politics bioethics science policy

Upload: eriol01

Post on 28-Feb-2018

212 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    1/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.DOI: 10.1007/s10730-008-9062-9 Springer 2008

    _____________________________________________________________________________________

    Leigh Turner Ph D Associate Professor William Dawson Scholar Biomedical Ethics Unit Department

    Politics, Bioethics, and Science Policy

    Leigh Turner

    Many commentators argue that science policy should be above or

    beyond politics; they insist that science policy ought to be based

    exclusively on science. However, science policy formation includesethical and political considerations. Science and scientific facts do not

    determine science policy, though bodies of evidence developed by

    communities of scientists play an important role during policy-making

    processes. I argue that science policyparticularly policy-making related to

    medicine, biotechnology, the life sciences and other areas raising basic

    questions about identity, morality, and social orderis inevitably

    politicized in pluralistic societies.

    Introduction

    A term regularly invoked in bioethics scholarship, moral consensus is

    frequently elusive in contemporary societies (Engelhardt, 2002; Moreno,

    2005; Powers, 2005). The achievement of consensus or wide reflective

    equilibrium often seems less likely than the persistence of normative

    conflict (Hampshire, 2000; MacIntyre, 1988; Stout, 1988). Several leading

    approaches in bioethicscasuistry and principlist bioethics as well as other

    models predicated upon the notion of reflective equilibriumemphasize

    shared, common resources for ethical deliberation. Many bioethicistspromote consensus-based models in which interlocutors articulate

    disagreements, provide reasons in support of particular moral claims,

    respond to criticisms, and reach consensus. This model of moral deliberation

    is optimistic that review of evidence or scientific findings coupled with

    reasoned argumentation will end in a common understanding of what

    constitutes sensible practices and policies. However, anyone who has played

    a role in developing policy within institutions, professional societies, or

    legislative assemblies will recognize the many challenges facing efforts to

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    2/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.30

    craft broadly acceptable policies. The difficulties facing members of policy-

    making bodies at hospitals and professional associations are multiplied at the

    level of provincial, state, federal, and transnational policy formation. At this

    level of policy development, many constituencies must be addressed. These

    groups can have different interests, objectives, and moral predispositions(Sowell, 2002). They often disagree with one another about what counts as

    credible evidence and who can be characterized as reliable authorities.

    Policy-making within Institutions

    Within hospitals, to select just one type of social institution where policy-

    making occurs, policy-makers are sometimes criticized for failing to seek

    appropriate representation from members of various groups. In other

    instances, policy-makers are criticized for not fully grasping thecomplexities of particular domains of medical research or clinical practice.

    Criticism can come from many sources. Critiques can be particularly intense

    when policy-makers are expected to address contentious, divisive moral

    issues that generate considerable passion. Interlocutors can disagree

    concerning what constitutes ethical practices and policies. Researchers,

    nurses, doctors, hospital administrators, patients and other social actors can

    all claim that their interests are inadequately represented in policy-making

    arenas or incorporated within institutional policies (DeVries and Forsberg,

    2002). Critiques can focus on the inclusiveness or exclusiveness of policy-making processes, fairness or legitimacy of processes of policy formation, or

    the substantive content of particular policies. Issues of substance and

    processinsofar as matters of process are not also substantivecan both

    serve as lightning rods for conflict. Disputants can complain that they were

    not properly consulted during the policy-making process. Critics can argue

    that a policy emphasizes particular moral norms while paying insufficient

    heed to other values. Alternatively, dissatisfied parties can claim that a

    policy reflects the interests of one group while failing adequately to address

    and incorporate the concerns of other social actors.To focus on policy-making within hospitals, nurses can assert that

    physicians are given too much influence over policy-making processes and

    organizational practices. Doctors, in turn, can argue that they are not

    adequately included in various phases of policy development. They can state

    that the voices of hospital administrators, rather than clinicians, are

    consistently given too much weight. Social workers, physical therapists, or

    occupational therapists can condemn overrepresentation of doctors and

    nurses and express dismay that the voices of members of allied health

    professions are neglected.

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    3/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947. 31

    Even if a particular category of professionals is well-represented during

    the policy-making process, members of that group will sometimes claim that

    their official spokespersons fail to represent diverse moral viewpoints within

    the institution. For example, nurses might express satisfaction that nurses

    serve on the clinical ethics committee crafting a particular policy, yet arguethat the particular nurses on this body are unrepresentative of all nurses at

    the institution. Charges of authoritarianism, marginalization of stakeholders,

    and unrepresentative decision-makers must be acknowledged and

    addressed. In settings informed by democratic, egalitarian values, criticisms

    about exclusion and lack of representation must be seriously considered.

    There are many ways that various organizational actors can challenge

    policies and the policy-making process.

    Extra-institutional Social Actors

    Even if caregivers from various health-related professions develop a

    consensus and agree that different constituencies are well-represented, the

    policy-making process is fair, and the completed institutional policy is

    reasonable, patient representatives, family representatives, or local

    community leaders can argue that the interests of patients, the moral

    concerns of family members of patients, or the interests of the larger local

    community were insufficiently recognized during the process of crafting a

    particular institutional policy. Non-clinicians with a stake in hospital policycan accuse health care professionals of being elitist, undemocratic, and

    inattentive to the interests and concerns of community stakeholders.

    Concerted institutional efforts to engage community members and involve

    them in organizational policy formation can generate a different set of

    problems. If the exclusion of various social actors from the policy-making

    arena sometimes leads to charges of elitism, efforts to promote more

    democratic policy-making exercises can increase the likelihood of

    encountering intractable conflicts concerning what values ought to guide the

    policy-making process. When interests and normative frameworks of groupsdiverge, policy-makers can find it impossible to achieve consensus.

    Representatives of religious groups, ethnic groups, community

    associations, political bodies, and other social organizations can have diverse

    views concerning the basic, core, or foundational moral norms that

    ought to guide policy formation. Even if all interlocutors share general moral

    principles, they can disagree over how general moral norms ought to be

    weighed, specified, and interpreted in particular circumstances (Engelhardt,

    2002). Agreement about statements of principle need not lead to agreement

    about specific policies or practices.

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    4/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.32

    Policy-making exercises within just a single institution can generate fierce

    debates. Ethical issues related to the beginning and ending of human life are

    particularly contentious. Priority setting and resource allocation exercises

    must often confront competing notions of justice and fairness (Hampshire,

    2000). Furthermore, professional rivalries, longstanding struggles forinstitutional power, personal conflicts, conflicting religious values, cultural

    differences, basic disagreements about fundamental moral values, perceived

    slights or perceptions of exclusion or marginalization, and, of course, the

    satisfaction some parties feel when provoking opponents or blocking their

    interests whenever opportunities arise can all serve to slow or derail policy-

    making initiatives.

    Making Social Policy

    Challenges facing efforts to achieve consensus or wide reflective

    equilibrium multiply when we move beyond the level of a single institution

    to the state, province, or nation. State, provincial, and federal policies can

    affect the lives of millions or hundreds of millions of individuals. Within

    political entities that have relatively homogenous cultural and religious

    traditions, a common normative framework can limit obstacles associated

    with crafting social policy. However, in multicultural, multifaith, pluralistic

    societiesmost contemporary Western liberal democracies contain multiple

    religious groups, religious communities, and political partiesthere can bemany different normative frameworks in play. In most contemporary liberal

    democracies, it does not make sense to refer to Christian, Jewish,

    Muslim, Hindu, or Buddhist values. (The list of religious traditions

    could be greatly expanded.) To the contrary, diversity will characterize

    various religious traditions.

    Just as moral frames can differ within and among various religious

    groups, it is often a gross simplification to refer to Hmong, Korean-

    American, or Chinese Canadian belief systems or worldviews.

    Ethnic groups, much like religious groups, are often diverse rather thanmonolithic. Disagreements over basic moral values and the morality of

    specific social practices and policies can occur within and not only between

    ethnic groups. Value orientations can differ across generations, intraethnic

    groupings, gender lines, socioeconomic status, and many other social

    categories.

    Fragmentation of Civil Religion

    In countries where there is a broad, pervasive, overarching civil religion

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    5/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947. 33

    (Bellah, 1975), cultural and religious differences might not have much

    influence on broad matters of social policy. Rather, members of various

    social groupings will share a common civil religious tradition or public

    philosophy (Almond and Verba, 1963; Kingdon, 1999; Sandel, 1996). This

    shared normative fabric will provide common symbols, metaphors, andnarratives; there will be many resources for mutual deliberation and shared

    moral convictions. However, if such a civil religion does not exist, or if this

    pervasive social ethic loses its public authority over time, the presence of

    multiple normative frameworks can make it very difficult to reach public

    agreement on ethical issues related to childrearing, parenting and family life,

    health, illness, dying, and death (Hunter, 1991). Interestingly, the bioethics

    movement in the United States emerged at a time when many social

    commentators suggested that the civil religion of the United States was

    fragmenting (Bellah, 1975). The rise of bioethics is sometimes seen as aresponse to developments in medicine, biotechnology, and the life sciences.

    Acknowledging the role of specific technologies in prompting questions

    about moral values, the emergence of bioethics as social movement,

    academic field, and occupation might also be connected to the fragmentation

    of civil religion in America (Bellah, 1975; Engelhardt, 2002). As

    background presuppositions about public morality were thrown into question

    and a crisis of moral legitimation occurred, philosophers, theologians, and

    clinicians were increasingly asked to justify particular social policies.

    Longstanding norms could no longer be assumed. Particular values, policies,and social practices required justification in the face of public disagreement.

    Competing Political Philosophies

    Social scientists pay considerable attention to the moral discourses,

    worldviews, and mores of various cultural and religious communities.

    Political traditionsconservative, liberal, libertarian, and social democratic,

    for examplealso transmit social norms and connect broad visions of

    society to particular policy issues (Holm, 2004; Sowell, 2002). Just asreligious and cultural traditions can promote different normative

    frameworks, competing political philosophies also characterize many

    Western liberal democratic societies. Some countries have a well-defined

    political center. Various political parties know that however much they

    might wish to differentiate themselves from competing political parties, they

    must try to claim the common ground of mainstream political discourse.

    To surrender this common ground is to accept a place on the periphery of

    power. In settings where there is a well-defined civil religion or public

    philosophy, political leaders fight to define, occupy, and control the political

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    6/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.34

    center. In other countries, political discourse is far more polarized (Hunter,

    1991). Common ground and possibilities for bipartisan accords shrink and

    the likelihood of conflict over basic moral premises and the normative basis

    of social order increases. James Davison Hunter (1991) argues that the

    United States provides an example of a democratic society locked in aculture war. In fractured political landscapes, bioethicists will not have an

    easy time claiming that their normative claims and arguments rise above

    or beyond political conflicts. Rather, discussion of ethical issues related to

    such topics as embryonic stem cell research and therapeutic cloning will

    occur within turbulent social arenas (Caplan, 2005; Moreno, 2005; Powers,

    2005).

    Culture Wars

    Moral issuesonce they shift from being perceived as personal, private

    matters of conscience to matters of public policybecome swept into the

    public sphere of political conflict. In polarized political arenas, bioethics

    becomes enrolled in the the culture wars (Callahan, 2005; Caplan, 2005;

    Charo, 2004; Charo, 2005; Check, 2005; Hunter, 1991; Mooney, 2005;

    Moreno, 2005). Within such settings, some social actors assert that

    scientific matters must remain uninfluenced by political values and moral

    agendas. Clinging to the assumption that science must not be politicized,

    they assume that scientific facts must drive public policy. However, inmulticultural, multifaith, politically diverse societies, scientific facts will

    not end policy disputes and ethical conflicts (May 2006; Moreira, 2007).

    Rather, studies by scientists are swept into larger social conflicts; the

    meaning and credibility of various scientific claims becomes part of ethical

    debate and public policy formation. Science does not solve these political

    disputes and moral conflicts. Instead, scientific facts are used to lend

    legitimacy to particular normative claims and policy recommendations

    (May, 2006). Studies produced by scientists are used to establish credibility

    and authority in the same manner that religious injunctions, exegesis ofparticular sacred texts, or other authoritative conversation-stoppers (Rorty,

    1999) are used in settings where particular religious convictions hold broad

    sway.

    Politicizing Science Policy

    At the level of national policy deliberations, policy-making often occurs

    against a backdrop of partisan conflicts between political parties,

    longstanding moral conflicts dividing citizens, considerable scientific

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    7/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947. 35

    uncertainty, and questions concerning the legitimacy of particular advisory

    bodies (Barke, 2003; Green, 2006; Gutmann and Thompson, 1996; Kennedy,

    2003; Moreno, 2002; Pellegrino, 2006; Pielke, 2002; Pollard, 2001; Powers,

    2005; Revkin, 2004; United States House of Representatives Committee on

    Government Report, 2003). At this level of policy formation, one of the mostcommon accusations directed at policy-making bodies is that they are

    politicizing science and technology policy (Blackburn, 2004a; Blackburn,

    2004b; Grimes, 2004; Kass, 2004; Shulmar, 2007). Critics rarely explain

    what shape an apolitical policy somehow above or beyond politics

    would take. The usual assumption is that political opponents are partisan

    ideologues whereas the critics themselves are guided by common sense and

    reasonable convictions. Accusations that science is being politicized can

    emerge from all points along the political spectrum.

    Sometimes, these criticisms have a straightforward meaning. Accusationsof the politicization of policy-making can mean that evidence is being

    neglected, research is being ignored, and qualified individuals are removed

    or blocked from advisory bodies. Accusations of politicization of science

    policy can refer to the failure to include diverse voices or an incapacity to

    defend particular policy claims against criticisms from reputable authorities.

    Acknowledging that accusations of the politicization of science can have a

    straightforward, legitimate meaning, I want to nonetheless argue that policy-

    making is inevitably politicized or political in nature.

    Opponents of particular public policies or advisory bodies regularly arguethat science and not politics ought to dictate science and technology

    policy (Grimes, 2004; Leshner, 2003; Malakoff, 2003). In the United States,

    the current Bush Administration is repeatedly excoriated by its critics for

    politicizing science and technology policy formation (Blackburn, 2004a;

    Boonstra, 2003; Ferber, 2002; Greenberg, 2001; Greenberg, 2004; Grimes,

    2004; Malakoff, 2003; Mooney, 2005; Novak, 2003; Shulman, 2007; Union

    of Concerned Scientists, 2004). At present, the Bush Administration is

    accused by Democrats of politicizing science. At some point, Republicans

    will lose political power and Democrats will drive national science policyformation. When this occurs, we can anticipate that Republicans will accuse

    Democrats of politicizing science. I want to challenge the assumption that

    science policy can somehow take an apolitical form.

    Policy-making as Political Process

    In democratic social orders, the formation of science policy is an ethical and

    political process; science alone cannot serve as the sole basis for crafting

    science policy (Barke, 2003; Powers, 2005). Though we might want to

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    8/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.36

    criticize particular policies, we should not criticize policy-makers for

    politicizing questions related to science and technology. We can criticize

    policy-makers for the values they hold or the way they interpret particular

    values in specific contexts. Criticisms can also be directed toward the uses of

    evidence, selection of scientific authorities, and exclusion of particularscientific voices from the policy-making process. The suppression or

    exclusion of dissent can serve as one example of an unwiseand potentially

    dangerousresponse to science and technology policy formation (Ferber,

    2002; Greenberg, 2004; Novak, 2003; Union of Concerned Scientists, 2004).

    However, even if dissenting voices are included in deliberative bodies,

    policy formation will still be political. It will still include contestable

    judgments, the search for credibility and legitimation, the marshalling and

    critique of evidence, and often rhetorical appeals to the public good. Policy-

    making is a key element of what politicians and their designated advisorybodies do in democratic societies. Reaching resolutionhowever

    temporaryon contestable, often divisive topics is a highly political process.

    Conflicts, disagreements, accusations and counter-accusations of bias, and

    questions about the suitability of particular policymakers are standard

    features of making public policy in pluralistic democratic societies

    (Gutmann and Thompson, 1996).

    Policy-making as a Value-laden Enterprise

    The positivist attitude toward science policy formation rests on the

    assumption that science, nature, or the laws of physics can automatically

    dictate social policies. This view assumes that scientific knowledge free of

    substantive ethical, social, economic, and political judgments can be used to

    generate social policy. To the contrary, public policies are not based solely

    on scientific research findings. For example, scientific research can provide

    information concerning the risks and benefits of particular pharmaceutical

    products or medical devices. However, determining what counts as minimal

    risks, acceptable risks, or a reasonable risk/benefit ratio cannot bedecided exclusively on the basis of particular outcomes. The determination

    of what counts as an appropriate risk/benefit threshold involves a moral

    judgement; numbers alone do not set the bar for evaluating risks posed by

    particular interventions or technologies.

    Policy-making must address many factors, including ethical, legal, social,

    economic, and environmental issues. The politicization of science is

    widely characterized in negative terms, reflecting the common assumption

    that value judgments should be squeezed from science policies. Such

    accusations commonly make reference to the suppression of important

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    9/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947. 37

    scientific research, exaggerated emphasis on the significance of particular

    scientific findings, Machiavellian manipulations behind closed doors, the

    stacking of advisory and regulatory bodies with partisan members and the

    exclusion of credible voices of dissent from deliberative processes

    (Boonstra, 2003; Kennedy, 2003; Novak, 2003; Lancet Editors, 2002;Mooney, 2005). The politicization of science, in this sense, justifiably has

    negative connotations. In effect, the phrase refers to breakdowns or

    shortcomings in democratic processes required to craft robust, credible,

    science policies. However, in another sense, policy-making will inevitably

    occur as a contentious, argumentative, value-laden political process.

    Particular social actors must make decisions. Evidence needs to be weighed,

    judgments defended, claims and counterclaims debated, risks and benefits

    assessed. Such exercises in reasoning involve substantive deliberations; they

    do not turn exclusively on scientific findings. We should expect that socialpolicies related to issues in bioethics will include substantive judgments and

    commitments, and that different actors will often disagree over the particular

    weight that ought to be accorded various moral principles, how guidelines

    should be interpreted, and how arguments ought to be assessed. Science

    policy-making draws upon substantive convictions that are not reducible to

    scientific forms of knowledge even though research by scientists informs

    policy-making.

    Substantive Judgments

    Social policies and advisory documents that recommend or characterize

    policy alternatives do not simply convey data extracted from scientific

    reports. They incorporate substantive judgments such as what benchmarks

    should be used when establishing reasonable risk/benefit ratios, whether

    short-term considerations should outweigh long-term consequences, and

    whether cost effectiveness analysis or cost-benefit assessment can serve as

    an adequate ethical framework for deliberation (Emery and Schneiderman,

    1989; Goklany, 2002; Marchant, 2003; van den Belt, 2003). While better orworse arguments can be made when forming substantive judgments and

    crafting policies, such judgments will be political and contestable. Rather

    than focusing upon the politicization of science policy-makingas though

    there is an alternative to political deliberationsattention might better be

    focused on the dangers of suppressing voices of dissent and forms of

    evidence that ought to be included in policy-making arenas. However, these

    points can be distinguished. Even more inclusive approaches to policy-

    making are political. To recognize the value of including dissenters or

    social critics in policy debates is not to argue that science policy-making

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    10/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.38

    should be above or beyond politics and guided only by science.

    Interpreting Scientific Studies

    Policy documents often draw upon findings from scientific studies. Forexample, advisory reports, policy briefings, and policy guidelines related to

    embryonic stem cell research, gene transfer technology, or therapeutic

    cloning will utilize findings from researchers working in various fields

    within the life sciences. Science policy necessarily engages scientists and

    scientific research. Engagement with scientific research commonly plays a

    crucial role when crafting science and technology policies related to such

    topics as gene transfer technology, embryonic stem cell research,

    xenotransplantation, and somatic cell nuclear transfer. However, research

    findings established on the basis of research methods broadly accepted byparticular communities of scientists constrain but do not determine how to

    craft regulations and guidelines. Decisions about which areas of scientific

    research to fund, regulate, or prohibit, how much biodiversity ought to be

    preserved, or which endangered species to protect involve considerations of

    ethical, legal, social, and economic arguments. Such decisions require

    debates about the risks and potential harms to which we are willing to

    expose humans and other organisms. Statistical estimates of risk inform risk

    analysis, but they do not automatically identify which risks to tolerate and

    which ones to minimize or prevent (Goklany, 2002).Decisions about tolerable levels of risk require exercises in moral

    judgment. Such judgments will draw upon cultural models of what risks are

    acceptable and which ones need to be reduced. Similarly, considerations of

    moral and legal norms beyond cost-benefit calculationssuch as the dignity

    of the person or obligations to future generationsinvolve deliberations that

    are not reducible to scientific findings. Discussions concerning the relative

    significance of individual liberty, the common good, the environment, the

    comparative effectiveness of market mechanisms and governments in

    distributing resources, and the demarcation of particular goods as public orprivate require political and ethical debates. Scientific findings and

    scientific research are important components of these debates but they are

    not the only elements of social policy formation. Findings from

    epidemiology, immunology, biochemistry, and physiology do not

    automatically dictate how to craft social policies and regulate particular

    practices. Rather than deploring the politicization of advisory bodies and

    policy development, we should expect political controversies and

    disagreements over science and technology policy formation for at least four

    reasons.

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    11/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947. 39

    Moral Politics of Technologies

    First, different political parties commonly have different core values, social

    agendas, and policy platforms (Sowell, 2002). In some countries, differences

    between mainstream political parties are quite minimal. A shared civilreligion or common public philosophy provides a bounded space within

    which mainstream political actors must function (Bellah, 1975). In other

    social contexts, various political parties offer markedly different visions of

    social order and the public good (Sowell, 2002). Even in countries where the

    political center is relatively easy to identify, political parties still offer

    somewhat different policy platforms to the voting public. These values and

    policy orientations are connected to scientific research, but include

    substantive ethical, legal, social, and economic judgments about how society

    ought to be organized. For example, more liberal or progressive politicalparties typically emphasize the role of government in promoting social

    justice and addressing social inequities. Progressive political parties have a

    history of crafting policy initiatives intended to redistribute wealth from

    wealthier to poorer members of society. In contrast, contemporary

    conservative parties tend to be less supportive of government exercises in

    redistributing wealth. They often seek to promote the role of markets in

    distributing goods and services. Democrats and Republicans, Liberals

    and Conservatives, and members of other political parties are concerned

    about justice, but what justice means and how justice is pursuedcommonly takes different forms when representatives of these parties debate

    matters of public significance.

    Scientific issues are debated within social, political, and economic

    environments in which different political actors are informed by distinctive

    normative convictions (Sowell, 2002). However, these social actors do not

    all have equal access to political power. In many political arenas, particularly

    in settings where one political party does not overwhelmingly dominate the

    political apparatus, bipartisan support is consequently an important

    component of gathering public legitimacy for a particular policy. In settingswhere major political parties offer quite different substantive agendas,

    dominant parties will often be susceptible to criticisms that they are paying

    insufficient attention to the concerns of voices outside the center of power.

    Here, politicization of policy-making refers to the exclusion or

    marginalization of competing claims.

    Policy frameworks and normative commitments do not always neatly map

    onto traditional political divisions. Debates and conflicts exist both within

    and across political parties. Many Republican politicians oppose embryonic

    stem cell research but some Republic politicians support increased federalfunding for this area of research. However, taken as a whole, different

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    12/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.40

    political parties are typically informed by particular constellations of norms.

    The presence of different substantive moral traditions in pluralistic liberal

    democracies means that policy issues are charged with ethical and political

    significance. Scientific findings do not directly address questions about

    whether stem cells should be obtained from embryos and used to developnovel stem cell therapies. Public policies concerning embryonic stem cell

    research, gene transfer technology, and xenotransplantation need to address

    ethical, legal, social, economic, and, in some social settings, religious

    considerations. Studies in elite scientific journals by experts in regenerative

    medicine, gene therapy, stem cell research, and other scientific domains will

    not tell policy-makers everything they need to know about how these

    technologies ought to be subject to legislation and regulation. Scientific

    research is not self-interpreting or self-regulating. In multicultural,

    multifaith, politically pluralistic societies, particular values used to shapepublic policy will often not be shared by all social actors (Powers, 2005;

    Sowell, 2002).

    Decisions about how to regulate particular technologies involve

    considerations about safety, risks, harms, benefits, respecting core moral

    norms, and protecting the public good. Such questions are political matters.

    The policy-making process involves many individuals engaging in public

    debate, relying upon different experts, drawing upon sometimes diverse

    bodies of evidence and argumentation, and making claims for alternative

    regulatory models. There are few instances where all social actorsimmediately agree upon the specifics of complex social policies.

    Disagreements can occur over general frameworks, particular guidelines, the

    interpretation of regulations and laws, the credibility of specific scientific

    claims, or the long-term implications of implementing particular policies.

    Scientific studies might reveal that specific technologies are unfeasible or

    have low rates of success. However, where evidence exists that technologies

    are practically feasible, questions will remain about whether the technology

    ought to be permitted and how it should be regulated. We might refer to

    substantive conflicts over core social norms and the use of particulartechnologies as the moral politics of technologies. Often, different social

    actors will disagree over whether a particular technology is ethically or

    legally justifiable. They will disagree over what they regard as reasonable

    regulatory frameworks. Legislation and social policy are crafted in the

    political realm. Scientific expertise addresses just one domain of questions

    about the regulation and appropriation of technologies.

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    13/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947. 41

    Politics of Authority

    Second, science advisory boards and other committees intended to provide

    recommendations and policy alternatives to government agencies are staffed

    by particular individuals. Typically, only a small subset of the available poolof possible participants will be invited to participate in the policy-making

    arena. For example, in the United States, The Presidents Council on

    Bioethics currently includes just seventeen members. Many other qualified

    citizens and professionals could serve on this body. Scientists, lawyers,

    physicians, economists, and other citizens who are equally qualifiedand

    doubtless viewed by their supporters as better qualified than existing

    memberswill inevitably be excluded from participation in the policy-

    making arena. Critics of the membership of particular bodies can quite

    credibly claim that politics was a factor in deciding who gets to sit at thedeliberative table (Anderson, 2004; Blackburn, 2004a; Kass, 2004; Weiss,

    2004). The process of selecting participants in the policy-making and

    advisory process is inherently political. Even where government

    administrations strive to seek balance and fair representation, some

    qualified individuals are bound to be excludedintentionally or

    unintentionallyfrom the deliberative arena. Even if representatives of

    various groups are given opportunities to present their concerns to advisory

    boards and policy-making bodies, they can legitimately charge that they are

    excluded from the powerful role of setting the agenda, defining the terms ofdebate, and playing a decisive role in decision-making processes. We might

    think of this realm as the practical politics of who gets to have authority

    within the arena of deliberation and policy-making. Complex social and

    technological issues are not assessed by neutral social actors. Rather, they

    are explored by particular human beings with personal histories, community

    roles, interests, preferences, and goals. Policy-making involves the view

    from somewhere. Policy-making does not occur behind a veil of

    ignorance. Particular humans make specific choices at concrete historical

    moments. Democrats and Republicans, social democrats and libertarians,progressivists and conservatives, all have interests, predispositions, and tacit

    values. In societies where significant social cleavages exist over matters of

    public policy, we should expect to see controversies over which individuals

    are excluded from the policy-making arena. In large, complex societies with

    different forms of representative democracy, most citizens have very limited

    access to policy-making arenas. The qualifications of those individuals who

    make it into the inner circle of policy formation can usually be challenged.

    Other individuals could take the place of those individuals granted access to

    the corridors of power. Social actors on the margins of debate will often takeissue with not just the substance of particular policies. They will also ask

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    14/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.42

    why those individuals in positions of power have authority and a place at the

    debating table.

    Politics of Knowledge

    Third, in some areas, disagreements exist among both scientists and

    nonscientists about what constitutes reliable, accurate, credible knowledge.

    Conflicting knowledge claims are quite common even though many

    individuals like to think of science as providing definitive, unambiguous

    answers. Some social actors will lay claim to a particular body of research

    and rely upon its data and expert scientists. Other social actors will turn to

    competing data and alternative claims to expertise. In domains where

    conflicting values and policy alternatives are present, different bodies of

    scientific research can often be used to legitimate divergent practicalconclusions. Various groups all claim that scientific research validates

    their preferred social policies or recommended guidelines. Different political

    actors will call upon scientists to support or oppose particular policy

    frameworks. Disputants will seek to use science and scientists to their

    advantage. In social settings where scientists have considerable cultural

    capital, supporters of particular policies know that they need to find

    respectable scientists to support their cause. To have the weight of

    scientific authority on the side of the opposition is to suffer a major loss of

    public credibility. We might think of this realm as the politics of knowledgeand claims to scientific expertise.

    In complex policy disputes, we can anticipate that participants in the

    debate will claim that their preferred policy has scientific backing and

    support from credible scientific experts. They will not just challenge the

    ethical framework or policy recommendations of their opponents. Often, a

    powerful strategy to undermine alternative policy options is to challenge the

    scientific claims used to support particular conclusions. In disputes about

    global warming and the emission of pollutants, we can see one example

    where social actors engage in fierce battles over which bodies of scientificresearch are credible and who can serve as reliable, trustworthy experts. In

    contemporary democratic societies, to fail to make a case for the credibility

    of claims to scientific expertise is to suffer a major crisis of legitimation in

    public debate.

    Politics of Uncertainty

    Fourth, when crafting guidelines for novel technologies or responding to

    other developments, existing scientific research can provide only limited

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    15/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947. 43

    insight into the long-term consequences of particular policies. Often, little

    will be known about the long-term implications of promoting a particular

    initiative. Policies commonly have unforeseen consequences. Technologies

    can be used in unanticipated ways; unexpected problems or benefits often

    emerge. For example, important questions about therapeutic cloning andxenotransplantation will need to be addressed before these biomedical

    technologies can ever become normal, relatively routine components of

    the clinical management of patients. Even if such technologies proceed

    through clinical trials and become routinized aspects of medical care,

    unresolved questions will likely remain about the long-term biological and

    social consequences of such technologies. Years will need to pass before the

    long-term benefits and harms of particular technologies become apparent.

    Some individuals will likely argue that the immediate needs of desperately

    ill patients ought to be given greater weight than concerns about the eventualspread of an unanticipated virus as a result of xenotransplantation. Other

    individuals might argue that we should set a high threshold for safety

    standards and not let the care of contemporaries potentially jeopardize the

    health of future generations. Such policy disputes involve conflicts over how

    to weigh individual goods and community goods, and possible short-term

    consequences versus potential long-term consequences. Calculations about

    costs and benefits are difficult to make; considerable uncertainty about

    future outcomes often permeates debates. Just what current generations

    owe future generations is a matter for discussion; science does not tellus how to weigh the interests of future citizens.

    Uncertainty about the ethical, social, economic, and environmental

    consequences of particular technologies will often generate different policy

    conclusions. Risk averse individuals will perhaps rely upon a version of the

    precautionary principle and insist that a technology should be deemed unsafe

    until it is proven safe (van den Belt, 2003). Here, the regulatory bar is placed

    quite high. All new technologies are subject to intense critical scrutiny and

    evidentiary standards. Other individuals will argue that, on the basis of

    existing research, a technology should be deemed safe, ethical, andpermissible until such time as evidence leading to a different conclusion

    emerges. Here, new technologies are seen in a more optimistic light and the

    regulatory bar is lowered. We might think of such debates as involving the

    politics of uncertainty and time-horizons. To focus on the immediate or

    long-term consequences is to shift the terms of debate. Even where scientific

    evidence offers reliable insight into the short-term implications of particular

    technologies, there will sometimes be considerable uncertainty about the

    long-term consequences of permitting a particular technology to proceed. In

    the early years of the 20th century, for example, it would have been difficult

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    16/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.44

    indeed to envision how aircraft would be used in the 21st

    century.

    Technologies are often used in ways unanticipated by their early proponents.

    Existing knowledge does not provide a crystal ball allowing clear visions

    of the future. Often, scientific studies provide little insight into important

    questions about the practical consequences of a particular technology as it isused over time. Decisions must still be made, notwithstanding the

    impossibility of knowing the consequences of developing a particular

    technology over years and decades. The view from the present invariably

    differs from retrospective analysis. In retrospect, problems often appear

    obviously recognizable and easy to anticipate. At the time decisions are

    made, even the most insightful specialists often have difficulty envisioning

    in fine-grain detail future benefits and problems. Policy-making occurs in the

    present; policy-makers lack the benefit of hindsight though they can look to

    past events as a source of guidance concerning how to think about currenttechnologies. Anticipated benefits and harms can be factored into analysis.

    However, policy-makers are not all-knowing. Interlocutors will often

    disagree about the long-term implications of particular policies.

    Conclusion

    Many commentators insistently claim that science and not politics must

    drive science policy. Science, nature, or scientific experts can supposedly tell

    us how to proceed. However, it is misguided to think that science orscientific facts alone can drive science and technology policy. Rather than

    criticizing the politicization of science policy, it makes more sense to

    question the substantive content of particular policies. Calling particular

    committees or policies politicized is a red herring; there are more effective

    allegations to make when opposing a particular public policy or advisory

    board recommendation. Similarly, if suppression of voices of dissent is at

    issue, or credible bodies of research are being neglected in policy

    deliberations, then arguments need to be made about the value of permitting

    dissent in democratic societies, responding to the concerns of dissenters, andrecognizing the extent to which legitimacy flows from inclusion of diverse

    social actors in policy-making processes. In instances where the concerns of

    significant portions of the public are not incorporated into policy-making

    arenas, a key problem is that policy-making is being shaped in ways that are

    at odds with the core norms of large segments of the populace. In such

    instances, policy-makers should be criticized not for politicizing social

    issues and particular technologies, but for ignoring the moral concerns of a

    significant portion of the citizenry. Of course, in settings where consensus

    cannot be reached and basic moral norms are in conflict, ignoring the moral

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    17/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947. 45

    concerns of significant numbers of citizens is precisely what happens when

    social policy is established. The price of resolution is social exclusion. Wide

    reflective equilibrium amongst interlocutors is not reached. There are

    political winners and losers in the policy-making struggles. Politicization

    is the word marginalized participants in public debate use to refer to theprocesses whereby their intellectual leaders, bodies of evidence, and modes

    of reasoning fail to set the terms of debate, define policy, and shape social

    order. The term politicization carries considerable rhetorical power even

    though the crafting of science policy is a thoroughly political matter in

    democratic societies where various political actors often have very different

    views about what constitute ethical practice.

    REFERENCES

    Almond, G. & Verba, S. (1963). The civic culture: political attitudes and

    democracy in five nations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Anderson, M. (2004). Bush dismisses council members. The Scientist,

    March 3.

    Barke, R.P. (2003). Politics and interests in the republic of science. Minerva,

    41, 305-325.

    Bellah, R.N. (1975).The broken covenant: American civil religion in time of

    trial. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Blackburn, E. (2004a). A full range of bioethical views just got narrower.Washington Post,March 7, B02.

    Blackburn, E. (2004b). Bioethics and the political distortion of biomedical

    science. New England Journal of Medicine, 350, 1379-1380.

    Blackburn, E. & Rowley, J. (2004). Reason as our guide. PloS Biology, 2,

    0001-0003.

    Boonstra, H. (2003). Critics charge Bush mix of science and politics is

    unprecedented and dangerous. The Guttmacher Report on Public Policy,

    May, 1-3.

    Callahan, D. (2005). Bioethics and the culture wars.Cambridge Quarterly ofHealthcare Ethics,14, 424-431.

    Caplan, A. (2005). Who lost China? A foreshadowing of todays

    ideological disputes in bioethics. Hastings Center Report, May-June, 12-

    13.

    Charo, R.A. (2004). Passing on the right: conservative bioethics is closer

    than it appears.Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics,32(2), 307-320.

    Charo, R.A. (2005). Realbioethik. Hastings Center Report, July-August, 13-

    14.

    Check, E. (2005). U.S. progressives fight for a voice in bioethics. Nature,

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    18/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947.46

    437, 932-933.

    Emery, D.D. & Schneiderman, L.J. (1989). Cost-effectiveness analysis in

    health care.Hastings Center Report,19(4), 8-13.

    Engelhardt, H.T., Jr. (2002). Consensus formation: the creation of an

    ideology.Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 11(1), 7-17.Ferber, D. (2002). Overhaul of CDC panel revives lead safety debate.

    Science,298, 732.

    Goklany, I.M. (2002). From precautionary principle to risk-risk analysis.

    Nature Biotechnology,20(11), 1075.

    Green, R. (2006). For richer or poorer? Evaluating the Presidents Council

    on bioethics.HEC Forum, 18, 108-124.

    Greenberg, D. (2004). New report accuses Bush of suppressing research

    data.The Lancet,363, 874.

    Greenberg, D. (2001). The Bush White House: science advice still out in thecold.The Lancet,357, 1773.

    Grimes, D. (2004). Emergency contraception: politics trumps science at the

    U.S. Food and Drug Administration.Obstetrics and Gynecology, 104(2),

    220-221.

    Gutmann, A. & Thompson, D. (1996). Democracy and disagreement.

    Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Hampshire, S. (2000). Justice is conflict. Princeton: Princeton University

    Press.

    Holm, S. (2004). Bioethics down undermedical ethics engages withpolitical philosophy.Journal of Medical Ethics,31(1), 1.

    Hunter, J.D. (1991). Culture wars: the struggle to define America. New

    York: Basic Books.

    Kass, L. (2004). We dont play politics with science. Washington Post,

    March 3, A27.

    Kennedy, D. (2003). An epidemic of politics.Science,299, 625.

    Kingdon, J. (1999).America the unusual. New York: Worth Publishers.

    Lancet Editors. (2002). Keeping scientific advice non-partisan. The Lancet,

    360, 1525.Leshner, A.I. (2003). Dont let ideology trump science.Science,302, 1479.

    Malakoff, D. (2003). Democrats accuse Bush of letting politics distort

    science.Science,301, 901.

    Marchant, G.E. (2003). From general policy to legal rule: aspirations and

    limitations of the precautionary principle. Environmental Health

    Perspectives111(14), 1799-1803.

    May, C. (2006). Mobilizing modern facts: health technology assessment and

    the politics of evidence.Sociology of Health and Illness,28, 513-532.

    Mooney, C. (2005). The Republican war on science. New York: Basic

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    19/20

    HEC Forum (2008) 20 (1): 2947. 47

    Books.

    Moreira, T. (2007). Entangled evidence: knowledge making in systematic

    reviews in healthcare.Sociology of Health and Illness,29, 180-197.

    Moreno, J.D. (2002). The brief career of a Government Advisory

    Committee: one members perspective. The American Journal ofBioethics, 2(4).

    Moreno, J.D. (2005). The end of the great bioethics compromise. Hastings

    Center Report,January-February, 14-15.

    Novak, K. (2003). U.S. scientific panels Bush-whacked. Nature Medicine,

    9(2), 153.

    Pellegrino, E. (2006). Bioethics and politics: doing ethics in the public

    square.Journal of Medicine and Philosophy,31, 569-584.

    Pielke, R.A. Jr. (2002). Policy, politics and perspective. Nature, 416, 367-

    368.Pollard, T.D. (2001). Life scientists and politics in the United States. Nature

    Reviews Molecular Cell Biology,2, 929-931.

    Powers, M. (2005). Bioethics as politics: the limits of moral expertise.

    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal,15(3), 205-322.

    Revkin, A.C. (2004). Bush vs. the laureates: how science became a partisan

    issue. The New York Times,October 19.

    Rorty, R. (1999).Philosophy and social hope. London: Penguin Books.

    Shulman, S. (2007). Undermining science: suppression and distortion in the

    Bush Administration. Berkeley: University of California Press.Sowell, T. (2002). A conflict of visions: ideological origins of political

    struggle. New York: Basic Books.

    Union of Concerned Scientists. (2004). Scientific integrity in policymaking:

    an investigation into the Bush Administrations misuse of science.

    February. Cambridge: Union of Concerned Scientists.

    United States House of Representatives Committee on Government

    ReformMinority Staff Special Investigation Division. (2003). Politics

    and science in the Bush Administration. Prepared for Henry A. Waxman.

    August. Van den Belt, H. (2003). Debating the precautionary principle:guilty until proven innocent, or innocent until proven guilty? Plant

    Physiology,132(3), 1122-1126.

    Weiss, R. (2004). Bush ejects two from bioethics council. Washington Post,

    February 28, A06.

  • 7/25/2019 Politics Bioethics Science Policy

    20/20

    Reproducedwithpermissionof thecopyrightowner. Further reproductionprohibitedwithoutpermission.