science education volume 66 issue 1 1982 [doi 10.1002%2fsce.3730660113] colin gauld -- the...

Upload: alhanun

Post on 07-Jul-2018

213 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    1/13

    ISSUES

    TRENDS

    ~~ ~~

    J a m e s

    R .

    Okey , Sec t ion Ed i to r

    The Scientific Attitude and Science

    Education:

    A

    Crit ical Reappraisal

    COLIN GAULD

    School

    of

    Education University

    of

    New South Wales Sydney Austral ia

    The Natu re of th e Scientif ic Att i tud e in Scienc e Education

    For m ore tha n 60 years science educ ators have included the development of the sci-

    entific attitude among the general aims of science education. Some writers label this

    att itu de as “scientific-mindedness” Bur nett, 1 944), “th e habit of scientific thinking”

    No ll, 1 933a ) or “the spirit of science” Educational Policies Comm ission, 1966) and

    it is most often characterize d by a list of component attitud es “scientific attitudes”)

    such as objectivity, open-mindedness, scepticism, and a willingness to suspend judgmen t

    if

    there is insufficient evidence.

    M an y writers have pointed out th at knowledge abou t scientific facts a nd skill in the

    use of scientific methods are of little value

    if

    there is no inclination to use them. The

    scientific attitude represents the motivation which converts this knowledge and skill into

    action and refers to a willingness to use scientific procedures and m ethods. I t may best

    be described as “an a ttitu de to ideas and information and to particular ways of evaluating

    them”, a formulation which distinguishes it from “an att itu de to science or scientists”

    on the one hand and from “an ability

    to

    carry ou t scientific procedures” on the other

    Ga uld Hukins, 1980).

    Major statements

    of

    the goals of science education in the

    US A

    have consistently

    stressed th e importance of developing scientific attitude s

    in

    studen ts see, for example,

    Whipp le, 1932; Hen ry, 1947; Henry, 1960; Educational Policies Comm ission, 1966;

    N.S.T.A. ,1971) and curriculum projects around the world include this among their aims

    Gauld Hukins, 1980).

    In

    an analysis of 1,547 aims culled from the science education

    literature Frase r 1977) found that almost half of these could be categorized as aims

    related to the development of the scientific attitude. However, there is a grea t deal of

    evidence that little emphasis is placed on this aim in the classroom, a ppare ntly because

    Scie nce Education 66 1): 109-121 1982)

    982 John Wiley

    Sons,

    lnc.

    CCC 0036-8326/82/010l09-13 01.30

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    2/13

    11

    GAULD

    methods for teaching and testing a ttitudes m ay not be widely available rather than be-

    cau se of a general dissatisfaction with the aim itself.

    Th e scientific attitu de as it appears

    in

    the science education literature embodies the

    adoption of a particular approach to solving problems, to assessing ideas and information

    or to m aking decisions. Using this approach evidence is collected and evalua ted objectively

    so tha t the idiosyncratic prejudices of the one making th e judgment do not intrude. N o

    source of relevant information is rejected before it is fully evaluated and all available

    evidence is carefully weighed before th e decision is made . If the evidence is considered

    to be insufficient then judgm ent is suspended until there is enough information to enable

    a decision to be made. N o idea, conclusion, decision or solution is accepted just because

    a particular person makes a claim but it is treated sceptically and critically until its

    soundness can be judged acco rding to the weight of evidence which is relevant to it.

    A

    person who is willing to follow such a procedure and who regu larly does so) it said by

    science educators to be motivated by the scientific attitude.

    It is clear tha t, in the minds of m any writers, “evidence” means “empirical evidence”

    Downing, 1928;

    Noll,

    1933a; W ard, 1933; Henry, 1947, pp. 168- 17

    1;

    Lampkin, 1951 ;

    Educational Policies Commission, 1966, p. 19; Diederich, 1967; Collette, 1973, pp. 14-1 5,

    20; Sund and Trowbridge, 1973, pp. 5-7) and the discussion usually implies that empirical

    evidence is the only type of evidence which needs to be considered in making scientific

    decisions. Th e ultima te test in science is how th e conclusion fits with th e facts. Thus a

    person who is motivated by t he scientific a tti tu de as it is generally conceived by science

    edu cato rs is someone who makes decisions solely on th e basis of the weight of empirical

    evidence and this view of the scientific attitude will be labelled here as “empiricist”.

    Lampkin 195 l), Feigl 1955) and Kurtz 1976) have clearly shown how such a con-

    ception is closely related to a particular view of knowledge in gene ral and of science

    in

    particular-a philosophical perspective which has also been labelled “em piricist”.

    Th e empiricist a ttitu de in science education takes one of two forms depending on th e

    type of decision which is presumed to follow from a consideration of the empirical evidence

    relevant to a theory. In the “verificationist” version, empirical evidence is used to uerifv

    or prove the truth of a proposition or hypothesis Dow ning, 1928; W ard, 1933; Lampkin,

    195

    1

    Van Deventer, 1960, p 104;Diederich, 1967). Diederich 1 967) includes “a desire

    for experimental verification” as a com ponent of the scientific attitude, while Lampkin

    1 95 1) defines the component labelled “scepticism” as “an unwillingness to accept

    statem ents w hich ar e not suppo rted by evidence defined as verification of predictions”.

    W ard 1933 ) sees science as “th e body of experience and theory th at can be verified by

    all observers alike” an d, for Kurz

    1

    976) “ a belief is tru e if, and only if, it has been con-

    firmed, directly or indirectly, by reference

    to

    observable evidence”.

    How ever, the realization t ha t logically the truth of a universal proposition canno t be

    finally proven by appealing t o a finite number of items of confirming d at a has led some

    writers to adopt a “falsificationist” version of the empiricist attitude. Empirical evidence

    allows one to sta te unambiguously, not when a theory is true, but when it is false.

    A

    single new scientific fact disagreeing with the theory com pletely invalidates the theo ry.

    T he w illingness to give up an old established theory as

    soon

    as it is proved to be definitely

    inconsisten t with a single fact is the attitu de of Science; no branch of knowledge without

    this attitud e can be called a science Podolsky, 19 65).

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    3/13

    SCIENTIFIC

    ATTITUDE 1 1 1

    Reasons for the Development of the Scienti fic Atti tude in Students

    For m any science educa tors the importance of the scientific attitud e is

    so

    obvious that

    no arg um ent is required to support its inclusion among those things which a school science

    course shou ld aim to develop in students. This idea is also reinforced by the fact th at there

    has been little, if any, argument

    against

    its inclusion among the aims of science education.

    However, w hile it may be obvious that the scientific attit ud e is importan t in the profes-

    sional lives of scientists and tha t students learning ab out science should also become aware

    of the motive power w hich impels scientists in their work, it is not a simple matte r to move

    on to the conclusion th at school students, many of whom do not intend t o become scien-

    tists, should actu ally be encouraged to ado pt this atti tud e for themselves.

    Two types of argum ent are offered by those who do provide reasons for taking this final

    step . In the first, it is argued that an effective way of learning abou t the natu re of scientific

    activity is for the student to act out th e role of a scientist in the classroom.

    Every child-not just those who manifest interest

    or

    high motivation-must be viewed as a young

    scientist by the teacher of science

    . . .

    he

    or

    she) must experience the mode and the excitement

    an d the frustration of th e scientist. Link, 1967 ).

    T h e student who enters this role most fully will be the one who ado pts for himself the

    atti tud e which also motivates the scientist N ay and Crocker, 1970 ).

    In th e second type of justification it is argu ed th at not only does the adoption of the

    scientific attit ud e for themselves help studen ts to understand the n atu re of science and

    th e activities of scientists better b ut scientific attitud es represen t desirable personal at-

    tributes for all people. Th e tendency to be accu rate, intellectually honest, open-minded,

    objective, and to demand reliable empirical evidence before making decisions may be

    most clearly seen in the problem solving activity of scientists so this argument goes) but

    they also represent predispositions appro pria te for solving problems

    in

    everyday life as

    well. Under t he influence of such attitudes as these, it is claimed th at problems will be

    approached in a m anner which is more likely to lead to successful solutions see, for ex-

    am ple, No11 1933b). For the Educationa l Policies Com mission 1966 ) possession of the

    scientific attitude is not only the mark of a scientifically-minded person , but also the sign

    of a rational one. These benefits of a scientific education are primarily for the individual

    but a number of writers have claimed additional benefits for the society.

    As we consider the future responsibilities of citizens, we

    will

    probably ag ree tha t helping children

    to become more co-operative, m ore responsible, more ‘open-minded’, an d, a t the s am e time, more

    ‘critical-minded’ is certainly worth the effort. He nry, 1947, p. 87).

    By adopting scientific attitudes and transferring these to situations in everyday life,

    students can be expected to be more tolerant of othe r points of view and to be more suc-

    cessful in living and w orking alongside other people. According to the Educational Policies

    Commission science can provide “power, prestige, standard of living, education, and

    hea lth” but the spirit of science” promises two less tangible but equally profound benefits:

    increased individuality and increased brotherhood of men” 1 966, p. 1 1).

    Behind both these arguments is the assumption that scientists really are motivated

    by the scientific attitu de as it is presented by science educators Offne r, 1937, Han ey,

    1964; Diederich, 1967). In o ther words, in solving scientific problems, scientists adopt

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    4/13

    112

    GAULD

    an empiricist a ttitude in which emp irical dat a, gathered objectively is the final judge of

    truth,

    if

    not

    in

    accepting as tru e those hypotheses which a re supported by the evidence,

    then certainly

    in

    rejecting as false those which conflict with i t ; an att i tude in which the

    ideas of other scien tists are received

    in

    an open-minded manner and given full, impartial

    but c ritical consideration.

    Scient ists and the Scient i f ic Att i tude: Research Evidence

    I n science education over the past sixty years a great deal of effort ha s been devoted

    to identifying the na tu re of th e scientific at titu de and m ost of this work has been based

    on detailed analyses of the w ritings of scientists, philosophers of science, and science

    educators Curtis, 1926; Noll, 1933a; Davis, 1935; Crowell, 1937; Ebel, 1938; Lampkin,

    1938; Vitrogan, 1967, 1969; N ay and Crocker, 1970; Cohen, 1971). In a num ber of cases,

    the results of these analyses were submitted to panels of scientists or science teachers

    to obtain e stimates of the relative value of each component of the scientific attitud e arising

    from the analyses. T he primary source material for these investigations was the w ritings

    o f philosophers of science who looked at science from an empiricist perspective and it

    is easy to understand why the conception of the scientific attitude which emerged also

    possessed an empiricist emphasis.

    I t

    is interesting to observe tha t,

    in

    spite of the obvious

    value placed

    on

    empirical evidence by science educators who write abou t the scientific

    attitude, almost no interest has been shown

    in

    whether scientists do, in fact, possess the

    affective characteristics attributed to them on the basis of such analyses of the literature.

    I t is difficult

    to

    find any reference in science education lite ratu re to studies of the psy-

    chology of scientists, of sociological research into th e nat ur e of th e ethos of science, of

    recent historical case studies of the activities of scientists,

    or

    of alternatives to the em-

    piricist model of science which seem s to lie behind the science edu cator’s conception of

    the scientific attitu de . For the past thirty years, relevant information from these areas

    has been accumulating and

    will

    be reviewed

    in

    the following sections.

    Th e Psychology

    of

    the Scientist

    In

    the early 195O’s, Roe carried out extensive psychological studies of em inent physical

    and biological scientists, anthropologists and psychologists. She repo rted som e of her

    conclusions from these investigations

    in

    the following way:

    Ch arac teriza tion s of scientists almost always em phasize the objectivity of their work

    and

    describe

    their cold, detached, impassive, unconcerned observation of phenomena which have no emotional

    meaning for them. This could hardly be further from the tru th . .

    The

    creative scientist whatever

    his field, is very deeply involved emotionally and personally in his wo rk . I think many scientists

    are genuinely unaware of the extent,

    or

    even of th e fact,

    of

    this

    personal

    involvement,

    and

    themselves

    accept the myth

    of

    impersonal objectivity Ro e,

    1961).

    Eiduson’s study of the psychological world of the scientist also led her to conclude that

    scientists themselves misrepresent the diversity of personal cha racte ristics which exist

    within

    their occuptional group and

    so

    “perpe tuate some of the fixed and stereotyped-

    notions that ex ist abo ut a scientist” 1962 , p.

    250;

    see also pp. 124, 153, 154, 255).

    T he more recent work of Maho ney 1976, 1979)

    in

    this area was directed towards

    exam ining the extent to which scientists possess the characteristics-objectivity, ra-

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    5/13

    SCIENTIFIC ATTITUDE

    113

    t i ona li t y , open-mindedness , supe r io r i n t e ll i gence, i n t eg ri t y , an d communa l i ty - tha t t h e

    wr i t i ngs of sc i en t i s t s and sc i e n ce e d u c a t o r s a t t r i b u t e d t o t h e m . H i s d e sc r ip t i o n of t h e

    “rea l”

    scientist

    depa r t s cons ide rab ly from t he p i c tu re p re sen ted in t he sc i ence educa t ion

    l i t e ra tu re . He a r r ived a t the fol lowing conclusions:

    I .

    Supe rior intelligence is neither a p rerequisite

    nor

    a correlate of scientific contribution ;

    2. T he scientist is often saliently illogical in his work, particula rly when he is defending a pre-

    ferred view or attack ing a rival one;

    3. In

    his experimen tal research, he is often selective, expedient, and not im mun e to distorting

    the data;

    4. Th e scientist

    is

    probably the most passionate of professionals; his theoretical and personal

    biases often color his alleged “openness” to the data;

    5.

    H e

    is

    often dogm atically tenacious in his opinions, even when t he co ntrar y evidence is over-

    whelming;

    6.

    H e is not the parago n of humility

    or

    disinterest but is, instead, often a selfish, ambitious a nd

    petulant defend er of personal recognition and territoriality;

    7. T he scientist often behaves in ways which a re diametrically opposite to commu nal sharin g

    of knowledge-he is frequently secretive and occasionally suppresses da ta for personal reasons;

    and

    8. Far fro m being a “suspender of judgm ent” th e scientist is often an impetuous tr ut h spinner

    who rushes to hypotheses and theories long before the data would warran t Ma honey , 1976,

    Mahoney’s por t ra i t of th e “ real” sc ient i s t

    is

    of som eone wh o displays both object ivi ty

    and emotionali ty, open-mindedness and tenac i ty , depending on t he con tex t . He speculates

    a n d t h e t r u th of his specu la t ion i s borne o u t b y t h e w o r k of o t h e r s ) t h a t i t i s t h e le ss

    eminent sc i en t i s t who

    comes

    c losest to possess ing th e qua l i t i e s

    of the

    empi r i c i s t ideal

    1

    979).

    Among a s a m p l e of fo r ty - two sc i en ti s t s who wer e ac t ive ly invo lved in r e sea rch

    r e l a t e d to data o b t a in e d t h r o u g h

    the

    A p o l l o m o o n missions, M i t r o f f

    and

    M a s o n 1974)

    found a similar r a n g e of pe rsona l i t y t r a i t s as t h a t r e fe r re d t o by other invest iga tors .

    Th e single dimension which most served to differentiate between t he scientists was th at of “spe-

    culativeness” or “willingness to ex trapolate beyond the available data” . A t one end of the spectrum

    whe re th e extrem e speculative scientists who in the words of the respondents “wouldn’t h esitate

    to build a whole theory of th e solar system based

    on no

    data at all”; on the other extreme were the

    data-bound scientists who “wouldn’t be able to save their own hide if a fire was burning next to

    them because they’d never have enough data to prove the fire was really there”. On every subsequent

    dimension on which these two types of scientists were compared they stood

    in

    extreme contrast

    to one ano ther. O ne of the most significant things ab out these differences is tha t th e more out-

    standing a scientist was, as judged by his peers, the more he lay near th e speculative end of the scale.

    Conversely, the more “mundane”, “typical”, or “run-of-the-mill” scientists fell tow ard the

    “data-bo und’’ end of the scale

    A t th e sam e time the m ore speculative scientists ar e also the kinds of scientists who ar e more likely

    to become rigidly com mitted to their ideas once they have produced them . Con trary to popular

    misconception, it is the ‘‘lesser’’ not th e “gre ater” scie ntist , who is more likely to have a n “open

    mind”. T he greater th e scientist the m ore likely he is to develop a line and to push it for all it is worth

    . . In a word, the gre ater th e scientist, th e more likely he is to belie the my th of the disinterested,

    uncom mitted scientist. 1974; see also Hill, 1 974).

    T h e r e i s one no tab le d i sc repancy be tween t he obse rva t ions o f Roe a n d E i d u so n

    on

    t h e

    o n e h a n d a n d M i t ro f f on the other . W hi le th e form er invest iga tors found th a t t he sc ienti s ts

    P. 6).

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    6/13

    114 GAULD

    they interviewed accepted t he emp iricist stereotype, “every one of the scientists inter-

    viewed on [Mitroffs] first round of interviews indicated that they thought the notion

    of the objective, emotionally disintere sted scientist naive” M itroff, I974 b). It may be

    tha t, when discussing th e work they ac tually do, scientists ar e more aw are of the inap-

    propriateness of the empiricist stereotype than when they ar e talking abou t science

    in

    gene ral see Mitroff, 1 974a, pp. 107-13 1).

    The Ethos

    of

    Science

    I n a n ar ticl e on th e ethos of science, originally published

    in

    1942, Merton described

    the ethos

    of

    science as “th at emotiona lly toned complex of values an d norm s which is

    held to be binding on the m an of science.” Control over th e scientist’s behavior is imposed

    through these norms by sanctions and rewards and “are in varying d egrees internalized

    by the scientist” M erton , 1968, p. 605).

    Merton identified “universalism”, “organized scepticism”, “communism”, and

    “disinterestedne ss” as four norms th roug h which h e claimed institutional control was

    exerted over the behavior of scientists.

    To

    these Barber 1952, pp. 84-94) added “ra-

    tionality” an d “emotional neutrality” an d Store r described the six norms as follows:

    Unioersalism:

    This norm

    . .

    refers both to the assumption that physical laws are everywhere

    th e sam e and to the principle tha t the tr ut h and value of a scientific statement is independent of

    the characteristics of its autho r . .

    Organized Scepticism:

    This norm embodies) the principle th at each scientist should be held in-

    dividually responsible for mak ing su re that previous research by o thers

    on

    which he bases his work

    is valid

    . .

    Communism or Communality:

    This norm directs the scientist to sh are his findings with other

    scientists freely and without favor.

    . . .

    Disinterestedness:

    This

    norm.

    .

    .

    makes it illicit for the scientist to profit personally

    i n

    any way

    from his research

    .

    .

    Rationality:

    This is) a faith in the moral virtue of reason

    . . .

    It may be interpre ted also as the

    assumption t ha t necessary

    to

    the achievement

    of

    the goals of science are

    1 )

    empirical test rather

    than tradition and

    2 )

    a critical approa ch to all empirical phenomena ra ther than a cceptance of

    certain phenomena as exempt from scru tiny .

    .

    Emotional N eutrality:

    This norm ) enjoins the scientist to avoid so much emotional involvement

    in his work that he cannot adopt a new appro ach

    or

    reject

    an old

    answer when his findings suggest

    th at this is necessary,

    or

    th at he intentionally distorts his findings in ord er to suppo rt a particular

    hypothesis

    1966,

    pp.

    78-80).

    Storer adds that “i t

    is

    relatively easy to show that this com bination of n orms is admi-

    rably suited to e nsure th e optimal progress

    of

    science; ideally, only when scientists’ be-

    havior is guided by these no rms is it possible to keep scientists in touch w ith the frontiers

    of knowledge” 196 6, pp. 82, 83). An exam ination of Storer’s description of t he norms

    of science show th at it is an expression in sociological te rm s of the empiricist conception

    of t he s cientific attit ud e foun d in science education.

    Late r research by M erton 1 963, 196 9) suggested th at in addition to working und er

    the control

    of

    norm s such a s those above, the scientist seemed als o to be influenced by

    a set of what have been called “counter -norms ”. T hese represen t pressure from the sci-

    entific institution to act legitimately that

    is,

    in th e interests of scie nce) in the

    opposite

    direction to that specified by the original norm s see also Rothm an, 197 2).

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    7/13

    SCIENTIFIC

    ATTITUDE

    115

    On e purpose of M itro ffs study of moon scientists was to investiga te the extent to which

    norm s and their counter-norms exercised control over scientists in their professional work.

    Ab out forty eminent scientists who were directly interested in moon rock sam ples collected

    on the Apollo missions were interviewed four times over a span of 3’/2 years between

    Apollo 1 1 and Apollo 16. In addition, they w ere asked to respond to a nu mber of tests

    and questionnaires. Extensive data were gathered which demonstrated the operation

    of both conventional norm s and counter-norms within this group of scientists and Mitroff

    produced an expanded list as

    a

    basis

    for

    further study 1974a, p. 79; 1974b).

    This lack of acceptance of th e simple empiricist stereotype was found in an earlier study

    in which W est 1960) ca rried out a survey of the scientific values of fifty-seven academic

    scientists at a midwestern university. H e found th at there was a w ide variation in the

    strength of adherence t o “th e classical ideology of science” and th at ther e was little re-

    lationship between this and the extent of productive research.

    Mulkay 1976 ,1979) has argued that neither the norms nor the counter-norms referred

    to above ar e the strong determiners of behavior tha t M erton and Mitroff consider them

    to be, since it is not the private behavior b ut th e public presentation of results which de-

    termines the allocation of rewards

    in

    science. For him the so-called norms and c ounter-

    norms constitute an informal, moral vocabulary “w hich scientists can use flexibly to

    categorize professional actions differently in various social contexts and, presumably,

    in

    accord ance with varying social interests”

    1

    976; see also Barnes and Dolby, 1970).

    Th is vocabulary points specifically to problem areas in scientific practice including those

    related to objectivity-subjectivity, rationality-irrationality, and impartiality-commitment,

    bu t it contains no solutions to these problems. F or example, a focus on the need for ob-

    jectivity may be used to counteract an opponent who is judged to have been unduly

    subjective, while an appeal to th e subjective aspects of science may be used w here claims

    for objectivity appe ar to be excessive.

    Historical Case Studies

    Information abou t th e scientific a ttitu de is often conveyed and reinforced

    in

    an edu-

    catio nal se tting by appealing to the work of scientists in the past. In particular, suppo rt

    for the empiricist conception of this attitude is derived from the way scientists

    in

    the past

    apparen tly constructed theories and made dec isions about their validity solely on the basis

    of experiments. It is claimed, for example, that the Michelson-Morley experiment si-

    multaneously d ealt the death blow to the L orentz electron theory and led to the birth

    of Einstein’s special theory of relativity; or that Millikan’s oil-drop experiment once and

    for all settled dispu te about th e indivisibility of the electron cha rge.

    In his history of the Michelson-Morley-Miller experiments before and after 1905,

    Swenson 1970 ) has shown that , following the 1887 version of the experiment, a num ber

    of explanations for the null result were still available which did not require the rejection

    of the concept of the aether. Because of this fact, modifications of the o riginal experiment

    were carried out over the next forty-five or fifty years to attemp t to dem onstrate con-

    clusively the presence or absence

    of

    an aethe r drift. In 1925, Miller announced th at he

    had obtained an aether drift velocity of about 200 meters per second but, instead of

    causing Einstein’s theory to be rejected, this result was effectively ignored for the next

    thirty yea rs, in spite of M iller’s acknowledged competence. In 1954, Shankland suggested

    th at the result may have been due to lack of ade quate tem perature control.

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    8/13

    116

    GAULD

    Holton’s research 1969), and th e work of others, has also shown th at the Michel-

    son-Morley experiment had little

    or

    no effect on the origin of the theory of relativity in

    Einstein’s m ind. Einstein

    was

    apparently prompted more by “t he essential requirement

    of finding sym metry an d universality in the op erations

    of

    nature” Holton, 1969) than

    by substanially emp irical considerations. T h e myth which describes a direct link between

    th e 1887 version of the Michelson-M orley expe rimen t and Einstein’s conception of the

    theor y of relativity is, for H olton , an ex amp le of th e effect of experimenticism which

    “is best recognized by the unquestioned priority assigned to experiments and experimental

    data in the analysis of how scien tists do their own work an d how the ir work is incorporated

    into the public e nterp rise of science.” 1 969).

    T h e later study by H olton of Millikan’s labora tory notebooks for the years 191 1 and

    19

    12,

    illuminates ano the r aspect of the “experimen ticist” notion of science. T h e results

    published in Millikan’s 1913 paper so clea rly support M illikan’s view of th e indivisibility

    of the electron ch arg e that , a t least in this case, it seems obvious that the oil-drop ex-

    periment conclusively decided the point at issue between M illikan and E hre nha ft.

    Mil-

    likan annou nced there tha t “th e largest depa rture from th e mean value found anywhere

    i n th e table [of values of

    e,

    determined

    for

    fifty-eight droplets] amounts to 0.5 percent”

    quoted in Ho lton, 1978, p. 61). Howev er, Millikan’s notebooks show tha t results for

    many more droplets were eliminated even a s they were being obtained. Millikan “eval-

    uated his da ta a nd assigned qua litative indications on their prospective use, guided by

    both a theory ab out th e natu re of the electric charg e and a sense of the quality or weight

    of

    the particular run” p.

    70).

    In ord er to account for Millikan’s behavior in the laboratory,

    Holton introduces the notion of suspension o disbelief to describe the procedure of

    holding in abeyance “final judgmen ts concerning the validity of app arent falsifications

    of a promising hypothesis” p. 71) especially during th e early stages of theory construction

    or

    testing . It may also be possible to expla in inconsistencies in Mendel’s pub lished work

    in a similar way Fishe r, 193 6).

    Millikan’s exam ple demo nstrates one possible respon se to data which conflict w ith

    expectations a t the sta ge of scientific work prior to publication. However, even after results

    ar e published, a scientist whose theory is appar ently falsified by the evidence can h andle

    the situation in a num ber of different ways in order to retain his theory. H e can deny the

    validity of the da ta a nd suggest possible reasons why it should be ignored; he

    can

    accept

    th e dat a but give reasons why it has no serious implications for the theory; or he can accept

    both th e data an d the implications for the theory but a rgu e that when all the problems

    have eventually been cleared up the theory will be vindicated Ma ho ney , 1976, 1979;

    Popper, 1968, p.

    50,

    Kuhn , 1970). T he treatm ent of Miller’s 1925 results for the aether

    dr ift velocity is one example of the third approach to da ta which apparently falsifies a

    theory. In anoth er example, clear deviations in the orbit of the planet Uran us from that

    expected on the basis of Newton’s t heory of grav itation did n ot lead to th e rejection of

    the th eory . Instead they w ere eventually found t o be caused by an originally unexpected

    factor-the existence of the planet Neptune-w hich had no part t o play in the theory

    itself. For many years, similar deviations in the orbit of Mercury were not counted against

    the th eory because it was felt th at th ey would eventually be explained when a furt her ,

    as yet unobserved planet was fou nd. Barber’s survey 196 1) of the extent to which sci-

    entists resist the in troduction of new ideas also dem onstra tes th e strength of opposition

    to falsifying evidence.

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    9/13

    SCIENTIFIC ATTITUDE 117

    If, as the above and m any other) examples demonstrate, experimental evidence does

    not conclusively speak for or against a particular theory one is led to adopt a non-empiricist

    position similar to that of Einstein who, “though unwilling to accep t the possibility of

    con firmation of a theo ry by ‘verification’ of its prediction , n prac tice also held to

    th e falsification principle only sceptically weakly) when the theory pu rportedly falsified

    by experimental test had

    in

    his views certain other merits compared with its rivals”

    Holton, 1978, p, 98).

    Alternative Models

    o

    Science

    T he above evidence concerning th e behavior of scientists and , in particular, their use

    of experimental data in coming to conclusions about theories is at odds both with the

    conception of th e scientific attitud e possessed by science educators and with an empiricist

    philosophy of science to which this attitude

    seems

    to be related Feigl, 1955; Kurtz, 1976).

    If

    the “orthodox” view of the scientific attitude is to be modified in a way which

    will

    accom modate the evidence presented above, it will also be necessary to chang e the m odel

    of science apparently adopted by science educators working in this area . Since about 1960,

    an increasing range of nonem piricist philosophies of science has becom e available from

    Kuhn’s model of paradigm conflict

    1

    962) to the anarchistic view of Feyerabend

    1

    970).

    Th ere is also evidence that strictly empiricist philosophies have been modified in the light

    of the mou nting evidence against them (see, for example, Scheffler, 1967).

    These developments

    in

    the philosophy of science are well known and will not be further

    discussed here. However, both Holton and Mitroff, whose research has been presented

    above, have offered f urthe r suggestions abou t views of science which they consider to

    be consistent w ith the results of their w ork.

    In

    1952, Holton introduced the distinction between “public” and “private” science

    1952 , pp. 234-256). T he way in which argu me nts and evidence are publicly presented

    “public” science) and not the way in which they were originally conceived, clarified,

    an d tested “private” science) is used by others to judg e the scientific value of the work

    of a scientist. Th e technical format of a scientific paper is such that references to personal

    characteristics

    of

    the au thor are rigorously excluded. Holton suggested tha t the empiricist

    stereotype of the scientist as detached and impartial is one which arises from this edited,

    public image and not from a study

    of

    scientists themselves as they engage

    in

    “private”

    science. His own work in the history of science has provided considerab le evidence tha t,

    in the private work of a sc ientist, the range of appropriate personal characteristics is almost

    unlimited. It certainly includes those which have been incorpo rated into the empiricist

    scientific atti tu de together with their opposites as outlined by Mitroff 1 974a , p. 79;

    1974 b). If the distinction between “public” an d “private” science is a valid one, it means

    th at the a ttitudes toward scientists held by science educators and science studen ts can

    be expected to have little, if any, necessary connection with the personal cha racte ristics

    of scientists.

    M itro ffs research raised for him th e problem that

    if,

    as seems to be t he case, the best

    scientists are those who tenaciously hold on to their theories almost

    in

    spite of th e evidence

    aga inst th em , how can science be considered to be objective even

    in

    the public domain?

    In

    order to solve this problem, he appealed to a dialectical

    or

    adversary

    notion

    of science

    1 972; 1974 a, pp. 21 9-250 ). I n his view, a theo ry is most likely to get a fair h earing

    i f

    there are individuals passionately committed to its validity and who do all they can to

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    10/13

    118 GAULD

    produce evidence and a rgum ents in its favor. Those most likely to come up with evidence

    and a rgum ents against the theory a re those who disagree with it

    or

    who ar e committed

    to an alternative view. The interaction between these two groups of passionately com-

    mitted individuals helps to bring t o light as much relevant evidence as possible for as-

    sessment by the relevant community of scientists without it being necessary for either

    group to show complete objectivity, open-mindedness, impartiality, or emotional neu-

    trality. The similarity between this way of

    \

    iewing science and the way tru th is sought

    in

    a courtroom is obvious as a re the parallels w ith Kuhn’s notion of parad igm conflict

    1

    962 ). Of course the degree of commitment which scientists adop t towards a particular

    theory varies from individual to individual and th e situation is not so clearly defined as

    may be suggested by th e above discussion. But, while th e empiricist stereotyp e allows

    for little variation among the personal attrib utes of scientists, the views of H olton and

    Mitroff appear to make more sense of their actual behavior.

    Conclusions

    Arguments for including the development of the scientific attitud e i n students among

    the main goals of science education rest firmly on the assumption that this attitude is

    dem ons trated in the professional behavior of successful scientists. Th e conception of the

    scientific attitud e which appea rs in the science educa tion lite ratur e sees the scientist as

    some one who m akes decisions solely on the basis of em pirical evidence and who at all

    times prevents his personal in terests from in truding into these decisions. Th e evidence

    presented dem onstrates clearly tha t this view, which seems to have been derived primarily

    from the writings of scientists and philosophers of science before about 1960, is completely

    untenable and may, a t best, be associated with th e less successful scientist.

    The lack of attention which has been given by the science educators who carry out

    research into the scientific att itu de to the evidence presented here from th e psychology,

    sociology, history and philosophy of science, may be just ano ther exam ple of how com-

    mitme nt to one view in this case , an empiricist view of science) can lead one to ignore

    contrary evidence. The proliferation, since 1960, of nonempiricist philosophies of science,

    has had little obvious influence on how the scientific at titu de is conceived by science

    educators. Even Klopfer’s recent extensive and detailed outline of the structure of the

    affective domain

    in

    relation to science education

    1

    976) retains many features of the

    empiricist stereotype with little acknowledgemen t that contrary evidence has been taken

    into account. One purpose of this paper has been to present the evidence against the

    empiricist conception of the scientific attitud e.

    A

    conclusion tha t could be drawn from the material and argu men ts presented here

    is tha t development of the scientific atti tud e in students should be elim inated a s one of

    the ma jor goals of science education, an d this certainly follows for the at tit ud e as it has

    been formulated by science educators for the past 60 years. Teaching that scientists

    possess these characteristics is bad enough but it is abhorren t tha t science educators should

    actually attem pt to mold children in the sam e false image. On the other hand, very few

    writers explain what they m ean by open -mindedness, objectivity, or scepticism, and little

    indication is given of how ev idence is weighed or of how o ne decides when the re is suffi-

    cient evidence to m ake a decision. It is possible that, if such terms were clarified and the

    way in which they r elate to scientific p ractice were more carefully discussed

    in

    the light

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    11/13

    SCIENTIFIC ATTITUDE 119

    of the material presented here, one could retain a reformulated and more acceptable

    version of the scientific attitud e.

    This second alternative requires considerably more discussion than has taken place

    up to th e present. I f any concep tion of the scientific attitude is to be retained

    in

    science

    education it is no longer sufficient to build unquestioningly on th e consensus of science

    educators.

    Too

    much relevant information has been ignored. If furth er work takes place

    which clarifies, in th e light of the above evidence, the role which the developm ent of the

    scientific attitude should play

    in

    science education then the second purpose of this paper

    will

    have been achieved.

    References

    Barber , B. Science and the Social Order. Glencoe, 111.: Free P ress, 1952.

    Bar ber , B. Resistance by scientists to scientific discovery. Science 1961, 1 34 , 596-602.

    Barnes, S B., Dolby,

    R.

    G. A. The scientific ethos: A deviant viewpoint. Archioes Europ6en

    Burnett , R. W. The science teacher and his objectives. Teachers College Record 1944, 45

    Cohen, D. C an scientific attitudes be evaluated? In Research 1971, R. P. Tisher Ed. ). Melbourne:

    Austra lian S cience Educa tion Research Association, 197 1, 135- 143 .

    Collette, A.

    T.

    Science teaching in the secondary school. Boston: Allyn a nd Bacon, 1973.

    Crowell, V. Th e scientific method. School Sci. Ma th. 1937, 37, 525-531.

    Curtis, F. D. A d etermina tion of th e scientific attitudes. J . Chem. Educ. 1926, 3,920-927.

    Davis, I C . T he measurement of scientific attitudes. Sci. Educ.

    1935,

    1 9

    117-1 22.

    Diederich, P. B. Com ponen ts of the scientific at titude . The Science Teacher

    1967, 34 2) , 23-

    Downing,

    E.

    R. T he elemen ts and safeguards of scientific thinking.

    Scienti fic M onth ly 1928,

    26 ,

    Ebel, R. L. W ha t is th e scientific attitude ?

    Sci. Educ. 1938, 2 2

    1-5,

    75-81.

    Educational Policies Commission,

    Education and the Spirit of Science.

    Washington, D.C.: National

    Eiduso n, B.

    T. Scientists: their psychological world .

    New York: Basic Books,

    1962.

    Feigl, H . Aims of education for our age of science: reflections of a logical empiricist. In

    The

    fi f ty- fou rth yearbook of the National Society fo r the St ud y of Education Part 1: Modern

    philosophies and education.

    N . B. Hen ry Ed.). Chicago: Nation al Society for the Stud y of

    Education,

    1955,304-341.

    Feyerabend, P.

    K.

    Against method.

    Minnesota Stud ies in the Philosophy of Science 1970, 4,

    Fisher,

    R.

    A. Has Mendel’s work been rediscovered?

    Anna ls of Science 1936, 1 2),

    1 15-1

    37.

    Fraser, B. Selection and validation of attitu de scales for curriculum evaluation.

    Sci. Educ. 1977,

    Cauld, C.

    F.,

    Hukins, A . A. Scientific attitudes: a review.

    Stud ies in Science Educa tion 1980,

    7 , 129-161.

    Hane y, R. E. T he development of scientific attitudes.

    Th e Science Teacher 1964,

    31

    1

    2), 33-

    35.

    Henry, N . B. Ed.).

    The orty-s ixth yearbook of the National Society fo r th es tu dy of Education.

    Part I: Science Education in American Schoo ls. Chicago: National Society for the Study of

    Education, 1947.

    Henry, N . B. Ed.). Thef i f ty -ninthyearbook of the National Society o r the Stu dy of Education.

    de Sociologie 1970, 9 3-25.

    241 -251.

    24.

    23 1-243.

    Educ ation Association,

    1966.

    17-1 30.

    61 3) , 317-330.

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    12/13

    120 GAULD

    Part

    I

    Rethinking science education.

    Chicago: National Society for the Stu dy of Education,

    1960.

    Hill,

    S.

    C . Questioning the influence of a ‘Social System of Science’:

    a

    study of Australian scientists.

    ScienceStudies

    19 74 ,4, 135-163.

    Holton,

    G.

    Introductio n to concepts and theories in physical science

    Readin g, Mass.: Addision-

    Wesley, 1952.

    Holton,

    G .

    Einstein, Michelson, and the “crucial” experiment. Isis, 1969, 60, 133-197.

    Holton, G. The scientific imagination: case studies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

    Klopfer, L. E. A struc ture for th e affective do main in relation to science education. Sci. Educ.

    Kuhn, T.

    S .

    The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,

    1962.

    Kuhn, T.

    S.

    Logic of discovery

    or

    psychology of research?

    I n

    Criticism and the growth o fkn ow l-

    edge

    I .

    Lakatos A Mu sgrave Eds.). London: Cam brid ge University Press, 1970, 1-23.

    Kurtz, P. The scientific attitude vs antiscience and pseudoscience. The Humanis t 1976,

    3 6

    Lampkin, R. H . Scientific attitudes. Sci. Educ. 1938, 22, 353-357.

    Lam pkin, R . H . Scientific enqiry for science teachers. Sci. Educ. 1951 3 5 17-39.

    Link F. An approa ch to a more adeq uate system of evaluation i n science. Th e Science Teacher

    Mahoney, M.

    J .

    Scientist as subject: the psychological imperatiue. Cambridge, Mass.: Ballinger,

    Mahoney, M.

    J .

    Psychology of the scientist: an evaluative review. Social Studie s of Science 1979,

    Me rton, R. K. The ambivalence of scientists. Th e Bulletin of the John Hopk ins Hosp ital 1963,

    Merton R.

    K.

    Social theory and social structure. New York:

    Free

    Press, 1968.

    Me rton, R . K. Behavior p atterns of scientists. American Scientist 1969, 57 1) , 1-23.

    Mitroff, I . 1. The myth of objectivity

    or

    why science needs a new psychology of science. Management

    Mitroff,

    I .

    I . The subjective side of science. Am ersterdam : Elsevier, 1974a.

    Mitroff,

    1.

    I . Norms and counter-norms in a select group of the A pollo moon scientists: a case study

    of the ambivalence of scientists. Amer.

    SOC.

    ev. 1974b ,39, 579-595.

    Mitroff,

    I. I .

    Mason, R. 0 On evaluating th e scientific contribution of the A pollo moon m issions

    via information theory: a study of the scientist-scientist relationship. Management Science:

    Applications 1974,20, 1501-1513.

    Mulkay, M.

    J.

    Norms and ideology in science. Social Science Informa tion 1976,

    15

    637-656.

    Mulkay, M. J . Science and the sociology of know ledge. London:

    Allen

    and Unwin, 1979.

    National Science Teach ers Association, School science education for the 70s. The Science Teacher

    Nay, M. A. Crocker,

    R.

    K. Science teaching and the affective attri bute s of scientists. Sci. Ed .

    Noll,

    V .

    H .

    Th e hab it of scientific thinking. Teachers College Re cord 1933a, 35, 1-9.

    Noll,

    V .

    H . Teaching the habit of scientific thinking. Teachers

    College

    Record 1933b, 35,

    Offner, M. F Fact versus theory. Sci. Educ. 1937 ,21 ,28-30 .

    Podolsky, B. W ha t is Science?

    Th e Physics Teacher

    196 5,3 2), 71-73.

    Popper, K.

    R. Th e logic ofscie ntific discooery.

    London: Hutchinson, 1968.

    Roe,

    A

    Th e psychology of the scientists.

    Science

    1961,

    134,

    456-459.

    1978.

    19 76 ,60 3), 299-312.

    27-3 I .

    196 7,34 2), 20-24.

    1976.

    9,349-375.

    112,77-97.

    Science: A pplications 1972, 1 8, B613-B618.

    197 38 8),46-51.

    197 0,54 1), 59-67.

    202-212.

  • 8/18/2019 Science Education Volume 66 Issue 1 1982 [Doi 10.1002%2Fsce.3730660113] Colin Gauld -- The Scientific Attitude…

    13/13

    SCIENTIFIC ATTITUDE 121

    Rothman,

    R . A . A

    dissenting view on th e scientific ethos.

    Br.

    J .

    Soc.

    1972,

    23

    102-108.

    Scheffler, I.

    Science and subjectiuity.

    Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1967.

    S to re r , N . W.

    The Social Sys tem of Science.

    New

    York:

    Holt, Rineha rt Winston, 1966.

    Sund, R.

    B.,

    Trowbridge,

    L.

    W .

    Teaching science by inquiry in the secondary school.

    Columbus,

    Swenson,

    L.

    S Th e Michelson-Morley-Miller experiments before and after 1905.J .

    Hist. Astron.

    Van Deventer, W. C. et al. Scie nce for general education in the colleges. I n Henry, 1960, pp.

    Vitrogan, D. Origins of the criteria of a generalized attitu de toward science.

    Sci. Educ.

    1967 ,5 / ,

    Vitrogan, D. Characteristics of a generalized attitude toward science.

    School Science and

    Ward , C. H. The goals

    of

    high-school science.

    Harvard Tearhers Record

    1933,3, 179-183.

    West,

    S.S

    Th e ideology

    of

    academic scientists.

    I.R.E. Transactions on Engineering Manag ement

    Whipple,

    G . M.

    Ed.).

    Th e thirty-f irst yearbook of the National Society fo r the Stud y of E d u -

    cation. Part I A program for teaching science.

    Chicago: National Society for the Study of

    Education, 1932.

    Ohio: Merrill, 1973.

    1970,

    Z l ) ,

    56-78.

    97-1 1 I .

    175-186.

    Mathemat i c s

    19 69 ,69 , 150-158.

    1960,

    EM-7 2),

    54-62.

    Received 9 March 1981

    Accepted

    20 Ju ly

    1981