research article chess-like games may have no uniform...

11
Hindawi Publishing Corporation Game eory Volume 2013, Article ID 534875, 10 pages http://dx.doi.org/10.1155/2013/534875 Research Article Chess-Like Games May Have No Uniform Nash Equilibria Even in Mixed Strategies Endre Boros, Vladimir Gurvich, and Emre Yamangil RUTCOR, Rutgers University, 640 Bartholomew Road, Piscataway, NJ 08854-8003, USA Correspondence should be addressed to Vladimir Gurvich; [email protected] Received 2 February 2013; Accepted 22 April 2013 Academic Editor: Walter Briec Copyright Β© 2013 Endre Boros et al. is is an open access article distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. Recently, it was shown that Chess-like games may have no uniform (subgame perfect) Nash equilibria in pure positional strategies. Moreover, Nash equilibria may fail to exist already in two-person games in which all infinite plays are equivalent and ranked as the worst outcome by both players. In this paper, we extend this negative result further, providing examples that are uniform Nash equilibria free, even in mixed or independently mixed strategies. Additionally, in case of independently mixed strategies we consider two different definitions for effective payoff: the Markovian and the a priori realization. 1. Introduction 1.1. Nash-Solvability in Pure and Mixed Strategies: Main Results. ere are two very important classes of the so- called uniformly Nash-solvable positional games with perfect information, for which a Nash equilibrium (NE) in pure stationary strategies, which are also independent of the initial position, exists for arbitrary payoffs. ese two classes are the two-person zero-sum games and the -person acyclic games. However, when (directed) cycles are allowed and the game is not zero sum, then a positional game with perfect information may have no uniform NE in pure stationary strategies. is may occur already in the special case of two players with all cycles equivalent and ranked as the worst outcome by both players. Such an example was recently constructed in [1]. Here we strengthen this result and show that for the same example no uniform NE exists even in mixed stationary strategies, not only in pure ones. Moreover, the same negative result holds for the so-called independently mixed strategies. In the latter case we consider two different definitions for the effective payoffs, based on Markovian and a priori realizations. In the rest of the introduction we give precise definitions and explain the above result in more details. Remark 1. In contrast, for the case of a fixed initial position, Nash-solvability in pure positional strategies holds for the two-person case and remains an open problem for >2; see [1] for more details; see also [2–20] for different cases of Nash-solvability in pure strategies. Furthermore, for a fixed initial position, the solvability in mixed strategies becomes trivial, due to the general result of Nash [21, 22]. us, our main example shows that Nash’s the- orem cannot be extended for positional games to the case of uniform equilibria. It is shown for the following four types of positional strategies: pure, mixed, and independently mixed, where in the last case we consider two types of effective payoffs, defined by Markovian and a priori realizations. 1.2. Positional Game Structures. Given a finite directed graph (digraph) = (,) in which loops and multiple arcs are allowed, a vertex V ∈ is interpreted as a position and a directed edge (arc) = (V, V ) ∈ as a move from V to V . A position of outdegree 0 (one with no moves) is called terminal. Let = { 1 ,..., } be the set of all terminal positions. Let us also introduce a set of players = {1, . . . , } and a partition := 1 βˆͺβ‹…β‹…β‹…βˆͺ βˆͺ , assuming that each player ∈ is in control of all positions in .

Upload: others

Post on 20-Oct-2020

12 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • Hindawi Publishing CorporationGameTheoryVolume 2013, Article ID 534875, 10 pageshttp://dx.doi.org/10.1155/2013/534875

    Research ArticleChess-Like Games May Have No Uniform Nash EquilibriaEven in Mixed Strategies

    Endre Boros, Vladimir Gurvich, and Emre Yamangil

    RUTCOR, Rutgers University, 640 Bartholomew Road, Piscataway, NJ 08854-8003, USA

    Correspondence should be addressed to Vladimir Gurvich; [email protected]

    Received 2 February 2013; Accepted 22 April 2013

    Academic Editor: Walter Briec

    Copyright Β© 2013 Endre Boros et al. This is an open access article distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution License,which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

    Recently, it was shown that Chess-like games may have no uniform (subgame perfect) Nash equilibria in pure positional strategies.Moreover, Nash equilibria may fail to exist already in two-person games in which all infinite plays are equivalent and ranked asthe worst outcome by both players. In this paper, we extend this negative result further, providing examples that are uniform Nashequilibria free, even inmixed or independentlymixed strategies. Additionally, in case of independentlymixed strategies we considertwo different definitions for effective payoff: the Markovian and the a priori realization.

    1. Introduction

    1.1. Nash-Solvability in Pure and Mixed Strategies: MainResults. There are two very important classes of the so-called uniformlyNash-solvable positional games with perfectinformation, for which a Nash equilibrium (NE) in purestationary strategies, which are also independent of the initialposition, exists for arbitrary payoffs.These two classes are thetwo-person zero-sum games and the 𝑛-person acyclic games.

    However, when (directed) cycles are allowed and thegame is not zero sum, then a positional game with perfectinformation may have no uniform NE in pure stationarystrategies. This may occur already in the special case of twoplayers with all cycles equivalent and ranked as the worstoutcome by both players. Such an example was recentlyconstructed in [1].

    Here we strengthen this result and show that for thesame example no uniformNE exists even inmixed stationarystrategies, not only in pure ones. Moreover, the same negativeresult holds for the so-called independently mixed strategies.In the latter case we consider two different definitions forthe effective payoffs, based on Markovian and a priorirealizations.

    In the rest of the introduction we give precise definitionsand explain the above result in more details.

    Remark 1. In contrast, for the case of a fixed initial position,Nash-solvability in pure positional strategies holds for thetwo-person case and remains an open problem for 𝑛 > 2;see [1] for more details; see also [2–20] for different cases ofNash-solvability in pure strategies.

    Furthermore, for a fixed initial position, the solvability inmixed strategies becomes trivial, due to the general result ofNash [21, 22]. Thus, our main example shows that Nash’s the-orem cannot be extended for positional games to the case ofuniform equilibria. It is shown for the following four types ofpositional strategies: pure, mixed, and independently mixed,where in the last case we consider two types of effectivepayoffs, defined by Markovian and a priori realizations.

    1.2. Positional Game Structures. Given a finite directed graph(digraph) 𝐺 = (𝑉, 𝐸) in which loops and multiple arcs areallowed, a vertex V ∈ 𝑉 is interpreted as a position and adirected edge (arc) 𝑒 = (V, V) ∈ 𝐸 as a move from V toV. A position of outdegree 0 (one with no moves) is calledterminal. Let 𝑉

    𝑇= {π‘Ž1, . . . , π‘Ž

    π‘š} be the set of all terminal

    positions. Let us also introduce a set of 𝑛 players 𝐼 = {1, . . . , 𝑛}and a partition 𝐷 : 𝑉 = 𝑉

    1βˆͺ β‹… β‹… β‹… βˆͺ 𝑉

    𝑛βˆͺ 𝑉𝑇, assuming that

    each player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 is in control of all positions in 𝑉𝑖.

  • 2 GameTheory

    1

    3

    2

    1

    2

    1

    2

    1

    2π‘Ž1

    π‘Ž2

    π‘Ž3

    𝒒1

    𝒒2

    π‘Ž1

    π‘Ž2

    π‘Ž3

    π‘Ž4

    π‘Ž5

    π‘Ž6

    Figure 1: Two Chess-like game structuresG1andG

    2. InG

    1, there are 3 players controlling one position each (i.e.,G

    1is play-once), while in

    G2there are only two players who alternate turns; hence, each of them controls 3 positions: V

    1, V3, V5are controlled by player 1 and V

    2, V4, V6by

    player 2. In each position Vβ„“, the corresponding player has only two options: (𝑝) to proceed to V

    β„“+1and (𝑑) to terminate at π‘Ž

    β„“, where β„“ ∈ {1, 2, 3}

    (V4= V1) inG

    1and β„“ ∈ {1, . . . , 6} (V

    7= V1) inG

    2. To save space, we show only symbols π‘Ž

    β„“, while the corresponding vertex names are omitted.

    An initial position V0∈ 𝑉 may be fixed. The triplet

    (𝐺,𝐷, V0) or pair G = (𝐺,𝐷) is called a Chess-like positional

    game structure (or just a game structure, for short), initializedor noninitialized, respectively. By default, we assume that it isnot initialized.

    Two examples of (noninitialized) game structuresG1and

    G2are given in Figure 1.

    1.3. Plays, Outcomes, Preferences, and Payoffs. Given an ini-tialized positional game structure (𝐺,𝐷, V

    0), a play is defined

    as a directed path that begins in V0and either ends in a

    terminal position π‘Ž ∈ 𝑉𝑇or is infinite. In this paper we

    assume that all infinite plays form one outcome π‘Žβˆž

    (or 𝑐),in addition to the standard Terminal outcomes of 𝑉

    𝑇. (In [5],

    this condition was referred to as AIPFOOT.)A utility (or payoff) function is amapping 𝑒 : 𝐼×𝐴 β†’ R,

    whose value 𝑒(𝑖, π‘Ž) is interpreted as a profit of the player 𝑖 ∈𝐼 = {1, . . . , 𝑛} in case of the outcome π‘Ž ∈ 𝐴 = {π‘Ž

    1, . . . , π‘Ž

    π‘š, π‘Žβˆž}.

    A payoff is called zero-sum ifβˆ‘π‘–βˆˆπΌπ‘’(𝑖, π‘Ž) = 0 for every π‘Ž ∈

    𝐴. Two-person zero sum games are important. For example,the standard Chess and Backgammon are two-person zero-sum games in which every infinite play is a draw, 𝑒(1, π‘Ž

    ∞) =

    𝑒(2, π‘Žβˆž) = 0. It is easy to realize that 𝑒(𝑖, π‘Ž

    ∞) = 0 can be

    assumed for all players 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 without any loss of generality.Another important class of payoffs is defined by the

    condition 𝑒(𝑖, π‘Žβˆž) < 𝑒(𝑖, π‘Ž) for all 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 and π‘Ž ∈ 𝑉

    𝑇; in other

    words, the infinite outcome π‘Žβˆž

    is ranked as the worst one byall players. Several possible motivations for this assumptionare discussed in [4, 5].

    A quadruple (𝐺,𝐷, V0, 𝑒) and triplet (𝐺,𝐷, 𝑒) will be

    called a Chess-like game, initialized and noninitialized,respectively.

    Remark 2. From the other side, the Chess-like games can beviewed as the transition-free deterministic stochastic gameswith perfect information; see, for example, [8–11].

    In these games, every nonterminal position is controlledby a player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 and the local reward π‘Ÿ(𝑖, 𝑒) is 0 for each player𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 and move 𝑒, unless 𝑒 = (V, V) is a terminal move, that is,V ∈ 𝑉𝑇. Obviously, in the considered case all infinite plays are

    equivalent since the effective payoff is 0 for every such play.Furthermore, obviously, π‘Ž

    ∞is the worst outcome for a player

    𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 if and only if π‘Ÿ(𝑖, 𝑒) > 0 for every terminal move 𝑒.If |𝐼| = 𝑛 = π‘š = |𝐴| = 2, then the zero-sum Chess-like

    games turn into a subclass of the so-called simple stochasticgames, which were introduced by Condon in [23].

    1.4. Pure Positional Strategies. Given game structure G =(𝐺,𝐷), a (pure positional) strategy π‘₯

    𝑖of a player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 is a

    mapping π‘₯𝑖: 𝑉𝑖→ 𝐸𝑖that assigns to each position V ∈ 𝑉

    𝑖a

    move (V, V) from this position.The concept of mixed strategies will be considered in

    Section 1.10; till then only pure strategies are considered.Moreover, in this paper, we restrict the players to theirpositional (pure) strategies. In other words, the move (V, V)of a player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 in a position V ∈ 𝑉

    𝑖depends only on the

    position V itself, not on the preceding positions or moves.Let 𝑋

    𝑖be the set of all strategies of a player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 and

    𝑋 = βˆπ‘–βˆˆπΌπ‘‹π‘–be the direct product of these sets. An element

    π‘₯ = {π‘₯1, . . . , π‘₯

    𝑛} ∈ 𝑋 is called a strategy profile or situation.

    1.5. Normal Forms. A positional game structure can berepresented in the normal (or strategic) form.

    Let us begin with the initialized case. Given a gamestructure G = (𝐺,𝐷, V

    0) and a strategy profile π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋, a play

    𝑝(π‘₯) is uniquely defined by the following rules: it begins inV0and in each position V ∈ 𝑉

    𝑖proceeds with the arc (V, V)

    determined by the strategy π‘₯𝑖. Obviously, 𝑝(π‘₯) either ends

    in a terminal position π‘Ž ∈ 𝑉𝑇or 𝑝(π‘₯) is infinite. In the

    latter case 𝑝(π‘₯) is a lasso; that is, it consists of an initial partand a directed cycle (dicycle) repeated infinitely. This holds,because all players are restricted to their positional strategies.In either case, an outcome π‘Ž = 𝑔(π‘₯) ∈ 𝐴 = {π‘Ž

    1, . . . , π‘Ž

    π‘š, π‘Žβˆž}

  • GameTheory 3

    1

    2

    3

    𝑔1

    𝑑

    𝑝

    𝑝𝑑

    𝑑

    𝑝

    𝑝

    𝑝

    𝑑

    π‘‘π‘Ž1 π‘Ž2 π‘Ž3 π‘Ž1 π‘Ž3 π‘Ž3

    π‘Ž2 π‘Ž2 π‘Ž3 π‘Ž3 π‘Ž3 π‘Ž3

    π‘Ž1 π‘Ž2 π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1

    π‘Ž2 π‘Ž2 π‘Ž2 𝑐 𝑐 𝑐

    𝑒(1, π‘Ž2) > 𝑒(1, π‘Ž1) > 𝑒(1, π‘Ž3) > 𝑒(1, 𝑐)

    𝑒(2, π‘Ž3) > 𝑒(2, π‘Ž2) > 𝑒(2, π‘Ž1) > 𝑒(2, 𝑐)

    𝑒(3, π‘Ž1) > 𝑒(3, π‘Ž3) > 𝑒(3, π‘Ž2) > 𝑒(3, 𝑐)

    Figure 2: The normal form 𝑔1of the positional game structures G

    1from Figure 1. Each player has only two strategies: to terminate (𝑑) or

    proceed (𝑝). Hence, 𝑔1is represented by a 2 Γ— 2 Γ— 2 table, each entry of which contains 3 terminals corresponding to the 3 potential initial

    positions V1, V2, V3of G1. The rows and columns are the strategies of the players 1 and 2, while two strategies of the player 3 are the left and

    right 2 Γ— 2 subtables. The corresponding game (𝑔1, 𝑒) has no uniform NE whenever a utility function 𝑒 : 𝐼 Γ— 𝐴 β†’ R satisfies the constraints

    π‘ˆ1specified in the figure.

    is assigned to each strategy profile π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋. Thus, a game form𝑔V0

    : 𝑋 β†’ 𝐴 is defined. It is called the normal form of theinitialized positional game structureG.

    If the game structureG = (𝐺,𝐷) is not initialized, thenwerepeat the above construction for every initial position V

    0∈

    𝑉\𝑉𝑇to obtain a play𝑝 = 𝑝(π‘₯, V

    0), outcome π‘Ž = 𝑔(π‘₯, V

    0), and

    mapping 𝑔 : 𝑋 Γ— (𝑉 \ 𝑉𝑇) β†’ 𝐴, which is the normal form

    of G in this case. In general we have 𝑔(π‘₯, V0) = 𝑔V0

    (π‘₯). Forthe (noninitialized) game structures in Figure 1 their normalforms are given in Figures 2 and 3.

    Given also a payoff 𝑒 : 𝐼 Γ— 𝐴 β†’ R, the pairs (𝑔V0 , 𝑒) and(𝑔, 𝑒) define the games in the normal form, for the above twocases.

    Of course, these games can be also represented by thecorresponding real-valued mappings:

    𝑓V0: 𝐼 Γ— 𝑋 β†’ R, 𝑓 : 𝐼 Γ— 𝑋 Γ— (

    𝑉

    𝑉𝑇

    ) β†’ R, (1)

    where 𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯) = 𝑓(𝑖, π‘₯, V0) = 𝑒(𝑖, 𝑔V0(π‘₯)) = 𝑒(𝑖, 𝑔(π‘₯, V0)) forall 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼, π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋, V

    0∈ 𝑉 \ 𝑉

    𝑇.

    Remark 3. Yet, it seems convenient to separate the game from𝑔 and utility function 𝑒.

    By this approach, 𝑔 β€œtakes responsibility for structuralproperties” of the game (𝑔, 𝑒), that is, the properties that holdfor any 𝑒.

    1.6. Nash Equilibria in Pure Strategies. The concept of Nashequilibria is defined standardly [21, 22] for the normal formgames.

    First, let us consider the initialized case. Given 𝑔V0 :𝑋 β†’ 𝐴 and 𝑒 : 𝐼 Γ— 𝐴 β†’ R, a situation π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋 iscalled a Nash equilibrium (NE) in the normal form game(𝑔V0

    , 𝑒) if 𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯) β‰₯ 𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯) for each player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 and every

    strategy profile π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋 that can differ from π‘₯ only in the 𝑖thcomponent. In other words, no player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 can profit bychoosing a new strategy if all opponents keep their old strate-gies.

    In the noninitialized case, the similar property is requiredfor each V

    0∈ 𝑉\𝑉

    𝑇. Given a payoff𝑓 : 𝐼×𝑋×(𝑉\𝑉

    𝑇) β†’ R,

    a strategy profile π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋 is called a uniform NE if 𝑓(𝑖, π‘₯, V0) β‰₯

    𝑓(𝑖, π‘₯, V0) for each 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼, every π‘₯ defined as above, and for

    all V0∈ 𝑉 \ 𝑉

    𝑇, too.

    Remark 4. In the literature, the last concept is frequentlycalled a subgame perfect NE rather than a uniform NE. Thisname is justified when the digraph 𝐺 = (𝑉, 𝐸) is acyclic andeach vertex V ∈ 𝑉 can be reached from V

    0. Indeed, in this

    case (𝐺,𝐷, V, 𝑒) is a subgame of (𝐺,𝐷, V0, 𝑒) for each V ∈ 𝑉.

    However, if 𝐺 has a dicycle then any two its vertices V andV can be reached one from the other; that is, (𝐺,𝐷, V, 𝑒)is a subgame of (𝐺,𝐷, V, 𝑒) and vice versa. Thus, the nameuniform (or ergodic) NE seems more accurate.

    1.7. Uniformly Best Responses. Again, let us start with theinitialized case. Given the normal form 𝑓V0 : 𝐼 Γ— 𝑋 β†’ Rof an initialized Chess-like game, a player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼, and a pair ofstrategy profiles π‘₯, π‘₯ such that π‘₯ may differ from π‘₯ only inthe 𝑖th component, we say that π‘₯improves π‘₯ (for the player𝑖) if 𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯) < 𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯

    ). Let us underline that the inequality

    is strict. Furthermore, by this definition, a situation π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋is a NE if and only if it can be improved by no player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼;in other words, any sequence of improvements either can beextended, or terminates in an NE.

    Given a player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 and situation π‘₯ = (π‘₯𝑖| 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼), a

    strategy π‘₯βˆ—π‘–βˆˆ 𝑋𝑖is called a best response (BR) of 𝑖 in π‘₯ if

    𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯βˆ—) β‰₯ 𝑓V0

    (𝑖, π‘₯) for any π‘₯, where π‘₯βˆ— and π‘₯ are both

    obtained from π‘₯ by replacement of its 𝑖th component π‘₯𝑖by

    π‘₯βˆ—

    𝑖and π‘₯

    𝑖, respectively. A BR π‘₯βˆ—

    𝑖is not necessarily unique

    but the corresponding best achievable value 𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯βˆ—) is, of

    course, unique. Moreover, somewhat surprisingly, such bestvalues can be achieved by aBRπ‘₯βˆ—

    𝑖simultaneously for all initial

    positions V0∈ 𝑉 \ 𝑉

    𝑇. (See, e.g., [1, 4–6], of course, this result

    is well known inmuchmore general probabilistic setting; see,e.g., textbooks [24–26].)

  • 4 GameTheory

    𝑑𝑑𝑑 𝑑𝑑𝑝 𝑑𝑝𝑑 𝑑𝑝𝑝 𝑝𝑑𝑑 𝑝𝑑𝑝 𝑝𝑝𝑑 𝑝𝑝𝑝

    𝑑𝑑𝑑

    𝑑𝑑𝑝

    𝑑𝑝𝑑

    𝑑𝑝𝑝

    𝑝𝑑𝑑

    𝑝𝑑𝑝

    𝑝𝑝𝑑

    𝑝𝑝𝑝

    π‘œ1 : π‘Ž6 > π‘Ž5 > π‘Ž2 > π‘Ž1 > π‘Ž3 > π‘Ž4 > 𝑐, π‘œ2 : π‘Ž3 > π‘Ž2 > π‘Ž6 > π‘Ž4 > π‘Ž5 > 𝑐; π‘Ž6 > π‘Ž1 > 𝑐

    π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž1

    π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž1π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž1π‘Ž1π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž1π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž1π‘Ž1π‘Ž1

    π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž1

    π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž1π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž2π‘Ž1π‘Ž1π‘Ž1π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž1π‘Ž1 π‘Ž1π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž1π‘Ž1π‘Ž1π‘Ž1π‘Ž1π‘Ž1

    π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž2 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž2 π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž3 π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž3

    π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž2π‘Ž2 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž3π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž2 π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž4π‘Ž3π‘Ž3 π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3π‘Ž3

    π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž2 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž2 π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž5π‘Ž4 π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž6 π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5π‘Ž5

    π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž2π‘Ž2 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž2π‘Ž2 π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4π‘Ž4 π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6π‘Ž6 𝑐 𝑐 𝑐 𝑐 𝑐 𝑐

    𝑔2

    Figure 3: The normal form 𝑔2of the positional game structuresG

    2from Figure 1. There are two players controlling 3 positions each. Again,

    in every position there are only two options: to terminate (𝑑) or proceed (𝑝). Hence, in G2, each player has 8 strategies, which are naturally

    coded by the 3-letter words in the alphabet {𝑑, 𝑝}. Respectively, 𝑔2is represented by the 8 Γ— 8 table, each entry of which contains 6 terminals

    corresponding to the 6 (nonterminal) potential initial positions V1, . . . , V

    6of G2. Again, players 1 and 2 control the rows and columns,

    respectively. The corresponding game (𝑔1, 𝑒) has no uniform NE whenever a utility function 𝑒 : 𝐼 Γ— 𝐴 β†’ R satisfies the constraints π‘ˆ

    2

    specified under the table. Indeed, a (unique) uniformly best response of the player 1 (resp. 2) to each strategy of 2 (resp. 1) is shown by thewhite discs (resp. black squares). Since the obtained two sets are disjoint, no uniform NE exists in (𝑔

    1, 𝑒).

    Theorem 5. Let 𝑓 : 𝐼 Γ— 𝑋 Γ— (𝑉 \ 𝑉𝑇) β†’ R be the normal

    form of a (noninitialized) Chess-like game (𝐺,𝐷, 𝑒). Given aplayer 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 and a situation π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋, there is a (pure positional)strategy π‘₯βˆ—

    π‘–βˆˆ 𝑋𝑖which is a BR of 𝑖 in π‘₯ for all initial positions

    V0∈ 𝑉 \ 𝑉

    𝑇simultaneously.

    We will call such a strategy π‘₯βˆ—π‘–a uniformly BR of the

    player 𝑖 in the situation π‘₯. Obviously, the nonstrict inequality𝑓V(𝑖, π‘₯) ≀ 𝑓V(𝑖, π‘₯

    βˆ—) holds for each position V ∈ 𝑉. We will

    say that π‘₯βˆ—π‘–improves π‘₯ if this inequality is strict, 𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯) <

    𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯βˆ—), for at least one V

    0∈ 𝑉. This statement will

    serve as the definition of a uniform improvement for thenoninitialized case. Let us remark that, by this definition, asituation π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋 is a uniform NE if and only if π‘₯ can beuniformly improved by no player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼; in other words, anysequence of uniform improvements either can be extended orterminates in a uniform NE.

    For completeness, let us repeat here the simple proof ofTheorem 5 suggested in [1].

    Given a noninitialized Chess-like game G = (𝐺,𝐷, 𝑒), aplayer 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼, and a strategy profile π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋, in every positionV ∈ 𝑉 \ (𝑉

    𝑖βˆͺ 𝑉𝑇) let us fix a move (V, V) in accordance with

    π‘₯ and delete all other moves. Then, let us order 𝐴 accordingto the preference 𝑒

    𝑖= 𝑒(𝑖, βˆ—). Let π‘Ž1 ∈ 𝐴 be a best outcome.

    (Note that theremight be several such outcomes and also thatπ‘Ž1= 𝑐 might hold.) Let 𝑉1 denote the set of positions from

    which player 𝑖 can reach π‘Ž1 (in particular, π‘Ž1 ∈ 𝑉1). Let usfix corresponding moves in 𝑉1 ∩ 𝑉

    𝑖. Obviously, there is no

    move to π‘Ž1 from 𝑉 \ 𝑉1. Moreover, if π‘Ž1 = 𝑐, then player 𝑖cannot reach a dicycle beginning from 𝑉 \ 𝑉1; in particular,the induced digraph 𝐺

    1= 𝐺[𝑉 \ 𝑉

    1] contains no dicycle.

    Then, let us consider an outcome π‘Ž2 that is the best for𝑖 in 𝐴, except maybe π‘Ž1, and repeat the same arguments asabove for 𝐺

    1and π‘Ž2, and so forth. This procedure will result

    in a uniformly BR π‘₯βˆ—π‘–of 𝑖 in π‘₯ since the chosen moves of 𝑖 are

    optimal independently of V0.

    1.8. Two Open Problems Related to Nash-Solvability of Initial-ized Chess-Like Game Structures. Given an initialized gamestructureG = (𝐺,𝐷, V

    0), it is an open questionwhether anNE

    (in pure positional strategies) exists for every utility function𝑒. In [4], the problemwas raised and solved in the affirmativefor two special cases: |𝐼| ≀ 2 or |𝐴| ≀ 3. The last result wasstrengthened to |𝐴| ≀ 4 in [7]. More details can be found in[1] and in the last section of [6].

    In general the above problem is still open even if weassume that 𝑐 is the worst outcome for all players.

    Yet, if we additionally assume that G is play-once (i.e.,|𝑉𝑖| = 1 for each 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼), then the answer is positive [4].

    However, in the next subsection we will show that it becomesnegative if we ask for the existence of a uniform NE ratherthan an initialized one.

    1.9. Chess-Like Games with a Unique Dicycle and withoutUniform Nash Equilibria in Pure Positional Strategies. Letus consider two noninitialized Chess-like positional gamestructures G

    1and G

    2given in Figure 1. For 𝑗 = 1, 2, the

    corresponding digraph 𝐺𝑗= (𝑉𝑗, 𝐸𝑗) consists of a unique

    dicycle𝐢𝑗of length 3𝑗 and amatching connecting each vertex

    V𝑗

    β„“of 𝐢𝑗to a terminal π‘Žπ‘—

    β„“, where β„“ = 1, . . . , 3𝑗 and 𝑗 =

    1, 2. The digraph 𝐺2is bipartite; respectively, G

    2is a two-

    person game structures in which two players take turns; in

  • GameTheory 5

    other words, players 1 and 2 control positions V1, V3, V5and

    V2, V4, V6, respectively. In contrast, G

    1is a play-once three-

    person game structure, that is, each player controls a uniqueposition. In every nonterminal position V𝑗

    β„“there are only two

    moves: one of them (𝑑) immediately terminates in π‘Žπ‘—β„“, while

    the other one (𝑝) proceeds to V𝑗ℓ+1

    ; by convention, we assume3𝑗 + 1 = 1.

    Remark 6. In Figure 1, the symbols π‘Žπ‘—β„“for the terminal

    positions are shown but V𝑗ℓfor the corresponding positions

    of the dicycle are skipped; moreover, in Figures 1–3, we omitthe superscript 𝑗 in π‘Žπ‘—

    β„“, for simplicity and to save space.

    Thus, in G1each player has two strategies coded by the

    letters 𝑑 and 𝑝, while inG2each player has 8 strategies coded

    by the 3-letter words in the alphabet {𝑑, 𝑝}. For example, thestrategy (𝑑𝑝𝑑) of player 2 inG

    2requires to proceed to V2

    5from

    V24and to terminate in π‘Ž2

    2from V2

    2and in π‘Ž2

    6from V2

    6.

    The corresponding normal game forms 𝑔1and 𝑔

    2of size

    2 Γ— 2 Γ— 2 and 8 Γ— 8 are shown in Figures 2 and 3, respectively.Since both game structures are noninitialized, each situationis a set of 2 and 6 terminals, respectively. These terminalscorrespond to the nonterminal positions of G

    1and G

    2, each

    of which can serve as an initial position.A uniform NE free example for G

    1was suggested in

    [4]; see also [1, 8]. Let us consider a family π‘ˆ1of the utility

    functions defined by the following constraints:

    𝑒 (1, π‘Ž2) > 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    1) > 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    3) > 𝑒 (1, 𝑐) ,

    𝑒 (2, π‘Ž3) > 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    2) > 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    1) > 𝑒 (2, 𝑐) ,

    𝑒 (3, π‘Ž1) > 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    3) > 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    2) > 𝑒 (3, 𝑐) .

    (2)

    In other words, for each player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 = {1, 2, 3} toterminate is an average outcome; it is better (worse) whenthe next (previous) player terminates; finally, if nobody does,then the dicycle 𝑐 appears, which is the worst outcome for all.The considered game has an improvement cycle of length 6,which is shown in Figure 2. Indeed, let player 1 terminatesat π‘Ž1, while 2 and 3 proceed. The corresponding situation

    (π‘Ž1, π‘Ž1, π‘Ž1) can be improved by 2 to (π‘Ž

    1, π‘Ž2, π‘Ž1), which in its

    turn can be improved by 1 to (π‘Ž2, π‘Ž2, π‘Ž2). Repeating the similar

    procedure two times more we obtain the improvement cycleshown in Figure 2.

    There are two more situations, which result in (π‘Ž1, π‘Ž2, π‘Ž3)

    and (𝑐, 𝑐, 𝑐). They appear when all three players terminate orproceed simultaneously. Yet, none of these two situations is anNE either. Moreover, each of them can be improved by everyplayer 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 = {1, 2, 3}.

    Thus, the following negative result holds, which we recallwithout proof from [4]; see also [1].

    Theorem 7. Game (G1, 𝑒) has no uniform NE in pure strate-

    gies whenever 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ1.

    We note that each player has positive payoffs. This iswithout loss of generality as we can shift the payoffs by apositive constant without changing the game.

    A similar two-person uniform NE-free example wassuggested in [1], for G

    2. Let us consider a family π‘ˆ

    2of the

    utility functions defined by the following constraints:

    𝑒 (1, π‘Ž6) > 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    5) > 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    2) > 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    1)

    > 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž3) > 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    4) > 𝑒 (1, 𝑐) ,

    𝑒 (2, π‘Ž3) > 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    2) > 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    6)

    > 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž4) > 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    5) > 𝑒 (2, 𝑐) ,

    𝑒 (2, π‘Ž6) > 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    1) > 𝑒 (2, 𝑐) .

    (3)

    We claim that the Chess-like game (G2, 𝑒) has no uniform

    NE whenever 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ2.

    Let us remark that |π‘ˆ2| = 3 and that 𝑐 is theworst outcome

    for both players for all 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ2. To verify this, let us consider

    the normal form 𝑔2in Figure 3. By Theorem 5, there is a

    uniformly BR of player 2 to each strategy of player 1 and viceversa. It is not difficult to check that the obtained two setsof the BRs (which are denoted by the white discs and blacksquares in Figure 3) are disjoint. Hence, there is no uniformNE. Furthermore, it is not difficult to verify that the obtained16 situations induce an improvement cycle of length 10 andtwo improvement paths of lengths 2 and 4 that end in thiscycle.

    Theorem8 (see [1]). Game (G2, 𝑒) has no uniformNE in pure

    strategies whenever 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ2.

    The goal of the present paper is to demonstrate that theabove two game structures may have no uniform NE notonly in pure but also in mixed strategies. Let us note that byNash’s theorem [21, 22] NE in mixed strategies exist in anyinitialized game structure. Yet, this result cannot be extendedto the noninitialized game structure and uniform NE. In thisresearch we are motivated by the results of [8, 11].

    1.10. Mixed and Independently Mixed Strategies. Standardly,a mixed strategy 𝑦

    𝑖of a player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 is defined as a

    probabilistic distribution over the set𝑋𝑖of his pure strategies.

    Furthermore, 𝑦𝑖is called an independently mixed strategy if

    𝑖 randomizes in his positions V ∈ 𝑉𝑖independently. We

    will denote by π‘Œπ‘–and by 𝑍

    π‘–βŠ† π‘Œπ‘–the sets of mixed and

    independently mixed strategies of player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼, respectively.

    Remark 9. Let us recall that the players are restricted totheir positional strategies and let us also note that the latterconcept is closely related to the so-called behavioral strategiesintroduced by Kuhn [19, 20]. Although Kuhn restrictedhimself to trees, yet his construction can be extended todirected graphs, too.

    Let us recall that a game structure is called play-once ifeach player is in control of a unique position. For example,G1is play-once. Obviously, the classes of mixed and inde-

    pendently mixed strategies coincide for a play-once gamestructure. However, for G

    2these two notion differ. Each

    player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 = {1, 2} controls 3 positions and has 8

  • 6 GameTheory

    pure strategies. Hence, the set of mixed strategies π‘Œπ‘–is of

    dimension 7, while the setπ‘π‘–βŠ† π‘Œπ‘–of the independentlymixed

    strategies is only 3-dimensional.

    2. Markovian and A Priori Realizations

    For the independently mixed strategies we will consider twodifferent options.

    For every player 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 let us consider a probabilitydistribution 𝑃𝑖V for all positions V ∈ 𝑉𝑖, which assignsa probability 𝑝(V, V) to each move (V, V) from V ∈ 𝑉

    𝑖,

    standardly assuming

    0 ≀ 𝑝 (V, V) ≀ 1, βˆ‘

    Vβˆˆπ‘‰

    𝑝 (V, V) = 1,

    𝑝 (V, V) = 0 whenever (V, V) βˆ‰ 𝐸.

    (4)

    Now, the limit distributions of the terminals 𝐴 ={π‘Ž1, . . . , π‘Ž

    π‘š, π‘Žβˆž} can be defined in two ways, which we will be

    referred to as theMarkovian and a priori realizations.The first approach is classical; the limit distribution can

    be found by solving a π‘š Γ— π‘š system of linear equations; see,for example, [27] and also [26].

    For example, let us consider G1and let 𝑝

    𝑗be the

    probability to proceed in V𝑗for 𝑗 = 1, 2, 3. If 𝑝

    1= 𝑝2=

    𝑝3= 1, then, obviously, the play will cycle with probability 1

    resulting in the limit distribution (0, 0, 0, 1) for (π‘Ž1, π‘Ž2, π‘Ž3, 𝑐).

    Otherwise, assuming that V1is the initial position, we obtain

    the limit distribution:

    (

    1 βˆ’ 𝑝1

    1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3

    ,

    𝑝1(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2)

    1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3

    ,

    𝑝1𝑝2(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    3)

    1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3

    , 0) . (5)

    Indeed, positions V1, V2, V3are transient and the probabil-

    ity of cycling forever is 0 whenever 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3< 1. Obviously,

    the sum of the above four probabilities is 1.The Markovian approach assumes that for 𝑑 = 0, 1, . . .

    the move 𝑒(𝑑) = (V(𝑑), V(𝑑 + 1)) is chosen randomly, inaccordance with the distribution 𝑃V(𝑑), and independently forall 𝑑 (furthermore, V(0) = V

    0is a fixed initial position). In

    particular, if the play comes to the same position again, that is,V = V(𝑑) = V(𝑑) for some 𝑑 < 𝑑, then the moves 𝑒(𝑑) and 𝑒(𝑑)may be distinct although they are chosen (independently)with the same distribution 𝑃V.

    The concept of a priori realization is based on the follow-ing alternative assumptions. A move (V, V) is chosen accord-ing to 𝑃V, independently for all V ∈ 𝑉 \ 𝑉𝑇, but only once,before the game starts. Being chosen themove (V, V) is appliedwhenever the play comes at V. By these assumptions, eachinfinite play β„“ is a lasso; that is, it consists of an initial part(that might be empty) and an infinitely repeated dicycle 𝑐

    β„“.

    Alternatively, β„“ may be finite; that is, it terminates in a 𝑉𝑇.

    In both cases, β„“ begins in V0and the probability of β„“ is the

    product of the probabilities of all its moves, 𝑃ℓ= βˆπ‘’βˆˆβ„“π‘(𝑒).

    In this way, we obtain a probability distribution on the setof lassos of the digraph. In particular, the effective payoff isdefined as the expected payoffs for the corresponding lassos.Let us also note that (in contrast to the Markovian case)

    the computation of limit distribution is not computationallyefficient, since the set of plays may grow exponentially in sizeof the digraph. No polynomial algorithm computing the limitdistribution is known for a priori realizations. Returning toour exampleG

    1, we obtain the following limit distribution:

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1, 𝑝1(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2) , 𝑝1𝑝2(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    3) , 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3)

    for the outcomes (π‘Ž1, π‘Ž2, π‘Ž3, 𝑐) ,

    (6)

    with initial position V1. The probability of outcome 𝑐 is

    𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3; it is strictly positive whenever 𝑝

    𝑖> 0 for all 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼.

    Indeed, in contrast to theMarkovian realization, the cyclewillbe repeated infinitely whenever it appears once under a priorirealization.

    Remark 10. Thus, solving the Chess-like games in the inde-pendently mixed strategies looks more natural under apriori (rather than Markovian) realizations. Unfortunately, itseems not that easy to suggest more applications of a priorirealizations and we have to acknowledge that the conceptof the Markovian realization is much more fruitful. Let usalso note that playing in pure strategies can be viewed as aspecial case of both Markovian and a priori realizations withdegenerate probability distributions.

    As we already mentioned, the mixed and independentlymixed strategies coincide for G

    1since it is play-once. Yet,

    these two classes of strategies differ inG2.

    3. Chess-Like Games with No Uniform NE

    In the present paper, we will strengthen Theorems 7 and 8,showing that games (G

    1, 𝑒) and (G

    2, 𝑒) may fail to have an

    NE (not only in pure, but even) in mixed strategies, as well asin the independentlymixed strategies, under bothMarkovianand a priori realizations.

    For convenience, let 𝐽 = {1, . . . , π‘š} denote the set ofindices of nonterminal positions. We will refer to positionsgiving only these indices.

    Let us recall the definition of payoff function 𝑓V0(𝑖, π‘₯) ofplayer 𝑖 for the initial position V

    0and the strategy profile

    π‘₯; see Theorem 5. Let us extend this definition introducingthe payoff function for the mixed and independently mixedstrategies. In both cases, we define it as the expected payoff,under one of the above realizations, and denote by 𝐹V0(𝑖, 𝑝),where 𝑝 is an π‘š-vector whose 𝑗th coordinate 𝑝

    𝑗is the

    probability of proceeding (not terminating) at position 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽.

    Remark 11. Let us observe that, in both G1and G

    2, the

    payoff functions𝐹V0(𝑖, 𝑝), 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 are continuously differentiablefunctions of 𝑝

    𝑗when 0 < 𝑝

    𝑗< 1 for all 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽, for all players

    𝑖 ∈ 𝐼. Hence, if 𝑝 is a uniform NE such that 0 < 𝑝𝑗< 1 for all

    𝑗 ∈ 𝐽 (under either a priori or Markovian realization), then

    πœ•πΉV0(𝑖, 𝑝)

    πœ•π‘π‘—

    = 0, βˆ€π‘– ∈ 𝐼, 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽, V0∈ 𝑉. (7)

    In the next two sections, we will construct games thathave no uniform NE under both, a priori and Markovian,

  • GameTheory 7

    realizations. Assuming that a uniform mixed NE exists, wewill obtain a contradiction with (7) whenever 0 < 𝑝

    𝑗< 1 for

    all 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽.

    3.1. (G1,𝑒) Examples. The next lemma will be instrumental

    in the proofs of the following two theorems.

    Lemma 12. The probabilities to proceed satisfy 0 < 𝑝𝑗< 1 for

    all 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽 = {1, 2, 3} in any independently mixed uniform NEin game (G

    1, 𝑒), where 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    1, and under both a priori and

    Markovian realizations.

    Proof. Let us assume indirectly that there is an (indepen-dently) mixed uniform NE under a priori realization with𝑝𝑗= 0 for some 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽. This would imply the existence

    of an acyclic game with uniform NE, in contradiction withTheorem 7. Now let us consider the case 𝑝

    𝑗= 1. Due to the

    circular symmetry of (G1, 𝑒), we can choose any player, say,

    𝑗 = 1. The preference list of player 3 is 𝑒(3, π‘Ž1) > 𝑒(3, π‘Ž

    3) >

    𝑒(3, π‘Ž2) > 𝑒(3, 𝑐). His most favorable outcome, π‘Ž

    1, is not

    achievable since 𝑝1= 1. Hence, 𝑝

    3= 0 because his second

    best outcome is π‘Ž3. Thus, the game is reduced to an acyclic

    one, in contradiction withTheorem 7, again.

    Theorem 13. Game (G1, 𝑒) has no uniform NE in indepen-

    dently mixed strategies under a priori realization whenever𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    1.

    Proof. To simplify our notation we denote by 𝑗+and 𝑗

    βˆ’

    the following and preceding positions along the 3-cycle ofG1, respectively. Assume indirectly that (𝑝

    1, 𝑝2, 𝑝3) forms a

    uniform NE and considers the effective payoff of player 1:

    𝐹𝑗(1, 𝑝) = (1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    𝑗) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    𝑗) + 𝑝𝑗(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    𝑗+) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    𝑗+)

    + 𝑝𝑗𝑝𝑗+(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    π‘—βˆ’) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    π‘—βˆ’) + 𝑝𝑗𝑝𝑗+π‘π‘—βˆ’π‘’ (1, 𝑐) ,

    (8)

    where 𝑗 is the initial position.By Lemma 12, we must have 0 < 𝑝

    𝑗< 1 for 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽 =

    {1, 2, 3}. Therefore (7) must hold. Hence, (πœ•πΉπ‘—(1, 𝑝)/πœ•π‘

    π‘—βˆ’) =

    𝑝𝑗𝑝𝑗+(𝑒(1, 𝑐) βˆ’ 𝑒(1, π‘Ž

    π‘—βˆ’)) = 0 and 𝑝

    𝑗𝑝𝑗+

    = 0 follows since𝑒(1, π‘Žπ‘—βˆ’) > 𝑒(1, 𝑐). Thus, 𝑝

    1𝑝2𝑝3= 0, in contradiction to our

    assumption.

    Let us recall that for G1, independently mixed strategies

    and mixed strategies are the same.Now, let us consider the Markovian realization. Game

    (G1, 𝑒)may have noNE inmixed strategies underMarkovian

    realization either, yet, only for some special payoffs 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ1.

    Theorem 14. Game (G1, 𝑒), with 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    1, has no uniform NE

    in independentlymixed strategies underMarkovian realizationif and only if πœ‡

    1πœ‡2πœ‡3β‰₯ 1, where

    πœ‡1=

    𝑒 (1, π‘Ž2) βˆ’ 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    1)

    𝑒 (1, π‘Ž1) βˆ’ 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    3)

    ,

    πœ‡2=

    𝑒 (2, π‘Ž3) βˆ’ 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    2)

    𝑒 (2, π‘Ž2) βˆ’ 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    1)

    ,

    πœ‡3=

    𝑒 (3, π‘Ž1) βˆ’ 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    3)

    𝑒 (3, π‘Ž3) βˆ’ 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    2)

    .

    (9)

    It is easy to verify that πœ‡π‘–> 0 for 𝑖 = 1, 2, 3 whenever

    𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ1. Let us also note that in the symmetric case πœ‡

    1= πœ‡2=

    πœ‡3= πœ‡ the above condition πœ‡

    1πœ‡2πœ‡3β‰₯ 1 turns into πœ‡ β‰₯ 1.

    Proof. Let 𝑝 = (𝑝1, 𝑝2, 𝑝3) be a uniform NE in the game

    (G1, 𝑒) underMarkovian realization.Then, by Lemma 12, 0 <

    𝑝𝑖< 1 for 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 = {1, 2, 3}.Thepayoff function of a player, with

    respect to the initial position that this player controls, is givenby one of the next three formulas:

    𝐹1(1, 𝑝)

    =

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    1)+𝑝1(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    2)+𝑝1𝑝2(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    3) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    3)

    1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3

    ,

    𝐹2(2, 𝑝)

    =

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝2) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    2)+𝑝2(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    3) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    3)+𝑝2𝑝3(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    1) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    1)

    1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3

    ,

    𝐹3(3, 𝑝)

    =

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝3) 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    3)+𝑝3(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    1) 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    1)+𝑝3𝑝1(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2) 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    2)

    1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3

    .

    (10)

    By Lemma 12, (7) holds for any uniformNE.Therefore wehave

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3)2 πœ•πΉ1

    (1, 𝑝)

    πœ•π‘1

    = 𝑝2(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    3) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    3) + (𝑝

    2𝑝3βˆ’ 1) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    1)

    + (1 βˆ’ 𝑝2) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    2) = 0,

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3)2 πœ•πΉ2

    (2, 𝑝)

    πœ•π‘2

    = 𝑝3(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    1) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    1) + (𝑝

    1𝑝3βˆ’ 1) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    2)

    + (1 βˆ’ 𝑝3) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    3) = 0,

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3)2 πœ•πΉ3

    (3, 𝑝)

    πœ•π‘3

    = 𝑝1(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2) 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    2) + (𝑝

    1𝑝2βˆ’ 1) 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    3)

    + (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1) 𝑒 (3, π‘Ž

    1) = 0.

    (11)

    Setting πœ†π‘–= πœ‡π‘–+ 1 for 𝑖 = 1, 2, 3, we can transform the

    above equations to the following form:

    πœ†1(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2) = 1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2𝑝3,

    πœ†2(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    3) = 1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    1𝑝3,

    πœ†3(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    1) = 1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    1𝑝2.

    (12)

  • 8 GameTheory

    Assuming 0 < 𝑝𝑗< 1, 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽 and using successive elimination,

    we uniquely express 𝑝 via πœ† as follows:

    0 < 𝑝1=

    πœ†2+ πœ†3βˆ’ πœ†1πœ†2βˆ’ πœ†2πœ†3+ πœ†1πœ†2πœ†3βˆ’ 1

    πœ†1πœ†3βˆ’ πœ†1+ 1

    < 1,

    0 < 𝑝2=

    πœ†1+ πœ†3βˆ’ πœ†1πœ†3βˆ’ πœ†2πœ†3+ πœ†1πœ†2πœ†3βˆ’ 1

    πœ†1πœ†2βˆ’ πœ†2+ 1

    < 1,

    0 < 𝑝3=

    πœ†1+ πœ†2βˆ’ πœ†1πœ†2βˆ’ πœ†1πœ†3+ πœ†1πœ†2πœ†3βˆ’ 1

    πœ†2πœ†3βˆ’ πœ†3+ 1

    < 1.

    (13)

    Interestingly, all three 𝑝𝑗< 1 inequalities are equivalent

    with the condition (πœ†1βˆ’1)(πœ†

    2βˆ’1)(πœ†

    3βˆ’1) < 1, that is,πœ‡

    1πœ‡2πœ‡3<

    1, which completes the proof.

    3.2. (G2,𝑒) Examples. Here we will show that (G

    2, 𝑒) may

    have no uniform NE for both Markovian and a priorirealizations, in independently mixed strategies, whenever𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    2. As for the mixed (unlike the independently mixed)

    strategies, we obtain NE-free examples only for some (not forall) 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    2.

    We begin with extending Lemma 12 to game (G2, 𝑒) and

    𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ2as follows.

    Lemma 15. The probabilities to proceed satisfy 0 < 𝑝𝑗< 1 for

    all 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽 = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6} in any independently mixed uniformNE in game (G

    2, 𝑒), where 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    2, and under both a priori

    and Markovian realizations.

    Proof. To prove that 𝑝𝑗< 1 for all 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽 let us consider the

    following six cases:

    (i) If 𝑝1= 1, then player 2 will proceed at position 6, as

    π‘Ž2> π‘Ž6in π‘ˆ2, implying 𝑝

    6= 1.

    (ii) If 𝑝2= 1, then either 𝑝

    1= 0 or 𝑝

    3= 1, as player 1,

    prefers π‘Ž1to π‘Ž3.

    (iii) If 𝑝3= 1, then 𝑝

    2= 0, as player 2 cannot achieve his

    best outcome of π‘Ž3, while π‘Ž

    2is his second best one.

    (iv) If 𝑝4= 1, then 𝑝

    3= 1, as player 1’s worst outcome is

    π‘Ž3in the current situation.

    (v) If 𝑝5= 1, then 𝑝

    4= 1, as player 2, prefers π‘Ž

    6to π‘Ž4.

    (vi) If 𝑝6= 1, then 𝑝

    5= 0, as player 1’s best outcome, is π‘Ž

    5

    now.

    It is easy to verify that, by the above implications, in all sixcases at least one of the proceeding probabilities should be 0,in contradiction toTheorem 8.

    Let us show that the game (G2, 𝑒) might have no NE in

    independently mixed strategies under both Markovian and apriori realizations. Let us consider the Markovian one first.

    Theorem 16. Game (G2, 𝑒) has no uniform NE in the inde-

    pendently mixed strategies under Markovian realization for all𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    2.

    Proof. Let us consider the uniform NE conditions for player2. Lemma 15 implies that (7) must be satisfied. Applying it tothe partial derivatives with respect to 𝑝

    4and 𝑝

    6we obtain

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3𝑝4𝑝5𝑝6)2

    𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3𝑝4𝑝5

    πœ•πΉ1(2, 𝑝)

    πœ•π‘6

    = ((1 βˆ’ 𝑝1) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    1) + 𝑝1(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    2)

    + 𝑝1𝑝2(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    3) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    3)

    + 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    4) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    4)

    + 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3𝑝4(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    5) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    5)

    βˆ’ (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3𝑝4𝑝5) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    6)) = 0,

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3𝑝4𝑝5𝑝6)2

    𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3𝑝5𝑝6

    πœ•πΉ5(2, 𝑝)

    πœ•π‘4

    = (1 βˆ’ 𝑝5) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    5) + 𝑝5(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    6) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    6)

    + 𝑝5𝑝6(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    1) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    1) + 𝑝5𝑝6𝑝1(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    2)

    + 𝑝5𝑝6𝑝1𝑝2(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    3) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    3)

    βˆ’ (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3𝑝5𝑝6) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    4) = 0.

    (14)

    Let us multiply the first equation by 𝑝5𝑝6and subtract it

    from the second one, yielding

    (1 βˆ’ 𝑝1𝑝2𝑝3𝑝4𝑝5𝑝6) [βˆ’π‘’ (2, π‘Ž

    4) + (1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    5) 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    5)

    +𝑝5𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    6)] = 0,

    (15)

    or equivalently, 𝑒(2, π‘Ž4) βˆ’ (1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    5)𝑒(2, π‘Ž

    5) βˆ’ 𝑝5𝑒(2, π‘Ž6) = 0.

    From this equation, we find

    𝑝5=

    𝑒 (2, π‘Ž4) βˆ’ 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    5)

    𝑒 (2, π‘Ž6) βˆ’ 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    5)

    . (16)

    Furthermore, the condition 0 < 𝑝5< 1 implies that either

    𝑒(2, π‘Ž5) < 𝑒(2, π‘Ž

    4) < 𝑒(2, π‘Ž

    6) or 𝑒(2, π‘Ž

    5) > 𝑒(2, π‘Ž

    4) >

    𝑒(2, π‘Ž6). Both orders contradict the preference list π‘ˆ

    2, thus,

    completing the proof.

    Now let us consider the case of a priori realization.

    Theorem 17. Game (G2, 𝑒) has no uniform NE in indepen-

    dentlymixed strategies under a priori realization for all 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ2.

    Proof. Let us assume indirectly that 𝑝 =(𝑝1, 𝑝2, 𝑝3, 𝑝4, 𝑝5, 𝑝6) form a uniform NE. Let us consider

    the effective payoff of the player 1 with respect to the initialposition 2:

    𝐹2(1, 𝑝) = (1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    2) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    2) + 𝑝2(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    3) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    3)

    + 𝑝2𝑝3(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    4) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    4)

  • GameTheory 9

    + 𝑝2𝑝3𝑝4(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    5) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    5)

    + 𝑝2𝑝3𝑝4𝑝5(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    6) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    6)

    + 𝑝2𝑝3𝑝4𝑝5𝑝6(1 βˆ’ 𝑝

    1) 𝑒 (1, π‘Ž

    1) .

    (17)By Lemma 15, we have 0 < 𝑝

    𝑗< 1 for 𝑗 ∈ 𝐽 = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6}.

    Hence, (7) must hold; in particular, (πœ•πΉ2(1, 𝑝)/πœ•π‘

    1) = 0 and,

    since 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ2is positive, we obtain 𝑝

    2𝑝3𝑝4𝑝5𝑝6= 0, that is a

    contradiction.

    The last result can be extended from the independentlymixed to mixed strategies. However, the correspondingexample is constructed not for all but only for some 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    2.

    Theorem 18. The game (G2, 𝑒) has no uniform, NE in mixed

    strategies, at least for some 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ2.

    Proof. Let us recall that there are two players inG2controling

    three positions each and there are two possible moves inevery position. Thus, each player has eight pure strategies.Standardly, the mixed strategies are defined as probabilitydistributions on the set of the pure strategies, that is, π‘₯, 𝑦 ∈S8, where 𝑧 = (𝑧

    1, . . . , 𝑧

    8) ∈ S8if and only if βˆ‘8

    𝑖=1𝑧𝑖= 1 and

    𝑧 β‰₯ 0.Furthermore, let us denote by π‘Ž

    π‘˜π‘™(V0) the outcome of the

    game beginning in the initial position V0∈ 𝑉 in case when

    player 1 chooses his pure strategy π‘˜ and player 2 chooses herpure strategy 𝑙, where π‘˜, 𝑙 ∈ {1, . . . , 8}.

    Given a utility function 𝑒 : 𝐼 ×𝐴 β†’ R, if a pair of mixedstrategies π‘₯, 𝑦 ∈ S

    8form a uniform NE then

    8

    βˆ‘

    π‘˜=1

    π‘₯π‘˜π‘’ (2, π‘Ž

    π‘˜π‘™(V0)) {

    = 𝑧V0, if 𝑦

    𝑙> 0

    ≀ 𝑧V0, otherwise

    (18)

    must hold for some 𝑧V0 value for all initial positions V0 βˆˆπ‘‰. Indeed, otherwise player 2 would change the probabilitydistribution 𝑦 to get a better value. Let 𝑆 = {𝑖 | 𝑦

    𝑖> 0} denote

    the set of indices of all positive components of𝑦 ∈ S8. By (19),

    there exists a subset 𝑆 βŠ† {1, . . . , 𝑛} such that the next systemis feasible:

    8

    βˆ‘

    π‘˜=1

    π‘₯π‘˜π‘’ (2, π‘Ž

    π‘˜π‘™(V0)) = 𝑧V0

    , βˆ€π‘™ ∈ 𝑆,

    8

    βˆ‘

    π‘˜=1

    π‘₯π‘˜π‘’ (2, π‘Ž

    π‘˜π‘™(V0)) ≀ 𝑧V0

    , βˆ€π‘™ βˆ‰ 𝑆,

    8

    βˆ‘

    π‘˜=1

    π‘₯π‘˜= 1,

    π‘₯π‘˜β‰₯ 0, βˆ€π‘˜ = 1, . . . , 8,

    𝑧V0unrestricted, βˆ€V

    0∈ 𝑉.

    (19)

    Then, let us consider, for example, a utility function 𝑒 βˆˆπ‘ˆ2with the following payoffs of player 2:

    𝑒 (2, π‘Ž1) = 43, 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    2) = 81, 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    3) = 93,

    𝑒 (2, π‘Ž4) = 50, 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    5) = 15, 𝑒 (2, π‘Ž

    1) = 80,

    𝑒 (2, 𝑐) = 0.

    (20)

    We verified that (19) is infeasible for all subsets 𝑆 βŠ† {1, . . . , 8}such that |𝑆| β‰₯ 2. Since for any𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    2there is no pure strategy

    NE either, we obtain a contradiction.

    3.3. Concluding Remarks

    Remark 19. In the last two theorems, in contrast withTheorem 14, uniform NE exist for no 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    2.

    Remark 20. Let us note that Nash’s results [21, 22], guarantee-ing the existence of an NE in mixed strategies for any normalform games, are applicable in case of a fixed initial position.Yet, our results show that Nash’s theorem, in general, does notextend to the case of uniform NE, except for the 𝑛-personacyclic case [12, 19, 20] and the two-person zero sum cases.

    Remark 21. It seems that the same holds for all 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ2.

    We tested (19) for many randomly chosen 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ2and

    encountered infeasibility for all 𝑆 βŠ† {1, . . . , 8} such that |𝑆| β‰₯2. Yet, we have no proof and it still remains open whether forany 𝑒 ∈ π‘ˆ

    2there is no NE in mixed strategies.

    Remark 22. Finally, let us note that for an arbitrary Chess-likegame structure (not only for G

    1and G

    2) in independently

    mixed strategies under both the Markovian and a priorirealizations for any 𝑖 ∈ 𝐼 and π‘˜, 𝑙 ∈ 𝐽, the ratio (πœ•πΉ

    𝑙(𝑖, 𝑝)/

    πœ•π‘π‘–)/(πœ•πΉπ‘˜(𝑖, 𝑝)/πœ•π‘

    𝑖) = 𝑃(𝑖, π‘˜, 𝑙) is a positive constant.

    Acknowledgments

    The first and third authors acknowledge the partial supportby the NSF Grants IIS-1161476 and also CMMI-0856663.The second author is thankful to János Flesch for helpfuldiscussions. All author are also thankful to an anonymousreviewer for many helpful remarks and suggestions.

    References

    [1] E. Boros, K. Elbassioni, V. Gurvich, and K. Makino, β€œOn Nashequilibria and improvement cycles in pure positional strategiesfor Chess-like and Backgammon-like n-person games,”DiscreteMathematics, vol. 312, no. 4, pp. 772–788, 2012.

    [2] D. Andersson, V. Gurvich, and T. D. Hansen, β€œOn acyclicity ofgames with cycles,” Discrete Applied Mathematics, vol. 158, no.10, pp. 1049–1063, 2010.

    [3] D. Andersson, V. Gurvich, and T. D. Hansen, β€œOn acyclicity ofgames with cycles,” in Algorithmic Aspects in Information andManagement, vol. 5564, pp. 15–28, 2009.

    [4] E. Boros and V. Gurvich, β€œOn Nash-solvability in pure station-ary strategies of finite games with perfect information whichmay have cycles,” Mathematical Social Sciences, vol. 46, no. 2,pp. 207–241, 2003.

    [5] E. Boros and V. Gurvich, β€œWhy chess and backgammon can besolved in pure positional uniformly optimal strategies,” RUT-COR Research Report 21-2009, Rutgers University.

    [6] E. Boros, V. Gurvich, K. Makino, and W. Shao, β€œNash-solvabletwo-person symmetric cycle game forms,” Discrete AppliedMathematics, vol. 159, no. 15, pp. 1461–1487, 2011.

  • 10 GameTheory

    [7] E. Boros and R. Rand, β€œTerminal games with three terminalshave proper Nash equilibria,” RUTCOR Research Report RRR-22-2009, Rutgers University.

    [8] J. Flesch, J. Kuipers, G. Shoenmakers, and O. J. Vrieze, β€œSub-game-perfect equilibria in free transition games,” ResearchMemorandum RM/08/027, University of Maastricht, Maas-tricht, The Netherlands, 2008.

    [9] J. Flesch, J. Kuipers, G. Shoenmakers, and O. J. Vrieze, β€œSub-game-perfection equilibria in stochastic games with perfectinformation and recursive payos,” Research MemorandumRM/08/041, University of Maastricht, Maastricht, The Nether-lands, 2008.

    [10] J. Kuipers, J. Flesch, G. Schoenmakers, and K. Vrieze, β€œPuresubgame-perfect equilibria in free transition games,” EuropeanJournal of Operational Research, vol. 199, no. 2, pp. 442–447,2009.

    [11] J. Flesch, J. Kuipers, G. Schoenmakers, and K. Vrieze, β€œSubgameperfection in positive recursive games with perfect informa-tion,”Mathematics of Operations Research, vol. 35, no. 1, pp. 193–207, 2010.

    [12] D.Gale, β€œA theory ofN-person gameswith perfect information,”Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, vol. 39, no. 6,pp. 496–501, 1953.

    [13] V. A. Gurvich, β€œOn theory of multistep games,”USSR Computa-tional Mathematics and Mathematical Physics, vol. 13, no. 6, pp.143–161, 1973.

    [14] V. A. Gurvich, β€œThe solvability of positional games in purestrategies,” USSR Computational Mathematics and Mathemat-ical Physics, vol. 15, no. 2, pp. 74–87, 1975.

    [15] V. Gurvich, β€œEquilibrium in pure strategies,” Soviet Mathemat-ics, vol. 38, no. 3, pp. 597–602, 1989.

    [16] V. Gurvich, β€œA stochastic game with complete information andwithout equilibrium situations in pure stationary strategies,”Russian Mathematical Surveys, vol. 43, no. 2, pp. 171–172, 1988.

    [17] V. Gurvich, β€œA theorem on the existence of equilibrium situ-ations in pure stationary strategies for ergodic extensions of(2 Γ— π‘˜) bimatrix games,” Russian Mathematical Surveys, vol. 45,no. 4, pp. 170–172, 1990.

    [18] V. Gurvich, β€œSaddle point in pure strategies,” Russian Academyof ScienceDokladyMathematics, vol. 42, no. 2, pp. 497–501, 1990.

    [19] H. Kuhn, β€œExtensive games,” Proceedings of the NationalAcademy of Sciences, vol. 36, pp. 286–295, 1950.

    [20] H. Kuhn, β€œExtensive games and the problems of information,”Annals of Mathematics Studies, vol. 28, pp. 193–216, 1953.

    [21] J. Nash, β€œEquilibrium points in n-person games,” Proceedings ofthe National Academy of Sciences, vol. 36, no. 1, pp. 48–49, 1950.

    [22] J. Nash, β€œNon-cooperative games,” Annals of Mathematics, vol.54, no. 2, pp. 286–295, 1951.

    [23] A. Condon, β€œAn algorithm for simple stochastic games,” inAdvances in Computational Complexity Theory, vol. 13 ofDIMACS series in discrete mathematics and theoretical computerscience, 1993.

    [24] I. V. Romanovsky, β€œOn the solvability of Bellman’s functionalequation for a Markovian decision process,” Journal of Mathe-matical Analysis and Applications, vol. 42, no. 2, pp. 485–498,1973.

    [25] R. A. Howard, Dynamic Programming and Markov Processes,The M.I.T. Press, 1960.

    [26] H. Mine and S. Osaki, Markovian Decision Process, AmericanElsevier, New York, NY, USA, 1970.

    [27] J. G. Kemeny and J. L. Snell, Finite Markov Chains, Springer,1960.

  • Submit your manuscripts athttp://www.hindawi.com

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    MathematicsJournal of

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Mathematical Problems in Engineering

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com

    Differential EquationsInternational Journal of

    Volume 2014

    Applied MathematicsJournal of

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Probability and StatisticsHindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Journal of

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Mathematical PhysicsAdvances in

    Complex AnalysisJournal of

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    OptimizationJournal of

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    CombinatoricsHindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    International Journal of

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Operations ResearchAdvances in

    Journal of

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Function Spaces

    Abstract and Applied AnalysisHindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    International Journal of Mathematics and Mathematical Sciences

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    The Scientific World JournalHindawi Publishing Corporation http://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Algebra

    Discrete Dynamics in Nature and Society

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Decision SciencesAdvances in

    Discrete MathematicsJournal of

    Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com

    Volume 2014 Hindawi Publishing Corporationhttp://www.hindawi.com Volume 2014

    Stochastic AnalysisInternational Journal of