 29–30, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011)

(No. 10-98). 122 Justice Scalia wrote on various occasions that he subscribes to the “absurdity

doctrine,” which allows judges to reject absurd results even if these are mandated by the statutory text. See, e.g., City of Columbus v. Ours Garage & Wrecker Serv., Inc., 536 U.S. 424, 449 n.4 (2002) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (citing the rule that “a statute should not be interpreted to produce absurd results”).

123 A textualist Michigan Supreme Court, for example, made a number of absurd decisions. See, e.g., Devillers v. Auto Club Ins. Ass’n., 473., 562 (Mich. 2005) (an insured must sue or lose her rights for payments owed under insurance policy even before the insurer denied the claim); Cameron v. Auto Club Ins. Ass’n., 718 N.W.2d 784 (Mich.

Page 29: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

469 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

they propose textualism: forget about purpose or intent (or anything else, for that matter) and concentrate exclusively on the literal text.116 This methodology—so goes the claim—allows for a more objective, less discretionary and therefore less politicized form of legal interpretation, thus reducing the ability of judges to impose their ideological preferences on the legal materials.117 Justice Scalia is, as we know, a leading proponent of this approach. His advocacy of clear textual commands as the only relevant consideration appears regularly in his scholarly works118 and in his judicial output.119 The claim that the Material Witness Statute can authorize pretextual arrests is in lockstep with this textualist approach. Simply put, just as legislative purpose should be irrelevant to the application of statutes, so should executive purpose be irrelevant. Indeed the government, well aware of Justice Scalia’s position, made that very point in its Supreme Court brief in al-Kidd:

Respondent . . . contends (Br. 24-31) that Section 3144 precludes the use of a material-witness warrant for the subjective purpose of investigation . . . . Respondent arrives at his reading of the statute with little discussion of the

REV. 533 (1983); ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997); John F. Manning, The Absurdity Doctrine, 116 HARV. L. REV. 2387 (2003).

116 See generally, supra note 6. 117 Id. 118 See, e.g., SCALIA, supra note 115, at 24 (“words do have a limited range of

meaning, and no interpretation that goes beyond that range is permissible”). 119 See, e.g., MCI Telecomms. Corp. v. AT&T Co., 512 U.S. 218, 231 n.4

(1994) (Scalia, J.) (judges “are bound, not only by the ultimate purposes Congress has selected, but by the means it has deemed appropriate, and prescribed, for the pursuit of those purposes”); Pa. Dep't of Corr. v. Yeskey, 524 U.S. 206, 212 (1998) (Scalia, J.) (“[A]ssuming . . . that Congress did not ‘envisio[n] that the [Americans with Disabilities Act] would be applied to state prisoners,’ in the context of an unambiguous statutory text that is irrelevant.” (second alteration in original) (citation omitted)); W. Va. Univ. Hosps., Inc. v. Casey, 499 U.S. 83, 98–99 (1991) (Scalia, J.) (“[T]he purpose of a statute includes not only what it sets out to change, but also what it resolves to leave alone. The best evidence of that purpose is the statutory text adopted by both Houses of Congress and submitted to the President.” (citation omitted) (final disposition later superseded by statute)).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 470

statutory language, which contains two requirements: that the testimony be material and that securing the presence of the witness be impracticable. 18 U.S.C. 3144. Those are objective criteria, and nothing in the statute calls for an inquiry into the motive or purpose of the prosecutor who seeks the warrant. Rather than focus on the text of the statute, respondent attempts to demonstrate (Br. 27) that Congress did not intend “to turn the law into a detention and investigation tool.” Congress provided an objective standard for obtaining a material-witness warrant, however, and that standard, on its face, does not turn upon the prosecutor's alleged motive. Cf. Oncale v. Sundowner Offshore Servs., Inc., 523 U.S. 75, 79 (1998) (“[I]t is ultimately the provisions of our laws rather than the principal concerns of our legislators by which we are governed.” [opinion by Justice Scalia]).120

The claim sounds absurd: the Material Witness Statute, claimed the government, authorizes the arrest of people who are not intended to serve as witnesses. Al-Kidd’s brief underlined that absurdity by asking what judge would sign a Material Witness Warrant that disclosed such circumstances.121 But the Supreme Court accepted it. Indeed notwithstanding his repetitive claim to the contrary,122 over the years Justice Scalia has repeatedly embraced unreasonable legal solutions (as have many of his fellow textualists).123 Here are two prime

120 Reply Brief of Petitioner at 15, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011)

(No. 10-98) (brackets added). 121 Brief for Respondent at 29–30, Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 131 S. Ct. 2074 (2011)

(No. 10-98). 122 Justice Scalia wrote on various occasions that he subscribes to the “absurdity

doctrine,” which allows judges to reject absurd results even if these are mandated by the statutory text. See, e.g., City of Columbus v. Ours Garage & Wrecker Serv., Inc., 536 U.S. 424, 449 n.4 (2002) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (citing the rule that “a statute should not be interpreted to produce absurd results”).

123 A textualist Michigan Supreme Court, for example, made a number of absurd decisions. See, e.g., Devillers v. Auto Club Ins. Ass’n., 473., 562 (Mich. 2005) (an insured must sue or lose her rights for payments owed under insurance policy even before the insurer denied the claim); Cameron v. Auto Club Ins. Ass’n., 718 N.W.2d 784 (Mich.

Page 30: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

471 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

examples—the first taken from a case decided eleven months before al-Kidd, the second from a case involving another legally dubious action by Attorney General John Ashcroft. Hamilton v. Lanning involved an interpretation of the federal Bankruptcy Code.124 In calculating the payments that bankrupt debtors must make, the Code requires a determination of debtors’ future earnings.125 A 2005 amendment to the Code, the Bankruptcy Abuse Prevention and Consumer Protection Act of 2005, defined a debtor’s future earnings as “the average monthly income . . . during the 6-month period ending on [one of two specified dates],” minus certain specified expenses.126 The case before the Supreme Court involved a debtor who received an exceptional one-time payment during the statutory six-month period.127 As a result, the statutory formula yielded a projected monthly income that was more than double the actual one, which meant monthly payments that the debtor clearly could not make.128 The Supreme Court held that the calculated expected income needed to be adjusted, notwithstanding the clear statutory language: “the method outlined [in the statutory formula] should be determinative in most cases,” said the Court, “but . . . where significant changes in a debtor's financial circumstances are known or virtually certain, a bankruptcy court has discretion to make an appropriate adjustment.”129 Justice Scalia alone dissented from that decision. “The Court . . . can arrive at its compromise construction only by rewriting the statute,” he wrote,130 and added: “The Court says [that the formula] makes no sense unless the debtor is actually able to pay an amount equal to his projected disposable income. But it makes no sense only if one assumes that the

2006) (a statute tolling the time for minors to sue does not also toll their right to damages from their lawsuits).

124 Hamilton v. Lanning, 130 S. Ct. 2464 (2010). 125 Id. at 2469; see 11 U.S.C. §§ 1306(b), 1321, 1322(a)(1), 1328(a). 126 11 U.S.C. § 101(10A)(A). 127 Hamilton, 130 S. Ct. at 2470. 128 Id. 129 Id. at 2469. 130 Id. at 2479 (Scalia, J., dissenting).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 472

debtor is entitled to [bankruptcy protection].”131 That assumption, said Scalia, was wrong: if the debtor cannot make the payments required under the bankruptcy program, then she is simply not entitled to bankruptcy protection. In other words, if textualist construction results in denial of bankruptcy protection because of a fluke, so be it. The same methodology also led Justice Scalia to dissent in Gonzales v. Oregon, where Attorney General John Ashcroft resorted to shenanigans similar to those alleged in al-Kidd when attempting to block Oregon’s Death With Dignity Act (“ODWDA”).132 The Act exempts from civil and criminal liability physicians who, following the strict requirements of the statute, prescribe lethal doses of drugs to terminally ill patients who request them.133 John Ashcroft, a religious conservative who opposed ODWDA, issued a directive under the Controlled Substances Act (“CSA”)—a 1970 federal statute aimed at combatting drug use and addiction—declaring that Oregon physicians who prescribe drugs under ODWDA do not do so “for a legitimate medical purpose” and their license to practice medicine therefore could be revoked.134 The directive was challenged as unlawful, and the U.S. Supreme Court agreed: the CSA did not allow the Attorney General to prohibit Oregon doctors from prescribing regulated drugs for use in physician-assisted suicide.135 Justice Scalia, joined by Justice Thomas and Chief Justice Roberts, dissented:

We have repeatedly observed that Congress often passes statutes that sweep more broadly than the main problem they were designed to address. . . . “. . . [I]t is ultimately the provisions of our laws rather than the principal concerns of our legislators by which we are governed.”136

That the purpose of the Controlled Substances Act was to combat drug addiction was irrelevant for its applicability to the prescription of drugs for

131 Id. at 2481. 132 Gonzales v. Oregon, 546 U.S. 243 (2006). 133 ORE. REV. STAT. § 127.800 et seq. (2003). 134 Dispensing of Controlled Substances to Assist Suicide, 66 Fed. Reg. 56607-

08 (Nov. 9, 2001) (was to be codified at 21 C.F.R. pt. 1306). 135 Gonzales, 546 U.S. at 274–75. 136 Id. at 288 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (citation omitted).

Page 31: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

471 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

examples—the first taken from a case decided eleven months before al-Kidd, the second from a case involving another legally dubious action by Attorney General John Ashcroft. Hamilton v. Lanning involved an interpretation of the federal Bankruptcy Code.124 In calculating the payments that bankrupt debtors must make, the Code requires a determination of debtors’ future earnings.125 A 2005 amendment to the Code, the Bankruptcy Abuse Prevention and Consumer Protection Act of 2005, defined a debtor’s future earnings as “the average monthly income . . . during the 6-month period ending on [one of two specified dates],” minus certain specified expenses.126 The case before the Supreme Court involved a debtor who received an exceptional one-time payment during the statutory six-month period.127 As a result, the statutory formula yielded a projected monthly income that was more than double the actual one, which meant monthly payments that the debtor clearly could not make.128 The Supreme Court held that the calculated expected income needed to be adjusted, notwithstanding the clear statutory language: “the method outlined [in the statutory formula] should be determinative in most cases,” said the Court, “but . . . where significant changes in a debtor's financial circumstances are known or virtually certain, a bankruptcy court has discretion to make an appropriate adjustment.”129 Justice Scalia alone dissented from that decision. “The Court . . . can arrive at its compromise construction only by rewriting the statute,” he wrote,130 and added: “The Court says [that the formula] makes no sense unless the debtor is actually able to pay an amount equal to his projected disposable income. But it makes no sense only if one assumes that the

2006) (a statute tolling the time for minors to sue does not also toll their right to damages from their lawsuits).

124 Hamilton v. Lanning, 130 S. Ct. 2464 (2010). 125 Id. at 2469; see 11 U.S.C. §§ 1306(b), 1321, 1322(a)(1), 1328(a). 126 11 U.S.C. § 101(10A)(A). 127 Hamilton, 130 S. Ct. at 2470. 128 Id. 129 Id. at 2469. 130 Id. at 2479 (Scalia, J., dissenting).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 472

debtor is entitled to [bankruptcy protection].”131 That assumption, said Scalia, was wrong: if the debtor cannot make the payments required under the bankruptcy program, then she is simply not entitled to bankruptcy protection. In other words, if textualist construction results in denial of bankruptcy protection because of a fluke, so be it. The same methodology also led Justice Scalia to dissent in Gonzales v. Oregon, where Attorney General John Ashcroft resorted to shenanigans similar to those alleged in al-Kidd when attempting to block Oregon’s Death With Dignity Act (“ODWDA”).132 The Act exempts from civil and criminal liability physicians who, following the strict requirements of the statute, prescribe lethal doses of drugs to terminally ill patients who request them.133 John Ashcroft, a religious conservative who opposed ODWDA, issued a directive under the Controlled Substances Act (“CSA”)—a 1970 federal statute aimed at combatting drug use and addiction—declaring that Oregon physicians who prescribe drugs under ODWDA do not do so “for a legitimate medical purpose” and their license to practice medicine therefore could be revoked.134 The directive was challenged as unlawful, and the U.S. Supreme Court agreed: the CSA did not allow the Attorney General to prohibit Oregon doctors from prescribing regulated drugs for use in physician-assisted suicide.135 Justice Scalia, joined by Justice Thomas and Chief Justice Roberts, dissented:

We have repeatedly observed that Congress often passes statutes that sweep more broadly than the main problem they were designed to address. . . . “. . . [I]t is ultimately the provisions of our laws rather than the principal concerns of our legislators by which we are governed.”136

That the purpose of the Controlled Substances Act was to combat drug addiction was irrelevant for its applicability to the prescription of drugs for

131 Id. at 2481. 132 Gonzales v. Oregon, 546 U.S. 243 (2006). 133 ORE. REV. STAT. § 127.800 et seq. (2003). 134 Dispensing of Controlled Substances to Assist Suicide, 66 Fed. Reg. 56607-

08 (Nov. 9, 2001) (was to be codified at 21 C.F.R. pt. 1306). 135 Gonzales, 546 U.S. at 274–75. 136 Id. at 288 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (citation omitted).

Page 32: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

473 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

terminally ill patients wishing to control the time and manner of their death. The only thing that mattered was the text of the statute; and that text, said Scalia, could bear the meaning that Ashcroft gave it. The legal literature contains extensive debates over the textualist approach. In truth, these debates should have ended long ago. Lon Fuller, for one, had already demonstrated the absurdity of the textualist position in the 1950’s.137 Justice Scalia’s opinions are more grist for the mill: a statute targeting drug addiction is used to block Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act; calculations of debtors’ future income are allowed to result in denial of bankruptcy protection; and a statute allowing the exceptional detention of witnesses authorizes the detention of criminal suspects. This is the distorted legal universe inhabited by Justice Scalia and his fellow judicial fundamentalists. But then again, such absurdities mean little to these fundamentalists: indeed some of them explicitly claim that judges have a duty to adopt absurd solutions if that’s where the fundamentalist methodology leads.138 Such absurd results, they say, should be left to be corrected by the legislative process (no matter the harm caused in the meantime, or whether they actually ever get corrected).

VI. EMASCULATING FOURTH AMENDMENT PROTECTIONS

The al-Kidd decision is not only a paragon of poor craftsmanship and a shining example of judicial fundamentalism; it is also a real threat to Fourth Amendment protections. Its guiding principle—that the state of mind of executive officers is irrelevant for the constitutionality of searches and seizures (“the Fourth Amendment,” proclaimed the opinion, “regulates conduct rather than thoughts”139)—is at odds both with precedent and with sound Fourth Amendment doctrine.

137 It would mean, he said, that an ordinance forbidding “vehicles” from entering a municipal park also forbade the erection of a World War II memorial consisting of a World War II truck; and that an overworked professional dozing on a subway bench was guilty of an ordinance forbidding people from sleeping in subway stations, whereas a homeless person lying supine but awake was innocent. See Fuller, supra note 113, at 499.

138 See, e.g., John F. Manning, The Absurdity Doctrine, 116 HARV. L. REV. 2387, 2393 (2003) (calling for the abandonment of the absurdity doctrine). See also Cameron v. Auto Club Ins. Ass’n., 718 N.W.2d 784, 790–91 (Mich. 2006) (denying the claim that judges should reject absurd results).

139 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2080.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 474

Examples abound. In Franks v. Delaware, the Supreme Court recognized that false warrant applications made “knowingly and intentionally, or with reckless disregard for the truth” could invalidate the ensuing warrants.140 Thus, the very same warrant application could produce a valid or an invalid warrant, depending on the officer’s state of mind. In Hill v. California, the Supreme Court held that even where there is no probable cause for an arrest, an arrest and a subsequent search incident to arrest are constitutional if conducted by officers who reasonably and in good faith mistook that individual for another.141 The constitutionality of these actions revolved, once again, around what transpired in the arresting officers’ minds: if those officers knew they were detaining the wrong individual, the arrest would have been unconstitutional no matter how objectively reasonable the contrary belief would have been. Similarly, in Maryland v. Garrison the Supreme Court held that officers who searched the wrong apartment did not violate the Fourth Amendment if they reasonably and actually believed that they were searching the premises for which they held a search warrant.142 Indeed the Court has stated that the very existence of probable cause may depend on the personal experiences of the police officers involved.143 In fact, the Fourth Amendment itself puts stock in officers’ thoughts: by requiring that warrant applications be “supported by Oath or affirmation,” the Amendment makes clear that the honesty of police officers’ representations is a constitutional requirement.144 Additionally, a long line of cases makes the operation of the Fourth Amendment’s exclusionary rule dependent on officers’ thoughts

140 Franks v. Delaware, 438 U.S. 154, 155 (1978). 141 Hill v. California, 401 U.S. 797, 803–04 (1971) (“[T]he officers in good faith

believed Miller was Hill and arrested him. They were quite wrong as it turned out, and subjective good-faith belief would not in itself justify either the arrest or the subsequent search. But . . . the officers' mistake was understandable and the arrest a reasonable response to the situation facing them at the time.”).

142 Maryland v. Garrison, 480 U.S. 79, 88 (1987) (“Prior to the officers’ discovery of the factual mistake, they perceived McWebb’s apartment and the third-floor premises as one and the same . . . .”).

143 Ornelas v. United States, 517 U.S. 690, 699–700 (1996). 144 U.S. CONST. amend. IV.

Page 33: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

473 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

terminally ill patients wishing to control the time and manner of their death. The only thing that mattered was the text of the statute; and that text, said Scalia, could bear the meaning that Ashcroft gave it. The legal literature contains extensive debates over the textualist approach. In truth, these debates should have ended long ago. Lon Fuller, for one, had already demonstrated the absurdity of the textualist position in the 1950’s.137 Justice Scalia’s opinions are more grist for the mill: a statute targeting drug addiction is used to block Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act; calculations of debtors’ future income are allowed to result in denial of bankruptcy protection; and a statute allowing the exceptional detention of witnesses authorizes the detention of criminal suspects. This is the distorted legal universe inhabited by Justice Scalia and his fellow judicial fundamentalists. But then again, such absurdities mean little to these fundamentalists: indeed some of them explicitly claim that judges have a duty to adopt absurd solutions if that’s where the fundamentalist methodology leads.138 Such absurd results, they say, should be left to be corrected by the legislative process (no matter the harm caused in the meantime, or whether they actually ever get corrected).

VI. EMASCULATING FOURTH AMENDMENT PROTECTIONS

The al-Kidd decision is not only a paragon of poor craftsmanship and a shining example of judicial fundamentalism; it is also a real threat to Fourth Amendment protections. Its guiding principle—that the state of mind of executive officers is irrelevant for the constitutionality of searches and seizures (“the Fourth Amendment,” proclaimed the opinion, “regulates conduct rather than thoughts”139)—is at odds both with precedent and with sound Fourth Amendment doctrine.

137 It would mean, he said, that an ordinance forbidding “vehicles” from entering a municipal park also forbade the erection of a World War II memorial consisting of a World War II truck; and that an overworked professional dozing on a subway bench was guilty of an ordinance forbidding people from sleeping in subway stations, whereas a homeless person lying supine but awake was innocent. See Fuller, supra note 113, at 499.

138 See, e.g., John F. Manning, The Absurdity Doctrine, 116 HARV. L. REV. 2387, 2393 (2003) (calling for the abandonment of the absurdity doctrine). See also Cameron v. Auto Club Ins. Ass’n., 718 N.W.2d 784, 790–91 (Mich. 2006) (denying the claim that judges should reject absurd results).

139 Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2080.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 474

Examples abound. In Franks v. Delaware, the Supreme Court recognized that false warrant applications made “knowingly and intentionally, or with reckless disregard for the truth” could invalidate the ensuing warrants.140 Thus, the very same warrant application could produce a valid or an invalid warrant, depending on the officer’s state of mind. In Hill v. California, the Supreme Court held that even where there is no probable cause for an arrest, an arrest and a subsequent search incident to arrest are constitutional if conducted by officers who reasonably and in good faith mistook that individual for another.141 The constitutionality of these actions revolved, once again, around what transpired in the arresting officers’ minds: if those officers knew they were detaining the wrong individual, the arrest would have been unconstitutional no matter how objectively reasonable the contrary belief would have been. Similarly, in Maryland v. Garrison the Supreme Court held that officers who searched the wrong apartment did not violate the Fourth Amendment if they reasonably and actually believed that they were searching the premises for which they held a search warrant.142 Indeed the Court has stated that the very existence of probable cause may depend on the personal experiences of the police officers involved.143 In fact, the Fourth Amendment itself puts stock in officers’ thoughts: by requiring that warrant applications be “supported by Oath or affirmation,” the Amendment makes clear that the honesty of police officers’ representations is a constitutional requirement.144 Additionally, a long line of cases makes the operation of the Fourth Amendment’s exclusionary rule dependent on officers’ thoughts

140 Franks v. Delaware, 438 U.S. 154, 155 (1978). 141 Hill v. California, 401 U.S. 797, 803–04 (1971) (“[T]he officers in good faith

believed Miller was Hill and arrested him. They were quite wrong as it turned out, and subjective good-faith belief would not in itself justify either the arrest or the subsequent search. But . . . the officers' mistake was understandable and the arrest a reasonable response to the situation facing them at the time.”).

142 Maryland v. Garrison, 480 U.S. 79, 88 (1987) (“Prior to the officers’ discovery of the factual mistake, they perceived McWebb’s apartment and the third-floor premises as one and the same . . . .”).

143 Ornelas v. United States, 517 U.S. 690, 699–700 (1996). 144 U.S. CONST. amend. IV.

Page 34: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

475 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

(including cases dealing with the “good faith” exception).145 A recent Supreme Court decision went so far as to hold that the exclusionary rule applies only to instances involving “deliberate, reckless, or grossly negligent conduct” on the part of the police.146 Whether an officer acted “deliberately or recklessly” is, of course, not a matter of “conduct” but of “thought.” True, a number of these cases declared that the inquiry is “objective”: “[t]he pertinent analysis,” proclaimed one such typical pronouncement, “is objective, not an ‘inquiry into the subjective awareness of arresting officers.’”147 But as the Court was quick to concede, this “objective” inquiry does depend on “a particular officer's knowledge and experience . . .”148 Like it or not, the inquiry is about officers’ state of mind. The insistence on “objectivity” may come to guarantee that the inquiry does not deteriorate into mere psychological speculation. But al-Kidd certainly did not seek to support his allegations with psychological speculation but with verifiable facts regarding Ashcroft’s executive policy (public declarations, executive orders, etc.). In any case, if an arrest can becomes constitutional, despite the absence of probable cause, because the officer acted in good faith, why can’t an arrest turn unconstitutional because the Attorney General acted in bad faith? The al-Kidd decision joins a number of recent cases that, together, leave Fourth Amendment protections in tatters. Among other things, current doctrine allows the police to arrest individuals for the pettiest of crimes if they have probable cause to believe a crime has been committed (seatbelt violation, jaywalking, driving with an inoperable headlight, riding a bicycle without an audible bell, violating a dog leash law)149—even if statutory law forbids an arrest for such a petty offense.150 And once arrested, a person can be subjected to an invasive strip search, no matter the cause for the arrest (the suspect can be stripped naked while an officer examines her entire body for scars and tattoos and then peers into her

145 See, e.g., United States v. Leon, 468 U.S. 897, 914, 919–23 (1984). 146 Herring v. United States, 555 U.S. 135, 144 (2009). 147 Id. at 145. 148 Id. at 145. 149 See generally Atwater v. Lago Vista, 532 U.S. 318 (2001). 150 Virginia v. Moore, 553 U.S. 164 (2008).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 476

mouth, ears, nose, hair, scalp, armpits, anus and genitals).151 (Again, the Supreme Court authorized this procedure for people arrested for dog leash violations.152) When litigants voiced concern that officers will use common minor violations, including ubiquitous traffic violations, as pretexts for such invasive searches and seizures, the Court brushed these arguments aside:

The dissent insists that a minor traffic infraction “may often serve as an excuse” for harassment . . . [and that] the rule that we recognize today . . . “carries with it grave potential for abuse.” Post, at 371, 372. But the dissent’s own language (e.g., “may,” “potentially”) betrays the speculative nature of its claims. Noticeably absent from the parade of horribles is any indication that the “potential for abuse” has ever ripened into a reality.153

But with Whren and al-Kidd it does not even matter, so far as the Fourth Amendment is concerned, if these concerns “ripen into a reality”: officers and executive officials are explicitly authorized to make pretextual searches and seizures.154 Indeed if al-Kidd is taken at its word, officials can search people’s homes for evidence of a crime if a magistrate finds that their home is eligible for a fire inspection.155 Given the reasoning of the Court, it may not even violate the Fourth Amendment for the police to arrest or search people for punitive or vindictive purposes, so long as there is some “objective” basis for the search or the arrest.156 In fact, last June the Court held that Secret Service agents were immune from lawsuit for arresting a man for his expressed opposition to the Iraq war, where there

151 Florence v. Bd. of Chosen Freeholders of Burlington, 132 S. Ct. 1510, 1514 (2012).

152 Id. at 1527 (Breyer, J., dissenting). 153 Atwater, 532 U.S. at 353 n.25. But see Charles L. Becton, The Drug Courier

Profile: “All Seems Infected That th’ Infected Spy, as All Looks Yellow to the Jaundic’d Eye”, 65 N.C. L. REV. 417, 427 (1987) (linking racial profiling to pretextual searches and seizures).

154 See Whren, 517 U.S. 806. 155 See Camara v. Mun. Court of S.F., 387 U.S. 523 (1967) (authorizing entry of

homes for purposes of safety inspection based on area-wide evaluation of such need). 156 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2085 (2011).

Page 35: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

475 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

(including cases dealing with the “good faith” exception).145 A recent Supreme Court decision went so far as to hold that the exclusionary rule applies only to instances involving “deliberate, reckless, or grossly negligent conduct” on the part of the police.146 Whether an officer acted “deliberately or recklessly” is, of course, not a matter of “conduct” but of “thought.” True, a number of these cases declared that the inquiry is “objective”: “[t]he pertinent analysis,” proclaimed one such typical pronouncement, “is objective, not an ‘inquiry into the subjective awareness of arresting officers.’”147 But as the Court was quick to concede, this “objective” inquiry does depend on “a particular officer's knowledge and experience . . .”148 Like it or not, the inquiry is about officers’ state of mind. The insistence on “objectivity” may come to guarantee that the inquiry does not deteriorate into mere psychological speculation. But al-Kidd certainly did not seek to support his allegations with psychological speculation but with verifiable facts regarding Ashcroft’s executive policy (public declarations, executive orders, etc.). In any case, if an arrest can becomes constitutional, despite the absence of probable cause, because the officer acted in good faith, why can’t an arrest turn unconstitutional because the Attorney General acted in bad faith? The al-Kidd decision joins a number of recent cases that, together, leave Fourth Amendment protections in tatters. Among other things, current doctrine allows the police to arrest individuals for the pettiest of crimes if they have probable cause to believe a crime has been committed (seatbelt violation, jaywalking, driving with an inoperable headlight, riding a bicycle without an audible bell, violating a dog leash law)149—even if statutory law forbids an arrest for such a petty offense.150 And once arrested, a person can be subjected to an invasive strip search, no matter the cause for the arrest (the suspect can be stripped naked while an officer examines her entire body for scars and tattoos and then peers into her

145 See, e.g., United States v. Leon, 468 U.S. 897, 914, 919–23 (1984). 146 Herring v. United States, 555 U.S. 135, 144 (2009). 147 Id. at 145. 148 Id. at 145. 149 See generally Atwater v. Lago Vista, 532 U.S. 318 (2001). 150 Virginia v. Moore, 553 U.S. 164 (2008).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 476

mouth, ears, nose, hair, scalp, armpits, anus and genitals).151 (Again, the Supreme Court authorized this procedure for people arrested for dog leash violations.152) When litigants voiced concern that officers will use common minor violations, including ubiquitous traffic violations, as pretexts for such invasive searches and seizures, the Court brushed these arguments aside:

The dissent insists that a minor traffic infraction “may often serve as an excuse” for harassment . . . [and that] the rule that we recognize today . . . “carries with it grave potential for abuse.” Post, at 371, 372. But the dissent’s own language (e.g., “may,” “potentially”) betrays the speculative nature of its claims. Noticeably absent from the parade of horribles is any indication that the “potential for abuse” has ever ripened into a reality.153

But with Whren and al-Kidd it does not even matter, so far as the Fourth Amendment is concerned, if these concerns “ripen into a reality”: officers and executive officials are explicitly authorized to make pretextual searches and seizures.154 Indeed if al-Kidd is taken at its word, officials can search people’s homes for evidence of a crime if a magistrate finds that their home is eligible for a fire inspection.155 Given the reasoning of the Court, it may not even violate the Fourth Amendment for the police to arrest or search people for punitive or vindictive purposes, so long as there is some “objective” basis for the search or the arrest.156 In fact, last June the Court held that Secret Service agents were immune from lawsuit for arresting a man for his expressed opposition to the Iraq war, where there

151 Florence v. Bd. of Chosen Freeholders of Burlington, 132 S. Ct. 1510, 1514 (2012).

152 Id. at 1527 (Breyer, J., dissenting). 153 Atwater, 532 U.S. at 353 n.25. But see Charles L. Becton, The Drug Courier

Profile: “All Seems Infected That th’ Infected Spy, as All Looks Yellow to the Jaundic’d Eye”, 65 N.C. L. REV. 417, 427 (1987) (linking racial profiling to pretextual searches and seizures).

154 See Whren, 517 U.S. 806. 155 See Camara v. Mun. Court of S.F., 387 U.S. 523 (1967) (authorizing entry of

homes for purposes of safety inspection based on area-wide evaluation of such need). 156 See Ashcroft, 131 S. Ct. at 2085 (2011).

Page 36: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

477 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

was probable cause for his arrest.157 The Court did not even stop to consider whether such a vindictive, retaliatory arrest comported with the Fourth Amendment: it simply assumed that it did, and only granted review over the question of whether the arrest violated the First Amendment (the Court then concluded it didn’t).158

CONCLUSION

The al-Kidd decision is a natural outgrowth of Justice Scalia’s judicial philosophy. And that judicial philosophy is, of course, equally applicable to other bodies of law revolving around the purposes or motives of legislative or executive officials—from the First Amendment to Equal Protection guarantees to issues of federalism.159 It remains to be seen whether, and to what extent, these doctrines would also fall prey to Scalia’s interpretive dogma. The problem with this sort of fundamentalism—like the problem with political or religious fundamentalism—is its reductive approach to complex social and political problems. Judicial fundamentalism wants

157 See Reichle v. Howards, 132 S. Ct. 2088 (2012). 158 “The questions presented are: . . . 2. Whether the Tenth Circuit erred by

denying qualified and absolute immunity to petitioners where probable cause existed for respondent's arrest, the arrest comported with the Fourth Amendment, it was not (and is not) clearly established that Hartman does not apply to First Amendment retaliatory arrest claims, and the denial of immunity threatens to interfere with the split-second, life-or-death decisions of Secret Service agents protecting the President and Vice President.” Petition for Certiorari at i, Reichle v. Howards, 634 F.3d 1131 (10th Cir. 2011) (No. 11-262), 2011 WL 3809375 at i.

159 See, e.g., Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520, 532 (1993) (“In our Establishment Clause cases we have often stated the principle that the First Amendment forbids an official purpose to disapprove of a particular religion or of religion in general. See, e.g., Bd. of Ed. of Westside Community Sch. (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U.S. 226, 248 (1990) (plurality opinion); Sch. Dist. of Grand Rapids v. Ball, 473 U.S. 373, 389 (1985); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U.S. 38, 56 (1985); Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U.S. 97, 106–107 (1968); Sch. Dist. of Abington v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203, 225 (1963); Everson v. Bd. of Ed. of Ewing, 330 U.S. 1, 15–16 (1947).”); Batson v. Kentucky, 476 U.S. 79, 93 (1986); Minnesota v. Clover Leaf Creamery, 449 U.S. 456, 471 n.15 (1981); See generally McCreary Cnty., Ky. v. Am. Civil Liberties Union of Ky., 545 U.S. 844, 861 (2005) (“[G]overnmental purpose is a key element of a good deal of constitutional doctrine . . .”).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 478

lawyers and judges to reach legal conclusions while closing their eyes to considerations that everybody considers relevant and important to legal requirements—like fairness, justice, efficiency, and, of course, the purpose of a statute or an executive action. No one denies that purpose, fairness, justice, and efficiency are relevant and important factors in using the coercive power of the state; yet judicial fundamentalists call for banishing these factors from legal decision-making, and for leaving them exclusively to the consideration of legislative or executive officials. Why? What’s behind this impoverished approach to judicial reasoning? The wish to eliminate judicial discretion is, of course, the immediate cause: conservative jurists like Scalia embrace textualism as a way to curb what they see as an elitist liberal judiciary bent on reading its liberal ideology into the law. But the deliberate impoverishment of judicial decision-making has deeper intellectual roots. In The Open Society and Its Enemies, Karl Popper explored the antagonism between an “open society” characterized by commitment to answering social, moral, and political questions through critical rational deliberations, and a “closed society” marked by commitment to unquestioned authority and political totalitarianism.160 Popper—who traces the antagonism back to Athenian democracy and its enemies—locates the essence of the conflict in the antagonists’ approach to reason: “The great difference [between the two camps] is the [belief in the] possibility of rational reflection . . . .”161 The proponents of the closed society, who advocate strict obedience to authority, exhibit deep skepticism toward rationality in the domains of politics and ethics: “[A]uthoritarian or conservative principles are usually an expression of ethical nihilism; that is to say, of an extreme moral scepticism, of a distrust of man and of his possibilities.”162 The ethical and political norms

160 Karl R. Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. I (4th ed. 1963). 161 Id. at 1732. 162 Id. at 72; see also KARL R. POPPER, CONJECTURES AND REFUTATIONS 6 (2d

ed. 1962) (“Man can know: thus, he can be free. This is the formula which explains the link between epistemological optimism and the idea of liberalism. This link is paralleled by the opposite link. Disbelief in the power of human reason, in man’s power to discern the truth, is almost invariably linked with distrust of man. Thus epistemological pessimism is linked, historically, with a doctrine of human depravity, and it tends to lead to the demand for the establishment of powerful traditions and the entrenchment of a powerful authority which would save man from his folly and wickedness . . . . [W]e can

Page 37: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

477 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

was probable cause for his arrest.157 The Court did not even stop to consider whether such a vindictive, retaliatory arrest comported with the Fourth Amendment: it simply assumed that it did, and only granted review over the question of whether the arrest violated the First Amendment (the Court then concluded it didn’t).158

CONCLUSION

The al-Kidd decision is a natural outgrowth of Justice Scalia’s judicial philosophy. And that judicial philosophy is, of course, equally applicable to other bodies of law revolving around the purposes or motives of legislative or executive officials—from the First Amendment to Equal Protection guarantees to issues of federalism.159 It remains to be seen whether, and to what extent, these doctrines would also fall prey to Scalia’s interpretive dogma. The problem with this sort of fundamentalism—like the problem with political or religious fundamentalism—is its reductive approach to complex social and political problems. Judicial fundamentalism wants

157 See Reichle v. Howards, 132 S. Ct. 2088 (2012). 158 “The questions presented are: . . . 2. Whether the Tenth Circuit erred by

denying qualified and absolute immunity to petitioners where probable cause existed for respondent's arrest, the arrest comported with the Fourth Amendment, it was not (and is not) clearly established that Hartman does not apply to First Amendment retaliatory arrest claims, and the denial of immunity threatens to interfere with the split-second, life-or-death decisions of Secret Service agents protecting the President and Vice President.” Petition for Certiorari at i, Reichle v. Howards, 634 F.3d 1131 (10th Cir. 2011) (No. 11-262), 2011 WL 3809375 at i.

159 See, e.g., Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520, 532 (1993) (“In our Establishment Clause cases we have often stated the principle that the First Amendment forbids an official purpose to disapprove of a particular religion or of religion in general. See, e.g., Bd. of Ed. of Westside Community Sch. (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U.S. 226, 248 (1990) (plurality opinion); Sch. Dist. of Grand Rapids v. Ball, 473 U.S. 373, 389 (1985); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U.S. 38, 56 (1985); Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U.S. 97, 106–107 (1968); Sch. Dist. of Abington v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203, 225 (1963); Everson v. Bd. of Ed. of Ewing, 330 U.S. 1, 15–16 (1947).”); Batson v. Kentucky, 476 U.S. 79, 93 (1986); Minnesota v. Clover Leaf Creamery, 449 U.S. 456, 471 n.15 (1981); See generally McCreary Cnty., Ky. v. Am. Civil Liberties Union of Ky., 545 U.S. 844, 861 (2005) (“[G]overnmental purpose is a key element of a good deal of constitutional doctrine . . .”).

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 478

lawyers and judges to reach legal conclusions while closing their eyes to considerations that everybody considers relevant and important to legal requirements—like fairness, justice, efficiency, and, of course, the purpose of a statute or an executive action. No one denies that purpose, fairness, justice, and efficiency are relevant and important factors in using the coercive power of the state; yet judicial fundamentalists call for banishing these factors from legal decision-making, and for leaving them exclusively to the consideration of legislative or executive officials. Why? What’s behind this impoverished approach to judicial reasoning? The wish to eliminate judicial discretion is, of course, the immediate cause: conservative jurists like Scalia embrace textualism as a way to curb what they see as an elitist liberal judiciary bent on reading its liberal ideology into the law. But the deliberate impoverishment of judicial decision-making has deeper intellectual roots. In The Open Society and Its Enemies, Karl Popper explored the antagonism between an “open society” characterized by commitment to answering social, moral, and political questions through critical rational deliberations, and a “closed society” marked by commitment to unquestioned authority and political totalitarianism.160 Popper—who traces the antagonism back to Athenian democracy and its enemies—locates the essence of the conflict in the antagonists’ approach to reason: “The great difference [between the two camps] is the [belief in the] possibility of rational reflection . . . .”161 The proponents of the closed society, who advocate strict obedience to authority, exhibit deep skepticism toward rationality in the domains of politics and ethics: “[A]uthoritarian or conservative principles are usually an expression of ethical nihilism; that is to say, of an extreme moral scepticism, of a distrust of man and of his possibilities.”162 The ethical and political norms

160 Karl R. Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. I (4th ed. 1963). 161 Id. at 1732. 162 Id. at 72; see also KARL R. POPPER, CONJECTURES AND REFUTATIONS 6 (2d

ed. 1962) (“Man can know: thus, he can be free. This is the formula which explains the link between epistemological optimism and the idea of liberalism. This link is paralleled by the opposite link. Disbelief in the power of human reason, in man’s power to discern the truth, is almost invariably linked with distrust of man. Thus epistemological pessimism is linked, historically, with a doctrine of human depravity, and it tends to lead to the demand for the establishment of powerful traditions and the entrenchment of a powerful authority which would save man from his folly and wickedness . . . . [W]e can

Page 38: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

479 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

endorsed by the “closed society” camp are therefore derived from authority and tradition, as opposed to norms formulated in rational deliberations. Such outlook, it seems to me, is reflected in Justice Scalia’s take on legal decision-making. Scalia is by no means an ethical nihilist: to the contrary, he is a moralist who considers purely moralistic legislation (like the prohibition of homosexual sodomy or adultery, or even masturbation) perfectly constitutional.163 But this moralistic position, with its roots in religion and tradition, is similarly rooted in deep skepticism over the possibility of objectively rational deliberations on matters of social policy and morality.164 It may sound unfair—perhaps even paradoxical—to accuse textualism of authoritarian affinities, since the very justification of textualism is its purported fidelity to democracy: textualists claim that non-textualist adjudication usurps the role of elected representatives by legislating from the bench, and that textualism is therefore the one truly democratic method of legal interpretation.165 But the fundamentalists’

interpret traditionalism as the belief that, in the absence of an objective and discernible truth, we are faced with the choice between accepting the authority of tradition, and chaos; while rationalism has, of course, always claimed the right of reason and of empirical science to criticize, and to reject, any tradition, and any authority, as being based on sheer unreason or prejudice or accident.”).

163 See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 585–605 (2003) (Scalia, J., dissenting).

164 See, e.g., ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION 17–18 (1997) (“[U]nder the guise or even the self-delusion of pursuing unexpressed legislative intents, common-law judges will in fact pursue their own objectives and desires . . . . When you are told to decide, not on the basis of what the legislature said, but on the basis of what it meant . . . your best shot at figuring out what the legislature meant is to ask yourself what a wise and intelligent person should have meant; and that will surely bring you to the conclusion that the law means what you think it ought to mean—which is precisely how judges decide things under the common law . . .”); Antonin Scalia, Originalism: the Lesser Evil, 57 U. CINN. L. REV. 849, 863 (1989) (“Now the main danger in judicial interpretation of the Constitution—or, for that matter, in judicial interpretation of any law—is that the judges will mistake their own predilections for the law . . . . Nonoriginalism, which under one or another formulation invokes ‘fundamental values’ as the touchstone of constitutionality, plays precisely to this weakness. It is very difficult for a person to discern a difference between those political values that he personally thinks most important, and those political values that are ‘fundamental to our society.’”).

165 See, e.g., Antonin Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 56 U. CHI. L.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 480

declared fidelity to democracy need not mean, of course, that their position is actually faithful to it. (Conversely, as Popper reminds us, Socrates’ alleged opposition to democracy leaves intact his exemplification of the democratic spirit of open and critical inquiry.166) Judicial fundamentalism is rooted in skepticism toward judicial rationality in matters of politics and morality, and such skepticism, claimed Karl Popper, has historically and intellectually aligned itself with the forces of authoritarianism against the forces of freedom. Popper’s observation strikes me as intuitively correct and also applicable to Justice Scalia and his ideological allies: there is an authoritarian streak to their judicial fundamentalism—both to its decision-making process and (as al-Kidd amply demonstrates) to the substantive decisions it manages to make.

REV. 1175, 1179 (1989). 166 See POPPER, supra note 160. Popper offers a reinterpretation of Socrates,

which depicts Plato’s description of Socrates as an opponent of democracy as a misrepresentation and a great betrayal of the Master.

Page 39: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

479 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

endorsed by the “closed society” camp are therefore derived from authority and tradition, as opposed to norms formulated in rational deliberations. Such outlook, it seems to me, is reflected in Justice Scalia’s take on legal decision-making. Scalia is by no means an ethical nihilist: to the contrary, he is a moralist who considers purely moralistic legislation (like the prohibition of homosexual sodomy or adultery, or even masturbation) perfectly constitutional.163 But this moralistic position, with its roots in religion and tradition, is similarly rooted in deep skepticism over the possibility of objectively rational deliberations on matters of social policy and morality.164 It may sound unfair—perhaps even paradoxical—to accuse textualism of authoritarian affinities, since the very justification of textualism is its purported fidelity to democracy: textualists claim that non-textualist adjudication usurps the role of elected representatives by legislating from the bench, and that textualism is therefore the one truly democratic method of legal interpretation.165 But the fundamentalists’

interpret traditionalism as the belief that, in the absence of an objective and discernible truth, we are faced with the choice between accepting the authority of tradition, and chaos; while rationalism has, of course, always claimed the right of reason and of empirical science to criticize, and to reject, any tradition, and any authority, as being based on sheer unreason or prejudice or accident.”).

163 See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 585–605 (2003) (Scalia, J., dissenting).

164 See, e.g., ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION 17–18 (1997) (“[U]nder the guise or even the self-delusion of pursuing unexpressed legislative intents, common-law judges will in fact pursue their own objectives and desires . . . . When you are told to decide, not on the basis of what the legislature said, but on the basis of what it meant . . . your best shot at figuring out what the legislature meant is to ask yourself what a wise and intelligent person should have meant; and that will surely bring you to the conclusion that the law means what you think it ought to mean—which is precisely how judges decide things under the common law . . .”); Antonin Scalia, Originalism: the Lesser Evil, 57 U. CINN. L. REV. 849, 863 (1989) (“Now the main danger in judicial interpretation of the Constitution—or, for that matter, in judicial interpretation of any law—is that the judges will mistake their own predilections for the law . . . . Nonoriginalism, which under one or another formulation invokes ‘fundamental values’ as the touchstone of constitutionality, plays precisely to this weakness. It is very difficult for a person to discern a difference between those political values that he personally thinks most important, and those political values that are ‘fundamental to our society.’”).

165 See, e.g., Antonin Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 56 U. CHI. L.

2013] Judicial Fundamentalism 480

declared fidelity to democracy need not mean, of course, that their position is actually faithful to it. (Conversely, as Popper reminds us, Socrates’ alleged opposition to democracy leaves intact his exemplification of the democratic spirit of open and critical inquiry.166) Judicial fundamentalism is rooted in skepticism toward judicial rationality in matters of politics and morality, and such skepticism, claimed Karl Popper, has historically and intellectually aligned itself with the forces of authoritarianism against the forces of freedom. Popper’s observation strikes me as intuitively correct and also applicable to Justice Scalia and his ideological allies: there is an authoritarian streak to their judicial fundamentalism—both to its decision-making process and (as al-Kidd amply demonstrates) to the substantive decisions it manages to make.

REV. 1175, 1179 (1989). 166 See POPPER, supra note 160. Popper offers a reinterpretation of Socrates,

which depicts Plato’s description of Socrates as an opponent of democracy as a misrepresentation and a great betrayal of the Master.

Page 40: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

481 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

THE FOURTH AMENDMENT IN THE INFORMATION AGE

Ricardo J. Bascuas

ABSTRACT

In 2013, the Supreme Court tacitly conceded that the expectations-of-privacy test used since 1967 to assess claims of Fourth Amendment violations was inadequate. It asserted that the previous property-based test for Fourth Amendment violations had never—despite widespread agreement to the contrary—been overruled. The Court compounded its artfulness by applying a new, significantly weaker trespass test that, like the expectations-of-privacy test, enjoys no legal pedigree. This new trespass test, which is to be applied together with the expectations-of-privacy test, suffers from the same defect as the test it purportedly supplements. It does not require the government to respect private property rights absent probable cause. Part I describes Olmstead v. United States, an early missed opportunity to have created a pragmatic Fourth Amendment trespass test that set the stage for the unpredictable and unprincipled jurisprudence that Justice Brandeis’ ill-conceived dissent later inspired. Part II explains how the expectations-of-privacy test that originated with Katz v. United States in 1967 allowed the Court to put sensitive records and communications as well as contraband beyond the Fourth Amendment’s scope. Katz also helped turn the ever-growing number of pervasive corporations against their customers and into surveillance agents for the government. Part III demonstrates how Katz’s superfluous and sweeping pronouncements about privacy expectations added no significant constitutional

Professor, University of Miami School of Law.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 482

protection that the trespass test it supplanted did not already afford. Instead, it enabled the erosion of significant rights that had existed. Jones consciously perpetuates these flaws, affording courts no help in adjudicating Fourth Amendment claims involving new technology. Part IV shows that, in federal fraud cases, the Court identifies property interests using a pragmatic, flexible, common-law approach consistent with the pre-Katz trespass test. It argues that this same analysis could be applied to Fourth Amendment claims, resolving the problems that the expectations-of-privacy approach has generated.

TABLE OF CONTENTS

I. KATZ’S FLAWED FOUNDATION .......................................... 491

II. KATZ’S CURTAILMENT OF PRIVACY .................................. 500

A. Katz’s Failure to Protect “Papers” ................................ 501 B. Katz’s Failure to Protect “Effects” ............................... 509

III. KATZ, JONES, AND THE POSTMODERN FOURTH AMENDMENT

............................................................................................ 515

IV. PRAGMATIC PROPERTY IN THE INFORMATION AGE ........ 528

V. CONCLUSION ...................................................................... 537 In October 2009, Sprint Nextel’s manager of electronic surveillance spoke at a conference in Washington, D.C., for telecommunications company employees and law enforcement and intelligence agents.1 He boasted that the cellular telephone carrier had created an automated system for law enforcement officers to easily learn

1 Christopher Soghoian, DEA Rejects FOIA for 38 Pages of Docs Related to

Sprint’s Digital Surveillance API, SLIGHT PARANOIA (March 23, 2011), http://paranoia.dubfire.net/2011/03/dea-rejects-foia-for-38-pages-of-docs.html.

Page 41: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

481 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

THE FOURTH AMENDMENT IN THE INFORMATION AGE

Ricardo J. Bascuas

ABSTRACT

In 2013, the Supreme Court tacitly conceded that the expectations-of-privacy test used since 1967 to assess claims of Fourth Amendment violations was inadequate. It asserted that the previous property-based test for Fourth Amendment violations had never—despite widespread agreement to the contrary—been overruled. The Court compounded its artfulness by applying a new, significantly weaker trespass test that, like the expectations-of-privacy test, enjoys no legal pedigree. This new trespass test, which is to be applied together with the expectations-of-privacy test, suffers from the same defect as the test it purportedly supplements. It does not require the government to respect private property rights absent probable cause. Part I describes Olmstead v. United States, an early missed opportunity to have created a pragmatic Fourth Amendment trespass test that set the stage for the unpredictable and unprincipled jurisprudence that Justice Brandeis’ ill-conceived dissent later inspired. Part II explains how the expectations-of-privacy test that originated with Katz v. United States in 1967 allowed the Court to put sensitive records and communications as well as contraband beyond the Fourth Amendment’s scope. Katz also helped turn the ever-growing number of pervasive corporations against their customers and into surveillance agents for the government. Part III demonstrates how Katz’s superfluous and sweeping pronouncements about privacy expectations added no significant constitutional

Professor, University of Miami School of Law.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 482

protection that the trespass test it supplanted did not already afford. Instead, it enabled the erosion of significant rights that had existed. Jones consciously perpetuates these flaws, affording courts no help in adjudicating Fourth Amendment claims involving new technology. Part IV shows that, in federal fraud cases, the Court identifies property interests using a pragmatic, flexible, common-law approach consistent with the pre-Katz trespass test. It argues that this same analysis could be applied to Fourth Amendment claims, resolving the problems that the expectations-of-privacy approach has generated.

TABLE OF CONTENTS

I. KATZ’S FLAWED FOUNDATION .......................................... 491

II. KATZ’S CURTAILMENT OF PRIVACY .................................. 500

A. Katz’s Failure to Protect “Papers” ................................ 501 B. Katz’s Failure to Protect “Effects” ............................... 509

III. KATZ, JONES, AND THE POSTMODERN FOURTH AMENDMENT

............................................................................................ 515

IV. PRAGMATIC PROPERTY IN THE INFORMATION AGE ........ 528

V. CONCLUSION ...................................................................... 537 In October 2009, Sprint Nextel’s manager of electronic surveillance spoke at a conference in Washington, D.C., for telecommunications company employees and law enforcement and intelligence agents.1 He boasted that the cellular telephone carrier had created an automated system for law enforcement officers to easily learn

1 Christopher Soghoian, DEA Rejects FOIA for 38 Pages of Docs Related to

Sprint’s Digital Surveillance API, SLIGHT PARANOIA (March 23, 2011), http://paranoia.dubfire.net/2011/03/dea-rejects-foia-for-38-pages-of-docs.html.

Page 42: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

483 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

the location of any Sprint Nextel customer.2 Federal agents accessed the automated tracking system eight million times between September 2008 and October 2009 without oversight or demonstration of good cause.3 Paul Taylor, the Sprint Nextel manager, boasted about the Drug Enforcement Agency’s use of the company’s state-of-the-art interface:

We have a pilot program with them, where they have a subpoena generation system in-house where their agents actually sit down and enter case data, it gets approved by the head guy at the office, and then from there, it gets electronically sent to Sprint, and we get it … So, the DEA is using this, they’re sending a lot and the turn-around time is 12-24 hours. So we see a lot of uses there.4

Privacy researcher and blogger Christopher Soghoian, who was in attendance, posted recordings of the panel discussion on the Internet.5 The blog post drew attention to Soghoian’s ongoing efforts to ascertain the scope of government surveillance conducted with corporate help.6 Two days later, TeleStrategies, the company hosting the “Intelligence Support Systems for Lawful Interception, Criminal Investigation and Intelligence Gathering” conference, forced Soghoian to remove the videos, claiming copyright infringement.7 Sprint Nextel disingenuously said via Twitter that Taylor’s unabridged comments were “taken out of context.”8

2 Id. 3 Id. 4 Id. (alteration in original). 5 Christopher Soghoian, 8 Million Reasons for Real Surveillance Oversight,

SLIGHT PARANOIA (Dec. 1, 2009), http://paranoia.dubfire.net/2009_12_01_archive.html. 6 Jon Stokes, Sprint Fed Customer GPS Data to Cops over 8 Million Times, ARS

TECHNICA (Dec. 1, 2009, 6:38 PM), http://arstechnica.com/telecom/news/2009/12/sprint-fed-customer-gps-data-to-leos-over-8-million-times.ars.

7 Soghoian, supra note 5. 8 Rich Pesce, Sharing Location Information, SPRINT COMMUNITY (Dec. 1, 2009,

3:30 PM), http://community.sprint.com/baw/community/sprintblogs/announcements/blog/2009/12/01/sharing-location-information.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 484

In his blog post publicizing Sprint Nextel’s disclosure, Soghoian pointed out that Sprint Nextel is not the only company handing over customer data to the government: “These Internet/telecommunications firms all have special departments, many open 24 hours per day, whose staff do nothing but respond to legal requests. Their entire purpose is to facilitate the disclosure of their customers’ records to law enforcement and intelligence agencies . . . .”9 The information routinely disclosed includes “the telephone numbers dialed, text messages, emails and instant messages sent, web pages browsed, the queries submitted to search engines, and geolocation data, detailing exactly where an individual was located at a particular date and time.”10 The scale on which this type of surveillance occurs is unknown. Soghoian had long been working to learn how much government surveillance is conducted through telecommunications companies. Before the 2009 ISS World conference, he theorized that knowing the rates these companies charge the government for each surveillance request—they do not do this for free—would help him estimate the frequency of requests. Soghoian made Freedom of Information Act requests to federal law enforcement agencies to learn the prices carriers charged them for customer data.11 Carriers objected, claiming that all information related to their disclosures to law enforcement agencies is secret.12 After the conference, Soghoian specifically requested information regarding the DEA’s use of Sprint Nextel’s system; the DEA declined to produce any information.13 Even small, local police departments now routinely obtain location information, text messages, and other data from cellular carriers.14

9 Soghoian, supra note 5. 10 Id. 11 Christopher Soghoian, FOIA Returns 91 Invoices for Yahoo Surveillance, 1

for Google, SLIGHT PARANOIA (Jan. 18, 2010), http://paranoia.dubfire.net/2010/01/foia-returns-91-invoices-for-yahoo.html; Soghoian, supra note 5.

12 Soghoian, supra note 5. 13 Soghoian, supra note 1. 14 Eric Lichtblau, Police Are Using Phone Tracking as a Routine Tool, N.Y.

TIMES, Apr. 1, 2012, at A1.

Page 43: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

483 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

the location of any Sprint Nextel customer.2 Federal agents accessed the automated tracking system eight million times between September 2008 and October 2009 without oversight or demonstration of good cause.3 Paul Taylor, the Sprint Nextel manager, boasted about the Drug Enforcement Agency’s use of the company’s state-of-the-art interface:

We have a pilot program with them, where they have a subpoena generation system in-house where their agents actually sit down and enter case data, it gets approved by the head guy at the office, and then from there, it gets electronically sent to Sprint, and we get it … So, the DEA is using this, they’re sending a lot and the turn-around time is 12-24 hours. So we see a lot of uses there.4

Privacy researcher and blogger Christopher Soghoian, who was in attendance, posted recordings of the panel discussion on the Internet.5 The blog post drew attention to Soghoian’s ongoing efforts to ascertain the scope of government surveillance conducted with corporate help.6 Two days later, TeleStrategies, the company hosting the “Intelligence Support Systems for Lawful Interception, Criminal Investigation and Intelligence Gathering” conference, forced Soghoian to remove the videos, claiming copyright infringement.7 Sprint Nextel disingenuously said via Twitter that Taylor’s unabridged comments were “taken out of context.”8

2 Id. 3 Id. 4 Id. (alteration in original). 5 Christopher Soghoian, 8 Million Reasons for Real Surveillance Oversight,

SLIGHT PARANOIA (Dec. 1, 2009), http://paranoia.dubfire.net/2009_12_01_archive.html. 6 Jon Stokes, Sprint Fed Customer GPS Data to Cops over 8 Million Times, ARS

TECHNICA (Dec. 1, 2009, 6:38 PM), http://arstechnica.com/telecom/news/2009/12/sprint-fed-customer-gps-data-to-leos-over-8-million-times.ars.

7 Soghoian, supra note 5. 8 Rich Pesce, Sharing Location Information, SPRINT COMMUNITY (Dec. 1, 2009,

3:30 PM), http://community.sprint.com/baw/community/sprintblogs/announcements/blog/2009/12/01/sharing-location-information.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 484

In his blog post publicizing Sprint Nextel’s disclosure, Soghoian pointed out that Sprint Nextel is not the only company handing over customer data to the government: “These Internet/telecommunications firms all have special departments, many open 24 hours per day, whose staff do nothing but respond to legal requests. Their entire purpose is to facilitate the disclosure of their customers’ records to law enforcement and intelligence agencies . . . .”9 The information routinely disclosed includes “the telephone numbers dialed, text messages, emails and instant messages sent, web pages browsed, the queries submitted to search engines, and geolocation data, detailing exactly where an individual was located at a particular date and time.”10 The scale on which this type of surveillance occurs is unknown. Soghoian had long been working to learn how much government surveillance is conducted through telecommunications companies. Before the 2009 ISS World conference, he theorized that knowing the rates these companies charge the government for each surveillance request—they do not do this for free—would help him estimate the frequency of requests. Soghoian made Freedom of Information Act requests to federal law enforcement agencies to learn the prices carriers charged them for customer data.11 Carriers objected, claiming that all information related to their disclosures to law enforcement agencies is secret.12 After the conference, Soghoian specifically requested information regarding the DEA’s use of Sprint Nextel’s system; the DEA declined to produce any information.13 Even small, local police departments now routinely obtain location information, text messages, and other data from cellular carriers.14

9 Soghoian, supra note 5. 10 Id. 11 Christopher Soghoian, FOIA Returns 91 Invoices for Yahoo Surveillance, 1

for Google, SLIGHT PARANOIA (Jan. 18, 2010), http://paranoia.dubfire.net/2010/01/foia-returns-91-invoices-for-yahoo.html; Soghoian, supra note 5.

12 Soghoian, supra note 5. 13 Soghoian, supra note 1. 14 Eric Lichtblau, Police Are Using Phone Tracking as a Routine Tool, N.Y.

TIMES, Apr. 1, 2012, at A1.

Page 44: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

485 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Providers of Internet, email, cloud-storage, and “social-networking” services also provide information.15 Companies and government agencies seek to minimize the attention paid to this practice undoubtedly because of the Orwellian flavor to the idea that the corporations responsible for everyone’s personal communications and files are government clients. One police department, for example, instructed officers not to discuss cellular tracking publicly and not to mention it in police reports.16 But neither do agencies and corporations conceal their information trade, which is, from the point of view of big government and big business, just the natural result of the way things are. The corporations have information, the government can subpoena it, and the corporations have no choice but to turn it over. It’s that way in China,17 and it’s that way in the United States of America. For more than 80 years, the Supreme Court has fretted over the surveillance capabilities the information age has provided the federal, state, and local governments. Listening devices,18 recording equipment,19 tracking devices,20 surveillance aircraft,21 thermal imagers,22 urinalysis,23

15 See, e.g., Transparency Report, GOOGLE, http://www.google.com/transparencyreport/ userdatarequests/US/?p=2011-12 (last visited Apr. 20, 2013).

16 Lichtblau, supra note 14. 17 See Ricardo J. Bascuas, Property and Probable Cause: The Fourth

Amendment’s Principled Protection of Privacy, 60 RUTGERS L. REV. 575, 575–80 (2008) (describing Congressional hearings over an email service provider’s giving a political dissident’s emails to the Chinese government, which then imprisoned the dissident).

18 United States v. White, 401 U.S. 745 (1971) (plurality opinion) (holding that conversations with bugged informant were not protected by the Fourth Amendment); Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 509 (1961) (holding use of “spike mike” unconstitutional and describing parabolic microphone).

19 Lopez v. United States, 373 U.S. 427 (1963) (holding that recording of undercover agent’s conversation with defendant did not violate the Fourth Amendment).

20 United States v. Karo, 468 U.S. 705 (1984); United States v. Knotts, 460 U.S. 276 (1983).

21 Florida v. Riley, 488 U.S. 445 (1989); California v. Ciraollo, 476 U.S. 207 (1986).

22 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27 (2001). 23 Bd. of Educ. v. Earls, 536 U.S. 822 (2002); Ferguson v. City of Charleston,

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 486

and hemanalysis24 have had justices fretting over the Fourth Amendment’s ability to protect private life from technological encroachment. In 1928, Justice Brandies forebodingly warned: “Ways may some day be developed by which the Government, without removing papers from secret drawers, can reproduce them in court, and by which it will be enabled to expose to a jury the most intimate occurrences of the home.”25 Nearly 40 years later, Justice Douglas feared the situation had grown dire: “We are rapidly entering the age of no privacy, where everyone is open to surveillance at all times; where there are no secrets from government.”26 “The law, though jealous of individual privacy, has not kept pace with these advances in scientific knowledge,” concluded Justice Clark a year later.27 Consternation over tomorrow’s surveillance technology has been the constant feature of an otherwise haphazard Fourth Amendment jurisprudence. The Court tried proceeding incrementally, as in 1961’s Silverman v. United States, when Justice Stewart’s majority reached a narrow holding rather than attempting one that would curtail the use of parabolic microphones “and other frightening paraphernalia which the vaunted marvels of an electronic age may visit upon human society.”28 Forty years later, another majority took the opposite tack. Alarmed that X-ray vision “is a clear, and scientifically feasible, goal of law enforcement research and development,” Justice Scalia’s opinion in Kyllo v. United States sought to craft a future-proof holding: “While the technology used in the present case was relatively crude, the rule we adopt must take account of more sophisticated systems that are already in use or in development.”29 532 U.S. 67 (2001); Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v. Acton, 515 U.S. 646 (1995); Nat’l Treasury Emps. Union v. Von Raab, 489 U.S. 656 (1989).

24 Schmerber v. United States, 384 U.S. 757, 767 (1966). 25 Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438, 474 (1928) (Brandeis, J.,

dissenting). 26 Osborn v. United States, 385 U.S. 323, 342–43 (1966) (Douglas, J., dissenting

in two cases and concurring in one); see also Schmerber, 384 U.S. at 778–79 (Douglas, J., dissenting).

27 Berger v. New York, 388 U.S. 41, 49 (1967). 28 Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 509 (1961). 29 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27, 35 & n.3 (2001).

Page 45: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

485 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Providers of Internet, email, cloud-storage, and “social-networking” services also provide information.15 Companies and government agencies seek to minimize the attention paid to this practice undoubtedly because of the Orwellian flavor to the idea that the corporations responsible for everyone’s personal communications and files are government clients. One police department, for example, instructed officers not to discuss cellular tracking publicly and not to mention it in police reports.16 But neither do agencies and corporations conceal their information trade, which is, from the point of view of big government and big business, just the natural result of the way things are. The corporations have information, the government can subpoena it, and the corporations have no choice but to turn it over. It’s that way in China,17 and it’s that way in the United States of America. For more than 80 years, the Supreme Court has fretted over the surveillance capabilities the information age has provided the federal, state, and local governments. Listening devices,18 recording equipment,19 tracking devices,20 surveillance aircraft,21 thermal imagers,22 urinalysis,23

15 See, e.g., Transparency Report, GOOGLE, http://www.google.com/transparencyreport/ userdatarequests/US/?p=2011-12 (last visited Apr. 20, 2013).

16 Lichtblau, supra note 14. 17 See Ricardo J. Bascuas, Property and Probable Cause: The Fourth

Amendment’s Principled Protection of Privacy, 60 RUTGERS L. REV. 575, 575–80 (2008) (describing Congressional hearings over an email service provider’s giving a political dissident’s emails to the Chinese government, which then imprisoned the dissident).

18 United States v. White, 401 U.S. 745 (1971) (plurality opinion) (holding that conversations with bugged informant were not protected by the Fourth Amendment); Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 509 (1961) (holding use of “spike mike” unconstitutional and describing parabolic microphone).

19 Lopez v. United States, 373 U.S. 427 (1963) (holding that recording of undercover agent’s conversation with defendant did not violate the Fourth Amendment).

20 United States v. Karo, 468 U.S. 705 (1984); United States v. Knotts, 460 U.S. 276 (1983).

21 Florida v. Riley, 488 U.S. 445 (1989); California v. Ciraollo, 476 U.S. 207 (1986).

22 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27 (2001). 23 Bd. of Educ. v. Earls, 536 U.S. 822 (2002); Ferguson v. City of Charleston,

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 486

and hemanalysis24 have had justices fretting over the Fourth Amendment’s ability to protect private life from technological encroachment. In 1928, Justice Brandies forebodingly warned: “Ways may some day be developed by which the Government, without removing papers from secret drawers, can reproduce them in court, and by which it will be enabled to expose to a jury the most intimate occurrences of the home.”25 Nearly 40 years later, Justice Douglas feared the situation had grown dire: “We are rapidly entering the age of no privacy, where everyone is open to surveillance at all times; where there are no secrets from government.”26 “The law, though jealous of individual privacy, has not kept pace with these advances in scientific knowledge,” concluded Justice Clark a year later.27 Consternation over tomorrow’s surveillance technology has been the constant feature of an otherwise haphazard Fourth Amendment jurisprudence. The Court tried proceeding incrementally, as in 1961’s Silverman v. United States, when Justice Stewart’s majority reached a narrow holding rather than attempting one that would curtail the use of parabolic microphones “and other frightening paraphernalia which the vaunted marvels of an electronic age may visit upon human society.”28 Forty years later, another majority took the opposite tack. Alarmed that X-ray vision “is a clear, and scientifically feasible, goal of law enforcement research and development,” Justice Scalia’s opinion in Kyllo v. United States sought to craft a future-proof holding: “While the technology used in the present case was relatively crude, the rule we adopt must take account of more sophisticated systems that are already in use or in development.”29 532 U.S. 67 (2001); Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v. Acton, 515 U.S. 646 (1995); Nat’l Treasury Emps. Union v. Von Raab, 489 U.S. 656 (1989).

24 Schmerber v. United States, 384 U.S. 757, 767 (1966). 25 Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438, 474 (1928) (Brandeis, J.,

dissenting). 26 Osborn v. United States, 385 U.S. 323, 342–43 (1966) (Douglas, J., dissenting

in two cases and concurring in one); see also Schmerber, 384 U.S. at 778–79 (Douglas, J., dissenting).

27 Berger v. New York, 388 U.S. 41, 49 (1967). 28 Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 509 (1961). 29 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27, 35 & n.3 (2001).

Page 46: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

487 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

The Court has vacillated not only over the breadth of its holdings but also over the substance of what the Fourth Amendment prohibits. Until 1967, the Court evaluated Fourth Amendment claims using property law concepts, reasoning that the amendment prohibited government from trespassing property without good reason. So, in 1928’s Olmstead v. United States, the Court upheld wiretaps of telephone lines used by the defendants but physically located outside their homes and offices.30 The intercepted conversations, being neither papers nor effects, could not be seized, reasoned the Court.31 After years of intermittent progress toward repudiating Olmstead’s faulty reasoning, the Court abandoned the property framework in 1967, holding in Katz v. United States that the Fourth Amendment protects an implicit right to privacy.32 This created a great many problems and solved none. Forty-five years after Katz, a bare majority of the Court implicitly conceded what had for decades been obvious: that the Katz test often sanctions intrusions that the Fourth Amendment ought, by its plain terms, to condemn. The Court unanimously concluded in United States v. Jones that police officers violated the Fourth Amendment when they attached a tracking device to a Jeep parked in a public lot—but divided over why.33 Four justices believed GPS tracking infringed on “expectations of privacy”34 while the majority invoked the pre-Katz property framework,35 claiming that “the Katz reasonable-expectation-of-privacy test has been added to, not substituted for, the common-law trespassory test.”36 If this

30 Olmstead, 277 U.S. at 464. 31 Id. 32 Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 259 (1967). 33 United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945 (2012). 34 Id. at 958 (Alito, J., concurring). 35 This is not the first time Justice Scalia has channeled Chief Justice Taft in a

Fourth Amendment case. In Wyoming v. Houghton, 526 U.S. 295 (1999), Justice Scalia applied the same methodology that Chief Justice Taft used for determining whether a search was unreasonable in Carroll v. United States, 267 U.S. 132 (1925). See Ricardo J. Bascuas, Fourth Amendment Lessons from the Highway and the Subway: A Principled Approach to Suspicionless Searches, 38 RUTGERS L.J. 719, 739–41 (2007).

36 Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 952.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 488

were true, it would mean that the Court had been lying for years.37 Nearly every justice to sit on the Court since Katz—including every justice on the Jones Court (except the recently confirmed Justice Elena Kagan)—had until Jones said that Katz overruled Olmstead—and not by elaborating on its approach but by supplanting the property framework with one based only on an ill-defined notion of privacy.38 An earlier majority opinion,

37 None of the cases on which Jones relied to support its re-characterization of Katz lent support. On the contrary, these cases went to great pains to explain why the Katz formulation alone sufficed to determine whether a search occurred and pretended that the Katz test invariably offers broader Fourth Amendment protection than the trespass test it supplanted. Alderman v. United States, 394 U.S. 165 (1969), gave a property owner standing to object to the admission of conversations other people had in his premises not on the basis of a trespass theory, but on the theory (coincidentally also espoused by Justice Scalia’s majority opinion in Kyllo v. United States) that everything inside a home is private. The Court held that, whether there is a trespass or not, “officialdom invades an area in which the homeowner has the right to expect privacy for himself, his family, and his invitees, and the right to object to the use against him of the fruits of that invasion, not because the rights of others have been violated, but because his own were.” Id. at 179 n.11. Oliver v. United States predicated its holding not on “open fields” being outside of the Fourth Amendment’s scope, but on their not being private: “The existence of a property right is but one element in determining whether expectations of privacy are legitimate.” 466 U.S. 170 (1984). United States v. Soldal involved a seizure, not a search, and consequently it was enough that the mobile-home owners had been unlawfully dispossessed of their property: “[S]eizures of property are subject to Fourth Amendment scrutiny even though no search within the meaning of the Amendment has taken place.” 506 U.S. 58, 68 (1992).

38 See City of Ontario v. Quon, 130 S. Ct. 2619, 2629 (2010) (opinion of the Court by Kennedy, J., joined by Roberts, C.J., & Stevens, Thomas, Ginsburg, Breyer, Alito & Sotomayor, JJ.) (citing Olmstead as being overruled by Katz); United States v. Knotts, 460 U.S. 276, 280 (1983) (opinion of the Court by Rehnquist, C.J., joined by Burger, White, Marshall, Powell & O’Connor, JJ.) (noting that in Katz, “the Court overruled Olmstead saying that the Fourth Amendment’s reach ‘cannot turn upon the presence or absence of a physical intrusion into any given enclosure’”); United States v. Johnson, 457 U.S. 537, 559 (1982) (opinion of the Court by Blackmun, J., joined by Brennan, Marshall, Powell & Stevens, JJ.) (citing Katz as overruling Olmstead); Rakas v. Illinois, 439 U.S. 128, 143 (1978) (opinion of the Court by Rehnquist, J., joined by Burger, C.J., & Stewart, Blackmun & Powell, JJ.); (stating that Katz “repudiate[ed] the doctrine derived from” Olmstead and Goldman); Kaiser v. New York, 394 U.S. 280, 282 (1969) (opinion of the Court by Stewart, J., joined by Warren, C.J., & Brennan, White & Marshall, JJ.) (“[Olmstead], then, stated the controlling interpretation of the Fourth Amendment with respect to wiretapping until it was overruled by [Katz].”); Desist v.

Page 47: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

487 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

The Court has vacillated not only over the breadth of its holdings but also over the substance of what the Fourth Amendment prohibits. Until 1967, the Court evaluated Fourth Amendment claims using property law concepts, reasoning that the amendment prohibited government from trespassing property without good reason. So, in 1928’s Olmstead v. United States, the Court upheld wiretaps of telephone lines used by the defendants but physically located outside their homes and offices.30 The intercepted conversations, being neither papers nor effects, could not be seized, reasoned the Court.31 After years of intermittent progress toward repudiating Olmstead’s faulty reasoning, the Court abandoned the property framework in 1967, holding in Katz v. United States that the Fourth Amendment protects an implicit right to privacy.32 This created a great many problems and solved none. Forty-five years after Katz, a bare majority of the Court implicitly conceded what had for decades been obvious: that the Katz test often sanctions intrusions that the Fourth Amendment ought, by its plain terms, to condemn. The Court unanimously concluded in United States v. Jones that police officers violated the Fourth Amendment when they attached a tracking device to a Jeep parked in a public lot—but divided over why.33 Four justices believed GPS tracking infringed on “expectations of privacy”34 while the majority invoked the pre-Katz property framework,35 claiming that “the Katz reasonable-expectation-of-privacy test has been added to, not substituted for, the common-law trespassory test.”36 If this

30 Olmstead, 277 U.S. at 464. 31 Id. 32 Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 259 (1967). 33 United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945 (2012). 34 Id. at 958 (Alito, J., concurring). 35 This is not the first time Justice Scalia has channeled Chief Justice Taft in a

Fourth Amendment case. In Wyoming v. Houghton, 526 U.S. 295 (1999), Justice Scalia applied the same methodology that Chief Justice Taft used for determining whether a search was unreasonable in Carroll v. United States, 267 U.S. 132 (1925). See Ricardo J. Bascuas, Fourth Amendment Lessons from the Highway and the Subway: A Principled Approach to Suspicionless Searches, 38 RUTGERS L.J. 719, 739–41 (2007).

36 Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 952.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 488

were true, it would mean that the Court had been lying for years.37 Nearly every justice to sit on the Court since Katz—including every justice on the Jones Court (except the recently confirmed Justice Elena Kagan)—had until Jones said that Katz overruled Olmstead—and not by elaborating on its approach but by supplanting the property framework with one based only on an ill-defined notion of privacy.38 An earlier majority opinion,

37 None of the cases on which Jones relied to support its re-characterization of Katz lent support. On the contrary, these cases went to great pains to explain why the Katz formulation alone sufficed to determine whether a search occurred and pretended that the Katz test invariably offers broader Fourth Amendment protection than the trespass test it supplanted. Alderman v. United States, 394 U.S. 165 (1969), gave a property owner standing to object to the admission of conversations other people had in his premises not on the basis of a trespass theory, but on the theory (coincidentally also espoused by Justice Scalia’s majority opinion in Kyllo v. United States) that everything inside a home is private. The Court held that, whether there is a trespass or not, “officialdom invades an area in which the homeowner has the right to expect privacy for himself, his family, and his invitees, and the right to object to the use against him of the fruits of that invasion, not because the rights of others have been violated, but because his own were.” Id. at 179 n.11. Oliver v. United States predicated its holding not on “open fields” being outside of the Fourth Amendment’s scope, but on their not being private: “The existence of a property right is but one element in determining whether expectations of privacy are legitimate.” 466 U.S. 170 (1984). United States v. Soldal involved a seizure, not a search, and consequently it was enough that the mobile-home owners had been unlawfully dispossessed of their property: “[S]eizures of property are subject to Fourth Amendment scrutiny even though no search within the meaning of the Amendment has taken place.” 506 U.S. 58, 68 (1992).

38 See City of Ontario v. Quon, 130 S. Ct. 2619, 2629 (2010) (opinion of the Court by Kennedy, J., joined by Roberts, C.J., & Stevens, Thomas, Ginsburg, Breyer, Alito & Sotomayor, JJ.) (citing Olmstead as being overruled by Katz); United States v. Knotts, 460 U.S. 276, 280 (1983) (opinion of the Court by Rehnquist, C.J., joined by Burger, White, Marshall, Powell & O’Connor, JJ.) (noting that in Katz, “the Court overruled Olmstead saying that the Fourth Amendment’s reach ‘cannot turn upon the presence or absence of a physical intrusion into any given enclosure’”); United States v. Johnson, 457 U.S. 537, 559 (1982) (opinion of the Court by Blackmun, J., joined by Brennan, Marshall, Powell & Stevens, JJ.) (citing Katz as overruling Olmstead); Rakas v. Illinois, 439 U.S. 128, 143 (1978) (opinion of the Court by Rehnquist, J., joined by Burger, C.J., & Stewart, Blackmun & Powell, JJ.); (stating that Katz “repudiate[ed] the doctrine derived from” Olmstead and Goldman); Kaiser v. New York, 394 U.S. 280, 282 (1969) (opinion of the Court by Stewart, J., joined by Warren, C.J., & Brennan, White & Marshall, JJ.) (“[Olmstead], then, stated the controlling interpretation of the Fourth Amendment with respect to wiretapping until it was overruled by [Katz].”); Desist v.

Page 48: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

489 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

also penned by Justice Scalia, outright said that the Court had “decoupled violation of a person’s Fourth Amendment rights from trespassory violation of his property . . . .”39 Katz itself hinted as much when it held that Olmstead’s underpinnings “have been so eroded by our subsequent decisions that the ‘trespass’ doctrine there enunciated can no longer be regarded as controlling.”40 Until Jones, Katz’s overruling of Olmstead was

United States, 394 U.S. 244, 247–48 (1969) (opinion of the Court by Stewart, J., joined by Warren, C.J., & Brennan, White & Marshall, JJ.) (“Our holding [in Katz] that [Goldman] and [Olmstead] ‘can no longer be regarded as controlling’ recognized that those decisions had not been overruled until that day.”) (citation omitted); see also Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 920 (2010) (Roberts, C.J., concurring, joined by Alito, J.) (citing Olmstead as being overruled by Katz); Harper v. Va. Dep’t of Taxation, 509 U.S. 86, 109 (1993) (Scalia, J., concurring) (same); Florida v. Riley, 488 U.S. 445, 459 n.3 (1989) (Brennan, J., dissenting, joined by Stevens, J.) (“And of course [Katz], which overruled Olmstead, made plain that the question whether or not the disputed evidence had been procured by means of a trespass was irrelevant.”); California v. Greenwood, 486 U.S. 35, 51 (1988) (Brennan, J., dissenting, joined by Marshall, J.) (“The Court properly rejects the State’s attempt to distinguish trash searches from other searches on the theory that trash is abandoned and therefore not entitled to an expectation of privacy.”); California v. Rooney, 483 U.S. 307, 320 (1987) (White, J., dissenting from dismissal of writ of certiorari, joined by Rehnquist, C.J., & Powell, J.) (assuming that petitioner retained ownership of garbage and stating, “Rooney’s property interest, however, does not settle the matter for Fourth Amendment purposes, for the reach of the Fourth Amendment is not determined by state property law”); United States v. Jacobsen, 466 U.S. 109, 138 (1984) (Brennan, J., dissenting, joined by Marshall, J.) (“Fortunately, we know from precedents such as [Katz], overruling the ‘trespass’ doctrine of [Goldman] and [Olmstead], that this Court ultimately stands ready to prevent this Orwellian world from coming to pass.”); United States v. Peltier, 422 U.S. 531, 547 n.5 (1975) (Brennan, J., dissenting, joined by Stewart & Marshal, JJ.) (citing Katz as having “explicitly” overruled Olmstead); Williams v. United States, 401 U.S. 646, 653–54 (1971) (plurality opinion by White, J., joined by Burger, C.J., & Stewart & Blackmun, JJ.) (“[Katz] overruled [Olmstead] and [Goldman] and gave expanded Fourth Amendment protection against nonconsensual eavesdropping.”); United States v. White, 401 U.S. 745, 748–49 (1971) (plurality opinion by White, J., joined by Burger, C.J., & Stewart & Blackmun, JJ.) (recognizing that the Court in Katz overruled Goldman and Olmstead); id. at 780 (Harlan, J., dissenting) (“[Katz] added no new dimension to the law. At most it was a formal dispatch of [Olmstead] and the notion that such problems may usefully be resolved in the light of trespass doctrine . . . .”).

39 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27, 32 (2001) (citing Rakas, 439 U.S. at 143). 40 Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 353 (1967).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 490

such a foregone certainty that the most influential legal style manual used Olmstead to illustrate how to cite an overruled case.41 Katz declared “expectations of privacy” to be the concept at the core of the Fourth Amendment, disregarding its language as well as the trespass standard. With Katz, the Court licensed itself to withdraw the Fourth Amendment’s protection from virtually all modern records and communications and from contraband—two types of property that the Fourth Amendment was most certainly meant to protect. In the process, the Court turned corporate service providers against their customers and conscripted them into service as government spies.42 Given that relationships with giant corporations penetrate even the most intimate aspects of modern life, the expectations-of-privacy framework has ironically proven deeply inimical to individual privacy. Despite its pretentions, Jones does not redress Katz’s flaws so much as mimic them. Jones creates a new trespass test, just as malleable as Katz’s expectations-of-privacy approach. The test combines a narrow, recently contrived definition of “seizure” with narrow, colonial-era notions of houses, papers, and effects. Jones thus repudiates the idea, embodied in the Court’s pre-Katz holdings, that technological innovation yields new forms of property entitled to full Fourth Amendment protection. By 1967, the Court had made significant progress toward a pragmatic, flexible understanding of “papers” and “effects”—one adaptable to technological change—repudiating Olmstead’s two key premises. It ruled that the amendment protected against trespasses in a broad rather than a legalistic sense and that conversations, despite being intangible, were protected “papers” or “effects”. The Court’s post-Katz Fourth Amendment jurisprudence, including Jones, has disregarded that pragmatic, principled understanding of a Fourth Amendment violation. But the property notions underlying it have endured. Outside of the Fourth Amendment context, the Supreme Court and the lower federal courts have

41 THE BLUEBOOK: A UNIFORM SYSTEM OF CITATION R. 10.7.1(c)(i), at 102

(Columbia Law Review Ass’n et al. eds., 19th ed. 2010). 42 See Charles A. Reich, The New Property, 73 YALE L.J. 733, 773 (1964)

(“Today it is the combined power of government and the corporations that presses against the individual.”).

Page 49: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

489 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

also penned by Justice Scalia, outright said that the Court had “decoupled violation of a person’s Fourth Amendment rights from trespassory violation of his property . . . .”39 Katz itself hinted as much when it held that Olmstead’s underpinnings “have been so eroded by our subsequent decisions that the ‘trespass’ doctrine there enunciated can no longer be regarded as controlling.”40 Until Jones, Katz’s overruling of Olmstead was

United States, 394 U.S. 244, 247–48 (1969) (opinion of the Court by Stewart, J., joined by Warren, C.J., & Brennan, White & Marshall, JJ.) (“Our holding [in Katz] that [Goldman] and [Olmstead] ‘can no longer be regarded as controlling’ recognized that those decisions had not been overruled until that day.”) (citation omitted); see also Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 920 (2010) (Roberts, C.J., concurring, joined by Alito, J.) (citing Olmstead as being overruled by Katz); Harper v. Va. Dep’t of Taxation, 509 U.S. 86, 109 (1993) (Scalia, J., concurring) (same); Florida v. Riley, 488 U.S. 445, 459 n.3 (1989) (Brennan, J., dissenting, joined by Stevens, J.) (“And of course [Katz], which overruled Olmstead, made plain that the question whether or not the disputed evidence had been procured by means of a trespass was irrelevant.”); California v. Greenwood, 486 U.S. 35, 51 (1988) (Brennan, J., dissenting, joined by Marshall, J.) (“The Court properly rejects the State’s attempt to distinguish trash searches from other searches on the theory that trash is abandoned and therefore not entitled to an expectation of privacy.”); California v. Rooney, 483 U.S. 307, 320 (1987) (White, J., dissenting from dismissal of writ of certiorari, joined by Rehnquist, C.J., & Powell, J.) (assuming that petitioner retained ownership of garbage and stating, “Rooney’s property interest, however, does not settle the matter for Fourth Amendment purposes, for the reach of the Fourth Amendment is not determined by state property law”); United States v. Jacobsen, 466 U.S. 109, 138 (1984) (Brennan, J., dissenting, joined by Marshall, J.) (“Fortunately, we know from precedents such as [Katz], overruling the ‘trespass’ doctrine of [Goldman] and [Olmstead], that this Court ultimately stands ready to prevent this Orwellian world from coming to pass.”); United States v. Peltier, 422 U.S. 531, 547 n.5 (1975) (Brennan, J., dissenting, joined by Stewart & Marshal, JJ.) (citing Katz as having “explicitly” overruled Olmstead); Williams v. United States, 401 U.S. 646, 653–54 (1971) (plurality opinion by White, J., joined by Burger, C.J., & Stewart & Blackmun, JJ.) (“[Katz] overruled [Olmstead] and [Goldman] and gave expanded Fourth Amendment protection against nonconsensual eavesdropping.”); United States v. White, 401 U.S. 745, 748–49 (1971) (plurality opinion by White, J., joined by Burger, C.J., & Stewart & Blackmun, JJ.) (recognizing that the Court in Katz overruled Goldman and Olmstead); id. at 780 (Harlan, J., dissenting) (“[Katz] added no new dimension to the law. At most it was a formal dispatch of [Olmstead] and the notion that such problems may usefully be resolved in the light of trespass doctrine . . . .”).

39 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27, 32 (2001) (citing Rakas, 439 U.S. at 143). 40 Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 353 (1967).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 490

such a foregone certainty that the most influential legal style manual used Olmstead to illustrate how to cite an overruled case.41 Katz declared “expectations of privacy” to be the concept at the core of the Fourth Amendment, disregarding its language as well as the trespass standard. With Katz, the Court licensed itself to withdraw the Fourth Amendment’s protection from virtually all modern records and communications and from contraband—two types of property that the Fourth Amendment was most certainly meant to protect. In the process, the Court turned corporate service providers against their customers and conscripted them into service as government spies.42 Given that relationships with giant corporations penetrate even the most intimate aspects of modern life, the expectations-of-privacy framework has ironically proven deeply inimical to individual privacy. Despite its pretentions, Jones does not redress Katz’s flaws so much as mimic them. Jones creates a new trespass test, just as malleable as Katz’s expectations-of-privacy approach. The test combines a narrow, recently contrived definition of “seizure” with narrow, colonial-era notions of houses, papers, and effects. Jones thus repudiates the idea, embodied in the Court’s pre-Katz holdings, that technological innovation yields new forms of property entitled to full Fourth Amendment protection. By 1967, the Court had made significant progress toward a pragmatic, flexible understanding of “papers” and “effects”—one adaptable to technological change—repudiating Olmstead’s two key premises. It ruled that the amendment protected against trespasses in a broad rather than a legalistic sense and that conversations, despite being intangible, were protected “papers” or “effects”. The Court’s post-Katz Fourth Amendment jurisprudence, including Jones, has disregarded that pragmatic, principled understanding of a Fourth Amendment violation. But the property notions underlying it have endured. Outside of the Fourth Amendment context, the Supreme Court and the lower federal courts have

41 THE BLUEBOOK: A UNIFORM SYSTEM OF CITATION R. 10.7.1(c)(i), at 102

(Columbia Law Review Ass’n et al. eds., 19th ed. 2010). 42 See Charles A. Reich, The New Property, 73 YALE L.J. 733, 773 (1964)

(“Today it is the combined power of government and the corporations that presses against the individual.”).

Page 50: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

491 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

shown that they have relatively little difficulty identifying new forms of property in a changing world. Because the Fourth Amendment expressly protects property, it can do the work it was designed to do only if it is understood as protecting property in all its forms against unjustified intrusion.

I. KATZ’S FLAWED FOUNDATION

In 1927, when a wired telephone was cutting-edge communications technology, AT&T and the other phone companies of the day sided with their customers against the government in a case testing the scope of the Fourth Amendment. The text’s guarantee of the people’s right “to be secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects” was understood as a right to exclusive dominion over their property (and their bodies).43 The case, Olmstead v. United States, asked whether this protection extended to the telephone conversations of a large-scale Seattle bootlegging operation. It was the dawn of the information age, a time when AT&T was completing its consolidation of regional telephone carriers into the Bell System, with the audacious aim of linking the entire world. “Indeed, the phrase used to describe the era that the Bell scientists helped create, the age of information, suggested we had left the material world behind. A new commodity—weightless, invisible, fleet as light itself—defined the times.”44 Ethereal though it might be, from the telephone companies’ standpoint, that commodity—information—was no less property because it was not recorded on paper. They urged the Court to recognize that

43 Boyd v. United States, 116 U.S. 616, 630 (1886) (noting that the Fourth

Amendment’s underlying principles “apply to all invasions on the part of the government and its employees of the sanctity of a man’s home and the privacies of life. It is not the breaking of his doors, and the rummaging of his drawers, that constitutes the essence of the offense; but it is the invasion of his indefeasible right of personal security, personal liberty, and private property . . . .”).

44 JON GERTNER, THE IDEA FACTORY 11 (2012).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 492

telephone calls were, like letters sent through the mail, protected by the Fourth Amendment from unauthorized tapping by federal agents:

When the lines of two “parties” are connected at the central office, they are intended to be devoted to the exclusive use, and in that sense to be turned over to the exclusive possession, of the parties. A third person who taps the lines violates the property rights of both persons then using the telephone, and of the telephone company as well.45

While “deplor[ing] the use of their facilities in furtherance of any criminal or wrongful enterprise,” the phone companies maintained that “it is better that a few criminals escape than that the privacies of life of all the people be exposed to the agents of the Government, who will act at their own discretion, the honest and the dishonest, unauthorized and unrestrained by the courts.”46 Judge Frank Rudkin, who was on the Ninth Circuit panel that considered the case, likewise envisioned a Fourth Amendment encompassing new forms of property created by technology. (The phone companies’ brief and one of the petitioners’ briefs quoted his dissent.47) Judge Rudkin relied on Ex parte Jackson,48 a landmark nineteenth-century case holding that the Fourth Amendment protected mailed letters and packages from inspection. If people’s thoughts were in the telephonic age to be carried by wires rather than papers, he reasoned, the word “papers” in the Fourth Amendment was capacious enough to embrace those messages:

[I]t is the contents of the letter, not the mere paper, that is thus protected. What is the distinction between a message sent by letter and a message sent by telegraph or by

45 Brief for Pac. Tel. & Tel. Co. et al. as Amici Curiae at 4, Olmstead v. United

States, 277 U.S. 438 (1928) (No. 493) (citing Int’l News Serv. v. Assoc. Press, 248 U.S. 215 (1918)).

46 Id. at 9. 47 Id. at 7; Brief of Petitioners Edward H. McInnis, Charles S. Green, Emory A.

Kern, Z.J. Hendrick, Edward Erickson, William P. Smith at 11–12, Olmstead v. United States, Green v. United States, McInnis v. United States (Feb. 6, 1927).

48 96 U.S. 727, 733 (1877).

Page 51: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

491 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

shown that they have relatively little difficulty identifying new forms of property in a changing world. Because the Fourth Amendment expressly protects property, it can do the work it was designed to do only if it is understood as protecting property in all its forms against unjustified intrusion.

I. KATZ’S FLAWED FOUNDATION

In 1927, when a wired telephone was cutting-edge communications technology, AT&T and the other phone companies of the day sided with their customers against the government in a case testing the scope of the Fourth Amendment. The text’s guarantee of the people’s right “to be secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects” was understood as a right to exclusive dominion over their property (and their bodies).43 The case, Olmstead v. United States, asked whether this protection extended to the telephone conversations of a large-scale Seattle bootlegging operation. It was the dawn of the information age, a time when AT&T was completing its consolidation of regional telephone carriers into the Bell System, with the audacious aim of linking the entire world. “Indeed, the phrase used to describe the era that the Bell scientists helped create, the age of information, suggested we had left the material world behind. A new commodity—weightless, invisible, fleet as light itself—defined the times.”44 Ethereal though it might be, from the telephone companies’ standpoint, that commodity—information—was no less property because it was not recorded on paper. They urged the Court to recognize that

43 Boyd v. United States, 116 U.S. 616, 630 (1886) (noting that the Fourth

Amendment’s underlying principles “apply to all invasions on the part of the government and its employees of the sanctity of a man’s home and the privacies of life. It is not the breaking of his doors, and the rummaging of his drawers, that constitutes the essence of the offense; but it is the invasion of his indefeasible right of personal security, personal liberty, and private property . . . .”).

44 JON GERTNER, THE IDEA FACTORY 11 (2012).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 492

telephone calls were, like letters sent through the mail, protected by the Fourth Amendment from unauthorized tapping by federal agents:

When the lines of two “parties” are connected at the central office, they are intended to be devoted to the exclusive use, and in that sense to be turned over to the exclusive possession, of the parties. A third person who taps the lines violates the property rights of both persons then using the telephone, and of the telephone company as well.45

While “deplor[ing] the use of their facilities in furtherance of any criminal or wrongful enterprise,” the phone companies maintained that “it is better that a few criminals escape than that the privacies of life of all the people be exposed to the agents of the Government, who will act at their own discretion, the honest and the dishonest, unauthorized and unrestrained by the courts.”46 Judge Frank Rudkin, who was on the Ninth Circuit panel that considered the case, likewise envisioned a Fourth Amendment encompassing new forms of property created by technology. (The phone companies’ brief and one of the petitioners’ briefs quoted his dissent.47) Judge Rudkin relied on Ex parte Jackson,48 a landmark nineteenth-century case holding that the Fourth Amendment protected mailed letters and packages from inspection. If people’s thoughts were in the telephonic age to be carried by wires rather than papers, he reasoned, the word “papers” in the Fourth Amendment was capacious enough to embrace those messages:

[I]t is the contents of the letter, not the mere paper, that is thus protected. What is the distinction between a message sent by letter and a message sent by telegraph or by

45 Brief for Pac. Tel. & Tel. Co. et al. as Amici Curiae at 4, Olmstead v. United

States, 277 U.S. 438 (1928) (No. 493) (citing Int’l News Serv. v. Assoc. Press, 248 U.S. 215 (1918)).

46 Id. at 9. 47 Id. at 7; Brief of Petitioners Edward H. McInnis, Charles S. Green, Emory A.

Kern, Z.J. Hendrick, Edward Erickson, William P. Smith at 11–12, Olmstead v. United States, Green v. United States, McInnis v. United States (Feb. 6, 1927).

48 96 U.S. 727, 733 (1877).

Page 52: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

493 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

telephone? True, the one is visible, the other invisible; the one is tangible, the other intangible; the one is sealed, and the other unsealed; but these are distinctions without a difference. A person using the telegraph or telephone is not broadcasting to the world. His conversation is sealed from the public as completely as the nature of the instrumentalities employed will permit, and no federal officer or federal agent has a right to take his message from the wires, in order that it may be used against him.49

This pragmatic view of information constituting property drew support from the Supreme Court’s 1918 decision in International News Service v. Associated Press.50 The Associated Press sought to enjoin International News Service from republishing news that AP reporters had gathered and published.51 As Justice Holmes noted, the telegraph and telephone made it possible for the INS to republish AP-generated news very shortly after—and, on the west coast, sometimes before—AP published it.52 The Court undertook to decide whether information gathered by a news company’s reporters constitutes property and, if so, whether that news loses its character as property once it is published.53 Rather than trying to determine whether news would have technically constituted property at common law, the Court used a functional approach to sustain its jurisdiction over the cause.54 Applying this same pragmatic view of property to the merits, the Court had little trouble concluding that

49 Olmstead v. United States, 19 F.2d 842, 850 (9th Cir. 1927) (Rudkin, J.,

dissenting), aff’d, 277 U.S. 438 (1928). 50 Brief for Pac. Tel., supra note 45, at 4 (citing Int’l News Serv., 248 U.S. 215). 51 248 U.S. at 231. 52 Id. at 247 (Holmes, J., dissenting). 53 Id. at 232 (majority opinion). 54 Id. at 236–37 (“In order to sustain the jurisdiction of equity over the

controversy, we need not affirm any general and absolute property in the news as such. The rule that a court of equity concerns itself only in the protection of property rights treats any civil right of a pecuniary nature as a property right and the right to acquire property by honest labor or the conduct of a lawful business is as much entitled to protection as the right to guard property already acquired.” (citations omitted)).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 494

the news gathered by AP reporters was the company’s property because it took effort to acquire and was marketable:

Not only do the acquisition and transmission of news require elaborate organization and a large expenditure of money, skill, and effort; not only has it an exchange value to the gatherer, dependent chiefly upon its novelty and freshness, the regularity of the service, its reputed reliability and thoroughness, and its adaptability to the public needs; but also, as is evident, the news has an exchange value to one who can misappropriate it.55

The Court rejected the idea that news ceased to be property for these purposes upon publication: “The peculiar value of news is in the spreading of it while it is fresh; and it is evident that a valuable property interest in the news, as news, cannot be maintained by keeping it secret.”56 Ten years later, however, the Court was far more rigid in evaluating the Bell Companies’ contention that a telephone conversation similarly constituted property. Chief Justice William Howard Taft’s opinion for the Court in Olmstead framed the issue as whether the Fourth Amendment could be violated by a wiretap effected “without trespass upon any property of the defendants.”57 The majority held that the case did not implicate the Fourth Amendment for two reasons. First, the conversations themselves, being intangible, were not papers or effects and could not be seized.58 Second, because the wiretaps were made without entering the defendants’ houses or offices, there was no trespass of any property.59

55 Id. at 238. 56 Id at 235. 57 Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438, 455–57 (1928). 58 Id. at 466. 59 Id. (“Neither the cases we have cited nor any of the many federal decisions

brought to our attention hold the Fourth Amendment to have been violated as against a defendant unless there has been an official search and seizure of his person, or such a seizure of his papers or his tangible material effects, or an actual physical invasion of his house ‘or curtilage’ for the purpose of making a seizure.”).

Page 53: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

493 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

telephone? True, the one is visible, the other invisible; the one is tangible, the other intangible; the one is sealed, and the other unsealed; but these are distinctions without a difference. A person using the telegraph or telephone is not broadcasting to the world. His conversation is sealed from the public as completely as the nature of the instrumentalities employed will permit, and no federal officer or federal agent has a right to take his message from the wires, in order that it may be used against him.49

This pragmatic view of information constituting property drew support from the Supreme Court’s 1918 decision in International News Service v. Associated Press.50 The Associated Press sought to enjoin International News Service from republishing news that AP reporters had gathered and published.51 As Justice Holmes noted, the telegraph and telephone made it possible for the INS to republish AP-generated news very shortly after—and, on the west coast, sometimes before—AP published it.52 The Court undertook to decide whether information gathered by a news company’s reporters constitutes property and, if so, whether that news loses its character as property once it is published.53 Rather than trying to determine whether news would have technically constituted property at common law, the Court used a functional approach to sustain its jurisdiction over the cause.54 Applying this same pragmatic view of property to the merits, the Court had little trouble concluding that

49 Olmstead v. United States, 19 F.2d 842, 850 (9th Cir. 1927) (Rudkin, J.,

dissenting), aff’d, 277 U.S. 438 (1928). 50 Brief for Pac. Tel., supra note 45, at 4 (citing Int’l News Serv., 248 U.S. 215). 51 248 U.S. at 231. 52 Id. at 247 (Holmes, J., dissenting). 53 Id. at 232 (majority opinion). 54 Id. at 236–37 (“In order to sustain the jurisdiction of equity over the

controversy, we need not affirm any general and absolute property in the news as such. The rule that a court of equity concerns itself only in the protection of property rights treats any civil right of a pecuniary nature as a property right and the right to acquire property by honest labor or the conduct of a lawful business is as much entitled to protection as the right to guard property already acquired.” (citations omitted)).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 494

the news gathered by AP reporters was the company’s property because it took effort to acquire and was marketable:

Not only do the acquisition and transmission of news require elaborate organization and a large expenditure of money, skill, and effort; not only has it an exchange value to the gatherer, dependent chiefly upon its novelty and freshness, the regularity of the service, its reputed reliability and thoroughness, and its adaptability to the public needs; but also, as is evident, the news has an exchange value to one who can misappropriate it.55

The Court rejected the idea that news ceased to be property for these purposes upon publication: “The peculiar value of news is in the spreading of it while it is fresh; and it is evident that a valuable property interest in the news, as news, cannot be maintained by keeping it secret.”56 Ten years later, however, the Court was far more rigid in evaluating the Bell Companies’ contention that a telephone conversation similarly constituted property. Chief Justice William Howard Taft’s opinion for the Court in Olmstead framed the issue as whether the Fourth Amendment could be violated by a wiretap effected “without trespass upon any property of the defendants.”57 The majority held that the case did not implicate the Fourth Amendment for two reasons. First, the conversations themselves, being intangible, were not papers or effects and could not be seized.58 Second, because the wiretaps were made without entering the defendants’ houses or offices, there was no trespass of any property.59

55 Id. at 238. 56 Id at 235. 57 Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438, 455–57 (1928). 58 Id. at 466. 59 Id. (“Neither the cases we have cited nor any of the many federal decisions

brought to our attention hold the Fourth Amendment to have been violated as against a defendant unless there has been an official search and seizure of his person, or such a seizure of his papers or his tangible material effects, or an actual physical invasion of his house ‘or curtilage’ for the purpose of making a seizure.”).

Page 54: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

495 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Only Justice Pierce Butler would have sustained AT&T’s contention that the Court should give “papers” and “effects” a more flexible definition and treat telephone conversations the same way as mailed correspondence: “The contracts between telephone companies and users contemplate the private use of the facilities employed in the service. The communications belong to the parties between whom they pass.”60 In a dissent regrettably destined to be more influential, Justice Louis Brandeis availed himself of some of the more colorful flourishes from the phone companies’ brief. (For example, the brief stated: “[T]he telephone system offers a means of espionage compared to which general warrants and writs of assistance were the puniest instruments of tyranny and oppression.”61 Justice Brandeis’ opinion: “As a means of espionage, writs of assistance and general warrants are but puny instruments of tyranny and oppression when compared with wire tapping.”62) But Justice Brandeis’ argument swept far more broadly and metaphysically than the Bell System’s. It grandiloquently trumpeted that the Framers of the Fourth Amendment intended to protect not mere property but the thoughts and feelings comprising every individual personality:

The makers of our Constitution undertook to secure conditions favorable to the pursuit of happiness. They recognized the significance of man’s spiritual nature, of his feelings and of his intellect. They knew that only a part of the pain, pleasure and satisfactions of life are to be found in material things. They sought to protect Americans in their beliefs, their thoughts, their emotions and their sensations. They conferred, as against the Government, the right to be let alone—the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilized men. To protect that right, every unjustifiable intrusion by the Government upon the privacy of the individual, whatever the means employed, must be deemed a violation of the Fourth Amendment.63

60 Id. at 487 (Butler, J., dissenting). 61 Brief for Pac. Tel., supra note 45, at 7–8. 62 Olmstead, 277 U.S. at 474 (Brandeis, J., dissenting) (footnotes omitted). 63 Id. at 478.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 496

This was a quite romantic view of history. It was not the Founders but Louis Brandeis himself and his law partner, Samuel Warren, who sought legal recognition of “man’s spiritual nature, of his feelings and of his intellect,” in their 1890 Harvard Law Review article, The Right to Privacy.64 That article suggested how tort law might develop to deal with invasions of privacy committed not by the government but by a sensational press eager to meet the timeless demand for scandal. In 1890, “instantaneous photographs” made possible “the unauthorized circulation of portraits of private persons” while newspapers freely publicized people’s words and acts.65 The article lamented the proliferation of photography and yellow journalism, precursors to today’s costless propagation of compromising images, videos, and other information on the Internet. Brandeis and Warren complained that the newspapers’ profiteering from vice and banalities muffled civic discourse:

Gossip is no longer the resource of the idle and of the vicious, but has become a trade, which is pursued with industry as well as effrontery. To satisfy a prurient taste the details of sexual relations are spread broadcast in the columns of the daily papers. … When personal gossip attains the dignity of print, and crowds the space available for matters of real interest to the community, what wonder that the ignorant and thoughtless mistake its relative importance.66

The article has a lot to say about whether being “tagged” in an embarrassing photograph on Facebook should give rise to a cause of action67 but nothing at all to do with government surveillance or the Fourth Amendment.

64 Samuel Warren & Louis Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV.

193, 193 (1890). 65 Id. at 195. 66 Id. at 196. 67 See, e.g., Christopher Danzig, No, You Can’t Sue Your Uncle for Putting

Embarrassing Family Photos on Facebook, ABOVE THE LAW (Feb. 16, 2012), http://abovethelaw.com/2012/02/no-you-cant-sue-your-uncle-for-putting-embarrassing-family-photos-on-facebook/#more-136286.

Page 55: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

495 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Only Justice Pierce Butler would have sustained AT&T’s contention that the Court should give “papers” and “effects” a more flexible definition and treat telephone conversations the same way as mailed correspondence: “The contracts between telephone companies and users contemplate the private use of the facilities employed in the service. The communications belong to the parties between whom they pass.”60 In a dissent regrettably destined to be more influential, Justice Louis Brandeis availed himself of some of the more colorful flourishes from the phone companies’ brief. (For example, the brief stated: “[T]he telephone system offers a means of espionage compared to which general warrants and writs of assistance were the puniest instruments of tyranny and oppression.”61 Justice Brandeis’ opinion: “As a means of espionage, writs of assistance and general warrants are but puny instruments of tyranny and oppression when compared with wire tapping.”62) But Justice Brandeis’ argument swept far more broadly and metaphysically than the Bell System’s. It grandiloquently trumpeted that the Framers of the Fourth Amendment intended to protect not mere property but the thoughts and feelings comprising every individual personality:

The makers of our Constitution undertook to secure conditions favorable to the pursuit of happiness. They recognized the significance of man’s spiritual nature, of his feelings and of his intellect. They knew that only a part of the pain, pleasure and satisfactions of life are to be found in material things. They sought to protect Americans in their beliefs, their thoughts, their emotions and their sensations. They conferred, as against the Government, the right to be let alone—the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilized men. To protect that right, every unjustifiable intrusion by the Government upon the privacy of the individual, whatever the means employed, must be deemed a violation of the Fourth Amendment.63

60 Id. at 487 (Butler, J., dissenting). 61 Brief for Pac. Tel., supra note 45, at 7–8. 62 Olmstead, 277 U.S. at 474 (Brandeis, J., dissenting) (footnotes omitted). 63 Id. at 478.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 496

This was a quite romantic view of history. It was not the Founders but Louis Brandeis himself and his law partner, Samuel Warren, who sought legal recognition of “man’s spiritual nature, of his feelings and of his intellect,” in their 1890 Harvard Law Review article, The Right to Privacy.64 That article suggested how tort law might develop to deal with invasions of privacy committed not by the government but by a sensational press eager to meet the timeless demand for scandal. In 1890, “instantaneous photographs” made possible “the unauthorized circulation of portraits of private persons” while newspapers freely publicized people’s words and acts.65 The article lamented the proliferation of photography and yellow journalism, precursors to today’s costless propagation of compromising images, videos, and other information on the Internet. Brandeis and Warren complained that the newspapers’ profiteering from vice and banalities muffled civic discourse:

Gossip is no longer the resource of the idle and of the vicious, but has become a trade, which is pursued with industry as well as effrontery. To satisfy a prurient taste the details of sexual relations are spread broadcast in the columns of the daily papers. … When personal gossip attains the dignity of print, and crowds the space available for matters of real interest to the community, what wonder that the ignorant and thoughtless mistake its relative importance.66

The article has a lot to say about whether being “tagged” in an embarrassing photograph on Facebook should give rise to a cause of action67 but nothing at all to do with government surveillance or the Fourth Amendment.

64 Samuel Warren & Louis Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV.

193, 193 (1890). 65 Id. at 195. 66 Id. at 196. 67 See, e.g., Christopher Danzig, No, You Can’t Sue Your Uncle for Putting

Embarrassing Family Photos on Facebook, ABOVE THE LAW (Feb. 16, 2012), http://abovethelaw.com/2012/02/no-you-cant-sue-your-uncle-for-putting-embarrassing-family-photos-on-facebook/#more-136286.

Page 56: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

497 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Despite its immateriality to constitutional interpretation, Justice Brandeis’ conception of a right to privacy gained traction in Fourth Amendment adjudication.68 Concern that technology made spying possible without a trespass led some justices to call for abandoning the trespass test in favor of a privacy inquiry.69 In 1967, Katz v. United States70 cemented the notion that the Fourth Amendment protects the right to privacy with its holding that a warrantless government wiretap of a telephone booth used for illegal bookmaking was unconstitutional. That there was no trespass on the defendant’s property was irrelevant.71 Rather, what mattered was that, given “the vital role that the public telephone has come to play in private communication,” a person was entitled to expect “that the words he utters into the mouthpiece will not be broadcast to the world.”72 Katz thus emphasized its purpose of more readily bringing modern forms of communication within the Fourth Amendment’s scope. The Court’s definition of “privacy” was sourced to Brandeis and Warren’s The Right to Privacy.73

68 See, e.g., Warden v. Hayden, 387 U.S. 294, 299, 303, 305–06 (1967) (“We

have recognized that the principal object of the Fourth Amendment is the protection of privacy rather than property, and have increasingly discarded fictional and procedural barriers rested on property concepts.”); id. at 310–11 (Fortas, J., concurring); Davis v. United States, 328 U.S. 582 (1946) (stating that the Fourth Amendment protects “the privacy of the individual, his right to be let alone”); see also Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 373 (1967) (Black, J., dissenting) (“With this decision the Court has completed, I hope, its rewriting of the Fourth Amendment, which started only recently when the Court began referring incessantly to the Fourth Amendment not so much as a law against unreasonable searches and seizures as one to protect an individual’s privacy.”).

69 See, e.g., Osborn v. United States, 385 U.S. 323, 342–43 (1966) (Douglas, J., dissenting in two cases and concurring in one) (“[T]here begins to emerge a society quite unlike any we have seen—a society in which government may intrude into the secret regions of man’s life at will.”); Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 513 (1961) (Douglas, J., concurring) (“[O]ur sole concern should be whether the privacy of the home was invaded.”); Goldman v. United States, 316 U.S. 129, 138–40 (1942) (Murphy, J., dissenting) (“Physical entry may be wholly irrelevant.”).

70 389 U.S. 347. 71 Id. at 359. 72 Id. at 352. 73 See id. at 350 n.6 (citing Warren & Brandeis, supra note 64).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 498

Katz was an infelicitous vindication of Justice Brandeis’ wide-ranging Olmstead dissent. Justice Stewart’s majority opinion set out not merely to overrule Olmstead but to broaden the scope of the Fourth Amendment by rendering its text illustrative rather than binding. As vague as it was ambitious, the opinion offered courts no practical help in giving effect to this new “right to privacy.”74 So, they turned to Justice John Harlan’s concurrence. The test for deciding whether the Fourth Amendment applied to an official intrusion became whether the government disappointed a “reasonable expectation of privacy.”75 A privacy expectation is “reasonable” if the judiciary decides that “society is prepared to recognize [it] as ‘reasonable.’”76 The Supreme Court later adopted this circular inquiry as law, committing judges to a jurisprudence lacking a well-articulated core concept and necessarily requiring guesswork about what Americans think about privacy claims.77 Justice Black’s dissent in Katz rightly lambasted the Court for “referring incessantly to the Fourth Amendment not so much as a law against unreasonable searches and seizures as one to protect an individual’s privacy.”78 But he incorrectly predicted that the reimagined amendment would be the Court’s “vehicle for holding all laws violative of the Constitution which offend the Court’s broadest concept of privacy.”79 Katz shared its theoretical underpinnings with Griswold v. Connecticut,80 which invalidated a law criminalizing the use of contraceptives during spousal relations on the basis of a constitutional

74 See Peter Winn, Katz and the Origins of the “Reasonable Expectation of

Privacy” Test, 40 MCGEORGE L. REV. 1, 6 (2009). 75 Katz, 389 U.S. at 361 (Harlan, J., concurring); see, e.g., Kyllo v. United

States, 533 U.S. 27, 33 (2001); United States v. Jacobsen, 466 U.S. 109, 113 (1984); Smith v. Maryland, 442 U.S. 735, 740–41 (1979).

76 Katz, 389 U.S. at 361 (Harlan, J., concurring). 77 See Kyllo, 533 U.S. at 32–34 (discussing Katz test); Minnesota v. Carter, 525

U.S. 83, 97–98 (Scalia, J., concurring) (describing Katz test as “self-indulgent” and lacking any “plausible foundation in the text of the Fourth Amendment”).

78 Katz, 389 U.S. at 373 (Black, J., dissenting). 79 Id. 80 Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965).

Page 57: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

497 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Despite its immateriality to constitutional interpretation, Justice Brandeis’ conception of a right to privacy gained traction in Fourth Amendment adjudication.68 Concern that technology made spying possible without a trespass led some justices to call for abandoning the trespass test in favor of a privacy inquiry.69 In 1967, Katz v. United States70 cemented the notion that the Fourth Amendment protects the right to privacy with its holding that a warrantless government wiretap of a telephone booth used for illegal bookmaking was unconstitutional. That there was no trespass on the defendant’s property was irrelevant.71 Rather, what mattered was that, given “the vital role that the public telephone has come to play in private communication,” a person was entitled to expect “that the words he utters into the mouthpiece will not be broadcast to the world.”72 Katz thus emphasized its purpose of more readily bringing modern forms of communication within the Fourth Amendment’s scope. The Court’s definition of “privacy” was sourced to Brandeis and Warren’s The Right to Privacy.73

68 See, e.g., Warden v. Hayden, 387 U.S. 294, 299, 303, 305–06 (1967) (“We

have recognized that the principal object of the Fourth Amendment is the protection of privacy rather than property, and have increasingly discarded fictional and procedural barriers rested on property concepts.”); id. at 310–11 (Fortas, J., concurring); Davis v. United States, 328 U.S. 582 (1946) (stating that the Fourth Amendment protects “the privacy of the individual, his right to be let alone”); see also Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 373 (1967) (Black, J., dissenting) (“With this decision the Court has completed, I hope, its rewriting of the Fourth Amendment, which started only recently when the Court began referring incessantly to the Fourth Amendment not so much as a law against unreasonable searches and seizures as one to protect an individual’s privacy.”).

69 See, e.g., Osborn v. United States, 385 U.S. 323, 342–43 (1966) (Douglas, J., dissenting in two cases and concurring in one) (“[T]here begins to emerge a society quite unlike any we have seen—a society in which government may intrude into the secret regions of man’s life at will.”); Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 513 (1961) (Douglas, J., concurring) (“[O]ur sole concern should be whether the privacy of the home was invaded.”); Goldman v. United States, 316 U.S. 129, 138–40 (1942) (Murphy, J., dissenting) (“Physical entry may be wholly irrelevant.”).

70 389 U.S. 347. 71 Id. at 359. 72 Id. at 352. 73 See id. at 350 n.6 (citing Warren & Brandeis, supra note 64).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 498

Katz was an infelicitous vindication of Justice Brandeis’ wide-ranging Olmstead dissent. Justice Stewart’s majority opinion set out not merely to overrule Olmstead but to broaden the scope of the Fourth Amendment by rendering its text illustrative rather than binding. As vague as it was ambitious, the opinion offered courts no practical help in giving effect to this new “right to privacy.”74 So, they turned to Justice John Harlan’s concurrence. The test for deciding whether the Fourth Amendment applied to an official intrusion became whether the government disappointed a “reasonable expectation of privacy.”75 A privacy expectation is “reasonable” if the judiciary decides that “society is prepared to recognize [it] as ‘reasonable.’”76 The Supreme Court later adopted this circular inquiry as law, committing judges to a jurisprudence lacking a well-articulated core concept and necessarily requiring guesswork about what Americans think about privacy claims.77 Justice Black’s dissent in Katz rightly lambasted the Court for “referring incessantly to the Fourth Amendment not so much as a law against unreasonable searches and seizures as one to protect an individual’s privacy.”78 But he incorrectly predicted that the reimagined amendment would be the Court’s “vehicle for holding all laws violative of the Constitution which offend the Court’s broadest concept of privacy.”79 Katz shared its theoretical underpinnings with Griswold v. Connecticut,80 which invalidated a law criminalizing the use of contraceptives during spousal relations on the basis of a constitutional

74 See Peter Winn, Katz and the Origins of the “Reasonable Expectation of

Privacy” Test, 40 MCGEORGE L. REV. 1, 6 (2009). 75 Katz, 389 U.S. at 361 (Harlan, J., concurring); see, e.g., Kyllo v. United

States, 533 U.S. 27, 33 (2001); United States v. Jacobsen, 466 U.S. 109, 113 (1984); Smith v. Maryland, 442 U.S. 735, 740–41 (1979).

76 Katz, 389 U.S. at 361 (Harlan, J., concurring). 77 See Kyllo, 533 U.S. at 32–34 (discussing Katz test); Minnesota v. Carter, 525

U.S. 83, 97–98 (Scalia, J., concurring) (describing Katz test as “self-indulgent” and lacking any “plausible foundation in the text of the Fourth Amendment”).

78 Katz, 389 U.S. at 373 (Black, J., dissenting). 79 Id. 80 Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965).

Page 58: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

499 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

right to marital privacy.81 These two cases are products of the mid-century belief that a right to privacy must be implied in the Bill of Rights to serve as a bulwark against government spying and oppression.82 They describe a single “right to privacy” emanating from several constitutional provisions.83 Not surprisingly, then, the critique that Professor Henry Monaghan leveled at Griswold applies equally to Katz.84 Instead of interpreting the Fourth Amendment’s words to account for new ways of doing old things—as the Bell Companies suggested in 1927—Katz posits that an individual’s property rights must yield whenever a court decides the government’s interest in trespassing is more important. For judges to find the Fourth Amendment’s meaning not “in its history or in judicial precedent, but in current social consensus”85 of what ought to be private is as illegitimate as it is unworkable. With the text no longer constraining interpretation, the inherent “difficulty of relating ancient norms to a world radically different from that of the Framers” leaves courts to resolve search-and-seizure challenges by “balancing the interests at stake, with the constitutional guarantees assessed in functional, rather than historical, terms.”86 The Court’s notion that the law could protect abstract privacy directly was a doomed exercise in “perfectionist”87 or “noninterpretivist”88 constitutional interpretation with little connection to the Fourth Amendment’s wording. This is neither surprising nor accidental. “[I]n a society that chiefly values material well-being, the power to control a particular portion of that well-being is the very foundation of

81 Id. at 485. 82 See United States v. Watson, 423 U.S. 411, 445 (1976) (“Indeed, the privacy

guaranteed by the Fourth Amendment is quintessentially personal.”) (discussing Katz and citing Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973), and Griswold, 381 U.S. 479).

83 Griswold, 381 U.S. at 484. 84 Henry P. Monaghan, Our Perfect Constitution, 56 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 353 (1981). 85 Id. at 355. 86 Id. at 393. 87 Id. at 358. 88 JOHN HART ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST 1 (1980).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 500

individuality.”89 Justice Harlan’s formulation of Katz instead tied the Fourth Amendment’s scope to the judiciary’s best guess as to what most Americans consider private. For judges insulated by constitutional design from popular sentiment, gauging America’s privacy expectations is an impossible task.90

II. KATZ’S CURTAILMENT OF PRIVACY

Rather than broadening the amendment’s protection, Katz teed up a narrowing of its scope when the Burger Court adopted a more parsimonious view of privacy than the Warren Court had envisioned. Despite the Jones majority’s unsupported claim that “Katz did not narrow the Fourth Amendment’s scope,”91 Katz diluted the rights of those who are not, in one way or another, like a typical judge—the young, the poor, the uneducated, the technologically savvy, and the nonconforming.92 It proved, however, steadfastly solicitous of privacy concerns with which judges could immediately identify.93 For example, although the justices could not agree on a majority rationale, the Supreme Court unanimously held that government employees have a constitutional expectation of privacy in their government offices.94 It took just a few years for an insular and out-of-touch judiciary operating with a cabined understanding of privacy to remove two core

89 Reich, supra note 42 at 733, 774. 90 Monaghan, supra note 84, at 386 (“[Courts] are the least capable of divining

what is acceptable to the populace.”). 91 United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945, 951 (2012). 92 See Bascuas, supra note 17, at 630 & n.322; see also United States v.

Robinson, 414 U.S. 218, 257 (1973) (Marshall, J., dissenting); United States v. Pineda-Moreno, 617 F.3d 1120, 1123 (9th Cir. 2010) (Kozinski, C.J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc).

93 See Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27, 34 (2001) (describing Katz test as circular, subjective, and unpredictable); Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 962 (Alito, J., concurring) (same); Minnesota v. Carter, 525 U.S. 83, 97–98 (1998) (Scalia, J., concurring) (same).

94 O’Connor v. Ortega, 480 U.S. 709, 717 (1987) (plurality opinion); id. at 731 (Scalia, J., concurring); id. at 737 (Blackmun, J., dissenting).

Page 59: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

499 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

right to marital privacy.81 These two cases are products of the mid-century belief that a right to privacy must be implied in the Bill of Rights to serve as a bulwark against government spying and oppression.82 They describe a single “right to privacy” emanating from several constitutional provisions.83 Not surprisingly, then, the critique that Professor Henry Monaghan leveled at Griswold applies equally to Katz.84 Instead of interpreting the Fourth Amendment’s words to account for new ways of doing old things—as the Bell Companies suggested in 1927—Katz posits that an individual’s property rights must yield whenever a court decides the government’s interest in trespassing is more important. For judges to find the Fourth Amendment’s meaning not “in its history or in judicial precedent, but in current social consensus”85 of what ought to be private is as illegitimate as it is unworkable. With the text no longer constraining interpretation, the inherent “difficulty of relating ancient norms to a world radically different from that of the Framers” leaves courts to resolve search-and-seizure challenges by “balancing the interests at stake, with the constitutional guarantees assessed in functional, rather than historical, terms.”86 The Court’s notion that the law could protect abstract privacy directly was a doomed exercise in “perfectionist”87 or “noninterpretivist”88 constitutional interpretation with little connection to the Fourth Amendment’s wording. This is neither surprising nor accidental. “[I]n a society that chiefly values material well-being, the power to control a particular portion of that well-being is the very foundation of

81 Id. at 485. 82 See United States v. Watson, 423 U.S. 411, 445 (1976) (“Indeed, the privacy

guaranteed by the Fourth Amendment is quintessentially personal.”) (discussing Katz and citing Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973), and Griswold, 381 U.S. 479).

83 Griswold, 381 U.S. at 484. 84 Henry P. Monaghan, Our Perfect Constitution, 56 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 353 (1981). 85 Id. at 355. 86 Id. at 393. 87 Id. at 358. 88 JOHN HART ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST 1 (1980).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 500

individuality.”89 Justice Harlan’s formulation of Katz instead tied the Fourth Amendment’s scope to the judiciary’s best guess as to what most Americans consider private. For judges insulated by constitutional design from popular sentiment, gauging America’s privacy expectations is an impossible task.90

II. KATZ’S CURTAILMENT OF PRIVACY

Rather than broadening the amendment’s protection, Katz teed up a narrowing of its scope when the Burger Court adopted a more parsimonious view of privacy than the Warren Court had envisioned. Despite the Jones majority’s unsupported claim that “Katz did not narrow the Fourth Amendment’s scope,”91 Katz diluted the rights of those who are not, in one way or another, like a typical judge—the young, the poor, the uneducated, the technologically savvy, and the nonconforming.92 It proved, however, steadfastly solicitous of privacy concerns with which judges could immediately identify.93 For example, although the justices could not agree on a majority rationale, the Supreme Court unanimously held that government employees have a constitutional expectation of privacy in their government offices.94 It took just a few years for an insular and out-of-touch judiciary operating with a cabined understanding of privacy to remove two core

89 Reich, supra note 42 at 733, 774. 90 Monaghan, supra note 84, at 386 (“[Courts] are the least capable of divining

what is acceptable to the populace.”). 91 United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945, 951 (2012). 92 See Bascuas, supra note 17, at 630 & n.322; see also United States v.

Robinson, 414 U.S. 218, 257 (1973) (Marshall, J., dissenting); United States v. Pineda-Moreno, 617 F.3d 1120, 1123 (9th Cir. 2010) (Kozinski, C.J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en banc).

93 See Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27, 34 (2001) (describing Katz test as circular, subjective, and unpredictable); Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 962 (Alito, J., concurring) (same); Minnesota v. Carter, 525 U.S. 83, 97–98 (1998) (Scalia, J., concurring) (same).

94 O’Connor v. Ortega, 480 U.S. 709, 717 (1987) (plurality opinion); id. at 731 (Scalia, J., concurring); id. at 737 (Blackmun, J., dissenting).

Page 60: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

501 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

categories of “papers and effects” from the Fourth Amendment’s protection. First, the records corporations maintain on behalf of their customers were held to be not private on the theory that customers voluntarily disclose that information to corporations to obtain services. Second, whether someone possessed contraband, the Court concluded, was not worthy of constitutional protection because, on balance, society’s interest in getting that information outweighed any individual’s interest in withholding it. Katz distorts Fourth Amendment jurisprudence by penalizing the sharing of information and by balancing the perceived desirability of enforcing a right against that of enforcing a criminal statute.

A. KATZ’S FAILURE TO PROTECT “PAPERS”

Just as the Associated Press decision recognized that “a valuable property interest in the news . . . cannot be maintained by keeping it secret,”95 the Warren Court understood privacy to include not only a right to keep information secret but also a right to control its dissemination. As Justice Brennan recognized in a pre-Katz opinion: “The right of privacy would mean little if it were limited to a person’s solitary thoughts, and so fostered secretiveness. It must embrace a concept of the liberty of one’s communications, and historically it has.”96 But, because the Katz notion of “privacy” was not rooted in the Constitution’s text, future decisions could limit the Fourth Amendment’s scope by adopting a narrower view of privacy. Less than a decade after Katz, the Burger Court defined what is constitutionally “private” as that which is secret—rather than that which is not public.97 In United States v. Miller,98 the Court held that a bank customer, by revealing his transactions “to a third party” (i.e., the bank),

95 Int’l News Serv. v. Assoc. Press, 248 U.S. 215, 235 (1918). 96 Lopez v. United States, 373 U.S. 427, 449 (1963) (Brennan, J., dissenting). 97 Compare Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 351 (1967) (“What a person

knowingly exposes to the public, even in his own home or office, is not a subject of Fourth Amendment protection.” (emphasis added)).

98 425 U.S. 435 (1976).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 502

risked that the government might subpoena the information.99 The Court reasoned that a depositor conducting business with his bank takes the same risk as a criminal who mistakenly confides in an undercover agent or informant.100 Three years later, Smith v. Maryland held that the numbers people dial on their telephones are not private because people must realize that the carriers can record, and hence reveal, that information.101 California v. Greenwood102 extended this notion even further. In that case, the Supreme Court held that police can search and seize garbage put out for collection without probable cause or a warrant, reasoning that, because it is “common knowledge” that raccoons, children, and reporters sometimes get into garbage, people cannot expect police not to search it.103 By equating “privacy” with “secrecy” and banks with government informants, the Court helped make all corporations, willing or unwilling, de facto government agents, transforming the relationship among individuals, the government, and corporations in America.104 In an earlier age, correspondence and sensitive records were protected as “papers” typically kept in “houses.”105 Building on that history, the telephone companies in 1927 saw it in their interest to argue that their customers owned their telephone conversations. But, after Miller and Smith, corporations no longer had that option. Corporate records, despite being not public, were not private and, hence, were thrown open to the

99 Id. at 442–43. 100 Id. at 443 (citing United States v. White, 401 U.S. 745 (1971) (plurality

opinion) (holding that conversations with a bugged informant were not protected by Fourth Amendment); Hoffa v. United States, 385 U.S. 293 (1966) (holding that use of an informant to infiltrate a suspect’s inner sanctum did not violate Fourth Amendment); Lewis v. United States, 385 U.S. 206 (1966) (holding that an undercover agent’s entering a suspect’s home to purchase marijuana did not violate the Fourth Amendment)).

101 442 U.S. 735, 743 (1979). 102 486 U.S. 35 (1988). 103 Id. at 40–41. 104 See Charles A. Reich, The Individual Sector, 100 YALE L.J. 1409, 1429–30

(1991) (arguing that the distinction between the government and corporations has been eviscerated).

105 Boyd v. United States, 116 U.S. 616, 630 (1886).

Page 61: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

501 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

categories of “papers and effects” from the Fourth Amendment’s protection. First, the records corporations maintain on behalf of their customers were held to be not private on the theory that customers voluntarily disclose that information to corporations to obtain services. Second, whether someone possessed contraband, the Court concluded, was not worthy of constitutional protection because, on balance, society’s interest in getting that information outweighed any individual’s interest in withholding it. Katz distorts Fourth Amendment jurisprudence by penalizing the sharing of information and by balancing the perceived desirability of enforcing a right against that of enforcing a criminal statute.

A. KATZ’S FAILURE TO PROTECT “PAPERS”

Just as the Associated Press decision recognized that “a valuable property interest in the news . . . cannot be maintained by keeping it secret,”95 the Warren Court understood privacy to include not only a right to keep information secret but also a right to control its dissemination. As Justice Brennan recognized in a pre-Katz opinion: “The right of privacy would mean little if it were limited to a person’s solitary thoughts, and so fostered secretiveness. It must embrace a concept of the liberty of one’s communications, and historically it has.”96 But, because the Katz notion of “privacy” was not rooted in the Constitution’s text, future decisions could limit the Fourth Amendment’s scope by adopting a narrower view of privacy. Less than a decade after Katz, the Burger Court defined what is constitutionally “private” as that which is secret—rather than that which is not public.97 In United States v. Miller,98 the Court held that a bank customer, by revealing his transactions “to a third party” (i.e., the bank),

95 Int’l News Serv. v. Assoc. Press, 248 U.S. 215, 235 (1918). 96 Lopez v. United States, 373 U.S. 427, 449 (1963) (Brennan, J., dissenting). 97 Compare Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 351 (1967) (“What a person

knowingly exposes to the public, even in his own home or office, is not a subject of Fourth Amendment protection.” (emphasis added)).

98 425 U.S. 435 (1976).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 502

risked that the government might subpoena the information.99 The Court reasoned that a depositor conducting business with his bank takes the same risk as a criminal who mistakenly confides in an undercover agent or informant.100 Three years later, Smith v. Maryland held that the numbers people dial on their telephones are not private because people must realize that the carriers can record, and hence reveal, that information.101 California v. Greenwood102 extended this notion even further. In that case, the Supreme Court held that police can search and seize garbage put out for collection without probable cause or a warrant, reasoning that, because it is “common knowledge” that raccoons, children, and reporters sometimes get into garbage, people cannot expect police not to search it.103 By equating “privacy” with “secrecy” and banks with government informants, the Court helped make all corporations, willing or unwilling, de facto government agents, transforming the relationship among individuals, the government, and corporations in America.104 In an earlier age, correspondence and sensitive records were protected as “papers” typically kept in “houses.”105 Building on that history, the telephone companies in 1927 saw it in their interest to argue that their customers owned their telephone conversations. But, after Miller and Smith, corporations no longer had that option. Corporate records, despite being not public, were not private and, hence, were thrown open to the

99 Id. at 442–43. 100 Id. at 443 (citing United States v. White, 401 U.S. 745 (1971) (plurality

opinion) (holding that conversations with a bugged informant were not protected by Fourth Amendment); Hoffa v. United States, 385 U.S. 293 (1966) (holding that use of an informant to infiltrate a suspect’s inner sanctum did not violate Fourth Amendment); Lewis v. United States, 385 U.S. 206 (1966) (holding that an undercover agent’s entering a suspect’s home to purchase marijuana did not violate the Fourth Amendment)).

101 442 U.S. 735, 743 (1979). 102 486 U.S. 35 (1988). 103 Id. at 40–41. 104 See Charles A. Reich, The Individual Sector, 100 YALE L.J. 1409, 1429–30

(1991) (arguing that the distinction between the government and corporations has been eviscerated).

105 Boyd v. United States, 116 U.S. 616, 630 (1886).

Page 62: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

503 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

government. This transformation was part of a broader alignment of power between government and large corporations based on the “conviction that private power was a chief enemy of society and of individual liberty. Property was subjected to ‘reasonable’ limitations in the interests of society.”106 Communications companies today generally do not question the government’s right to buy customers’ personal information with public funds. The carriers sell their services to the public and then quietly receive government payments to divulge the sensitive information those services generate. The permeation of every aspect of life by mammoth corporations promising ever more efficient and convenient ways of archiving, processing, and transmitting information means that, if only what is secret is private, then not much of any significance is private. Equating privacy with secrecy convolutes Fourth Amendment analysis by requiring judges to make factual findings about how Americans understand new technology to work as well as about how new technology actually does work. If communicating or storing information entails conveying it to someone else, then the Fourth Amendment may not apply.107 The analysis is all the more difficult because it is predicated on the near contradiction that telephone conversations are private (as Katz evidently held), but information shared with entities like banks and telephone companies is not (as Miller and Smith said). Because “expectations of privacy” are too difficult to discern objectively, the post-Katz Fourth Amendment’s application to new ways of communication and storing information is always uncertain and unpredictable.108

106 Reich, supra note 42, at 773. 107 See, e.g., United States v. Forrester, 512 F.3d 500, 510 (9th Cir. 2008)

(following Smith v. Maryland and holding that the names of people with whom one corresponds by email as well as the addresses of the websites one visits are not private because users “should know that this information is provided to and used by Internet service providers for the specific purpose of directing the routing of information”).

108 Cf. Reich, supra note 104, at 1445 (“It is quite useless, for example, to repeat in case after case the formula—little better than an incantation—about an ‘expectation of privacy.’”).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 504

The Supreme Court itself is hopelessly confused. The Court threw up its hands in 2010 and confessed that it had no idea how to apply its own Fourth Amendment jurisprudence to text messages.109 City of Ontario v. Quon raised the issue of whether the Fourth Amendment protected text messages sent by a municipal police sergeant with a two-way pager issued by his department.110 Seeking to determine whether the officer was sending too many personal messages while on duty, the police department got transcripts of his messages from the carrier. Nearly all of the messages turned out to be personal, and many of them were sexually explicit. The sergeant was disciplined, and he audaciously sued the city for violating his “right to privacy.”111 Even with the briefs of both parties and ten amici curiae, the Court said that it could not discern societal expectations of privacy in text messages.112 In its apologia (from which Justice Scalia disassociated himself113), the Court frankly admitted that, with respect to anything other than age-old ways of transacting business and communicating, it can predict neither subjective privacy expectations nor “the degree to which society will be prepared to recognize those expectations as reasonable.”114 Instead of deciding the case, the Court assumed arguendo that text messages enjoy constitutional protection.115 The Court then sidestepped another issue that the Katz test had failed to resolve (for more than 20 years) by further assuming that the department’s action, obtaining and reading its

109 See, e.g., City of Ontario v. Quon, 130 S. Ct. 2619, 2625 (2010) (comparing

how text messages and emails are transmitted). 110 Id. 111 Id. at 2626 (the officer’s main text-message correspondents—his estranged

wife, his girlfriend, and a fellow sergeant—were also plaintiffs). 112 Id. at 2629. 113 Id. at 2635 (Scalia, J., concurring) (“To whom do we owe an additional

explanation for declining to decide an issue, once we have explained that it makes no difference?”); id. (“The Court’s implication that where electronic privacy is concerned we should decide less than we otherwise would . . .—or that we should hedge our bets by concocting case-specific standards or issuing opaque opinions—is in my view indefensible. The-times-they-are-a-changin’ is a feeble excuse for disregard of duty.”).

114 Id. at 2630 (majority opinion). 115 Id.

Page 63: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

503 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

government. This transformation was part of a broader alignment of power between government and large corporations based on the “conviction that private power was a chief enemy of society and of individual liberty. Property was subjected to ‘reasonable’ limitations in the interests of society.”106 Communications companies today generally do not question the government’s right to buy customers’ personal information with public funds. The carriers sell their services to the public and then quietly receive government payments to divulge the sensitive information those services generate. The permeation of every aspect of life by mammoth corporations promising ever more efficient and convenient ways of archiving, processing, and transmitting information means that, if only what is secret is private, then not much of any significance is private. Equating privacy with secrecy convolutes Fourth Amendment analysis by requiring judges to make factual findings about how Americans understand new technology to work as well as about how new technology actually does work. If communicating or storing information entails conveying it to someone else, then the Fourth Amendment may not apply.107 The analysis is all the more difficult because it is predicated on the near contradiction that telephone conversations are private (as Katz evidently held), but information shared with entities like banks and telephone companies is not (as Miller and Smith said). Because “expectations of privacy” are too difficult to discern objectively, the post-Katz Fourth Amendment’s application to new ways of communication and storing information is always uncertain and unpredictable.108

106 Reich, supra note 42, at 773. 107 See, e.g., United States v. Forrester, 512 F.3d 500, 510 (9th Cir. 2008)

(following Smith v. Maryland and holding that the names of people with whom one corresponds by email as well as the addresses of the websites one visits are not private because users “should know that this information is provided to and used by Internet service providers for the specific purpose of directing the routing of information”).

108 Cf. Reich, supra note 104, at 1445 (“It is quite useless, for example, to repeat in case after case the formula—little better than an incantation—about an ‘expectation of privacy.’”).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 504

The Supreme Court itself is hopelessly confused. The Court threw up its hands in 2010 and confessed that it had no idea how to apply its own Fourth Amendment jurisprudence to text messages.109 City of Ontario v. Quon raised the issue of whether the Fourth Amendment protected text messages sent by a municipal police sergeant with a two-way pager issued by his department.110 Seeking to determine whether the officer was sending too many personal messages while on duty, the police department got transcripts of his messages from the carrier. Nearly all of the messages turned out to be personal, and many of them were sexually explicit. The sergeant was disciplined, and he audaciously sued the city for violating his “right to privacy.”111 Even with the briefs of both parties and ten amici curiae, the Court said that it could not discern societal expectations of privacy in text messages.112 In its apologia (from which Justice Scalia disassociated himself113), the Court frankly admitted that, with respect to anything other than age-old ways of transacting business and communicating, it can predict neither subjective privacy expectations nor “the degree to which society will be prepared to recognize those expectations as reasonable.”114 Instead of deciding the case, the Court assumed arguendo that text messages enjoy constitutional protection.115 The Court then sidestepped another issue that the Katz test had failed to resolve (for more than 20 years) by further assuming that the department’s action, obtaining and reading its

109 See, e.g., City of Ontario v. Quon, 130 S. Ct. 2619, 2625 (2010) (comparing

how text messages and emails are transmitted). 110 Id. 111 Id. at 2626 (the officer’s main text-message correspondents—his estranged

wife, his girlfriend, and a fellow sergeant—were also plaintiffs). 112 Id. at 2629. 113 Id. at 2635 (Scalia, J., concurring) (“To whom do we owe an additional

explanation for declining to decide an issue, once we have explained that it makes no difference?”); id. (“The Court’s implication that where electronic privacy is concerned we should decide less than we otherwise would . . .—or that we should hedge our bets by concocting case-specific standards or issuing opaque opinions—is in my view indefensible. The-times-they-are-a-changin’ is a feeble excuse for disregard of duty.”).

114 Id. at 2630 (majority opinion). 115 Id.

Page 64: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

505 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

employee’s text messages, was a search.116 And, finally, the Court assumed that government employees have the same expectation of privacy in electronic messages as they do in the things they keep in their offices.117 Having thus ignored all the technological aspects of the case, the Court decided the search was constitutional because the police department had a “noninvestigatory work-related purpose” for reading the texts.118 Evincing no appreciation of the irony, the Court explained that the expectations-of-privacy inquiry—the one that promised to make the Fourth Amendment flexible enough to deal with technological change—necessitated moving slowly: “The judiciary risks error by elaborating too fully on the Fourth Amendment implications of emerging technology before its role in society has become clear.”119 How a text-messaging pager was an “emerging technology” in 2010—three years after Steve Jobs unveiled the first iPhone—went unexplained. More revealing was the citation used to illustrate the sort of error the judiciary risked by “elaborating too fully” on legal questions: The Court cited Katz’s overruling of Olmstead. In other words, the Quon Court suggested that Olmstead was decided incorrectly because the Court moved precipitously in 1928—when the telephone had been in widespread use for about 35 years.120

116 Id. In O’Connor v. Ortega, 480 U.S. 709 (1987), the Court could not agree

on a methodology for deciding whether a government employee can expect privacy in his office. The case generated no majority opinion. Later decisions skirted the issue, and the Quon Court passed on it as well: “In the two decades since O’Connor, . . . the threshold test for determining the scope of an employee’s Fourth Amendment rights has not been clarified further. . . . The case can be decided by determining that the search was reasonable even assuming Quon had a reasonable expectation of privacy.” Quon, 130 S. Ct. at 2628–29.

117 Quon, 130 S. Ct. at 2630. 118 Id. at 2631 (quoting O’Connor, 480 U.S. at 726 (plurality opinion)). The

Court avoided having to decide whether the officer’s co-respondents had a Fourth Amendment claim because they failed to claim their own privacy was unconstitutionally violated. Id. at 2633.

119 Id. at 2629 (citing Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 353 (1967)). 120 A Brief History: Origins, AT&T,

http://www.corp.att.com/history/history1.html (last visited Apr. 20, 2013).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 506

For a court to assume but not decide that a right exists is not a harmless ploy; it insulates government illegalities, even deliberate ones, from redress. A month after the Quon debacle, the Eleventh Circuit considered a suit against a Georgia district attorney and chief investigator who, as a favor to the management of a local hospital, conspired to falsely charge a troublesome hospital employee with various crimes.121 In the course of their malicious prosecution, the prosecutor and the investigator subpoenaed the employee’s phone records and emails from his communications carriers.122 Relying on Miller and Smith, the court in Rehberg v. Paulk had no trouble concluding that “Rehberg lacked a legitimate expectation of privacy in the phone and fax numbers he dialed.”123 Whether the illegal demand for the emails that Rehberg sent and received offended the Fourth Amendment was, the court believed, a close question.124 Even while criticizing Quon for its “marked lack of clarity in what privacy expectations as to content of electronic communications are reasonable,”125 the appellate court refused to decide whether the emails were constitutionally protected. If the Supreme Court was unable “to answer the constitutional question of whether the plaintiff’s privacy expectation was reasonable or even to set forth the governing principles to answer that question,” then the court of appeals would not try.126 Instead, the court held that, even if the Constitution were violated, the prosecutor and his investigator were entitled to immunity.127 Bizarrely, the court faulted the plaintiff for failing to show that “his alleged constitutional right”—the one that courts only hypothetically assume exists—“was clearly established.”128 Keeping rights hypothetical means that police and

121 Rehberg v. Paulk, 611 F.3d 828 (11th Cir. 2010), aff’d on other grounds, 132 S. Ct. 1497 (2012).

122 Id. at 842. 123 Id. at 843. 124 Id. 125 Id. at 844. 126 Id. at 845, 846. 127 Id. at 846. 128 Id. at 846.

Page 65: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

505 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

employee’s text messages, was a search.116 And, finally, the Court assumed that government employees have the same expectation of privacy in electronic messages as they do in the things they keep in their offices.117 Having thus ignored all the technological aspects of the case, the Court decided the search was constitutional because the police department had a “noninvestigatory work-related purpose” for reading the texts.118 Evincing no appreciation of the irony, the Court explained that the expectations-of-privacy inquiry—the one that promised to make the Fourth Amendment flexible enough to deal with technological change—necessitated moving slowly: “The judiciary risks error by elaborating too fully on the Fourth Amendment implications of emerging technology before its role in society has become clear.”119 How a text-messaging pager was an “emerging technology” in 2010—three years after Steve Jobs unveiled the first iPhone—went unexplained. More revealing was the citation used to illustrate the sort of error the judiciary risked by “elaborating too fully” on legal questions: The Court cited Katz’s overruling of Olmstead. In other words, the Quon Court suggested that Olmstead was decided incorrectly because the Court moved precipitously in 1928—when the telephone had been in widespread use for about 35 years.120

116 Id. In O’Connor v. Ortega, 480 U.S. 709 (1987), the Court could not agree

on a methodology for deciding whether a government employee can expect privacy in his office. The case generated no majority opinion. Later decisions skirted the issue, and the Quon Court passed on it as well: “In the two decades since O’Connor, . . . the threshold test for determining the scope of an employee’s Fourth Amendment rights has not been clarified further. . . . The case can be decided by determining that the search was reasonable even assuming Quon had a reasonable expectation of privacy.” Quon, 130 S. Ct. at 2628–29.

117 Quon, 130 S. Ct. at 2630. 118 Id. at 2631 (quoting O’Connor, 480 U.S. at 726 (plurality opinion)). The

Court avoided having to decide whether the officer’s co-respondents had a Fourth Amendment claim because they failed to claim their own privacy was unconstitutionally violated. Id. at 2633.

119 Id. at 2629 (citing Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 353 (1967)). 120 A Brief History: Origins, AT&T,

http://www.corp.att.com/history/history1.html (last visited Apr. 20, 2013).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 506

For a court to assume but not decide that a right exists is not a harmless ploy; it insulates government illegalities, even deliberate ones, from redress. A month after the Quon debacle, the Eleventh Circuit considered a suit against a Georgia district attorney and chief investigator who, as a favor to the management of a local hospital, conspired to falsely charge a troublesome hospital employee with various crimes.121 In the course of their malicious prosecution, the prosecutor and the investigator subpoenaed the employee’s phone records and emails from his communications carriers.122 Relying on Miller and Smith, the court in Rehberg v. Paulk had no trouble concluding that “Rehberg lacked a legitimate expectation of privacy in the phone and fax numbers he dialed.”123 Whether the illegal demand for the emails that Rehberg sent and received offended the Fourth Amendment was, the court believed, a close question.124 Even while criticizing Quon for its “marked lack of clarity in what privacy expectations as to content of electronic communications are reasonable,”125 the appellate court refused to decide whether the emails were constitutionally protected. If the Supreme Court was unable “to answer the constitutional question of whether the plaintiff’s privacy expectation was reasonable or even to set forth the governing principles to answer that question,” then the court of appeals would not try.126 Instead, the court held that, even if the Constitution were violated, the prosecutor and his investigator were entitled to immunity.127 Bizarrely, the court faulted the plaintiff for failing to show that “his alleged constitutional right”—the one that courts only hypothetically assume exists—“was clearly established.”128 Keeping rights hypothetical means that police and

121 Rehberg v. Paulk, 611 F.3d 828 (11th Cir. 2010), aff’d on other grounds, 132 S. Ct. 1497 (2012).

122 Id. at 842. 123 Id. at 843. 124 Id. 125 Id. at 844. 126 Id. at 845, 846. 127 Id. at 846. 128 Id. at 846.

Page 66: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

507 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

prosecutors enjoy immunity for even the flagrant abuses of power perpetrated on Rehberg. A few months later, the Sixth Circuit acknowledged that Katz discourages courts from acknowledging and enforcing rights and observed that the problem is an intractable aspect of Katz’s atextual interpretation of the Fourth Amendment. In United States v. Warshak, the court refused to assume a Fourth Amendment violation just for the sake of argument before deciding that the aggrieved was not entitled to any remedy.129 The court recognized that judicial shirking of Fourth Amendment questions gives the government “carte blanche to violate constitutionally protected privacy rights.”130 It also recognized that email had achieved a “prominent role” and, indeed, that “an explosion of Internet-based communication has taken place.”131 Reasoning that emails had become as prevalent as letters and telephone calls, the court relied on Ex parte Jackson’s protection of the mails132 and Katz’s protection of the wires to conclude that emails stored by an Internet carrier are constitutionally protected.133 The court distinguished Miller on the ground that the bank in Miller was not an intermediary but the intended recipient of the records seized.134 Because it was forced to build on the Katz framework, Warshak perpetuated the idea that messages cease to be private once they reach the intended recipient, from whom they can be seized. Worse, despite its pretense to progressivism, the decision reaffirmed the notion that legitimate expectations of privacy coalesce only once a practice is so pervasive as to be utterly mainstream. So, just as Katz anachronistically intimated that the telephone had only recently come into widespread use and Quon called two-way pagers an “emerging technology” in 2010, Warshak described email that same year as though it were new. Conditioning the constitutional status of a private message on who happens to have possession of it when the government intercepts it and

129 Warshak, 631 F.3d at 292. 130 Id. at 282 n.13. 131 Id. at 284. 132 Ex parte Jackson, 96 U.S. at 733. 133 Warshak, 631 F.3d at 284. 134 Id. at 288.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 508

how popular the medium used to create it has become produces an arbitrary and needlessly complex jurisprudence. If the Fourth Amendment applies only to ways of keeping and communicating information that Supreme Court justices consider prevalent, all indications are that it will stay perpetually obsolete. Speaking to a group of bankruptcy judges in late 2011, Justice Elena Kagan said that the justices “ignore 25 years of technology” and “do not email each other.”135 “The clerks e-mail each other, but the justices do not.”136 Instead, they dispatch messengers carrying paper notes to communicate with each other.137 During oral argument, rather than using the Internet to consult source materials, the justices have pages, who sit out of sight behind the bench, fetch opinions or books.138 At conference, each justice has, rather than a laptop or an iPad, a cart piled with “all the briefs they need to consult during deliberations.”139 Such superannuated practices would seem quaint but innocuous if Katz did not require judges to gauge America’s privacy expectations in the present. But, until some critical mass of the judiciary recognizes society’s adoption of a new technological norm, the expectations-of-privacy framework wrongfully denies constitutional protection to new ways of communicating and recording ideas. In the meantime, courts fumble about trying to discover society’s privacy expectations by drawing analogies to the past: Emails are like letters.140 Computers are like file cabinets.141 Furthermore, Katz’s failure to grapple with the realities of everyday life

135 Supreme Court Justice Elena Kagan Speaks in Tampa, TAMPA TRIBUNE, Oct.

15, 2011, http://tbo.com/news/crime/supreme-court-justice-elena-kagan-speaks-in-tampa-272250.

136 Id. 137 Id.; see also JOHN PAUL STEVENS, FIVE CHIEFS 73 (2011). 138 STEVENS, supra note 137, at 117. 139Id. at 213. 140 See, e.g., United States v. Warshak, 631 F.3d 266, 284 (6th Cir. 2010). 141 See, e.g., United States v. Williams, 592 F.3d 511 (4th Cir. 2010) (“At

bottom, we conclude that the sheer amount of information contained on a computer does not distinguish the authorized search of the computer from an analogous search of a file cabinet containing a large number of documents.”).

Page 67: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

507 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

prosecutors enjoy immunity for even the flagrant abuses of power perpetrated on Rehberg. A few months later, the Sixth Circuit acknowledged that Katz discourages courts from acknowledging and enforcing rights and observed that the problem is an intractable aspect of Katz’s atextual interpretation of the Fourth Amendment. In United States v. Warshak, the court refused to assume a Fourth Amendment violation just for the sake of argument before deciding that the aggrieved was not entitled to any remedy.129 The court recognized that judicial shirking of Fourth Amendment questions gives the government “carte blanche to violate constitutionally protected privacy rights.”130 It also recognized that email had achieved a “prominent role” and, indeed, that “an explosion of Internet-based communication has taken place.”131 Reasoning that emails had become as prevalent as letters and telephone calls, the court relied on Ex parte Jackson’s protection of the mails132 and Katz’s protection of the wires to conclude that emails stored by an Internet carrier are constitutionally protected.133 The court distinguished Miller on the ground that the bank in Miller was not an intermediary but the intended recipient of the records seized.134 Because it was forced to build on the Katz framework, Warshak perpetuated the idea that messages cease to be private once they reach the intended recipient, from whom they can be seized. Worse, despite its pretense to progressivism, the decision reaffirmed the notion that legitimate expectations of privacy coalesce only once a practice is so pervasive as to be utterly mainstream. So, just as Katz anachronistically intimated that the telephone had only recently come into widespread use and Quon called two-way pagers an “emerging technology” in 2010, Warshak described email that same year as though it were new. Conditioning the constitutional status of a private message on who happens to have possession of it when the government intercepts it and

129 Warshak, 631 F.3d at 292. 130 Id. at 282 n.13. 131 Id. at 284. 132 Ex parte Jackson, 96 U.S. at 733. 133 Warshak, 631 F.3d at 284. 134 Id. at 288.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 508

how popular the medium used to create it has become produces an arbitrary and needlessly complex jurisprudence. If the Fourth Amendment applies only to ways of keeping and communicating information that Supreme Court justices consider prevalent, all indications are that it will stay perpetually obsolete. Speaking to a group of bankruptcy judges in late 2011, Justice Elena Kagan said that the justices “ignore 25 years of technology” and “do not email each other.”135 “The clerks e-mail each other, but the justices do not.”136 Instead, they dispatch messengers carrying paper notes to communicate with each other.137 During oral argument, rather than using the Internet to consult source materials, the justices have pages, who sit out of sight behind the bench, fetch opinions or books.138 At conference, each justice has, rather than a laptop or an iPad, a cart piled with “all the briefs they need to consult during deliberations.”139 Such superannuated practices would seem quaint but innocuous if Katz did not require judges to gauge America’s privacy expectations in the present. But, until some critical mass of the judiciary recognizes society’s adoption of a new technological norm, the expectations-of-privacy framework wrongfully denies constitutional protection to new ways of communicating and recording ideas. In the meantime, courts fumble about trying to discover society’s privacy expectations by drawing analogies to the past: Emails are like letters.140 Computers are like file cabinets.141 Furthermore, Katz’s failure to grapple with the realities of everyday life

135 Supreme Court Justice Elena Kagan Speaks in Tampa, TAMPA TRIBUNE, Oct.

15, 2011, http://tbo.com/news/crime/supreme-court-justice-elena-kagan-speaks-in-tampa-272250.

136 Id. 137 Id.; see also JOHN PAUL STEVENS, FIVE CHIEFS 73 (2011). 138 STEVENS, supra note 137, at 117. 139Id. at 213. 140 See, e.g., United States v. Warshak, 631 F.3d 266, 284 (6th Cir. 2010). 141 See, e.g., United States v. Williams, 592 F.3d 511 (4th Cir. 2010) (“At

bottom, we conclude that the sheer amount of information contained on a computer does not distinguish the authorized search of the computer from an analogous search of a file cabinet containing a large number of documents.”).

Page 68: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

509 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

also reaches backward as courts reconsider the Fourth Amendment’s application to ancient media. Under the expectations-of-privacy framework, a letter can cease to be private once the Post Office delivers it to the intended recipient, even if that happens to be the writer’s spouse.142 This means that the government is barred by Ex parte Jackson from reading mail while it is in transit.143 But, the moment the message reaches its recipient, government agents can search the recipient’s house (or computer) without cause, seize the correspondence, and use it against the sender, who, having suffered no invasion of privacy, lacks standing to complain.144

B. KATZ’S FAILURE TO PROTECT “EFFECTS”

Katz put contraband as well as correspondence and records outside the Fourth Amendment’s protection. Before Katz, the Court had repeatedly affirmed that, although the federal and state governments could by statute extinguish the right to possess certain taboo things, like whiskey, the Fourth Amendment nonetheless protected those things from unreasonable search and seizure. Contraband, in other words, could be trespassed like any property for Fourth Amendment purposes, even though technically it could not be owned.145 This made sense as both a matter of

142 United States v. King, 55 F.3d 1193, 1195–96 (6th Cir. 1995) (“In this case, King voluntarily mailed the letters at issue to his wife. Although he may have instructed her to preserve the confidentiality of the letters, there is no evidence that he expected her to return the letters to him. Under those circumstances, his expectation of privacy in the letters terminated upon delivery of the letters to his wife.”); see also United States v. Knoll, 16 F.3d 1313, 1321 (2nd Cir. 1994) (holding that expectation of privacy in correspondence terminates upon delivery); Ray v. United States Dep’t of Justice, 658 F.2d 608, 611 (8th Cir. 1981) (same).

143 Ex parte Jackson, 96 U.S. at 733. 144 Cf. United States v. Payner, 447 U.S. 727 (1980) (defendant lacked Fourth

Amendment standing to move for suppression of documents that IRS agents illegally seized from another person’s briefcase and surreptitiously photocopied).

145 See United States v. Jeffers, 342 U.S. 48, 53 (1951) (holding that Congress’ declaring cocaine to be contraband was “intended to aid in their forfeiture . . . rather than to abolish the exclusionary rule formulated by the courts in furtherance of the high

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 510

history and of law. The Fourth Amendment’s protection of contraband is at the very core of its guarantee, given that the amendment was directed at the general warrants that the English crown had used to search for libelous writings, whose possession was if not itself illegal at least evidence of guilt.146 Today, whether a person possesses something that the legislature has banned is, according to numerous decisions, a fact not entitled to any privacy.147 Before 1967, contraband was treated like all other effects for Fourth Amendment purposes, except that the government was in all events entitled to confiscate it. In Trupiano v. United States, the Court suppressed an illegal still, alcohol, and brewing equipment seized during a warrantless raid on a farm because agents had surveilled the bootleggers for weeks and could easily have obtained a warrant.148 The Court ruled the seizure unconstitutional even though there was no trespass except to the contraband itself. Because the agents could see a man operating the illegal still inside the leased barn from a place where the farm’s owner allowed them to be, they were allowed to arrest him without a warrant.149 That, however, did not excuse their failure to obtain a warrant to seize the contraband. While the evidence was deemed property for Fourth Amendment purposes, its statutory status as contraband meant that the petitioners had “no right to have it returned to them.”150 Just two years before Katz, the Court affirmed Trupiano’s protection of contraband in One 1958 Plymouth Sedan v. Pennsylvania.151 purposes of the Fourth Amendment”).

146 Bascuas, supra note 17, at 631; Warden v. Hayden, 387 U.S. 294, 313–15 (1967) (Douglas, J., dissenting).

147 See, e.g., Illinois v. Caballes, 543 U.S. 405, 408–09 (2005); United States v. Place, 462 U.S. 696, 707 (1983).

148 334 U.S. 699, 707 (1948), overruled in part by United States v. Rabinowitz, 339 U.S. 56, 66 (1950); see also Lewis v. United States, 385 U.S. 206, 210 (1966) (holding that marijuana and statements obtained at defendant’s home by undercover officer were admissible because defendant voluntarily made the statements and sold the marijuana); id. at 213 (Brennan, J., concurring).

149 Trupiano, 334 U.S. at 704–05. 150 Id. at 710. 151 380 U.S. 693 (1965).

Page 69: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

509 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

also reaches backward as courts reconsider the Fourth Amendment’s application to ancient media. Under the expectations-of-privacy framework, a letter can cease to be private once the Post Office delivers it to the intended recipient, even if that happens to be the writer’s spouse.142 This means that the government is barred by Ex parte Jackson from reading mail while it is in transit.143 But, the moment the message reaches its recipient, government agents can search the recipient’s house (or computer) without cause, seize the correspondence, and use it against the sender, who, having suffered no invasion of privacy, lacks standing to complain.144

B. KATZ’S FAILURE TO PROTECT “EFFECTS”

Katz put contraband as well as correspondence and records outside the Fourth Amendment’s protection. Before Katz, the Court had repeatedly affirmed that, although the federal and state governments could by statute extinguish the right to possess certain taboo things, like whiskey, the Fourth Amendment nonetheless protected those things from unreasonable search and seizure. Contraband, in other words, could be trespassed like any property for Fourth Amendment purposes, even though technically it could not be owned.145 This made sense as both a matter of

142 United States v. King, 55 F.3d 1193, 1195–96 (6th Cir. 1995) (“In this case, King voluntarily mailed the letters at issue to his wife. Although he may have instructed her to preserve the confidentiality of the letters, there is no evidence that he expected her to return the letters to him. Under those circumstances, his expectation of privacy in the letters terminated upon delivery of the letters to his wife.”); see also United States v. Knoll, 16 F.3d 1313, 1321 (2nd Cir. 1994) (holding that expectation of privacy in correspondence terminates upon delivery); Ray v. United States Dep’t of Justice, 658 F.2d 608, 611 (8th Cir. 1981) (same).

143 Ex parte Jackson, 96 U.S. at 733. 144 Cf. United States v. Payner, 447 U.S. 727 (1980) (defendant lacked Fourth

Amendment standing to move for suppression of documents that IRS agents illegally seized from another person’s briefcase and surreptitiously photocopied).

145 See United States v. Jeffers, 342 U.S. 48, 53 (1951) (holding that Congress’ declaring cocaine to be contraband was “intended to aid in their forfeiture . . . rather than to abolish the exclusionary rule formulated by the courts in furtherance of the high

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 510

history and of law. The Fourth Amendment’s protection of contraband is at the very core of its guarantee, given that the amendment was directed at the general warrants that the English crown had used to search for libelous writings, whose possession was if not itself illegal at least evidence of guilt.146 Today, whether a person possesses something that the legislature has banned is, according to numerous decisions, a fact not entitled to any privacy.147 Before 1967, contraband was treated like all other effects for Fourth Amendment purposes, except that the government was in all events entitled to confiscate it. In Trupiano v. United States, the Court suppressed an illegal still, alcohol, and brewing equipment seized during a warrantless raid on a farm because agents had surveilled the bootleggers for weeks and could easily have obtained a warrant.148 The Court ruled the seizure unconstitutional even though there was no trespass except to the contraband itself. Because the agents could see a man operating the illegal still inside the leased barn from a place where the farm’s owner allowed them to be, they were allowed to arrest him without a warrant.149 That, however, did not excuse their failure to obtain a warrant to seize the contraband. While the evidence was deemed property for Fourth Amendment purposes, its statutory status as contraband meant that the petitioners had “no right to have it returned to them.”150 Just two years before Katz, the Court affirmed Trupiano’s protection of contraband in One 1958 Plymouth Sedan v. Pennsylvania.151 purposes of the Fourth Amendment”).

146 Bascuas, supra note 17, at 631; Warden v. Hayden, 387 U.S. 294, 313–15 (1967) (Douglas, J., dissenting).

147 See, e.g., Illinois v. Caballes, 543 U.S. 405, 408–09 (2005); United States v. Place, 462 U.S. 696, 707 (1983).

148 334 U.S. 699, 707 (1948), overruled in part by United States v. Rabinowitz, 339 U.S. 56, 66 (1950); see also Lewis v. United States, 385 U.S. 206, 210 (1966) (holding that marijuana and statements obtained at defendant’s home by undercover officer were admissible because defendant voluntarily made the statements and sold the marijuana); id. at 213 (Brennan, J., concurring).

149 Trupiano, 334 U.S. at 704–05. 150 Id. at 710. 151 380 U.S. 693 (1965).

Page 70: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

511 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Relying on a statute that made vehicles carrying illegal liquor contraband, Pennsylvania argued that a car could be searched without probable cause because it was contraband—as established by liquor discovered in it during a search.152 Rejecting that bootstrapping argument, the Court reiterated that the Fourth Amendment protects contraband just like any other property.153 The Court held that the liquor had to be suppressed from the proceeding to forfeit the car. After Katz, the Court could—and did—treat contraband more cavalierly because its status as property was beside the point. Framing the issue as whether one has a “legitimate expectation of privacy” in hidden contraband left little doubt as to how the Court would resolve it. In United States v. Place, the Court stated that “briefly” seizing a person’s luggage so that a dog can sniff it for drugs does not implicate the Fourth Amendment because “the sniff discloses only the presence or absence of narcotics, a contraband item” and “does not expose noncontraband items that otherwise would remain hidden from public view.”154 Because Katz fails to accord due deference to property rights, the opinion fails to acknowledge a person’s right to stubbornly—even irrationally—refuse to hand over one’s suitcase for even an instant absent probable cause. Place thus holds that the privacy-based Fourth Amendment subordinates property rights to the courts’ view of the communal good.155 The following year, the Court heard United States v. Jacobsen,156 a case in which Federal Express employees reported a package containing cocaine to the Drug Enforcement Agency. Justice John Paul Stevens’ majority opinion held that the Fourth Amendment did not apply to the inspection of the package or to the field test for cocaine because neither infringed a privacy expectation. The opening of the package did not infringe privacy because “the Federal Express employees had just examined the package and had, of their own accord, invited the federal

152 Id. at 694 & n.3. 153 Id. at 699. 154 462 U.S. 696, 707 (1983). 155 See Reich, supra note 42 at 774. 156 466 U.S. 109 (1984).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 512

agent to their offices for the express purpose of viewing its contents.”157 Relying on Place, the Court further held that the seizure of the package’s contents was reasonable because “it is well-settled that it is constitutionally reasonable for law enforcement officials to seize ‘effects’ that cannot support a justifiable expectation of privacy without a warrant, based on probable cause to believe they contain contraband.”158 Justice Brennan complained in dissent that the Court’s “new Fourth Amendment jurisprudence” was not proceeding along the lines he had expected when the Court decided Katz.159 Brennan disagreed “with the blanket assumption, implicit in Place and explicit in this case, that individuals in our society have no reasonable expectation of privacy in the fact that they have contraband in their possession. . . .”160 He worried that the Court’s refusal to recognize a privacy interest in contraband meant that “law enforcement officers could release a trained cocaine-sensitive dog . . .… to roam the streets at random, alerting the officers to people carrying cocaine.”161 He was prescient on this point but did not live to see the DEA fully realize his nightmare two decades later.162 In Illinois v. Caballes, the Court, again speaking through Justice Stevens, extended Place’s rationale to systematic, routine dog sniffs of cars pulled over for speeding: “We have held that any interest in possessing contraband cannot be deemed ‘legitimate,’ and thus, governmental conduct that only reveals the possession of contraband ‘compromises no legitimate privacy interest.’”163 Comparing Trupiano to Jacobsen suggests Prohibition might have fared better under the post-Katz Fourth Amendment. Jacobsen presented essentially the same facts as Trupiano. In both cases, a private actor (the farm owner in Trupiano, the Federal Express employees in Jacobsen) called federal agents to report trafficking in prohibited substances (booze,

157 Id. at 119. 158 Id. at 121–22. 159 Id. at 137 (Brennan, J., dissenting). 160 Id. 161 Id. at 138. 162 Bascuas, supra note 35, at 761–63 (describing DEA’s Operation Pipeline). 163 543 US. 405, 409 (2005).

Page 71: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

511 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Relying on a statute that made vehicles carrying illegal liquor contraband, Pennsylvania argued that a car could be searched without probable cause because it was contraband—as established by liquor discovered in it during a search.152 Rejecting that bootstrapping argument, the Court reiterated that the Fourth Amendment protects contraband just like any other property.153 The Court held that the liquor had to be suppressed from the proceeding to forfeit the car. After Katz, the Court could—and did—treat contraband more cavalierly because its status as property was beside the point. Framing the issue as whether one has a “legitimate expectation of privacy” in hidden contraband left little doubt as to how the Court would resolve it. In United States v. Place, the Court stated that “briefly” seizing a person’s luggage so that a dog can sniff it for drugs does not implicate the Fourth Amendment because “the sniff discloses only the presence or absence of narcotics, a contraband item” and “does not expose noncontraband items that otherwise would remain hidden from public view.”154 Because Katz fails to accord due deference to property rights, the opinion fails to acknowledge a person’s right to stubbornly—even irrationally—refuse to hand over one’s suitcase for even an instant absent probable cause. Place thus holds that the privacy-based Fourth Amendment subordinates property rights to the courts’ view of the communal good.155 The following year, the Court heard United States v. Jacobsen,156 a case in which Federal Express employees reported a package containing cocaine to the Drug Enforcement Agency. Justice John Paul Stevens’ majority opinion held that the Fourth Amendment did not apply to the inspection of the package or to the field test for cocaine because neither infringed a privacy expectation. The opening of the package did not infringe privacy because “the Federal Express employees had just examined the package and had, of their own accord, invited the federal

152 Id. at 694 & n.3. 153 Id. at 699. 154 462 U.S. 696, 707 (1983). 155 See Reich, supra note 42 at 774. 156 466 U.S. 109 (1984).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 512

agent to their offices for the express purpose of viewing its contents.”157 Relying on Place, the Court further held that the seizure of the package’s contents was reasonable because “it is well-settled that it is constitutionally reasonable for law enforcement officials to seize ‘effects’ that cannot support a justifiable expectation of privacy without a warrant, based on probable cause to believe they contain contraband.”158 Justice Brennan complained in dissent that the Court’s “new Fourth Amendment jurisprudence” was not proceeding along the lines he had expected when the Court decided Katz.159 Brennan disagreed “with the blanket assumption, implicit in Place and explicit in this case, that individuals in our society have no reasonable expectation of privacy in the fact that they have contraband in their possession. . . .”160 He worried that the Court’s refusal to recognize a privacy interest in contraband meant that “law enforcement officers could release a trained cocaine-sensitive dog . . .… to roam the streets at random, alerting the officers to people carrying cocaine.”161 He was prescient on this point but did not live to see the DEA fully realize his nightmare two decades later.162 In Illinois v. Caballes, the Court, again speaking through Justice Stevens, extended Place’s rationale to systematic, routine dog sniffs of cars pulled over for speeding: “We have held that any interest in possessing contraband cannot be deemed ‘legitimate,’ and thus, governmental conduct that only reveals the possession of contraband ‘compromises no legitimate privacy interest.’”163 Comparing Trupiano to Jacobsen suggests Prohibition might have fared better under the post-Katz Fourth Amendment. Jacobsen presented essentially the same facts as Trupiano. In both cases, a private actor (the farm owner in Trupiano, the Federal Express employees in Jacobsen) called federal agents to report trafficking in prohibited substances (booze,

157 Id. at 119. 158 Id. at 121–22. 159 Id. at 137 (Brennan, J., dissenting). 160 Id. 161 Id. at 138. 162 Bascuas, supra note 35, at 761–63 (describing DEA’s Operation Pipeline). 163 543 US. 405, 409 (2005).

Page 72: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

513 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

cocaine). In both cases, federal agents investigated without getting a warrant, although they surely could have. In the pre-1967 regime, the Court divided five to four over whether the seizure was constitutional despite the failure to get a warrant. After 1967, a majority of the Court decided that the Fourth Amendment did not even apply to the inspection of a private package because a third party had destroyed the aggrieved’s expectation of privacy in his belongings. Katz’s disregard of contraband is not confined to drug cases. It means that any unpopular group can have its Fourth Amendment rights curtailed through the enactment of possession offenses.164 Indeed, it is not hard to find examples of how the argument that contraband is outside the Constitution’s protection could be applied to suppress political dissent and marginalize minority viewpoints.165 Walter v. United States,166 on which Jacobsen relied, involved a shipment of “12 large, securely sealed packages containing 871 boxes of 8-millimeter film depicting homosexual activities.”167 The box was misdirected and opened by employees of a company that was not the intended recipient. Each individual box of film was labeled with “suggestive drawings” and “explicit descriptions of the contents.”168 The employees alerted the Federal Bureau of Investigation, whose agents later viewed the films without a search warrant. No justice who had been on the Court when Katz was decided thought the viewing of these films was constitutional—but it was Katz that

164 See generally Markus Dirk Dubber, Policing Possession: The War on Crime

and the End of Criminal Law, 91 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 829, 836 (2001) (“So broad is the reach of possession offenses, and so easy are they to detect and then to prove, that possession has replaced vagrancy as the sweep offense of choice.”).

165 See, e.g., Uphaus v. Wyman, 364 U.S. 388, 407 n.3 (1960) (Douglas, J., dissenting from dismissal of appeal) (“The Attorney General of New Hampshire in the motion to dismiss in this case states, ‘Those who voluntarily and knowingly appear with, consult with, confer with, attend functions with and otherwise act in concert with Communists or former Communists in America cannot possibly have any reasonable right of privacy in regard to such activities.’”).

166 447 U.S. 649 (1980). 167 Id. at 651 (plurality opinion). 168 Id. at 652.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 514

let four more recent appointees conclude that it was.169 Although the decision generated no majority opinion, six justices agreed that, under Katz, the legality of the search depended on whether the FBI agents went beyond what the company employees already had done. Justices Stevens and Stewart believed that, because the employees did not view the films, the FBI agents’ viewing of them was a further invasion of privacy that required a warrant.170 The four dissenters contended that the “employees so fully ascertained the nature of the films before contacting the authorities” that the FBI’s screenings were not an “additional search subject to the warrant requirement.”171 They reasoned that, because it “was obvious from the drawings and labels on the containers” that “the films were of an explicit sexual nature,” the “petitioners had no remaining expectation of privacy” in the films.172 Only Justices White and Brennan believed that ascribing dispositive significance to whether the employees happened to watch the films was an unsatisfactory way to determine the scope of a constitutional right:

The notion that private searches insulate from Fourth Amendment scrutiny subsequent governmental searches of the same or lesser scope is inconsistent with traditional Fourth Amendment principles.173

Underlying Walter and Jacobsen is the idea that once private property is trespassed, any subsequent trespass inflicts no harm (or only trivial harm) on the owner. So, it is not wrongful. It is as though, once property is trespassed, its owner loses the exclusivity of dominion and control that is property’s essence. Then, anyone, including government agents, can have a look. To believe that is to believe that the Founding Fathers would not have been offended had a messenger read seditious

169 Justice Marshall concurred only in the judgment in Walter and recused

himself in Katz because he had been solicitor general while the case was pending. 170 Id. at 654. 171 Id. at 663–64 (Blackmun, J., dissenting) (citing Walter v. United States, 592

F.2d 788, 793–94 (5th Cir. 1979)). 172 Id. at 663. 173 Id. at 660–61 (White, J., concurring in part).

Page 73: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

513 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

cocaine). In both cases, federal agents investigated without getting a warrant, although they surely could have. In the pre-1967 regime, the Court divided five to four over whether the seizure was constitutional despite the failure to get a warrant. After 1967, a majority of the Court decided that the Fourth Amendment did not even apply to the inspection of a private package because a third party had destroyed the aggrieved’s expectation of privacy in his belongings. Katz’s disregard of contraband is not confined to drug cases. It means that any unpopular group can have its Fourth Amendment rights curtailed through the enactment of possession offenses.164 Indeed, it is not hard to find examples of how the argument that contraband is outside the Constitution’s protection could be applied to suppress political dissent and marginalize minority viewpoints.165 Walter v. United States,166 on which Jacobsen relied, involved a shipment of “12 large, securely sealed packages containing 871 boxes of 8-millimeter film depicting homosexual activities.”167 The box was misdirected and opened by employees of a company that was not the intended recipient. Each individual box of film was labeled with “suggestive drawings” and “explicit descriptions of the contents.”168 The employees alerted the Federal Bureau of Investigation, whose agents later viewed the films without a search warrant. No justice who had been on the Court when Katz was decided thought the viewing of these films was constitutional—but it was Katz that

164 See generally Markus Dirk Dubber, Policing Possession: The War on Crime

and the End of Criminal Law, 91 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 829, 836 (2001) (“So broad is the reach of possession offenses, and so easy are they to detect and then to prove, that possession has replaced vagrancy as the sweep offense of choice.”).

165 See, e.g., Uphaus v. Wyman, 364 U.S. 388, 407 n.3 (1960) (Douglas, J., dissenting from dismissal of appeal) (“The Attorney General of New Hampshire in the motion to dismiss in this case states, ‘Those who voluntarily and knowingly appear with, consult with, confer with, attend functions with and otherwise act in concert with Communists or former Communists in America cannot possibly have any reasonable right of privacy in regard to such activities.’”).

166 447 U.S. 649 (1980). 167 Id. at 651 (plurality opinion). 168 Id. at 652.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 514

let four more recent appointees conclude that it was.169 Although the decision generated no majority opinion, six justices agreed that, under Katz, the legality of the search depended on whether the FBI agents went beyond what the company employees already had done. Justices Stevens and Stewart believed that, because the employees did not view the films, the FBI agents’ viewing of them was a further invasion of privacy that required a warrant.170 The four dissenters contended that the “employees so fully ascertained the nature of the films before contacting the authorities” that the FBI’s screenings were not an “additional search subject to the warrant requirement.”171 They reasoned that, because it “was obvious from the drawings and labels on the containers” that “the films were of an explicit sexual nature,” the “petitioners had no remaining expectation of privacy” in the films.172 Only Justices White and Brennan believed that ascribing dispositive significance to whether the employees happened to watch the films was an unsatisfactory way to determine the scope of a constitutional right:

The notion that private searches insulate from Fourth Amendment scrutiny subsequent governmental searches of the same or lesser scope is inconsistent with traditional Fourth Amendment principles.173

Underlying Walter and Jacobsen is the idea that once private property is trespassed, any subsequent trespass inflicts no harm (or only trivial harm) on the owner. So, it is not wrongful. It is as though, once property is trespassed, its owner loses the exclusivity of dominion and control that is property’s essence. Then, anyone, including government agents, can have a look. To believe that is to believe that the Founding Fathers would not have been offended had a messenger read seditious

169 Justice Marshall concurred only in the judgment in Walter and recused

himself in Katz because he had been solicitor general while the case was pending. 170 Id. at 654. 171 Id. at 663–64 (Blackmun, J., dissenting) (citing Walter v. United States, 592

F.2d 788, 793–94 (5th Cir. 1979)). 172 Id. at 663. 173 Id. at 660–61 (White, J., concurring in part).

Page 74: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

515 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

writings entrusted to him for delivery and then handed them over to agents of the Crown.

III. KATZ, JONES, AND THE POSTMODERN FOURTH AMENDMENT

That Katz puts personal information and contraband beyond the Fourth Amendment’s protection is all the more lamentable because the decision made no countervailing contribution to the nation’s jurisprudence. By the time Katz was decided, the Court had already repudiated Olmstead’s holdings (reaffirmed in 1942174) that electronic surveillance entailing no trespass did not implicate the Fourth Amendment and that conversations were incapable of being seized. Olmstead’s rationale having already been repudiated, Katz could have been decided applying the more pragmatic, flexible trespass test that was Fourth Amendment law in the 1960s. In 1961, Silverman v. United States held that the slightest imaginable warrantless conversion of a defendant’s property—even if it was not technically a trespass under local law—violated the Fourth Amendment.175 In Silverman, police officers inserted a spike mike from a vacant row house into the neighboring house until it hit the defendants’ heating duct, “thus converting their entire heating system into a conductor of sound.”176 The Court unanimously held that this violated the Fourth Amendment.177 Two years later, Wong Sun v. United States relied on Silverman to conclude for the first time that conversations could, like “papers” and “effects,” be the subject of a Fourth Amendment seizure.178

174 Goldman v. United States, 316 U.S. 129, 135 (1942). 175 Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 511–12 (1961). 176 Id. at 506–07. 177 Id. at 511–12 (“This Court has never held that a federal officer may without

warrant and without consent physically entrench into a man’s office or home, there secretly observe or listen, and relate at the man’s subsequent trial what was seen or heard.”).

178 Wong Sun v. United States, 371 U.S. 471, 485 (1963) (“It follows from our holding in [Silverman] that the Fourth Amendment may protect against the overhearing

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 516

Building on Silverman, Wong Sun equated oral communications with written ones for Fourth Amendment purposes. In the term before Katz, Berger v. United States made express what Wong Sun and Silverman implied. It held that conversations were a species of “papers” or “effects” within the Fourth Amendment’s terms. Berger struck down a New York statute that authorized wiretapping a private office without a proper warrant. An indispensable premise of the Court’s rationale was that Olmstead was wrong in holding that conversations were not capable of being seized: “Statements in the opinion that a conversation passing over a telephone wire cannot be said to come within the Fourth Amendment’s enumeration of ‘persons, houses, papers, and effects’ have been negated by our subsequent cases as hereinafter noted.”179 Further in the opinion, the Court again described conversations as a type of property. Explaining that New York’s statute did not require a warrant “particularly describing . . . the persons or things to be seized,”180 the Court observed that the statute was defective for not requiring “that the ‘property’ sought, the conversations, be particularly described.”181 So, by 1967, the two premises that the Bell System and Justice Butler had urged in Olmstead were validated. First, rather than conditioning the Fourth Amendment’s protection on the vagaries of local property law, courts would decide whether the government, as a practical matter, converted or trespassed property. Second, conversations could be “seized” under the Fourth Amendment just as tangible property. This was enough to convert the old trespass test into a highly flexible but principled

of verbal statements as well as against the more traditional seizure of ‘papers and effects.’ . . . Thus, verbal evidence which derives so immediately from an unlawful entry and an unauthorized arrest as the officers’ action in the present case is no less the ‘fruit’ of official illegality than the more common tangible fruits of the unwarranted intrusion.”).

179 Berger v. New York, 388 U.S. 41, 51 (1967). 180 U.S. CONST. amend. IV. 181 Berger, 388 U.S. at 58–59; see also Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 372

(1967) (Black, J., dissenting) (“It is the Court’s opinions in this case and Berger which for the first time since 1791, when the Fourth Amendment was adopted, have declared that eavesdropping is subject to Fourth Amendment restrictions and that conversation can be ‘seized.’”).

Page 75: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

515 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

writings entrusted to him for delivery and then handed them over to agents of the Crown.

III. KATZ, JONES, AND THE POSTMODERN FOURTH AMENDMENT

That Katz puts personal information and contraband beyond the Fourth Amendment’s protection is all the more lamentable because the decision made no countervailing contribution to the nation’s jurisprudence. By the time Katz was decided, the Court had already repudiated Olmstead’s holdings (reaffirmed in 1942174) that electronic surveillance entailing no trespass did not implicate the Fourth Amendment and that conversations were incapable of being seized. Olmstead’s rationale having already been repudiated, Katz could have been decided applying the more pragmatic, flexible trespass test that was Fourth Amendment law in the 1960s. In 1961, Silverman v. United States held that the slightest imaginable warrantless conversion of a defendant’s property—even if it was not technically a trespass under local law—violated the Fourth Amendment.175 In Silverman, police officers inserted a spike mike from a vacant row house into the neighboring house until it hit the defendants’ heating duct, “thus converting their entire heating system into a conductor of sound.”176 The Court unanimously held that this violated the Fourth Amendment.177 Two years later, Wong Sun v. United States relied on Silverman to conclude for the first time that conversations could, like “papers” and “effects,” be the subject of a Fourth Amendment seizure.178

174 Goldman v. United States, 316 U.S. 129, 135 (1942). 175 Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 511–12 (1961). 176 Id. at 506–07. 177 Id. at 511–12 (“This Court has never held that a federal officer may without

warrant and without consent physically entrench into a man’s office or home, there secretly observe or listen, and relate at the man’s subsequent trial what was seen or heard.”).

178 Wong Sun v. United States, 371 U.S. 471, 485 (1963) (“It follows from our holding in [Silverman] that the Fourth Amendment may protect against the overhearing

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 516

Building on Silverman, Wong Sun equated oral communications with written ones for Fourth Amendment purposes. In the term before Katz, Berger v. United States made express what Wong Sun and Silverman implied. It held that conversations were a species of “papers” or “effects” within the Fourth Amendment’s terms. Berger struck down a New York statute that authorized wiretapping a private office without a proper warrant. An indispensable premise of the Court’s rationale was that Olmstead was wrong in holding that conversations were not capable of being seized: “Statements in the opinion that a conversation passing over a telephone wire cannot be said to come within the Fourth Amendment’s enumeration of ‘persons, houses, papers, and effects’ have been negated by our subsequent cases as hereinafter noted.”179 Further in the opinion, the Court again described conversations as a type of property. Explaining that New York’s statute did not require a warrant “particularly describing . . . the persons or things to be seized,”180 the Court observed that the statute was defective for not requiring “that the ‘property’ sought, the conversations, be particularly described.”181 So, by 1967, the two premises that the Bell System and Justice Butler had urged in Olmstead were validated. First, rather than conditioning the Fourth Amendment’s protection on the vagaries of local property law, courts would decide whether the government, as a practical matter, converted or trespassed property. Second, conversations could be “seized” under the Fourth Amendment just as tangible property. This was enough to convert the old trespass test into a highly flexible but principled

of verbal statements as well as against the more traditional seizure of ‘papers and effects.’ . . . Thus, verbal evidence which derives so immediately from an unlawful entry and an unauthorized arrest as the officers’ action in the present case is no less the ‘fruit’ of official illegality than the more common tangible fruits of the unwarranted intrusion.”).

179 Berger v. New York, 388 U.S. 41, 51 (1967). 180 U.S. CONST. amend. IV. 181 Berger, 388 U.S. at 58–59; see also Katz v. United States, 389 U.S. 347, 372

(1967) (Black, J., dissenting) (“It is the Court’s opinions in this case and Berger which for the first time since 1791, when the Fourth Amendment was adopted, have declared that eavesdropping is subject to Fourth Amendment restrictions and that conversation can be ‘seized.’”).

Page 76: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

517 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

tool for applying the Fourth Amendment to new forms of property without risking diminution of its traditional protection. The outcome in Katz was thus assured by very recent precedent. There was no need for the decision to do anything more than clarify certain ambiguities Berger created regarding the procedures for authorizing a wiretap and reiterate that conversations were within the Fourth Amendment’s protection of papers and effects.182 Had the Court refrained from broad and vague pronouncements regarding a supposed right to privacy, judges could have set about refining the pragmatic property approach adopted in Silverman and Berger using common-law methods restrained by the text’s solicitude for property rights.183 This endeavor would have yielded a more predictable and principled jurisprudence and facilitated applying the amendment to new technology. Instead, they spent more than four decades attempting to divine societal expectations of privacy. Over Justice Black’s pointed criticism, Katz needlessly and heedlessly brushed aside the Fourth Amendment’s text to give the Court an unbounded jurisprudential tool for dealing with the threat it perceived from electronic surveillance. Katz allowed the Court to withdraw the Fourth Amendment’s protection whenever it felt that the interests of “society” outweighed an individual’s property rights—and the Court did so repeatedly.184 It

182 See Katz, 389 U.S. at 364 (Black, J., dissenting) (“The Court’s opinion in this case . . . removes the doubts about state power in this field and abates to a large extent the confusion and near-paralyzing effect of the Berger holding.”); see also Lopez v. United States, 373 U.S. 427, 463 (Brennan, J., dissenting) (explaining that the Court had feared that bringing electronic surveillance within the Fourth Amendment’s reach would effectively outlaw its use because complying with the warrant requirement would be impossible); Winn, supra note 74, at 2–6.

183 Monaghan, supra note 84, at 394 (“One could, after all, argue that elaboration of the specific guarantees of the bill of rights exhibits characteristics of both common law and statutory interpretation: common law because their content is worked out in the manner of the analogical and precedential reasoning characteristic of the common law courts; statutory because, so far as is practicable, emphasis has been and still should be placed on historical setting and original intent.”).

184 See Reich, supra note 42, at 761; see also, e.g., United States v. Place, 462 U.S. 696, 703 (1983) (holding that the Fourth Amendment’s scope is ascertained by “balancing the competing interests to determine the reasonableness of the type of seizure

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 518

extended no countervailing protection that the trespass test it displaced would not have afforded. The vast majority of the Supreme Court’s cases invalidating a search would, like Jones and Katz itself, turn out the same way under either a trespass or an expectations-of-privacy analysis. Kyllo v. United States, decided in 2001, is one of those rare cases to invalidate a search entailing no trespass.185 It held that using a thermal imager to measure the relative amount of heat emanating from a house constituted a search because the Fourth Amendment shields all information about the inside of a home “from prying government eyes.”186 Struggling to imagine what, if any, consequence a thermal imager might reveal, Justice Scalia’s majority opinion posited that it “might disclose, for example, at what hour each night the lady of the house takes her daily sauna and bath—a detail that many would consider ‘intimate’ … .” The trespass test, as Justice Stevens’ dissent implied, would have led to the conclusion that no Fourth Amendment search or seizure occurred. The dissent explained that, while warrantless “through-the-wall” surveillance (which entails a trespass in the Silverman sense) would violate the Fourth Amendment, “off-the-wall” measurement of heat emanating from a house does not.187 “[P]ublic officials should not have to avert their senses or their equipment from detecting emissions in the public domain such as excessive heat, traces of smoke, suspicious odors, odorless gases, airborne particulates, or radioactive emissions, any of which could identify hazards to the community.”188 Kyllo is no justification for Katz. Its strange equating of constitutional privacy with a Victorian sort of modesty or prudishness allowed the Court to be magnanimous regarding the hypothetical Mrs. Kyllo’s toilet habits. But that same wordplay exposed many actual people to more revealing searches. An earlier decision, also written by Justice Scalia, held that high school football players could be subjected to random

involved”); Texas v. Brown, 460 U.S. 730, 739 (1983) (plurality opinion).

185 It is arguably the only such case. Katz, as Silverman and Berger make clear, is not one.

186 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27, 37 (2001). 187 Id. at 46 (Stevens, J., dissenting). 188 Id. at 45.

Page 77: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

517 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

tool for applying the Fourth Amendment to new forms of property without risking diminution of its traditional protection. The outcome in Katz was thus assured by very recent precedent. There was no need for the decision to do anything more than clarify certain ambiguities Berger created regarding the procedures for authorizing a wiretap and reiterate that conversations were within the Fourth Amendment’s protection of papers and effects.182 Had the Court refrained from broad and vague pronouncements regarding a supposed right to privacy, judges could have set about refining the pragmatic property approach adopted in Silverman and Berger using common-law methods restrained by the text’s solicitude for property rights.183 This endeavor would have yielded a more predictable and principled jurisprudence and facilitated applying the amendment to new technology. Instead, they spent more than four decades attempting to divine societal expectations of privacy. Over Justice Black’s pointed criticism, Katz needlessly and heedlessly brushed aside the Fourth Amendment’s text to give the Court an unbounded jurisprudential tool for dealing with the threat it perceived from electronic surveillance. Katz allowed the Court to withdraw the Fourth Amendment’s protection whenever it felt that the interests of “society” outweighed an individual’s property rights—and the Court did so repeatedly.184 It

182 See Katz, 389 U.S. at 364 (Black, J., dissenting) (“The Court’s opinion in this case . . . removes the doubts about state power in this field and abates to a large extent the confusion and near-paralyzing effect of the Berger holding.”); see also Lopez v. United States, 373 U.S. 427, 463 (Brennan, J., dissenting) (explaining that the Court had feared that bringing electronic surveillance within the Fourth Amendment’s reach would effectively outlaw its use because complying with the warrant requirement would be impossible); Winn, supra note 74, at 2–6.

183 Monaghan, supra note 84, at 394 (“One could, after all, argue that elaboration of the specific guarantees of the bill of rights exhibits characteristics of both common law and statutory interpretation: common law because their content is worked out in the manner of the analogical and precedential reasoning characteristic of the common law courts; statutory because, so far as is practicable, emphasis has been and still should be placed on historical setting and original intent.”).

184 See Reich, supra note 42, at 761; see also, e.g., United States v. Place, 462 U.S. 696, 703 (1983) (holding that the Fourth Amendment’s scope is ascertained by “balancing the competing interests to determine the reasonableness of the type of seizure

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 518

extended no countervailing protection that the trespass test it displaced would not have afforded. The vast majority of the Supreme Court’s cases invalidating a search would, like Jones and Katz itself, turn out the same way under either a trespass or an expectations-of-privacy analysis. Kyllo v. United States, decided in 2001, is one of those rare cases to invalidate a search entailing no trespass.185 It held that using a thermal imager to measure the relative amount of heat emanating from a house constituted a search because the Fourth Amendment shields all information about the inside of a home “from prying government eyes.”186 Struggling to imagine what, if any, consequence a thermal imager might reveal, Justice Scalia’s majority opinion posited that it “might disclose, for example, at what hour each night the lady of the house takes her daily sauna and bath—a detail that many would consider ‘intimate’ … .” The trespass test, as Justice Stevens’ dissent implied, would have led to the conclusion that no Fourth Amendment search or seizure occurred. The dissent explained that, while warrantless “through-the-wall” surveillance (which entails a trespass in the Silverman sense) would violate the Fourth Amendment, “off-the-wall” measurement of heat emanating from a house does not.187 “[P]ublic officials should not have to avert their senses or their equipment from detecting emissions in the public domain such as excessive heat, traces of smoke, suspicious odors, odorless gases, airborne particulates, or radioactive emissions, any of which could identify hazards to the community.”188 Kyllo is no justification for Katz. Its strange equating of constitutional privacy with a Victorian sort of modesty or prudishness allowed the Court to be magnanimous regarding the hypothetical Mrs. Kyllo’s toilet habits. But that same wordplay exposed many actual people to more revealing searches. An earlier decision, also written by Justice Scalia, held that high school football players could be subjected to random

involved”); Texas v. Brown, 460 U.S. 730, 739 (1983) (plurality opinion).

185 It is arguably the only such case. Katz, as Silverman and Berger make clear, is not one.

186 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27, 37 (2001). 187 Id. at 46 (Stevens, J., dissenting). 188 Id. at 45.

Page 78: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

519 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

urinalysis testing for drugs on the bizarre rationale that players see each other nude: “School sports are not for the bashful. They require ‘suiting up’ before each practice or event, and showering and changing afterwards. Public school locker rooms, the usual sites for these activities, are not notable for the privacy they afford.”189 Putting aside the fact that many athletes are bashful, even the most uninhibited exhibitionist is entitled to be free from suspicionless seizures and searches of his bodily fluids. The Court made this clear in a pre-Katz case involving forced blood testing of a man suspected of driving drunk: “Such testing procedures plainly constitute searches of ‘persons,’ and depend antecedently upon seizures of ‘persons,’ within the meaning of [the Fourth] Amendment.”190 More recently, the Court held that police can, at least in some circumstances, strip search anyone arrested for anything, indicating that Kyllo’s protection is not very far-reaching.191 It is hard to find merit in a jurisprudence that considers the timing of showers “intimate” information but countenances compelling schoolchildren to urinate for their teachers and misdemeanants to be strip searched. Jardines v. Florida192 further illustrates that neither Katz nor Kyllo’s specific application of it offers any significant analytical benefit. That case pitted Kyllo’s holding that all information about what happens inside a home is constitutionally protected against Place’s holding that whether someone possesses illegal drugs never is. Police officers confirmed that marijuana was being cultivated inside a home by walking a drug-sniffing dog up to the front door. Justice Scalia’s majority opinion held that the officers unconstitutionally searched the house because “they gathered that information by physically entering and occupying [a constitutionally protected] area to engage in conduct not explicitly or implicitly permitted by the homeowner.”193 The Court noted, “One virtue

189 Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v. Acton, 515 U.S. 646, 657 (1995). 190 Schmerber v. United States, 384 U.S. 757, 767 (1966). 191 Florence v. Bd. of Chosen Freeholders of Burlington, 132 S. Ct. 1510 (2012);

see also Hudson v. Michigan, 547 U.S. 586, 597 (2006) (stating that knock-and-announce rule protects “the right not to be intruded upon in one’s nightclothes”).

192 133 S. Ct. 1409 (2013). 193 Id. at 1414.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 520

of the Fourth Amendment’s property-rights baseline is that it keeps easy cases easy.”194 Justice Kagan’s concurrence, joined by Justices Ginsburg and Sotomayor, reached the same conclusion using Katz’s expectations-of-privacy rubric. The concurrence believed that the case was “already resolved” by Kyllo, “suggesting that a focus on Jardines’ privacy interests would make an ‘easy case easy’ twice over . . . .”195 Jones v. United States, decided the year before Jardines, acknowledged that Katz is a failed experiment that should never have been allowed to escape the laboratory, but it did not repudiate its unworkable test. All nine justices agreed on the outcome in Jones, but the majority gratuitously purported to resuscitate what it called the “common-law trespassory test,” suggesting some fundamental dissatisfaction with Katz.196 Nonetheless, Justice Scalia’s majority opinion agreed with the concurrences that expectations of privacy remain important to Fourth Amendment jurisprudence. (Four justices disputed that any trespass test survived Katz and would have relied exclusively on Katz.197 Justice Sonia Sotomayor’s separate concurrence intimated that she believed the GPS tracking of an automobile violates both the Katz test and the trespass test.198) Jones, however, actually creates a new trespass test, one that incorporates an unduly restrictive, Katz-era definition of “seizure”. Whereas Silverman reasoned that any conversion of property is a seizure, Justice Alito’s Jones concurrence asserted, and the majority agreed, that a seizure of property “occurs, not when there is a trespass, but ‘when there is some meaningful interference with an individual’s possessory interest in

194 Id. at 1417. 195 Id. at 1419, 1420 (Kagan, J., concurring) (brackets omitted). 196 Jones v. United States, 132 S. Ct. 945, 952 (2012). The Court attempted to

revive the trespass test once before in a unanimous decision by Justice White, then the only remaining member of the Katz Court. See Soldal v. Cook County, 506 U.S. 56, 62 (1992) (“[O]ur cases unmistakably hold that the Amendment protects property as well as privacy.”). Soldal had little impact. See Bascuas, supra note 35, at 736–37 & n.110; see also Minnesota v. Carter, 525 U.S. 83, 97–98 (1998) (Scalia, J., concurring).

197 Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 955–56 (Sotomayor, J., concurring); id. at 964 (Alito, J., concurring).

198 Id. at 955, 957 (Sotomayor, J., concurring).

Page 79: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

519 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

urinalysis testing for drugs on the bizarre rationale that players see each other nude: “School sports are not for the bashful. They require ‘suiting up’ before each practice or event, and showering and changing afterwards. Public school locker rooms, the usual sites for these activities, are not notable for the privacy they afford.”189 Putting aside the fact that many athletes are bashful, even the most uninhibited exhibitionist is entitled to be free from suspicionless seizures and searches of his bodily fluids. The Court made this clear in a pre-Katz case involving forced blood testing of a man suspected of driving drunk: “Such testing procedures plainly constitute searches of ‘persons,’ and depend antecedently upon seizures of ‘persons,’ within the meaning of [the Fourth] Amendment.”190 More recently, the Court held that police can, at least in some circumstances, strip search anyone arrested for anything, indicating that Kyllo’s protection is not very far-reaching.191 It is hard to find merit in a jurisprudence that considers the timing of showers “intimate” information but countenances compelling schoolchildren to urinate for their teachers and misdemeanants to be strip searched. Jardines v. Florida192 further illustrates that neither Katz nor Kyllo’s specific application of it offers any significant analytical benefit. That case pitted Kyllo’s holding that all information about what happens inside a home is constitutionally protected against Place’s holding that whether someone possesses illegal drugs never is. Police officers confirmed that marijuana was being cultivated inside a home by walking a drug-sniffing dog up to the front door. Justice Scalia’s majority opinion held that the officers unconstitutionally searched the house because “they gathered that information by physically entering and occupying [a constitutionally protected] area to engage in conduct not explicitly or implicitly permitted by the homeowner.”193 The Court noted, “One virtue

189 Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v. Acton, 515 U.S. 646, 657 (1995). 190 Schmerber v. United States, 384 U.S. 757, 767 (1966). 191 Florence v. Bd. of Chosen Freeholders of Burlington, 132 S. Ct. 1510 (2012);

see also Hudson v. Michigan, 547 U.S. 586, 597 (2006) (stating that knock-and-announce rule protects “the right not to be intruded upon in one’s nightclothes”).

192 133 S. Ct. 1409 (2013). 193 Id. at 1414.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 520

of the Fourth Amendment’s property-rights baseline is that it keeps easy cases easy.”194 Justice Kagan’s concurrence, joined by Justices Ginsburg and Sotomayor, reached the same conclusion using Katz’s expectations-of-privacy rubric. The concurrence believed that the case was “already resolved” by Kyllo, “suggesting that a focus on Jardines’ privacy interests would make an ‘easy case easy’ twice over . . . .”195 Jones v. United States, decided the year before Jardines, acknowledged that Katz is a failed experiment that should never have been allowed to escape the laboratory, but it did not repudiate its unworkable test. All nine justices agreed on the outcome in Jones, but the majority gratuitously purported to resuscitate what it called the “common-law trespassory test,” suggesting some fundamental dissatisfaction with Katz.196 Nonetheless, Justice Scalia’s majority opinion agreed with the concurrences that expectations of privacy remain important to Fourth Amendment jurisprudence. (Four justices disputed that any trespass test survived Katz and would have relied exclusively on Katz.197 Justice Sonia Sotomayor’s separate concurrence intimated that she believed the GPS tracking of an automobile violates both the Katz test and the trespass test.198) Jones, however, actually creates a new trespass test, one that incorporates an unduly restrictive, Katz-era definition of “seizure”. Whereas Silverman reasoned that any conversion of property is a seizure, Justice Alito’s Jones concurrence asserted, and the majority agreed, that a seizure of property “occurs, not when there is a trespass, but ‘when there is some meaningful interference with an individual’s possessory interest in

194 Id. at 1417. 195 Id. at 1419, 1420 (Kagan, J., concurring) (brackets omitted). 196 Jones v. United States, 132 S. Ct. 945, 952 (2012). The Court attempted to

revive the trespass test once before in a unanimous decision by Justice White, then the only remaining member of the Katz Court. See Soldal v. Cook County, 506 U.S. 56, 62 (1992) (“[O]ur cases unmistakably hold that the Amendment protects property as well as privacy.”). Soldal had little impact. See Bascuas, supra note 35, at 736–37 & n.110; see also Minnesota v. Carter, 525 U.S. 83, 97–98 (1998) (Scalia, J., concurring).

197 Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 955–56 (Sotomayor, J., concurring); id. at 964 (Alito, J., concurring).

198 Id. at 955, 957 (Sotomayor, J., concurring).

Page 80: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

521 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

that property.’”199 By this, the Court apparently meant that, as long as Antoine Jones’ Jeep functioned, it was not seized. The majority instead concluded that attaching the GPS to the Jeep was an unconstitutional search because “[t]he Government physically occupied private property for the purpose of obtaining information.”200 The Jones Court’s cabined definition of “seizure” was concocted in 1984’s United States v. Jacobsen201 and is inconsistent with the pre-Katz trespass test that Jones purports to apply. Under Silverman, property is seized regardless of whether its owner’s enjoyment of it is at all impeded; any conversion of private property to the government’s own use suffices because what the owner is entitled to is exclusive use. The spike mike used in Silverman made contact with a pipe, “usurping part of the petitioners’ house or office—a heating system which was an integral part of the premises occupied by the petitioners … .”202 The heating system presumably worked just as before, a fact the Court gave no attention. Yet, on the basis of mere contact with a pipe the Court distinguished Goldman v. United States,203 a 1942 case that affirmed Olmstead’s trespass test in which agents used a listening device that did not touch the target’s property.204 While the opinion might be more clear on the point, Silverman’s emphasis on the government’s “usurpation” or conversion of the heating system is more naturally characterized as a seizure of that system than as a search of the house.205

199 Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 951 n.5 (quoting id. at 958 (Alito, J., concurring)). To

carry the Coke analogy forward, this adulterating definition of seizure is the high fructose corn syrup in the Jones mix.

200 Id. at 949 (majority opinion). 201 466 U.S. 109, 113 (1984). 202 Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 511 (1961). 203 316 U.S. 129 (1942). 204 Silverman, 365 U.S. at 512. 205 Justice Douglas’ concurrence indirectly supports this reading of the case.

Anticipating Katz’s approach, he would have characterized the invasions of privacy in both Silverman and Goldman as Fourth Amendment searches because “the invasion of privacy is as great in one case as in the other.” Id. at 512 (Douglas, J., concurring). But, given that the Court’s view at the time was that the amendment protected property, the majority opted for a different approach, presumably one that entailed characterizing the

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 522

Claiming that “the concept of a ‘seizure’ of property is not much discussed in our cases,” Jacobsen adapted language the Court had used to determine whether a person was seized—whether there was meaningful interference with his freedom of movement—to invent its new definition.206 None of the cases it cited as direct authority for this definition applied it. The only pre-Katz case, dated to 1906, dealt with a challenge to a subpoena to produce corporate documents, and referred to a seizure as ordinarily “contemplat[ing] a forcible dispossession of the owner” in passing.207 Any doubt that this definition of seizure substantially departed from Silverman is dispelled by Justice Stevens’ opinion in United States v. Karo, a case decided just three months after Jacobsen. Relying on Silverman, the author of the Jacobsen majority clarified that any conversion of property to the government’s use satisfies the “meaningful interference” criterion. Joined by Justices Brennan and Marshall, Justice Stevens argued that the government’s placing a tracking device inside a container owned by the defendant was a Fourth Amendment seizure because it deprived the owner of exclusive use of his property:

The attachment of the beeper, in my judgment, constituted a “seizure.” The owner of property, of course, has a right to exclude from it all the world, including the Government, and a concomitant right to use it exclusively for his own purposes. When the Government attaches an electronic monitoring device to that property, it infringes that exclusionary right; in a fundamental sense it has converted the property to its own use. Surely such an invasion is an “interference” with possessory rights; the right to exclude, which attached as soon as the can respondents purchased was delivered, had been infringed. That interference is also “meaningful”; the character of the property is profoundly

invasions more naturally as a seizure of the heating system.

206 Jacobsen, 466 U.S. at 113 n.5. 207 Hale v. Henkel, 201 U.S. 43, 76 (1906).

Page 81: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

521 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

that property.’”199 By this, the Court apparently meant that, as long as Antoine Jones’ Jeep functioned, it was not seized. The majority instead concluded that attaching the GPS to the Jeep was an unconstitutional search because “[t]he Government physically occupied private property for the purpose of obtaining information.”200 The Jones Court’s cabined definition of “seizure” was concocted in 1984’s United States v. Jacobsen201 and is inconsistent with the pre-Katz trespass test that Jones purports to apply. Under Silverman, property is seized regardless of whether its owner’s enjoyment of it is at all impeded; any conversion of private property to the government’s own use suffices because what the owner is entitled to is exclusive use. The spike mike used in Silverman made contact with a pipe, “usurping part of the petitioners’ house or office—a heating system which was an integral part of the premises occupied by the petitioners … .”202 The heating system presumably worked just as before, a fact the Court gave no attention. Yet, on the basis of mere contact with a pipe the Court distinguished Goldman v. United States,203 a 1942 case that affirmed Olmstead’s trespass test in which agents used a listening device that did not touch the target’s property.204 While the opinion might be more clear on the point, Silverman’s emphasis on the government’s “usurpation” or conversion of the heating system is more naturally characterized as a seizure of that system than as a search of the house.205

199 Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 951 n.5 (quoting id. at 958 (Alito, J., concurring)). To

carry the Coke analogy forward, this adulterating definition of seizure is the high fructose corn syrup in the Jones mix.

200 Id. at 949 (majority opinion). 201 466 U.S. 109, 113 (1984). 202 Silverman v. United States, 365 U.S. 505, 511 (1961). 203 316 U.S. 129 (1942). 204 Silverman, 365 U.S. at 512. 205 Justice Douglas’ concurrence indirectly supports this reading of the case.

Anticipating Katz’s approach, he would have characterized the invasions of privacy in both Silverman and Goldman as Fourth Amendment searches because “the invasion of privacy is as great in one case as in the other.” Id. at 512 (Douglas, J., concurring). But, given that the Court’s view at the time was that the amendment protected property, the majority opted for a different approach, presumably one that entailed characterizing the

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 522

Claiming that “the concept of a ‘seizure’ of property is not much discussed in our cases,” Jacobsen adapted language the Court had used to determine whether a person was seized—whether there was meaningful interference with his freedom of movement—to invent its new definition.206 None of the cases it cited as direct authority for this definition applied it. The only pre-Katz case, dated to 1906, dealt with a challenge to a subpoena to produce corporate documents, and referred to a seizure as ordinarily “contemplat[ing] a forcible dispossession of the owner” in passing.207 Any doubt that this definition of seizure substantially departed from Silverman is dispelled by Justice Stevens’ opinion in United States v. Karo, a case decided just three months after Jacobsen. Relying on Silverman, the author of the Jacobsen majority clarified that any conversion of property to the government’s use satisfies the “meaningful interference” criterion. Joined by Justices Brennan and Marshall, Justice Stevens argued that the government’s placing a tracking device inside a container owned by the defendant was a Fourth Amendment seizure because it deprived the owner of exclusive use of his property:

The attachment of the beeper, in my judgment, constituted a “seizure.” The owner of property, of course, has a right to exclude from it all the world, including the Government, and a concomitant right to use it exclusively for his own purposes. When the Government attaches an electronic monitoring device to that property, it infringes that exclusionary right; in a fundamental sense it has converted the property to its own use. Surely such an invasion is an “interference” with possessory rights; the right to exclude, which attached as soon as the can respondents purchased was delivered, had been infringed. That interference is also “meaningful”; the character of the property is profoundly

invasions more naturally as a seizure of the heating system.

206 Jacobsen, 466 U.S. at 113 n.5. 207 Hale v. Henkel, 201 U.S. 43, 76 (1906).

Page 82: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

523 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

different when infected with an electronic bug than when it is entirely germ free.208

Antoine Jones relied on the quoted passage from Justice Stevens’ Karo opinion to argue that attachment of the GPS tracking device was a seizure of his Jeep.209 Had anyone anticipated that the Court would decide the case using a trespass test, Mr. Jones might have argued that requiring a showing of “meaningful interference” makes no sense in a world where the Fourth Amendment is understood to protect property rather than (or in addition to) privacy. Instead, the parties naturally accepted that Jacobsen redefined “seizure” to account for Katz’s abandonment of property law in Fourth Amendment adjudication. Thus, the government responded to Mr. Jones’ contention by explaining that the Karo Court rejected Justice Stevens’ reasoning on the ground “that placing the beeper in the can amounted at most to a technical trespass, which was only ‘marginally relevant’ to the Fourth Amendment inquiry. The same is true here.”210 Of course, once the Court decided that a trespass was (once again) an event of constitutional significance, the government’s concession that installing a GPS device was a “technical” trespass should have been dispositive. Karo assumed trespasses were only marginally relevant to the Fourth Amendment analysis because at the time a trespass merely informed the expectations-of-privacy inquiry. As soon as Jones held that trespasses were independently significant, the government’s own logic should have lead inexorably to the conclusion that it had seized Mr. Jones’ Jeep. The Court did not mention Mr. Jones’ seizure argument, much less explain why it was wrong. This is odd as it puts a tremendous strain on the language to call what happened to Mr. Jones a “search”. It is not at all clear what “the place to be searched” 211 was in this case. Attaching the tracking device to the Jeep did not “search” it in the sense of revealing

208 Karo, 468 U.S. at 729 (1984) (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).

209 Brief for Respondent at 45–52, United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945 (2012) (No. 10-1259).

210 Reply Brief for the United States at 18, Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945 (No. 10-1259). 211 U.S. CONST. amend. IV.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 524

what was inside it. If anything was searched, it was the metropolitan area around Washington, D.C., throughout which the government tracked the Jeep’s movements. It makes much more sense to say the Jeep was seized, in the sense that the government “usurped” or converted the Jeep to its own use.212 In other words, because the government interfered with Mr. Jones’ exclusive use of the Jeep, it seized it.213 This linguistic contortion has one obvious effect. It preserves the results in cases like Miller, Jacobsen, and Place that withdrew constitutional protection from personal records and contraband.214 The holdings in those cases depended on the assumption that the seizure test of Wong Sun, Silverman, and Berger did not survive Katz. Jones’ new trespass test provides a way to preserve the outcomes in these decisions. Jacobsen’s “meaningful interference” requirement has no basis in a jurisprudence that purports to be solicitous of property rights. A trespass has never required a showing of harmful effect, and that is demonstrably true of the trespasses that concerned the framers of the Fourth Amendment. Entick v. Carrington, an eighteenth-century English case universally agreed to be among the primary inspirations for the Fourth Amendment,215 firmly declared that government agents must respect property rights to the same degree as private actors:

212 Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 949 n.2 (noting that Mr. Jones’ wife was the registered

owner of the Jeep, a fact to which the Court attached no consequence because, as an authorized user, he effectively had the rights of an owner).

213 Common understanding regarding the extent of property rights is relevant to understanding the scope of those rights. See O. W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 477 (1897).

214 In Miller, that would entail conceiving of the bank records as information that, like a conversation, is capable of being seized. In Place, even the most fleeting seizure of luggage for a dog to sniff it would be a seizure. In Jacobsen, the federal agents’ handling of a package entrusted to Federal Express for delivery would likewise be a seizure. The “meaningful interference” concept allows courts to avoid what some might view as undesirable implications of a property-based Fourth Amendment.

215 See JED RUBENFELD, REVOLUTION BY JUDICIARY 32 (2005); TELFORD TAYLOR, TWO STUDIES IN CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION 29–38 (1969); Akhil Reed Amar, Fourth Amendment First Principles, 107 HARV. L. REV. 757, 772–75 (1994); Anthony G. Amsterdam, Perspectives on the Fourth Amendment, 58 MINN. L. REV. 349, 411-12 (1974); Thomas K. Clancy, The Fourth Amendment’s Concept of

Page 83: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

523 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

different when infected with an electronic bug than when it is entirely germ free.208

Antoine Jones relied on the quoted passage from Justice Stevens’ Karo opinion to argue that attachment of the GPS tracking device was a seizure of his Jeep.209 Had anyone anticipated that the Court would decide the case using a trespass test, Mr. Jones might have argued that requiring a showing of “meaningful interference” makes no sense in a world where the Fourth Amendment is understood to protect property rather than (or in addition to) privacy. Instead, the parties naturally accepted that Jacobsen redefined “seizure” to account for Katz’s abandonment of property law in Fourth Amendment adjudication. Thus, the government responded to Mr. Jones’ contention by explaining that the Karo Court rejected Justice Stevens’ reasoning on the ground “that placing the beeper in the can amounted at most to a technical trespass, which was only ‘marginally relevant’ to the Fourth Amendment inquiry. The same is true here.”210 Of course, once the Court decided that a trespass was (once again) an event of constitutional significance, the government’s concession that installing a GPS device was a “technical” trespass should have been dispositive. Karo assumed trespasses were only marginally relevant to the Fourth Amendment analysis because at the time a trespass merely informed the expectations-of-privacy inquiry. As soon as Jones held that trespasses were independently significant, the government’s own logic should have lead inexorably to the conclusion that it had seized Mr. Jones’ Jeep. The Court did not mention Mr. Jones’ seizure argument, much less explain why it was wrong. This is odd as it puts a tremendous strain on the language to call what happened to Mr. Jones a “search”. It is not at all clear what “the place to be searched” 211 was in this case. Attaching the tracking device to the Jeep did not “search” it in the sense of revealing

208 Karo, 468 U.S. at 729 (1984) (Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).

209 Brief for Respondent at 45–52, United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945 (2012) (No. 10-1259).

210 Reply Brief for the United States at 18, Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945 (No. 10-1259). 211 U.S. CONST. amend. IV.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 524

what was inside it. If anything was searched, it was the metropolitan area around Washington, D.C., throughout which the government tracked the Jeep’s movements. It makes much more sense to say the Jeep was seized, in the sense that the government “usurped” or converted the Jeep to its own use.212 In other words, because the government interfered with Mr. Jones’ exclusive use of the Jeep, it seized it.213 This linguistic contortion has one obvious effect. It preserves the results in cases like Miller, Jacobsen, and Place that withdrew constitutional protection from personal records and contraband.214 The holdings in those cases depended on the assumption that the seizure test of Wong Sun, Silverman, and Berger did not survive Katz. Jones’ new trespass test provides a way to preserve the outcomes in these decisions. Jacobsen’s “meaningful interference” requirement has no basis in a jurisprudence that purports to be solicitous of property rights. A trespass has never required a showing of harmful effect, and that is demonstrably true of the trespasses that concerned the framers of the Fourth Amendment. Entick v. Carrington, an eighteenth-century English case universally agreed to be among the primary inspirations for the Fourth Amendment,215 firmly declared that government agents must respect property rights to the same degree as private actors:

212 Jones, 132 S. Ct. at 949 n.2 (noting that Mr. Jones’ wife was the registered

owner of the Jeep, a fact to which the Court attached no consequence because, as an authorized user, he effectively had the rights of an owner).

213 Common understanding regarding the extent of property rights is relevant to understanding the scope of those rights. See O. W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 477 (1897).

214 In Miller, that would entail conceiving of the bank records as information that, like a conversation, is capable of being seized. In Place, even the most fleeting seizure of luggage for a dog to sniff it would be a seizure. In Jacobsen, the federal agents’ handling of a package entrusted to Federal Express for delivery would likewise be a seizure. The “meaningful interference” concept allows courts to avoid what some might view as undesirable implications of a property-based Fourth Amendment.

215 See JED RUBENFELD, REVOLUTION BY JUDICIARY 32 (2005); TELFORD TAYLOR, TWO STUDIES IN CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION 29–38 (1969); Akhil Reed Amar, Fourth Amendment First Principles, 107 HARV. L. REV. 757, 772–75 (1994); Anthony G. Amsterdam, Perspectives on the Fourth Amendment, 58 MINN. L. REV. 349, 411-12 (1974); Thomas K. Clancy, The Fourth Amendment’s Concept of

Page 84: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

525 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

No man can set his foot upon my ground without my license, but he is liable to an action, though the damage be nothing; which is proved by every declaration in trespass, where the defendant is called upon to answer for bruising the grass and even treading upon the soil.216

This explains why, for example, Justice Scalia or Justice Alito would be irked to find his car scratched, dinged, or otherwise minutely vandalized and would not be much consoled by the car being just as functional as before. Indeed, one might well be angered if someone else so much as spit on his car. Having property means being able to exclude all other people from it, even to the point of irrationality. “Liberty is more than the right to do what the majority wants, or to do what is ‘reasonable.’ Liberty is the right to defy the majority, and to do what is unreasonable.”217 Requiring a showing of harm before an unjustified government intrusion is legally condemned is like arguing that only people who have something to hide should complain about pervasive government surveillance. This thinking encourages the proliferation of suspicionless, general searches for contraband—precisely the sort of searches that animated the Fourth Amendment in the first place. Before Katz, Silverman made clear that any unauthorized “usurpation” of a person’s property by the government—even if it did not affect the use of that property at all—violated the Fourth Amendment. Schmerber v. United States concomitantly held that taking a person’s bodily fluids for testing entailed both a seizure and a search of that person.218 After Katz, the Court held that forcing students to produce urine for drug testing, requiring travelers to surrender their luggage to be sniffed by a dog, and stopping drivers to conduct random searches were all constitutional without any

Reasonableness, 2004 UTAH L. REV. 977, 982-87 (2004); Thomas Y. Davies, Recovering the Original Fourth Amendment, 98 MICH. L. REV. 547, 603–07 (1999); William J. Stuntz, The Substantive Origins of Criminal Procedure, 105 YALE L.J. 393, 396–97 (1995).

216 Entick v. Carrington, (1765) 19 Howell’s State Trials 1029 (K.B.). 217 Reich, supra note 42. 218 Schmerber v. California, 384 U.S. 757, 767 (1966).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 526

particularized suspicion.219 “In none of these cases did the courts attempt to assign any weight to the value of unfettered exercise of constitutional rights.”220 This is why the Fourth Amendment makes no sense unless it is understood to protect all forms of property, including informational property and contraband. Property is what creates space for dissenting from controversial regulations—ranging from those suppressing political activities to those enacting temperance crimes:

Property draws a circle around the activities of each private individual or organization. Within that circle, the owner has a greater degree of freedom than without. Outside, he must justify or explain his actions, and show his authority. Within, he is master, and the state must explain and justify any interference. . . . Thus, property performs the function of maintaining independence, dignity and pluralism in society by creating zones within which the majority has to yield to the owner. Whim, caprice, irrationality and “antisocial” activities are given the protection of law; the owner may do what all or most of his neighbors decry.221

Katz put many activities that had been within the circle of property’s protection outside of it. Characterizing the attachment of a GPS device to Mr. Jones’ Jeep as a search rather than a seizure makes a difference in cases involving government surveillance of documents or other data created by an

219 See Bd. of Educ. v. Earls, 536 U.S. 822 (2002); Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v.

Acton, 515 U.S. 646 (1995); United States v. Place, 462 U.S. 696, 706 (1983) (holding that “some brief detentions of personal effects” are constitutional without probable cause); United States v. Martinez-Fuerte, 428 U.S. 543 (1976); Mich. Dep’t. of State Police v. Sitz, 496 U.S. 444 (1990); Texas v. Brown, 460 U.S 730, 739 (1983) (plurality opinion) (stating that “routine” driver’s license checkpoints are constitutional); Delaware v. Prouse, 440 U.S. 648, 654–55, 663 (1979) (suggesting that random driver’s license checkpoints would be constitutional under the Katz balancing test).

220 Reich, supra note 42 at 776. 221 Id. at 771.

Page 85: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

525 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

No man can set his foot upon my ground without my license, but he is liable to an action, though the damage be nothing; which is proved by every declaration in trespass, where the defendant is called upon to answer for bruising the grass and even treading upon the soil.216

This explains why, for example, Justice Scalia or Justice Alito would be irked to find his car scratched, dinged, or otherwise minutely vandalized and would not be much consoled by the car being just as functional as before. Indeed, one might well be angered if someone else so much as spit on his car. Having property means being able to exclude all other people from it, even to the point of irrationality. “Liberty is more than the right to do what the majority wants, or to do what is ‘reasonable.’ Liberty is the right to defy the majority, and to do what is unreasonable.”217 Requiring a showing of harm before an unjustified government intrusion is legally condemned is like arguing that only people who have something to hide should complain about pervasive government surveillance. This thinking encourages the proliferation of suspicionless, general searches for contraband—precisely the sort of searches that animated the Fourth Amendment in the first place. Before Katz, Silverman made clear that any unauthorized “usurpation” of a person’s property by the government—even if it did not affect the use of that property at all—violated the Fourth Amendment. Schmerber v. United States concomitantly held that taking a person’s bodily fluids for testing entailed both a seizure and a search of that person.218 After Katz, the Court held that forcing students to produce urine for drug testing, requiring travelers to surrender their luggage to be sniffed by a dog, and stopping drivers to conduct random searches were all constitutional without any

Reasonableness, 2004 UTAH L. REV. 977, 982-87 (2004); Thomas Y. Davies, Recovering the Original Fourth Amendment, 98 MICH. L. REV. 547, 603–07 (1999); William J. Stuntz, The Substantive Origins of Criminal Procedure, 105 YALE L.J. 393, 396–97 (1995).

216 Entick v. Carrington, (1765) 19 Howell’s State Trials 1029 (K.B.). 217 Reich, supra note 42. 218 Schmerber v. California, 384 U.S. 757, 767 (1966).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 526

particularized suspicion.219 “In none of these cases did the courts attempt to assign any weight to the value of unfettered exercise of constitutional rights.”220 This is why the Fourth Amendment makes no sense unless it is understood to protect all forms of property, including informational property and contraband. Property is what creates space for dissenting from controversial regulations—ranging from those suppressing political activities to those enacting temperance crimes:

Property draws a circle around the activities of each private individual or organization. Within that circle, the owner has a greater degree of freedom than without. Outside, he must justify or explain his actions, and show his authority. Within, he is master, and the state must explain and justify any interference. . . . Thus, property performs the function of maintaining independence, dignity and pluralism in society by creating zones within which the majority has to yield to the owner. Whim, caprice, irrationality and “antisocial” activities are given the protection of law; the owner may do what all or most of his neighbors decry.221

Katz put many activities that had been within the circle of property’s protection outside of it. Characterizing the attachment of a GPS device to Mr. Jones’ Jeep as a search rather than a seizure makes a difference in cases involving government surveillance of documents or other data created by an

219 See Bd. of Educ. v. Earls, 536 U.S. 822 (2002); Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v.

Acton, 515 U.S. 646 (1995); United States v. Place, 462 U.S. 696, 706 (1983) (holding that “some brief detentions of personal effects” are constitutional without probable cause); United States v. Martinez-Fuerte, 428 U.S. 543 (1976); Mich. Dep’t. of State Police v. Sitz, 496 U.S. 444 (1990); Texas v. Brown, 460 U.S 730, 739 (1983) (plurality opinion) (stating that “routine” driver’s license checkpoints are constitutional); Delaware v. Prouse, 440 U.S. 648, 654–55, 663 (1979) (suggesting that random driver’s license checkpoints would be constitutional under the Katz balancing test).

220 Reich, supra note 42 at 776. 221 Id. at 771.

Page 86: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

527 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

individual. This potentially means that emails and other documents stored on remote computers are open to government copying and inspection without restriction. Even if the information is deemed to be the author’s property, there is no meaningful interference with it if the government merely copies it. And, because the information resides on a server that does not belong to the author, the author has no standing to complain about it.222 Thus, the “meaningful interference” requirement works to curtail the protection extended to intangible forms of property that could plausibly be said to be owned by an individual targeted by the government. The view that a seizure requires “meaningful interference”, for example, leaves the federal, state, and local governments free to continue tracking people by obtaining location data from mobile telephone carriers. By the time Jones was decided, cellular telephone tracking without judicial oversight was already widespread, involving thousands of demands for data per day, and rapidly growing even more commonplace.223 In her concurrence, Justice Sotomayor agreed that Jones did not necessarily say anything about tracking people through their own electronic devices. “Owners of GPS-equipped cars and smartphones do not contemplate that these devices will be used to enable covert surveillance of their movements.”224 Even while endorsing the Katz test, she asked whether Miller and Smith should be reconsidered to handle the challenges to privacy posed by a digitalized world necessitating the constant sharing of personal information.225 Justice Sotomayor’s notion that this problem can be worked out within the Katz framework is simply question begging. If the privacy-equals-secrecy holdings of Miller and

222 Compare Silverthorne Lumber Co. v. United States, 251 U.S. 385, 391–92

(1920) (holding that government could not make use of copies of documents unconstitutionally seized from defendant’s office).

223 See Eric Lichtblau, Cell Carriers Called on More in Surveillence, N.Y. TIMES, July 9, 2012, at A1, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2012/07/09/us/cell-carriers-see-uptick-in-requests-to-aid-surveillance.html?pagewanted=all; Lichtblau, supra note 14.

224 United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945, 956 (2012) (Sotomayor, J., concurring).

225 Id. at 956.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 528

Smith were overruled, the Katz test would require some other definition of privacy, and Justice Sotomayor proposed none. She disagreed with Justice Alito’s claim that societal expectations of privacy erode as information becomes more public, but offered no criteria for distinguishing disclosures that vitiate privacy from those that do not. Recognizing that the Fourth Amendment protects informational property from unjustified seizure even if there is no further “meaningful interference” with it solves the problem. Cellular data tracking is not the only government tool to render the Jones holding obsolete no sooner than it was handed down. Cameras deployed throughout the country by state and municipal police scan license plates at the rate of dozens per second to track the movements of millions of people.226 They are fixed on roadways and attached to police cruisers.227 It is hard to argue with the idea “that a motorist has no reasonable expectation of privacy in the information contained on his license plate . . . .”228 Consequently, the Katz framework forces those concerned about such pervasive tracking techniques to argue that the government’s use of computers to agglomerate and manipulate data implicates the Fourth Amendment.229 (Jones echoes this argument in its concern over the accumulation of GPS data.) Saying that the government violates the Fourth Amendment by accessing data it lawfully collected stretches the notion of “search” further than seems plausible. The problem, if there is one, must inhere in how the data is collected.

IV. PRAGMATIC PROPERTY IN THE INFORMATION AGE

The trespass test the Court had developed and reaffirmed in the

term before Katz is more faithful to the Fourth Amendment’s aims and

226 Cyrus Farivar, Your Car, Tracked: The Rapid Rise of License Plate Readers,

ARS TECHNICA (Aug. 15, 2012), http://arstechnica.com/tech-policy/2012/09/your-car-tracked-the-rapid-rise-of-license-plate-readers.

227 Id. 228 United States v. Ellison, 462 F.3d 557, 561–63 (6th Cir. 2006) (collecting

cases). 229 See, e.g., id. at 567–68 (Moore, J., dissenting).

Page 87: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

527 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

individual. This potentially means that emails and other documents stored on remote computers are open to government copying and inspection without restriction. Even if the information is deemed to be the author’s property, there is no meaningful interference with it if the government merely copies it. And, because the information resides on a server that does not belong to the author, the author has no standing to complain about it.222 Thus, the “meaningful interference” requirement works to curtail the protection extended to intangible forms of property that could plausibly be said to be owned by an individual targeted by the government. The view that a seizure requires “meaningful interference”, for example, leaves the federal, state, and local governments free to continue tracking people by obtaining location data from mobile telephone carriers. By the time Jones was decided, cellular telephone tracking without judicial oversight was already widespread, involving thousands of demands for data per day, and rapidly growing even more commonplace.223 In her concurrence, Justice Sotomayor agreed that Jones did not necessarily say anything about tracking people through their own electronic devices. “Owners of GPS-equipped cars and smartphones do not contemplate that these devices will be used to enable covert surveillance of their movements.”224 Even while endorsing the Katz test, she asked whether Miller and Smith should be reconsidered to handle the challenges to privacy posed by a digitalized world necessitating the constant sharing of personal information.225 Justice Sotomayor’s notion that this problem can be worked out within the Katz framework is simply question begging. If the privacy-equals-secrecy holdings of Miller and

222 Compare Silverthorne Lumber Co. v. United States, 251 U.S. 385, 391–92

(1920) (holding that government could not make use of copies of documents unconstitutionally seized from defendant’s office).

223 See Eric Lichtblau, Cell Carriers Called on More in Surveillence, N.Y. TIMES, July 9, 2012, at A1, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2012/07/09/us/cell-carriers-see-uptick-in-requests-to-aid-surveillance.html?pagewanted=all; Lichtblau, supra note 14.

224 United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945, 956 (2012) (Sotomayor, J., concurring).

225 Id. at 956.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 528

Smith were overruled, the Katz test would require some other definition of privacy, and Justice Sotomayor proposed none. She disagreed with Justice Alito’s claim that societal expectations of privacy erode as information becomes more public, but offered no criteria for distinguishing disclosures that vitiate privacy from those that do not. Recognizing that the Fourth Amendment protects informational property from unjustified seizure even if there is no further “meaningful interference” with it solves the problem. Cellular data tracking is not the only government tool to render the Jones holding obsolete no sooner than it was handed down. Cameras deployed throughout the country by state and municipal police scan license plates at the rate of dozens per second to track the movements of millions of people.226 They are fixed on roadways and attached to police cruisers.227 It is hard to argue with the idea “that a motorist has no reasonable expectation of privacy in the information contained on his license plate . . . .”228 Consequently, the Katz framework forces those concerned about such pervasive tracking techniques to argue that the government’s use of computers to agglomerate and manipulate data implicates the Fourth Amendment.229 (Jones echoes this argument in its concern over the accumulation of GPS data.) Saying that the government violates the Fourth Amendment by accessing data it lawfully collected stretches the notion of “search” further than seems plausible. The problem, if there is one, must inhere in how the data is collected.

IV. PRAGMATIC PROPERTY IN THE INFORMATION AGE

The trespass test the Court had developed and reaffirmed in the

term before Katz is more faithful to the Fourth Amendment’s aims and

226 Cyrus Farivar, Your Car, Tracked: The Rapid Rise of License Plate Readers,

ARS TECHNICA (Aug. 15, 2012), http://arstechnica.com/tech-policy/2012/09/your-car-tracked-the-rapid-rise-of-license-plate-readers.

227 Id. 228 United States v. Ellison, 462 F.3d 557, 561–63 (6th Cir. 2006) (collecting

cases). 229 See, e.g., id. at 567–68 (Moore, J., dissenting).

Page 88: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

529 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

would have averted, had it endured, many of the difficulties that Katz introduced into the law. It recognized that a trespass or conversion is complete despite there being no interference with an owner’s use; that property can be tangible or intangible; that sharing property does not vitiate an owner’s ability to preclude government inspection; and that a strong government interest does not make an unjustified intrusion any less of a trespass. Adopting this test today would resolve the shortcomings that Jones’ weaker trespass test perpetuates, but doing so might well mean that the government cannot without suspicion have dogs sniff luggage230 or cars231 for drugs; force adolescents to produce urine for testing;232 or stop cars on the highway without individualized suspicion.233 The Katz framework sanctions such invasions of privacy only because, by trivializing the property interests involved, it subjugates unprivileged individuals into ritual compliance with a false notion of the public interest. “High-status people do not undergo drug testing. Lawyers, professors, executives, judges, and other members of the professional and administrative class are exempt from this calculated humiliation.”234 Predicating the Fourth Amendment’s protection on a pragmatic understanding of property leads to more equal treatment. The Supreme Court already enforces, as a matter of federal common law, an understanding of property consistent with Silverman and Berger in mail and wire fraud prosecutions, which generally require proof of intent to deprive235 the victim of property.236 When interpreting federal

230 United States v. Place, 462 U.S. 696 (1983). 231 Illinois v. Caballes, 543 U.S. 405 (2005). 232 See Bd. of Educ. v. Earls, 536 U.S. 822 (2002); Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v.

Acton, 515 U.S. 646 (1995). 233 See Illinois v. Lidster, 540 U.S. 419 (2004); Mich. Dep’t of State Police v.

Sitz, 496 U.S. 444 (1990); United States v. Martinez-Fuerte, 428 U.S. 543 (1976). 234 Reich, supra note 104, at 1425. 235 This common formulation of fraud (or any form of theft) is linguistically

rooted in a different type of “privacy” than Katz. To deprive means to de-privatize in the sense of stripping the owner’s exclusivity of use.

236 For present purposes, honest-services fraud can be set aside. See Cleveland v. United States, 531 U.S. 12, 18–20 (2000) (every fraud charge must specify whether the object was a property-deprivation fraud or an honest-services-deprivation fraud; thus the

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 530

fraud statutes, the Court has had no difficulty recognizing deprivations of property interests—despite arguments that there was no meaningful interference, that the assets were merely intangible, and that the victim had shared the information. The result is a coherent, logical, flexible understanding of property that could readily be used in Fourth Amendment cases, obviating any need to ever discuss privacy expectations again. In 1987, the Court unanimously rejected in Carpenter v. United States two fraud defendants’ claims that their convictions were invalid because their actions did not interfere with the victim’s use of the property they allegedly stole.237 A Wall Street Journal reporter who co-wrote “Heard on the Street,” a column reviewing stocks, partnered with some stockbrokers to trade on information to be printed in the column.238 It did not matter that the Journal was able to use the information exactly as it would have in the absence of any scheme. In fact, the success of the scheme depended on the Journal’s doing so. If the Journal did not proceed to publish the information, the defendants would not have profited from their investments. In Jones, Justice Alito used that rationale to conclude there was no seizure, reasoning that the government’s surveillance technique depended on Mr. Jones being able to use the Jeep notwithstanding the tracking device.239 But the Carpenter Court rejected it. What mattered was that the defendants did something with the Journal’s property that the Journal did not authorize: “[I]t is sufficient that the Journal has been deprived of its right to exclusive use of the information, for exclusivity is an important aspect of confidential business information and most private property for that matter.”240 In this same

fraud cases elaborating on what constitutes a property interest are unadulterated by the cases discussing a deprivation of honest services).

237 484 U.S. 19 (1987). 238 Id. at 23. 239 United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945, 958 (2012) (Alito, J., concurring)

(“Indeed, the surveillance technique that the officers employed was dependent on the fact that the GPS did not interfere in any way with the operation of the vehicle, for if any such interference had been detected, the device might have been discovered.”).

240 Carpenter, 484 U.S. at 26–27; see also id. at 26 (“The Journal had a property right in keeping confidential and making exclusive use, prior to publication, of the

Page 89: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

529 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

would have averted, had it endured, many of the difficulties that Katz introduced into the law. It recognized that a trespass or conversion is complete despite there being no interference with an owner’s use; that property can be tangible or intangible; that sharing property does not vitiate an owner’s ability to preclude government inspection; and that a strong government interest does not make an unjustified intrusion any less of a trespass. Adopting this test today would resolve the shortcomings that Jones’ weaker trespass test perpetuates, but doing so might well mean that the government cannot without suspicion have dogs sniff luggage230 or cars231 for drugs; force adolescents to produce urine for testing;232 or stop cars on the highway without individualized suspicion.233 The Katz framework sanctions such invasions of privacy only because, by trivializing the property interests involved, it subjugates unprivileged individuals into ritual compliance with a false notion of the public interest. “High-status people do not undergo drug testing. Lawyers, professors, executives, judges, and other members of the professional and administrative class are exempt from this calculated humiliation.”234 Predicating the Fourth Amendment’s protection on a pragmatic understanding of property leads to more equal treatment. The Supreme Court already enforces, as a matter of federal common law, an understanding of property consistent with Silverman and Berger in mail and wire fraud prosecutions, which generally require proof of intent to deprive235 the victim of property.236 When interpreting federal

230 United States v. Place, 462 U.S. 696 (1983). 231 Illinois v. Caballes, 543 U.S. 405 (2005). 232 See Bd. of Educ. v. Earls, 536 U.S. 822 (2002); Vernonia Sch. Dist. 47J v.

Acton, 515 U.S. 646 (1995). 233 See Illinois v. Lidster, 540 U.S. 419 (2004); Mich. Dep’t of State Police v.

Sitz, 496 U.S. 444 (1990); United States v. Martinez-Fuerte, 428 U.S. 543 (1976). 234 Reich, supra note 104, at 1425. 235 This common formulation of fraud (or any form of theft) is linguistically

rooted in a different type of “privacy” than Katz. To deprive means to de-privatize in the sense of stripping the owner’s exclusivity of use.

236 For present purposes, honest-services fraud can be set aside. See Cleveland v. United States, 531 U.S. 12, 18–20 (2000) (every fraud charge must specify whether the object was a property-deprivation fraud or an honest-services-deprivation fraud; thus the

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 530

fraud statutes, the Court has had no difficulty recognizing deprivations of property interests—despite arguments that there was no meaningful interference, that the assets were merely intangible, and that the victim had shared the information. The result is a coherent, logical, flexible understanding of property that could readily be used in Fourth Amendment cases, obviating any need to ever discuss privacy expectations again. In 1987, the Court unanimously rejected in Carpenter v. United States two fraud defendants’ claims that their convictions were invalid because their actions did not interfere with the victim’s use of the property they allegedly stole.237 A Wall Street Journal reporter who co-wrote “Heard on the Street,” a column reviewing stocks, partnered with some stockbrokers to trade on information to be printed in the column.238 It did not matter that the Journal was able to use the information exactly as it would have in the absence of any scheme. In fact, the success of the scheme depended on the Journal’s doing so. If the Journal did not proceed to publish the information, the defendants would not have profited from their investments. In Jones, Justice Alito used that rationale to conclude there was no seizure, reasoning that the government’s surveillance technique depended on Mr. Jones being able to use the Jeep notwithstanding the tracking device.239 But the Carpenter Court rejected it. What mattered was that the defendants did something with the Journal’s property that the Journal did not authorize: “[I]t is sufficient that the Journal has been deprived of its right to exclusive use of the information, for exclusivity is an important aspect of confidential business information and most private property for that matter.”240 In this same

fraud cases elaborating on what constitutes a property interest are unadulterated by the cases discussing a deprivation of honest services).

237 484 U.S. 19 (1987). 238 Id. at 23. 239 United States v. Jones, 132 S. Ct. 945, 958 (2012) (Alito, J., concurring)

(“Indeed, the surveillance technique that the officers employed was dependent on the fact that the GPS did not interfere in any way with the operation of the vehicle, for if any such interference had been detected, the device might have been discovered.”).

240 Carpenter, 484 U.S. at 26–27; see also id. at 26 (“The Journal had a property right in keeping confidential and making exclusive use, prior to publication, of the

Page 90: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

531 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

way, attaching a tracking device to someone’s property deprives the owner of the exclusive use of the property. Carpenter also demonstrates that the idea, approved in Silverman, Wong Sun, and Burger, that intangible information constitutes property endures after Katz. The Carpenter defendants argued that their fraud convictions could not stand because “the Journal’s interest in prepublication confidentiality for the ‘Heard’ columns is no more than an intangible consideration . . . .”241 Relying on 1918’s International News Service v. Associated Press (just as AT&T and Justice Butler advocated in Olmstead), the Carpenter Court concluded that intangible information is property: “Here, the object of the scheme was to take the Journal’s confidential business information—the publication schedule and contents of the ‘Heard’ column—and its intangible nature does not make it any less ‘property’ protected by the mail and wire fraud statutes.”242 Carpenter’s view of property does not penalize one who shares his property with another. Unlike in Miller and Smith, the Carpenter Court did not suggest that the Journal assumed the risk that an employee would divulge or use information acquired through his work. On the contrary, the Court pointed out that “‘even in the absence of a written contract, an employee has a fiduciary obligation to protect confidential information obtained during the course of his employment.’”243 The employment-at-will relationship hardly distinguishes Miller and Smith. The depositor in Miller and the telephone customer in Smith had contractual agreements with the bank and with the carrier respectively. No less than the Journal’s employee, these entities were obliged “to protect confidential information obtained during the course” of performing their contractual duties. This same idea—whether information, once shared, became public—was a sticking point in Associated Press. But the Court then recognized that some information is only valuable when it is shared: “The schedule and contents of the ‘Heard’ column.” (emphasis added)).

241Id. at 25. 242 Id.; see also United States v. O’Hagan, 521 U.S. 642, 654 (1997)

(reaffirming Carpenter on this point). 243 Carpenter, 484 U.S. at 27 (quoting Snepp v. United States, 444 U.S. 507, 515

(1980) (per curiam)).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 532

peculiar value of news is in the spreading of it while it is fresh; and it is evident that a valuable property interest in the news, as news, cannot be maintained by keeping it secret.”244 The same is true, of course, of instructions to the bank, telephone numbers dialed, web sites visited, and nearly all the information that consumers share with corporations to receive their services. There is no reason why the information the Associated Press shares with its subscribers should be deemed property while the information than an individual communicates to corporate service providers should be held to be in the public domain. Sharing information can result in its communication to the government, of course, but that does not mean the government is entitled to it. AT&T argued in Olmstead that participants to a conversation are “co-owners” of it. The Court approved this notion at least implicitly in Silverman, Wong Sun, Berger, and Katz. The idea that the intended recipient of information becomes a co-owner of it means that the recipient may divulge it voluntarily without implicating the Fourth Amendment. This explains a line of cases decided in the years between Wong Sun and Berger, holding that the government’s use of false friends, undercover agents, and informants to transmit or record conversations constituted neither a search nor a seizure.245 In each of those cases, the government became a “co-owner” of information voluntarily communicated to it by a defendant.246 That the defendant did not expect to have his confidence betrayed or his words recorded did not implicate the Constitution. These holdings survived Katz intact and, somewhat ironically, formed the basis for Miller and Smith. (For a short time after Katz, the Court was equally

244 Int’l News Serv. v. Assoc. Press, 248 U.S. 215, 235 (1918). 245 Osborn v. United States, 385 U.S. 323, 327 (1966); Hoffa v. United States,

385 U.S. 293 (1966); Lewis v. United States, 385 U.S. 206 (1966); Lopez v. United States, 373 U.S. 427, 439 (1963).

246 Osborn, 385 U.S. at 327 (upholding “the use by one party of a device to make an accurate recording of a conversation about which that party later testified”); Lewis, 385 U.S. at 210 (“During neither of his visits to petitioner’s home did the agent see, hear, or take anything that was not contemplated, and in fact intended, by petitioner as a necessary part of his illegal business.”); Lopez, 373 U.S. at 438 (“The only evidence obtained consisted of statements made by Lopez to Davis, statements which Lopez knew full well could be used against him by Davis if he wished.”).

Page 91: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

531 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

way, attaching a tracking device to someone’s property deprives the owner of the exclusive use of the property. Carpenter also demonstrates that the idea, approved in Silverman, Wong Sun, and Burger, that intangible information constitutes property endures after Katz. The Carpenter defendants argued that their fraud convictions could not stand because “the Journal’s interest in prepublication confidentiality for the ‘Heard’ columns is no more than an intangible consideration . . . .”241 Relying on 1918’s International News Service v. Associated Press (just as AT&T and Justice Butler advocated in Olmstead), the Carpenter Court concluded that intangible information is property: “Here, the object of the scheme was to take the Journal’s confidential business information—the publication schedule and contents of the ‘Heard’ column—and its intangible nature does not make it any less ‘property’ protected by the mail and wire fraud statutes.”242 Carpenter’s view of property does not penalize one who shares his property with another. Unlike in Miller and Smith, the Carpenter Court did not suggest that the Journal assumed the risk that an employee would divulge or use information acquired through his work. On the contrary, the Court pointed out that “‘even in the absence of a written contract, an employee has a fiduciary obligation to protect confidential information obtained during the course of his employment.’”243 The employment-at-will relationship hardly distinguishes Miller and Smith. The depositor in Miller and the telephone customer in Smith had contractual agreements with the bank and with the carrier respectively. No less than the Journal’s employee, these entities were obliged “to protect confidential information obtained during the course” of performing their contractual duties. This same idea—whether information, once shared, became public—was a sticking point in Associated Press. But the Court then recognized that some information is only valuable when it is shared: “The schedule and contents of the ‘Heard’ column.” (emphasis added)).

241Id. at 25. 242 Id.; see also United States v. O’Hagan, 521 U.S. 642, 654 (1997)

(reaffirming Carpenter on this point). 243 Carpenter, 484 U.S. at 27 (quoting Snepp v. United States, 444 U.S. 507, 515

(1980) (per curiam)).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 532

peculiar value of news is in the spreading of it while it is fresh; and it is evident that a valuable property interest in the news, as news, cannot be maintained by keeping it secret.”244 The same is true, of course, of instructions to the bank, telephone numbers dialed, web sites visited, and nearly all the information that consumers share with corporations to receive their services. There is no reason why the information the Associated Press shares with its subscribers should be deemed property while the information than an individual communicates to corporate service providers should be held to be in the public domain. Sharing information can result in its communication to the government, of course, but that does not mean the government is entitled to it. AT&T argued in Olmstead that participants to a conversation are “co-owners” of it. The Court approved this notion at least implicitly in Silverman, Wong Sun, Berger, and Katz. The idea that the intended recipient of information becomes a co-owner of it means that the recipient may divulge it voluntarily without implicating the Fourth Amendment. This explains a line of cases decided in the years between Wong Sun and Berger, holding that the government’s use of false friends, undercover agents, and informants to transmit or record conversations constituted neither a search nor a seizure.245 In each of those cases, the government became a “co-owner” of information voluntarily communicated to it by a defendant.246 That the defendant did not expect to have his confidence betrayed or his words recorded did not implicate the Constitution. These holdings survived Katz intact and, somewhat ironically, formed the basis for Miller and Smith. (For a short time after Katz, the Court was equally

244 Int’l News Serv. v. Assoc. Press, 248 U.S. 215, 235 (1918). 245 Osborn v. United States, 385 U.S. 323, 327 (1966); Hoffa v. United States,

385 U.S. 293 (1966); Lewis v. United States, 385 U.S. 206 (1966); Lopez v. United States, 373 U.S. 427, 439 (1963).

246 Osborn, 385 U.S. at 327 (upholding “the use by one party of a device to make an accurate recording of a conversation about which that party later testified”); Lewis, 385 U.S. at 210 (“During neither of his visits to petitioner’s home did the agent see, hear, or take anything that was not contemplated, and in fact intended, by petitioner as a necessary part of his illegal business.”); Lopez, 373 U.S. at 438 (“The only evidence obtained consisted of statements made by Lopez to Davis, statements which Lopez knew full well could be used against him by Davis if he wished.”).

Page 92: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

533 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

divided over the narrow question of whether Katz limited the use of informants wired with transmitters.247 But, after Justices Black, Harlan, and Douglas retired, the Court quietly adopted the view that it did not.248) Another advantage of the pre-Katz property approach is that it discourages judicial balancing of interests. Property rights are, compared to privacy interests, well defined and, consequently, cannot be easily overridden by platitudes about societal good. Thirteen years after Carpenter, the Court concluded in Cleveland v. United States249—again unanimously—that a state license to operate computerized poker machines was not property under the federal fraud statutes.250 The government alleged that the petitioner schemed to obtain a gaming license, concealing his participation because he would not have met Louisiana’s moral and fiscal integrity requirements.251 Tracking Carpenter, the Court distinguished the state’s regulatory interest as sovereign in the licensing scheme “from traditional concepts of property.”252 The Louisiana licensing scheme specified that a license “is not property or a protected

247 See United States v. White, 401 U.S. 745, 751 (1971) (plurality opinion); id. at 755 (Brennan, J., concurring); id. at 762–63 (Douglas, J., dissenting); id. at 787–89 (Harlan, J., dissenting); id. at 795–96 (Marshall, J., dissenting). Justice Black, insisting that Katz itself was fundamentally illegitimate, took no position on its implications. Id. at 754 (Black, J., concurring). Justice Harlan’s dissent in White did the best job of explaining why this might be so. A person might willingly risk voicing unpopular or controversial views to someone he knows well, knowing the friend might betray him. That risk becomes unacceptably high when the government can bribe or cajole a person’s close friends into becoming government agents. One is a world where people can’t trust others they don’t know very well. The other is a world where people cannot afford to trust anyone. Justice Harlan is self-consciously focused on what makes sense for our political system and society. He is not asking what the defendant actually risked. He is asking what the nation can afford to risk.

248 See United States v. Miller, 425 U.S. 435, 443 (1976) (citing White, 401 U.S. at 751 (plurality opinion)); United States v. Caceres, 440 U.S. 741, 743 n.2 (1979) (same).

249 531 U.S. 12 (2000). 250 Although there was a circuit split over whether a license constitutes property

of which a state may be defrauded, the large majority of the circuits had concluded that it did not. Id. at 17–18.

251 Id. at 15–16. 252 Id. at 24.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 534

interest under the constitutions of either the United States or the state of Louisiana.”253 The Court, however, noted that the federal courts were not bound by that declaration, stating, “the question whether a state-law right constitutes ‘property’ or ‘rights to property’ is a matter of federal law.”254 The Court concluded that Louisiana’s “sovereign right to exclude applicants deemed unsuitable to run video poker operations” was not a property interest under federal law.255 In the same way that whether an interest constitutes property in a federal fraud case is a matter of federal common law, whether a tangible or intangible thing constitutes a “paper” or an “effect” has been, since at least the time of Olmstead, a matter of federal constitutional law. A legislature’s declaration that certain beverages, plants, chemicals, movies, or books are contraband does not place them outside the Constitution’s protection, especially given that searches for seditious libels inspired passage of the Fourth Amendment. The amendment protects even effects whose possession Congress or a state legislature decides to outlaw. Property law has long accommodated the idea that a person may have legally cognizable interests in property despite a legal incapacity to possess it. In one case, for example, the Seventh Circuit blocked the federal government’s attempt to confiscate and destroy a convicted felon’s firearms holding that the government had to sell, bail, or store the weapons for him.256 Because of this distinction between ownership rights and possessory rights, there is no reason for treating contraband as outside the Fourth Amendment’s ambit and a good reason for not doing so: it causes the proliferation of suspicionless dragnet searches.257 By focusing on exclusivity of dominion over private property, including information obtained pursuant to a contract for services, the pre-

253 Id. at 25 n.4 (quoting La. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 27:301(D) (2000)). 254 Id. (quoting Drye v. United States, 528 U.S. 49, 58 (1999)). 255 Id. at 24, 25 n.4 (quoting Drye, 528 U.S. at 58). 256 See, e.g., United States v. Miller, 588 F.3d 418, 420 (7th Cir. 2009)

(“Because the United States did not commence a timely forfeiture proceeding, Miller’s property interest in the firearms continues even though his possessory interest has been curtailed.”).

257 See Bascuas, supra note 35, at 758–69 (describing Operation Pipeline).

Page 93: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

533 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

divided over the narrow question of whether Katz limited the use of informants wired with transmitters.247 But, after Justices Black, Harlan, and Douglas retired, the Court quietly adopted the view that it did not.248) Another advantage of the pre-Katz property approach is that it discourages judicial balancing of interests. Property rights are, compared to privacy interests, well defined and, consequently, cannot be easily overridden by platitudes about societal good. Thirteen years after Carpenter, the Court concluded in Cleveland v. United States249—again unanimously—that a state license to operate computerized poker machines was not property under the federal fraud statutes.250 The government alleged that the petitioner schemed to obtain a gaming license, concealing his participation because he would not have met Louisiana’s moral and fiscal integrity requirements.251 Tracking Carpenter, the Court distinguished the state’s regulatory interest as sovereign in the licensing scheme “from traditional concepts of property.”252 The Louisiana licensing scheme specified that a license “is not property or a protected

247 See United States v. White, 401 U.S. 745, 751 (1971) (plurality opinion); id. at 755 (Brennan, J., concurring); id. at 762–63 (Douglas, J., dissenting); id. at 787–89 (Harlan, J., dissenting); id. at 795–96 (Marshall, J., dissenting). Justice Black, insisting that Katz itself was fundamentally illegitimate, took no position on its implications. Id. at 754 (Black, J., concurring). Justice Harlan’s dissent in White did the best job of explaining why this might be so. A person might willingly risk voicing unpopular or controversial views to someone he knows well, knowing the friend might betray him. That risk becomes unacceptably high when the government can bribe or cajole a person’s close friends into becoming government agents. One is a world where people can’t trust others they don’t know very well. The other is a world where people cannot afford to trust anyone. Justice Harlan is self-consciously focused on what makes sense for our political system and society. He is not asking what the defendant actually risked. He is asking what the nation can afford to risk.

248 See United States v. Miller, 425 U.S. 435, 443 (1976) (citing White, 401 U.S. at 751 (plurality opinion)); United States v. Caceres, 440 U.S. 741, 743 n.2 (1979) (same).

249 531 U.S. 12 (2000). 250 Although there was a circuit split over whether a license constitutes property

of which a state may be defrauded, the large majority of the circuits had concluded that it did not. Id. at 17–18.

251 Id. at 15–16. 252 Id. at 24.

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 534

interest under the constitutions of either the United States or the state of Louisiana.”253 The Court, however, noted that the federal courts were not bound by that declaration, stating, “the question whether a state-law right constitutes ‘property’ or ‘rights to property’ is a matter of federal law.”254 The Court concluded that Louisiana’s “sovereign right to exclude applicants deemed unsuitable to run video poker operations” was not a property interest under federal law.255 In the same way that whether an interest constitutes property in a federal fraud case is a matter of federal common law, whether a tangible or intangible thing constitutes a “paper” or an “effect” has been, since at least the time of Olmstead, a matter of federal constitutional law. A legislature’s declaration that certain beverages, plants, chemicals, movies, or books are contraband does not place them outside the Constitution’s protection, especially given that searches for seditious libels inspired passage of the Fourth Amendment. The amendment protects even effects whose possession Congress or a state legislature decides to outlaw. Property law has long accommodated the idea that a person may have legally cognizable interests in property despite a legal incapacity to possess it. In one case, for example, the Seventh Circuit blocked the federal government’s attempt to confiscate and destroy a convicted felon’s firearms holding that the government had to sell, bail, or store the weapons for him.256 Because of this distinction between ownership rights and possessory rights, there is no reason for treating contraband as outside the Fourth Amendment’s ambit and a good reason for not doing so: it causes the proliferation of suspicionless dragnet searches.257 By focusing on exclusivity of dominion over private property, including information obtained pursuant to a contract for services, the pre-

253 Id. at 25 n.4 (quoting La. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 27:301(D) (2000)). 254 Id. (quoting Drye v. United States, 528 U.S. 49, 58 (1999)). 255 Id. at 24, 25 n.4 (quoting Drye, 528 U.S. at 58). 256 See, e.g., United States v. Miller, 588 F.3d 418, 420 (7th Cir. 2009)

(“Because the United States did not commence a timely forfeiture proceeding, Miller’s property interest in the firearms continues even though his possessory interest has been curtailed.”).

257 See Bascuas, supra note 35, at 758–69 (describing Operation Pipeline).

Page 94: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

535 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Katz test facilitates resolution of issues that are needlessly convoluted under Jones as well as Katz. Rather than musing wincingly in California v. Greenwood258 about nocturnal foragers and dirty urchins getting into garbage cans, the Court could have answered the real question: whether garbage put at the curb is abandoned for Fourth Amendment purposes. Colorable arguments might be made on either side, but courts are better able to credibly determine when an individual’s property rights in trash are extinguished than when one’s expectation that her trash is “private” becomes unreasonable. Justice Sotomayor’s concern over cellular telephone tracking would be easily assuaged. Mobile telephone users would have standing to complain that the government converted their telephones into tracking devices, trespassing (and thereby seizing) the devices by depriving the owner of exclusive use of the phone and the information it generates. The telephone, after all, reveals the user’s location only incidentally to achieving its function of putting the user in telephonic contact with others. It is the user who pays for the telephone and the communications service. Today’s mobile phones and the information that flows from them are, for Fourth Amendment purposes, no different from Silverman’s heating pipes and the conversations that echoed throughout them in 1958. Tapping the phone to seize information is functionally indistinguishable from tapping the pipes to seize conversations. Similarly, viewed from Silverman’s vantage, the problem with license plate tracking is the license plate itself and the purpose it serves. Requiring every driver to affix a license plate to a car as part of a vehicle taxing scheme might not constitute a Fourth Amendment “seizure” any more than requiring a building to have plumbing does. This is not because the license plate does not “meaningful interfere” with the car’s use. Rather, it is because the reason why the government does something is

258 486 U.S. 35, 51 (1988) (Brennan, J., dissenting) (“The Court properly rejects the State’s attempt to distinguish trash searches from other searches on the theory that trash is abandoned and therefore not entitled to an expectation of privacy.”); see also California v. Rooney, 483 U.S. 307, 320 (1987) (White, J., dissenting from dismissal of writ of certiorari) (“Rooney’s property interest, however, does not settle the matter for Fourth Amendment purposes, for the reach of the Fourth Amendment is not determined by state property law.”).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 536

often a critical question in determining whether the action is allowed or prohibited.259 The government can require plumbing as a health and safety regulation, but it does not follow that it can then tap the pipes to overhear conversations. In the same way, it does not follow from the government’s being able to require license plates to raise revenue that it can use them as tracking devices without committing an unconstitutional conversion of each automobile.260 The Fourth Amendment may well require changes to license plates to make tracking impossible or suppression of evidence obtained through license-plate tracking even if requiring license plates for a purpose other than tracking is permissible. Had the Court abandoned expectations of privacy and relied instead on property concepts, it would not have had to duck the critical issues in City of Ontario v. Quon. Rather than having to divine whether society expects text messages to be private, the Court could have undertaken to decide whose property the messages were, just as it decided in Carpenter that the Journal owned the information its reporter gathered. That is not to say that the question of ownership over text messages sent on city equipment issued to police officers is free from all doubt. Its resolution might have been influenced by the city’s having acquiesced in the police sergeant sending personal text messages so long as he reimbursed the city for the cost.261 Rather, the point is that framing the question with reference to property concepts rather than expectations of privacy makes it possible for a court to answer it with authority.

259 See Jardines v. Florida, 133 S. Ct. 1409, 1416–17 (2013) (“Here, however, the question before the court is precisely whether the officer’s conduct was an objectively reasonable search. As we have described, that depends upon whether the officers had an implied license to enter the porch, which in turn depends upon the purpose for which they entered. Here, their behavior objectively reveals a purpose to conduct a search, which is not what anyone would think he had license to do.”); National Aero. & Space Admin. v. Nelson, 131 S. Ct. 746, 757 (2011) (holding that the government has greater latitude in gathering personal information when it acts as an employer than when it acts as sovereign).

260 Cf. Reich, supra note 104, at 1428 (“Regulatory power over the right to drive is delegated by the people to the state for one purpose alone—to ensure safety on the public highways. It is a manifest abuse for the state to use its licensing power for any purpose whatsoever except to ensure safe driving.”).

261 City of Ontario v. Quon, 130 S. Ct. 2619, 2625–26 (2010).

Page 95: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

535 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Katz test facilitates resolution of issues that are needlessly convoluted under Jones as well as Katz. Rather than musing wincingly in California v. Greenwood258 about nocturnal foragers and dirty urchins getting into garbage cans, the Court could have answered the real question: whether garbage put at the curb is abandoned for Fourth Amendment purposes. Colorable arguments might be made on either side, but courts are better able to credibly determine when an individual’s property rights in trash are extinguished than when one’s expectation that her trash is “private” becomes unreasonable. Justice Sotomayor’s concern over cellular telephone tracking would be easily assuaged. Mobile telephone users would have standing to complain that the government converted their telephones into tracking devices, trespassing (and thereby seizing) the devices by depriving the owner of exclusive use of the phone and the information it generates. The telephone, after all, reveals the user’s location only incidentally to achieving its function of putting the user in telephonic contact with others. It is the user who pays for the telephone and the communications service. Today’s mobile phones and the information that flows from them are, for Fourth Amendment purposes, no different from Silverman’s heating pipes and the conversations that echoed throughout them in 1958. Tapping the phone to seize information is functionally indistinguishable from tapping the pipes to seize conversations. Similarly, viewed from Silverman’s vantage, the problem with license plate tracking is the license plate itself and the purpose it serves. Requiring every driver to affix a license plate to a car as part of a vehicle taxing scheme might not constitute a Fourth Amendment “seizure” any more than requiring a building to have plumbing does. This is not because the license plate does not “meaningful interfere” with the car’s use. Rather, it is because the reason why the government does something is

258 486 U.S. 35, 51 (1988) (Brennan, J., dissenting) (“The Court properly rejects the State’s attempt to distinguish trash searches from other searches on the theory that trash is abandoned and therefore not entitled to an expectation of privacy.”); see also California v. Rooney, 483 U.S. 307, 320 (1987) (White, J., dissenting from dismissal of writ of certiorari) (“Rooney’s property interest, however, does not settle the matter for Fourth Amendment purposes, for the reach of the Fourth Amendment is not determined by state property law.”).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 536

often a critical question in determining whether the action is allowed or prohibited.259 The government can require plumbing as a health and safety regulation, but it does not follow that it can then tap the pipes to overhear conversations. In the same way, it does not follow from the government’s being able to require license plates to raise revenue that it can use them as tracking devices without committing an unconstitutional conversion of each automobile.260 The Fourth Amendment may well require changes to license plates to make tracking impossible or suppression of evidence obtained through license-plate tracking even if requiring license plates for a purpose other than tracking is permissible. Had the Court abandoned expectations of privacy and relied instead on property concepts, it would not have had to duck the critical issues in City of Ontario v. Quon. Rather than having to divine whether society expects text messages to be private, the Court could have undertaken to decide whose property the messages were, just as it decided in Carpenter that the Journal owned the information its reporter gathered. That is not to say that the question of ownership over text messages sent on city equipment issued to police officers is free from all doubt. Its resolution might have been influenced by the city’s having acquiesced in the police sergeant sending personal text messages so long as he reimbursed the city for the cost.261 Rather, the point is that framing the question with reference to property concepts rather than expectations of privacy makes it possible for a court to answer it with authority.

259 See Jardines v. Florida, 133 S. Ct. 1409, 1416–17 (2013) (“Here, however, the question before the court is precisely whether the officer’s conduct was an objectively reasonable search. As we have described, that depends upon whether the officers had an implied license to enter the porch, which in turn depends upon the purpose for which they entered. Here, their behavior objectively reveals a purpose to conduct a search, which is not what anyone would think he had license to do.”); National Aero. & Space Admin. v. Nelson, 131 S. Ct. 746, 757 (2011) (holding that the government has greater latitude in gathering personal information when it acts as an employer than when it acts as sovereign).

260 Cf. Reich, supra note 104, at 1428 (“Regulatory power over the right to drive is delegated by the people to the state for one purpose alone—to ensure safety on the public highways. It is a manifest abuse for the state to use its licensing power for any purpose whatsoever except to ensure safe driving.”).

261 City of Ontario v. Quon, 130 S. Ct. 2619, 2625–26 (2010).

Page 96: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

537 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

This is not to say that courts never have any trouble identifying property interests.262 Appeals involving fraudulent schemes to obtain unearned frequent-flier travel awards, for example, mistakenly have focused on the question of whether frequent-flier miles are “property” of the airline.263 But that is not the actual issue. In United States v. Loney, American Airlines was not defrauded out of frequent flier miles when the defendant fraudulently obtained tickets and sold them. It was defrauded of the value of the travel service it provides, whether that is measured as the amount for which the defendant sold the tickets or as the full retail value of the tickets. The miles probably are not property at all, but the Fifth Circuit’s alternative rationale—that the scheme deprived the airline of its “lawful revenues”—is more or less correct.264 (There is a needless discussion to the effect that proof of harm is not an element of federal fraud, but there is no doubt that American was harmed because it flew at least two passengers without being compensated.265) United States v. Schrier likewise erroneously focuses on whether airline miles are property, but the late Judge Edward Dumbauld’s brief concurring opinion is on the money in concluding that issued tickets were property.266 Whatever the difficulties entailed in identifying property interests as a matter of federal common law, the process is a customary one for judges and lawyers, while identifying expectations of privacy is not.

V. CONCLUSION

Olmstead, Katz, and Jones each presented the same basic problem: how to meet the challenge to privacy posed by the technological advances

262 See, e.g., Jolly v. United States, 170 U.S. 402 (1898) (analyzing whether

unissued postage stamps have “intrinsic value” and are thus property of the United States).

263 See, e.g., United States v. Loney, 959 F.2d 1332, 1335–36 (5th Cir. 1992) (discussing Trans-World Airlines v. Am. Coupon Exch., 913 F.2d 676 (9th Cir. 1990)).

264 Id. at 1336. 265 Id. at 1337 n.13. 266 908 F.2d 645, 648 (10th Cir. 1990) (Dumbauld, J., concurring).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 538

of the Information Age. That challenge has not been met by the Court’s long experiment with protecting expectations of privacy directly. On the contrary, the Katz test has been a dismal failure, yielding an arbitrary and unpredictable jurisprudence that allowed the Court to withdraw the amendment’s protection over some traditional forms of property, like contraband. The Katz framework is irremediable because, even assuming that anyone can correctly gauge societal expectations of privacy, courts have shown that they cannot. Jones fails to improve upon it because, like Katz, it proceeds from a misguided assumption that minor conversions of property are allowed even without any individualized suspicion. Meeting the challenge to privacy in the Information Age requires understanding “persons, houses, papers, and effects” in a way that is grounded in law yet can evolve as quickly as surveillance and communication technology. It means interpreting those terms in a way that is consistent with our understanding of property across various fields of law and is therefore principled and predictable. The federal courts’ interpretation of federal fraud statutes shows that courts are capable of doing just that. Courts have for years successfully identified new forms of property created by new forms of storing and transmitting data and new ways of transacting business. The Supreme Court has protected informational property against fraud, rejecting the rationales and justifications it deploys to allow the government to infringe on property rights. The federal courts can and should protect all property from government incursions in the same way that they protect it from fraudsters. Understanding that the Fourth Amendment protects property is unavailing unless it is also accepted that the amendment protects property from even slight incursions. A government trespass or conversion of property is not “reasonable” in a constitutional sense because a court deems it minor or in society’s interest. Conversions of private property are reasonable only when they are justified by individualized suspicion amounting to probable cause. Despite its pretensions, Jones fails to restore the Fourth Amendment’s protection of property because it adopts an unduly narrow understanding of “seizure”, one that excludes many government conversions of property from the amendment’s reach. This perpetuates the abuses that Katz fostered—abuses of the very sort the framers sought to curb. It encourages corporations to sell sensitive

Page 97: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

537 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

This is not to say that courts never have any trouble identifying property interests.262 Appeals involving fraudulent schemes to obtain unearned frequent-flier travel awards, for example, mistakenly have focused on the question of whether frequent-flier miles are “property” of the airline.263 But that is not the actual issue. In United States v. Loney, American Airlines was not defrauded out of frequent flier miles when the defendant fraudulently obtained tickets and sold them. It was defrauded of the value of the travel service it provides, whether that is measured as the amount for which the defendant sold the tickets or as the full retail value of the tickets. The miles probably are not property at all, but the Fifth Circuit’s alternative rationale—that the scheme deprived the airline of its “lawful revenues”—is more or less correct.264 (There is a needless discussion to the effect that proof of harm is not an element of federal fraud, but there is no doubt that American was harmed because it flew at least two passengers without being compensated.265) United States v. Schrier likewise erroneously focuses on whether airline miles are property, but the late Judge Edward Dumbauld’s brief concurring opinion is on the money in concluding that issued tickets were property.266 Whatever the difficulties entailed in identifying property interests as a matter of federal common law, the process is a customary one for judges and lawyers, while identifying expectations of privacy is not.

V. CONCLUSION

Olmstead, Katz, and Jones each presented the same basic problem: how to meet the challenge to privacy posed by the technological advances

262 See, e.g., Jolly v. United States, 170 U.S. 402 (1898) (analyzing whether

unissued postage stamps have “intrinsic value” and are thus property of the United States).

263 See, e.g., United States v. Loney, 959 F.2d 1332, 1335–36 (5th Cir. 1992) (discussing Trans-World Airlines v. Am. Coupon Exch., 913 F.2d 676 (9th Cir. 1990)).

264 Id. at 1336. 265 Id. at 1337 n.13. 266 908 F.2d 645, 648 (10th Cir. 1990) (Dumbauld, J., concurring).

2013] The Fourth Amendment in the Information Age 538

of the Information Age. That challenge has not been met by the Court’s long experiment with protecting expectations of privacy directly. On the contrary, the Katz test has been a dismal failure, yielding an arbitrary and unpredictable jurisprudence that allowed the Court to withdraw the amendment’s protection over some traditional forms of property, like contraband. The Katz framework is irremediable because, even assuming that anyone can correctly gauge societal expectations of privacy, courts have shown that they cannot. Jones fails to improve upon it because, like Katz, it proceeds from a misguided assumption that minor conversions of property are allowed even without any individualized suspicion. Meeting the challenge to privacy in the Information Age requires understanding “persons, houses, papers, and effects” in a way that is grounded in law yet can evolve as quickly as surveillance and communication technology. It means interpreting those terms in a way that is consistent with our understanding of property across various fields of law and is therefore principled and predictable. The federal courts’ interpretation of federal fraud statutes shows that courts are capable of doing just that. Courts have for years successfully identified new forms of property created by new forms of storing and transmitting data and new ways of transacting business. The Supreme Court has protected informational property against fraud, rejecting the rationales and justifications it deploys to allow the government to infringe on property rights. The federal courts can and should protect all property from government incursions in the same way that they protect it from fraudsters. Understanding that the Fourth Amendment protects property is unavailing unless it is also accepted that the amendment protects property from even slight incursions. A government trespass or conversion of property is not “reasonable” in a constitutional sense because a court deems it minor or in society’s interest. Conversions of private property are reasonable only when they are justified by individualized suspicion amounting to probable cause. Despite its pretensions, Jones fails to restore the Fourth Amendment’s protection of property because it adopts an unduly narrow understanding of “seizure”, one that excludes many government conversions of property from the amendment’s reach. This perpetuates the abuses that Katz fostered—abuses of the very sort the framers sought to curb. It encourages corporations to sell sensitive

Page 98: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

539 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

information to government agencies on an unprecedented scale and encourages police to conduct dragnet searches for contraband. Over the long run, this fuels the government’s agglomeration of data to track individuals’ thoughts and movements while degrading them by demanding urine from schoolchildren, stopping drivers at highway checkpoints, and searching travelers’ personal belongings on the basis of a dog’s instinct. As Silverman illustrates, a Fourth Amendment seizure is complete with the government’s slightest touching of private property.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 540

UNBINDING BINDING ARBITRATION OF POLICE DISCIPLINE:

THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION

Mark Iris, Ph.D.

ABSTRACT

Police chiefs are often confronted with having to reinstate former officers, discharged for serious misconduct, after their discharges are reversed through arbitration. Such arbitral decisions are presumably binding, with no appeal. There are strong case law precedents affirming the concept of judicial deference to arbitral decisions; state and federal statutes appear to afford few options. Nonetheless, some state courts allow judicial reversal of presumably binding arbitration decisions when those decisions appear to contravene a clearly defined public policy. State courts vary in their willingness to exercise this option. This article examines case law for public policy exceptions in six states showing a wide degree of variation on this dimension: Pennsylvania, Texas, Nebraska, Massachusetts, Illinois, and Connecticut.

Department of Political Science and Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences Program, Northwestern University. I wish to thank Max Caproni, Ph.D., Executive Director, Chicago Police Board; Craig Ferrell, Chief’s Counsel (retired), Houston Police Department; Roger Goldman, the Callis Family Professor of Law, School of Law, St. Louis University; and counselor Laurie Joseph Wasserman, J.D., Ph.D. for their assistance in reading and commenting upon drafts of this article.

Page 99: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

539 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

information to government agencies on an unprecedented scale and encourages police to conduct dragnet searches for contraband. Over the long run, this fuels the government’s agglomeration of data to track individuals’ thoughts and movements while degrading them by demanding urine from schoolchildren, stopping drivers at highway checkpoints, and searching travelers’ personal belongings on the basis of a dog’s instinct. As Silverman illustrates, a Fourth Amendment seizure is complete with the government’s slightest touching of private property.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 540

UNBINDING BINDING ARBITRATION OF POLICE DISCIPLINE:

THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION

Mark Iris, Ph.D.

ABSTRACT

Police chiefs are often confronted with having to reinstate former officers, discharged for serious misconduct, after their discharges are reversed through arbitration. Such arbitral decisions are presumably binding, with no appeal. There are strong case law precedents affirming the concept of judicial deference to arbitral decisions; state and federal statutes appear to afford few options. Nonetheless, some state courts allow judicial reversal of presumably binding arbitration decisions when those decisions appear to contravene a clearly defined public policy. State courts vary in their willingness to exercise this option. This article examines case law for public policy exceptions in six states showing a wide degree of variation on this dimension: Pennsylvania, Texas, Nebraska, Massachusetts, Illinois, and Connecticut.

Department of Political Science and Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences Program, Northwestern University. I wish to thank Max Caproni, Ph.D., Executive Director, Chicago Police Board; Craig Ferrell, Chief’s Counsel (retired), Houston Police Department; Roger Goldman, the Callis Family Professor of Law, School of Law, St. Louis University; and counselor Laurie Joseph Wasserman, J.D., Ph.D. for their assistance in reading and commenting upon drafts of this article.

Page 100: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

541 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

TABLE OF CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION ................................................................................ 541 II. POLICE DISCIPLINARY ARBITRATION IN PRACTICE ..... 543 III. THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION: LEGAL

UNDERPINNINGS ......................................................................... 547 IV. THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION IN OPERATION ........... 558

A. PENNSYLVANIA ............................................................................ 559 B. TEXAS .......................................................................................... 564 C. NEBRASKA ................................................................................... 569 D. MASSACHUSETTS ......................................................................... 571 E. ILLINOIS ....................................................................................... 579 F. CONNECTICUT .............................................................................. 584

CONCLUSION ..................................................................................... 590

INTRODUCTION

Among the problems that bedevil police chiefs across the United States are the constraints upon chiefs’ authority to impose discipline upon officers for proven misconduct. The quasi-military heritage of policing, the exceptional powers vested in officers, the high visibility and serious consequences of police misconduct all combine to make chiefs deem their authority to suspend, and if necessary fire, errant officers a crucial aspect of their positions. Yet that authority is significantly constrained by a variety of factors. And one of the most, perhaps the most, significant of these factors is arbitration. In many jurisdictions across the U.S., law enforcement officers enjoy a broad array of employment protections, safeguards not available to the vast majority of workforce employees. As public employees, typically vested with civil service protection after the completion of their probationary periods, police (and other civil service protected workers) are deemed to have a proprietary stake in their employment, and thus may not

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 542

be dismissed from employment without due process of law.1 Within the sphere of employees with civil service status and protection, police in particular typically enjoy an additional layer of employment protection as numerous states have enacted police officer or peace officer Bill of Rights statutes, which afford a wide variety of procedural safeguards to officers accused of misconduct.2 Additionally, in many agencies, especially larger ones, internal investigative files with sustained findings and recommendations for proposed disciplinary action will pass through several layers of internal supervisory and managerial review and comment before the chief of police orders an officer’s suspension or discharge. These protections and procedures are simply nonexistent for the vast majority of the American private sector workforce, who typically serve in an employment at will capacity. For many chiefs, however, perhaps the most significant factor impacting the disciplinary orders they hand down is the after the fact phenomenon of binding arbitration. In many jurisdictions, either collective bargaining agreements and/or state statutes allow officers who are being disciplined to challenge such disciplinary action through the arbitration process. A presumably neutral, independent third party will convene an arbitration hearing (or in certain instances simply review the relevant investigative file) and issue a decision: a decision which may uphold, modify or overturn in full the disciplinary action. And a core precept is that such arbitral decisions are binding; the parties agree in advance to accept the decision as final. Unlike most civil or criminal litigation, there is no appellate recourse. But this general rule has a twist: binding arbitration is not necessarily binding. There is a legal exception, neither as well known nor well understood among police leadership as it ought to be. In a number of states, case law has carved out what is referred to as the public policy exception. This legal caveat states in essence that if an arbitrator’s decision reverses discipline imposed upon a public employee, a public employer may initiate litigation to seek a court order to set aside that

1 Cleveland Bd. of Educ. v. Loudermill, 470 U.S 532, 541 (1985). 2 See, e.g., 735 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 5/3-101-113 (2008) and CAL. GOVT.

CODE §§ 3300-3312 (2003).

Page 101: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

541 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

TABLE OF CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION ................................................................................ 541 II. POLICE DISCIPLINARY ARBITRATION IN PRACTICE ..... 543 III. THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION: LEGAL

UNDERPINNINGS ......................................................................... 547 IV. THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION IN OPERATION ........... 558

A. PENNSYLVANIA ............................................................................ 559 B. TEXAS .......................................................................................... 564 C. NEBRASKA ................................................................................... 569 D. MASSACHUSETTS ......................................................................... 571 E. ILLINOIS ....................................................................................... 579 F. CONNECTICUT .............................................................................. 584

CONCLUSION ..................................................................................... 590

INTRODUCTION

Among the problems that bedevil police chiefs across the United States are the constraints upon chiefs’ authority to impose discipline upon officers for proven misconduct. The quasi-military heritage of policing, the exceptional powers vested in officers, the high visibility and serious consequences of police misconduct all combine to make chiefs deem their authority to suspend, and if necessary fire, errant officers a crucial aspect of their positions. Yet that authority is significantly constrained by a variety of factors. And one of the most, perhaps the most, significant of these factors is arbitration. In many jurisdictions across the U.S., law enforcement officers enjoy a broad array of employment protections, safeguards not available to the vast majority of workforce employees. As public employees, typically vested with civil service protection after the completion of their probationary periods, police (and other civil service protected workers) are deemed to have a proprietary stake in their employment, and thus may not

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 542

be dismissed from employment without due process of law.1 Within the sphere of employees with civil service status and protection, police in particular typically enjoy an additional layer of employment protection as numerous states have enacted police officer or peace officer Bill of Rights statutes, which afford a wide variety of procedural safeguards to officers accused of misconduct.2 Additionally, in many agencies, especially larger ones, internal investigative files with sustained findings and recommendations for proposed disciplinary action will pass through several layers of internal supervisory and managerial review and comment before the chief of police orders an officer’s suspension or discharge. These protections and procedures are simply nonexistent for the vast majority of the American private sector workforce, who typically serve in an employment at will capacity. For many chiefs, however, perhaps the most significant factor impacting the disciplinary orders they hand down is the after the fact phenomenon of binding arbitration. In many jurisdictions, either collective bargaining agreements and/or state statutes allow officers who are being disciplined to challenge such disciplinary action through the arbitration process. A presumably neutral, independent third party will convene an arbitration hearing (or in certain instances simply review the relevant investigative file) and issue a decision: a decision which may uphold, modify or overturn in full the disciplinary action. And a core precept is that such arbitral decisions are binding; the parties agree in advance to accept the decision as final. Unlike most civil or criminal litigation, there is no appellate recourse. But this general rule has a twist: binding arbitration is not necessarily binding. There is a legal exception, neither as well known nor well understood among police leadership as it ought to be. In a number of states, case law has carved out what is referred to as the public policy exception. This legal caveat states in essence that if an arbitrator’s decision reverses discipline imposed upon a public employee, a public employer may initiate litigation to seek a court order to set aside that

1 Cleveland Bd. of Educ. v. Loudermill, 470 U.S 532, 541 (1985). 2 See, e.g., 735 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 5/3-101-113 (2008) and CAL. GOVT.

CODE §§ 3300-3312 (2003).

Page 102: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

543 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

decision, and reinstate the original disciplinary action. Such a lawsuit is grounded in the notion that the arbitration decision is so contrary and anathema to a clearly defined public policy of the state that courts have the authority to intercede and block the enforcement of that arbitration award. Typically, the roots of this practice are grounded in case law, not statutes. The goal of this paper is to explore the nature of this public policy exception among the various states, explore state case law precedents, and note the sorts of misconduct which may—and may not—give rise to a claim of a public policy exception.

I. POLICE DISCIPLINARY ARBITRATION IN PRACTICE

Empirical findings confirm the reality that from a police chief’s perspective, the results of the arbitration process are not pretty. For example, in Chicago, two separate pools of data were examined. In one pool, there was a total of 1,584 days of suspension handed down by the Superintendent of the Chicago Police Department3 over a four years’ period, involving 328 separate cases. Arbitrators upheld 794 days of discipline for management, while reversing 790 days—a virtual 50/50 split.4 That same study examined a separate pool of cases involving fast track advisory opinions. Although formally non-binding, labor and management agreed to accept these advisory opinions in the overwhelming majority of instances. Of these 205 cases, arbitrators upheld 515 days of suspension, and reversed 508, again essentially a 50/50 split.5 A similar study of disciplinary actions in the Houston Police Department documented 149 cases over a five years’ period, with 899 days of discipline under appeal. Arbitrators upheld 480 days for management, and gave back to officers 419 days (in percentage terms,

3 The title of Superintendent of the Chicago Police Department is equivalent to

the chief’s position in most other agencies. 4 Mark Iris, Police Discipline in Chicago: Arbitration or Arbitrary?, 89 J. CRIM.

L. & CRIMINOLOGY 215, 235 (1998). 5 Id. at 237–38.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 544

53% of the days upheld, 47% overturned).6 The same study also examined a separate set of data for what Texas law labels “indefinite” suspensions, which are in reality discharges. Of thirty-six such cases, the Chief’s discharge orders were upheld in seventeen, reversed outright in ten (that is, the officer reinstated with no disciplinary penalty whatsoever), and modified to a lesser penalty in nine.7 And perhaps the best—or worst, depending on one’s perspective—example is that of the Cincinnati, Ohio, Police Department, where outside arbitrators, over a period of several years, handed down fourteen consecutive decisions reinstating officers previously ordered discharged.8 It appears that in Cincinnati, the only way a discharge stayed in place was if the officer had also been convicted of a felony in criminal court proceedings.9 Anecdotal evidence can easily be generated from many other jurisdictions to illustrate the fact that disciplinary actions, grounded in conduct which chiefs of police and presumably the public at large would find simply unacceptable, are often overturned by arbitrators. For example, an arbitrator’s decision compelled the Philadelphia Police Department to return to duty two officers, discharged after their use of excessive force in beating three suspects was captured on video taken from a news helicopter and widely publicized. Three other officers involved in that same incident had their disciplinary suspensions reduced to reprimands; a sergeant’s demotion to police officer was reversed, and two discharged probationary officers would likely be reinstated even though they were not parties to the arbitration.10 Two San Jose police

6 Mark Iris, Police Discipline in Houston: The Arbitration Experience, 5 POLICE Q. 132, 141 (2002).

7 Id. at 142. 8 Robert Anglen & Dan Horn, Police Discipline Inconsistent: Sanctions Most

Likely to be Reduced, CINCINNATI ENQUIRER, Oct. 21, 2001, http://enquirer.com/editions/2001/10/21/loc_police_discipline.html.

9 Cincinnati has a somewhat different practice, in that the Chief of Police recommends proposed disciplinary action, but the actual decision is made by the City Manager.

10 Allison Steele, Cops in Televised Beating Reinstated, PHILA. INQUIRER, Mar.

Page 103: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

543 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

decision, and reinstate the original disciplinary action. Such a lawsuit is grounded in the notion that the arbitration decision is so contrary and anathema to a clearly defined public policy of the state that courts have the authority to intercede and block the enforcement of that arbitration award. Typically, the roots of this practice are grounded in case law, not statutes. The goal of this paper is to explore the nature of this public policy exception among the various states, explore state case law precedents, and note the sorts of misconduct which may—and may not—give rise to a claim of a public policy exception.

I. POLICE DISCIPLINARY ARBITRATION IN PRACTICE

Empirical findings confirm the reality that from a police chief’s perspective, the results of the arbitration process are not pretty. For example, in Chicago, two separate pools of data were examined. In one pool, there was a total of 1,584 days of suspension handed down by the Superintendent of the Chicago Police Department3 over a four years’ period, involving 328 separate cases. Arbitrators upheld 794 days of discipline for management, while reversing 790 days—a virtual 50/50 split.4 That same study examined a separate pool of cases involving fast track advisory opinions. Although formally non-binding, labor and management agreed to accept these advisory opinions in the overwhelming majority of instances. Of these 205 cases, arbitrators upheld 515 days of suspension, and reversed 508, again essentially a 50/50 split.5 A similar study of disciplinary actions in the Houston Police Department documented 149 cases over a five years’ period, with 899 days of discipline under appeal. Arbitrators upheld 480 days for management, and gave back to officers 419 days (in percentage terms,

3 The title of Superintendent of the Chicago Police Department is equivalent to

the chief’s position in most other agencies. 4 Mark Iris, Police Discipline in Chicago: Arbitration or Arbitrary?, 89 J. CRIM.

L. & CRIMINOLOGY 215, 235 (1998). 5 Id. at 237–38.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 544

53% of the days upheld, 47% overturned).6 The same study also examined a separate set of data for what Texas law labels “indefinite” suspensions, which are in reality discharges. Of thirty-six such cases, the Chief’s discharge orders were upheld in seventeen, reversed outright in ten (that is, the officer reinstated with no disciplinary penalty whatsoever), and modified to a lesser penalty in nine.7 And perhaps the best—or worst, depending on one’s perspective—example is that of the Cincinnati, Ohio, Police Department, where outside arbitrators, over a period of several years, handed down fourteen consecutive decisions reinstating officers previously ordered discharged.8 It appears that in Cincinnati, the only way a discharge stayed in place was if the officer had also been convicted of a felony in criminal court proceedings.9 Anecdotal evidence can easily be generated from many other jurisdictions to illustrate the fact that disciplinary actions, grounded in conduct which chiefs of police and presumably the public at large would find simply unacceptable, are often overturned by arbitrators. For example, an arbitrator’s decision compelled the Philadelphia Police Department to return to duty two officers, discharged after their use of excessive force in beating three suspects was captured on video taken from a news helicopter and widely publicized. Three other officers involved in that same incident had their disciplinary suspensions reduced to reprimands; a sergeant’s demotion to police officer was reversed, and two discharged probationary officers would likely be reinstated even though they were not parties to the arbitration.10 Two San Jose police

6 Mark Iris, Police Discipline in Houston: The Arbitration Experience, 5 POLICE Q. 132, 141 (2002).

7 Id. at 142. 8 Robert Anglen & Dan Horn, Police Discipline Inconsistent: Sanctions Most

Likely to be Reduced, CINCINNATI ENQUIRER, Oct. 21, 2001, http://enquirer.com/editions/2001/10/21/loc_police_discipline.html.

9 Cincinnati has a somewhat different practice, in that the Chief of Police recommends proposed disciplinary action, but the actual decision is made by the City Manager.

10 Allison Steele, Cops in Televised Beating Reinstated, PHILA. INQUIRER, Mar.

Page 104: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

545 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

officers were fired for failing to properly investigate an auto accident, thus covering up the intoxication of the driver, an off-duty district attorney’s investigator whose husband was a San Jose police sergeant, and whose father-in law was a former police lieutenant. As a result of that multi-car auto accident, the driver in fact eventually pleaded guilty to DUI and causing injury. The discharged officers contested the discipline; an arbitrator in essence upheld the findings as to their guilt, but concluded the penalties were too severe. So the officers were ordered reinstated to duty with suspensions of eleven months each.11 Police discipline in some agencies may be subject to an administrative hearing process before a civil service commission or similar body. Those bodies too can hand down decisions, which may overturn an experienced police executive’s considered judgment. What distinguishes arbitration from these other quasi-judicial forums is the fact that an administrative agency’s decision is typically subject to appeal through litigation in civil courts.12 After exhausting one’s administrative remedies, recourse to an appropriate civil court by a losing party who wishes to contest an administrative decision is a basic, core component of administrative law. But arbitration is typically binding arbitration: the parties have in essence agreed, in advance, to abide by the arbitrator’s decision; there is no appeal. Thus, when an arbitrator reversed the indefinite suspension of a St. Paul, Minnesota, officer—imposed after his criminal conviction for an off-duty misdemeanor sex offense—the chief of that department was left with no option but to return to duty a convicted sex offender.13 12, 2010, available at http://www.philadelphiaspeaks.com/forum/general-discussion/10901-not-sure-what-make.html.

11 Sean Webby, Arbitrators Rescind Firing of San Jose Cops Accused in Coverup, SAN JOSE MERCURY NEWS, Nov. 11, 2010, http://www.mercurynews.com/ci_16588874.

12 See, e.g., 735 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 5/3-113 (2008), which allows a decision of an administrative agency, such as the Chicago Police Board, to be challenged through a suit in administrative review.

13 Conrad deFiebre, Ruling on Convicted Cop’s Job Explained; Work Record and Treatment Cited, MINNEAPOLIS/ST. PAUL STAR TRIB., Aug. 17, 1993, 1B. Roughly a year after his reinstatement, however, the officer was convicted of a separate sex offense that occurred while on duty, and agreed to resign from his position as a police officer. A

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 546

Such arbitration decisions are heartily disliked by police chiefs. They are widely perceived as undermining, compromising the chief’s ability to manage the agency and ensure proper discipline. They can have a corrosive effect on police discipline and morale, telling the misbehaving officers they may continue their misconduct without fear of adverse action, while undermining the morale of those who adhere to police regulations and ethical norms. These decisions also carry a financial cost. Reversal of a disciplinary action will typically carry with it reinstatement to duty with back pay and benefits retroactive to the date of termination.14 Depending upon the time lag from the date of the discharge until the date of reinstatement pursuant to an arbitration award, the amount could be substantial. Back pay awards arising from arbitration cost the City of Philadelphia $2.4 million between January 2008 and June 2010.15 There are occasional local variations on this financial norm. For example, arbitrators adjudicating grievances filed by Philadelphia police officers have a practice of not simply awarding back pay when a discharge or suspension is reduced or overturned (making that individual whole, the norm in most locales), but also awarding the additional amount of money the officer would probably have earned from overtime but for the disciplinary action. For example, one officer was suspended for ten days for falsely claiming three and a half hours overtime. He was also transferred to a different unit, one in which the overtime earnings’ potential was much lower than in the officer’s prior unit of assignment. The officer filed a grievance. The arbitrator sustained the infraction of a false overtime report, and upheld the disciplinary suspension, but struck

state administrative proceeding then stripped him of his certification, making him ineligible to serve as a police officer anywhere in Minnesota. See Michael Alan Kveene, State of Minnesota Office of Admin. Hearings, Jan. 13, 1997, available at http://www.oah.state.mn.us/aljBase/24020724.rt.htm.

14 Sometimes an arbitrator will reduce discharge to a lesser penalty, e.g., a suspension of X days duration. In these instances, the back pay award is adjusted accordingly to account for the suspension.

15 David Gambacorta, Quick on the Trigger? Ramsey’s Firings Strain City Coffers, PHILA. DAILY NEWS, June 7, 2010, http://articles.philly.com/2010-06-07/news/24968128_1_firings-top-cop-internal-affairs-bureau.

Page 105: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

545 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

officers were fired for failing to properly investigate an auto accident, thus covering up the intoxication of the driver, an off-duty district attorney’s investigator whose husband was a San Jose police sergeant, and whose father-in law was a former police lieutenant. As a result of that multi-car auto accident, the driver in fact eventually pleaded guilty to DUI and causing injury. The discharged officers contested the discipline; an arbitrator in essence upheld the findings as to their guilt, but concluded the penalties were too severe. So the officers were ordered reinstated to duty with suspensions of eleven months each.11 Police discipline in some agencies may be subject to an administrative hearing process before a civil service commission or similar body. Those bodies too can hand down decisions, which may overturn an experienced police executive’s considered judgment. What distinguishes arbitration from these other quasi-judicial forums is the fact that an administrative agency’s decision is typically subject to appeal through litigation in civil courts.12 After exhausting one’s administrative remedies, recourse to an appropriate civil court by a losing party who wishes to contest an administrative decision is a basic, core component of administrative law. But arbitration is typically binding arbitration: the parties have in essence agreed, in advance, to abide by the arbitrator’s decision; there is no appeal. Thus, when an arbitrator reversed the indefinite suspension of a St. Paul, Minnesota, officer—imposed after his criminal conviction for an off-duty misdemeanor sex offense—the chief of that department was left with no option but to return to duty a convicted sex offender.13 12, 2010, available at http://www.philadelphiaspeaks.com/forum/general-discussion/10901-not-sure-what-make.html.

11 Sean Webby, Arbitrators Rescind Firing of San Jose Cops Accused in Coverup, SAN JOSE MERCURY NEWS, Nov. 11, 2010, http://www.mercurynews.com/ci_16588874.

12 See, e.g., 735 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 5/3-113 (2008), which allows a decision of an administrative agency, such as the Chicago Police Board, to be challenged through a suit in administrative review.

13 Conrad deFiebre, Ruling on Convicted Cop’s Job Explained; Work Record and Treatment Cited, MINNEAPOLIS/ST. PAUL STAR TRIB., Aug. 17, 1993, 1B. Roughly a year after his reinstatement, however, the officer was convicted of a separate sex offense that occurred while on duty, and agreed to resign from his position as a police officer. A

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 546

Such arbitration decisions are heartily disliked by police chiefs. They are widely perceived as undermining, compromising the chief’s ability to manage the agency and ensure proper discipline. They can have a corrosive effect on police discipline and morale, telling the misbehaving officers they may continue their misconduct without fear of adverse action, while undermining the morale of those who adhere to police regulations and ethical norms. These decisions also carry a financial cost. Reversal of a disciplinary action will typically carry with it reinstatement to duty with back pay and benefits retroactive to the date of termination.14 Depending upon the time lag from the date of the discharge until the date of reinstatement pursuant to an arbitration award, the amount could be substantial. Back pay awards arising from arbitration cost the City of Philadelphia $2.4 million between January 2008 and June 2010.15 There are occasional local variations on this financial norm. For example, arbitrators adjudicating grievances filed by Philadelphia police officers have a practice of not simply awarding back pay when a discharge or suspension is reduced or overturned (making that individual whole, the norm in most locales), but also awarding the additional amount of money the officer would probably have earned from overtime but for the disciplinary action. For example, one officer was suspended for ten days for falsely claiming three and a half hours overtime. He was also transferred to a different unit, one in which the overtime earnings’ potential was much lower than in the officer’s prior unit of assignment. The officer filed a grievance. The arbitrator sustained the infraction of a false overtime report, and upheld the disciplinary suspension, but struck

state administrative proceeding then stripped him of his certification, making him ineligible to serve as a police officer anywhere in Minnesota. See Michael Alan Kveene, State of Minnesota Office of Admin. Hearings, Jan. 13, 1997, available at http://www.oah.state.mn.us/aljBase/24020724.rt.htm.

14 Sometimes an arbitrator will reduce discharge to a lesser penalty, e.g., a suspension of X days duration. In these instances, the back pay award is adjusted accordingly to account for the suspension.

15 David Gambacorta, Quick on the Trigger? Ramsey’s Firings Strain City Coffers, PHILA. DAILY NEWS, June 7, 2010, http://articles.philly.com/2010-06-07/news/24968128_1_firings-top-cop-internal-affairs-bureau.

Page 106: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

547 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

down the transfer as being without just cause (the applicable standard, typical in many collective bargaining agreements). The arbitrator awarded back pay (later calculated as over $83,000) to compensate the officer for over 2,000 hours of overtime he did not work, but likely would have worked, during the two and a half years from the transfer until the issuance of the arbitration award.16 Numerous other officers were similarly awarded substantial compensation for overtime not worked.17 Again, binding arbitration left the agency with no apparent recourse in these situations.

II. THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION: LEGAL UNDERPINNINGS

For decades, the prevailing legal concept has been that arbitration is a desirable process for adjudication of disputes. It is seen as quicker than conventional civil litigation, and less costly due to the absence of discovery, depositions, jury selection, and other aspects of a typical civil lawsuit. The diversion of substantial numbers of disputes into arbitration also lessens the workload of the courts. The Federal Arbitration Act, initially enacted in 1925, empowers arbitration agreements in strong, unambiguous language. An agreement to arbitrate disputes “ . . . shall be valid, irrevocable, and enforceable, save upon such grounds as exist at law or in equity for the revocation of any contract.”18 Various provisions of that Act have long been upheld through a number of U.S. Supreme Court cases. In June 2010, the Court upheld arbitration as a process for adjudicating employer-employee disputes.19 More recently, in a dispute between a consumer and a mobile phone company, the decision made it

16 City of Philadelphia and Fraternal Order of Police Lodge 5 (Officer John

Mouzon Suspension & Transfer), American Arbitration Association, AAA Case No. 14 390 01326 05 (2007).

17 Barbara Laker &Wendy Ruderman, For Some Cops, Getting Overtime Is No Work at All, PHILA. DAILY NEWS, Feb. 4, 2011, http://articles.philly.com/2011-02-04/news/27100758_1_overtime-thomas-w-jennings-arbitration-system.

18 Federal Arbitration Act, 9 U.S.C. § 2 (2006). 19 Rent-A-Ctr., W., Inc. v. Jackson, 558 U.S. 1142 (2010).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 548

clear that the Court, as currently comprised, is firmly committed to upholding the primacy of the Federal Arbitration Act.20 In the police disciplinary context, the Court’s preference for arbitration is reinforced by the fact that, in many instances, arbitration of disciplinary actions has been voluntarily agreed to by both the employer and the employees’ union or association through a collective bargaining agreement. That agreement is a contract, and courts are reluctant to set aside the results of a contractually agreed-to process for resolution of disputes arising from interpretations of that contract. Arbitration is endorsed by courts as a speedier, more cost efficient way to resolve disputes and reduce the burdens on courts. Thus, at some level, courts are reluctant to encourage post-arbitration litigation. The benefits of arbitration over court litigation are quickly dissipated if courts routinely open the doors to subsequently contest substantial numbers of arbitration decisions. To that end, it is also worth noting that when courts, either state or federal, do undertake review of an arbitration decision, there is a significant difference between that litigation and the typical court review of an administrative agency’s decision. As will be discussed later, arbitration decisions are effectively immunized against court oversight of both legal and factual findings. The scope of court review of those decisions is typically very narrow. By way of contrast, if a civil service commission or another equivalent administrative agency discharges a public employee such as a police officer, there will typically be a decision which details findings of fact and conclusions of law. While a reviewing court is obligated to show deference to the agency’s findings, especially its factual findings, neither those factual findings nor legal conclusions are immune from judicial scrutiny. Thus, for example, the Chicago Police Board, acting as a quasi-judicial administrative forum, holds hearings in cases in which the discharge of Chicago police officers is sought. A losing party—either the officer who has been disciplined, or the Superintendent of Police, if the discharge effort was unsuccessful—may seek judicial relief by filing a suit in Cook County Circuit Court, with appeal to the Illinois Appellate Court. Illinois case law provides for a two-step process.

20 AT&T Mobility L.L.C. v. Concepcion, 131 S. Ct. 1740 (2011).

Page 107: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

547 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

down the transfer as being without just cause (the applicable standard, typical in many collective bargaining agreements). The arbitrator awarded back pay (later calculated as over $83,000) to compensate the officer for over 2,000 hours of overtime he did not work, but likely would have worked, during the two and a half years from the transfer until the issuance of the arbitration award.16 Numerous other officers were similarly awarded substantial compensation for overtime not worked.17 Again, binding arbitration left the agency with no apparent recourse in these situations.

II. THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION: LEGAL UNDERPINNINGS

For decades, the prevailing legal concept has been that arbitration is a desirable process for adjudication of disputes. It is seen as quicker than conventional civil litigation, and less costly due to the absence of discovery, depositions, jury selection, and other aspects of a typical civil lawsuit. The diversion of substantial numbers of disputes into arbitration also lessens the workload of the courts. The Federal Arbitration Act, initially enacted in 1925, empowers arbitration agreements in strong, unambiguous language. An agreement to arbitrate disputes “ . . . shall be valid, irrevocable, and enforceable, save upon such grounds as exist at law or in equity for the revocation of any contract.”18 Various provisions of that Act have long been upheld through a number of U.S. Supreme Court cases. In June 2010, the Court upheld arbitration as a process for adjudicating employer-employee disputes.19 More recently, in a dispute between a consumer and a mobile phone company, the decision made it

16 City of Philadelphia and Fraternal Order of Police Lodge 5 (Officer John

Mouzon Suspension & Transfer), American Arbitration Association, AAA Case No. 14 390 01326 05 (2007).

17 Barbara Laker &Wendy Ruderman, For Some Cops, Getting Overtime Is No Work at All, PHILA. DAILY NEWS, Feb. 4, 2011, http://articles.philly.com/2011-02-04/news/27100758_1_overtime-thomas-w-jennings-arbitration-system.

18 Federal Arbitration Act, 9 U.S.C. § 2 (2006). 19 Rent-A-Ctr., W., Inc. v. Jackson, 558 U.S. 1142 (2010).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 548

clear that the Court, as currently comprised, is firmly committed to upholding the primacy of the Federal Arbitration Act.20 In the police disciplinary context, the Court’s preference for arbitration is reinforced by the fact that, in many instances, arbitration of disciplinary actions has been voluntarily agreed to by both the employer and the employees’ union or association through a collective bargaining agreement. That agreement is a contract, and courts are reluctant to set aside the results of a contractually agreed-to process for resolution of disputes arising from interpretations of that contract. Arbitration is endorsed by courts as a speedier, more cost efficient way to resolve disputes and reduce the burdens on courts. Thus, at some level, courts are reluctant to encourage post-arbitration litigation. The benefits of arbitration over court litigation are quickly dissipated if courts routinely open the doors to subsequently contest substantial numbers of arbitration decisions. To that end, it is also worth noting that when courts, either state or federal, do undertake review of an arbitration decision, there is a significant difference between that litigation and the typical court review of an administrative agency’s decision. As will be discussed later, arbitration decisions are effectively immunized against court oversight of both legal and factual findings. The scope of court review of those decisions is typically very narrow. By way of contrast, if a civil service commission or another equivalent administrative agency discharges a public employee such as a police officer, there will typically be a decision which details findings of fact and conclusions of law. While a reviewing court is obligated to show deference to the agency’s findings, especially its factual findings, neither those factual findings nor legal conclusions are immune from judicial scrutiny. Thus, for example, the Chicago Police Board, acting as a quasi-judicial administrative forum, holds hearings in cases in which the discharge of Chicago police officers is sought. A losing party—either the officer who has been disciplined, or the Superintendent of Police, if the discharge effort was unsuccessful—may seek judicial relief by filing a suit in Cook County Circuit Court, with appeal to the Illinois Appellate Court. Illinois case law provides for a two-step process.

20 AT&T Mobility L.L.C. v. Concepcion, 131 S. Ct. 1740 (2011).

Page 108: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

549 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

“First, the reviewing court must determine if the agency’s factual findings are contrary to the manifest weight of the evidence . . . . Second, the reviewing court must determine if the findings of fact provide a sufficient basis for the agency’s conclusion that cause for discharge exists.”21 While courts do give the Police Board, as the fact finder, substantial deference, that is not absolute. The decisions in these police disciplinary proceedings are subject to judicial scrutiny regarding both findings of fact and conclusions of law. Nonetheless, while arbitration is generally endorsed by courts as a means of dispute resolution, there are a number of clearly articulated, but narrow, exceptions which allow a party to arbitration to challenge a decision. The Federal Arbitration Act recognizes a number of grounds for setting aside an arbitrator’s decision. These include an award procured through corruption or fraud, evident partiality by the arbitrator, arbitrator misconduct in refusing to allow pertinent evidence or improperly denying a continuance of the proceedings or an arbitrator exceeding the scope of authority.22 The Federal Arbitration Act (FAA), while seminal legislation in this field, covers arbitrations arising from interstate commerce disputes. State and local government employees, such as police officers, would typically not be covered by its specific provisions. That gap was addressed by the promulgation of the Uniform Arbitration Act, first set forth in 1955 and revised significantly in 2000. Its grounds for setting aside an arbitration award closely parallel those set forth in the FAA. Significantly, in their comments on the proposed 2000 revisions, the drafters noted the inclusion of a public policy grounds for setting aside an arbitration award had been considered but rejected, in part because of unsettled, conflicting case law precedents in various courts, and especially in light of the absence of any public policy exception in the Federal act.23 Most states have adopted the Uniform Arbitration Act in whole or in substantial part. This usually means a public policy exception to

21 Rodriguez v. Weis, 946 N.E.2d 501, 504 (Ill. App. 2011). 22 Federal Arbitration Act, 9 U.S.C. § 10 (2006). 23 Unif. Arbitration Act § 23(C)(5) (2000).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 550

enforcement of arbitration awards is not included in the relevant statute. Thus, typically, a court challenge to an arbitrator’s decision may be initiated only for certain very limited reasons, as specified by statute. Some variations are quite narrow. For example, Texas law governing police arbitrations directly limits civil court challenges to those instances where the arbitrator or arbitration panel was “ . . . without jurisdiction or exceeded its jurisdiction or that the order was procured by fraud, collusion, or other unlawful means.”24 Thus, in a typical police disciplinary arbitration, an arbitrator who determined after a hearing there was insufficient evidence to sustain the allegations, would be within the scope of authority to reverse the officer’s discharge, order reinstatement to employment, and award back pay and benefits retroactive to the date of the officer’s discharge. However, in a hypothetical case, if the arbitrator determined the officer’s reputation had been tarnished, and the officer suffered severe emotional harm as a result of the discharge, and thus also ordered the employing police department to pay, say, $100,000 in damages, that would, under Texas law, presumably be fair game for a legal challenge to the arbitration decision. But such grounds for a legal challenge rarely occur. The typical employment arbitration award will limit itself to addressing the issue of reversing the disciplinary action, and related measures necessary to make whole the employee and undo the economic deprivation arising from that disciplinary action. Therefore, a common scenario could involve an officer serving, and then grieving, an unpaid fifteen days’ suspension from duty. If the officer prevails, the award would typically order fifteen days’ back pay be paid to the officer, and any record of the disciplinary action expunged from the officer’s record. That an arbitration decision could be successfully challenged in court because the arbitrator was corrupt, or exceeded his/her authority under the terms of the applicable collective bargaining agreement, is fairly

24 TEX. LOC. GOV’T CODE, § 143.057(j) (West 2005); TEX. LOC. GOV’T CODE §

143.1016(j) (West 2005). Sections 143.057(j) and 143.1016(j) contain identical wording. The former is applicable to all jurisdictions with populations of less than 1.5 million people; the latter is applicable to those with populations greater than 1.5 million—which at this time covers only the City of Houston.

Page 109: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

549 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

“First, the reviewing court must determine if the agency’s factual findings are contrary to the manifest weight of the evidence . . . . Second, the reviewing court must determine if the findings of fact provide a sufficient basis for the agency’s conclusion that cause for discharge exists.”21 While courts do give the Police Board, as the fact finder, substantial deference, that is not absolute. The decisions in these police disciplinary proceedings are subject to judicial scrutiny regarding both findings of fact and conclusions of law. Nonetheless, while arbitration is generally endorsed by courts as a means of dispute resolution, there are a number of clearly articulated, but narrow, exceptions which allow a party to arbitration to challenge a decision. The Federal Arbitration Act recognizes a number of grounds for setting aside an arbitrator’s decision. These include an award procured through corruption or fraud, evident partiality by the arbitrator, arbitrator misconduct in refusing to allow pertinent evidence or improperly denying a continuance of the proceedings or an arbitrator exceeding the scope of authority.22 The Federal Arbitration Act (FAA), while seminal legislation in this field, covers arbitrations arising from interstate commerce disputes. State and local government employees, such as police officers, would typically not be covered by its specific provisions. That gap was addressed by the promulgation of the Uniform Arbitration Act, first set forth in 1955 and revised significantly in 2000. Its grounds for setting aside an arbitration award closely parallel those set forth in the FAA. Significantly, in their comments on the proposed 2000 revisions, the drafters noted the inclusion of a public policy grounds for setting aside an arbitration award had been considered but rejected, in part because of unsettled, conflicting case law precedents in various courts, and especially in light of the absence of any public policy exception in the Federal act.23 Most states have adopted the Uniform Arbitration Act in whole or in substantial part. This usually means a public policy exception to

21 Rodriguez v. Weis, 946 N.E.2d 501, 504 (Ill. App. 2011). 22 Federal Arbitration Act, 9 U.S.C. § 10 (2006). 23 Unif. Arbitration Act § 23(C)(5) (2000).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 550

enforcement of arbitration awards is not included in the relevant statute. Thus, typically, a court challenge to an arbitrator’s decision may be initiated only for certain very limited reasons, as specified by statute. Some variations are quite narrow. For example, Texas law governing police arbitrations directly limits civil court challenges to those instances where the arbitrator or arbitration panel was “ . . . without jurisdiction or exceeded its jurisdiction or that the order was procured by fraud, collusion, or other unlawful means.”24 Thus, in a typical police disciplinary arbitration, an arbitrator who determined after a hearing there was insufficient evidence to sustain the allegations, would be within the scope of authority to reverse the officer’s discharge, order reinstatement to employment, and award back pay and benefits retroactive to the date of the officer’s discharge. However, in a hypothetical case, if the arbitrator determined the officer’s reputation had been tarnished, and the officer suffered severe emotional harm as a result of the discharge, and thus also ordered the employing police department to pay, say, $100,000 in damages, that would, under Texas law, presumably be fair game for a legal challenge to the arbitration decision. But such grounds for a legal challenge rarely occur. The typical employment arbitration award will limit itself to addressing the issue of reversing the disciplinary action, and related measures necessary to make whole the employee and undo the economic deprivation arising from that disciplinary action. Therefore, a common scenario could involve an officer serving, and then grieving, an unpaid fifteen days’ suspension from duty. If the officer prevails, the award would typically order fifteen days’ back pay be paid to the officer, and any record of the disciplinary action expunged from the officer’s record. That an arbitration decision could be successfully challenged in court because the arbitrator was corrupt, or exceeded his/her authority under the terms of the applicable collective bargaining agreement, is fairly

24 TEX. LOC. GOV’T CODE, § 143.057(j) (West 2005); TEX. LOC. GOV’T CODE §

143.1016(j) (West 2005). Sections 143.057(j) and 143.1016(j) contain identical wording. The former is applicable to all jurisdictions with populations of less than 1.5 million people; the latter is applicable to those with populations greater than 1.5 million—which at this time covers only the City of Houston.

Page 110: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

551 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

straightforward. But these grounds for reversal are simply absent in the typical police disciplinary arbitration. Most pertinent for this paper, however, is the public policy exception. At the federal level, the seminal U.S. Supreme Court case in this area is W.R. Grace and Co. v. Rubber Workers. The Court stated:

[A] court may not enforce a collective bargaining agreement that is contrary to public policy. . . . If the contract as interpreted by [the arbitrator] violates some explicit public policy, we are obliged to refrain from enforcing it. . . . Such a public policy, however, must be well defined and dominant, and is to be ascertained “by reference to the laws and legal precedents and not from general considerations of supposed public interests.”25

The Court subsequently made clear that reviewing courts may not substitute their own fact-finding for that of the arbitrator. Thus, in the Misco case,26 a factory worker was discharged for possession and use of marijuana on company premises, a violation of company policy. Arbitration reinstated him. The employer acted to have the arbitration award set aside on public policy grounds, as the employee posed a threat by operating hazardous machinery at work while under the influence of drugs. While the Fifth Circuit set aside the arbitration award, the Supreme Court reversed the decision. The Supreme Court noted that not only had the Fifth Circuit overridden the arbitrator’s fact-finding, it had also failed to establish a clear, well-defined and dominant public policy against the operation of hazardous machinery while under the influence of illegal drugs.27 Even if the accused employee’s misconduct violates a clear public policy, that in and of itself is not necessarily grounds for court action to reverse an arbitration decision. The U.S. Supreme Court confronted the

25 W.R. Grace & Co. v. Local Union 759, 461 U.S. 757, 766 (1983) (emphasis

added) (citations omitted). 26 United Paperworkers Int’l Union, AFL-CIO v. Misco, Inc., 484 U.S. 29

(1987). 27 Id. at 39, 44.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 552

issue of an arbitration decision which reduced an employer-imposed penalty of discharge to a suspension of three months in the Eastern Associated Coal case. In that case, the employee, a truck driver, had failed a random drug screen test as mandated by U.S. Department of Transportation regulations. Even though public policy explicitly called for drug-free truck operators as a key public policy concern, in the Court’s eyes, that was not sufficient to mandate reversal of the arbitration decision. The Court noted the key question is “not whether [the employee’s] drug use itself violates public policy, but whether the agreement to reinstate him does so.”28 Grounds for court intervention in arbitration proceedings were further narrowed in the case of Hall Street Associates L.L.C. v. Mattel, Inc.29 The Supreme Court held that the FAA’s narrow grounds for vacatur of arbitration decisions are mandatory, and may not be expanded. Thus, reversals of arbitration awards on grounds such as “manifest disregard of the law” would, presumably, no longer be valid. This rationale has been interpreted by some as essentially sounding the death knell for reversing arbitration awards on public policy grounds.30 However, note that the Court addressed court review of arbitration decisions under the FAA. As will be later discussed, challenges to police disciplinary arbitrations are typically brought in state court under state law jurisdiction. Thus, the applicability of Hall Street to these questions is presumably not controlling. Empirical research, immediately predating the Hall Street case, examined the outcomes of challenges to arbitration decisions, with an eye towards how ready courts were to uphold the finality of those decisions.31 Attributing the pattern to changes in the Revised Uniform Arbitration Act,

28 E. Associated Coal Corp. v. Mine Workers of Am., Dist. 17, 531 U.S. 57, 62-

63 (2000). 29 Hall St. Assocs. L.L.C. v. Mattel, Inc., 552 U.S. 576 (2008). 30 Jonathan A. Marcantel, The Crumbled Difference Between Legal and Illegal

Arbitration Awards: Hall Street Associates and the Waning Public Policy Exception, 14 FORDHAM J. CORP. & FIN. L. 597 (2009).

31 Michael H. LeRoy, Misguided Fairness? Regulating Arbitration by Statute: Empirical Evidence of Declining Award Finality, 83 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 551 (2008).

Page 111: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

551 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

straightforward. But these grounds for reversal are simply absent in the typical police disciplinary arbitration. Most pertinent for this paper, however, is the public policy exception. At the federal level, the seminal U.S. Supreme Court case in this area is W.R. Grace and Co. v. Rubber Workers. The Court stated:

[A] court may not enforce a collective bargaining agreement that is contrary to public policy. . . . If the contract as interpreted by [the arbitrator] violates some explicit public policy, we are obliged to refrain from enforcing it. . . . Such a public policy, however, must be well defined and dominant, and is to be ascertained “by reference to the laws and legal precedents and not from general considerations of supposed public interests.”25

The Court subsequently made clear that reviewing courts may not substitute their own fact-finding for that of the arbitrator. Thus, in the Misco case,26 a factory worker was discharged for possession and use of marijuana on company premises, a violation of company policy. Arbitration reinstated him. The employer acted to have the arbitration award set aside on public policy grounds, as the employee posed a threat by operating hazardous machinery at work while under the influence of drugs. While the Fifth Circuit set aside the arbitration award, the Supreme Court reversed the decision. The Supreme Court noted that not only had the Fifth Circuit overridden the arbitrator’s fact-finding, it had also failed to establish a clear, well-defined and dominant public policy against the operation of hazardous machinery while under the influence of illegal drugs.27 Even if the accused employee’s misconduct violates a clear public policy, that in and of itself is not necessarily grounds for court action to reverse an arbitration decision. The U.S. Supreme Court confronted the

25 W.R. Grace & Co. v. Local Union 759, 461 U.S. 757, 766 (1983) (emphasis

added) (citations omitted). 26 United Paperworkers Int’l Union, AFL-CIO v. Misco, Inc., 484 U.S. 29

(1987). 27 Id. at 39, 44.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 552

issue of an arbitration decision which reduced an employer-imposed penalty of discharge to a suspension of three months in the Eastern Associated Coal case. In that case, the employee, a truck driver, had failed a random drug screen test as mandated by U.S. Department of Transportation regulations. Even though public policy explicitly called for drug-free truck operators as a key public policy concern, in the Court’s eyes, that was not sufficient to mandate reversal of the arbitration decision. The Court noted the key question is “not whether [the employee’s] drug use itself violates public policy, but whether the agreement to reinstate him does so.”28 Grounds for court intervention in arbitration proceedings were further narrowed in the case of Hall Street Associates L.L.C. v. Mattel, Inc.29 The Supreme Court held that the FAA’s narrow grounds for vacatur of arbitration decisions are mandatory, and may not be expanded. Thus, reversals of arbitration awards on grounds such as “manifest disregard of the law” would, presumably, no longer be valid. This rationale has been interpreted by some as essentially sounding the death knell for reversing arbitration awards on public policy grounds.30 However, note that the Court addressed court review of arbitration decisions under the FAA. As will be later discussed, challenges to police disciplinary arbitrations are typically brought in state court under state law jurisdiction. Thus, the applicability of Hall Street to these questions is presumably not controlling. Empirical research, immediately predating the Hall Street case, examined the outcomes of challenges to arbitration decisions, with an eye towards how ready courts were to uphold the finality of those decisions.31 Attributing the pattern to changes in the Revised Uniform Arbitration Act,

28 E. Associated Coal Corp. v. Mine Workers of Am., Dist. 17, 531 U.S. 57, 62-

63 (2000). 29 Hall St. Assocs. L.L.C. v. Mattel, Inc., 552 U.S. 576 (2008). 30 Jonathan A. Marcantel, The Crumbled Difference Between Legal and Illegal

Arbitration Awards: Hall Street Associates and the Waning Public Policy Exception, 14 FORDHAM J. CORP. & FIN. L. 597 (2009).

31 Michael H. LeRoy, Misguided Fairness? Regulating Arbitration by Statute: Empirical Evidence of Declining Award Finality, 83 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 551 (2008).

Page 112: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

553 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

the author documented that state courts have shown an overall lesser willingness to confirm arbitration decisions than federal courts have. Confirmation rates at the trial court level were 92.7% in U.S. courts, but only 78.8% in state courts; the respective figures for appellate level courts were 87.7% and 71.4%.32 What is crucial for police managers is the extent to which various state appellate courts, and courts of last resort, have interpreted the Hall Street case rationale, and applied it to the various factual scenarios presented in police disciplinary cases. At this point, before considering whether to initiate a court challenge to an unfavorable arbitration decision, a crucial question for a police chief to ask is the basis of the arbitrator’s reversal of discipline. Broadly speaking, reversals can be categorized into two groups: (1) Yes, the officer did in fact commit the alleged misconduct (in whole or in part), but discharge is not warranted because the penalty is too harsh, certain procedural rights were violated, the penalty is disproportionate to that meted out to other officers guilty of similar actions, etc., and thus the penalty should be eliminated or reduced; and (2) No, the officer’s misconduct cannot be proven, and therefore no penalty at all should be imposed. Let us address the first group: those cases in which arbitrators agree that officers’ misconduct was proven. That a police officer’s conduct can be convincingly shown as contrary to an established public policy does not, in and of itself, ensure that a police chief’s efforts to reverse an arbitration decision to reinstate the officer will be successful. Recall the Supreme Court’s Eastern Coal decision. It is not a question of whether the officer’s conduct violated public policy, but whether reinstating the officer to duty would do so. Presumably, one could argue that an arbitration decision which reverses an officer’s discharge, and orders the officer’s reinstatement, but with a lesser penalty, such as a suspension of X duration, is not contrary to public policy. After all, such a decision is not tolerating the offensive conduct; it is simply imposing an alternative penalty, a lesser sanction. Under those conditions, a court may,

32 Id. at 556.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 554

not shall, set aside the arbitration decision. There is room for judicial discretion here. What of the second group, those cases in which the arbitrator’s reinstatement is based upon the conclusion that no officer misconduct has been proven? Typically, an arbitration proceeds as a quasi-judicial hearing. These are adversarial proceedings. Each party may call witnesses, who are subject to both direct and cross examination. The decision will thus be drawn upon the arbitrator’s assessment of the demeanor and credibility of the witnesses. An arbitrator may reverse an internal affairs’ sustained finding of misconduct, and the chief’s resultant disciplinary penalty, based upon those credibility conclusions. Under these circumstances, a chief’s challenge of an unfavorable decision will run into a serious problem. Our legal system in general affords great deference to the fact finder’s credibility assessment, and also expects courts to show great deference to the arbitrators’ decisions. Unlike appellate courts reviewing the proceedings of a trial court, courts will typically not address whether the arbitrator committed errors of fact or law. “The strong public policy favoring arbitration requires us to uphold an arbitrator’s decision even where it is wrong on the facts or the law, and whether it is wise or foolish, clear or ambiguous.”33 The whole notion of arbitration is to offer a speedier, less costly alternative to court litigation. If courts were to engage in a broad pattern of second guessing arbitrators’ findings of fact and conclusions of law, that could easily lead to a very substantial increase in litigation, totally negating the key justification for using arbitration in the first place. Thus, cases of this type (i.e., an arbitrator found the employee factually not guilty) are typically absent from the court cases lodged on public policy grounds.34 This two-fold categorization of the bases for arbitration decisions reversing police discipline is made more complex in that some arbitration decisions will include components of both categories. For instance, a chief

33 City of Boston v. Boston Police Patrolmen’s Ass’n, 443 Mass. 813, 818 (2005).

34 Of the many dozens of court cases involving arbitration and public policy researched in the course of this project, the author encountered not a single one in which the arbitrator simply found the accused officer (or other public employee) not guilty on factual grounds.

Page 113: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

553 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

the author documented that state courts have shown an overall lesser willingness to confirm arbitration decisions than federal courts have. Confirmation rates at the trial court level were 92.7% in U.S. courts, but only 78.8% in state courts; the respective figures for appellate level courts were 87.7% and 71.4%.32 What is crucial for police managers is the extent to which various state appellate courts, and courts of last resort, have interpreted the Hall Street case rationale, and applied it to the various factual scenarios presented in police disciplinary cases. At this point, before considering whether to initiate a court challenge to an unfavorable arbitration decision, a crucial question for a police chief to ask is the basis of the arbitrator’s reversal of discipline. Broadly speaking, reversals can be categorized into two groups: (1) Yes, the officer did in fact commit the alleged misconduct (in whole or in part), but discharge is not warranted because the penalty is too harsh, certain procedural rights were violated, the penalty is disproportionate to that meted out to other officers guilty of similar actions, etc., and thus the penalty should be eliminated or reduced; and (2) No, the officer’s misconduct cannot be proven, and therefore no penalty at all should be imposed. Let us address the first group: those cases in which arbitrators agree that officers’ misconduct was proven. That a police officer’s conduct can be convincingly shown as contrary to an established public policy does not, in and of itself, ensure that a police chief’s efforts to reverse an arbitration decision to reinstate the officer will be successful. Recall the Supreme Court’s Eastern Coal decision. It is not a question of whether the officer’s conduct violated public policy, but whether reinstating the officer to duty would do so. Presumably, one could argue that an arbitration decision which reverses an officer’s discharge, and orders the officer’s reinstatement, but with a lesser penalty, such as a suspension of X duration, is not contrary to public policy. After all, such a decision is not tolerating the offensive conduct; it is simply imposing an alternative penalty, a lesser sanction. Under those conditions, a court may,

32 Id. at 556.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 554

not shall, set aside the arbitration decision. There is room for judicial discretion here. What of the second group, those cases in which the arbitrator’s reinstatement is based upon the conclusion that no officer misconduct has been proven? Typically, an arbitration proceeds as a quasi-judicial hearing. These are adversarial proceedings. Each party may call witnesses, who are subject to both direct and cross examination. The decision will thus be drawn upon the arbitrator’s assessment of the demeanor and credibility of the witnesses. An arbitrator may reverse an internal affairs’ sustained finding of misconduct, and the chief’s resultant disciplinary penalty, based upon those credibility conclusions. Under these circumstances, a chief’s challenge of an unfavorable decision will run into a serious problem. Our legal system in general affords great deference to the fact finder’s credibility assessment, and also expects courts to show great deference to the arbitrators’ decisions. Unlike appellate courts reviewing the proceedings of a trial court, courts will typically not address whether the arbitrator committed errors of fact or law. “The strong public policy favoring arbitration requires us to uphold an arbitrator’s decision even where it is wrong on the facts or the law, and whether it is wise or foolish, clear or ambiguous.”33 The whole notion of arbitration is to offer a speedier, less costly alternative to court litigation. If courts were to engage in a broad pattern of second guessing arbitrators’ findings of fact and conclusions of law, that could easily lead to a very substantial increase in litigation, totally negating the key justification for using arbitration in the first place. Thus, cases of this type (i.e., an arbitrator found the employee factually not guilty) are typically absent from the court cases lodged on public policy grounds.34 This two-fold categorization of the bases for arbitration decisions reversing police discipline is made more complex in that some arbitration decisions will include components of both categories. For instance, a chief

33 City of Boston v. Boston Police Patrolmen’s Ass’n, 443 Mass. 813, 818 (2005).

34 Of the many dozens of court cases involving arbitration and public policy researched in the course of this project, the author encountered not a single one in which the arbitrator simply found the accused officer (or other public employee) not guilty on factual grounds.

Page 114: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

555 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

may order an officer’s discharge based on an internal investigation which concluded there were sustained violations of departmental rules X and Y. An arbitrator may determine, after a hearing, that the testimony supports a guilty decision as to violation of Rule X, but not Rule Y. With one guilty finding struck down, the arbitrator may then conclude the now-reduced infractions do not justify a penalty of discharge, and thus reduce the penalty. Anecdotal evidence suggests it is the first category (upholding guilt but reducing the penalty), not the second, which especially galls police managers. That a presumably neutral third party heard the witnesses and concluded there was insufficient evidence to prove misconduct is something which many police chiefs may, albeit with some grumbling, accept. What particularly frustrates police chiefs are cases in which the underlying misconduct was deemed proven by the arbitrator, who nonetheless determined it was ‘no big deal’ and reduced a significant penalty to something much more lenient. Consider the St. Paul officer discussed above, in which the arbitrator stated in essence, yes, he was a convicted sex offender, but it was only a misdemeanor, so let him come back to work as a cop.35 As another example, two Cincinnati, Ohio officers were fired for having sex, while on duty, with a clearly intoxicated woman, whom they had escorted to her apartment. They lied about the incident during the course of the subsequent internal investigation. These facts were uncontested, confirmed in separate decisions, one for each of the two officers.36 Citing procedural lapses in the internal investigation and the department’s own matrix of penalties for various disciplinary infractions, one arbitrator reduced one officer’s penalty from discharge to a suspension of five days; the second arbitrator reduced the other officer’s penalty from discharge to a three days’ suspension.37 The case of

35 See, supra note 13. 36 These cases illustrate a problem in police regulations: given the wide variety

of situations in which police officers can become involved, it is extremely difficult to devise a set of regulations which can address every potential type of misconduct. Cincinnati did not have a rule that explicitly barred on-duty officers from having sexual relations with intoxicated citizens.

37 In the Matter of the Arbitration Between Queen City Lodge No. 69, Fraternal Order of Police and City of Cincinnati, Ohio, American Arbitration Association, AAA

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 556

Pennsylvania State Trooper Smith, to be discussed later (drunk, he accosted his ex-girlfriend, placing his gun in her mouth), is yet another example of this phenomenon. For the purposes of this paper, it is these very cases in which arbitrators agree the officers are guilty of various infractions (and typically very serious infractions), but deem the penalties too harsh, that also offer the potential for reversal on public policy grounds. Over and above contractual language and case law precedents, one needs to recognize a pervasive political reality. Almost invariably, appeals of arbitration decisions involving state, city or county public employees fall under the jurisdiction of state courts, not federal courts. Nationally, in the U.S., a very substantial proportion of state court judges are elected. Police officers are, in both large cities and not so large communities, heavily unionized—and these unions tend to be politically very active. The electoral endorsement of an officers’ union is no doubt seen as a desirable asset by most judicial candidates. Conversely, most candidates would wish to avoid raising these unions’ ire and earning their enmity and electoral opposition. This raises the very real possibility that especially at the margin, in those cases where the law is not absolutely clear cut and a judge has discretion in deciding a case, a judge may tacitly decide not to antagonize officers and their union by reversing a favorable (from the union’s perspective) arbitration decision. The role of campaign finance donations in shaping judicial decision making has been convincingly demonstrated elsewhere.38 Another study noted that corporate employers fared significantly better in post-arbitration litigation in those courts staffed by judges chosen through partisan elections.39 It is not unreasonable to speculate that other pressures, such as potential union endorsements or opposition, could affect judicial decisions in these cases.

Case No. 52 390 0006 03; In the Matter of the Arbitration Between Queen City Lodge No. 69, Fraternal Order of Police and City of Cincinnati, Ohio, American Arbitration Association, AAA Case No. 52 390 0007 03.

38 Vernon Valentine Palmer & John Levendis, The Louisiana Supreme Court in Question: An Empirical and Statistical Study of the Effects of Campaign Money on the Judicial Function, 82 TULANE L. REV. 1291–1314 (2008).

39 Michael H. LeRoy, Do Partisan Elections of Judges Produce Unequal Justice When Courts Review Employment Arbitrations?, 95 IOWA L. REV. 1569 (2010).

Page 115: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

555 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

may order an officer’s discharge based on an internal investigation which concluded there were sustained violations of departmental rules X and Y. An arbitrator may determine, after a hearing, that the testimony supports a guilty decision as to violation of Rule X, but not Rule Y. With one guilty finding struck down, the arbitrator may then conclude the now-reduced infractions do not justify a penalty of discharge, and thus reduce the penalty. Anecdotal evidence suggests it is the first category (upholding guilt but reducing the penalty), not the second, which especially galls police managers. That a presumably neutral third party heard the witnesses and concluded there was insufficient evidence to prove misconduct is something which many police chiefs may, albeit with some grumbling, accept. What particularly frustrates police chiefs are cases in which the underlying misconduct was deemed proven by the arbitrator, who nonetheless determined it was ‘no big deal’ and reduced a significant penalty to something much more lenient. Consider the St. Paul officer discussed above, in which the arbitrator stated in essence, yes, he was a convicted sex offender, but it was only a misdemeanor, so let him come back to work as a cop.35 As another example, two Cincinnati, Ohio officers were fired for having sex, while on duty, with a clearly intoxicated woman, whom they had escorted to her apartment. They lied about the incident during the course of the subsequent internal investigation. These facts were uncontested, confirmed in separate decisions, one for each of the two officers.36 Citing procedural lapses in the internal investigation and the department’s own matrix of penalties for various disciplinary infractions, one arbitrator reduced one officer’s penalty from discharge to a suspension of five days; the second arbitrator reduced the other officer’s penalty from discharge to a three days’ suspension.37 The case of

35 See, supra note 13. 36 These cases illustrate a problem in police regulations: given the wide variety

of situations in which police officers can become involved, it is extremely difficult to devise a set of regulations which can address every potential type of misconduct. Cincinnati did not have a rule that explicitly barred on-duty officers from having sexual relations with intoxicated citizens.

37 In the Matter of the Arbitration Between Queen City Lodge No. 69, Fraternal Order of Police and City of Cincinnati, Ohio, American Arbitration Association, AAA

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 556

Pennsylvania State Trooper Smith, to be discussed later (drunk, he accosted his ex-girlfriend, placing his gun in her mouth), is yet another example of this phenomenon. For the purposes of this paper, it is these very cases in which arbitrators agree the officers are guilty of various infractions (and typically very serious infractions), but deem the penalties too harsh, that also offer the potential for reversal on public policy grounds. Over and above contractual language and case law precedents, one needs to recognize a pervasive political reality. Almost invariably, appeals of arbitration decisions involving state, city or county public employees fall under the jurisdiction of state courts, not federal courts. Nationally, in the U.S., a very substantial proportion of state court judges are elected. Police officers are, in both large cities and not so large communities, heavily unionized—and these unions tend to be politically very active. The electoral endorsement of an officers’ union is no doubt seen as a desirable asset by most judicial candidates. Conversely, most candidates would wish to avoid raising these unions’ ire and earning their enmity and electoral opposition. This raises the very real possibility that especially at the margin, in those cases where the law is not absolutely clear cut and a judge has discretion in deciding a case, a judge may tacitly decide not to antagonize officers and their union by reversing a favorable (from the union’s perspective) arbitration decision. The role of campaign finance donations in shaping judicial decision making has been convincingly demonstrated elsewhere.38 Another study noted that corporate employers fared significantly better in post-arbitration litigation in those courts staffed by judges chosen through partisan elections.39 It is not unreasonable to speculate that other pressures, such as potential union endorsements or opposition, could affect judicial decisions in these cases.

Case No. 52 390 0006 03; In the Matter of the Arbitration Between Queen City Lodge No. 69, Fraternal Order of Police and City of Cincinnati, Ohio, American Arbitration Association, AAA Case No. 52 390 0007 03.

38 Vernon Valentine Palmer & John Levendis, The Louisiana Supreme Court in Question: An Empirical and Statistical Study of the Effects of Campaign Money on the Judicial Function, 82 TULANE L. REV. 1291–1314 (2008).

39 Michael H. LeRoy, Do Partisan Elections of Judges Produce Unequal Justice When Courts Review Employment Arbitrations?, 95 IOWA L. REV. 1569 (2010).

Page 116: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

557 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Even in the absence of any actual case outcomes affected by this, police chiefs’ and city/county attorneys’ perceptions that judicial decision making might be impacted this way can likely, in some jurisdictions, exercise a significant deterrent effect, blocking such cases from being pursued in court. And the political power of police officers’ (and, to a lesser extent, firefighters’) unions is a major reality, not just a perception, in many jurisdictions. For example, during the winter of 2011, national attention was focused on Wisconsin, where the Governor and state legislature enacted a law that wholly decimated collective bargaining rights of state and local government employees. Significantly, and much less well-known, that law exempted from its coverage police and fire employees.40 In California, that state’s Supreme Court, in the Copley Press case, effectively forced all of California’s numerous citizen oversight panels to cease holding public hearings, citing confidentiality requirements in a state public employee personnel statute.41 Decided on a specific interpretation of statutory wording, and not on federal or state constitutional grounds, the remedy (for those supporting public hearings) was in theory simple: a narrow amendment of the statute. Although supported by a variety of organizations, including the American Civil Liberties Union, news media, and citizen oversight groups, the legislation was opposed by police unions. More than one hundred union representatives showed up when the appropriate legislative committee was to take action on the bill. With that show of opposition, the entire committee (except for the bill’s sponsor) literally remained silent when the bill was called for a vote, effectively killing the measure.42 And in Wisconsin, state law has been amended over time to require that the City of Milwaukee pay police officers, discharged

40 Steven Greenhouse, Ohio’s Anti-Union Law Is Tougher Than Wisconsin’s,

N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 31, 2011, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2011/04/01/us/01ohio.html?scp=1&sq=wisconsin%20collective%20bargaining%20police&st=cse.

41 Copley Press, Inc. v. Super. Ct., 39 Cal. 4th 1272 (2006). 42 Mark Schlossberg, Lawmakers Submit to Police Union Threats: Recent Press,

ACLU of Santa Cruz County, CA, available at http://www.aclusantacruz.org/node/145.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 558

for cause, their full salaries during the pendency of their appeals of their discharges.43 These are but three examples of a widespread reality. The precise impact of such political pressure by officers’ unions on behalf of their members facing disciplinary action cannot be definitively measured, but one would have to be very naïve to conclude such extra-legal factors are not pertinent.

III. THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION IN OPERATION

Previous studies have examined how courts have addressed the public policy exception. One study limited its scope to cases litigated in U.S. courts.44 The subject matter here—police officer disciplinary arbitration—is however exclusively a matter for state court adjudication. Another study examined New York state court dispositions of challenges to arbitration awards, noting rates of arbitration affirmation/reversals across the various regions of that state. While very useful from an

43 Gina Barton & John Diedrich, Three Democrats Seek Gov. Walker Veto of

Plan to Pay Fired Officers, MILWAUKEE SENTINEL J., June 20, 2011, available at http://www.jsonline.com/news/statepolitics/124209678.html. The irrationality of requiring significant pay for work not performed should resonate with Marx Brothers fans, who may recall an exchange in Animal Crackers in which Groucho Marx asked Chico (playing a musician) how much he and Harpo charged for performing:

“Chico: For playing, we get-a ten dollars an hour.

Groucho: I see. What do you get for not playing?

Chico: Twelve dollars an hour. . . Now for rehearsing, we make special rate. That’s-a fifteen dollars an hour. . .

Groucho: And what do you get for not rehearsing?

Chico: You couldn’t afford it. . .”

Tim Dirks, Animal Crackers (1930), AMC FILMSITE, www.filmsite.org/anim.html.

44 Ann C. Hodges, Judicial Review of Arbitration Awards on Public Policy Grounds: Lessons from the Case Law, 16 OHIO ST. J. ON DISP. RESOL. 91 (2000).

Page 117: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

557 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Even in the absence of any actual case outcomes affected by this, police chiefs’ and city/county attorneys’ perceptions that judicial decision making might be impacted this way can likely, in some jurisdictions, exercise a significant deterrent effect, blocking such cases from being pursued in court. And the political power of police officers’ (and, to a lesser extent, firefighters’) unions is a major reality, not just a perception, in many jurisdictions. For example, during the winter of 2011, national attention was focused on Wisconsin, where the Governor and state legislature enacted a law that wholly decimated collective bargaining rights of state and local government employees. Significantly, and much less well-known, that law exempted from its coverage police and fire employees.40 In California, that state’s Supreme Court, in the Copley Press case, effectively forced all of California’s numerous citizen oversight panels to cease holding public hearings, citing confidentiality requirements in a state public employee personnel statute.41 Decided on a specific interpretation of statutory wording, and not on federal or state constitutional grounds, the remedy (for those supporting public hearings) was in theory simple: a narrow amendment of the statute. Although supported by a variety of organizations, including the American Civil Liberties Union, news media, and citizen oversight groups, the legislation was opposed by police unions. More than one hundred union representatives showed up when the appropriate legislative committee was to take action on the bill. With that show of opposition, the entire committee (except for the bill’s sponsor) literally remained silent when the bill was called for a vote, effectively killing the measure.42 And in Wisconsin, state law has been amended over time to require that the City of Milwaukee pay police officers, discharged

40 Steven Greenhouse, Ohio’s Anti-Union Law Is Tougher Than Wisconsin’s,

N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 31, 2011, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2011/04/01/us/01ohio.html?scp=1&sq=wisconsin%20collective%20bargaining%20police&st=cse.

41 Copley Press, Inc. v. Super. Ct., 39 Cal. 4th 1272 (2006). 42 Mark Schlossberg, Lawmakers Submit to Police Union Threats: Recent Press,

ACLU of Santa Cruz County, CA, available at http://www.aclusantacruz.org/node/145.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 558

for cause, their full salaries during the pendency of their appeals of their discharges.43 These are but three examples of a widespread reality. The precise impact of such political pressure by officers’ unions on behalf of their members facing disciplinary action cannot be definitively measured, but one would have to be very naïve to conclude such extra-legal factors are not pertinent.

III. THE PUBLIC POLICY EXCEPTION IN OPERATION

Previous studies have examined how courts have addressed the public policy exception. One study limited its scope to cases litigated in U.S. courts.44 The subject matter here—police officer disciplinary arbitration—is however exclusively a matter for state court adjudication. Another study examined New York state court dispositions of challenges to arbitration awards, noting rates of arbitration affirmation/reversals across the various regions of that state. While very useful from an

43 Gina Barton & John Diedrich, Three Democrats Seek Gov. Walker Veto of

Plan to Pay Fired Officers, MILWAUKEE SENTINEL J., June 20, 2011, available at http://www.jsonline.com/news/statepolitics/124209678.html. The irrationality of requiring significant pay for work not performed should resonate with Marx Brothers fans, who may recall an exchange in Animal Crackers in which Groucho Marx asked Chico (playing a musician) how much he and Harpo charged for performing:

“Chico: For playing, we get-a ten dollars an hour.

Groucho: I see. What do you get for not playing?

Chico: Twelve dollars an hour. . . Now for rehearsing, we make special rate. That’s-a fifteen dollars an hour. . .

Groucho: And what do you get for not rehearsing?

Chico: You couldn’t afford it. . .”

Tim Dirks, Animal Crackers (1930), AMC FILMSITE, www.filmsite.org/anim.html.

44 Ann C. Hodges, Judicial Review of Arbitration Awards on Public Policy Grounds: Lessons from the Case Law, 16 OHIO ST. J. ON DISP. RESOL. 91 (2000).

Page 118: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

559 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

empirical stance, highlighting overall patterns in that state’s courts, the study looked at all arbitration cases subsequently litigated, with no special focus on public policy exceptions.45 The author noted in that state, the Court of Appeals has limited court reversals of arbitration on public policy grounds in cases arising from public sector employment, based on specific legislation.46 What insights can be gleaned? Legal efforts to reverse unfavorable (from the chiefs’ perspectives) arbitration decisions have had mixed results. Various cases discussed below will illustrate the potentials and pitfalls of such efforts. A comprehensive fifty states’ overview of this issue is beyond the scope of this study. The intent here is to shed light on the phenomenon by drawing upon cases from several states. These examples will show clearly that the pattern varies significantly from state to state, depending in large part on the case law precedents from appellate courts and courts of last resort in those states. The case studies which follow are listed in a rough continuum, starting with the states with courts that appear least receptive to public policy claims (Pennsylvania and Texas), followed by a state which has just begun to open the door to such claims (Nebraska), and on to states which appear increasingly more receptive to such claims (Massachusetts, Illinois, and especially Connecticut).

A. PENNSYLVANIA

In contrast to other states, Pennsylvania presents an example of case law expansion of statutory language so as to effectively bar almost any public policy exception. In 1968, the Pennsylvania legislature enacted Act 111.47 This Act afforded police officers and firefighters in that state the right to engage in collective bargaining. The Act went on to outline the

45 Monica R. Skanes, The Truth Behind “Final and Binding” Arbitration: A

Study of Vacated Arbitration Awards in the New York State Appellate Division, 74 ALB. L. REV. 983 (2011).

46 Id. at 997. 47 43 PA. STAT. ANN. § 217.1 (West).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 560

process to be followed when there is an impasse in reaching a collective bargaining agreement. The process requires a three member arbitration panel. The panel’s decision is binding, the Act stating (relative to any such decision): “No appeal therefrom shall be allowed to any court.”48 Note once again this act illustrates the special position these public safety employees enjoy relative to other civil servants, presumably yet another example of the political influence wielded by police and fire unions. There is only tangential mention of grievances in the opening section, which states that police and fire personnel “. . . shall have the right to an adjustment or settlement of their grievances or disputes in accordance with the terms of this act.”49 The detailed requirements of arbitration which follow in the rest of this Act make no reference whatsoever to an individual employee’s grievances. The wording makes it quite clear the arbitration process, as described, applies to what is generally known as interest arbitration. Typically, that refers to arbitration used in reaching an overall collective bargaining agreement, resolving employee-employer differences over wages, overtime, benefits, holiday and vacation, and other common conditions of employment. Despite the statute’s near-silence on the issue of individual employees’ disciplinary-related grievances, the case law history of Pennsylvania shows that courts have issued decisions which expand, rather than contract, the coverage of Act 111. In Chirico, the Pennsylvania Supreme Court addressed the apparent contradiction within Act 111: granting police and fire employees the right to having their grievances settled, but not specifying how those grievances would be settled.

We acknowledge it is clearly inadequate to recognize a right "to a settlement of grievances or disputes", while failing to provide any method for the implementation of those rights. This obvious vacuum must not be countenanced. Yet resort to the courts to meet this need would contravene the strong affirmance of the use of non-adversarial methods for the resolution of disputes between

48 Id. at § 217.7(a). 49 Id. at § 217.1.

Page 119: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

559 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

empirical stance, highlighting overall patterns in that state’s courts, the study looked at all arbitration cases subsequently litigated, with no special focus on public policy exceptions.45 The author noted in that state, the Court of Appeals has limited court reversals of arbitration on public policy grounds in cases arising from public sector employment, based on specific legislation.46 What insights can be gleaned? Legal efforts to reverse unfavorable (from the chiefs’ perspectives) arbitration decisions have had mixed results. Various cases discussed below will illustrate the potentials and pitfalls of such efforts. A comprehensive fifty states’ overview of this issue is beyond the scope of this study. The intent here is to shed light on the phenomenon by drawing upon cases from several states. These examples will show clearly that the pattern varies significantly from state to state, depending in large part on the case law precedents from appellate courts and courts of last resort in those states. The case studies which follow are listed in a rough continuum, starting with the states with courts that appear least receptive to public policy claims (Pennsylvania and Texas), followed by a state which has just begun to open the door to such claims (Nebraska), and on to states which appear increasingly more receptive to such claims (Massachusetts, Illinois, and especially Connecticut).

A. PENNSYLVANIA

In contrast to other states, Pennsylvania presents an example of case law expansion of statutory language so as to effectively bar almost any public policy exception. In 1968, the Pennsylvania legislature enacted Act 111.47 This Act afforded police officers and firefighters in that state the right to engage in collective bargaining. The Act went on to outline the

45 Monica R. Skanes, The Truth Behind “Final and Binding” Arbitration: A

Study of Vacated Arbitration Awards in the New York State Appellate Division, 74 ALB. L. REV. 983 (2011).

46 Id. at 997. 47 43 PA. STAT. ANN. § 217.1 (West).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 560

process to be followed when there is an impasse in reaching a collective bargaining agreement. The process requires a three member arbitration panel. The panel’s decision is binding, the Act stating (relative to any such decision): “No appeal therefrom shall be allowed to any court.”48 Note once again this act illustrates the special position these public safety employees enjoy relative to other civil servants, presumably yet another example of the political influence wielded by police and fire unions. There is only tangential mention of grievances in the opening section, which states that police and fire personnel “. . . shall have the right to an adjustment or settlement of their grievances or disputes in accordance with the terms of this act.”49 The detailed requirements of arbitration which follow in the rest of this Act make no reference whatsoever to an individual employee’s grievances. The wording makes it quite clear the arbitration process, as described, applies to what is generally known as interest arbitration. Typically, that refers to arbitration used in reaching an overall collective bargaining agreement, resolving employee-employer differences over wages, overtime, benefits, holiday and vacation, and other common conditions of employment. Despite the statute’s near-silence on the issue of individual employees’ disciplinary-related grievances, the case law history of Pennsylvania shows that courts have issued decisions which expand, rather than contract, the coverage of Act 111. In Chirico, the Pennsylvania Supreme Court addressed the apparent contradiction within Act 111: granting police and fire employees the right to having their grievances settled, but not specifying how those grievances would be settled.

We acknowledge it is clearly inadequate to recognize a right "to a settlement of grievances or disputes", while failing to provide any method for the implementation of those rights. This obvious vacuum must not be countenanced. Yet resort to the courts to meet this need would contravene the strong affirmance of the use of non-adversarial methods for the resolution of disputes between

48 Id. at § 217.7(a). 49 Id. at § 217.1.

Page 120: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

561 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

governmental employers and police and firemen50 embodied in section two of the Act.51

The remedy, in the court’s decision was clear: the arbitration process would apply to individual employees’ grievances, as well as union-employer contract negotiations.

Act 111 specifically avoids the use of the courts for dispute resolution. This policy is so strong that section seven of the Act, 43 P.S. 217.7, provides for binding arbitration and contains the unique provision that "[n]o appeal therefrom shall be allowed to any court." Thus the only method for settling grievance disputes allowable within the framework of Act 111 is arbitration. This objective would be completely frustrated if we were to superimpose, by judicial fiat, a layer of court intervention.52

As a result, Pennsylvania courts have consistently interpreted Article 111 to constrict their ability to intervene and disturb an arbitration award. In what Pennsylvania courts commonly refer to as the Betancourt case,53 the Pennsylvania Supreme Court made clear its requirement for a very focused scope of review. “[T]he narrow certiorari scope of review limits courts to reviewing questions concerning (1) the jurisdiction of the arbitrators; (2) the regularity of the proceedings; (3) an excess of the arbitrator’s powers; and (4) deprivation of constitutional rights.” While the letter of the wording differs from that found in other states such as Nebraska and Illinois, the spirit is arguably the same.

50 It is curious that the court refers to arbitration as a “non-adversarial method,”

given the format of the typical grievance arbitration, with attorneys for each party representing their clients’ positions, calling and examining witnesses, and cross-examining the opposing side’s witnesses, before a presiding, relatively passive, non-inquisitorial arbiter. If that does not capture the essence of an adversarial proceeding in the U.S. legal system, this author is at a loss as to what does.

51 James Chirico v. Bd. of Supervisors for Newton Twp., 504 Pa. 71,78–79 (1983).

52 Id. at 79. 53 Pa. State Police v. Pa. State Troopers Ass’n, 540 Pa. 66 (1995).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 562

Act 111, and the Betancourt precedent applying that Act, have been cited in subsequent judicial proceedings to constrain court intervention.54 As such, they serve as a major obstacle to any police (or fire) service employer seeking a reversal of an adverse disciplinary arbitration proceeding. The only other apparent judicially imposed constraint on arbitration is that the courts may not enforce an order which would compel a party to commit an illegal act. This stance was articulated in the Washington Arbitration Case.55 The city of Washington, Pennsylvania, challenged an arbitration panel award that required the city to provide hospitalization insurance, paid for solely at the city’s expense, for police officers’ family members.56 The Pennsylvania Supreme Court overturned this arbitration award, stating, “ . . . such [arbitration] panels may not mandate that a governing body carry out an illegal act.”57 Third class cities may exercise only those powers expressly granted to them by the legislature. State legislation dating from 1933 specifically allowed cities of the third class to enter into group insurance contracts for city officials and employees.58 The statute was silent as to employees’ family members. The city argued, and the court agreed, that such silence meant that ensuring employees’ families at public expense would thus be against the law. This escape valve, articulated in the context of a challenge to a non-disciplinary arbitration proceeding, is, however, virtually useless in addressing even the most egregious, factually uncontested instances of police misconduct. Again, when faced with the potential to modify the scope of Act 111, courts have passed on that opportunity. In perhaps the most noteworthy example, Pennsylvania State Police Trooper Rodney Smith, while off duty and intoxicated, accosted his ex-girlfriend, threatened her, and placed his loaded police issued firearm in her mouth.

54 See Pa. State Police v. Pa. State Troopers Ass’n, 902 A.2d 599, perm. app.

denied, 590 Pa. 690 (2006). 55 City of Washington v. Police Dep’t, 436 Pa. 168 (1969). 56 Id. at 170. 57 Id. at 176. 58 Id. at 177–78.

Page 121: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

561 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

governmental employers and police and firemen50 embodied in section two of the Act.51

The remedy, in the court’s decision was clear: the arbitration process would apply to individual employees’ grievances, as well as union-employer contract negotiations.

Act 111 specifically avoids the use of the courts for dispute resolution. This policy is so strong that section seven of the Act, 43 P.S. 217.7, provides for binding arbitration and contains the unique provision that "[n]o appeal therefrom shall be allowed to any court." Thus the only method for settling grievance disputes allowable within the framework of Act 111 is arbitration. This objective would be completely frustrated if we were to superimpose, by judicial fiat, a layer of court intervention.52

As a result, Pennsylvania courts have consistently interpreted Article 111 to constrict their ability to intervene and disturb an arbitration award. In what Pennsylvania courts commonly refer to as the Betancourt case,53 the Pennsylvania Supreme Court made clear its requirement for a very focused scope of review. “[T]he narrow certiorari scope of review limits courts to reviewing questions concerning (1) the jurisdiction of the arbitrators; (2) the regularity of the proceedings; (3) an excess of the arbitrator’s powers; and (4) deprivation of constitutional rights.” While the letter of the wording differs from that found in other states such as Nebraska and Illinois, the spirit is arguably the same.

50 It is curious that the court refers to arbitration as a “non-adversarial method,”

given the format of the typical grievance arbitration, with attorneys for each party representing their clients’ positions, calling and examining witnesses, and cross-examining the opposing side’s witnesses, before a presiding, relatively passive, non-inquisitorial arbiter. If that does not capture the essence of an adversarial proceeding in the U.S. legal system, this author is at a loss as to what does.

51 James Chirico v. Bd. of Supervisors for Newton Twp., 504 Pa. 71,78–79 (1983).

52 Id. at 79. 53 Pa. State Police v. Pa. State Troopers Ass’n, 540 Pa. 66 (1995).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 562

Act 111, and the Betancourt precedent applying that Act, have been cited in subsequent judicial proceedings to constrain court intervention.54 As such, they serve as a major obstacle to any police (or fire) service employer seeking a reversal of an adverse disciplinary arbitration proceeding. The only other apparent judicially imposed constraint on arbitration is that the courts may not enforce an order which would compel a party to commit an illegal act. This stance was articulated in the Washington Arbitration Case.55 The city of Washington, Pennsylvania, challenged an arbitration panel award that required the city to provide hospitalization insurance, paid for solely at the city’s expense, for police officers’ family members.56 The Pennsylvania Supreme Court overturned this arbitration award, stating, “ . . . such [arbitration] panels may not mandate that a governing body carry out an illegal act.”57 Third class cities may exercise only those powers expressly granted to them by the legislature. State legislation dating from 1933 specifically allowed cities of the third class to enter into group insurance contracts for city officials and employees.58 The statute was silent as to employees’ family members. The city argued, and the court agreed, that such silence meant that ensuring employees’ families at public expense would thus be against the law. This escape valve, articulated in the context of a challenge to a non-disciplinary arbitration proceeding, is, however, virtually useless in addressing even the most egregious, factually uncontested instances of police misconduct. Again, when faced with the potential to modify the scope of Act 111, courts have passed on that opportunity. In perhaps the most noteworthy example, Pennsylvania State Police Trooper Rodney Smith, while off duty and intoxicated, accosted his ex-girlfriend, threatened her, and placed his loaded police issued firearm in her mouth.

54 See Pa. State Police v. Pa. State Troopers Ass’n, 902 A.2d 599, perm. app.

denied, 590 Pa. 690 (2006). 55 City of Washington v. Police Dep’t, 436 Pa. 168 (1969). 56 Id. at 170. 57 Id. at 176. 58 Id. at 177–78.

Page 122: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

563 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

He pled guilty to five criminal charges, including three counts of driving under the influence, simple assault, and making terroristic threats.59 Nonetheless, the arbitrator concluded this misconduct was not serious enough to warrant discharge.60 Smith was ordered to be reinstated to duty, but with no back pay (in essence reducing the discipline from discharge to a suspension equal to time served, a period of approximately twenty months). The ensuing litigation to set aside the arbitration award and reinstate the discharge order reached the Pennsylvania Supreme Court. Six of the seven justices felt compelled to uphold the arbitrators’ awards (in a joint decision involving both this and an unrelated case of a state trooper reinstated by arbitration after he was discharged for a criminal conviction for shoplifting). In separate opinions, two justices indicated their reluctant concurrence based on existing precedents.61 One hoped these two cases would serve as a catalyst to legislative revision of Act 111 (a dubious and/or naïve hope, given the political power of officers’ unions previously discussed). The other concurrence expressed support for the court revisiting its standards for the scope of judicial review and considering “ . . . whether the arbitration decision is repugnant to public policy or shocks the conscience of the court.”62 One justice dissented, noting the court’s own precedent that “ . . Act 111 arbitration panels may not order a public employer to do an act that was forbidden,” and that Pennsylvania statutes and administrative code require that agencies appoint as police officers only those of “good moral character.”63 The dissent’s rationale was that requiring the state police to reinstate Mr. Smith as a trooper (given that his actions clearly showed a strong lack of moral character) was in essence requiring the employer to commit an illegal act; something clearly beyond the arbitrator’s power under existing case law. Justice Newman was alone in

59 Pa. State Police v. Pa. State Troopers Ass’n, 559 Pa. 586, 588–89 (1999). 60 Id. at 589. 61 Id. at 595, 597. 62 Id. at 597. 63 Id. at 599-600 (Newman, J., dissenting).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 564

her dissent. Given Trooper Smith’s actions in terrorizing his ex-girlfriend, it is probably not a coincidence that the sole dissent was authored by the court’s lone female justice.64

B. TEXAS

As previously noted, Texas statute limits court challenges of arbitration awards to very narrow grounds, alleging the arbitration panel was “ . . . without jurisdiction or exceeded its jurisdiction or that the order was procured by fraud, collusion, or other unlawful means.”65 While there are a number of cases reported in which losing parties challenged arbitration awards on the basis of one (or more) of these specified grounds, challenges on public policy grounds are rare. There is at least one case in which Texas courts overturned a public employment related arbitration decision. This was not a discipline-related matter, but instead dealt with a dispute over payment of accrued sick leave pay to a sheriff’s deputy. The county contended such back pay would be in violation of a provision of the Texas Constitution. The arbitrator, in an unusual move, awarded the back pay but acknowledged the constitutionality would have to be addressed by the courts. The trial court ruled the award was in violation of the Texas Constitution. The Texas Court of Appeals affirmed, noting, “[t]he public policy exception both allows and encourages trial courts to set aside arbitration awards that conflict with well defined and dominant public interests, which most certainly include compliance with the Texas Constitution.”66 This is consistent with the general principle that courts will not affirm an

64 See id., as it references Madame Justice Newman, as well as Mr. Justice Nigro, Mr. Justice Castille, and Mr. Justice Cappy. The gender of the other three—Justices Saylor and Zappala, and Chief Justice Flaherty can be verified through the Pennsylvania Supreme Court’s website, http://www.pacourts.us/T/SupremeCourt/.

65 See supra note 24; TEX. LOC. GOV’T CODE. § 143.057 (West 2005) (refering to “hearing examiner;” however, a full reading of the statute makes clear these individuals are in fact functioning as arbitrators, and should not be confused with those hearing examiners who serve as administrative law judges).

66 Willie Lee v. El Paso Cnty., 965 S.W.2d 668, 673 (Tex. App. 1998).

Page 123: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

563 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

He pled guilty to five criminal charges, including three counts of driving under the influence, simple assault, and making terroristic threats.59 Nonetheless, the arbitrator concluded this misconduct was not serious enough to warrant discharge.60 Smith was ordered to be reinstated to duty, but with no back pay (in essence reducing the discipline from discharge to a suspension equal to time served, a period of approximately twenty months). The ensuing litigation to set aside the arbitration award and reinstate the discharge order reached the Pennsylvania Supreme Court. Six of the seven justices felt compelled to uphold the arbitrators’ awards (in a joint decision involving both this and an unrelated case of a state trooper reinstated by arbitration after he was discharged for a criminal conviction for shoplifting). In separate opinions, two justices indicated their reluctant concurrence based on existing precedents.61 One hoped these two cases would serve as a catalyst to legislative revision of Act 111 (a dubious and/or naïve hope, given the political power of officers’ unions previously discussed). The other concurrence expressed support for the court revisiting its standards for the scope of judicial review and considering “ . . . whether the arbitration decision is repugnant to public policy or shocks the conscience of the court.”62 One justice dissented, noting the court’s own precedent that “ . . Act 111 arbitration panels may not order a public employer to do an act that was forbidden,” and that Pennsylvania statutes and administrative code require that agencies appoint as police officers only those of “good moral character.”63 The dissent’s rationale was that requiring the state police to reinstate Mr. Smith as a trooper (given that his actions clearly showed a strong lack of moral character) was in essence requiring the employer to commit an illegal act; something clearly beyond the arbitrator’s power under existing case law. Justice Newman was alone in

59 Pa. State Police v. Pa. State Troopers Ass’n, 559 Pa. 586, 588–89 (1999). 60 Id. at 589. 61 Id. at 595, 597. 62 Id. at 597. 63 Id. at 599-600 (Newman, J., dissenting).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 564

her dissent. Given Trooper Smith’s actions in terrorizing his ex-girlfriend, it is probably not a coincidence that the sole dissent was authored by the court’s lone female justice.64

B. TEXAS

As previously noted, Texas statute limits court challenges of arbitration awards to very narrow grounds, alleging the arbitration panel was “ . . . without jurisdiction or exceeded its jurisdiction or that the order was procured by fraud, collusion, or other unlawful means.”65 While there are a number of cases reported in which losing parties challenged arbitration awards on the basis of one (or more) of these specified grounds, challenges on public policy grounds are rare. There is at least one case in which Texas courts overturned a public employment related arbitration decision. This was not a discipline-related matter, but instead dealt with a dispute over payment of accrued sick leave pay to a sheriff’s deputy. The county contended such back pay would be in violation of a provision of the Texas Constitution. The arbitrator, in an unusual move, awarded the back pay but acknowledged the constitutionality would have to be addressed by the courts. The trial court ruled the award was in violation of the Texas Constitution. The Texas Court of Appeals affirmed, noting, “[t]he public policy exception both allows and encourages trial courts to set aside arbitration awards that conflict with well defined and dominant public interests, which most certainly include compliance with the Texas Constitution.”66 This is consistent with the general principle that courts will not affirm an

64 See id., as it references Madame Justice Newman, as well as Mr. Justice Nigro, Mr. Justice Castille, and Mr. Justice Cappy. The gender of the other three—Justices Saylor and Zappala, and Chief Justice Flaherty can be verified through the Pennsylvania Supreme Court’s website, http://www.pacourts.us/T/SupremeCourt/.

65 See supra note 24; TEX. LOC. GOV’T CODE. § 143.057 (West 2005) (refering to “hearing examiner;” however, a full reading of the statute makes clear these individuals are in fact functioning as arbitrators, and should not be confused with those hearing examiners who serve as administrative law judges).

66 Willie Lee v. El Paso Cnty., 965 S.W.2d 668, 673 (Tex. App. 1998).

Page 124: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

565 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

arbitration award requiring the performance of an illegal act. However, for a police chief, the reality is that in employee disciplinary matters, arbitrator-ordered reinstatement to duty of a discharged police officer, however repugnant the officer’s underlying misconduct, typically does not rise to the level of being an illegal act.67 With no pertinent case law on police discipline to serve as a basis for challenging adverse arbitration decisions, jurisdictions in Texas have sought to utilize the statutorily provided grounds as a basis for such challenges. Police chiefs dissatisfied with arbitration decisions have enjoyed some very limited success through these efforts. Thus, for instance, the issue of an arbitrator exceeding his/her jurisdiction was significant in the Texas Supreme Court’s decision in City of Pasadena v. Smith.68 Smith had been indefinitely suspended, and challenged that action through arbitration.69 At the time of the hearing, the arbitrator concluded that the chief had to be present in person at the hearing. The presence of the assistant chief was deemed insufficient. The arbitrator refused to hear any evidence relative to the actual misconduct at issue.70 The city challenged the decision to reinstate Smith, arguing the arbitrator had misinterpreted the law, by not allowing the assistant chief to stand in for the chief. The officer contested on jurisdictional grounds, with which the trial court agreed; the appellate court affirmed. On further review, the Texas Supreme Court reversed and remanded, noting that the arbitrator was required to make a decision based on the evidence. The arbitrator had exceeded his jurisdiction as no evidence had been presented.71 The jurisdictional objections raised by the officer were denied.

67 In extreme cases, that argument has been made—at least unsuccessfully, in a

dissenting opinion. See, e.g., supra note 59, referencing the Smith case involving the Pennsylvania State Police.

68 Pasadena v. Smith, 292 S.W.3d 14 (Tex. 2009). 69 Supra note 68. As noted previously, this means, in reality, discharge. 70 Pasadena, 292 S.W.3d at 14. The arbitrator also erred in applying to this case

statutory provisions applicable only to a city with a population greater than 1.5 million people.

71 Interestingly, with no evidence heard at the arbitration, the court decision is silent as to the nature of Smith’s alleged misconduct.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 566

A subsequent case, based in part on the [Texas] Smith precedent, also determined that the hearing examiner exceeded his jurisdiction.72 The officer had been indefinitely suspended after he was found to have had sex with a woman while on duty, as well as committing other rules violations. The arbitrator reversed the discipline, based on the police department’s failure to provide the accused officer with a copy of the signed complaint, as required by law. However, the Court of Appeals noted the statute was silent as to the consequences of such a procedural breach. “In the absence of a legislative directive that the failure to provide a complainant’s statement prior to discipline means that the officer will escape discipline, the hearing examiner exceeded his jurisdiction by crafting such a rule.”73 The Supreme Court of Texas denied the petition for review.74 Court challenges based on an arbitrator’s abuse of authority can also work to the advantage of the accused employee. In a case involving a fire department captain accused of having exposed himself to another firefighter, the resultant disciplinary recommendation was a demotion of two ranks. The arbitrator found insufficient evidence to support that allegation, and thus overturned the discipline. However, the arbitrator found the individual guilty of other infractions, not charged in the original disciplinary case, and imposed a thirty days’ suspension. The fire captain successfully challenged this in court, arguing that the arbitrator exceeded his authority by imposing discipline for an infraction not charged.75 The trial court granted a motion for summary judgment by the city. The Texas Court of Appeals reversed, and set aside the arbitration decision. In general, Texas courts show reluctance to reverse arbitration decisions. For example, in the Longoria case, the City of San Antonio sought to challenge an arbitrator’s decision voiding the indefinite suspension of a firefighter.76 In one pay check, Longoria was mistakenly

72 City of Athens v. MacAvoy, 353 S.W.3d 905 (Tex. App. 2011). 73 Id. 74 Id. 75 Kuykendall v. City of Grand Prairie, 257 S.W.3d 515 (Tex. App. 2008). 76 City of San Antonio v. Longoria, No. 04-04-00063-CV, 2004 WL 2098074

(Tex. App. 2004).

Page 125: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

565 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

arbitration award requiring the performance of an illegal act. However, for a police chief, the reality is that in employee disciplinary matters, arbitrator-ordered reinstatement to duty of a discharged police officer, however repugnant the officer’s underlying misconduct, typically does not rise to the level of being an illegal act.67 With no pertinent case law on police discipline to serve as a basis for challenging adverse arbitration decisions, jurisdictions in Texas have sought to utilize the statutorily provided grounds as a basis for such challenges. Police chiefs dissatisfied with arbitration decisions have enjoyed some very limited success through these efforts. Thus, for instance, the issue of an arbitrator exceeding his/her jurisdiction was significant in the Texas Supreme Court’s decision in City of Pasadena v. Smith.68 Smith had been indefinitely suspended, and challenged that action through arbitration.69 At the time of the hearing, the arbitrator concluded that the chief had to be present in person at the hearing. The presence of the assistant chief was deemed insufficient. The arbitrator refused to hear any evidence relative to the actual misconduct at issue.70 The city challenged the decision to reinstate Smith, arguing the arbitrator had misinterpreted the law, by not allowing the assistant chief to stand in for the chief. The officer contested on jurisdictional grounds, with which the trial court agreed; the appellate court affirmed. On further review, the Texas Supreme Court reversed and remanded, noting that the arbitrator was required to make a decision based on the evidence. The arbitrator had exceeded his jurisdiction as no evidence had been presented.71 The jurisdictional objections raised by the officer were denied.

67 In extreme cases, that argument has been made—at least unsuccessfully, in a

dissenting opinion. See, e.g., supra note 59, referencing the Smith case involving the Pennsylvania State Police.

68 Pasadena v. Smith, 292 S.W.3d 14 (Tex. 2009). 69 Supra note 68. As noted previously, this means, in reality, discharge. 70 Pasadena, 292 S.W.3d at 14. The arbitrator also erred in applying to this case

statutory provisions applicable only to a city with a population greater than 1.5 million people.

71 Interestingly, with no evidence heard at the arbitration, the court decision is silent as to the nature of Smith’s alleged misconduct.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 566

A subsequent case, based in part on the [Texas] Smith precedent, also determined that the hearing examiner exceeded his jurisdiction.72 The officer had been indefinitely suspended after he was found to have had sex with a woman while on duty, as well as committing other rules violations. The arbitrator reversed the discipline, based on the police department’s failure to provide the accused officer with a copy of the signed complaint, as required by law. However, the Court of Appeals noted the statute was silent as to the consequences of such a procedural breach. “In the absence of a legislative directive that the failure to provide a complainant’s statement prior to discipline means that the officer will escape discipline, the hearing examiner exceeded his jurisdiction by crafting such a rule.”73 The Supreme Court of Texas denied the petition for review.74 Court challenges based on an arbitrator’s abuse of authority can also work to the advantage of the accused employee. In a case involving a fire department captain accused of having exposed himself to another firefighter, the resultant disciplinary recommendation was a demotion of two ranks. The arbitrator found insufficient evidence to support that allegation, and thus overturned the discipline. However, the arbitrator found the individual guilty of other infractions, not charged in the original disciplinary case, and imposed a thirty days’ suspension. The fire captain successfully challenged this in court, arguing that the arbitrator exceeded his authority by imposing discipline for an infraction not charged.75 The trial court granted a motion for summary judgment by the city. The Texas Court of Appeals reversed, and set aside the arbitration decision. In general, Texas courts show reluctance to reverse arbitration decisions. For example, in the Longoria case, the City of San Antonio sought to challenge an arbitrator’s decision voiding the indefinite suspension of a firefighter.76 In one pay check, Longoria was mistakenly

72 City of Athens v. MacAvoy, 353 S.W.3d 905 (Tex. App. 2011). 73 Id. 74 Id. 75 Kuykendall v. City of Grand Prairie, 257 S.W.3d 515 (Tex. App. 2008). 76 City of San Antonio v. Longoria, No. 04-04-00063-CV, 2004 WL 2098074

(Tex. App. 2004).

Page 126: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

567 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

paid approximately $6,000 more than the correct amount. He noticed the overpayment, setting it aside in a savings account, but did not report it. After some time, city officials detected the error, notified Longoria, who eventually repaid the excess money. Despite this repayment, he was subsequently disciplined. The key issue at arbitration was whether or not the city had complied with the statutory requirement that it take disciplinary action within 180 days of learning of an infraction. The arbitrator granted the accused’s motion for summary judgment, based on a breach of the 180 days’ requirement. The city sued, claiming the arbitrator had exceeded his authority and jurisdiction. The trial court and Texas Court of Appeals denied the city’s claims, showing deference to the arbitrator’s interpretation of the statute mandating action within 180 days. The same issue—the 180 days’ limit—arose in the Phillips case. A Houston police officer challenged an indefinite suspension, which was upheld by an arbitrator. In this case, court action was initiated by the ex-officer, who sued to have the arbitration decision set aside, alleging the arbitrator exceeded his authority by not properly enforcing the 180 days’ limit. Again, both the trial court and Texas Court of Appeals showed deference and upheld the arbitrator’s interpretation of the time frame requirements.77 In yet another instance exemplifying the obstacles to reversing disciplinary arbitrations in Texas courts, the City of Houston engaged in protracted litigation (the incident occurred in 1999; the most recent court decision is from 2008) over a seven days’ suspension of a firefighter, Donald Clark. An arbitrator ruled that the evidence clearly supported this suspension. However, the arbitrator granted Clark’s motion to dismiss, on the grounds the suspension had been ordered by the acting chief of the fire department, and by statute only the chief had such authority.78 At one point in these lengthy court proceedings, the Court of Appeals dismissed the City’s claim for lack of subject matter jurisdiction. The city persevered, and the Supreme Court of Texas reversed and remanded the matter, holding that the City of Houston did in fact have the right to appeal

77 Claire Phillips v. City of Houston, 993 S.W.2d 357 (Tex. App. 1999). 78 City of Houston v. Donald Clark, 197 S.W.3d 314, 315 (Tex. 2006).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 568

in this case.79 But, in an example of winning a key battle but losing the war, the Texas high court’s decision was for naught. On remand, the Court of Appeals, having been told it did have jurisdiction, addressed the merits of the city’s appeal and concluded, “the hearing examiner’s determination and rulings, as set forth in the award, were not made without jurisdiction or in excess of jurisdiction. The district court did not err in rejecting the City’s appeal.”80 One issue seen in Texas, but not in the other states examined in this study, is that of outsourcing: the Texas Local Government Code provides that arbitrators shall be chosen from lists of qualified neutral arbitrators provided by either the American Arbitration Association or the Federal Mediation and Conciliation Service.81 Curiously, a fair amount of energy has been spent challenging arbitration decisions on the grounds that either the terms “qualified” and “neutral” are too ambiguous, and/or the statutory delegation of a governmental power to an outside entity such as the American Arbitration Association is not legally permissible. These efforts have been unsuccessful in a number of cases, both in the Texas Supreme Court,82 and the Texas Court of Appeals.83 Overall, examination of case law shows clearly that Texas courts are very reluctant to set aside arbitrators’ decisions, and have thus far made only a very minimal acknowledgement of a public policy exception.

79 Id. at 324. 80 City of Houston v. Donald Clark, 252 S.W.3d 561, 567 (Tex. App. 2008). 81 Supra note 24. In some jurisdictions, the police department and the union,

under Texas “meet and confer” procedures have agreed to alternative arbitrator selection processes. These may supercede the requirements of the Texas Local Government Code, for the duration of the contract.

82 See, e.g., Proctor v. Andrews, 972 S.W.2d 729 (Tex. 1998). 83 See, e.g., Blair v. Razis, 926 S.W.2d 784 (Tex. App. 1996); City of Garland v.

Byrd, 97 S.W.3d 601 (Tex. App. 2002).

Page 127: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

567 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

paid approximately $6,000 more than the correct amount. He noticed the overpayment, setting it aside in a savings account, but did not report it. After some time, city officials detected the error, notified Longoria, who eventually repaid the excess money. Despite this repayment, he was subsequently disciplined. The key issue at arbitration was whether or not the city had complied with the statutory requirement that it take disciplinary action within 180 days of learning of an infraction. The arbitrator granted the accused’s motion for summary judgment, based on a breach of the 180 days’ requirement. The city sued, claiming the arbitrator had exceeded his authority and jurisdiction. The trial court and Texas Court of Appeals denied the city’s claims, showing deference to the arbitrator’s interpretation of the statute mandating action within 180 days. The same issue—the 180 days’ limit—arose in the Phillips case. A Houston police officer challenged an indefinite suspension, which was upheld by an arbitrator. In this case, court action was initiated by the ex-officer, who sued to have the arbitration decision set aside, alleging the arbitrator exceeded his authority by not properly enforcing the 180 days’ limit. Again, both the trial court and Texas Court of Appeals showed deference and upheld the arbitrator’s interpretation of the time frame requirements.77 In yet another instance exemplifying the obstacles to reversing disciplinary arbitrations in Texas courts, the City of Houston engaged in protracted litigation (the incident occurred in 1999; the most recent court decision is from 2008) over a seven days’ suspension of a firefighter, Donald Clark. An arbitrator ruled that the evidence clearly supported this suspension. However, the arbitrator granted Clark’s motion to dismiss, on the grounds the suspension had been ordered by the acting chief of the fire department, and by statute only the chief had such authority.78 At one point in these lengthy court proceedings, the Court of Appeals dismissed the City’s claim for lack of subject matter jurisdiction. The city persevered, and the Supreme Court of Texas reversed and remanded the matter, holding that the City of Houston did in fact have the right to appeal

77 Claire Phillips v. City of Houston, 993 S.W.2d 357 (Tex. App. 1999). 78 City of Houston v. Donald Clark, 197 S.W.3d 314, 315 (Tex. 2006).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 568

in this case.79 But, in an example of winning a key battle but losing the war, the Texas high court’s decision was for naught. On remand, the Court of Appeals, having been told it did have jurisdiction, addressed the merits of the city’s appeal and concluded, “the hearing examiner’s determination and rulings, as set forth in the award, were not made without jurisdiction or in excess of jurisdiction. The district court did not err in rejecting the City’s appeal.”80 One issue seen in Texas, but not in the other states examined in this study, is that of outsourcing: the Texas Local Government Code provides that arbitrators shall be chosen from lists of qualified neutral arbitrators provided by either the American Arbitration Association or the Federal Mediation and Conciliation Service.81 Curiously, a fair amount of energy has been spent challenging arbitration decisions on the grounds that either the terms “qualified” and “neutral” are too ambiguous, and/or the statutory delegation of a governmental power to an outside entity such as the American Arbitration Association is not legally permissible. These efforts have been unsuccessful in a number of cases, both in the Texas Supreme Court,82 and the Texas Court of Appeals.83 Overall, examination of case law shows clearly that Texas courts are very reluctant to set aside arbitrators’ decisions, and have thus far made only a very minimal acknowledgement of a public policy exception.

79 Id. at 324. 80 City of Houston v. Donald Clark, 252 S.W.3d 561, 567 (Tex. App. 2008). 81 Supra note 24. In some jurisdictions, the police department and the union,

under Texas “meet and confer” procedures have agreed to alternative arbitrator selection processes. These may supercede the requirements of the Texas Local Government Code, for the duration of the contract.

82 See, e.g., Proctor v. Andrews, 972 S.W.2d 729 (Tex. 1998). 83 See, e.g., Blair v. Razis, 926 S.W.2d 784 (Tex. App. 1996); City of Garland v.

Byrd, 97 S.W.3d 601 (Tex. App. 2002).

Page 128: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

569 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

C. NEBRASKA

An alternative approach is presented by Nebraska. Consider the relatively recent (2009) case decided by the Nebraska Supreme Court.84 Until this decision, that state had no case law interpreting the relevant Nebraska statute. “We have not previously addressed whether an arbitration decision, under the Uniform Arbitration Act, can be vacated by a court on public policy grounds.”85 In 2005, the Nebraska State Patrol was informed that one of its troopers might be a member of the Ku Klux Klan. An internal investigation confirmed that State Trooper Robert Henderson was a member of the Knights Party of the Klan. As a result of that inquiry, the trooper was then discharged, his membership having “ . . . reflected negatively on the State Patrol and brought the State Patrol into disrepute.”86 A grievance was then filed, and the matter went to arbitration. The arbitrator, citing constitutional grounds (there was no question that Henderson had committed the acts for which he was charged), sustained the grievance and ordered the sworn member reinstated to duty.87 The State of Nebraska opted to sue, seeking a court order vacating the arbitration decision and reinstating the discharge order. A district court agreed. The troopers’ association appealed. In its opinion, the Nebraska Supreme Court affirmed the lower court’s decision. In considering the court’s action, it is worth noting that the Nebraska Uniform Arbitration Act allows limited grounds for challenging an arbitration decision.

(a) Upon application of a party, the court shall vacate an award when:

84 State of Nebraska v. Robert Henderson, 277 Neb. 240 (2009). 85 Id. at 245. 86 Id. at 241–42. 87 Id. at 242.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 570

(1) The award was procured by corruption, fraud, or other undue means; (2) There was evident partiality by an arbitrator appointed as a neutral or corruption in any of the arbitrators or misconduct prejudicing the rights of any party; (3) The arbitrators exceeded their powers; (4) The arbitrators refused to postpone the hearing upon sufficient cause being shown therefor, refused to hear evidence material to the controversy, or otherwise so conducted the hearing, contrary to the provisions of section 25-2606, as to prejudice substantially the rights of a party; (5) There was no arbitration agreement and the issue was not adversely determined in proceedings under section 25-2603, and the party did not participate in the arbitration hearing without raising the objection; or (6) An arbitrator was subject to disqualification pursuant to section 25-2604.01 and failed, upon receipt of timely demand, to disqualify himself or herself as required by such section.88

Of these six grounds, three may, broadly speaking, be considered ethical in nature (numbers in parentheses refer to the statutory sections listed above): (1) the award was the result of fraud or corruption, (2) the arbitrator showed evident partiality or other misconduct or (6) the arbitrator should have been disqualified. The other three grounds are more procedural in nature: (3) the arbitrator exceeded his powers, (4) the arbitrator refused to postpone a hearing despite good cause or otherwise breached proper procedures or (5) the arbitration was convened in the absence of an arbitration agreement. These grounds are not unique to Nebraska: similar wording exists in other states’ codes. Note in particular the absence of any wording explicitly or implicitly authorizing a public policy exception. In addition to the statutory silence on this issue, the Nebraska Supreme Court noted that Nebraska case law had not yet addressed the

88 NEB. REV. STAT. § 25-2613 (West 2012).

Page 129: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

569 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

C. NEBRASKA

An alternative approach is presented by Nebraska. Consider the relatively recent (2009) case decided by the Nebraska Supreme Court.84 Until this decision, that state had no case law interpreting the relevant Nebraska statute. “We have not previously addressed whether an arbitration decision, under the Uniform Arbitration Act, can be vacated by a court on public policy grounds.”85 In 2005, the Nebraska State Patrol was informed that one of its troopers might be a member of the Ku Klux Klan. An internal investigation confirmed that State Trooper Robert Henderson was a member of the Knights Party of the Klan. As a result of that inquiry, the trooper was then discharged, his membership having “ . . . reflected negatively on the State Patrol and brought the State Patrol into disrepute.”86 A grievance was then filed, and the matter went to arbitration. The arbitrator, citing constitutional grounds (there was no question that Henderson had committed the acts for which he was charged), sustained the grievance and ordered the sworn member reinstated to duty.87 The State of Nebraska opted to sue, seeking a court order vacating the arbitration decision and reinstating the discharge order. A district court agreed. The troopers’ association appealed. In its opinion, the Nebraska Supreme Court affirmed the lower court’s decision. In considering the court’s action, it is worth noting that the Nebraska Uniform Arbitration Act allows limited grounds for challenging an arbitration decision.

(a) Upon application of a party, the court shall vacate an award when:

84 State of Nebraska v. Robert Henderson, 277 Neb. 240 (2009). 85 Id. at 245. 86 Id. at 241–42. 87 Id. at 242.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 570

(1) The award was procured by corruption, fraud, or other undue means; (2) There was evident partiality by an arbitrator appointed as a neutral or corruption in any of the arbitrators or misconduct prejudicing the rights of any party; (3) The arbitrators exceeded their powers; (4) The arbitrators refused to postpone the hearing upon sufficient cause being shown therefor, refused to hear evidence material to the controversy, or otherwise so conducted the hearing, contrary to the provisions of section 25-2606, as to prejudice substantially the rights of a party; (5) There was no arbitration agreement and the issue was not adversely determined in proceedings under section 25-2603, and the party did not participate in the arbitration hearing without raising the objection; or (6) An arbitrator was subject to disqualification pursuant to section 25-2604.01 and failed, upon receipt of timely demand, to disqualify himself or herself as required by such section.88

Of these six grounds, three may, broadly speaking, be considered ethical in nature (numbers in parentheses refer to the statutory sections listed above): (1) the award was the result of fraud or corruption, (2) the arbitrator showed evident partiality or other misconduct or (6) the arbitrator should have been disqualified. The other three grounds are more procedural in nature: (3) the arbitrator exceeded his powers, (4) the arbitrator refused to postpone a hearing despite good cause or otherwise breached proper procedures or (5) the arbitration was convened in the absence of an arbitration agreement. These grounds are not unique to Nebraska: similar wording exists in other states’ codes. Note in particular the absence of any wording explicitly or implicitly authorizing a public policy exception. In addition to the statutory silence on this issue, the Nebraska Supreme Court noted that Nebraska case law had not yet addressed the

88 NEB. REV. STAT. § 25-2613 (West 2012).

Page 130: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

571 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

public policy exception.89 Thus that court was in essence creating a wholly new precedent for that state. While reaffirming the general state and federal stance in favor of arbitration as a desirable alternative to court litigation, the court clearly indicated such preference has its limits.

Although arbitration decisions are given great deference, they are not sacrosanct. Here we cannot say that the strong public policy favoring arbitration should trump the explicit, well-defined, and dominant public policy that laws should be enforced without racial or religious discrimination, and the public should reasonably perceive this to be so.90

Note also this decision was issued approximately one year after the U.S. Supreme Court decision in the Hall Street case. This highlights the dual nature of the U.S. court systems: the Nebraska high court reviewed the case under the terms of the Nebraska Uniform Arbitration Act and apparently did not feel compelled by the Hall Street precedent to narrow its grounds for review.

D. MASSACHUSETTS

As noted previously, police chiefs are particularly upset by decisions in which an arbitrator acknowledges an officer’s misconduct, but deems the misconduct insufficient to justify discharge as a penalty. Massachusetts offers a number of such cases in which the public policy exception has been raised. As an example, consider the case of Boston Police Officer John DiSciullo. While on-duty, he encountered a double parked car. Words were exchanged with one of the car’s occupants. Other passengers in the car were threatened, and two persons were arrested for disorderly conduct. Officer DiSciullo then added additional felony charges including assault and battery of a police officer. An internal investigation concluded, among other findings, that the assault and battery charges were

89 Supra note 83, at 245. 90 Id. at 265–66.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 572

groundless. Officer DiSciullo had falsified his incident report, and had assaulted and threatened the citizen.91 He was discharged.92 The Boston Police Patrolmen’s Association (BPPA) grieved the discharge on behalf of Mr. DiSciullo. The arbitrator did not find sufficient evidence to uphold the allegation that the officer had threatened one of the car’s occupants, but essentially upheld many other findings. She deemed the officer’s sworn arbitration testimony as “transparently phony.”93 Despite the numerous allegations proved, the arbitrator decided a one year’s suspension was sufficient. To appreciate more fully the inexplicability of this decision (from a police chief’s perspective), it should be noted that a significant trend in police disciplinary practices in recent years is growing support for a policy of “You lie, you die”; i.e., an officer’s false report or testimony (especially in the course of an internal investigation) constitutes grounds for discharge in and of itself, separate from the underlying incident being investigated.94 An officer with a proven track record of lying is in essence damaged goods. His/Her credibility when testifying in any subsequent proceedings, either civil, criminal, or administrative, can easily be challenged. That person’s worth and utility as an officer is thus seriously compromised for years afterwards. Here the arbitrator essentially called the officer an outright liar, in addition to his other transgressions, but felt these were not sufficient to warrant discharge.

91 City of Boston v. Boston Police Patrolmen’s Ass’n, 824 N.E.2d 855, 857

(Mass. 2005). 92 Id. at 816. As additional evidence of the political power of police officers’

unions and associations, in keeping with Boston police norms, Officer DiSciullo was on paid administrative leave during the pendency of the internal disciplinary investigation and hearing. In short, as a direct result of being accused of serious misconduct, he was rewarded an unspecified number of months of full pay for not working. This practice is widespread, and not unique to Boston. For most employees, paid time off from work is usually called vacation. Why financially strapped public agencies so frequently follow this practice is a separate question beyond the scope of this study. See also Barton & Diedrich, supra note 43.

93 Supra note 33, at 816. 94 See, e.g., Enric Volante, New Rule for Cops: You Lie, You’re Out, ARIZ.

DAILY STAR, Apr. 22, 2002.

Page 131: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

571 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

public policy exception.89 Thus that court was in essence creating a wholly new precedent for that state. While reaffirming the general state and federal stance in favor of arbitration as a desirable alternative to court litigation, the court clearly indicated such preference has its limits.

Although arbitration decisions are given great deference, they are not sacrosanct. Here we cannot say that the strong public policy favoring arbitration should trump the explicit, well-defined, and dominant public policy that laws should be enforced without racial or religious discrimination, and the public should reasonably perceive this to be so.90

Note also this decision was issued approximately one year after the U.S. Supreme Court decision in the Hall Street case. This highlights the dual nature of the U.S. court systems: the Nebraska high court reviewed the case under the terms of the Nebraska Uniform Arbitration Act and apparently did not feel compelled by the Hall Street precedent to narrow its grounds for review.

D. MASSACHUSETTS

As noted previously, police chiefs are particularly upset by decisions in which an arbitrator acknowledges an officer’s misconduct, but deems the misconduct insufficient to justify discharge as a penalty. Massachusetts offers a number of such cases in which the public policy exception has been raised. As an example, consider the case of Boston Police Officer John DiSciullo. While on-duty, he encountered a double parked car. Words were exchanged with one of the car’s occupants. Other passengers in the car were threatened, and two persons were arrested for disorderly conduct. Officer DiSciullo then added additional felony charges including assault and battery of a police officer. An internal investigation concluded, among other findings, that the assault and battery charges were

89 Supra note 83, at 245. 90 Id. at 265–66.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 572

groundless. Officer DiSciullo had falsified his incident report, and had assaulted and threatened the citizen.91 He was discharged.92 The Boston Police Patrolmen’s Association (BPPA) grieved the discharge on behalf of Mr. DiSciullo. The arbitrator did not find sufficient evidence to uphold the allegation that the officer had threatened one of the car’s occupants, but essentially upheld many other findings. She deemed the officer’s sworn arbitration testimony as “transparently phony.”93 Despite the numerous allegations proved, the arbitrator decided a one year’s suspension was sufficient. To appreciate more fully the inexplicability of this decision (from a police chief’s perspective), it should be noted that a significant trend in police disciplinary practices in recent years is growing support for a policy of “You lie, you die”; i.e., an officer’s false report or testimony (especially in the course of an internal investigation) constitutes grounds for discharge in and of itself, separate from the underlying incident being investigated.94 An officer with a proven track record of lying is in essence damaged goods. His/Her credibility when testifying in any subsequent proceedings, either civil, criminal, or administrative, can easily be challenged. That person’s worth and utility as an officer is thus seriously compromised for years afterwards. Here the arbitrator essentially called the officer an outright liar, in addition to his other transgressions, but felt these were not sufficient to warrant discharge.

91 City of Boston v. Boston Police Patrolmen’s Ass’n, 824 N.E.2d 855, 857

(Mass. 2005). 92 Id. at 816. As additional evidence of the political power of police officers’

unions and associations, in keeping with Boston police norms, Officer DiSciullo was on paid administrative leave during the pendency of the internal disciplinary investigation and hearing. In short, as a direct result of being accused of serious misconduct, he was rewarded an unspecified number of months of full pay for not working. This practice is widespread, and not unique to Boston. For most employees, paid time off from work is usually called vacation. Why financially strapped public agencies so frequently follow this practice is a separate question beyond the scope of this study. See also Barton & Diedrich, supra note 43.

93 Supra note 33, at 816. 94 See, e.g., Enric Volante, New Rule for Cops: You Lie, You’re Out, ARIZ.

DAILY STAR, Apr. 22, 2002.

Page 132: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

573 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

The City of Boston understandably sought to vacate the arbitrator’s decision. A Superior Court judge denied the City’s motion, and granted the BPPA’s motion to confirm the arbitration award. The Appeals Court affirmed the lower court’s decision. However, the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court (that state’s court of last resort) took a different position:

Given the arbitrator’s findings that DiSciullo had falsely arrested two individuals on misdemeanor and felony charges, lied in sworn testimony and over a period of two years about his official conduct, and knowingly and intentionally squandered the resources of the criminal justice system on false pretexts, an agreement to reinstate DiSciullo would offend public policy.95

In ordering the reinstatement of the discharge decision, and vacating the arbitration award, the Court stated:

Although arbitration decisions are given great deference, they are not sacrosanct. Here we cannot say that the strong public policy favoring arbitration should trump the strong (and in our view stronger) public policy,96 “explicit, well-defined and dominant,” . . . that police officers be truthful and obey the law in the performance of their official duties.97

Massachusetts’ statutory language on vacating arbitration decisions is in many respects similar to Nebraska’s:

. . . the superior court shall vacate an award if (1) the award was procured by corruption, fraud or other undue means; (2) there was evident partiality by an arbitrator appointed as a neutral, or corruption in any of the arbitrators, or misconduct prejudicing the rights of any party;

95 Supra note 33, at 819. 96 Note the Nebraska Supreme Court used this identical wording in the

Henderson case, supra note 84, at 241-42. 97 Supra note 33, at 823.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 574

(3) the arbitrators exceeded their powers or rendered an award requiring a person to commit an act or engage in conduct prohibited by state or federal law; (4) the arbitrators refused to postpone the hearing upon a sufficient cause being shown therefor or refused to hear evidence material to the controversy or otherwise so conducted the hearing, contrary to the provisions of section five as to prejudice substantially the rights of a party; (5) there was no arbitration agreement and the issue was not adversely determined in proceedings under section two and the party did not participate in the arbitration hearing without raising the objection; but the fact that the award orders reinstatement of an employee with or without back pay or grants relief such that it could not grant or would not be granted by a court of law or equity shall not be ground for vacating or refusing to confirm the award.98

There is no explicit public policy exception as such. The closest is section (3), which calls for vacating an arbitration decision if it required conduct prohibited by state or federal law. How this applies in practice, however, is case-law driven. The state’s high court has addressed the scope of this public policy exception in other cases involving public employees. An arbitrator’s decision reversed the discharge of a public school teacher who had used physical force against students on three separate occasions.99 The penalty reinstated him to his position, although without back pay, thus imposing a suspension of approximately ten months.100 The school district challenged this, and in the end the high court reversed the arbitration decision and reinstated the discharge order. Interestingly, the court noted that the original discharge decision was grounded in a state statute. The court acknowledged an arbitrator’s primacy in interpreting a contractual dispute,

98 Compare MASS. GEN. LAWS ch. 150C § 11 (West 2012), with NEB. REV.

STAT. § 25-2613 (West 2012). 99 Sch. Dist. of Beverly v. Geller, 435 Mass. 223, 226–27 (2001). 100 Id. at 227.

Page 133: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

573 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

The City of Boston understandably sought to vacate the arbitrator’s decision. A Superior Court judge denied the City’s motion, and granted the BPPA’s motion to confirm the arbitration award. The Appeals Court affirmed the lower court’s decision. However, the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court (that state’s court of last resort) took a different position:

Given the arbitrator’s findings that DiSciullo had falsely arrested two individuals on misdemeanor and felony charges, lied in sworn testimony and over a period of two years about his official conduct, and knowingly and intentionally squandered the resources of the criminal justice system on false pretexts, an agreement to reinstate DiSciullo would offend public policy.95

In ordering the reinstatement of the discharge decision, and vacating the arbitration award, the Court stated:

Although arbitration decisions are given great deference, they are not sacrosanct. Here we cannot say that the strong public policy favoring arbitration should trump the strong (and in our view stronger) public policy,96 “explicit, well-defined and dominant,” . . . that police officers be truthful and obey the law in the performance of their official duties.97

Massachusetts’ statutory language on vacating arbitration decisions is in many respects similar to Nebraska’s:

. . . the superior court shall vacate an award if (1) the award was procured by corruption, fraud or other undue means; (2) there was evident partiality by an arbitrator appointed as a neutral, or corruption in any of the arbitrators, or misconduct prejudicing the rights of any party;

95 Supra note 33, at 819. 96 Note the Nebraska Supreme Court used this identical wording in the

Henderson case, supra note 84, at 241-42. 97 Supra note 33, at 823.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 574

(3) the arbitrators exceeded their powers or rendered an award requiring a person to commit an act or engage in conduct prohibited by state or federal law; (4) the arbitrators refused to postpone the hearing upon a sufficient cause being shown therefor or refused to hear evidence material to the controversy or otherwise so conducted the hearing, contrary to the provisions of section five as to prejudice substantially the rights of a party; (5) there was no arbitration agreement and the issue was not adversely determined in proceedings under section two and the party did not participate in the arbitration hearing without raising the objection; but the fact that the award orders reinstatement of an employee with or without back pay or grants relief such that it could not grant or would not be granted by a court of law or equity shall not be ground for vacating or refusing to confirm the award.98

There is no explicit public policy exception as such. The closest is section (3), which calls for vacating an arbitration decision if it required conduct prohibited by state or federal law. How this applies in practice, however, is case-law driven. The state’s high court has addressed the scope of this public policy exception in other cases involving public employees. An arbitrator’s decision reversed the discharge of a public school teacher who had used physical force against students on three separate occasions.99 The penalty reinstated him to his position, although without back pay, thus imposing a suspension of approximately ten months.100 The school district challenged this, and in the end the high court reversed the arbitration decision and reinstated the discharge order. Interestingly, the court noted that the original discharge decision was grounded in a state statute. The court acknowledged an arbitrator’s primacy in interpreting a contractual dispute,

98 Compare MASS. GEN. LAWS ch. 150C § 11 (West 2012), with NEB. REV.

STAT. § 25-2613 (West 2012). 99 Sch. Dist. of Beverly v. Geller, 435 Mass. 223, 226–27 (2001). 100 Id. at 227.

Page 134: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

575 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

but indicated the court would not defer to an arbitrator on issues on statutory interpretation: that remained the court’s prerogative.101 In a non-disciplinary public employee case, an individual, William Wick, was denied employment as a rail repairer for the Boston transit system. He was hearing impaired, but was not allowed to use his hearing aids during the test, and thus failed the job’s physical exam.102 He then filed a handicap based state law discrimination claim. The transit system settled the matter by paying a $16,000 settlement, offering him employment (and a reasonable accommodation of allowing him to use his hearing aids on the job) with seniority retroactive to the date he would have begun employment.103 The union later objected, arguing on behalf of another employee who was denied his selection of shift due to Wick’s greater seniority. An arbitrator granted the grievance, concluding that since Wick was granted seniority by virtue of a settlement, not a court verdict affirming discrimination had taken place, Wick should be stripped of the seniority covering the period he was not actually working (1999–2004).104 Ultimately, the transit system (and Wick) prevailed.

The union does not argue that Wick was not handicapped or that he is not capable of performing the essential functions of his job with the reasonable accommodation of the use of hearing aids. There is no question that the MBTA withdrew its employment offer to Wick because he failed the hearing test. Where the settlement [of Wicks’ employment discrimination claim] is presumptively legitimate, and where the union has not shown that the settlement was a sham and in derogation of the collective bargaining agreement, public policy required the collective bargaining agreement to yield to Wick’s settlement agreement.105

101 Id. at 229-30. 102 Mass. Bay Transit Auth. v. Local 589, 454 Mass. 19, 21 (2009). 103 Id. 104 Id. at 23. 105 Id. at 29–30.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 576

However, these decisions should not be construed as an expression of strong judicial readiness to reverse arbitration decisions. In a number of other cases, that same court has taken an opposing stance. In City of Lynn v. Thompson, an arbitrator reversed the discharge of an officer who had broken the arm of a mentally ill woman whom he was attempting to restrain in order to take her to a psychiatric facility. The allegation of use of excessive force was not sustained. The arbitrator found the officer “lacking in sensitivity.” His action, sustained as to conduct unbecoming an officer, was deemed to warrant a two weeks’ suspension without pay.106 The City of Lynn went to Superior Court in an effort to have the arbitration award vacated, and the original discharge order reinstated. The Superior Court so ordered. On appeal, the Massachusetts Appeals Court affirmed the Superior Court’s decision. However, the Supreme Judicial Court concluded otherwise:

One may well take issue with the arbitrator's analysis. The conclusion that an officer, whose record includes a civil rights judgment against himself and the city for excessive force (including an award of $30,000 in punitive damages), nevertheless has an unblemished record because another arbitrator determined that Thompson should not be disciplined for that incident, appears notably unsound. Similarly, the conclusion that force sufficient to break a person's arm, even the arm of a person with fragile bones, is not "excessive" when the person does not even pose a current danger to the officers is a conclusion that seems indefensible. Finally, common sense would dictate that the city would not voluntarily pay E.R. $350,000 to settle her civil rights claim unless there were significant evidence supporting that claim. Yet, we are not free to ignore the arbitrator's conclusions merely because they appear unsound, poorly reasoned, or otherwise flawed (emphasis added).107

106 City of Lynn v. Thompson, 435 Mass. 54, 59 (2001). 107 Id. at 64.

Page 135: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

575 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

but indicated the court would not defer to an arbitrator on issues on statutory interpretation: that remained the court’s prerogative.101 In a non-disciplinary public employee case, an individual, William Wick, was denied employment as a rail repairer for the Boston transit system. He was hearing impaired, but was not allowed to use his hearing aids during the test, and thus failed the job’s physical exam.102 He then filed a handicap based state law discrimination claim. The transit system settled the matter by paying a $16,000 settlement, offering him employment (and a reasonable accommodation of allowing him to use his hearing aids on the job) with seniority retroactive to the date he would have begun employment.103 The union later objected, arguing on behalf of another employee who was denied his selection of shift due to Wick’s greater seniority. An arbitrator granted the grievance, concluding that since Wick was granted seniority by virtue of a settlement, not a court verdict affirming discrimination had taken place, Wick should be stripped of the seniority covering the period he was not actually working (1999–2004).104 Ultimately, the transit system (and Wick) prevailed.

The union does not argue that Wick was not handicapped or that he is not capable of performing the essential functions of his job with the reasonable accommodation of the use of hearing aids. There is no question that the MBTA withdrew its employment offer to Wick because he failed the hearing test. Where the settlement [of Wicks’ employment discrimination claim] is presumptively legitimate, and where the union has not shown that the settlement was a sham and in derogation of the collective bargaining agreement, public policy required the collective bargaining agreement to yield to Wick’s settlement agreement.105

101 Id. at 229-30. 102 Mass. Bay Transit Auth. v. Local 589, 454 Mass. 19, 21 (2009). 103 Id. 104 Id. at 23. 105 Id. at 29–30.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 576

However, these decisions should not be construed as an expression of strong judicial readiness to reverse arbitration decisions. In a number of other cases, that same court has taken an opposing stance. In City of Lynn v. Thompson, an arbitrator reversed the discharge of an officer who had broken the arm of a mentally ill woman whom he was attempting to restrain in order to take her to a psychiatric facility. The allegation of use of excessive force was not sustained. The arbitrator found the officer “lacking in sensitivity.” His action, sustained as to conduct unbecoming an officer, was deemed to warrant a two weeks’ suspension without pay.106 The City of Lynn went to Superior Court in an effort to have the arbitration award vacated, and the original discharge order reinstated. The Superior Court so ordered. On appeal, the Massachusetts Appeals Court affirmed the Superior Court’s decision. However, the Supreme Judicial Court concluded otherwise:

One may well take issue with the arbitrator's analysis. The conclusion that an officer, whose record includes a civil rights judgment against himself and the city for excessive force (including an award of $30,000 in punitive damages), nevertheless has an unblemished record because another arbitrator determined that Thompson should not be disciplined for that incident, appears notably unsound. Similarly, the conclusion that force sufficient to break a person's arm, even the arm of a person with fragile bones, is not "excessive" when the person does not even pose a current danger to the officers is a conclusion that seems indefensible. Finally, common sense would dictate that the city would not voluntarily pay E.R. $350,000 to settle her civil rights claim unless there were significant evidence supporting that claim. Yet, we are not free to ignore the arbitrator's conclusions merely because they appear unsound, poorly reasoned, or otherwise flawed (emphasis added).107

106 City of Lynn v. Thompson, 435 Mass. 54, 59 (2001). 107 Id. at 64.

Page 136: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

577 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

The Court went on to note that it is obligated to accept an arbitrator’s factual determinations, “[e]ven a grossly erroneous [arbitration] decision is binding in the absence of fraud.”108 This concept has been endorsed by a number of state courts, and the U.S. Supreme Court, which stated “ . . . that a court is convinced he [an arbitrator] committed serious error does not suffice to overturn his decision.”109 The Supreme Judicial Court has also refused to overturn, on public policy grounds, an arbitrator’s decision reinstating a state highway department employee, discharged for possession at work of a handgun (with an obliterated serial number).110 The reinstatement awarded no back pay. Thus, his disciplinary penalty was reduced from discharge to a suspension of approximately seven months. The court declined to reverse on public policy grounds. “Arbitration awards reinstating public employees are therefore upheld if the public policy, while disfavoring the employee’s conduct, does not require dismissal.”111 Similarly, the same court declined to reverse the arbitration decision reducing two discharges to suspensions of three months each.112 These employees had used their official positions to access online state tax records of both Boston sports celebrities and managers in their own department. Citing the highway department case just mentioned, the court noted the Bureau of Special Investigations did have a clearly articulated public policy of protecting confidential information. But there was no explicit policy requiring discharge of offending employees. Thus,

108 Id. at 61–62. 109 Supra note 26, at 38. One could hardly devise a better way to encourage

sloppy legal work and discourage attorney accountability than having case law precedents which consistently affirm near-total acceptance of arbitrators’ factual and legal determinations, no matter how outrageous or erroneous those decisions might be. Fuller exploration of this key issue, however, is beyond the scope of this paper.

110 Mass. Highway Dep’t. v. AFSCME, 420 Mass. 13, 20–21 (1994). 111 Id. at 19. 112 Bureau of Special Investigations v. Coal. of Pub. Safety, 430 Mass. 601, 602,

606 (2000).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 578

upholding, or reducing, the penalty was properly within the arbitrator’s discretion, and not a matter for court intervention.113 Lower courts have also addressed these public policy issues, with varying results The Appeals Court refused to vacate the reinstatement of a county jail officer, previously discharged for his role in covering up the beating of an inmate.114 However, the same court reinstated the discharge of a Boston police officer, involved in use of excessive force in an off-duty incident.115 An arbitrator had found the conduct “offensive, way out-of-line and worthy of substantial discipline” but reduced the penalty to a suspension of six months, resulting in back pay and benefits being awarded.116 The Appeals Court vacated the arbitration decision, and reinstated the discharge order, noting that as a matter of public policy, someone could not be hired (or presumably remain) as a police officer if he had engaged in felonious conduct, even in the absence of an actual felony conviction.117 A variety of trial court decisions, and unpublished appellate court opinions, make it clear that despite statutory narrowness, Massachusetts courts are, unlike their Texas and Pennsylvania counterparts, willing to engage the public policy exception to arbitration in a variety of cases.118

113 Id. at 605–06. 114 Sheriff of Suffolk Cnty. v. Jail Officers & Emps. of Suffolk Cnty., 860

N.E.2d 963, 966–67 (Mass. App. 2007). 115 City of Boston v. BPPA, 907 N.E.2d 241, 243 (Mass. App. 2009). 116 Id. at 242. 117 Id. at 242. 118 See, e.g., Mass. Corr. Officers Federated Union v. Dep’t. of Corr., No. 09-P-

849, 2010 Mass. App. Unpub. LEXIS 166 (2010) (union moved to set aside an arbitration decision upholding a correctional officer’s discharge for use of force against an inmate; union argued unsuccessfully the arbitrator had exceeded his authority); Essex Cnty. Sheriff’s Dep’t. v. Essex Cnty. Corr. Officers Ass’n., 27 Mass. L. Rep. 487 (Mass. 2010) (ruling the arbitration award reinstating sheriff’s supervisors to duty reversed, discharge order reinstated; these supervisors allowed racist and sexually harassing comments to be posted on a union sponsored website).

Page 137: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

577 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

The Court went on to note that it is obligated to accept an arbitrator’s factual determinations, “[e]ven a grossly erroneous [arbitration] decision is binding in the absence of fraud.”108 This concept has been endorsed by a number of state courts, and the U.S. Supreme Court, which stated “ . . . that a court is convinced he [an arbitrator] committed serious error does not suffice to overturn his decision.”109 The Supreme Judicial Court has also refused to overturn, on public policy grounds, an arbitrator’s decision reinstating a state highway department employee, discharged for possession at work of a handgun (with an obliterated serial number).110 The reinstatement awarded no back pay. Thus, his disciplinary penalty was reduced from discharge to a suspension of approximately seven months. The court declined to reverse on public policy grounds. “Arbitration awards reinstating public employees are therefore upheld if the public policy, while disfavoring the employee’s conduct, does not require dismissal.”111 Similarly, the same court declined to reverse the arbitration decision reducing two discharges to suspensions of three months each.112 These employees had used their official positions to access online state tax records of both Boston sports celebrities and managers in their own department. Citing the highway department case just mentioned, the court noted the Bureau of Special Investigations did have a clearly articulated public policy of protecting confidential information. But there was no explicit policy requiring discharge of offending employees. Thus,

108 Id. at 61–62. 109 Supra note 26, at 38. One could hardly devise a better way to encourage

sloppy legal work and discourage attorney accountability than having case law precedents which consistently affirm near-total acceptance of arbitrators’ factual and legal determinations, no matter how outrageous or erroneous those decisions might be. Fuller exploration of this key issue, however, is beyond the scope of this paper.

110 Mass. Highway Dep’t. v. AFSCME, 420 Mass. 13, 20–21 (1994). 111 Id. at 19. 112 Bureau of Special Investigations v. Coal. of Pub. Safety, 430 Mass. 601, 602,

606 (2000).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 578

upholding, or reducing, the penalty was properly within the arbitrator’s discretion, and not a matter for court intervention.113 Lower courts have also addressed these public policy issues, with varying results The Appeals Court refused to vacate the reinstatement of a county jail officer, previously discharged for his role in covering up the beating of an inmate.114 However, the same court reinstated the discharge of a Boston police officer, involved in use of excessive force in an off-duty incident.115 An arbitrator had found the conduct “offensive, way out-of-line and worthy of substantial discipline” but reduced the penalty to a suspension of six months, resulting in back pay and benefits being awarded.116 The Appeals Court vacated the arbitration decision, and reinstated the discharge order, noting that as a matter of public policy, someone could not be hired (or presumably remain) as a police officer if he had engaged in felonious conduct, even in the absence of an actual felony conviction.117 A variety of trial court decisions, and unpublished appellate court opinions, make it clear that despite statutory narrowness, Massachusetts courts are, unlike their Texas and Pennsylvania counterparts, willing to engage the public policy exception to arbitration in a variety of cases.118

113 Id. at 605–06. 114 Sheriff of Suffolk Cnty. v. Jail Officers & Emps. of Suffolk Cnty., 860

N.E.2d 963, 966–67 (Mass. App. 2007). 115 City of Boston v. BPPA, 907 N.E.2d 241, 243 (Mass. App. 2009). 116 Id. at 242. 117 Id. at 242. 118 See, e.g., Mass. Corr. Officers Federated Union v. Dep’t. of Corr., No. 09-P-

849, 2010 Mass. App. Unpub. LEXIS 166 (2010) (union moved to set aside an arbitration decision upholding a correctional officer’s discharge for use of force against an inmate; union argued unsuccessfully the arbitrator had exceeded his authority); Essex Cnty. Sheriff’s Dep’t. v. Essex Cnty. Corr. Officers Ass’n., 27 Mass. L. Rep. 487 (Mass. 2010) (ruling the arbitration award reinstating sheriff’s supervisors to duty reversed, discharge order reinstated; these supervisors allowed racist and sexually harassing comments to be posted on a union sponsored website).

Page 138: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

579 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

E. ILLINOIS

Illinois also presents a pattern of significant court willingness to consider motions to set aside arbitration decisions, involving both police officers and other public employees. In one of the most recent such cases, the Chicago Transit Authority (CTA) discharged a bus driver, Maurice Gibson, when it learned he had been convicted of aggravated criminal sexual abuse (frequent sexual conduct with his thirteen-year-old stepdaughter), and had violated terms of his felony probation in having unsupervised contact with minors (passengers on his bus). The transit workers union filed a grievance. An arbitrator issued a decision, reinstating the driver. The arbitrator noted that Gibson posed a very low risk for further offenses, given that years had elapsed since the initial felony, with no indication of any further incidents.119 The CTA sued, seeking to have the arbitrator’s award set aside. The trial court denied the CTA’s claim. On appeal, the Illinois Appellate Court noted that court review of an arbitration award is very limited. The parties voluntarily agreed that an arbitrator, not a judge, would resolve disputes. “A labor arbitration award must be enforced if the arbitrator acts within his scope of authority and the award draws its essence from the parties’ collective bargaining agreement.”120 The Court went on, stating “[h]owever, a court will vacate the award if it is repugnant to the established norms of public policy.”121 The Court further reiterated the narrow requirements set forth by the U.S. Supreme Court in the Grace decision, quoted above. With those as its criteria, the Illinois court went on to determine that Illinois has clearly set forth well-defined and dominant public policies both in terms of the safe and secure transportation of passengers, and protection of the public, especially juveniles, from convicted sex offenders. Finding clear statutory support for these policies, the arbitrator’s decision was reversed as

119 Chi. Transit Auth. v. ATU Local 241, 399 Ill. App. 3d 689, 694 (2010). 120 Id. at 696. 121 Id.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 580

contrary to those policies, thus reinstating Gibson’s discharge from employment.122 This case is perhaps the most recent in a series of Illinois Appellate Court and Illinois Supreme Court decisions negating arbitration awards. In a case involving the Illinois State Police, the Illinois Appellate Court addressed two separate, unrelated cases involving state troopers, in which essentially the same legal issue arose. In both, there were criminal investigations of state troopers, one of whom allegedly had sex with a fourteen-year-old girl. In both cases, the suspect troopers waived Miranda rights and gave statements. However, they were not advised of additional rights concerning such interrogations, under the troopers’ collective bargaining agreement. Those rights came into play during administrative investigations. The initial statements resulted in the troopers being placed in a no-pay status for some period of time. The issue for the arbitrator was whether the initial criminal interrogations were violations of the collective bargaining agreement. The arbitrator concluded they were, and ordered back pay compensation for the periods when these troopers were in no-pay status (the arbitration did not address the ultimate disciplinary dispositions of these cases).123 The State Police challenged the arbitrator’s order. The lower court granted the troopers’ union’s motion for summary judgment. On appeal, the Illinois Appellate Court reversed the lower court, and vacated the arbitrator’s award. The Court found that “ . . . the arbitrator’s award requiring compliance with Article 7 [of the collective bargaining agreement] for criminal investigations violates the public policy of effective law enforcement.”124 Disciplinary-related arbitration awards go beyond issues of discharge or suspension. A Springfield officer served a ten days’ suspension, and was directed to counseling, arising from an excessive force incident, and was also transferred out—and kept out—of third shift work (in Springfield, 11 p.m. to 7 a.m.) because the perceived likelihood

122 Id. at 697–98, 702. 123 Ill. State Police v. Fraternal Order of Police Troopers Lodge No. 41, 323 Ill.

App. 3d 322, 326 (2001). 124 Id. at 330.

Page 139: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

579 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

E. ILLINOIS

Illinois also presents a pattern of significant court willingness to consider motions to set aside arbitration decisions, involving both police officers and other public employees. In one of the most recent such cases, the Chicago Transit Authority (CTA) discharged a bus driver, Maurice Gibson, when it learned he had been convicted of aggravated criminal sexual abuse (frequent sexual conduct with his thirteen-year-old stepdaughter), and had violated terms of his felony probation in having unsupervised contact with minors (passengers on his bus). The transit workers union filed a grievance. An arbitrator issued a decision, reinstating the driver. The arbitrator noted that Gibson posed a very low risk for further offenses, given that years had elapsed since the initial felony, with no indication of any further incidents.119 The CTA sued, seeking to have the arbitrator’s award set aside. The trial court denied the CTA’s claim. On appeal, the Illinois Appellate Court noted that court review of an arbitration award is very limited. The parties voluntarily agreed that an arbitrator, not a judge, would resolve disputes. “A labor arbitration award must be enforced if the arbitrator acts within his scope of authority and the award draws its essence from the parties’ collective bargaining agreement.”120 The Court went on, stating “[h]owever, a court will vacate the award if it is repugnant to the established norms of public policy.”121 The Court further reiterated the narrow requirements set forth by the U.S. Supreme Court in the Grace decision, quoted above. With those as its criteria, the Illinois court went on to determine that Illinois has clearly set forth well-defined and dominant public policies both in terms of the safe and secure transportation of passengers, and protection of the public, especially juveniles, from convicted sex offenders. Finding clear statutory support for these policies, the arbitrator’s decision was reversed as

119 Chi. Transit Auth. v. ATU Local 241, 399 Ill. App. 3d 689, 694 (2010). 120 Id. at 696. 121 Id.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 580

contrary to those policies, thus reinstating Gibson’s discharge from employment.122 This case is perhaps the most recent in a series of Illinois Appellate Court and Illinois Supreme Court decisions negating arbitration awards. In a case involving the Illinois State Police, the Illinois Appellate Court addressed two separate, unrelated cases involving state troopers, in which essentially the same legal issue arose. In both, there were criminal investigations of state troopers, one of whom allegedly had sex with a fourteen-year-old girl. In both cases, the suspect troopers waived Miranda rights and gave statements. However, they were not advised of additional rights concerning such interrogations, under the troopers’ collective bargaining agreement. Those rights came into play during administrative investigations. The initial statements resulted in the troopers being placed in a no-pay status for some period of time. The issue for the arbitrator was whether the initial criminal interrogations were violations of the collective bargaining agreement. The arbitrator concluded they were, and ordered back pay compensation for the periods when these troopers were in no-pay status (the arbitration did not address the ultimate disciplinary dispositions of these cases).123 The State Police challenged the arbitrator’s order. The lower court granted the troopers’ union’s motion for summary judgment. On appeal, the Illinois Appellate Court reversed the lower court, and vacated the arbitrator’s award. The Court found that “ . . . the arbitrator’s award requiring compliance with Article 7 [of the collective bargaining agreement] for criminal investigations violates the public policy of effective law enforcement.”124 Disciplinary-related arbitration awards go beyond issues of discharge or suspension. A Springfield officer served a ten days’ suspension, and was directed to counseling, arising from an excessive force incident, and was also transferred out—and kept out—of third shift work (in Springfield, 11 p.m. to 7 a.m.) because the perceived likelihood

122 Id. at 697–98, 702. 123 Ill. State Police v. Fraternal Order of Police Troopers Lodge No. 41, 323 Ill.

App. 3d 322, 326 (2001). 124 Id. at 330.

Page 140: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

581 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

of an officer using force during those hours is greater.125 An arbitrator ruled this shift reassignment was in effect a disciplinary action, and one done without just cause. Thus, the award concluded that the officer was in fact entitled to work that shift.126 The city sued to have the award set aside on the grounds that the award was contrary to public policy and because the arbitrator exceeded his authority. Losing at the trial court stage, the city raised solely the public policy grounds on appeal. That did not prevail. The Illinois Appellate Court noted that police use of excessive force was clearly against public policy. But, the issue here was the department’s indefinite, open-ended bar to the officer working in a presumably higher-exposure setting. The ten days’ suspension from duty, and counseling, were not at issue. The arbitration award was deemed not contrary to public policy; “ . . . the record indicates the arbitrator’s award in this case was based upon the particular facts relating to [Officer] Workman’s conduct and completed discipline. The public policy issue is not clearly intertwined with the arbitrator’s decision.”127 The arbitrator’s award addressed solely the officer’s preferred work shift, and the employer’s action, even though it did not cost the officer lost time (and income) from not working, was deemed disciplinary in nature. It should be noted the potential pool of police arbitration cases that might otherwise be brought in Illinois courts is significantly reduced by the fact that discharge cases involving sworn personnel of the Chicago Police Department (by far the largest law enforcement agency in the state) are under the exclusive jurisdiction of the Chicago Police Board, and not cognizable before an arbitrator. Similarly, many smaller municipalities have boards of police and fire commissioners, which, among other duties, serve as civil service commissions and provide the Loudermill mandated due process opportunity for a police officer or firefighter to contest disciplinary action. Thus, significant disciplinary actions in many

125 City of Springfield v. Springfield PBA Unit # 5, 229 Ill. App. 3d 744, 747

(1992). 126 Id. at 745. 127 Id. at 750.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 582

communities bypass arbitration and instead proceed in an administrative law forum, with court review clearly available as an appeals process.128 As a result, while arbitration cases involving police officers are very infrequently seen in Illinois case law, Illinois courts have, over the years, used the public policy concept as justification to address arbitrator’s awards reversing disciplinary action against public employees, in a variety of non–law enforcement public agencies. The state’s highest court endorsed the public policy exception in the case of a state Department of Children and Family Services (DCFS) case worker who falsified a progress report on the status of children whose welfare she was responsible for monitoring. She reported the children were “doing fine,” when in fact they had all perished in a fire the previous month.129 An arbitrator reversed her discharge, citing DCFS’s failure to impose discipline in a timely manner, as required by the contract. That failure, the arbitrator added, made it unnecessary to address the merits of the case. The circuit court reversed the arbitration decision on public policy grounds, and remanded the matter for additional proceedings. On remand, the union ‘demurred,’ and stood by the original arbitration decision. The arbitrator then denied the grievance, stating the demurral prevented him from a hearing on the merits per the court remand. The Illinois Appellate Court reversed the circuit court and confirmed the arbitrator’s original decision to reinstate the worker. However, the Illinois Supreme Court, citing public policy grounds, reversed the arbitrator. Citing in detail DCFS’s legal obligations to oversee the well-being of children, and to provide courts (especially juvenile courts) with accurate reports to assist those courts in many child welfare related cases, the court stated: “We, therefore, have little difficulty in concluding that there exists a ‘well-defined and dominant’ public policy against DCFS’s employment of individuals whose dishonesty and neglect could seriously undermine the welfare, safety, and protection of minors.”130 The decision went on to address the serious consequences—for the public, DCFS case workers, judges who rely upon DCFS child welfare reports, etc.—of allowing the

128 Supra note 12. 129 AFSCME v. Dep’t of Cent. Mgmt. Serv., 173 Ill. 2d. 299, 301 (1996). 130 Id. at 316.

Page 141: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

581 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

of an officer using force during those hours is greater.125 An arbitrator ruled this shift reassignment was in effect a disciplinary action, and one done without just cause. Thus, the award concluded that the officer was in fact entitled to work that shift.126 The city sued to have the award set aside on the grounds that the award was contrary to public policy and because the arbitrator exceeded his authority. Losing at the trial court stage, the city raised solely the public policy grounds on appeal. That did not prevail. The Illinois Appellate Court noted that police use of excessive force was clearly against public policy. But, the issue here was the department’s indefinite, open-ended bar to the officer working in a presumably higher-exposure setting. The ten days’ suspension from duty, and counseling, were not at issue. The arbitration award was deemed not contrary to public policy; “ . . . the record indicates the arbitrator’s award in this case was based upon the particular facts relating to [Officer] Workman’s conduct and completed discipline. The public policy issue is not clearly intertwined with the arbitrator’s decision.”127 The arbitrator’s award addressed solely the officer’s preferred work shift, and the employer’s action, even though it did not cost the officer lost time (and income) from not working, was deemed disciplinary in nature. It should be noted the potential pool of police arbitration cases that might otherwise be brought in Illinois courts is significantly reduced by the fact that discharge cases involving sworn personnel of the Chicago Police Department (by far the largest law enforcement agency in the state) are under the exclusive jurisdiction of the Chicago Police Board, and not cognizable before an arbitrator. Similarly, many smaller municipalities have boards of police and fire commissioners, which, among other duties, serve as civil service commissions and provide the Loudermill mandated due process opportunity for a police officer or firefighter to contest disciplinary action. Thus, significant disciplinary actions in many

125 City of Springfield v. Springfield PBA Unit # 5, 229 Ill. App. 3d 744, 747

(1992). 126 Id. at 745. 127 Id. at 750.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 582

communities bypass arbitration and instead proceed in an administrative law forum, with court review clearly available as an appeals process.128 As a result, while arbitration cases involving police officers are very infrequently seen in Illinois case law, Illinois courts have, over the years, used the public policy concept as justification to address arbitrator’s awards reversing disciplinary action against public employees, in a variety of non–law enforcement public agencies. The state’s highest court endorsed the public policy exception in the case of a state Department of Children and Family Services (DCFS) case worker who falsified a progress report on the status of children whose welfare she was responsible for monitoring. She reported the children were “doing fine,” when in fact they had all perished in a fire the previous month.129 An arbitrator reversed her discharge, citing DCFS’s failure to impose discipline in a timely manner, as required by the contract. That failure, the arbitrator added, made it unnecessary to address the merits of the case. The circuit court reversed the arbitration decision on public policy grounds, and remanded the matter for additional proceedings. On remand, the union ‘demurred,’ and stood by the original arbitration decision. The arbitrator then denied the grievance, stating the demurral prevented him from a hearing on the merits per the court remand. The Illinois Appellate Court reversed the circuit court and confirmed the arbitrator’s original decision to reinstate the worker. However, the Illinois Supreme Court, citing public policy grounds, reversed the arbitrator. Citing in detail DCFS’s legal obligations to oversee the well-being of children, and to provide courts (especially juvenile courts) with accurate reports to assist those courts in many child welfare related cases, the court stated: “We, therefore, have little difficulty in concluding that there exists a ‘well-defined and dominant’ public policy against DCFS’s employment of individuals whose dishonesty and neglect could seriously undermine the welfare, safety, and protection of minors.”130 The decision went on to address the serious consequences—for the public, DCFS case workers, judges who rely upon DCFS child welfare reports, etc.—of allowing the

128 Supra note 12. 129 AFSCME v. Dep’t of Cent. Mgmt. Serv., 173 Ill. 2d. 299, 301 (1996). 130 Id. at 316.

Page 142: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

583 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

arbitrator’s reinstatement decision to stand. “We will not put our imprimatur on such a disaster. We do not believe that deference to arbitration, a concept with which we wholeheartedly agree, suffers at all if the judiciary retains the right to keep arbitrators within the bounds of public policy” (emphasis added).131 Similarly, another DCFS case worker (in a separate matter) was discharged after she fabricated an interview with a witness in her investigation of an alleged child abuse case.132 The arbitrator reversed the discharge as inconsistent with the progressive discipline requirements of the collective bargaining agreement. The Illinois Appellate Court reversed the arbitration award and reinstated the discharge order on public policy grounds. Noting such grounds must be based on clearly articulated laws, not some generalized consideration of supposed public interests, the court cited perhaps two dozen specific statutes which specifically address the state interest in protecting children.133 The court noted that truthful, accurate reports are an integral part of addressing this public policy. “Her lies defeat the essential purpose of her job—to investigate child abuse and protect children and families.”134 In another locally well-publicized case, twenty-eight on- and off-duty Chicago firefighters were caught on videotape, at a firehouse retirement party for a colleague. They were drinking alcoholic beverages, exposing themselves on video, and uttering a variety of racial and other slurs. At one point, they interrupted their partying for work, and drove off in their fire engines to respond to an alarm. A variety of disciplinary penalties were handed out, ranging from five day suspensions through discharge.135 An arbitrator reversed these actions because the employer did

131 Id. at 335. 132 Dep’t. of Cent. Mgmt. Serv. v. AFSCME, 245 Ill. App. 3d 87 (1993). 133 Id. at 94–95. 134 Id. at 98. 135 Chi. Fire Fighters Union Local No. 2 v. City of Chi., 323 Ill. App. 3d

168,170 (2001).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 584

not adhere to the time deadlines for internal investigations, as specified in the contract.136 After lengthy litigation, the Illinois Appellate Court stated:

Here, the arbitrator’s award reinstating the discharged firefighters violates the well-established public policy favoring safe and effective fire prevention services in the critical matter of public safety. The conduct at issue in the present case was recorded on videotape and reveals public safety workers in an on-going state of intoxication, some participants setting about to perform their duties by way of responding to an alarm for a fire.137

Once again, as was also the case in the Massachusetts and Nebraska examples discussed above, there was no explicit statutory language requiring or permitting court reversal of an arbitration decision on public policy grounds. Illinois statutes recognize five grounds for a court to vacate arbitration awards.138 These five grounds closely parallel the first five of the six grounds specified in the Nebraska statutes; the wording is in fact almost identical. Thus, yet another example highlights the reality that the authority for such public policy grounded reversals is typically driven by case law precedent, not legislative action and statutory wording.

F. CONNECTICUT

In sharp contrast to Pennsylvania’s statutory requirements and case law precedents which almost enshrine the sanctity of arbitrators’ decisions, Connecticut has substantial case law which allows courts significant leeway to vacate arbitration awards on public policy grounds. Arbitration, especially for public sector employees, is in Connecticut often administered by the Connecticut State Board of

136 Id. at 171. 137 Id. at 183. 138 710 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 5/12(a)(1)(5) (West 2013).

Page 143: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

583 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

arbitrator’s reinstatement decision to stand. “We will not put our imprimatur on such a disaster. We do not believe that deference to arbitration, a concept with which we wholeheartedly agree, suffers at all if the judiciary retains the right to keep arbitrators within the bounds of public policy” (emphasis added).131 Similarly, another DCFS case worker (in a separate matter) was discharged after she fabricated an interview with a witness in her investigation of an alleged child abuse case.132 The arbitrator reversed the discharge as inconsistent with the progressive discipline requirements of the collective bargaining agreement. The Illinois Appellate Court reversed the arbitration award and reinstated the discharge order on public policy grounds. Noting such grounds must be based on clearly articulated laws, not some generalized consideration of supposed public interests, the court cited perhaps two dozen specific statutes which specifically address the state interest in protecting children.133 The court noted that truthful, accurate reports are an integral part of addressing this public policy. “Her lies defeat the essential purpose of her job—to investigate child abuse and protect children and families.”134 In another locally well-publicized case, twenty-eight on- and off-duty Chicago firefighters were caught on videotape, at a firehouse retirement party for a colleague. They were drinking alcoholic beverages, exposing themselves on video, and uttering a variety of racial and other slurs. At one point, they interrupted their partying for work, and drove off in their fire engines to respond to an alarm. A variety of disciplinary penalties were handed out, ranging from five day suspensions through discharge.135 An arbitrator reversed these actions because the employer did

131 Id. at 335. 132 Dep’t. of Cent. Mgmt. Serv. v. AFSCME, 245 Ill. App. 3d 87 (1993). 133 Id. at 94–95. 134 Id. at 98. 135 Chi. Fire Fighters Union Local No. 2 v. City of Chi., 323 Ill. App. 3d

168,170 (2001).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 584

not adhere to the time deadlines for internal investigations, as specified in the contract.136 After lengthy litigation, the Illinois Appellate Court stated:

Here, the arbitrator’s award reinstating the discharged firefighters violates the well-established public policy favoring safe and effective fire prevention services in the critical matter of public safety. The conduct at issue in the present case was recorded on videotape and reveals public safety workers in an on-going state of intoxication, some participants setting about to perform their duties by way of responding to an alarm for a fire.137

Once again, as was also the case in the Massachusetts and Nebraska examples discussed above, there was no explicit statutory language requiring or permitting court reversal of an arbitration decision on public policy grounds. Illinois statutes recognize five grounds for a court to vacate arbitration awards.138 These five grounds closely parallel the first five of the six grounds specified in the Nebraska statutes; the wording is in fact almost identical. Thus, yet another example highlights the reality that the authority for such public policy grounded reversals is typically driven by case law precedent, not legislative action and statutory wording.

F. CONNECTICUT

In sharp contrast to Pennsylvania’s statutory requirements and case law precedents which almost enshrine the sanctity of arbitrators’ decisions, Connecticut has substantial case law which allows courts significant leeway to vacate arbitration awards on public policy grounds. Arbitration, especially for public sector employees, is in Connecticut often administered by the Connecticut State Board of

136 Id. at 171. 137 Id. at 183. 138 710 ILL. COMP. STAT. ANN. 5/12(a)(1)(5) (West 2013).

Page 144: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

585 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Mediation and Arbitration.139 Differing from many arbitrations in other states, Connecticut’s proceedings are often held before an arbitration panel rather than a sole arbitrator. The wording of the pertinent statute in Connecticut is no more inviting of judicial intervention on public policy grounds than are its equivalents in other states. Court vacation of arbitration awards is authorized under the following conditions; note the similarities between this wording and that of other states:

(1) If the award has been procured by corruption, fraud or undue means; (2) if there has been evident partiality or corruption on the part of any arbitrator; (3) if the arbitrators have been guilty of misconduct in refusing to postpone the hearing upon sufficient cause shown or in refusing to hear evidence pertinent and material to the controversy or of any other action by which the rights of any party have been prejudiced; or (4) if the arbitrators have exceeded their powers or so imperfectly executed them that a mutual, final and definite award upon the subject matter submitted was not made.140

Note that unlike Massachusetts’ statute (quoted above), Connecticut is silent as to a court vacating an arbitration award that requires a party to commit an illegal act. Despite the narrow scope of these grounds, Connecticut courts have not been reluctant to set aside arbitration decisions, in cases involving both police officers and other public employees. Courts in that state rely upon the Schoonmaker precedent in which the Connecticut Supreme Court held:

Although we recognize the important role that arbitration plays in settling private disputes, we take this opportunity to articulate expressly the role of the judiciary in reviewing public policy challenges to consensual arbitration awards. We conclude that when an arbitrator has been called upon

139 See CONN. DEP’T OF LABOR, http://www.ctdol.state.ct.us/csblr/default.htm

(last visited Aug. 25, 2011). 140 CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN. § 52-418 (West 2013).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 586

to determine whether an employment agreement violates a legitimate and clearly established public policy . . . de novo review is proper.141

There are examples of court reversals of arbitration decisions which predate the Schoonmaker case; this precedent clearly gave lower Connecticut courts substantially more latitude in addressing public policy challenges than before. Not surprisingly, there are numerous examples of courts using this authority. For example, in one case, a police officer was discharged after it was determined that he harassed and intimidated several females, groped their buttocks, made sexual remarks and asked one to display her breasts.142 An arbitration panel agreed this misconduct had occurred, but, citing various procedural violations (such as a delay in acting on the citizens’ complaints), reinstated him to duty although without back pay.143 The city, understandably reluctant to have such an individual back at work in a position of police authority, challenged the arbitration decision.144 The trial court granted the city’s motion to vacate the arbitration decision. The officer appealed. The Connecticut Appellate Court affirmed the trial court, noting well-defined public policies against such misconduct, including both sexual harassment under Connecticut law, and also civil rights violations under 42 U.S.C. § 1983.145 The court then noted that Stanley’s reinstatement would be a clear breach of public policy. “When a municipal employee violates the public policies enumerated in state statutes and employment regulations, a reviewing court cannot enforce an arbitral award reinstating him to employment as a police officer.”146

141 Samuel V. Schoonmaker III v. Cummings & Lockwood of Conn., P.C., 747 A.2d 1017, 1024 (Conn. 2000).

142 Bd. of Police Comm’r of the City of Ansonia v. Stanley, 887 A.2d 394 (Conn. App. Ct. 2005).

143 Id. at 400. 144 This is yet another example of the issue previously noted: police chiefs’

outrage at arbitrators who conclude serious misconduct did in fact occur, but nonetheless feel it was not sufficient to justify discharge.

145 Id. at 404–05. 146 Id. at 406.

Page 145: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

585 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

Mediation and Arbitration.139 Differing from many arbitrations in other states, Connecticut’s proceedings are often held before an arbitration panel rather than a sole arbitrator. The wording of the pertinent statute in Connecticut is no more inviting of judicial intervention on public policy grounds than are its equivalents in other states. Court vacation of arbitration awards is authorized under the following conditions; note the similarities between this wording and that of other states:

(1) If the award has been procured by corruption, fraud or undue means; (2) if there has been evident partiality or corruption on the part of any arbitrator; (3) if the arbitrators have been guilty of misconduct in refusing to postpone the hearing upon sufficient cause shown or in refusing to hear evidence pertinent and material to the controversy or of any other action by which the rights of any party have been prejudiced; or (4) if the arbitrators have exceeded their powers or so imperfectly executed them that a mutual, final and definite award upon the subject matter submitted was not made.140

Note that unlike Massachusetts’ statute (quoted above), Connecticut is silent as to a court vacating an arbitration award that requires a party to commit an illegal act. Despite the narrow scope of these grounds, Connecticut courts have not been reluctant to set aside arbitration decisions, in cases involving both police officers and other public employees. Courts in that state rely upon the Schoonmaker precedent in which the Connecticut Supreme Court held:

Although we recognize the important role that arbitration plays in settling private disputes, we take this opportunity to articulate expressly the role of the judiciary in reviewing public policy challenges to consensual arbitration awards. We conclude that when an arbitrator has been called upon

139 See CONN. DEP’T OF LABOR, http://www.ctdol.state.ct.us/csblr/default.htm

(last visited Aug. 25, 2011). 140 CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN. § 52-418 (West 2013).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 586

to determine whether an employment agreement violates a legitimate and clearly established public policy . . . de novo review is proper.141

There are examples of court reversals of arbitration decisions which predate the Schoonmaker case; this precedent clearly gave lower Connecticut courts substantially more latitude in addressing public policy challenges than before. Not surprisingly, there are numerous examples of courts using this authority. For example, in one case, a police officer was discharged after it was determined that he harassed and intimidated several females, groped their buttocks, made sexual remarks and asked one to display her breasts.142 An arbitration panel agreed this misconduct had occurred, but, citing various procedural violations (such as a delay in acting on the citizens’ complaints), reinstated him to duty although without back pay.143 The city, understandably reluctant to have such an individual back at work in a position of police authority, challenged the arbitration decision.144 The trial court granted the city’s motion to vacate the arbitration decision. The officer appealed. The Connecticut Appellate Court affirmed the trial court, noting well-defined public policies against such misconduct, including both sexual harassment under Connecticut law, and also civil rights violations under 42 U.S.C. § 1983.145 The court then noted that Stanley’s reinstatement would be a clear breach of public policy. “When a municipal employee violates the public policies enumerated in state statutes and employment regulations, a reviewing court cannot enforce an arbitral award reinstating him to employment as a police officer.”146

141 Samuel V. Schoonmaker III v. Cummings & Lockwood of Conn., P.C., 747 A.2d 1017, 1024 (Conn. 2000).

142 Bd. of Police Comm’r of the City of Ansonia v. Stanley, 887 A.2d 394 (Conn. App. Ct. 2005).

143 Id. at 400. 144 This is yet another example of the issue previously noted: police chiefs’

outrage at arbitrators who conclude serious misconduct did in fact occur, but nonetheless feel it was not sufficient to justify discharge.

145 Id. at 404–05. 146 Id. at 406.

Page 146: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

587 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

In another case, a police officer was discharged for a number of infractions, including revealing the identity of a confidential informant. An arbitration panel upheld guilt but reduced the penalty to a suspension of 150 days. The time the officer had been off duty was substantially longer by the time of decision, making him eligible for back pay.147 The employer filed to vacate the arbitration decision. The trial court so ordered. On appeal, the Appellate Court of Connecticut affirmed the trial court. In support of the public policy breach alleged by the employer, that court cited various statutes which make clear that the identity of confidential informants is just that—confidential—and affirmed the trial court’s decision in vacating the arbitration award.148 In a field related to police work, Connecticut courts have issued a number of decisions affirming reversal of arbitration decisions reinstating discharged state corrections officers. One officer was discharged for leaving an obscene, racist phone voice mail to a state senator, making the call from work, on a state telephone, while on duty. The arbitration decisions reduced the penalty to a sixty days’ suspension. The trial court vacated the arbitration award; the Supreme Court of Connecticut affirmed that decision.149 In an Appellate Court case, the court reversed an arbitration award reinstating a discharged corrections officer who had engaged in an ongoing pattern of sexual harassment, reducing his penalty from discharge to a suspension of one year.150 Significantly, the court based its decision in large part on the arbitrator’s finding of fact that harassment had in fact occurred.151 The court noted the oft-mentioned deference to arbitration as a preferred means of dispute resolution, but then added, “[b]ecause the plaintiff’s challenge raises such a [violation of public policy] claim, we undertake de novo review of the award. In this regard, we emphasize that

147 Town of South Windsor v. South Windsor Police Union, 677 A.2d 464, 466-

67 (Conn. App. Ct. 1996). 148 Id. at 470. 149 State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 387, 747 A.2d 480 (Conn. 2000). 150 State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 391, 7 A.3d 931 (Conn. App. Ct. 2010). 151 Id. at 939–40.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 588

in conducting our review, we are not concerned with the correctness of the arbitrator’s decision; our concern is only whether the award can be lawfully enforced.”152 This, in essence, conforms to the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in Eastern Associated Coal, noting the key point is not whether the employee’s misconduct itself violates public policy, but whether the agreement to reinstate him does so.153 In yet another case, a trial court’s recent decision addressed the state’s claim to set aside an arbitration decision reducing a corrections officer’s discharge to two suspensions totaling thirty-five days. This individual had used, purchased and dealt narcotics, and lied to investigators. The court, again relying on the arbitration’s findings of fact, determined the misconduct had occurred and from there proceeded to hold that these actions violated clearly defined public policy. The arbitration award was thus vacated.154 In various other cases involving arbitration of public employees’ discharges for cause, the Connecticut Supreme Court upheld the vacatur of a decision reinstating an employee who pled nolo contendre to embezzling town funds.155 The Appellate Court voided the reinstatement of a driver for the Department of Children and Families who had been found criminally guilty of possession with intent to sell of both marijuana and

152 Id. at 937. As of June 26, 2013, the case is open and pending before the

Connecticut Supreme Court, with review limited to the following issue: “Did the Appellate Court properly conclude that the arbitration award was correctly vacated on the ground that it violated the public policy against workplace sexual harassment?” State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 391, 13 A.2d 1101–02 (Conn. 2011).

153 E. Associated Coal Corp. v. United Mine Workers of Am., District 17, 531 U.S. 57, 62–63 (2000).

154 State v. AFSCME Council 4, Local 391, No. HHD-CV10-6010997-S, 2011 Conn. Super. LEXIS 880 (Conn. Super. Ct. 2011). The union subsequently appealed that decision, but then withdrew the appeal in January 2012. See Docket for HHD-CV10-6010997-S, STATE OF CONN. JUDICIAL BRANCH, http://civilinquiry.jud.ct.gov/CaseDetail/PublicCaseDetail.aspx?DocketNo=HHDCV106010997S (last modified Jan. 23, 2012).

155 Town of Groton v. United Steelworkers of Am., 757 A.2d 501 (Conn. 2000).

Page 147: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

587 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

In another case, a police officer was discharged for a number of infractions, including revealing the identity of a confidential informant. An arbitration panel upheld guilt but reduced the penalty to a suspension of 150 days. The time the officer had been off duty was substantially longer by the time of decision, making him eligible for back pay.147 The employer filed to vacate the arbitration decision. The trial court so ordered. On appeal, the Appellate Court of Connecticut affirmed the trial court. In support of the public policy breach alleged by the employer, that court cited various statutes which make clear that the identity of confidential informants is just that—confidential—and affirmed the trial court’s decision in vacating the arbitration award.148 In a field related to police work, Connecticut courts have issued a number of decisions affirming reversal of arbitration decisions reinstating discharged state corrections officers. One officer was discharged for leaving an obscene, racist phone voice mail to a state senator, making the call from work, on a state telephone, while on duty. The arbitration decisions reduced the penalty to a sixty days’ suspension. The trial court vacated the arbitration award; the Supreme Court of Connecticut affirmed that decision.149 In an Appellate Court case, the court reversed an arbitration award reinstating a discharged corrections officer who had engaged in an ongoing pattern of sexual harassment, reducing his penalty from discharge to a suspension of one year.150 Significantly, the court based its decision in large part on the arbitrator’s finding of fact that harassment had in fact occurred.151 The court noted the oft-mentioned deference to arbitration as a preferred means of dispute resolution, but then added, “[b]ecause the plaintiff’s challenge raises such a [violation of public policy] claim, we undertake de novo review of the award. In this regard, we emphasize that

147 Town of South Windsor v. South Windsor Police Union, 677 A.2d 464, 466-

67 (Conn. App. Ct. 1996). 148 Id. at 470. 149 State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 387, 747 A.2d 480 (Conn. 2000). 150 State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 391, 7 A.3d 931 (Conn. App. Ct. 2010). 151 Id. at 939–40.

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 588

in conducting our review, we are not concerned with the correctness of the arbitrator’s decision; our concern is only whether the award can be lawfully enforced.”152 This, in essence, conforms to the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in Eastern Associated Coal, noting the key point is not whether the employee’s misconduct itself violates public policy, but whether the agreement to reinstate him does so.153 In yet another case, a trial court’s recent decision addressed the state’s claim to set aside an arbitration decision reducing a corrections officer’s discharge to two suspensions totaling thirty-five days. This individual had used, purchased and dealt narcotics, and lied to investigators. The court, again relying on the arbitration’s findings of fact, determined the misconduct had occurred and from there proceeded to hold that these actions violated clearly defined public policy. The arbitration award was thus vacated.154 In various other cases involving arbitration of public employees’ discharges for cause, the Connecticut Supreme Court upheld the vacatur of a decision reinstating an employee who pled nolo contendre to embezzling town funds.155 The Appellate Court voided the reinstatement of a driver for the Department of Children and Families who had been found criminally guilty of possession with intent to sell of both marijuana and

152 Id. at 937. As of June 26, 2013, the case is open and pending before the

Connecticut Supreme Court, with review limited to the following issue: “Did the Appellate Court properly conclude that the arbitration award was correctly vacated on the ground that it violated the public policy against workplace sexual harassment?” State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 391, 13 A.2d 1101–02 (Conn. 2011).

153 E. Associated Coal Corp. v. United Mine Workers of Am., District 17, 531 U.S. 57, 62–63 (2000).

154 State v. AFSCME Council 4, Local 391, No. HHD-CV10-6010997-S, 2011 Conn. Super. LEXIS 880 (Conn. Super. Ct. 2011). The union subsequently appealed that decision, but then withdrew the appeal in January 2012. See Docket for HHD-CV10-6010997-S, STATE OF CONN. JUDICIAL BRANCH, http://civilinquiry.jud.ct.gov/CaseDetail/PublicCaseDetail.aspx?DocketNo=HHDCV106010997S (last modified Jan. 23, 2012).

155 Town of Groton v. United Steelworkers of Am., 757 A.2d 501 (Conn. 2000).

Page 148: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

589 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

cocaine;156 and the Superior Court granted a motion to vacate an arbitration award reversing the discharge of a police officer who lied.157 Public policy grounds can also be claimed by employees and their unions as justification for reversing an unfavorable arbitration award. Thus, an arbitration award upheld the discharge of a corrections officer for undue familiarity with inmates, and engaging in unprofessional behavior.158 The union unsuccessfully claimed the decision violated public policy, alleging that discipline was applied unevenly, thus denying equal protection of the law, in violation of the Fourteenth Amendment. The court rejected this argument. In a novel twist, one discharged police officer sought court action to reverse an arbitration decision on unusual public policy grounds. This part-time constable was discharged after he was found to have used racist and profane slurs in discussing whom he would not work with on future assignments. An arbitration panel upheld his discharge, whereupon he sued, claiming the panel’s failure to reinstate him to duty was a violation of public policy. The trial court denied his claim. Not content, he appealed. The Connecticut Appellate Court ruled, “additionally, in light of Senn’s use of a highly derogatory racial slur regarding his fellow officers, we find astonishing the plaintiff’s claim that considerations of public policy require his return to his law enforcement duties. Suffice it to say, we disagree.”159 As a side-note, this speaks to the oft-noted tenacity of police unions in aggressively supporting officers accused of blatant misconduct. The constable’s union, acting on his behalf (the union, not the officer, was the plaintiff party in this case), invested its presumably scarce resources to pursue a near-frivolous appeal that had the most dubious chances for success.

156 State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 2663, 758 A.2d 387 (Conn. App. Ct.

2000). 157 Town of Bloomfield v. United Electrical Radio & Machine Workers of

Am./Conn. Indep. Police Union Local No. 14, 916 A.2d 882 (Conn. Super. Ct. 2006). 158 AFSCME, Council 4, Local 1565 v. State Dep’t of Corr., No. CV 04-

0524924, 2005 Conn. Super. LEXIS 3646 (Conn. Super. Ct. 2005). 159 Westbrook Police Union, Local 1257, Council 15 v. Town of Westbrook, 6

A.3d 1164, 1167 (Conn. App. Ct. 2010).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 590

These decisions have been applied in a variety of public sector employment cases. In Connecticut, reversal of arbitration awards on public policy grounds is not limited simply to employee disciplinary proceedings. The scope of subjects raised is more varied than in other states. In one case example, the union representing staff attorneys working for the Connecticut Commission on Human Rights and Opportunities grieved the denial of overtime pay. The state’s position was that these attorneys were salaried professional employees and, as such, ineligible for overtime. An arbitrator sided with the union. The state went to court to have the decision vacated. The trial court confirmed the arbitration decision. On appeal, the state claimed the “ . . . arbitration award violates the clear public policy of prohibiting professional employees from receiving overtime compensation.”160 The court denied the appeal, and affirmed the trial court’s decision. For our purposes here, the specific case outcome is less important than the unusual circumstances of the public policy exception being raised in a wholly non-disciplinary context. One should not conclude that Connecticut courts routinely reverse arbitration decisions. There are any number of cases in which losing parties have sought court vacatur of arbitration awards on public policy grounds, and have failed in those attempts. But the various cases cited above illustrate the point that, unlike Texas and Pennsylvania, Connecticut courts are reasonably receptive to careful consideration of such efforts. Again, this is entirely a case-law driven practice. The wording of the pertinent Connecticut statute is no more inviting of a public policy claim than is its Texas counterpart. The crucial difference is how courts interpret that statutory wording.

CONCLUSION

The above examples, drawn from several states, are presented to provide a broad overview of the issue, not to present a comprehensive fifty states’ comparison of case law and statutes on the subject.

160 State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 2663, 777 A.2d 169, 177 (Conn. 2001).

Page 149: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

589 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

cocaine;156 and the Superior Court granted a motion to vacate an arbitration award reversing the discharge of a police officer who lied.157 Public policy grounds can also be claimed by employees and their unions as justification for reversing an unfavorable arbitration award. Thus, an arbitration award upheld the discharge of a corrections officer for undue familiarity with inmates, and engaging in unprofessional behavior.158 The union unsuccessfully claimed the decision violated public policy, alleging that discipline was applied unevenly, thus denying equal protection of the law, in violation of the Fourteenth Amendment. The court rejected this argument. In a novel twist, one discharged police officer sought court action to reverse an arbitration decision on unusual public policy grounds. This part-time constable was discharged after he was found to have used racist and profane slurs in discussing whom he would not work with on future assignments. An arbitration panel upheld his discharge, whereupon he sued, claiming the panel’s failure to reinstate him to duty was a violation of public policy. The trial court denied his claim. Not content, he appealed. The Connecticut Appellate Court ruled, “additionally, in light of Senn’s use of a highly derogatory racial slur regarding his fellow officers, we find astonishing the plaintiff’s claim that considerations of public policy require his return to his law enforcement duties. Suffice it to say, we disagree.”159 As a side-note, this speaks to the oft-noted tenacity of police unions in aggressively supporting officers accused of blatant misconduct. The constable’s union, acting on his behalf (the union, not the officer, was the plaintiff party in this case), invested its presumably scarce resources to pursue a near-frivolous appeal that had the most dubious chances for success.

156 State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 2663, 758 A.2d 387 (Conn. App. Ct.

2000). 157 Town of Bloomfield v. United Electrical Radio & Machine Workers of

Am./Conn. Indep. Police Union Local No. 14, 916 A.2d 882 (Conn. Super. Ct. 2006). 158 AFSCME, Council 4, Local 1565 v. State Dep’t of Corr., No. CV 04-

0524924, 2005 Conn. Super. LEXIS 3646 (Conn. Super. Ct. 2005). 159 Westbrook Police Union, Local 1257, Council 15 v. Town of Westbrook, 6

A.3d 1164, 1167 (Conn. App. Ct. 2010).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 590

These decisions have been applied in a variety of public sector employment cases. In Connecticut, reversal of arbitration awards on public policy grounds is not limited simply to employee disciplinary proceedings. The scope of subjects raised is more varied than in other states. In one case example, the union representing staff attorneys working for the Connecticut Commission on Human Rights and Opportunities grieved the denial of overtime pay. The state’s position was that these attorneys were salaried professional employees and, as such, ineligible for overtime. An arbitrator sided with the union. The state went to court to have the decision vacated. The trial court confirmed the arbitration decision. On appeal, the state claimed the “ . . . arbitration award violates the clear public policy of prohibiting professional employees from receiving overtime compensation.”160 The court denied the appeal, and affirmed the trial court’s decision. For our purposes here, the specific case outcome is less important than the unusual circumstances of the public policy exception being raised in a wholly non-disciplinary context. One should not conclude that Connecticut courts routinely reverse arbitration decisions. There are any number of cases in which losing parties have sought court vacatur of arbitration awards on public policy grounds, and have failed in those attempts. But the various cases cited above illustrate the point that, unlike Texas and Pennsylvania, Connecticut courts are reasonably receptive to careful consideration of such efforts. Again, this is entirely a case-law driven practice. The wording of the pertinent Connecticut statute is no more inviting of a public policy claim than is its Texas counterpart. The crucial difference is how courts interpret that statutory wording.

CONCLUSION

The above examples, drawn from several states, are presented to provide a broad overview of the issue, not to present a comprehensive fifty states’ comparison of case law and statutes on the subject.

160 State v. AFSCME, Council 4, Local 2663, 777 A.2d 169, 177 (Conn. 2001).

Page 150: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

591 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

The various states profiled herein show a variety of approaches to the public policy exception in operation. In Pennsylvania, the statutory wording of Act 111 severely constrains court options for judicial review. Court precedents take that very narrow statutory window of opportunity, and narrow it even further. Texas presents an example of a state in which courts have fairly consistently declined to set case law precedent and create a public policy exception. Interestingly, Texas is widely perceived by many as a state that is not particularly hospitable to organized labor. In contrast, Illinois, Massachusetts and Connecticut are states in which organized labor is perceived as having much more political clout. Yet courts in the more labor friendly states have issued a number of precedents that can undercut pro-labor arbitration decisions, while courts in the less organized labor friendly state have chosen not to make such decisions. Detailed analysis of how such extra-legal factors may play a role in shaping these courts’ decisions is beyond the scope of the paper, but nonetheless they warrant mention at this point. In Nebraska, a statutory and case law void was filled in 2009 when the Nebraska Supreme Court saw fit to create a public policy exception. How widely—or narrowly—that exception will be applied in other cases is a question which can be answered only through the passage of time, as that state’s courts are called upon to address other such cases. Massachusetts and Illinois present examples of state court precedents which appear, in comparison to other states, fairly generous (from a public employer’s perspective) in allowing arbitration decisions to be reversed on public policy grounds. Police officers, firefighters, transit system employees, child protective services workers, have all seen their success at disciplinary arbitration proceedings negated through subsequent court litigation. A note of caution is in order, however. While these states may appear fairly open to motions to invoke the public policy exception, these cases in total are a very small minority of the total pool of public employee disciplinary actions reversed by arbitrators. One may reasonably speculate that public employers exercise considerable restraint and opt to

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 592

pursue court remedies only in those cases which appear particularly egregious and/or have generated considerable public interest.161 Note that almost all of the cases discussed here (with the exception of the Clark case in Houston) involve arbitration decisions reversing discipline imposed in discharge cases, not suspensions. In theory, presumably a suspension could be challenged just the same as a discharge. However, as a practical matter, such a case would be a poor candidate to pursue in court. If a police chief ordered an officer suspended for ten days, and an arbitrator then reduced it to five days, or even none, it would be hard to mount a compelling public policy case over such a marginal difference. Thus, there is presumably a great deal of self-control exercised in choosing those cases to pursue in court on public policy grounds. They typically involve discharge decisions, and typically in cases readily perceived as particularly egregious. Connecticut courts appear fairly open to considering challenges based on public policy grounds. While the various cases typically recite the usual court position of strong deference to arbitration decisions, that incantation clearly carries a significantly different meaning in Connecticut than elsewhere. While numbers for all public employee arbitrations cases are not available, the readings of court decisions suggest that of these six states, Connecticut courts are the ones most willing to intervene on public policy grounds. This leads to an appropriate note of caution at this point. Comprehensive data on disciplinary arbitrations, either for public employees in general or police officers in particular, are simply not readily available. The fragmented nature of state and local government, and collective bargaining agreements, in the U.S. is a formidable barrier to systematic data collection on this topic. Policing in the U.S. is so decentralized we do not even have a fully accurate count as to the number of police departments in this country.162 Among these thousands of police

161 For instance, the author clearly recalls how the Chicago firefighters’ fire

station party antics (fire house meets Animal House) generated a great deal of public attention, with edited clips of the party widely aired on local television news outlets.

162 While estimates and surveys tend to cluster in the area of 18,000 separate police agencies in the U.S., the author has seen counts as high as 20,000. If those are the

Page 151: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

591 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

The various states profiled herein show a variety of approaches to the public policy exception in operation. In Pennsylvania, the statutory wording of Act 111 severely constrains court options for judicial review. Court precedents take that very narrow statutory window of opportunity, and narrow it even further. Texas presents an example of a state in which courts have fairly consistently declined to set case law precedent and create a public policy exception. Interestingly, Texas is widely perceived by many as a state that is not particularly hospitable to organized labor. In contrast, Illinois, Massachusetts and Connecticut are states in which organized labor is perceived as having much more political clout. Yet courts in the more labor friendly states have issued a number of precedents that can undercut pro-labor arbitration decisions, while courts in the less organized labor friendly state have chosen not to make such decisions. Detailed analysis of how such extra-legal factors may play a role in shaping these courts’ decisions is beyond the scope of the paper, but nonetheless they warrant mention at this point. In Nebraska, a statutory and case law void was filled in 2009 when the Nebraska Supreme Court saw fit to create a public policy exception. How widely—or narrowly—that exception will be applied in other cases is a question which can be answered only through the passage of time, as that state’s courts are called upon to address other such cases. Massachusetts and Illinois present examples of state court precedents which appear, in comparison to other states, fairly generous (from a public employer’s perspective) in allowing arbitration decisions to be reversed on public policy grounds. Police officers, firefighters, transit system employees, child protective services workers, have all seen their success at disciplinary arbitration proceedings negated through subsequent court litigation. A note of caution is in order, however. While these states may appear fairly open to motions to invoke the public policy exception, these cases in total are a very small minority of the total pool of public employee disciplinary actions reversed by arbitrators. One may reasonably speculate that public employers exercise considerable restraint and opt to

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 592

pursue court remedies only in those cases which appear particularly egregious and/or have generated considerable public interest.161 Note that almost all of the cases discussed here (with the exception of the Clark case in Houston) involve arbitration decisions reversing discipline imposed in discharge cases, not suspensions. In theory, presumably a suspension could be challenged just the same as a discharge. However, as a practical matter, such a case would be a poor candidate to pursue in court. If a police chief ordered an officer suspended for ten days, and an arbitrator then reduced it to five days, or even none, it would be hard to mount a compelling public policy case over such a marginal difference. Thus, there is presumably a great deal of self-control exercised in choosing those cases to pursue in court on public policy grounds. They typically involve discharge decisions, and typically in cases readily perceived as particularly egregious. Connecticut courts appear fairly open to considering challenges based on public policy grounds. While the various cases typically recite the usual court position of strong deference to arbitration decisions, that incantation clearly carries a significantly different meaning in Connecticut than elsewhere. While numbers for all public employee arbitrations cases are not available, the readings of court decisions suggest that of these six states, Connecticut courts are the ones most willing to intervene on public policy grounds. This leads to an appropriate note of caution at this point. Comprehensive data on disciplinary arbitrations, either for public employees in general or police officers in particular, are simply not readily available. The fragmented nature of state and local government, and collective bargaining agreements, in the U.S. is a formidable barrier to systematic data collection on this topic. Policing in the U.S. is so decentralized we do not even have a fully accurate count as to the number of police departments in this country.162 Among these thousands of police

161 For instance, the author clearly recalls how the Chicago firefighters’ fire

station party antics (fire house meets Animal House) generated a great deal of public attention, with edited clips of the party widely aired on local television news outlets.

162 While estimates and surveys tend to cluster in the area of 18,000 separate police agencies in the U.S., the author has seen counts as high as 20,000. If those are the

Page 152: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

593 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

agencies, how many arbitration decisions impacting police officer discipline are issued annually? Of those, how many substantially reduce or reverse police chiefs’ decisions in serious cases? Of those, how many, at least in theory, might be reasonably reversed on public policy grounds if courts were receptive to such arguments? How many suits to set aside arbitral decisions on public policy grounds are filed nationwide annually? What proportion of those ultimately prevails? These questions for now must remain unanswered and unanswerable. A full fifty states’ review of comprehensive arbitration data, pertinent statutes and case law is beyond the scope of this essay. The objective here is to inform readers and sensitize them to the fact that on a state by state basis, there is considerable variation in how courts have addressed this issue. And this variation is dynamic, not static, as new precedents (e.g., Nebraska in 2009) emerge or evolve. For a police chief faced with taking back an officer discharged for egregious misconduct, courtesy of an adverse arbitration decision, detailed scrutiny of the existing case law—or the absence of any on point case law—in that particular state may help decide whether mounting a judicial challenge to the arbitration decision is potentially viable. The evolving nature of this issue is illustrated by recent developments in Oregon. As this Article was in the final editorial stages (May, 2013), immediately before publication, the author learned of a case in the briefing stages before the Oregon Court of Appeals.163 The Portland Police Bureau discharged Officer Ronald Frashour after he fatally shot an unarmed mentally ill man. An arbitrator ordered his reinstatement; the City declined to do so, prompting an unfair labor practices finding from the state Employment Relations Bureau. At issue in this case is who has the authority in excessive force cases to determine if discipline is consistent with public policy or not—the Chief of Police or the arbitrator. This case, when decided, will likely set an important precedent for that state. Future changes are difficult to predict. As this was written (2011–2012), anti–public union employee sentiment in various state houses and

worst case extremes, either someone is counting as many as 2,000 departments which do not exist, or someone else is failing to count 2,000 departments which do exist!

163 Portland Police Ass’n v. City of Portland, Cal., No. A 152657 (Or. Ct. App. filed 2013).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 594

state legislatures was strong, with significant efforts to restrict those unions’ prerogatives advanced in Ohio, Wisconsin and elsewhere. While efforts to diminish arbitrators’ powers have not been a major component of these efforts, one could easily see such a trend evolving, given the perceived pro-union bias of these arbitrators. On the other hand, as noted previously, police and fire unions enjoy a particularly powerful and positive position, which may help to immunize them from any potential moves to constrain arbitrators’ authority. In summary, police chiefs (and the heads of other governmental agencies), faced with the prospect of taking back a public employee whose discharge for misconduct has been voided by an arbitrator, should keep the following principle in mind:

Binding arbitration of police officers’ disciplinary cases is always binding—except when it’s not!

Page 153: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith

593 Virginia Journal of Criminal Law [Vol. 1:3

agencies, how many arbitration decisions impacting police officer discipline are issued annually? Of those, how many substantially reduce or reverse police chiefs’ decisions in serious cases? Of those, how many, at least in theory, might be reasonably reversed on public policy grounds if courts were receptive to such arguments? How many suits to set aside arbitral decisions on public policy grounds are filed nationwide annually? What proportion of those ultimately prevails? These questions for now must remain unanswered and unanswerable. A full fifty states’ review of comprehensive arbitration data, pertinent statutes and case law is beyond the scope of this essay. The objective here is to inform readers and sensitize them to the fact that on a state by state basis, there is considerable variation in how courts have addressed this issue. And this variation is dynamic, not static, as new precedents (e.g., Nebraska in 2009) emerge or evolve. For a police chief faced with taking back an officer discharged for egregious misconduct, courtesy of an adverse arbitration decision, detailed scrutiny of the existing case law—or the absence of any on point case law—in that particular state may help decide whether mounting a judicial challenge to the arbitration decision is potentially viable. The evolving nature of this issue is illustrated by recent developments in Oregon. As this Article was in the final editorial stages (May, 2013), immediately before publication, the author learned of a case in the briefing stages before the Oregon Court of Appeals.163 The Portland Police Bureau discharged Officer Ronald Frashour after he fatally shot an unarmed mentally ill man. An arbitrator ordered his reinstatement; the City declined to do so, prompting an unfair labor practices finding from the state Employment Relations Bureau. At issue in this case is who has the authority in excessive force cases to determine if discipline is consistent with public policy or not—the Chief of Police or the arbitrator. This case, when decided, will likely set an important precedent for that state. Future changes are difficult to predict. As this was written (2011–2012), anti–public union employee sentiment in various state houses and

worst case extremes, either someone is counting as many as 2,000 departments which do not exist, or someone else is failing to count 2,000 departments which do exist!

163 Portland Police Ass’n v. City of Portland, Cal., No. A 152657 (Or. Ct. App. filed 2013).

2013] Unbinding Binding Arbitration 594

state legislatures was strong, with significant efforts to restrict those unions’ prerogatives advanced in Ohio, Wisconsin and elsewhere. While efforts to diminish arbitrators’ powers have not been a major component of these efforts, one could easily see such a trend evolving, given the perceived pro-union bias of these arbitrators. On the other hand, as noted previously, police and fire unions enjoy a particularly powerful and positive position, which may help to immunize them from any potential moves to constrain arbitrators’ authority. In summary, police chiefs (and the heads of other governmental agencies), faced with the prospect of taking back a public employee whose discharge for misconduct has been voided by an arbitrator, should keep the following principle in mind:

Binding arbitration of police officers’ disciplinary cases is always binding—except when it’s not!

Page 154: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith
Page 155: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith
Page 156: VIRGINIA JOURNAL OF CRIMINAL LAW V 1 2013 NOvirginiajournalofcriminallaw.com/wp-content/... · Luke Leichty M. Grant McArthur Yakov Medinets Brian Mink Nick Mongelluzzo Brandon Smith