social capital versus social history

27
This article was downloaded by: [University of New Hampshire] On: 19 November 2014, At: 20:25 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Social History Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rshi20 Social capital versus social history Ben Fine a a School of Oriental and African Studies, University of London Published online: 25 Feb 2010. To cite this article: Ben Fine (2008) Social capital versus social history , Social History, 33:4, 442-467, DOI: 10.1080/03071020802410445 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/03071020802410445 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms- and-conditions

Upload: ben

Post on 24-Mar-2017

215 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Social capital versus social history

This article was downloaded by: [University of New Hampshire]On: 19 November 2014, At: 20:25Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registeredoffice: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

Social HistoryPublication details, including instructions for authors andsubscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rshi20

Social capital versus social historyBen Fine aa School of Oriental and African Studies, University of LondonPublished online: 25 Feb 2010.

To cite this article: Ben Fine (2008) Social capital versus social history , Social History, 33:4,442-467, DOI: 10.1080/03071020802410445

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/03071020802410445

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the“Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis,our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as tothe accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinionsand views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Contentshould not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sourcesof information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims,proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever orhowsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arisingout of the use of the Content.

This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Anysubstantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms &Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

Page 2: Social capital versus social history

DISCUSSION

Ben Fine

Social capital versus social history*

1. INTRODUCTION

Social capital has enjoyed a meteoric rise across the social sciences over the past two decades.

Its leading proponent, Robert Putnam, has been identified as the most cited social scientist in

the last decade of the millennium. Social capital has rapidly assumed the role of standard

concept across a range of disciplines and topics, including economics, politics, sociology, and

management and business science. It has also been heavily promoted by the World Bank,

having been seen as the ‘missing link’ in development (studies). Corresponding policy fixes

have equally been anticipated in developed countries, with its promotion and acceptance at the

highest levels of government, inspiring major household surveys of its incidence. Only

globalization seems to have been more important to social science over the period that has seen

both so suddenly and fully gain prominence and widespread acceptance.

Dario Gaggio has opened up for social historians the concept of ‘civil society’ as derived

from Putnam’s identification of ‘social assets (trust, norms of reciprocity and networks of

interpersonal relations)’ that he called ‘social capital’.1 Gaggio draws attention to the way in

which this was judged to be the connection between ‘the traditional concerns of sociology (the

origins and consequences of sociability) and some of the hottest research agendas in economics

(the production of public goods and its relationship with economic development)’ (500). He

posed the question as to whether this might lead to ‘a new appreciation of economic action by

historians’ (499). It is this argument that I wish to revisit in this and seven other sections.

Despite its short life, social capital already has a ‘history’, or a number of histories, for it has

evolved almost as quickly as it has emerged, and its use has been rediscovered in the past. In

addition, its incidence and impact within and across disciplines have been diverse, not only in

the degree and manner of acceptance but also through whether it has also inspired vocal

*Thanks to the editors and an unknown refereefor invaluable suggestions.

1D. Gaggio, ‘Do social historians need socialcapital?’, Social History, XXIX, 4 (November 2004),499–513.

Social History Vol. 33 No. 4 November 2008

Social History ISSN 0307-1022 print/ISSN 1470-1200 online ª 2008 Taylor & Francishttp://www.informaworld.comDOI: 10.1080/03071020802410445

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 3: Social capital versus social history

opposition or silent disdain. Not surprisingly, social capital has drawn upon history for

illustration. Putnam’s classic study of Italy ranges from the twelfth century to the present day.2

He subsequently posits the decline of American associationalism identified by de Tocqueville

as characteristic of the nineteenth century.3 Further, with its focus on civil society, social

capital inevitably engages in similar preoccupations as history. Yet, paradoxically, as observed

by Gaggio, in one of the first critical attempts by an historian to come to terms with social

capital, historians have not adopted the concept, as is confirmed in Section 3.

Implicitly, at least, Gaggio offers good reasons why social capital should not have been

successful in attracting historians. It is because, for him, there is only one version of the

concept that is acceptable, drawing upon the work of radical sociologist Pierre Bourdieu. This

leads Gaggio into a radical critique of Putnam. The latter had taken functionalist rational

choice sociologist James Coleman as original exponent of social capital, on which see

Section 4, and so prompted the departure from Bourdieu’s approach. As a result, the bulk of

the literature that followed in the wake of Putnam is dismissed by Gaggio as methodologically

eclectic, opportunistically seeking a third way out of the individualistic orgy of the 1980s,

negligent of political economy, unduly reifying the separation between civil and political

society, and insensitive to the salience of context.

Despite these criticisms of social capital, Gaggio encourages historians to participate in its use

in order to drive out its erroneous manifestations and restore it in the image of Bourdieu. As

suggested in Section 7, it is questionable whether social capital can be satisfactorily rescued in

principle, even through Bourdieu. In practice, whether bringing Bourdieu back in or not, the use

of social capital within history is liable to subject it to the same poverty of outcome as has

universally occurred across its application to other disciplines and topics. This has been

recognized by Gaggio himself. Why should history be superior?

This difference of assessment of the potential of social capital for historians is built up out of

a series of arguments. First, in Section 2, is offered an account of the extent to which social

capital has become definitionally chaotic, potentially incorporating almost any variable and

method (but with empiricism to the fore) and open to any application. Nevertheless, social

capital tends to overlook the traditional concerns of much social science, especially history,

through lack of consideration of power, class, conflict and so on, as well as failing to situate

itself within a systemic understanding of society and social change, especially where the

economy is concerned. This is paradoxical for a term that includes both social and capital.

Moreover, these and other terms deployed by the social capital literature are invested with

such a bland content that the concepts which it does broach tend to be degraded and

homogenized in content, so much so that I have referred to a McDonaldization of social

theory.4

2R. Putnam, R. Leonardi and R. Y. Nanetti,Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in ModernItaly (Princeton, 1993).

3R. Putnam, Bowling Alone: The Collapse andRevival of American Community (New York, 2000).

4B. Fine, ‘Social capital goes to McDonald’s’,Plenary Address, Critical Management StudiesConference, University of Manchester, July

2007, text available from author. For other workon social capital, especially in the context of‘economics imperialism’, see http://www.soas.ac.uk/economics/research/econimp/. And for thebest website on social capital, in part for at leastacknowledging critical literature, see http://www.socialcapitalgateway.org

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 443

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 4: Social capital versus social history

In this light, Section 4 examines one aspect of the ‘history’ of social capital – how a search

has been made for its use in the past. This is shown to be a flawed approach, for what is more

important to recognize is how the concept essentially has nothing other than a nominal

history, reinvented to provide it with a tradition to underpin present-day application. Indeed,

to the extent that social capital does have a past, it belongs to an alternative and overlooked

history, one which emphasizes social capital as both economic and systemic. This begins to

explain why historians should have been slow on the uptake as far as social capital is concerned,

preferring to retain the economic and the systemic. But, in addition, as shown in Section 5,

those (economic) historians inclined to accept the social capital view of the world had already

an alternative way of doing so prior to social capital’s emergence, by relying upon the new

institutional economics. On the other hand, (social) historians emphasizing the systemic and

the contextual would find little of appeal in social capital (Section 6) – unless, of course, it

could be modified by bringing Bourdieu back in. This is an aspiration, as already suggested,

that is in part flawed and liable to be futile against the momentum of the social capital

juggernaut. Thus, as argued in the final section, Gaggio’s exhortation for historians to engage

with social capital is welcome, but not if it is to be by restoring it through Bourdieu, progress

though this may be. Rather, historians have more to offer by way of critical rejection of social

capital, drawing upon their own expertise and situation in relation to the other social sciences.

2. APPETITE WITHOUT LIMIT?

The most striking feature of social capital is its gargantuan appetite across the social sciences.

From humble beginnings, in terms of the quip that, ‘It’s not what you know, it’s whom you

know that counts’, social capital has spread rapidly across disciplines and applications. This

mantra from the scholarship of life has been turned into a corporate enterprise with many

affiliates within the academic world. From a simple causal relationship to (desired and

desirable) outcome, social capital has been fragmented into all varieties of interpretation.

Broadly, three different types of social capital have come to the fore, forging a template within

which to categorize its highly diverse forms. These are the structural, the cognitive and the

relational forms of social capital corresponding, for example, to networks or organizations,

mutual understanding or culture, and trust or reciprocity, respectively. These broad categories,

in part overlapping, are wide enough to admit an extensive membership, networks ranging, for

example, from within the family to any aspect of civil society. There are favoured variables as

far as defining social capital is concerned, such as levels of trust, networks of connections and

associational life. But the literature never fails to astonish with its invention. Colour of skin

alone, with some justification once entering the expansive world of the conceptualization of

social capital, becomes one of its elements, providing for better life outcomes.5

The hypothesized causal consequences of social capital also continue to grow without

apparent limit, promising positive outcomes across more or less any economic, social, political

and ideological functioning. Once again, there are more common areas of application such as

educational achievement, community development, economic growth and (local) governance.

The novelty and ambition of applications continue to surprise. A survey of literature on social

5M. Hunter, ‘‘‘If you’re light you’re alright’’:light skin color as social capital for women of

color’, Gender and Society, XVI, 2 (April 2002), 175–93.

444 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 5: Social capital versus social history

capital and health, for example, suggests those with it are liable to be less likely to suffer

accidents, mental problems, coronary heart disease, insomnia, short temper, teenage

pregnancy, sexually transmitted diseases, low birth weight of children, suicide, fatalism,

addiction to drugs including smoking and alcohol (but excluding cannabis), dental caries, and

feelings of sadness, stress, anxiety and ill-health!6

Thus there are many different types of social capital affecting many different types of

outcomes. The mechanisms by which these are realized often remains opaque, as does the

source of social capital itself (how it is created and sustained). There is also the issue of

distinguishing the impact of social capital from other variables that might be present either in

parallel or as its determinant. More specifically, if trade unions, classes and the state, for

example, are important to outcomes alongside social capital, and do themselves create or

condition social capital, then their exclusion (as has generally been the case) from consideration

will tend to bias, probably overstate, the role of social capital. The latter might just be a proxy

conduit for more important determinants.

This is, in part, nothing more than a cautionary tale over not conflating correlation with

causation, but more than this is involved in the expanding scope of social capital, for its own

definition is so amorphous that other conditioning variables tend to be incorporated as part of

the definition of social capital itself. Inevitably, as the literature has evolved, the salience of

omitted variables to outcomes comes to the fore whether for theoretical reasons or because

case-studies or empirical work more generally have rendered account of these variables

unavoidable. The response of the social capital literature can be dubbed as the ‘bringing back

in’ of such variables as soon as social capital as social interaction explodes out of its straitjacket

of personal interactions. The most extreme example of this is provided by Szreter, one of

Britain’s leading social capitalists, who seeks to rescue social capital from criticism by bringing

back in class, power, politics, ideology, mass unemployment, globalization, inequality,

hierarchy, the state and history, alongside a whole array of other analytical fragments.7

Interestingly, his own historical study of health and social capital in Britain appends the latter as

an afterthought whose absence explains all deficiencies and for which New Labour Third

Wayism needs to take more note, for problems arose out of ‘a surplus of bonding social capital

only, among the comfortably-off, and a deficiency of bridging and linking social capital’.8

Here, the reference to bonding, bridging and linking social capital is further evidence of

both the expanding universe of social capital and the attempt to contain its incoherence after

the event. The division into three types of social capital, as relational, cognitive and structural,

has already been noted. This is innocuous as far as it goes, if presuming the divisions to be

reasonably hard and fast, but it does not go very far and could be said to be characteristic of any

approach to social theory. This categorization has been complemented by the equally bland

attempt to reaggregate across the hundreds of variables that have made up social capital by

categorizing it as bonding (within groups), bridging (across groups) and linking (used variously,

and at times ambiguously, to refer to connections across hierarchies and power, as opposed to

those from lower to higher levels as in bringing back in the higher state to connect it to the

6B. Fine, ‘Social capital and health: the WorldBank through the looking glass after Deaton’.Available online at http://www.soas.ac.uk/cdpr/seminars/43279.pdf

7S. Szreter, ‘Health, class, place and politics: socialcapital and collective provision in Britain’, Con-temporary British History, XVI, 3 (Fall 2002), 27–57.

8ibid., 52.

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 445

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 6: Social capital versus social history

lower civil society). There tends to be some presumption that bonding capital is bad (as it can

lead to coercion or nepotism), and that bridging capital is good (as it signals cooperation) as is

linking capital as issues of power and conflict melt into cooperation or the state supports or

sustains such cooperation. The problem is that bonding, bridging and linking cut across the

traditional variables of social theory – such as class, gender, race and so on – and, as a result,

overlook that one person’s bond is another person’s bridge etc., or vice versa depending upon

context and issue, even for the same person, as with white male workers, for example. Such

tensions and conflicts within society cannot be wished away by aggregating social divisions and

complexities into the otherwise neutral categories of bonding, bridging and linking.

And, tellingly, social capital has tended to exhibit a number of no-go areas despite these

being at the heart of social interaction. Generalizing absolutely over such an extensive

literature is foolhardy, but omissions (apart from the economy in much of the non-economic

literature other than as some ephemeral object to be enhanced) include class, the state, trade

unions and political parties (although political participation by voting and otherwise has

received considerable attention without much of it to the substance of the politics

concerned).There has also been a neglect of gender, race and ethnicity, these beginning to

force their way onto the agenda after complaints of neglect (with disability now making a plea

to be included).

The reasons for these omissions are to be found in the analytical location of social capital

structurally. As a middle-range concept, it seeks to occupy a space within civil society,

interacting with but having its own independent effect on some aspect of society more

generally. Consequently, the more obvious and standard determinants of economic and social

functioning fade into the background, and with them go the standard variables of socio-

economic analysis such as power, conflict and hierarchy as emphasis is placed upon the

possibility and virtues to the individual of cooperation and collectivity.

From the perspective of social history, these omissions are extremely unattractive, especially

when they are complemented by what has been a more or less total disregard by social capital

of both the international and, for want of a better term, the elite – and, even more so, the

international elite. For its preferred domain is at the sub-national level (anywhere from family

to community or region), and its agents are the strata ranging from the impoverished to the

improvable. Those who hold and exercise power and privilege through the state are notable

for their absence (although benevolently applauding the notion from the sidelines). This,

together with other omissions, is hardly an attractive recipe for social history where one might

have hoped to find a more nuanced understanding of the factors making either for major

historical change or social stability, and the roles of power, class, conflict, gender, race, class,

etc. upon them.

Further, there are grander approaches to civil society, and its relationship to society more

generally, that have been more or less completely neglected by the social capital literature but

which are familiar to, and deployed by, historians. One of these, the gift relationship, derives

primarily from anthropology and its supposed antithesis to commodity relations.9 With

whatever validity it is applied, the opposition between gift and commodity is at least as rich as

social versus other types of capital as a means of approaching the historical as a relationship

9For critical overviews, see B. Fine, The Worldof Consumption: The Material and Cultural Revisited

(London, 2002); C. Lapavitsas, Social Foundations ofMarkets, Money and Credit (London, 2003).

446 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 7: Social capital versus social history

between the economic and the non-economic. Social capital has only occasionally and casually

been used in passing in the historical gift literature.10

A second alternative to social capital of appeal to historians is the analytical framework posed

by Polanyi, and the interaction between the commercial and the traditional, as captured by his

notions of the double movement (spread of the market and social protection) and

corresponding (dis)embeddedness. Once again, despite its potential affinities with the subject

matter and the strength of this tradition, Polanyi has been studiously ignored by the social

capital literature, although Granovetter and embeddedness have had some, predominantly

indirect, presence through appeal to networks. Interestingly, in the broader critical literature

on social capital, it has explicitly been seen both as an impoverished contribution relative to

Polanyi and as a way of promoting some form of compromise between neo-liberalism and

Third Wayism.11 As Craig and Porter put it, in part referring to social capital, such concepts

‘are hardly substitutes for the engines of social contest and embedding Polanyi

described. . . . Thus, a Polanyian perspective also encourages the prising apart of these

consensual domains and rationales, to see whose interests, contests and voices are being

smothered.’12 And, for Robison, social capital is simply the technocratic and neo-liberal

reflection of Polanyi’s double movement in the era of globalization under US hegemony.13 In

a JSTOR history journal search on Polanyi, the score is at least double that for social capital,

indicating where the discipline’s preference lies. But, possibly, the greatest put-down for social

capital in this respect comes from Granovetter. As modern pioneer, he is the least sophisticated

proponent of embeddedness,14 confessing to having drafted his classic contribution without

any thought of Polanyi,15 but he also describes how he sought unsuccessfully to push Putnam

to be more refined when the latter first mooted use of social capital. If social capital lies to the

other side of Granovetter in the understanding of the relationship between the economic and

the social, it is hardly surprising it has had little appeal to social historians.

These points are reinforced by consideration of an issue that has been kept in reserve until

now, although it was raised at an early stage of the literature, for everything is further

complicated by what has variously been termed dark, negative or perverse social capital. There

can be no presumption that outcomes will be beneficial for those with social capital, or those

without, either by their own or by external criteria. By its nature, social capital is both

10See J. Bestor, ‘Marriage transactions inRenaissance Italy and Mauss’s essay on the gift’,Past and Present, CLXIV (August 1999), 39; B.Cooper, ‘Women’s worth and wedding giftexchange in Maradi, Niger, 1907–89’, Journal ofAfrican History, XXXVI, 1 (1996), 121–40; and P.Benedict, ‘Faith, fortune and social structure inseventeenth-century Montpellier’, Past and Present,CLII (August 1996), 61. For Chinese guanxi associal capital and gift, see A. Kipnis, ‘The languageof gifts: managing guanxi in a north China village’,Modern China, XXII, 3 (July 1996), 285–314; M.Yang, ‘The gift economy and state power inChina’, Comparative Studies in Society and History,XXXI, 1 (January 1989), 25–54.

11D. Craig and D. Porter, ‘The Third Way andthe Third World: poverty reduction and social

inclusion strategies in the rise of ‘‘inclusive’’liberalism’, Review of International Political Economy,XII, 2 (May 2004), 226–63; R. Robison, ‘Neo-liberalism and the future of the world: markets andthe end of politics’, Critical Asian Studies, XXXVI, 3

(September 2004), 405–23.12Craig and Porter, op. cit., 257–8.13Robison, op. cit.14M. Granovetter, ‘Economic action and social

structure: the problem of embeddedness’, AmericanJournal of Sociology, XCI, 3 (November 1985), 481–510.

15See Thomas D. Beamish, Greta Krippner,Mark Granovetter, Nicole Biggart, Fred Block, etal., ‘Polanyi symposium: a conversation onembeddedness’, Socio-Economic Review, II, 1 (Jan-uary 2004), 109–35.

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 447

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 8: Social capital versus social history

inclusive and exclusive, so benefits for one can be at the expense of others, with obvious

relevance from the distribution of social capital across traditional socio-economic variables

such as rich and poor, powerful and weak, gender, race, age, class and so on. The putative

positive impact of social capital for one grouping can be at the expense of another. In addition,

social capital can be reasonably perceived to be negative in and of itself in light of its nature as

well as its purpose. Obvious and frequently cited examples are the Mafia, Nazism and the Ku

Klux Klan. From a conceptual point of view, the dark side to social capital is hardly surprising

since the analytical structure underpinning it is identical to that deployed by neo-liberalism’s

emphasis upon the virtues of the market, anti-statism, and the inevitability of rent-seeking

and/or corruption in case of non-market intervention. And the same social capital may be

positive in one instance but negative in another, depending on what, where, whom and how.

In general, though, the literature takes a benevolent view of social interaction with

corresponding implications for (how to achieve) social, and historical, change. It is surely no

accident that Fukuyama should quickly jump on the social capital bandwagon, perceiving it as

bountiful in developing countries but not in a way corresponding to modern political and

economic organizations and hence an obstacle to development.16 For him, familial ‘groups

have a narrow radius of trust’,17 and also the ‘economic function of social capital is to reduce

the transaction costs associated with formal coordination mechanisms like hierarchies,

bureaucratic rules, and the like’.18 So, for Fukuyama, globalization is the antidote, having

become the bearer of different types of social capital to developing countries, creating the

functionally new and destroying the dysfunctionally old.19 Does (modern) social capital also

bring the end of history, and a recognizable euthanasia of the historian? As Szreter puts it with

stunning clarity:20

It is implicit in this reading of social capital theory that there is an optimal dynamic

balance of bonding, bridging, and linking social capital, which simultaneously facilitates

democratic governance, economic efficiency and widely dispersed human welfare,

capabilities and functioning.

Such a stance has telling implications for development and transition as history in the

making, for social capital has been heavily promoted by the World Bank and has played a

correspondingly significant role in development studies. In a nutshell, social capital has served

as an ideal concept for easing the transition from the Washington to the post-Washington

Consensus.21 World Bank social capitalists have now accepted the analytical criticisms of social

16F. Fukuyama, ‘Social capital and develop-ment: the coming agenda’, SAIS Review, XXII, 1

(Winter/Spring 2002), 34.17F. Fukuyama, ‘Social capital and

civil society’, IMF Conference on SecondGeneration Reforms, Institute of PublicPolicy, George Mason University, 1 October1999, 3.

18ibid., 4.19F. Fukuyama, ‘Social capital, civil society and

development’, Third World Quarterly, XXII, 1

(February 2001), 7–20.

20S. Szreter, ‘The state of social capital: bringingback in power, politics, and history’, Theory andSociety, XXXI, 5 (October 2002), 580.

21For social capital from the World Bank itself,see A. Bebbington, M. Woolcock, S. Guggenheimand E. Olson,* ‘Grounding discourse in practice:exploring social capital debates at the WorldBank’, Journal of Development Studies, XL, 5 (June2004), 33–64; and A. Bebbington et al. (eds), TheSearch for Empowerment: Social Capital as Idea andPractice at the World Bank (Bloomfield, 2006). Andfor critique and context, see B. Fine, C. Lapavitsas

448 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 9: Social capital versus social history

capital and confess to having deployed it as a strategy to persuade World Bank economists to

take the social seriously. But, other than enhancing the economist’s rhetoric, the post-

Washington Consensus has primarily been used to legitimize the continuation of neo-liberal

policies in return for aid, albeit under the guise of being more state-friendly and promoting the

functioning of both market and non-market.

From humble beginnings, social capital has also mushroomed in its application to transition

economies. The World Bank sponsored a social capital initiative to explain ill-health in Russia

by distribution of social capital – this modest aim to be set against the drama of mortality rates

having risen over the country’s transition, unprecedented for a relatively developed economy.

In this vein, absence of social capital at all or of the right type has been seen as the cause of

malaise within transitional societies. The inevitable conclusion is that successful transition

depends on creating the right type of social capital, and/or social capital is seen as ameliorating,

for some at least, the negative excesses of an otherwise unexplained transition. For

Korosteleva,22 eastern Europe is subject to social capital as ‘the shadow societies of vertical

networks based on blat . . . rendering the official ‘‘democratic’’ settings inefficient and often

invalid. Such a system is also a good method of keeping discontent under control by diverting

the grievances and dissatisfaction to informal infrastructures that can deal with specific

concerns more efficiently.’ It all becomes a matter of, ‘How can a society break through to the

‘‘virtuous circle’’ that produces positive social capital?’23 Significantly, then, the bulk of this

literature has regressed to the modernization framework, taking some sort of ideal western

market democracy as its goal. Whether secure property rights (free from state interference and

inherited oligarchs), political participation through a well-functioning electoral system, or a

vibrant civil society, social capital offers analytical and policy panaceas. Yet this has, mercifully,

been recognized by the social capital literature itself to have unduly homogenized over a

highly diverse set of transitional societies for which individual histories and continuing context

are of decisive importance. As the most comprehensive and sophisticated review of the

literature puts it:24

The use of the term can be pseudoscientific and lead to poor quality research . . . pro-

blems with its definition, operationalization and measurement, as well as with

determining its sources, forms and consequences.

But there is still seen to be scope for continued use of social capital if avoiding ‘cultural

essentialism, ahistoricism, functionalism, blind rational choice adherence, apolitical attitude

and reductionism’, if only because it is ‘obvious that social capital has now firmly established

and J. Pincus (eds), Development Policy in theTwenty-First Century: Beyond the Post-WashingtonConsensus (London, 2001); B. Fine, Social Capitalversus Social Theory: Political Economy and SocialScience at the Turn of the Millennium (London,2001), chap. 8; B. Fine, ‘Social capital in wonder-land: the World Bank behind the looking glass’,Progress in Development Studies (forthcoming); andK. Jomo and B. Fine (eds), The New Development

Economics: After the Washington Consensus (Delhiand London, 2006).

22E. Korosteleva, ‘Can theories of social capitalexplain dissenting patterns of engagement in theNew Europe?’, Contemporary Politics, XII, 2 (June2006), 186.

23ibid., 187.24D. Mihaylova, Social Capital in Central and

Eastern Europe (Budapest, 2004), 136.

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 449

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 10: Social capital versus social history

itself in scholarly discourse and development practice and has a life (or many lives) of its own

which cannot easily be dismissed’.

3. THE HISTORICAL DOG THAT DID NOT BARK

Such a conclusion would appear to be inevitable from the evidence of Google. In debate over

the intellectual origins of social capital, Farr reports that ‘an internet search records some six

million items, among them the names of the Social Capital Foundation, Social Capital

Partners, Social Capital, Inc., and a new self-help book, Achieving Success through Social

Capital’.25 At a more academic level, I undertook full-scale literature searches on social capital

on three occasions, in 1999, 2002 and towards the end of 2006. For each, use was made of the

social science citation index, using social capital to search across title, abstract or key word, and

library catalogues were similarly searched for books on the topic. The task has become

increasingly taxing and difficult with over a thousand new articles for the last search, together

with a hundred or more new books teased out.

In addition, specifically for this article at end of 2006, a JSTOR search was made on social

capital. This has the advantage of being able to specify history journals alone. It has the

disadvantage of being subject to what those journals are, or are not, and a variable moving wall

of a few years across journals with access denied to more recent years – the most recent history

journal reference on social capital was to 2004. The JSTOR search, though, has been more

comprehensive, covering presence of the term anywhere in the text of the journals. No doubt,

there might have been better ways of going about seeking to place social capital in history

relative to the social sciences. But this is all liable to be good enough, with the general search

revealing more recent contributions across history, and the JSTOR search indicating its

presence during the formative and growth years.

Overall, these exercises confirm the relative absence of social capital from history journals.

While the JSTOR search threw up 292 items, only 161 of these were articles, with many book

reviews and front and back pieces (adverts etc.) making up the numbers. Only nineteen items

scored for title or abstract, over half of these coming from the special double issue on social

capital of the Journal of Interdisciplinary History (see below). Many of the items arose from area

publications such as the Journal of Southern African Studies or those also only related to history

such as Economic Geography that, none the less, did benefit from coverage as history journals.

Further, the ‘relevance ranking’ in the articles as far as social capital is concerned, an artefact of

the search engine provided as a service to readers, proved to be extremely low. One element in

relevance is the number of times the term appears and, across the articles covered, this soon

degenerated into one or two alone, frequently as a word in a cited reference only. By way of

contrast, general JSTOR searches across history journals for post-modernism and globalization

offered 3430 and 1558 items, respectively, and consumption essentially revealed a score of 216

on the narrower search by title or abstract.

The absence of social capital from history is confirmed by a useful, and independent, study

of the concept’s birth and growth by Forsman, a librarian offering a bibliographic study for

social capital of some quantitative and qualitative sophistication.26 She divides the diffusion of

25J. Farr, ‘In search of social capital’, PoliticalTheory, XXXV, 1 (February 2007), 54.

26M. Forsman, Development of Research Networks:The Case of Social Capital (Abo, 2005).

450 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 11: Social capital versus social history

social capital across the social sciences into three waves: the first to economics and sociology;

the second to education and medicine; and the third to business and psychology. History is

notable for its absence but, as will be seen, as and where it does make a presence, it does offer

insight even if by way of exception.

4. SOCIAL CAPITAL AS PLOUGHMAN’S LUNCH

One, possibly the single most important, way in which social capital has been addressed

historically, if not in history, has been through its own intellectual history as a term. A mini-

industry has emerged around who first used the term, when and how. Bourdieu is

acknowledged as the modern originator of the term and, after James Coleman, came Putnam

as the social capital superstar, popularizing the term in academia and beyond. Who preceded

them? The literature has stretched back further to highlight the work of, and presumed

precedent set by, Lyda Hanifan, in particular. However, by far the most accomplished

contribution of rediscovery in this vein has been Farr.27 He has brought the use of social capital

by John Dewey to the fore, implicitly charging earlier fans of Hanifan of oversight. And so the

search can go on for other and/or earlier pioneers.

I take an entirely different approach, that social capital does not have an intellectual history

at all, although such a history has been invented in light of its recent eruption.28 In setting aside

social capital as a concept with historical origins of its own, three arguments are of importance.

First, as already seen, the volume and influence of the literature over the past decade have been

as extraordinary as they had been so scarce before that. This, then, is not to suggest there is no

intellectual history or context to social capital, only that this must be used to explain its absence

in the past, not to trace its presence from there.

Second, then, why is use of social capital so minimal in the past (especially when present-day

proponents tend to argue that it was there in all but name)? One reason is that social capital is a

sort of oxymoron, with a minority critical literature appropriately questioning the extent to

which social capital is either social or capital, let alone both.29 In a nutshell, the terminology or

category of social capital bears with it a number of oppositions. If social capital is distinctive,

there must be some capital that is not social. The vast majority of social theory, and certainly

social history, mainstream neo-classical economics apart, with its methodological individualism

and physicalist interpretation of capital as a productive object or input, tends to see (economic)

capital in its social and historical context, as attached to capitalism. So there will be an aversion

to adopting a term that at least implicitly regards the economic as constituted by a capital that is

not social. By the same token, there will be an aversion to attaching the notion of social capital

to something that is non-economic, especially once the economic is associated with capitalism

and its market/non-market distinctions. In short, use of social capital carries connotations of

27J. Farr, ‘Social capital: a conceptual history’,Political Theory, XXXII, 1 (February 2004), 6–33. Seealso Farr, ‘In search’, op. cit., in response to B.Fine, ‘Eleven hypotheses on the conceptualhistory of social capital’, Political Theory, XXXV, 1

(February 2007), 47–53.28Fine, ‘Eleven hypotheses’, op. cit.

29See, for example, S. Smith and J. Kulynych, ‘Itmay be social, but why is it capital? The socialconstruction of social capital and the politics oflanguage’, Politics and Society, XXX, 1 (March 2002),149–86, and J. Roberts, ‘What’s ‘‘social’’ about‘‘social capital’’?’, British Journal of Politics and Interna-tional Relations, VI, 4 (November 2004), 471–93.

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 451

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 12: Social capital versus social history

economic capital being either private/individual or asocial. Who can accept such a

categorization of the economic other than Bourdieu as exception that proves the rule?

Third, as is evident from the ‘search and find’ intellectual history of social capital, this

conundrum has not entirely deterred its use in the past. None the less, those uses that do not

conform to the present perspective of social capitalists have simply been overlooked. This is

especially true, for example, of O’Connor’s Fiscal Crisis of the State, once a standard

contribution to the political economy of the welfare state in which social capital essentially

serves to represent state expenditures for social reproduction and, as such, is both economic

and social category.30

However, the JSTOR search through the social capital literature brings to light for the first

time, if not surprisingly, other more refined, interesting and significant marriages of the social

with capital, and ones that are appropriately used by historians. There has been a missing

history of the social capital of history. For historians, and others, have been concerned with

social as economic capital, not as its antithesis, and not least as differing social forms of economic

capital are attached to historical change. Leaving aside social capital as a capital city to nation or

region, the most common and least remarkable usage, other than in being overlooked in

intellectual histories, is use of social capital to stand for economic infrastructure, especially but

not exclusively transport. Such social capital is reasonably deemed in historical studies to be a

key element in economic development. And it is but a short step from social capital as physical

or economic infrastructure to its more general position as social and economic infrastructure,

incorporating education, for example. Strikingly, then, Dube et al. Suggest, in examining

Canada’s economic prospects, ‘Social capital is taken to include schools and universities,

churches and related buildings, hospitals, roads and streets, airports, sewer and water systems,

and other buildings and installations appertaining to public institutions and departments of

government’, with some agonizing over arbitrary boundaries in constructing statistical series

and the presence or not of direct or indirect profit motive (social capital as social or business

services).31 But they ultimately settle on a definition that is the reverse of its current location

within civil society, ‘assets for which society as a whole, through the medium of governments

and other public institutions, desires to assume a direct and continuing responsibility’.32

Inevitably, then, these considerations attach social capital to the role of the state, public

expenditure and nationalized industries, the opposite of its use today. Indeed, McDougall sees

social as state capital,33 Zobler as any economic other than physical capital,34 Simon argues that

social capital in the form of roads is a major factor reducing malnutrition,35 and Nast sees social

capital, as infrastructure, as the means of combating racial disadvantage by rectifying unequal

provision.36

30J. O’Connor, The Fiscal Crisis of the State(New York, 1973).

31Y. Dube, J. E. Howes and D. L. McQueen,Housing and Social Capital, Royal Commission onCanada’s Economic Prospects (Ottawa, 1957),1–2.

32ibid., 3.33D. McDougall, ‘Discussion of Shoyama and

Davis and Legler papers’, Journal of EconomicHistory, XXVI, 4 (December 1966), 553–5.

34L. Zobler ‘An economic-historical view ofnatural resource use and conservation’, EconomicGeography, XXXVIII, 3 (July 1962), 189–94.

35J. Simon, ‘The effects of population onnutrition and economic well-being’, Journal ofInterdisciplinary History, XIV, 2 (Autumn 1983),413–37.

36J. Nast, ‘Mapping the ‘‘unconscious’’: racismand the Oedipal family’, Annals of the Association ofAmerican Geographers, XC, 2 (June 2000), 215–55.

452 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 13: Social capital versus social history

On a different tack, as is entirely reasonable, social capital has appeared in the history

literature as the total or aggregate of economic capital. But, in general, such usage has been far

from mundane because it has been endowed with an analytical content that goes far beyond

adding up over individual capitals, and in a variety of ways. In general, there is the

presumption that the whole is more or different than the sum of the individual parts. To a large

extent, stepping outside the social capital literature, historical or otherwise, this is a matter of

economic theory or political economy. It concerns the workings of the economy as a whole,

and the place of the social as total capital within those workings. This is most obvious in the

case of Marxist political economy, and Marx himself, in addressing the laws of motion of

capitalism. More generally, it is indicative of the social capital in this sense having properties

that are different from, or independent of, the individual components out of which it is

constituted.

By the same token, social capital once considered in aggregate, systemically, can be broken

down again into its separate components in ways that differ from how it was made up out of

individual capitals. Thus, themes that have occurred across the history literature with explicit

reference to social capital include its national and international distribution, ownership and

control, its monopolization, and its impact upon the prospects for inducing productivity

increase through spillovers, diffusion or whatever. These and other themes around the total, or

social, capital are so well worn as to be obvious ports of call for occasional reference to them in

the past as social capital.

Another strand of the history literature lies somewhere askew of the infrastructure and total

capital approaches, for the idea of social capital can be attached to society and not just to

individuals. For all forms of revolutionary socialism, this is an incentive to highlight the

exploitation of those who work by those who do not, merely by virtue of (collective)

ownership or not of a portion of the social capital. Kelso quotes from the French cooperative

labour movement of the 1870s to this effect.37 The social capital should be owned by those

that produce it. Such considerations, in the context of solidarity over risk of injury in South

Wales coal mining, lead Bloor explicitly to reject social capital. Thus, ‘the Fed and the South

Wales miners were not engaging in civic effort, rather they were engaging in a process of

transformative conscientization. . . . Only if the coal owners and managers [and government

officials] are excluded from South Wales civic society can the collective health behaviour of

the miners be linked positively with contemporary analyses of social capital.’38 Or, as Smith

and Kulynych put it more generally, ‘for Putnam to conceptualize . . . [working class]

solidarity as a form of social capital makes a mockery of . . . aspirations that working-class

solidarity can help birth a new world not plagued by capitalist economic, political and social

relations’.39

Similarly, sentiments against the ravages of capitalism, but in favour of its reform, are to be

found in Catterall’s study of the British inter-war labour movement.40 Once understood as the

37M. Kelso, ‘The inception of the modernFrench labor movement (1871–79): a reappraisal’,Journal of Modern History, VIII, 2 (June 1936), 179.

38M. Bloor, ‘No longer dying for a living:collective responses to injury risks in South Walesmining communities, 1900–47’, Sociology, XXXVI, 1

(February 2002), 92.

39Smith and Kulynych, op. cit., 169.40P. Catterall, ‘Morality and politics: the Free

Churches and the Labour Party between the wars’,Historical Journal, XXXVI, 3 (September 1993), 683.

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 453

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 14: Social capital versus social history

capital of society, social capital for the labour movement, and especially for nonconformist

socialists, took on responsibilities of its own as well as requiring responsibility of individuals.

Social capital must be put to the public and individual good through moderating the excesses

of private ownership even to the point of abolishing it. Of course, milder stances can be

adopted, as reported by Elwitt’s study of education and the social question in late nineteenth-

century France. There is an appeal to social capital to show its human face, not least that, ‘the

summons to the rich held the hope that they would appear with generous purses’.41 For Smith,

though, in his account of the Tonypandy community in 1910, the social capital brings both

cheap consumer goods and entertainment as well as ‘the prevailing grimness of the

[manufacturing] environment’.42

Historical study and use of social capital as an economic category with social effect also arises

out of the impact of capitalism upon what has gone before. For, at the opposite extreme

politically to critique of social capital as reflecting negative aspects within the workings of

capitalism as a whole is the critique of the latter’s destructive implications for the powers (social

capital) of the ancien regime, as described by Wilson of early nineteenth-century Action

Francaise.43 Similarly, the claims of social capital against capitalism are to be found among

those who still retain an attachment to the land, and traditional forms of ownership. Social

capital takes on a meaning that is incompatible with capitalist ownership, social or otherwise.44

Thus, land as social capital is economic by departing from the principles of private ownership

and use.45

But the quintessential social capital of capitalism is money, and its ‘networks’, for the most

obvious collective and hence social form of ownership of capital is that attached to finance. As

Bryer perceptively reveals in his study of the controversy over the emergence of limited

liability in the UK in the 1850s, this is simply a commercial matter of efficiently pooling

society’s finances for the purposes of accumulation. Indeed, this ‘distinction between a world

fit for individual capitalists and a world fit for social capital, was the axis on which the debate

turned, a debate over, and choice between, different theories of political economy’.46 In short,

limited liability needed acceptance of social capital both in practice and in principle and, for

Bryer, this is itself best expressed by Marx for whom:47

With unlimited liability capital could not free itself from the idiosyncrasies of its owner

and conform to the law of social capital, to be employed to earn the risk-adjusted general

41S. Elwitt, ‘Education and the social questions:the Universites Populaires in late nineteenth-centuryFrance’, History of Education Quarterly, XXII, 1

(Spring 1982), 59.42D. Smith, ‘Tonypandy 1910: definitions of

community’, Past and Present, LXXXVII (May 1980),172.

43S. Wilson, ‘A view of the past: ActionFrancaise historiography and its socio-politicalfunction’, Historical Journal, XIX, 1 (March 1976),146.

44M. Fischbach, ‘Britain and the GhawrAbi ‘Ubayda Waqf controversy in TransJordan’,

International Journal of Middle Eastern Studies, XXXIII,4 (November 2001), 536.

45See also I. Logan and K. Mengisteab, ‘IMF–World Bank adjustment and structural transforma-tion in Sub-Saharan Africa’, Economic Geography,LXIX, 1 (January 1993), 1–24.

46R. Bryer, ‘The Mercantile Laws Commissionof 1854 and the political economy of limitedliability’, Economic History Review, L, 1 (February1997), 44.

47ibid., 49.

454 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 15: Social capital versus social history

rate of profit. From the point of view of social capital, an ‘equal return for equal capital’

was of a higher moral order than the responsibility of individual capitalists for their debts.

Thus, with limited liability, we have social capital without risk of loss of other assets contingent

upon collective performance, something anticipated in the commenda of mediaeval

Mediterranean trade, although Udovitch sees this as a reason for asserting that, ‘in the

commenda there is no social capital formed’, despite profits and risks being shared by investors

and their agents.48

Yet it is the stock exchange that is social capital par excellence. You share simply by putting

up money to buy. Barsky and de Long view it ‘as a social capital allocation mechanism’.49 This

is hardly controversial, although from Keynes onwards, if not before, there have been different

views than theirs over its efficacy in anticipating and generating the swings of the twentieth-

century economy in response to bull and bear markets. Does social capital in this form generate

sufficient investment, allocate it efficiently, and temper rather than generate economic crises?

Posing, let alone answering, such questions will not be found in the modern social capital

literature. Indeed, I do not even know of a single study of the social capital, in this sense, of

that legendary network of associates known as yuppies that drive the financial system or at least

its inflated rewards. Consequently, given how social capital has been deployed by historians, if

to a limited extent, two tentative conclusions can be drawn. On the one hand, attachment to

social capital as an economic category as discussed above can have prompted its more recent

use to be viewed with dismay. On the other hand, social capital as it has now become may

have discouraged historians from using the term at all. It is, for example, now widely

impossible to talk about economic and social infrastructure as social capital without running

the risk of being totally misunderstood. Put another way, from the perspective of historians, is

it possible that the appropriation of the term social capital in its modern form has driven out its

use in other ways, not least by historians themselves?

Furthermore, as revealed, the invented intellectual history of social capital is one that has

totally overlooked these other uses. It would be a mistake, though, to end the account of that

history at this point, for in taking the long view the most immediate history underpinning the

emergence of social capital has also tended to be overlooked (as well as how little but in diverse

ways that social capital has not been used in the past). This has two crucial elements. One,

already remarked, is how Bourdieu’s approach has given way to that of Coleman as

inspirational source. The second, totally overlooked in the literature, without exception,50

concerns the origins of social capital for Coleman himself (other than to refer to his empirically

flawed accounts of the relationship between social capital as family and neighbourhood and

educational attainment). Coleman was a late participant in the social exchange debate that began

in the 1960s and that sought to base social theory on aggregation across individual interactions,

primarily basing its methodological individualism on psychological motivation. Just as the

leading proponents of social exchange admitted defeat, Coleman adopted the remarkable

48A. Udovitch, ‘At the origins of the westernCommenda: Islam, Israel, Byzantium?’, Speculum,XXXVII, 2 (January 1962), 198.

49R. Barsky and J. Bradford de Long, ‘Bull andbear markets in the twentieth century’, Journal ofEconomic History, L, 2 (June 1990), 268.

50Although this is fully documented inFine, Social Capital versus Social Theory, op. cit.,chap. 5.

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 455

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 16: Social capital versus social history

expedients of switching from psychological to economic motivation, and terminologically

switching from social exchange to social capital. This both launched the latter and detached it

from the humiliation of social exchange to which Coleman himself never made any reference.

In addition, newly discovered are the earlier rational choice origins for social capital in

the work of James Buchanan, the Nobel Prize Winner for public choice theory. For him: ‘The

simple exchange of apples and oranges between two traders – this institutional model is the

starting point for all I have done.’51 But Buchanan is not dismissive of the social as such as

opposed to the individual as if trading fruit, for he is wary of the loss of America’s idealized

tradition of liberty:52

My diagnosis of American society is informed by the notion that we are living during a

period of erosion of ‘social capital’ that provides the basic framework for our culture, our

economy, and our polity – a framework within which the ‘free society’ in the classically

liberal ideal perhaps came closest to realization in all of history.

This was, in fact, first published by Buchanan in 1981. And the quote continues: ‘My efforts

have been directed at trying to identify and to isolate the failures and breakdowns in

institutions that are responsible for this erosion.’53 In effect, putting this provocatively,

Coleman uses Buchanan without acknowledgement (with Putnam to follow Coleman),

surprising not least as Coleman and Buchanan were heavily involved together in The Public

Choice Society from its origins, suggesting there is no way that Coleman could not know of

Buchanan’s views on social capital.

The explicit rationale for social capital as far as Coleman is concerned is the single-minded

promotion of rational choice theory. Within the social capital literature this has been

acknowledged, to some extent, but the use of social categories of analysis and the buffer

provided by Putnam have tended to conceal this motivation. Indeed, social capital to a large

extent is inconsistent with rational choice theory, seeking to deploy social categories

independent of their individualistic origins or at least some mix of the two. Thus, it cannot be

argued that the suspicion of the rational choice origins of social capital had deterred historians,

for these have been more concealed than highlighted by the literature itself. The one

exception is with the economic.

5. WHY NOT FROM ECONOMICS TO HISTORY?

For the vast bulk of the social capital literature, economics does not figure at all. The economic

at most sits unexamined in the background or is the object favourably enhanced by the

presence of social capital. Significantly, this does imply a breach with the purest commitment

to laissez-faire. Markets work imperfectly in the absence of social capital or, putting it more

positively, markets work better in its presence. But, crucially, and reflecting its lack of systemic

51Quoted in S. Amadae, Rationalizing CapitalistDemocracy: The Cold War Origins of Rational ChoiceLiberalism (Chicago, 2003), 151.

52J. Buchanan, Liberty, Market and State: PoliticalEconomy in the 1980s (Brighton, 1986), 108, cited inAmadae, op. cit., 151–2.

53J. Buchanan, ‘Moral community, moral order,or moral anarchy’, Abbot Memorial Lecture, no.17, Colorado College (Colorado Springs, 1981).

456 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 17: Social capital versus social history

and critical content, such putative economic benefits are presumed in the absence of any

economic analysis itself. However the economy performs, and whichever economy it is, it

does better if supported by social capital.

This has placed social capital in a particular relationship with mainstream economics. It has

meant that the concept has been treated with suspicion since, from an orthodox perspective, a

capital should be a stock purposively built up by deliberate investment and underpinning a

return. However, this partly physicalist interpretation of capital has also been the basis for

broaching (social) capital as those (productive) resources that depart from this simple formula.

While natural, physical, human (and, more generally, personal) and financial capital serve as

the core in resource allocation, efficiency and equilibrium, social capital stands for anything

else, not private or tangible, that might contribute to economic performance. Significantly,

one of the earliest economists to deploy the notion of social capital was Gary Becker, the most

hard-boiled and leading proponent of his so-called economic approach to social science in

which all economic and social phenomena are reduced to the ‘as if’ market-based

consequences of rational optimizing individuals. As the co-organizer with Coleman of the

rational choice seminar at the University of Chicago, he was the pioneer economist in using

social capital as a residual explanatory factor after taking all other types of capital into

account.54

It is not surprising that Becker’s early use of social capital should have been overlooked by

the majority of the literature, economic or otherwise. His as if perfect market approach to

economic and social analysis departs from the ethos of social capital in the latter’s emphasis on

both the imperfections of the market and the potential for motives other than economic

rationality even when pitched at the individualistic level. Like Bourdieu, but at the opposite

extreme, Becker is an embarrassment. Consequently, the more natural home for social capital

within mainstream economics is the market imperfections, especially information-theoretic,

approach that emphasizes the significance of transaction costs (and how social capital might

reduce them). Without going into details, this argues both that markets work imperfectly and

non-market responses are explained by this, with the possibility of tempering and even

eliminating inefficiencies. Social capital neatly falls within the realm of this economic framing

of the rationale for the non-market or non-economic.

There are, though, three important aspects of the incorporation of social capital into

economics. First, as argued by Fine and Milonakis,55 the highest priority within an orthodoxy

that excludes alternatives to an unprecedented degree is its commitment to its technical

apparatus of production and utility functions and, to a high if lesser extent, its commitment to

its technical architecture of optimization, efficiency and equilibrium. As a result, social capital

is treated, and often appears formally, as an element in a production or utility function as if a

material input or consumption good, respectively. Alternatively it is presumed to reduce

transaction costs or to smooth the operation of the market. Second, mainstream economics

purports to assess theory against the evidence through econometrics. This has rendered social

capital a particularly attractive avenue for investigation as its many dimensions and

54Fine, Social Capital versus Social Theory, op. cit.,chap. 3.

55B. Fine and D. Milonakis, From EconomicsImperialism to Freakonomics: The Shifting Boundaries

between Economics to Other Social Sciences (London,2009).

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 457

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 18: Social capital versus social history

corresponding data sets, generally available or case-study constructed, fit readily into

professional practices.

Third, social capital has emerged across the social sciences just as economics imperialism, or

its colonization of the other disciplines, has entered a new phase corresponding to the shift

away from Becker’s economic approach, reducing the social to the narrowly conceived

economic rationality in as if perfect market conditions. By contrast, the market imperfections

approach to economics has opened up the social as never before, both in scope and palatability

to the other social sciences. Not only is the market no longer seen as primarily perfect, but the

non-market or social is also seen as significant as the endogenized response to those

imperfections. To put it in the vernacular, institutions, customs, history, culture and, of course,

social capital now matter to economic performance, and economists can prove it by

mathematics, and especially through game theory!56

This new phase of economics imperialism has spawned a range of new fields in and around

economics, or developments within them: the new economic sociology, the new institutional

economics, the new political economy, the new economic geography, the new

financial economics, the new development economics, the new welfare economics and so

on. These have offered corresponding incursions into the other social sciences. But the nature

and extent of its impact across the social sciences is uneven, reflecting both the continuing

dynamic of colonized disciplines and, in particular, the acceptability of the methods and

content of mainstream economics. For, while the new phase of economics imperialism does

accept the salience of the non-economic, it continues to rely upon the technical apparatus and

architecture of the methodological individualism associated with economic rationality.

All this is pertinent to the general reception of the new economics imperialism within

history, and of social capital in particular. The discipline is marked by a division between

‘economic’ and ‘social’ history, whose origins derive from the earlier assault of mainstream

economics upon history in its earlier phase of economics imperialism, giving rise to the

cliometric revolution, or aptly named new economic history.57 Inevitably, social history has

either steered away from the economic altogether, on which see below, or has deployed an

entirely different basis for its economics in its understanding of capital, capitalism, class, power,

institutions and so on.

With the new phase of economics imperialism, however, cliometrics has itself gone through

a corresponding reform, and advance on its own terms, to give rise to what can be dubbed the

newer economic history.58 It purports to accept the criticisms of the new economic history for

its neglect of institutions, culture, etc., and to re-engage with social history on these terms.

Some time after this initiative had been launched, one of its originators, Peter Temin, felt it

appropriate to suggest to the readers of the Journal of Economic History that it is ‘kosher to talk

56ibid.,57N. Lamoreaux, ‘Economic history and the

cliometric revolution’ in A. Molho and G. Wood(eds), Imagined Histories: American Historians Interpretthe Past (Princeton, 1998).

58B. Fine, ‘From the newer economic history toinstitutions and development?’, Institutions andEconomic Development, I, 1, 105–36; Fine and

Milonakis, op. cit.; D. Milonakis and B. Fine,‘Douglass North’s remaking of economic history:a critical appraisal’, Review of Radical PoliticalEconomics, XXXIX, 1 (March 2007), 27–57 andReinventing the Economic Past: Method and Theory inthe Evolution of Economic History (London, 2010;forthcoming).

458 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 19: Social capital versus social history

about culture’ as a force of economic history.59 He made explicit reference to Putnam and to

social capital, seeing it as a force for industrialization and as a reason why ‘historians need to

make these connections themselves to get through the plethora of information and

communicate with economists’.60 Indeed, little less modest than Putnam’s claim that social

capital is the key to differential development between the north and south of Italy over the best

part of a millennium, Temin argues ‘that the particular form of social capital I call Anglo-

Saxon culture was uniquely suited to the progress of industrialization over the past two

centuries’.61

This is very big history on a very wide scale, and there are good reasons why the

corresponding overtures to social historians will and should have failed in light of the

continuing antipathy to mainstream economics even in its market imperfections version. Most

telling, Temin’s casual use apart, with its exaggerated claims, is the limited extent to which

social capital has been used by economic as opposed, paradoxically, to social historians (see

below). If, indeed, Temin and his culture are the historical handmaidens of mainstream

economics, social capital should have been adopted within (the newer) economic history itself

at an early stage, and extensively, just as it has across the other social sciences. Why has this not

been the case?

The simple and compelling answer is that an equally flexible and all-encompassing category

was already in place within the new(er) economic history prior to the emergence of the social

capital juggernaut. It was the idea of institutions and its corresponding attachment to the new

institutional economics; see Hadiz for a critique of the new institutionalism with social capital

as a component part in the context of decentralization in Indonesia.62 And, just as the single

figure of Putnam more than any other has symbolized social capital, so the idea of institutions

as the residual explanatory factor for economic history has been identified with Douglass

North. As a leading figure in founding the new economic history, he subsequently refined his

analysis to incorporate property relations followed by institutions. Significantly, these are

defined as the formal or informal arrangements through which society governs itself and the

economy, either more or less efficiently through customary behaviour and ideological beliefs.

There is an exact analytical correspondence with social capital; and North’s treatment of

institutions in this way attained its analytical pinnacle and point of reference for the new

institutional economics and economic history with the publication of Institutions, Institutional

Change and Economic Performance in 1990.63

Thus, just as social history has had scant regard for social capital, especially in light of the

direction it has taken, so economic history has had no need for it. For the latter, this is an

accident of the division of the discipline into these two camps, and the evolution of the

new(er) economic history around the trajectory taken by Douglass North and the new

institutional economics more generally. For the former, the more palatable version of social

capital for social historians associated with Bourdieu was already in decline by the mid-1990s as

the concept took off. At most, social capital for social historians occasionally retained that link

59P. Temin, ‘Is it kosher to talk about culture?’,Journal of Economic History, LVII, 2 (June 1997), 267–87.

60ibid., 282. See also 272.61ibid., 268.62V. Hadiz, ‘Decentralization and democracy

in Indonesia: a critique of neo-institutionalist

perspectives’, Development and Change, XXXV, 4

(September 2004), 697–718.63D. North, Institutions, Institutional Change and

Economic Performance (Cambridge, 1990).

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 459

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 20: Social capital versus social history

while discarding the uses that had equally occasionally arisen on an entirely different basis in

the past.

6. FROM SOCIAL CAPITAL TO HISTORY

This all provides the context within which to review in more detail, if selectively, the impact

of social capital on history. The obvious starting point is the special two-part issue of Journal of

Interdisciplinary History,64 and, presumably, there must have been some social capital, as it were,

putting this together, not least with Putnam contributing as an author. It was edited by

Rotberg, who offered an introductory essay entitled ‘Social capital and political culture in

Africa, America, Australasia, and Europe’ that, together with the chronological span of

the articles, indicated the putative geographical as well as the historical scope of the

contributions.65 What is most significant about the double special issue is that it is the

exception that proves the rule. Presumably, it was intended to be the launching pad for social

capital within history. If so, it has failed miserably. There have been no further special issues

(which are common across the other social sciences), and limited numbers of subsequent

contributions that do fully embrace the notion as opposed to casual mention in passing.

In this vein, contributions from within history have tended to fall on either side of the

discipline in economic or social orientation, flirting with the new institutional economics and

its analytical foundations in offering an alternative in line with the new economics imperialism

or following a cultural route without economic content, respectively. Some fall across the

divide, as social capital is a recipe for eclecticism, and the motivation and origins for

contributions in using, or referring to, social capital are idiosyncratic and not always

transparent. What follows is a cursory overview, drawing predominantly upon the JSTOR

search.

For the economic, Allen and Reed construct duelling from 1500 to 1900 as a screening

device, a means of demonstrating commitment to, and gaining, patronage, a way of

overcoming informational imperfections with regard to loyalty to the crown.66 Carp points

positively as social capital to the bonds between firefighters in the eighteenth-century United

States, not least in Charleston and the South more generally, a consequence of their defence of

private property and their connections with local politicians.67 This allowed them to take a

lead in the fight for independence from Britain, and even to start fires in order to prevent

property falling into British hands. One cannot help but wonder, however, about the

implications for slavery and racism.68 Carmona and Simpson deploy social capital in their

account of the rise and fall of sharecropping in Catalonia, but essentially rely upon the moral

hazard, opportunism and principal-agent discourse of the new information-theoretic approach

64Journal of Interdisciplinary History, XXIX, 3–4

(1999), reprinted as R. Rotberg (ed.), Patterns ofSocial Capital: Stability and Change in HistoricalPerspective (Cambridge, 2001).

65R. Rotberg ‘Social capital and politicalculture in Africa, America, Australasia, andEurope’, Journal of Interdisciplinary History, XXIX, 3

(Winter 1999), 339–56.66D. Allen and C. Reed, ‘The duel of honor:

screening for unobservable social capital’, American

Law and Economics Review, VIII, 1 (March 2006),81–115.

67B. Carp, ‘Fire of liberty: firefighters, urbanvoluntary culture, and the revolutionary move-ment’, William and Mary Quarterly, LVIII, 4

(October 2001), 781–818.68For this for contemporary New York, see

S. McNamee and R. Miller, The Meritocracy Myth(Lanham, 2004), 76.

460 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 21: Social capital versus social history

to economics.69 This has itself been prominent in new literature on sharecropping, offered as

an alternative to analyses based on class and power (and, it would appear, sharecroppers’ own

self-perception). As they put it, ‘Contemporaries often considered the contract synonymous

with ‘‘exploitation’’ and ‘‘impoverishment’’, terms frequently found in the more traditional

literature on sharecropping.’70 Contracting is also perceived to be difficult across scattered

Australian gold mines at the end of the nineteenth century, meaning less social capital by

which to come to amicable agreements and, hence, more costly litigation in the courts.71 In an

early application in this vein, the notion of social capital, referencing Coleman, has been

deployed to explain the laying of plank roads in New York as a reflection of the ability of

community spirit to overcome the problem of free riders.72 Unfortunately, for the authors, by

comparison with the contemporaneously published Putnam on Italy, they do not seem to have

been able to project planks to present-day US civil society.

Not surprisingly, social historians have referenced social capital when dealing with gender

and marriage (see also below). For Brightman, social capital facilitates foraging and hunting in

primitive societies but offers more in terms of standard anthropological concerns with taboo

and gender politics.73 In Kapteijn’s study of northern Somali, with reference to gifts,

bridewealth and reciprocity, women are social capital for their men, and children for their

mothers, relations that tend to be undermined by commercialization and the state.74 And

Pouwels sees marriage as the social capital by which merchants could integrate themselves and

promote their business along the African east coast prior to 1800.75

In an unwitting anticipation of a rapidly growing literature on (lack of) social capital and

crime (or any other deviancy), McIntosh suddenly imports the idea into her response for a

debate on the Controlling of Misbehavior across the medieval/early modern divide.76 It

accumulates with the formation of the nation-state, again anticipating social capital as

modernization. She wishes to incorporate religion and social factors. To do so, she

draws ‘upon the powerful concept of ‘‘social capital’’’. Her analytical opportunism, freely

referencing Bourdieu, Coleman and Putnam as an unproblematic troika of sources, is scarcely

concealed:77

Regardless of whether one prefers a definition drawn from sociology/political science or

a more anthropologically focused usage, social capital is produced by interactions between

people, either informally or through more structured associations. . . . Because social

69J. Carmona and J. Simpson, ‘The ‘‘RabassaMorta’’ in Catalan viticulture: the rise and declineof a long-term sharecropping contract, 1670s–1920s’, Journal of Economic History, LIX, 2 (June1999), 290–315.

70ibid., 290.71B. Khan, ‘Commerce and cooperation:

litigation and settlement of civil disputeson the Australian frontier, 1860–1900’, Journal ofEconomic History, LX, 4 (December 2000), 1088–119.

72J. Majewski, Christopher Baier and DanielKlein, ‘Responding to relative decline: the plankroad boom of antebellum New York’, Journal ofEconomic History, LIII, 1 (March 1993), 106–22.

73R. Brightman, ‘The sexual division of fora-ging labor: biology, taboo, and gender politics’,Comparative Studies in Society and History, XXXVIII, 4

(October 1996), 687–729.74L. Kapteijns, ‘Gender relations and the

transformation of the northern Somali pastoraltradition’, International Journal of African HistoricalStudies, XXVIII, 2 (1995), 241–59.

75R. Pouwels, ‘Eastern Africa and the IndianOcean to 1800: reviewing relations in historicalperspective’, International Journal of African HistoricalStudies, XXXV, 2–3 (2002), 385–425.

76M. McIntosh, ‘Response’, Journal of BritishStudies, XXXVII, 3 (July 1998), 291–305.

77ibid., 294.

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 461

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 22: Social capital versus social history

capital serves to link individuals and groups, operating both laterally and vertically, it is an

important explanatory tool when examining the development of a participatory nation-

state.

And, also, one that controls ‘misbehaviour’. Significantly, as Gaggio also recognizes,78 her

contribution to the special issue of the Journal of Interdisciplinary History is one that emphasizes

the positive gains and role of women in medieval and early modern England, as opposed to

their exclusion and oppression.79

Other, more sophisticated uses of social capital are explicit about their ties to Bourdieu-type

interpretations and uses of the concept. Shetler focuses on as limited an object as a Kiroba text

of popular history as a form of social capital in Tanzania since it depicts a constellation of

networks and social relations that can inform and sustain those who draw upon it.80 Pellow

perceives the powers and legitimacy of chiefs as representing their shifting social capital in

response to shifting circumstances in turn of the last century Accra, not least in being

contingent upon British patronage.81 Smith allows for intersection between race, ethnicity and

gender, as colour of skin as social capital allows for a better marriage in Guatemala.82 Franklin

has inspired a number of studies of the way in which Afro Americans have used their social and

other capital to promote community education and other advances, although the social capital

of racism is equally important in the history of ‘exclusion’.83 MacHardy does deploy

Bourdieu’s approach to address dissent among Protestant nobles in sixteenth- and seventeenth-

century Habsburg.84 The same is so of Schoenbrun’s account of gendered relations around the

East African Great Lakes before the fifteenth century.85 Without explicit reference to

Bourdieu as such, Muldrew rounds up ‘the social capital of display’ in and of itself as a feature

of early modern England, and through generosity, ‘[Silver] plate was also an important item in

gift exchange’.86 But such social capital is perceived to have been under threat from money or

monied capital, for the ‘hoarding of money, and the advantage it gave one person to do what

they wanted, were always seen as a threat to trust, sociability and the circulation of social

capital upon which early modern exchange depended’.87

78Gaggio, op. cit., 509.79M. McIntosh, ‘The diversity of social capital

in English communities, 1300–1640 (with a glanceat modern Nigeria)’, Journal of InterdisciplinaryHistory, XIX, 3 (Winter 1999), 459–90.

80J. Shetler, ‘A gift for generations to come: aKiroba popular history from Tanzania and identityas social capital in the 1980s’, International Journal ofAfrican Historical Studies, XXVIII, 1 (1995), 69–112.

81D. Pellow, ‘The power of space in theevolution of an Accra Zongo’, Ethnohistory,XXXVIII, 4 (Autumn 1991), 414–50.

82C. Smith, ‘Race–class–gender ideology in Gua-temala: modern and anti-modern forms’, ComparativeStudies in Society and History, XXXVII, 4 (October 1995),723–49. See also Hunter, op. cit.

83V. Franklin, ‘‘‘ Location, location, location’’:the cultural geography of African Americans:

introduction to a journey’, Journal of AfricanAmerican History, LXXXVII, 1 (January 2002), 1–11.

84K. MacHardy, ‘The rise of absolutism andnoble rebellion in early modern Habsburg Austria,1570 to 1620’, Comparative Studies in Society andHistory, XXXIV, 3 (July 1992), 407–38 and ‘Culturalcapital, family strategies and noble identity in earlymodern Habsburg Austria 1579–1620’, Past andPresent, CLXIII (May 1999), 36–75.

85D. Schoenbrun, ‘Gendered histories betweenthe Great Lakes: varieties and limits’, InternationalJournal of African Historical Studies, XXIX, 3 (1997),461–92.

86C. Muldrew, ‘‘‘Hard food for Midas’’: cashand its social value in early modern England’, Pastand Present, CLXX (February 2001), 78–120, 111.

87ibid., 119.

462 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 23: Social capital versus social history

Literature for the modern period sends this antithesis between social capital and money into

reverse, with the one serving to support the other in light of the need for trust of the borrower

on the part of the lender. Interestingly, this theme within the newer economic history and the

newer financial economics has been muted as far as social capital is concerned, except when it

comes to Grameen Banking and the like, for the new institutional economics suffices for the

purpose. Yet for van Leeuwen, at least, such money allowed an entree into higher status

through charitable giving.88 The poor themselves, though, are perceived to have had less

honourable motives, displaying ‘an intuitive knowledge of the value of what sociologists and

anthropologists call social capital’, creating norms of mutual support, ‘not solely a form of

spreading risks over time’ but also as a means of accessing information on support from

others.89 In short, as far as social capital is concerned, ‘The virtual certainty that an investment

would pay off in the future naturally increased the willingness to invest.’

But, by a long way, the most accomplished use of social capital in history is to be found in

Ogilvie’s book on women in early modern Germany, and the role of guilds.90 Her starting

point is social networks, and these are used to frame the creation and significance of social

capital (which only really appears in her book after page 340). Networks only become social

capital through closure, by restricting membership as well as allowing it, whether by gender,

ethnicity, religion or whatever.91 Just as inclusion can benefit those who are members, so

exclusion can harm those who are not. She concludes, ‘Social networks generate social capital,

which not only facilitates collective action but also sustains commonly shared norms . . . these

norms not only penalized women in each generation, but perpetuated and entrenched

themselves, penalizing future generations’.92 She seems, however, to go further in her article,

recognizing that guilds ‘achieved or lost power not as a function of whether their social capital

offered efficient institutional solutions to market failures, but as a function of whether it

endowed them with a powerful bargaining position within the local institutional and political

framework’.93 In other words, ‘social capital’, and she herself uses inverted commas, is a

consequence of the social networks of power, and not the more or less effective correction of

market imperfections as would be proposed by economic theory and its extrapolation to

history. With this approach, and its application, there can be few complaints, but it is far from

clear what light is shed by appealing to social capital, or that it is open to generalization from

one case-study to another.

7. HISTORY BY BRINGING BOURDIEU BACK IN?

Whether for economic history by being beaten to the starting line by new institutional

economics or for social history in filling a mixed but small bag of applications, social capital is

notable for its absence from history. Is there a greater role for social capital in social history if,

as is suggested by Gaggio, it draws upon Bourdieu’s approach? The latter’s profile in the

88M. van Leeuwen, ‘Logic of charity: poor reliefin pre-industrial Europe’, Journal of InterdisciplinaryHistory, XXIV, 4 (Spring 1994), 596.

89ibid., 603.90S. Ogilive, A Bitter Living: Women, Markets,

and Social Capital in Early Modern Germany(Oxford, 2003).

91ibid., 341.92ibid., 352.93S. Ogilvie, ‘Guilds, efficiency, and social

capital: evidence from German proto-industry’,Economic History Review, LVII, 2 (December 2002),329.

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 463

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 24: Social capital versus social history

literature sank considerably during the late 1990s as rational choice functionalist sociologist,

Coleman, and then Putnam came to the fore. But, recently, Bourdieu has become more

acknowledged once again, especially as a way of bringing ‘context’ back in.

There is much to commend in Bourdieu’s approach to social capital. First, he sees it as one

among a number of capitals, alongside the cultural, symbolic and economic, all but the last of

which have tended to be subsumed under social capital in the subsequent literature. Second,

while appeal to these different types of capital is generalized across a huge historical range, from

the Sun King to contemporary French society, Bourdieu is adamant that each application is

context-specific, for which he posits his own investigative apparatus involving habitus and

field, corresponding notions notably absent from other social capital literature. Instead, context

for the social capital literature has generally been limited to the acknowledgement of the

presence of other variables rather than attention to meaning grounded in discursive practices.

Third, Bourdieu is focused upon questions of class, power, conflict and the way in which

different capitals are formed and play a role in reproduction and transformation. Again, the

contrast with the subsequent literature is striking.

Despite, or even because of, these favourable elements, Bourdieu’s notion of (social) capital

also exhibits serious weaknesses. First and foremost is the limited understanding of economic

capital. If this were there, for example, then it would be impossible for other capitals to range

so freely historically across contexts where the economic has yet to develop its modern forms

and which play an influential role on the symbolic, cultural and social. For, once capital as such

is pinned down, it is necessary to have distinguished between capitalism and its economics, and

that of other historical periods where capitalism does not prevail. ‘Habitus’ and ‘field’ are

permissive in this respect, but they make little headway from an analytical point of view.

In addition, it is precisely the peculiar nature of ‘economic’ capital, and its attachment to

capitalism, that has inspired social theory to comprehend the special relationship between the

economic and the non-economic, ranging over Weber’s Protestant ethic and rationality and

order, Polanyi’s embeddedness and double movement, anthropology’s gift versus commodity,

and so on. Despite his emphasis on context, Bourdieu’s notion of capital floats too freely across

history in failing to identify the structures, processes and relations to which capital and

capitalism are attached.

Second, and an exception that proves the rule, is the fluidity that accompanies the notion of

capital in Bourdieu, of whatever type and context. Specifically, for him, if not exactly as if a

price relationship, each capital is money-like in the sense of being exchangeable to greater or

lesser degree into another type. But the qualitative and quantitative nature of such relations are

so diverse and variable, with the exception of money capital itself, that it makes little sense to

treat the cultural, symbolic and social as if they were capital.

It also courts the risk, not only of taking the economic as given, but as non-social as opposed

to the non-economic. By contrast, for Marxist political economy, for example (economic)

capital is profoundly social with definite relations, structures, forms, processes and laws of

development of its own as well as with profound implications for corresponding impact upon

the cultural, symbolic and social (as non-economic). This is not a matter of reducing these to

the economic but of not reducing the economic to the asocial.

Of this, of course, Bourdieu is not deeply guilty if only because of his insistence upon class,

power, conflict, etc., and context, even if not drawing heavily upon a political economy of

capitalism. If the social capital literature had confined itself to Bourdieu-type analyses, there

464 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 25: Social capital versus social history

would be only little of which to complain, and we would have received a bag of disparate case-

studies with nothing to connect them to one another other than a common and peculiar

terminology. Such was the situation before Coleman trumped Bourdieu, after which the

common terminology is taken to suggest that the different case-studies share something

substantive in common, the social as represented by social capital. Paradoxically, as indicated,

Bourdieu was sidelined during social capital’s meteoric rise, but he is now being brought back

in on a piecemeal basis as an incoherent fixing device for context for the unduly abstract social

capital, so diverse and contingent is its scope of application. Significantly, Bourdieu’s other

types of capital, and his emphasis on class, conflict and power, etc., remain notable for their

absence other than occasionally as a token addition of context. The point is that while

Bourdieu can be brought back in,94 this does not mean you get Bourdieu back by doing so, as

is evident from the attempt by Svendsen and Svendsen to construct a social capital with

‘Bourdieuconomics’ that moulds him in a market imperfection direction, entirely compatible

with mainstream economics.95

Is this necessarily the case, or does history have the capacity to use social capital to restore

Bourdieu within its own borders and even, by example, without? Gaggio presumes so, but

without much account of history’s own dynamic and relations with the other social sciences,

and why it, unlike other disciplines, should be able to avoid social capital’s unsubtle charms.

Essentially, his case rests on his own case-study, for which he finds Bourdieu and social capital

of use. But, as addressed here, the bigger historiographical questions concern why history

should not have jumped the social capital bandwagon already and, if it had, what would have

been the result.

8. THERE IS NO ALTERNATIVE?

It is apparent, and with Gaggio in agreement, that there have been compelling reasons why

social history should have eschewed social capital in view of its content and momentum. Will

this continue to be the case? Across the profession, there are three potential, not mutually

exclusive, directions that might be followed. One is for social capital to gather strength and to

prosper, contingent in part upon how social capital itself evolves, most likely within newer

economic history as it opportunistically complements or displaces ‘institutions’ at the current

edge of mainstream economic history. The second option, at the opposite extreme, is for

historians to continue in the main to ignore social capital although, as and when it does prosper

on or across the discipline’s boundaries, it will prove both irksome and potentially a Trojan

horse for the previous outcome. Significantly, a recent book on civil society fails to address the

social capital phenomenon, apparently because it was not to be taken seriously.96 At the very

least, historians can hardly be expected to take seriously the claim by social capitalists that they

are bringing back in civil society or civilizing economists, for whatever the validity of social

94Szreter, ‘The state of social capital’, op. cit.,616–17.

95G. Svendsen and G. Svendsen, ‘On the wealthof nations: Bourdieuconomics and social capital’,Theory and Society, XXXII, 5/6 (2003), 607–31 andThe Creation and Destruction of Social Capital:

Entrepreneurship, Cooperative Movements andInstitutions (Cheltenham, 2004).

96J. Hall and F. Trentmann (eds), Civil Society: AReader in History, Theory and Global Politics(Basingstoke, 2005).

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 465

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 26: Social capital versus social history

capital’s claim that it rectifies the absence of civil society across the other social sciences, this is

laughable as far as (social) history and historians are concerned.

Nevertheless, the third option, and the one favoured here, is for historians to engage fully

and uncompromisingly critically with social capital by exposing its legion deficiencies and

offering constructive alternatives, that reject it rather than proposing new, improved versions.

This is a departure from Gaggio although, as already observed, there is considerable agreement

over the impoverishment of the bulk of the social capital literature as it is. But there are also

differences. His stance is one of acknowledging the limitations of social capital and of putting

these right in individual case-study. This is a possibility, as social capital is sufficiently fluid

conceptually that it can take on any mantle; but it is also to take an unduly narrow view of the

intellectual dynamic of social capital for the following reasons.

First, Gaggio takes insufficient account of the collective weight of the critical deficiencies of

social capital that have been exposed here and which explain the historian’s reluctance to

engage. Second, in particular, this means that individual contributions, however scathing and

reconstructive, will be deployed to legitimize and not to move social capital from its current

trajectory of simply absorbing criticism as addition of another variable. Third, and most

important, Gaggio takes no account of the broader intellectual environment that has spawned

social capital.

Social capital has thrived in that intellectual context peculiar to the 1990s, in which there has

been a dual reaction against the extremes both of neo-liberalism and post-modernism. Like its

counterpart, globalization, but as its complement and opposite in many respects, social capital

has rejected the idea that markets work perfectly and embraced the idea of getting real about

how people go about their (daily) lives.97 The global, though, is notable for its absence from

the world of social capital, with the exception of a more recently burgeoning literature around

global management. Social capital is more about communities accepting the world as it is and

bettering themselves on this basis.

Thus, while both globalization and social capital parallel one another in seeking to come to

terms with the nature of contemporary capitalism, and extend their insights into the past, they

otherwise differ considerably in content and direction (although each is equally promiscuous, if

selective, in range of application, method and impact). Globalization has been won away from

the neo-liberal agenda that the market is benevolently triumphant over the state. Instead, it has

been situated systemically, as a matter of power and conflict, where the role of the state

remains significant, and context by time and place is paramount (as neatly captured by the

notion of glocalization). By contrast, social capital has compromised with neo-liberalism, is

middle range at the expense of the systemic (with roots in methodological individualism), and

is most uncomfortable if not self-destructive in bringing back in power, conflict, etc., and,

most significantly, the contextual.

On the whole, history’s disregard for social capital is a reflection of the discipline’s positive

qualities. But it is precisely because of these that it should critically engage with social capital,

shedding light on the methodological and theoretical lessons that can be gleaned historically for

understanding the past and contemporary capitalism. The point is not only to halt social capital

97B. Fine, ‘Examining the idea of globalizationand development critically: what role for political

economy?’, New Political Economy, IX, 2 (June2004), 213–31.

466 Social History vol. 33 : no. 4

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014

Page 27: Social capital versus social history

in its tracks but also to offer alternatives to social science, currently as open as it has ever

been, in the dual retreats from post-modernism and neo-liberalism. Otherwise, there is the

prospect of the creeping if not forward march of social capital across the newer economic

history, correspondingly reducing the scope and influence of a genuine economic and social

history.

School of Oriental and African Studies, University of London

November 2008 Social capital versus social history 467

Dow

nloa

ded

by [

Uni

vers

ity o

f N

ew H

amps

hire

] at

20:

25 1

9 N

ovem

ber

2014