psychological study of empathy

Upload: cfilloscribd

Post on 04-Jun-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    1/35

    Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 brill.com/jpp

    pheno

    menol

    ogicalpsych

    ology

    jour

    nalof

    Edith Stein and the Contemporary Psychological

    Study of Empathy

    Rita W. MenesesCatolica-Lisbon School of Business and Economics,

    Universidade Catlica Portuguesa, Lisbon, Portugal

    Michael LarkinSchool of Psychology, University of Birmingham, Birmingham, UK

    Abstract

    Illuminated by the writings of Edith Stein (1917/1989), this paper presents a model

    of empathy as a very particular intersubjective understanding. This is commonly a

    view absent from psychology literature. For Stein, empathy is the experience of

    experientially and directly knowing another persons experience, as it unfolds in

    the present, together with the awareness of the otherness of that experience. It

    can be conceptually distinguished, in terms of process and experience, from

    current models that propose that empathic understandings are intellectual expe-

    riences (e.g., explicit simulation theories, perspective-taking) or sympathetic expe-

    riences (e.g., implicit simulation theories, contagion-related theories). As such,

    she provides an additional or alternative aspect to understanding other peoples

    experiences. Our paper provides a summary of Steins key analytic claims about

    three key facets of empathy (directly perceiving, experientially projecting, and

    interpretatively mentalizing). Her views are discussed in the light of debates rele-

    vant for contemporary psychology and social cognition.

    Keywords

    empathy, social understandings, sympathy, intersubjectivity

    Empathy entered everyday discourse surprisingly recently. The German

    philosopher Theodor Lipps was inuential in this. In 1903, Lipps adopted

    This is a common contemporary historical view, although Duan and Hill (1994, p. 261)

    were able to track down the use ofEinfhlungto Robert Vischer (1873), in the aesthetic eld,

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    2/35

    152 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    the German termEinfhlung, derived from the Greek empatheia(fromem-

    in and pathosfeeling), in his thesis on aesthetic experiences. This con-

    ceptwas translated by Titchener into English as empathy. It was used todescribe the process of humanizing objects, of reading or feeling ourselves

    into them (Titchener, 1924, p. 417, cf. Duan & Hill, 1996, p. 261). At the core

    of this concept is the idea of going into a strong feeling-connection with

    another (Barrett-Lennard, 1981, p. 91).

    Soon after this, Max Schelers (1913/1979) work on sympathy appeared,

    (Sympathie/mitgefhl), followed by Edith Steins thesis on empathy

    (1917/1989). Lipps, Scheler and Stein proposed theoretically distinct views

    of these interpersonal phenomena (sympathy and empathy), which, overtime, have been confused with one another. Among Scheler, Lipps and

    Stein, there is, however, an agreement that empathy is a way of knowing or

    understanding others: there are three spheres of knowledge. I know about

    things, about myself, and about others. . . . The source of the third type of

    knowledge is empathy (Barrett-Lennard, 1981, p. 91, cf. Allport, 1937, p. 351).

    This was the core consensual meaning of empathy in philosophy in the

    beginning of the twentieth century.

    Aims

    Presently, the stance that empathy is a way of knowing or understanding

    others sometimes appears to be a non-consensual position, although it is

    the one adopted in this paper. For example, in psychology, empathy can be

    regarded as a responsive sympathetic feeling, also named empathic con-

    cern (i.e., an other-oriented emotional response elicited by and congruent

    with the perceived welfare of someone else, Batson, 2009, p. 8).

    Among those who have psychologically investigated interpersonal

    understandings, some have proposed that these come about via an explicit

    which would be the predecessor of empathy, to mean humans spontaneous projection of real

    psychic feeling into the people and things they perceive. On the other hand, Zepf and Hart-

    mann (2008, p. 56) remarked that the word empathy was rst used by Lotze, in 1858, to

    describe how we can deploy our imagination to place ourselves in, and participate in the expe-

    rience of nature, as well as to Herder, in 1774, to describe how one feels oneself into every-

    thing. Therefore, although there are alternative historical versions, in these early beginnings,

    empathy was a term that described an act that connected a subject to an object (person or

    other) by means of which some sort of knowing of that object occurred.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    3/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 153

    simulation process, that is, a higher-order intellectual process of adopting

    someone elses perspective (intellectual understandings); and some more

    suggested that social understandings are the result of an implicit simulationprocessthat involves ones personal emotional responses to other peoples

    experiences (sympathetic understandings).

    In this paper, we suggest that these two models capture two distinctive

    routes to understanding other peoples experiences; and that there is an

    additional form of understanding (intuitive understandings). It has also

    been proposed as an alternative route in phenomenology (e.g., Gallagher,

    2007). Although this particular form of understanding appears to underlie

    some psychotherapy approaches (e.g., Rogers, 1957/2007), psychologicalmodels do not usually address this type of understanding as a phenomenon

    on its own right (e.g., Kerem, Fishman & Josselson, 2001).

    The experience of an intuitive understanding was thoroughly described

    by Edith Stein. Her thesis, On the problem of empathy (1917/1989; Zum

    Problem der Einfhlung), was conducted under the supervision of Edmund

    Husserl. It is a rare, canonical example of orthodox, Husserlian, phenome-

    nological inquiry. In this work, Stein provides one of the most systematic,

    complete, and thorough applications of Husserls methodological approach

    to experience. It is also a text which offfers a remarkably contemporary,

    theoretically coherent, and clear delineation of the psychological phenom-

    enon of empathy, as it appears in consciousness.

    Steins clarity about the limits and nature of empathy was achieved by

    means of the phenomenological method. This required her to establish the

    essential features of empathy, and to rule out of her account those simula-

    cra of empathy which, without close examination, might be mistaken for

    empathy itself. Given that the eld of empathy studies is in some concep-

    tual disarray (e.g. see Batson, 2009), and that the term itself has a relativelyrecent history, Steins conceptual clarity is worthy of re-discovery and offfers

    a sound basis for further psychological research. Unfortunately, the con-

    ceptual clarity of her thinking is not mirrored by theaccessibility of her

    workthe text of her thesis on empathy is embedded within the dense and

    specialist phrasing of the German phenomenologists. In this article, we hope

    to unpack Steins ideas for a contemporary psychological audience. We

    hope to persuade those interested in the nature of empathy, that through

    its study as a lived experience, a theoretically and coherently grounded

    understanding of this particular form of understanding can be generated.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    4/35

    154 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    Steins work on empathy has been overlooked by much contemporary

    psychologyin contrast with Lipps and Schelers theses on the theme. As

    we shall see, her work is also sometimes misinterpreted, or only partiallyportrayed. Recently, however, there has been a growing resurgence of inter-

    est in some of her doctoral claims, both in the phenomenological and

    psychological elds of research (e.g., Barrett-Lennard, 1981; Boulanger &

    Lanon, 2006; Depraz, 2008, 2001; Gallagher, 2007; Gurmin, 2007; Prinz,

    2006; Reik, 1948/1971; Rockwell, 2007; Rogers, 1957/2007; Thompson, 2001;

    White, 1997; Zahavi, 2008, 2007, 2001).

    We think that her ideas have the potential to clarify the concept of empa-

    thy for psychology, and to open up new directions for researchers in thiseld. We will therefore focus upon the key aspects of Steins thesis, drawing

    out those which have most relevance for the psychology of empathy. Steins

    views sometimes contradict widely-held contemporary views about empa-

    thy, but they are developed with a logic and elegance which is persuasive,

    and we hope that the reader will nd these points of diffference illuminat-

    ing and informative; and that a particular picture of empathy emerges.

    Steins Brief Biography

    Edith Stein (18911942) was born at Freiburg im Breisgau, Germany, into a

    Jewish family. In her youth, she declared herself an atheist. Stein began her

    doctoral work while working as an assistant to Husserl at the University of

    Gttingen, but her studies were interrupted by the war, and the death of

    Husserls son. For a period she worked as a nurse at a eld hospital in Aus-

    tria. In 1916, the eld hospital was dissolved, and Husserl took up a new post

    at Freiburg im Breisgau, so Stein returned to the town of her birth, where

    she completed her doctorate in 1917. Stein worked alongside Martin Heide-

    gger, who was also an assistant to Husserl during this period. In Germany,

    professorial posts were not easily obtained by women or Jews at this time;

    and Stein appears to have struggled to nd a niche for herself. She held

    posts at Freiburg and Gttingen, before working as a schoolteacher for

    some years. Academically, she retained an interest in phenomenology, phi-

    losophy and psychology, but in the 1920s she also converted to Catholicism,

    and an increasingly theological focus informed her later work. She left her

    For a biography, see Oben (1988/2010), and Macintyre (2006).

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    5/35

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    6/35

    156 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    Gallagher, 2007; Gurmin, 2007; Hart, 1999; Prinz, 2006; Scheler, 1913; Stein,

    1917; Thompson, 2001; Zahavi, 2008, 2007, 2001), andprojection theories(under-

    standing via a identication-related projected experience; e.g., Bachelor, 1988;Boulanger & Lanon, 2006; Gladstein, 1983; Hkansson & Montgomery,

    2003; Kerem et al., 2001; Tempel, 2007; Zepf & Hartmann, 2008).

    Explicit simulation(perspective-taking, role-taking, theories of mind) is

    a higher-order, usually deliberated reasoning about available information

    or cues (Batson, 2009, p. 4), based on the others experience or situation,

    such as what she says and does and your knowledge of her character, values,

    and desires (Batson, 2009, p. 7). Here, one intellectually imagines, predicts

    or simulates another persons experience. For example, if a friend tells youthat he is going to father a child, and you knew that he had been trying to

    have children for a while, you now imagine that he is happy. This is how

    explicit simulation works; and hence it can be said that it is an intellectual

    form of understandingothers.

    Implicit simulationtheories see social understandings as the result of a

    contamination and/or mimicking experience and a lower-order imagina-

    tive experience. That is, people have the the tendency to automatically

    mimic and synchronize facial expressions, vocalizations, postures and move-

    ments with those of another person, and, consequently, to converge emotion-

    ally (Hateld et al., 2009 p. 19). This reaction is subsequentlyused as the

    source of knowledge of the experience of another, in a stepwise manner

    (rst mimicry, then contagion, and then understanding). Thus, one infers

    from ones afffective reaction the experience of another. For example, you

    encounter a friend, feel unexpectedly happy, and you may somewhere

    along the line conclude that it is your friend that is happy after all. This is

    consistent with Lipps theory, and with the contemporary model of inter-

    personal understandings provided by neurocognitive theories. Projectionofffers a similar reading of events but via a distinctive terminology (through

    the concepts of identication, and then projection; e.g., Zepf & Hartmann,

    2008); and without determining that the reactive emotional experience

    (and perhaps the projective experience as well) necessarilyhappens sub-

    consciously, as generally observed with implicit simulation theories.

    Lipps would argue that this experience amounts to an empathic form of

    interpersonal understanding. Scheler would counter-argue by suggesting

    that contamination and identication are examples of sympathetic phe-

    nomena; and that sympathy is to be distinguished from empathy. Certainly,

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    7/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 157

    sympathy is rst and foremost a response to anothers experience, although

    it sometimes leaves the impression that one understands others too: we

    seem to have an immediate understanding of anothers experiences, whilealso participating in them (Scheler, 1913, p. 3). For Scheler, these respon-

    sive afffective phenomena should better be called sympathynot empa-

    thy. We propose that the interpersonal understanding achieved through

    sympathy should perhaps be conceptualized as a sympathetic form of

    understanding, and one which should be distinguished, on the one hand,

    from the intellectual form of understanding described by explicit simula-

    tion theories.

    Stein would not accept any of the above explanations as illustrative ofthe phenomenon of empathy. Her position is in accordance with current

    phenomenological theories. From this phenomenological perspective, we

    can use our minds and experiences to personally simulate (explicitly or

    implicitly) anothers experience, in order to gain insight about these, but

    this is not the only, or most ordinary way, of understanding others. That is,

    most commonly, from the viewpoint of the lived experience, one does not

    need to react in any emotional (contagion), behavioural (mimicking) or

    rational (remembering our knowledge or similar past experiences) way for

    the understanding to come about.

    Rather, people can understand one another not by inference, but directly,

    as a sort of primary perception (Scheler, 1913, p. 10). This ability is present

    from infancy, when already in a non-mentalizing way, I am able to see

    meaning, intention, and emotions in the actions of others (Gallagher, 2007,

    p. 354). For example, you look at your friend and just see how happy he is,

    while disclosing the news to you. That is, you would have a perceptive kind

    of understanding of his experiencefor claritys sake, say, an intuitive form

    of understanding. In broad strokes, this is what empathy is, for Stein. Thisexperience is sometimes described as an experiential understanding,

    anchored in the having of the experience of another, and thus confused

    with sympathetic understandings.

    We here propose that these explanations for interpersonal understand-

    ings (intellectual, sympathetic and intuitive) are distinctive psychological

    experiences, and merit to be explained in the light of appropriate psycho-

    logical theories. By offfering Steins views to a contemporary readership, we

    offfer to discussion an alternative (intuitive) form of interpersonal under-

    standing that is often absent from psychology literature.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    8/35

    158 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    Empathy and Sympathy: A Distinction

    According to a useful distinction made by Batson (2009), we can place Steinalongside those researchers who understand empathy as a way of knowing

    what another person is experiencing, and in opposition to those for whom

    empathy is a response to that knowledge. For instance, many psychologists

    would hold that empathys afffective component consists of a personal

    emotional response, congruent with the afffective state of another person

    (e.g., Batson, 2009; Boulanger & Lanon, 2006; Decety & Jackson, 2006,

    2004; Depraz, 2001; Duan & Hill, 1996; Eisenberg, 2000; Gladstein, 1983;

    Hkansson, 2003; Hofffman, 2000; Hassenstab et al., 2007; Hateld et al.,

    2009; Jabbi et al., 2007; Kerem et al., 2001; Preston & Waal, 2002). Two formsof afffective responses commonly investigated by these authors are conta-

    gion and distress; and their importance in current empathy-related litera-

    ture is evident in the following: all forms of empathy involve some level of

    emotional contagion and personal distress (Preston & Waal, 2002, p. 4).

    Stein explicitly rejects this idea, not because these responses do not

    exist, but because, for her, it is not the response, in itself, that is empathic.

    For Stein, empathy is, by denition, a means through which knowledge

    is acquired about another persons experienceand not a reaction orresponse to that understanding. As Zahavi says, empathy (. . .)amounts to

    experiencing, say, the other persons emotion without being in the correspond-

    ing emotional state yourself (2008, p. 517). Contagion and distress are ruled

    out as mere simulacra of empathy, precisely because these arepersonaland

    responsiveexperiencesnotanothers experience.

    An Example

    In neurocognitive psychology, mirror neuron activation is often read as acontamination or contagion response. According to Scheler (1913), conta-

    gion is a discrete, personal, reactive phenomenon that does not presuppose

    any sort of knowledge of the joy which others feel (p. 15), sometimes happen-

    ing subconsciously, beyond awareness, in the sense that we get into these

    states without realizing that this is how this comes about (Scheler, 1913,

    pp. 16/17). Furthermore, during contagion, there is nothing in the mournful

    feeling itself to point to its origin; only by inference from causal consideration

    does it become clear where it came from. That is, contagion can only become

    a form of interpersonal understanding if one infers from ones personal

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    9/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 159

    reaction that the other person is probably having a similar experience (i.e.,

    projects the contaminated experience onto the empathee), as implicit sim-

    ulation theories propose.Contagion researchers commonly back up their empathy theories with

    cross-species studies of emotional contagion, social imitation, and the work

    of audiovisuomotor neurons/mirror neurons (van Baaren et al., 2009; Bou-

    langer & Lanon, 2006; Decety & Jackson, 2006, 2004; Dinstein, Thomas,

    Behrmann & Heeger, 2008; Gallese, 2003; Goldman, 2006; Hateld et al.,

    2009; Preston & Waal, 2002). In short, researchers experimenting on

    macaque monkeys have found that some neurons are active both when

    performing a goal-directed action, and when observing it being performedby another monkey or person. They called these mirror, or audiovisuomo-

    tor, neurons. The activation of these neurons is hypothesised to underpin a

    form of social understanding (implicit simulation theories). This illustrates

    the contamination-as-knowing hypothesis that we have suggested as an

    example of a sympathetic understanding.

    On the other hand, in phenomenologically-informed research areas,

    the neurobiological and behavioural evidence is often interpreted in a

    coupling-as-knowingsense (Depraz, 2008, 2001; Gallagher, 2007; Thompson,

    2001). The diffference between the neurocognitive contamination-as-knowing

    interpretation and the neurophenomenological coupling-as-knowingreading

    of the (sometimes same) evidence is irreconcilable; they cannot both be

    accepted to explain the same evidence. One excludes the other.

    The term coupling originated from Humberto Maturanas biological

    research (1975) on autopoiesis (theoretical description of the inter-

    relationships between living beings and the environment), currently most

    often associated with his student, Francisco Varela and his neurophenom-

    enological approach to psychology. Coupling is a self-other linkage occur-ring at a biological cellular level. It is a pre-reexive, permanently dynamic

    and co-generative self-other link. For him, both environment and organ-

    isms are said to be constantly changing and co-determining each other,

    even at a cellular level. This theory is sometimes criticized for its solipsism,

    though given the intrinsic intersubjective meaning of coupling, this criti-

    cism is perhaps a misinterpretation. Claiming that the observer and

    Steins approach is phenomenological and descriptivenot explanatory. She does not

    address the whys, the genesis or psychological mechanisms behind the experience of empa-

    thy. For these, we must turn elsewhere.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    10/35

    160 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    observed change one another at such a primordial level of analysis is not an

    elegy to solipsism, it is not a defence that the world is nothing but a subjec-

    tivity inside ones mind.Rather, it is accepting that the world is intersubjectively constructed, in

    the more Heideggerian sense of being-in-the-world. This view does not

    obliterate or clash with the premise that there is a world out there to be

    perceived and experienced. Subject and object are still two diffferent enti-

    ties, despite their mutual inuences upon each other. Coupling is not merg-

    ing, or a dissolution of self and other identities as some tend to suggest (e.g.,

    Finlay, 2005). It is simply an interaction occurring at a biological level. Gal-

    lagher (2007, p. 356) gives a good example of this coupling mechanism:

    If we think of perception as an enactive process (e.g., Hurley, 1998; No,

    2004)as involving sensory-motor skills, rather than as just sensory input/

    processing; as an active, skilful, embodied engagement with the world rather

    than the passive reception of information from the environmentthen it

    may be more appropriate to think of the resonance processes as part of the

    structure of the perceptual process when perception is of the action of conspe-

    cics. Fogassi and Gallese, despite their simulationist interpretation, put this

    point clearly: perception, far from being just the nal outcome of sensory inte-gration, is the result of sensorimotor coupling (2002, p. 27). Mirror activation,

    on this interpretation, is not the initiation of simulation, it is part of a direct

    intersubjective perception of what the other is doing.

    Gallagher does not dissociate the mirror neuron activation from empathic

    experiences; he reads it as a sign of the phenomenon of coupling; and asso-

    ciates it with the meaning of direct perception. For instance, you are seeing

    your friends happiness, rather than feeling happy yourself, while listening

    to the news. This illustrates the coupling-as-knowing interpretation.Through coupling, the empathizers experience is composed of 1) a percep-

    tive side; 2) a self-felt resonant personal side (inclusively, mirror neuron

    activation). For him, mirror neuron activation is part of the empathic per-

    ceptive act; but it is not a contamination emotional reaction as this phe-

    nomenon is dened. Rather, it is a response insofar as a perception can be

    conceptualized as a response (to the existence of an object in the environ-

    ment). This is a radically diffferent interpretation of the mirror neuron acti-

    vation; and one which does not involve an inferential act, nor an emotionalcontagion reaction, for the understanding to happen, as with the contami-

    k Th

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    11/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 161

    theories are illustrated in Figure 10. Coupling-as-knowing(intersubjective

    empathic direct understanding experience) is not to be confused with

    the contamination-as-knowingtheory (a personal response, an experiencewhich is no longer, or never was, anothers, and that is subsequently taken

    for anothers via an additional act).

    From the typical neurocognitive viewpoint, empathic understandings

    are a step-by-step experience with each step (the cells identied in the

    Neurocognitive Perspective: contamination-as-knowing column) follow-

    ing upon the contamination and/or mimicry response. This means that

    peoples social understandings are seen are the result of a prior sympathetic

    (Scheler, 1913) response; they are always purely subjective experiencesderived from a personal afffective reaction.

    Figure 1: Comparison between the neurocognitive and the neuro-

    h l l l f h k

    Neurocognitive perspective:

    contamination-as-knowing

    Foreign experience

    Perception of external cues

    Imitation and contagion-as-

    contamination responses

    Simulation of an experience

    Self-other diffferentiation

    Inferential knowledge of the

    foreign experience

    Neurophenomenological

    perspective:

    coupling-as-knowing

    Foreign experience

    Direct awareness of the foreign

    experience via an intersubjective

    coupling experience (perceiving

    and contagion-as-coupling)

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    12/35

    162 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    On the other hand, neurophenomenology proposes that empathy is a

    direct, experiential, non-mediated, intersubjective understandingthat is

    not ttingly conceived as a plain afffective sympathetic response, nor anintellectual or inferential or projective knowing. It is rather an intersubjec-

    tive experience, in terms of process andin terms of experiential qualities.

    Empathy is to experience anothers experience at once, and know that it is

    anothers experience, simultaneously, as part of the same act. This is con-

    gruent with Steins position.

    Empathy as an Intersubjective Process

    To introduce what Stein means by empathy, we will begin by clarifying theepistemological assumptions behind her reasoning, which are drawn from

    the rst phases of Husserls phenomenology (Gurmin, 2007; Macintyre,

    2006/2007).

    The rst of these is that people are embodied and minded, and embed-

    ded in the world. Secondly, the world is objectively out there to be per-

    ceived, in the sense that it is not merely a subjective representation inside

    the mind. Thirdly, people relate to the world by means of an intentional

    act of consciousness. This intentional act is what brings the world andits objects into consciousness, as phenomena. Consciousness is always

    intentionalit connects a self to an object, in consciousnessand it is

    always relationalin the sense that it places a self and an object in relation

    to one another, by means of an intentional act. Fourthly, phenomena bear

    in themselves essential qualities of the given world (object). Finally, it is

    held that through phenomenology it is possible to inspect these phenom-

    ena and identify the worlds essential qualities.

    For Stein (p. 6; p. 21), empathy is an intentional act in this phenomeno-

    logical sense. However, it is a very particular kind of intentional act, because

    its object is the experience of another. It is generally a core assumption that

    empathy is about our experience of another. This is referred to in the litera-

    ture as the alterity, othernessorforeignquality of an experience. For Stein,

    empathy deals with the givenness, to oneself, of this foreign experience;

    and it is through empathy that foreign experience is comprehended ( p. 6).

    Steins understanding of empathy difffers from some contemporary deni-

    tions because she explicitly denes empathy as a way of knowing, rather

    than as a response to the foreign experience (after Batson, 2009), andin terms of her description of the way this knowledge comes about. In

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    13/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 163

    particular, for her, empathy is a direct givenness, as opposed to the indi-

    rect inference (sympathetic and intellectual understandings) favoured by

    some authors.Steins conception of empathy always involves at least two perspectives,

    self and other. Thus, psychologically speaking, empathy can be said to

    be an interpersonal process (and intersubjective in the phenomenological

    sense outlined above). There is always the empathizer, relating to the

    empathized (even given the case of empathizing with oneself ).

    On the other hand, in the models of empathy proposed by her predeces-

    sor, Lipps, and in implicit simulation theories, a kind of merging of empa-

    thizer and empathized is hypothesisedone during which self and otherbecome one.

    Stein rejects the idea that empathy is the experience of oneness with

    another. For Stein, Lipps view of empathy describes a kind of inner par-

    ticipation in others experiences (p. 12), which is only complete when there

    is no longer a distinction between oneself and the other. For Lipps, the ulti-

    mate level of empathy is a unity between self and other, captured by a feel-

    ing of oneness (p. 16). Lipps explains this with a theory of imitation, which

    resonates with contemporary ideas about contagion and mirroring (e.g.

    Hateld et al., 2009), but is distinct from empathy as Stein understands it.

    Perhaps as a consequence of Lipps work, we nd a number of recent

    authors asserting that empathy is, or involves, a lack of self-other distinc-

    tion (Preston & Waal, 2002, p. 4, tab. 2), or a total identication without

    discrimination between ones feelings and those of the other (Decety &

    Jackson, 2004, p. 75); or a merging-with, where subject and object function

    as an unique body (Finlay, 2005); or a feeling of at-oneness (Davis, C., 1990,

    p. 709), or a connection that temporarily unites the separate social entities

    of self and other (Davis, M., 2009).For Stein, empathy is not the feeling of oneness (p. 17). Empathy as this

    oneness, entanglement (Decety & Jackson, 2006, p. 56), fusion, or confu-

    sion, is, for Stein, an impossible position, simply because what my body is

    doing to my body and the foreign body is doing to the foreign body would then

    remain completely obscure (p. 16). We would further argue that this degree

    of perceptual and embodied confusion is simply not a phenomenological

    Despite Steins clarity on this, she is still portrayed by White (1997) and C. Davis (1990) as

    supporting the notion of empathy-as-oneness.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    14/35

    164 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    feature of peoples experiences of empathy. It lacks persuasive face validity.

    As Gallagher (2007, p. 359) points out:

    At the phenomenological level, when I see the others action or gesture, I see

    (I directly perceive) [original italics] the meaning in the action or gesture. I see

    the joy or I see the anger, or I see the intention in the face or in the posture or

    in the gesture or action of the other. I see it. I do not have to simulate it. And I

    immediately see that it is their action, gesture, emotion, or intention, and it is

    extremely rare that I would be in a position to confuse it with my own.

    Lipps concept of empathy implies a blurring of ones self-identity with

    anothers, in a manner which is not consistent with most peoples experi-

    ences. Indeed, in a clinical sense, this degree of fusion is usually seen as

    either infantile or pathological. For example:

    From object relations theory to transpersonal psychology, there is a presump-

    tion that the newborn experiences the world in a preegoic fusion with the

    primary caregiver and the world at large. (. . .) There may be similar empathic

    fusion in adults who have unusually permeable boundaries and a symbiotic

    relational style (see Johnson, 1994). In conventional diagnostic formulations,this may occur with some regularity in Borderline or Dependent personality

    disorders. The symbiotic character style may know the other by introjecting,

    or swallowing whole, the others experience without digesting the experience

    so as to understand or appreciate it as the others. (Hart, 1999, p. 113/114)

    For Stein, empathy involves a self-object connection, not a self-object

    fusion. This is perhaps more in line with Heideggers mitsein(being with),

    than with Lipps Einfhlung. Stein explicitly denies that empathy is a

    fusionor even an analogical feeling of self-other similarity (p. 87). Hence,even though we might even feel something which, though weaker in degree,

    is not altogether unlike them (Hateld et al., 2009, p. 20), it is not this feeling

    that should be seen as empathic in nature.

    To summarise then, for Stein, empathy is neither a reactionto anothers

    experience (neither contagion, nor imitation, nor sympathy); nor any form

    of intellectually-reasonedknowledge about anothers experience (neither infer-

    ence, nor projection, nor fantasy, nor analogy, nor perspective-taking, nor

    memory), and it is not a mergingof selves or feeling ofoneness. In Figure 2,we have illustrated how Stein applies her phenomenologically-derived

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    15/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 165

    criteria (right column) to exclude a number of related concepts and pro-

    cesses as non-empathic phenomena. This list is not exhaustive, but it illus-

    trates the reasoning behind Steins derivation of the essence of empathy.

    For Stein, empathy is an interpersonal process lived as a direct coming-

    to-know anothers experience. Or, better, more in line with a contemporary

    phenomenological view, empathy is the intersubjectiveprocess of directly

    knowing the foreign experience.

    Figure 2: What Empathy is not: Steins logical path towards a pheno-

    menological denition of empathy

    Contagion

    Imitation

    Oneness

    Sympathy

    Identication

    Empathy

    isnot

    Analogy

    Projection

    Association

    Inference

    MemoryFantasy

    Simulation

    Perspective-taking

    EXCLUSION CRITERIA:

    I personal response

    I personal knowing

    Produced by intellectual

    activity

    Mediated

    Past intentional object

    Undiffferentiated,

    unconsious selfness and

    otherness

    Necessary similarity inexperiencing

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    16/35

    166 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    Three Levels of Empathy

    There are three levels to Steins understanding of empathy, which meritfurther exposition. The term levelwhich Stein employsmay be slightly

    misleading. There is not a strongly hierarchical element to her account.

    Stein notes that while one might usually progress throughthe levels (from

    rst, to second, to third) this is not always the case. As we will see, it is

    possible to imagine that one might move from level 1 to level 3 (p. 10, p. 70).

    For reasons which will become obvious, it is unlikely that Stein considered

    that someone could be said to be having an empathic experience if they

    had accessed only level 3, however.

    Each of the levels she describes has particular dening characteristics,but each is also a way of knowing anothers experience. That is, the three

    levels share one of empathys essential qualities: all are experiences which

    bring anothers experience to our awareness. This means that, in a way, we

    can look at these levels as diffferent kinds of empathic phenomena, or dif-

    ferentways intoempathy.

    We have attempted to label the three levels of Steins conception of

    empathy in ways which are reasonably clear and meaningful to the con-

    temporary reader. As we have named them, these levels are: 1. Directlyperceiving(the immediate perception of anothers present, minded, embod-

    ied, embedded, experience); 2. Experientially projecting(the non-intellec-

    tual experience of anothers unfolding experience); and 3. Interpretatively

    mentalizing(the higher-level recognition and interpretation of our knowl-

    edge of the others experience). In the following sub-sections, we expand

    upon each of them in a little more detail.

    Level 1: Direct Immediate Perceiving

    For Stein, empathy is a founding or fundamental act, which, in this level,

    has a status analogous to direct perception; that is, it is not a product of

    other deliberated, intellectual, or cognitive processes (Stein, 1917/1989, e.g.,

    p. 14; p. 20; p. 24; p. 27). Rather, it is the result of a perceptual act, which

    directly brings anothers experience into ones own awareness. This distin-

    guishes empathy from perspective-taking and simulation.

    For reference, in Steins (p. 10) thesis, these are: 1) the emergence of the experience; 2) the

    fullling explanation; and 3) the comprehensive objectication of the explain experience.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    17/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 167

    What it is that We Perceive [Anothers Experience]

    Direct perception is a special case of perception (a kind of an act of perceiv-

    ing sui generis , p. 11), because what is immediately perceived is the for-eign experience. That is, it is not a meaningless external cue, such as a

    gesture or a facial expression, into which some meaning is subsequently,

    imaginatively, and intellectually, infused. Even though we grasp the others

    experience with the same perceptual intention that we grasp a thing (Mous-

    takas, 1994, p. 94) there is a contrast between ordinary perceptive acts and

    empathic perception. The former bring concrete objects of the world

    (physical objects, closely wedded in appearances, Prinz, 2006, p. 434) to

    our awareness, but empathic perceptions bring us an experience in itsentire embodied and embedded form. In empathic perception, when we

    perceive an expressive gesture, the gesture andits meaning are given to us

    immediately and together.

    A key feature of empathic perception is that it involves our immediate

    knowledge of anothers present experience. It has the foreign experience

    for its intentional object. Empathy is an act of perception, and the object of

    that act is the embodied, embedded experience of another, as it is given in

    consciousness. This distinguishes empathy from some related phenomena,

    such as fantasy, or contagion.

    How we do this [Directly, Immediately, Non-Inferentially]

    Stein emphasises at the outset that empathy deals with grasping here-and-

    now (1917, p. 7). She stresses (p. 10) that empathy is always the primordial expe-

    rience (by which she means, immediate, here-and-now) of a non-primordial

    We understand this adjective, in Steins thesis, to mean here-and-now, Bournemark

    (2005, p. 124) translates it as original instead. Original accentuates a facet relative to theauthenticity or the source location. When Stein denes empathy as an act which is primor-

    dial as present experience though non-primordial in content (p. 10), it would be precise to

    infer that empathys content is originally located in the other (empathy being responsible

    for its subsequent givenness to the perceiver). However, when Stein discusses acts of mem-

    ory (p. 8), she highlights that memory deals with non-primordial phenomena. And, in

    memory, the source is the perceiver. Hence, the term primordial cannot be read as relative

    to the source location. To avoid this interpretation of primordial as meaning located in the

    self, we dene primordial as present, actual, and here-and-now. In this quote, then, we

    understand that Stein means that the empathic experience is happening in the now for the

    perceiver, but its content (foreign experience) is not happening in the nowit is anothers

    experience after all. Or, better, empathy is an intersubjective experience.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    18/35

    168 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    source (the experience of another). These two aspects both contribute

    to the nature of empathy: whilst the act, for the perceiver, occurs in the

    here-and-now; the content of this act is not happening in the here-and-now, for the perceiver. The perceived experience is not presently occurring

    to the perceiver, but to the perceived person. In this level, then, Stein

    is concerned with what happens when we directly perceive anothers expe-

    rience, as it unfolds in the present. This distinguishes empathy from mem-

    ory, and contagion.

    Stein refers to this possibility of perceiving the body and its experience

    as empathys con-primordiality (1917, p. 57), or double given-ness

    (p. 43)by which she means that seen, averted and interior sides aregiven to the perceiver at once. As Zahavi (2001) would add, experiences are

    not internal, they are not hidden in the head (p. 153)hence, co-perceiving

    anothers experience is a perceptive possibility. In phenomenology, expe-

    rience is perhaps best understood as a kind of convenient, psychological

    shorthand for our relationship to the world. It is located betweenperson

    and world.

    In short, much like any ordinary perceptive act, empathy happens here-

    and-now, but specically to bring to our awareness the experience of

    another. In everyday language we might understand this sort of perception

    in terms of having a sense, an intuitive knowledge, or a feeling about

    anothers experience. Steins preference is simply to say that we are able to

    see the foreign experience, as it happens.

    Example

    Steins model of empathic perception, then, has a gestalt quality. She calls

    this its con-primordiality. Stein uses a spatial metaphor to unpack this,

    imagining that empathic perception might be understood by analogy withvisuo-spatial perception. Hence, here-and-now, in the present ongoing

    moment, she suggests that it is as if the averted and interior sides of a spa-

    tial thing are co-given with its seen sides. In short, the whole thing is seen

    (1917, p. 57)the con-primordial concept.

    Imagine that you perceive a chair. When you perceive it, you see the

    presenting sides of the chair (those which face you), and you see the sur-

    rounding area (the context). You would not literally see the back of the

    chair (averted sides) or its underlying structure (interior sides), of course,

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    19/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 169

    but the chair is still perceptively given to you in its wholeness (i.e. as a com-

    posite of its seen and averted sides andits structure). Under normal condi-

    tions we do not perceive a fragmentary chair, composed only of that whichis literally accessible to our gaze.

    In empathy, this analogy means that one simultaneously perceives at the

    same time (co-perceives) the others outward, expressive, visible (seen

    sides) and non-visible behaviour (averted sides), as well as the others expe-

    rience (structure). This is what we mean when we say that for Stein the

    given-ness of empathic perception is direct. In empathy, we directly co-

    perceive body-and-mind, together, at once, in its context. We directly per-

    ceive anothers minded, embodied, embedded, expressive experience. Wehave access to this gestalt other through empathic perceptive acts.

    How Might this be Understood?

    As we have seen, then, Stein views the givenness of anothers experience

    as a core feature of empathy, and she wishes to emphasise that there is a

    direct and unmediated quality to this. In her own text, Stein calls this level,

    the emergence of the experience (1917, p. 10). This might suggest that she

    sees empathic experience as a process, and one which begins at this level,

    but this is not necessarily the case. Stein emphasises that in a concrete case

    people do not always go through all levels (1917, p. 10), and that ones

    empathic lived experience may be carried out in a manner diffferent from

    her own order of presentation (p. 14/15; p. 70; see also Depraz, 2001 for a

    similar formulation).

    Steins approach is phenomenological, and not explanatory. However,

    in the most recent phenomenological examination of empathys levels,

    Depraz (2008, p. 172), relates this direct perception to Paarung (after Hus-

    serl), or coupling (after Maturanas acoplamiento, 1975). Similarly, Zahavi(2007; 2001) sees direct perception as the most fundamental mechanism

    underlying our daily interpersonal relationships. Empathy, he argues,

    makes people intelligible to each other in a direct, immediate manner, and

    is the core form of interpersonal knowledge. But even from a completely

    diffferent background, relative to the study of neurosciences and articial

    intelligence, a similar claim can be found: there is a kind of mind reading

    which is in a certain sense purely perceptual and unaided by any verbal

    theoretical elements (Rockwell, 2007, p. 2).

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    20/35

    170 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    Level 2: Experientially Projecting

    Why Empathy is a Form of ProjectingStein herself describes this level as the fullling explication (1917, p. 10).

    The reason for this is discussed below. We have chosen to emphasize

    instead the importance of another feature of Steins perspective for this

    level: the sense of empathy as involving a kind of transposal or projection

    of the self.

    Through an examination of Steins step-by-step elimination of what

    empathy is not, we can conclude that, for her, empathic projections:

    1) areexperienced(not reasoned, or imagined, or simulated, such as in per-spective-taking; 1917, p. 14); 2) are a means of accessing genuinely foreign

    experiences(not hypothetical, probable, p. 27; nor conjured, or projected,

    experiences, p. 20); and 3) this access is direct(not based in any kind of

    past knowledge, such as the empathizers past experiences, p. 27) and

    immediate.

    In more common usage, projection is understood as an intellectual pro-

    cess, based on pre-acquired knowledge and concrete evidence-based rea-

    soning; and does not necessarily happen here-and-now. In contrast, Steins

    projection is a very particular kind of projection. It is an experiential, non-

    intellectual, and intuitive (1917, p. 20) kind of projection. This notion is

    much closer to Lipps understanding of empathy, though it can be distin-

    guished from contemporary neuropsychological theories because this is

    still a direct non-simulative experience that is given as anothers. That is,

    the experienced projection is not an intellectual simulation, and is imme-

    diately co-perceived as foreign.

    An ExampleImagine that we are watching a novice acrobat balancing on a wire. At rst,

    we directly see his/her fear of heights (direct perception level). We may

    also experience this fear to some degree, but for that experience to be an

    Thompson (2001) offfers a similar reading by explaining this level as a kind of projection.

    This supports our reading, even though, explicitly, in her text, Stein never connects empathic

    projections, discussed at length, with the second level as put forward in the beginning of the

    dissertation. Though, after careful analysis and consideration, this is the most reasonableand probable reading of her ideas for this level.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    21/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 171

    empathic one, the fright could not be our own personal fear (e.g. contagion),

    or an imagined probable fright (a simulated or remembered one), or a fear

    forthe safety of the acrobat (Schelers fellow-feeling, or sympathy). Instead,it would have to be the acrobats fright, given to us via experiential projec-

    tion. As we observe the acrobat, we may project into the objects experi-

    ence, turning with it towards the wire and the depths below. At such a

    point we are empathically given an experience of the acrobats own fear.

    Critically, we experience it, not in the fullest sense (the sense with which

    we might experience our ownfear, for our own safety), but only partially

    as the acrobatsfear. The fright, for the empathising observer, is non-pri-

    mordial; it is not happening in the here-and-now. It is anothersandhence distinct from contagion, as the latter is usually dened. After all, it is

    not the empathiser who is balancing on the wire and experiencing fear

    he/she is just watching the acrobat and having an empathic experience.

    As Stein puts it, I am not one with the acrobat, but only at him. I do not

    actually go through his emotions but quasi (1917, p. 16).

    In the previous section, we noted that empathic perception has the

    others experience for its intentional object (e.g. the acrobats fear). For

    empathicprojection, the intentional object shiftsand we become focused

    on the intentional object which is at the center of the othersexperience

    (e.g. the high wire, the looming depths below). In both empathic projec-

    tions and empathic perceptions, however, subject and object are not one,

    because they are not having the very same single experience. The otherness

    of the experience, implicitly a self-other diffferentiation, is one of empathys

    dening attributes. The observer does not really feel any threat for him

    or herself (only quasi fear), but rather gains access to the acrobats fear

    by feeling it with him/her. Metaphorically speaking, it is a second-person

    fear, where we are with the other, experiencing the others extant ongoingstate, almost as if we were having the experience ourselves, but aware

    that we are not. In our example, for the empathising observer, the fear is

    not happening here-and-now, and nor is the act of wire walking. The

    experience and content are anothers, and yet we are withthe other, expe-

    riencing it. Hence, Stein claims that this level exhibits the non-primordial

    parallel to the having of the experience (1917, p. 10).

    It is important to note that, for Stein, empathic experiences can be about

    sensations just as easily as they can be about emotions. This makes sense

    when we think about the features of her approach, but it is a dimension of

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    22/35

    172 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    empathy which is not always included in contemporary writing. In Steins

    description, the movement from perception to projection is identical,

    regardless of whether the observed experience is an emotion or a sensa-tion; a feeling into and then a feeling with. This idea is explored in her

    thesis as sensual empathy (1917, p. 58/60).

    Why Stein Calls this the Fullling Explication

    Stein uses the term self-transposal. This delineation is applied in some con-

    temporary work, too, such as when Depraz (2001) describes an equivalent

    stage as being about a spontaneous, highly embodied, imaginative and kin-

    aesthetic self-transposal to anothers experience. In Stein, this concept isperhaps closer to the notion of a sensing-in, a feeling-at, a feeling with

    (p. 58)denitely not a feeling for (sympathy); or an imagined feeling, as

    perspective-taking and simulation are usually conceived. It is an intersub-

    jective experience all along.

    From this point, it is easier to see why this second level might be referred

    to as the fullling explication. Returning to the novice acrobats fear of

    heights, recall that, initially, one empathically perceived the acrobats fear.

    However, it is only through projectingintothis experience, that one is able

    to explore this foreign experience, and to inspect its many sides. For

    instance, one might acknowledge that the acrobat is looking beyond the

    wire, down into the void below. This happens in an exploratory lived man-

    ner, unfolding in the present with the foreign experience. Through this act,

    other sides of the foreign experience are revealed, such as acknowledging

    the trembling of the wire or the absence of a safety net. Consequently,

    one fulls (the term adopted by Stein) ones awareness of the others

    experienceor, at least, ones awareness is enriched. The act is an explica-

    tion because it reveals in more detail and depth that which was initiallyperceived as merely fear.

    It seems to us that referring to this as an imaginative projection, as

    Depraz (2001) and Thompson (2001) have done, falls short of this levels

    experiential, present-tense, intuitive, sensing-in essence. Imagination may

    suggest that Steins view is much closer to intellectual conjecture, than it is;

    as Stein points out, this experience is not about the feeling of ones own

    experience via anothers screen (p. 20). It is about how we come to feel the

    experience of another.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    23/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 173

    Level 3: Interpretatively Mentalizing

    Since empathy is often represented in psychology as partly, or wholly, anintellectualized ability, this level is probably the aspect of Steins account

    which seem most familiar to a contemporary readership. Thompson (2001)

    claims that, in this level, the experience faces me again, but now in a clari-

    ed or explicated way (p. 16) and this level is usually seen as following on

    from the explicative, experiential level. However, for us, this is not its most

    distinguishing characteristic. What is fundamental, and fundamentally dif-

    ferent, is that, for the rst time, empathy includes a clearly intellectual

    facet, responsible for its more intellectual comprehensibility. Thus, with

    this level, Stein describes the point at which the interpersonal process ofempathic knowing reaches its inevitable conclusionthis is where we

    actively interpret our directly perceived feeling-in of the others experi-

    ence, and it becomes more explicitly and linguistically accessible to us as

    knowledge. Simultaneously, then, this is the point at which the process

    more clearly resembles a non-direct ways of knowing the foreign experi-

    ence, though still distinguishable because its intentional object is a directly

    given foreign experience (not a deduced, inferred one).

    What is Mentalized (The Foreign Experience)

    Here, for the rst time, that which was directly intuitively given about the

    others experience (during direct perception and/or experiential projec-

    tion) is represented, in awareness, as a mental object. That is, the content

    of the intuition is mentalized, becoming, in awareness, an intellectual idea

    about the foreign experience. This is most transparent when Stein states

    that, at this level, empathy can be seen as an intuitive idea about anothers

    experience. Before this level, empathy is not an idea, or a representation,

    but intuition only (p. 20). But now we have a form of knowledge about the

    foreign experience, in the usual conception of the word knowledge.

    Through mentalizationthe making of an experience into a mental

    objectempathy becomes comprehension. The novel quality that we have

    emphasised in the naming of this level is that this act partly transforms the

    empathic experience into an intellectually intelligible one. More precisely,

    during this level, the empathizer is nally given the foreign experience

    in an intelligible, partly interpreted, manner. Consequently, the foreign

    experience becomes once more, as it was during direct perception, theintentional object of the empathic actwith the diffference here that

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    24/35

    174 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    now the others experience is not the target of an intuitive act, but of a

    mentalizingone.

    Example

    To extend the example of the acrobat, recall that, initially, the acrobats

    fear was directly perceived (rst level). Then, the perceiver projected into

    it, to explore some of its non-perceptively given sides (second level), say,

    the escalating intensity of the acrobats fear. Then, nally, the perceiver

    gives to the intuition an intellectual formwhich might hypothetically

    mean the empathizer saying to him/herself that the acrobat is experienc-

    ing something that could be called fear of falling (third level). In thisintellectual manner, the acrobats experience becomes an intelligibly inter-

    pretedthus partly, or fully, comprehended; the empathic experience

    completed. Hence, it is only through this level that empathy is, as previ-

    ously noted, a more intellectual act through which the foreign experience

    is comprehended (p. 6).

    These three aspects (i.e. occurring after experiential projection; requir-

    ing the making of the experience into a mental object; and being an

    interpretative activity) explain the name given by Stein to this level: com-

    prehensive objectication of the experience (p. 10).

    The Importance of the Mentalization Level

    For Stein, the empathic experience can only be complete with the intellec-

    tual interpretative act (representation is the term she adopts), which is

    simply the giving of an intellectual meaning to an intuition. More than

    that, she even tells us that the empathic representation is the only fullment

    possible (p. 57).

    In order to understand the meaning behind this claim, we must inspectthe term fullment. We have used it in relation to the second level,

    and translated it in terms of the enrichment and revelation of the non-

    perceptively given aspects of the others experience. We have also noted

    that Steins sees the third level as the fruition and end of the empathic pro-

    cess. Metaphorically-speaking, we might imagine a river owing through

    the earth, exploring the surroundings as it goes. This would be the experi-

    ential fullment. At the point where the river reaches the ocean, in a sense,

    it ceases to be a riverbut by ceasing to be, its path is complete. This would

    be the representational act. When Stein claims that the empathic act can

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    25/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 175

    only be completed by establishing an intellectual representation, it as

    though the empathic act arrives at its destination, and in doing so, the pro-

    cess of knowing is transformed, and becomes something else.

    Summary of Steins Approach

    Steins phenomenological equation includes the self, the intentional act

    (empathy) and its object (foreign experience). With this equation, Stein is

    able to detect three kinds of empathic phenomena: direct perception;

    experiential projection; and interpretative mentalization. And although

    these ways into empathy are about the knowing of the foreign experience,it is only the latter (mentalization) that can be properly qualied as a form

    of intellectual knowledge. The rst two are intuitive, not ideational.

    In short, the rst level, direct perception, is about the direct, non-medi-

    ated (e.g. by expressive behaviour or aprioristic knowledge) co-givenness

    of another persons present embodied, embedded, minded experience.

    Here, one immediately sees the foreign experience. The second level,

    experiential projection, is about exploring, as if with the other person, their

    unfolding experience. Here, one feels aspects of the foreign experience,some of which may not have been perceived at level 1. Finally, in the third

    level, interpretative mentalization, empathy is transformed into an intel-

    lectual, interpretative act. During this level, one recognises and represents

    the others experience by forming an intellectual interpretation of what

    was given of it. And, since the intentional object of this act is still an intui-

    tively directly given foreign experience, then, although of an intellectual

    nature, this is still an empathic act. This act completes the empathic experi-

    ence. Although organized in a sequential manner, people may perhaps

    enter into empathy at any of these levels, as they may even skip a few (p. 10,

    p. 70)though level 3, alone, cannot count as an empathic experience. It

    must always be an interpretation of either level 1, 2, or both.

    These levels share some essential characteristics that distinguish them

    from non-empathic acts of consciousness. First, the act of empathizing is

    immediate, it is here and now experience (p. 7). Secondly, it is an inten-

    tional act of consciousness. Thirdly, its intentional object is foreign (the

    foreign experience, or the foreign intentional object). Fourthly, this experi-

    ence is, to a great extent, direct, non-intellectual and non-mediated. Fifthly,empathy is specically about the knowing of anothers experience. Finally,

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    26/35

    176 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    what is given through empathy is always a second-person experience. It is

    not an authentic personal experience. This is what essentially denes

    empathy as a phenomenon across the three levels: empathy is the coming-to-know anothers experience.

    Discussion

    The direct implication of the nature of empathy is that selfness and other-

    ness are never absent or confused. Rather, the otherness of the foreign

    experience is permanently co-given with the empathizers experience, even

    if only in the background of experiencing. Hence, self and other are alwaystwo beings with diffferent experiences and identities, even while relating

    empathically: both experiences are actually diffferent in themselves (Stein,

    1917, p. 23).

    It is in this givenness of otherness that Steins empathy becomes more

    clearly an intersubjective experience. For her, the empathic act can be

    understood as intersubjective in nature, because it has two sides, it has two

    essences (p. 19): 1) the foreign experience; and 2) ones own experience.

    Consequently, it is fundamental in any interpersonal encounter, it acts asthe bases of intersubjective experience (p. 64) because it is how human

    beings comprehend the psychic life of their fellows (p. 11)it is even seen as

    a key to ones individuality. Empathy is then a core aspect of ones lived

    daily experience, both in an individual and in an interpersonal sense. It

    allows for a mutual interpersonal understanding.

    Accepting this, the problem of how it is possible to perceive other minds

    becomes one of those pseudo problems (Zahavi, 2001, p. 155). Reference to

    the other is already inherent to ones being-in-the-world. For Stein, self-

    other similarity is indeed enabled by empathy, but it is a non-empathic

    phenomenon. It is a only its consequence, in the sense that, before the

    apprehension of similarity takes place, the other must rst have been

    directly given to oneself. That is, empathy allows for the understanding of

    oneself as a living body among many other living bodies (p. 88).

    Correspondence with Psychotherapeutic Theories

    Stein describes three types of empathic experiences, though none of them

    are commonly called empathy in the mainstream psychology literature.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    27/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 177

    There are a few exceptions in the humanistic, existentialist and psycho-

    dynamic approaches to psychotherapy, however (e.g., Bozarth, 2009; Geist,

    2009; Rogers, 1957/2007; Zepf & Hartmann, 2008). There is no other areawhich is so fundamentally concerned with other peoples genuine experi-

    ences as psychotherapy. And, in contrast with neurocognitive and develop-

    mental psychology, some humanistic and psychodynamic approaches to

    psychotherapy more commonly offfer a view of empathy much closer to

    Steins conception.

    In this particular Steinian sense, empathic understandings are con-

    ceived as a key aspect of the therapeutic process. The therapists claims can

    be received by the client as correct or incorrect, but, through the continu-ous maintenance of an empathic rapport, the client develops a sense of

    realness, an awareness of being alive, personally present, and invested (Geist,

    2009, p. 64) to the point when the accuracy of the intervention is less impor-

    tant (with both right or wrong commentaries serving as an invitation for

    exploration, and each responsible for personal growth).

    For example, Rogers (Bozarth, 2009, p. 103, cf. Rogers, 1959, p. 210) pro-

    poses that experiencing an accurate, empathic understanding of the clients

    awareness of his own experience is a necessary condition for the success of

    therapy. For him, empathy is sensing, perceiving (Steins level 1) and as if

    experiencing (Steins quasi quality of level 2) the clients experience and

    meaning:

    The state of empathy, or being empathic, is to perceive the internal frame of

    reference of another with accuracy, and with the emotional components and

    meanings that pertain thereto, as if one were the other person, but without

    losing the as if condition.

    For Rogers, empathy is the perceptive ability of knowing anothers experi-

    ential meaning; and it involves an experiential resonance side that is never

    to be confused with a genuinely personal experience. Barrett-Lennards

    (1981) description of empathy also seems to t with Steins views on inter-

    subjectivity: It [empathy] is an experiencing of the consciousness behind

    anothers outward communication, but with continuous awareness that this

    consciousness is originating and proceeding in the other. (p. 92). A core

    aspect of Barrett-Lennards understanding of empathy is precisely this

    direct immediate relationship between beings. For Freud, this experience

    corresponds perhaps to a temporary, partial, identication mechanism,

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    28/35

    178 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    used to get into anothers feelings without being directly implicated; and a

    mechanism helpful for the psychoanalysts comprehension of what is felt

    as foreign in the self of another person (e.g., Boulanger & Lanon, 2006;Zepf & Hartmann, 2008). Similarly, for Reik (1948; Arnold, 2006), psycho-

    analytic listening involves an intuitive detection of the clients experiential

    meanings, a perceiving of the tip of the iceberg of anothers initially

    unknown psychic dynamics. From these perspectives, as with phenome-

    nology, empathy fosters a moment-to-moment understanding of that eluding

    otherness, that foreign, hence strange and perhaps estranged, experience.

    A moment-to-moment awareness, from these perspectives, involves an

    experiential resonation, an emotional (though the emotional adjectivefalls shorts of the meaning of experiential) and personal side, where the

    impressions aroused in the individual are experienced as belonging to an

    object (Zepf & Hartmann, 2008, p. 749), the location of clients and thera-

    pists experiences are clearly diffferentiated, their belongingness clearly

    given to the therapist throughout the empathic experience.

    Thus, in the light of Steins work and these approaches, there is no need

    to become an emotional stone-therapist, or to introduce a distance between

    subject and object, as some have proposed (e.g., in the experience of empa-

    thy, individuals must be able to disentangle themselves from others. This

    distance is a key characteristic in psychotherapy, Decety & Jackson, 2006,

    p. 56). Since there is no merging to begin with, any defusing or distancing

    is irrelevant.

    To conclude, Steins writings, thorough and detailed, can inform the

    research, practice and teaching of psychotherapy, by illuminating empa-

    thys lived experience, from the empathees side, one which is not com-

    monly studied in this area (Greenberg et al., 2001).

    Limits and Deception in Empathy

    Stein answers to the question of authenticity by offfering that it is possible

    to experientially distinguish between fake, or empty (p. 62; p. 77) expres-

    sions; and genuine ones. Faking is in itself an experience, and one which is

    empathically given to the empathizer as an empty one, we then generally

    assume that empathy is about the givenness of anothers genuine present

    experience.

    However the empathic act is not free from error. Empathic experiencesare shaped by the empathizers life-long habits of intuiting and thinking

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    29/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 179

    (p. 62). That is, the intuitive and the interpretative acts are subjected to

    habits, hence permeable to the empathizers past experiences and knowl-

    edge, more vulnerable to the inuence of idiographic perspectives, precon-ceptions, or habits. Although these habits are not necessarily responsible

    for inaccurate knowing (for example, they may just condition the selective-

    ness of the empathizers attention), through them, empathy becomes sus-

    ceptible to inaccurate or deceptive knowledge.

    This potential inaccuracy is not restricted to empathic acts. Indeed, for

    Stein, non-empathic acts more frequently generate deceptive knowledge.

    For example, if the interpretation draws upon ones similar past experi-

    ences (analogy) there is a heightened risk of deception: we come to falseconclusions if we empathically take our own individual characteristics as a

    basis (p. 87).

    Stein wishes to emphasize that the odds of inaccuracy can be reduced by

    combining empathic acts and inferential, intellectual acts. For example,

    the perceiver wonders whether pain (p. 85) is a good interpretation of the

    others experience, and looks elsewhere for intellectual conrmation (as

    offfered by external cues such as expressive behaviour and the context of

    the experience). It is the content of the intuitive act that requires interpre-

    tation, but it is the interpretation itself (level 3) that is usually prone to

    evaluations of accuracy or falsity. This combination of acts helps us in

    accurately interpreting equivocal expressions (p. 85).

    Empathy does not necessarily reveal to oneself the foreign experience in

    its entireness, as there is perhaps as well a sphere of absolute privacy

    (Scheler, 1913, p. 10). Both self and other are never perceived as complete.

    To use Steins expression, each is always absently available (Stein, p. 19),

    to oneself and to another. Nevertheless, to only be given a partial aspect of

    anothers experience does not make our access less direct, less experiential,less accurate, or less empathic: there is so to speak more to the mind of the

    other than what we are grasping, but this does not make our understanding

    non-experiential (Zahavi, 2008, p. 520).

    As Barrett-Lennard (1981, p. 92) noted, empathic understandings are

    about the knowing of at least those aspects of his awareness that are most

    important to him at the moment. In fact, it is exactly this inaccessibility, this

    limit, which I can experience (cf. Husserl, 1973a, p. 144). And when I do have an

    authentic experience of another subject, I am exactly experiencing that the

    other eludes me (Zahavi, 2001, p. 153). There is then a limit to that which

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    30/35

    180 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    can be accessed through empathy. Imagine that the acrobat was fearful,

    but also thrilled with the performances suspense. By noticing only the fear,

    the observer is still having an experience that is suitably described as anempathic experience.

    In conclusion, empathic knowing can be inaccurately interpreted and

    subjected to intuiting habits; and it does not necessarily reveal to the

    empathizer all there is to know about the foreign experience. Despite this,

    accuracy can be enhanced by complementing consecutive empathic acts

    (moment-to-moment empathy) with non-empathic intellectual acts. They

    can be used in a complementary fashion, with the goal of correctly inter-

    preting that which was empathically experienced, but they are to be distin-guished by their nature.

    Conclusion

    Taken together, our argument suggests that conceptually, and in the light

    of the lived experience, there is a social intuitive understanding that is not

    properly explained by current empathy models. These models propose that

    empathy may be understood as if it were a case of perspective-taking, anal-ogy, sympathy, mimicking, contagion, and/or fusion. These are alternative

    forms of understanding that Stein does not accept as empathic, and their

    distinctive nature is part of the experience itself (Stein, 1917, p. 62). Further-

    more, many of these models seem to merge together several of the many

    phenomena which empathy has been claimed to be (Batson, 2009), or

    argue against each other (e.g., the feedback given to Preston & Waal, 2002)

    as if they were referring to one and the same phenomenon.

    For Stein, an empathic understanding is an experiential intuitive know-

    ing of someone elses present experience that is not lived as a personal,

    sympathetic or intellectual form of social understanding. This form of

    interpersonal understanding is a natural everyday form of relating with

    other people and their experiences. Recently there has been a revived interest

    in Steins phenomenological claims about the nature of empathy, principally

    in phenomenological and phenomenology-informed theories. For example,

    Deprazs (2001) empathy levels; Gallaghers (2007) situated cognition;

    Prinz (2006) perception of abstract content; and Zahavis (2008, 2001) non-

    simulative direct perceptive access all draw upon Stein.Then, the empathy eld would benet from some conceptual revision and

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    31/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 181

    that might deserve to be empirically investigated, rstly qualitatively, to

    gather evidence of its presence in peoples experiences of their social

    understandings; and then also from within experimental and neuropsy-chology paradigms, so that the underlying processes may be put to test. As

    Gurmin (2007), we propose that Steins phenomenological approach can

    offfer neurologists a comprehensive account of empathy that will aid them

    insofar as they relect on scientic explanations(p. 100), and that its impli-

    cations have the potential to extend some way beyond this.9

    ReferencesBachelor, A. (1988) How clients perceive therapist empathy: a content analysis of received

    empathy,Psychotherapy, 25, 2, 227240.

    Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., Hill, J. J., Raste, Y., & Plumb, I. (2001) The Reading the

    Mind in the Eyes TestRevised version: A study with normal adults, and adults with

    Asperger syndrome or high-functioning autism,Journal of Child Psychology and Psychia-

    try, 42, 241251.

    Barrett-Lennard, G. T. (1981) The empathy cycle: Renement of a nuclear concept,Journal of

    Counselling Psychology, 28, 2, 91100.

    Batson, C. D. (2009) These Things Called Empathy: Eight Related But Distinct Phenomena,In J. Decety & W. Ickes (Eds) The Social Neuroscience of Empathy, 1, 313, Cambridge:

    MIT press.

    Boulanger, C. & Lanon, C. (2006) Lempathie: rexions sur un concept. Discussion,

    Annales mdico-psychologiques, 164, 6, 497505.

    Bornemark, J. (2005) Alterity in the Philosophy of Edith Stein: Empathy and God, In

    H. R. Sepp & I. Copoeru (eds) Phenomenology 2005Selected Essays from Northern

    Europe, 4, pp. 121152.

    Bozarth, J. D. (2009) Rogerian Empathy in an Organismic Theory: A Way of Being, In Decety

    J. Editor & Ickes, W. Editor (Eds) The Social Neuroscience of Empathy, 1, 101112, Cam-

    bridge: MIT press.Darling, N. & Clarke, S. A. (2009) Seeing the Partner: A Video Recall Study of Emotional

    Behavior in Same- and Mixed-Sex Late Adolescent Romantic Couples, Journal of Youth

    and Adolescence, 38, 10151026.

    Davis, C. M. (1990) What is empathy and can empathy be taught?, Physical Therapy, 70,

    707711.

    Davis, M. H. (2009) Empathy, In Reis H. T. & Sprecher, S. (Eds), Encyclopaedia of Human

    Relationships, SAGE Publications, Inc, at . accessed 10 October 2009.

    Chapter three of Meneses (2011) followed on the layout and content of this paper and,

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    32/35

    182 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    Decety, J. & Jackson, P. I. (2006) A social neuroscience perspective on empathy, Current

    Directions in Psychological Science, 15, 2, 5458.

    Decety, J. & Jackson, P. I. (2004) The Functional Architecture of Human Empathy, Behav-ioral and Cognitive Neuroscience Reviews, 3, 2, 71100.

    Depraz, N. (2008) Rainbow of Emotions: at the crossroads of neurobiology and phenome-

    nology, Contemporary Philosophy Review, 41, 237259.

    Depraz, N. (2001) The Husserlian Theory of Intersubjectivity as Alterology: Emergent

    Theories and Wisdom Traditions in The Light of the Genetic Phenomenology, Journal of

    Consciousness Studies, 8, 57, 169178.

    Dinstein, I., Thomas, C., Behrmann, M., Heeger, D. J. (2008) A mirror up to nature, Current

    Biology, 18, 1, 1318.

    Duan, C. & Hill, C. E. (1996) The current state of empathy research, Journal of Counselling

    Psychology, 43, 3, 261274.Eisenberg, N. (2000) Emotion, Regulation, and moral development, Annual Reviews of

    Psychology, 51, 665697.

    Finlay, L. (2005) Reexive embodied empathy: a phenomenology of participant-researcher

    intersubjectivity, Methods Issue: The Humanistic Psychologist, 33(4), 271292.

    Gallagher, S. (2007) Simulation Trouble, Social Neuroscience, 2, 3, 353365.

    Gallese, V. (2003) The Roots of Empathy: The Shared Manifold Hypothesis and the Neural

    Basis of Intersubjectivity,Psychopathology, 36, 4, 171180.

    Geist, R. A. (2009) Empathic Understanding The Foundation of Self-Psychological Psycho-

    analysis, Self and Systems: Annals of the New York Academy Science, 1159, 6374.

    Gladstein (1983) How clients perceive therapist empathy: a content analysis of receivedempathy,Psychotherapy, 25, 2, 227-240.

    Goldman, A. I. (2006) Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of

    Mindreading.New York: Oxford University Press.

    Gurmin, H. (2007) Edith Stein and Tania Singer: A Comparison of Phenomenological and

    Neurological Approaches to the Problem of Empathy Maynooth Philosophical Papers,

    4, 99122.

    Hkansson, J. (2003) Exploring the phenomenon of Empathy, Ph.D dissertation, Department

    of Psychology, Stockholm University, http://www.emotionalcompetency.com/papers/

    empathydissertation.pdf, Accessed 6 August 2010.

    Hkansson, J. & Montgomery, H. (2003) Empathy as an Interpersonal Phenomenon, Journalof Social and Personal Relationships, 20, 3, 267284.

    Hall, J. A. & Mast, M. S. (2007) Sources of Accuracy in the Empathic Accuracy Paradigm,

    Emotion, 7, 2, 438446.

    Hancock, M. & Ickes, W. (1996) Empathic Accuracy: When does the Perceiver-Target Rela-

    tionship Make a Diffference?,Journal of Social and Personal Relationships, 13, 2, 179199.

    Hart, T. (1999) The renement of Empathy,Journal of Humanistic Psychology, 39, 111125.

    Hassenstab, J., Dziobek, I., Rogers, K., Wolf, O. T. & Convit, A. (2007) Knowing What Others

    Know, Feeling what others Feel: A Controlled Study of Empathy is Psychotherapists,

    The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 195, 4, 277281.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    33/35

    R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184 183

    Hateld, C. D., Rapson, R. L. & Le, Y. L. (2009) Emotional Contagion and Empathy, In

    J. Decety & W. Ickes (Eds) The Social Neuroscience of Empathy, 1, 313, Cambridge: MIT

    Press.Hess, U. & Blairy, S. (2001) Facial Mimicry and Emotional Contagion to Dynamic Emotional

    Facial Expressions and their Inuence on Decoding Accuracy, International Journal of

    Psychophysiology, 40, 129141.

    Hofffman, M. L. (2000) Empathy and moral development: Implications for caring and justice,

    New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Jabbi, M., Swart, M. & Keysers, C. (2007) Empathy for Positive and Negative Emotions in the

    Gustatory Cortex,NeuroImage,34, 4, 17441753.

    Kerem, E., Fishman, N. & Josselson, R. (2001) The Experience of Empathy in Everyday Rela-

    tionships: Cognitive and Afffective Elements,Journal of Social and Personal Relationships,

    18, 5, 709729.Lobchuk, M. M. (2006) Concept Analysis of Perspective-taking: Meeting Informal Caregiver

    needs for Communication Competence and Accurate Perception, Journal of Advanced

    Nursing, 54, 3, 330341.

    Macintyre, A. (2006/2007)Edith Stein: A philosophical prologue, 2nd ed., London: Continuum.

    Maturana, H. R. (1975) The Organization of the living: A theory of the living organization,

    The International Journal of Man-Machine Studies 7, 313332.

    Meneses, R. W. (2011) Experiences of Empathy, Ph.D. dissertation, School of Psychology,

    University of Birmingham, http://etheses.bham.ac.uk/2892/.

    Moustakas, C. (1994) Phenomenological research methods, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

    Oben, F. M. (1988/2010)Edith Stein: Scholar, Feminist, Saint, New York: Alba House.Paal, T. & Bereczkei, T. (2007) Adult Theory of Mind, Cooperation, Machiavellianism: the

    Efffect of Mindreading on Social Relations, Personality and Individual Diffferences, 43,

    54155.

    Preston, S. D. & de Waal, F. B. M. (2002) Empathy: Its ultimate and proximate bases,Behavio-

    ral and Brain Sciences, 25, 172.

    Prinz, J. (2006) Beyond Appearances: The Content of Perception and Sensation, in T. S. Gen-

    dler and J. Hawthorne (Eds.) Perceptual Experience,434459. Oxford: Oxford University

    Press.

    Reik, T. (1948/1971)Listening with the Third Ear, 5th ed., NY: Arena Books.

    Rockwell, T. (2007) Dynamic empathy: A new formulation for the simulation theory of mindreading, Cognitive Systems Research, 9, 5263.

    Rogers, C. (1957/2007) The necessary and suffcient conditions of therapeutic personality

    change,Psychotherapy: Theory, Research, Practice, Training, 44, 3, 240248.

    Scheler, M. (1913/ 1979)The Nature of Sympathy, 2nd ed., P. Heath (Trans.), Hamden, CT:

    Archon Books.

    Stein, E. (1917/ 1989). On the problem of empathy, 3rd ed, trad. Waltraut Stein, Washington:

    ICS Publications.

    Tempel, L. R. (2007) Pathways to the Clinicians Experience of Empathy in Engaging Single

    Mothers at Risk for Physical Abuse of their Children, Clinical Social Work Journal, 35,

    257265, DOI 10.1007/s10615-007-0106-4.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    34/35

    184 R. W. Meneses, M. Larkin / Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (2012)151184

    Thompson, E. (2001) Empathy and Consciousness, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 57,

    132.

    van Baaren, R. B., Decety, J., Dijksterhuis, A., van der Leij, A., van Leewen, M. L. (2009) BeingImitated: Consequences of Nonconsciously Showing Empathy, In J. Decety & W. Ickes

    (Eds) The Social Neuroscience of Empathy, 1, 313, Cambridge: MIT press.

    White, S. J. (1997) Empathy: a literature review and concept analysis, Journal of Clinical

    Nursing, 6, 253257.

    Zahavi, D. (2001) Beyond Empathy: Phenomenological Approaches to Intersubjectivity,

    Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 57, 15167.

    Zahavi, D. (2007)Expressions and Empathy, in Folk Psychology Re-Assessed, M. M. Ratclifffe

    and D. Hutto (eds.), 1, 2540.

    Zahavi, D. (2008) Simulation, projection and empathy, Consciousness and Cognition, 7, 2,

    514522.Zepf, S. & Hartmann, S. (2008) Some Thoughts on Empathy and Countertransference, Jour-

    nal of the American Am Psychoanalytical Association, 56, 741768.

  • 8/13/2019 Psychological Study of Empathy

    35/35

    Copyright of Journal of Phenomenological Psychology is the property of Brill Academic Publishers and its

    content may not be copied or ema