valid and sound argument (disclaimer)

45
Validity and Soundness

Upload: ivy-fabro

Post on 17-Jan-2017

541 views

Category:

Education


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Validity and

Soundness

Inductive and Deductive Arguments

•  Inductive arguments are arguments which do not attempt to establish a thesis conclusively.

• Rather, they cite evidence which makes the conclusion somewhat reasonable to believe.

Ex.It won't snow on June 1st this year, because it hasn't snowed on June 1st for any of the last 100 years.

• Validity is a property of the argument's form. It doesn't matter what the premises and the conclusion actually say. It just matters whether the argument has the right form. So, in particular, a valid argument need not have true premises, nor need it have a true conclusion.

Validity

The following is a valid argument: Identify the pattern.

All cats are reptiles.Bugs Bunny is a cat.

So Bugs Bunny is a reptile.

Validity

ValidityA valid form of argument can never lead you from true premises to a false conclusion.Ex. If Socrates was a philosopher, then he wasn't a historian.Socrates wasn't a historian.So Socrates was a philosopher.

Question:The conclusion of the argument is true. But is it a valid form of argument?Answer:It is not. How can you tell? Because the following argument is of the same form, and it has true premises but a false conclusion.

Validity

If Socrates was a horse, then Socrates was warm-blooded.Socrates was warm-blooded .So Socrates was a horse.

IDENTIFY THE PATTERN.

Validity

If there is a hedgehog in my gas tank, then my car will not start.My car will not start.Hence, there must be a hedgehog in my gas tank.

Identify the pattern.

Validity

If I publicly insult my mother-in-law, then my wife will be angry at me.I will not insult my mother-in-law.Hence, my wife will never be angry at me.

Identify the pattern.

Validity

Either Athens is in Greece or it is in Turkey.Athens is in Greece.Therefore, Athens is in Turkey.

Identify the pattern.

Validity

If I move my knight, Christian will take my knight.If I move my queen, Christian will take my knight.Therefore, if I move my knight, then I move my queen.

Identify the pattern.

Validity

• Invalid arguments give us no reason to believe their conclusions. But be careful: The fact that an argument is invalid doesn't mean that the argument's conclusion is false. The conclusion might be true. It's just that the invalid argument doesn't give us any good reason to believe that the conclusion is true.

Validity

VALID or INVALID.Your high idle is caused either by a problem with the transmission, or by too little oil, or both.You have too little oil in your car.Therefore, your transmission is fine.

Validity

VALID or INVALID.

If the moon is made of green cheese, then cows jump over it.The moon is made of green cheese.Therefore, cows jump over the moon.

Validity

VALID or INVALID.

Either Colonel Mustard or Miss Scarlet is the culprit.Miss Scarlet is not the culprit.Hence, Colonel Mustard is the culprit.

Validity

VALID or INVALID.

All engineers enjoy ballet.Therefore, some males enjoy ballet.

Validity

• Sometimes an author will not explicitly state all the premises of his argument. This will render his argument invalid as it is written. In such cases we can often "fix up" the argument by supplying the missing premise, assuming that the author meant it all along.

Validity

Ex.

All engineers enjoy ballet.Therefore, some males enjoy

ballet.

Validity

We just need to supply the hidden premise:

All engineers enjoy ballet.Some engineers are male.

Therefore, some males enjoy ballet.

Validity

Try to supply the missing premises in the following arguments:

If you keep driving your car with a faulty carburetor, it will eventually explode.Therefore, if you keep driving your car with a faulty carburetor, you will eventually get hurt.

Validity

Try to supply the missing premises in the following arguments:

Abortion is morally wrong.Abortion is not a constitutional right.Therefore, abortion ought to be against the law.

Validity

Soundness• An argument is sound just in case it's

valid and all its premises are true.• A property of both arguments and the

statements in them, i.e., the argument is valid and all the statement are

true.

Valid argument can never take you from true premises to a false conclusion. So, if you have a sound argument for a given conclusion, then, since the argument has true premises, and since the argument is valid, and valid arguments can never take you from true premises to a false conclusion, the argument's conclusion must be true. Sound arguments always have true conclusions.

Soundness

If the moon is made of green cheese, then cows jump over it.The moon is made of green cheese.Therefore, cows jump over the moon.

Valid argument which is not sound

Soundness

• If Socrates is a man, then Socrates is mortal. Socrates is a man. So, Socrates is mortal.

• If Socrates is a horse, then Socrates is mortal. Socrates is a horse. So, Socrates is mortal.

Soundness

• If Socrates is a horse, then Socrates has four legs. Socrates is a horse. So, Socrates has four legs.

• If Socrates is a horse, then Socrates has four legs. Socrates doesn't have four legs. So, Socrates is not a horse.

Soundness

• If Socrates is a man, then he's a mammal. Socrates is not a mammal. So Socrates is not a man.

• If Socrates is a horse, then he's warm-blooded. Socrates is warm-blooded. So Socrates is a horse.

• If Socrates was a philosopher then he wasn't a historian. Socrates wasn't a historian. So, Socrates was a philosopher.

Soundness

Argument Analysis An argument is valid if its premises necessarily lead to

its conclusion. That is, if you accept that the premises are all true, you must accept that the conclusion is true.

An argument is sound if it is valid and you accept that all its premises are true.

A good, convincing argument is a sound argument. That is, since you accept all the premises are true, you must accept the conclusion is true (because the argument is valid).

A bad argument is any other kind of argument.

Argument Analysis“Every animal needs to breathe in order to live. Fish are animals. Fish cannot breathe in the air. Therefore, fish cannot live in the air.”

Here, the claim is that “fish cannot live in the air.” The premises are “Every animal needs to breathe in order to live,” “Fish are animals,” and “Fish cannot breathe in the air.” The argument is valid – the premises necessarily lead to the conclusion. The argument is also sound – the premises are true. It is a good argument.

Argument Analysis

“Oranges are green. All green things make me sick. Therefore, oranges make me sick.”

Argument Analysis

The claim is “oranges make me sick.” The premises are “Oranges are green,” and “All green things make me sick.” The argument is valid – if we accept the premises, we are forced to accept the conclusion. However, the argument is not sound – oranges are not, in fact, green, so one of the premises is false. This is a bad argument.

Argument Analysis

“Broccoli is green. Some green things make me sick. Therefore, broccoli makes me sick.”

Argument Analysis

The claim is “broccoli makes me sick.” The premises are “Broccoli is green,” and “Some green things make me sick.” Here, all the premises are true. However, the argument is not valid – even if we accept the premises, we are not forced to accept the conclusion. Just because some green things are sickening does not mean that broccoli is. This is a bad or unsound argument. (Notice, it doesn’t make any difference whether or not broccoli makes me sick – whether or not the conclusion is true. Even if the conclusion is true, the premises have not given us reason to believe that it is true.)

Argument Analysis

“Whales know how to play hockey.

Therefore, Canadians like winter.”

Argument Analysis

The claim is “Canadians like winter.” The premise is “Whales know how to play hockey.” The argument is neither valid nor sound. It’s a bad argument. (Again, it doesn’t make any difference whether the conclusion is true.)

Argument Analysis

Usually arguments come in complicated prose. It is therefore difficult to figure out what the argument is, let alone whether it is good. Our first step is to reconstruct the argument. That is, we must convert the argument into a series of statements, identifying the premises and the conclusion and laying them out so that the premises lead to the conclusion.• 

Reconstructing the Argument

Take Socrates’s argument in the Apology:“For Death is to be as it were nothing, and to be deprived

of all sensation... And if no sensation remains, then death is like a dreamless sleep. In this case, death will be a blessing. For, if any one compares such a night as this, in which he so profoundly sleeps as not even to see a dream, with the other nights and days of his life, and should declare how many he had passed better and more pleasantly than this night, I think that not only a private man, but even the great king himself, would find so small a number that they might be easily counted.”

Reconstructing the Argument

• The first step is to identify the conclusion. Go through the passage and try to find the point. What is Socrates trying to establish?

It’s buried in there: “Death will be a blessing.”

Reconstructing the Argument

To proceed, we first have to get rid of anything unnecessary – mere rhetorical flourishes, repetitions, and irrelevancies. Go through the passage and get rid of anything that doesn’t support the conclusion in some way:•“For Death is to be deprived of all sensation... if no sensation remains, then death is like a dreamless sleep. ...death will be a blessing. ...if any one compares such a night [of sleep without dreams]... with the other nights and days of his life, and should declare how many he had passed better and more pleasantly than this night, I think.. [he] would find so small a number...”

Reconstructing the Argument

Once we’ve dispensed with what we don’t need, we can reformulate the argument as a series of statements:•Death is to be deprived of all sensation.•If no sensation remains, death is like a dreamless sleep.•Anyone will consider a dreamless sleep better than most days and nights.•---•Death is a blessing.

Reconstructing the Argument

• Now we’re ready to add anything that seems to be missing. Are there any premises that seem to be assumed, but aren’t stated?

1. Death is to be deprived of all sensation.2. If no sensation remains, death is like a dreamless sleep.3. Death is like a dreamless sleep.4. Anyone will consider a dreamless sleep better than most days

and nights.5. Anyone will consider death better than most days and nights.6. Anything that is better than most days and nights is a blessing.7.---8.Death is a blessing.

Reconstructing the Argument

• Now, we need to say something about the inference in the argument. We need to say how the argument is put together. We should identify assumed premises and sub-arguments – conclusions that are premises for the main conclusion. This will also help us to identify if anything else is missing.

1. Death is to be deprived of all sensation. (Assumption)2. If no sensation remains, death is like a dreamless sleep. (Assumption)3. Death is like a dreamless sleep. (Conclusion from 1 and 2)4. Anyone will consider a dreamless sleep better than most days and nights.

(Assumption)5. Anyone will consider death better than most days and nights. (Conclusion

from 3 and 4)6. Anything that is better than most days and nights is a blessing.

(Assumption)---7. Death is a blessing. (From 3, 5, and 6)

Reconstructing the Argument

Once we’ve reconstructed an argument – shown what we think it is and how it is supposed to work – we can begin to say whether an argument is good or bad. We need to evaluate the argument’s validity and soundness.

Reconstructing the Argument

• Socrates’s argument that death is a blessing in the Apology is interesting, but suffers from some weaknesses. As it stands it is not convincing. In the first place, Socrates cannot establish what death really is, but only what people think about it. He never discusses what death is, only what people think about it. Therefore, he cannot reach his intended conclusion. Moreover, the whole argument hinges on whether it is correct to say that lack of sensation is like a dreamless sleep. Sleeping seems to imply the possibility of waking, so it is quite different in this respect from a complete lack of sensation. Is it fair to say that a corpse, or even a stone, is doing something “like sleeping” just because they cannot sense anything? If we do not accept this assumed analogy, Socrates’s argument does not follow. That said, Socrates does raise the interesting point that death might be compared to the rest of the days of one’s life. In this case, it might be that death is better than some days, but worse than the very best days. If so, then death is perhaps not something to seek, but not something to fear, either. Even if death is not a blessing, perhaps it is not a curse, either. Socrates’s argument does lead us to reconsider our common view of death as something invariably bad and the worst of all possibilities.

Critiquing an Argument