on sequential and simultaneous contributions under...

27
Int J Game Theory (2011) 40:119–145 DOI 10.1007/s00182-010-0230-1 On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information Parimal Kanti Bag · Santanu Roy Accepted: 21 February 2010 / Published online: 16 March 2010 © Springer-Verlag 2010 Abstract When contributors to a common cause (or public good) are uncertain about each others’ valuations, early contributors are likely to be cautious in free-riding on future contributors. Contrary to the case of complete information, when contributors have independent private valuations for the public good, the expected total contribu- tion generated in a sequential move game may be higher than in a simultaneous move game. This is established in a conventional framework with quasi-linear utility where agents care only about the total provision of the public good (rather than individual contribution levels) and there is no non-convexity in the provision of the public good. We allow for arbitrary number of agents and fairly general distribution of types. Keywords Fundraising · Sequential vs. simultaneous contributions · Public goods · Incomplete information JEL Classification D73 · H41 · L44 1 Introduction Fundraising by charities and non-profit organizations, and other campaigns for solic- iting voluntary contributions to public goods (or common goals), are complex events P. K. Bag (B ) Department of Economics, National University of Singapore, AS2 Level 6, 1 Arts Link, Singapore 117570, Singapore e-mail: [email protected] S. Roy Department of Economics, Southern Methodist University, 3300 Dyer Street, Dallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: [email protected] 123

Upload: others

Post on 16-Oct-2020

2 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

Int J Game Theory (2011) 40:119–145DOI 10.1007/s00182-010-0230-1

On sequential and simultaneous contributionsunder incomplete information

Parimal Kanti Bag · Santanu Roy

Accepted: 21 February 2010 / Published online: 16 March 2010© Springer-Verlag 2010

Abstract When contributors to a common cause (or public good) are uncertain abouteach others’ valuations, early contributors are likely to be cautious in free-riding onfuture contributors. Contrary to the case of complete information, when contributorshave independent private valuations for the public good, the expected total contribu-tion generated in a sequential move game may be higher than in a simultaneous movegame. This is established in a conventional framework with quasi-linear utility whereagents care only about the total provision of the public good (rather than individualcontribution levels) and there is no non-convexity in the provision of the public good.We allow for arbitrary number of agents and fairly general distribution of types.

Keywords Fundraising · Sequential vs. simultaneous contributions · Public goods ·Incomplete information

JEL Classification D73 · H41 · L44

1 Introduction

Fundraising by charities and non-profit organizations, and other campaigns for solic-iting voluntary contributions to public goods (or common goals), are complex events

P. K. Bag (B)Department of Economics, National University of Singapore, AS2 Level 6,1 Arts Link, Singapore 117570, Singaporee-mail: [email protected]

S. RoyDepartment of Economics, Southern Methodist University, 3300 Dyer Street,Dallas, TX 75275-0496, USAe-mail: [email protected]

123

Page 2: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

that often take place over a length of time. Fundraisers or providers of the public goodhave limited resources to expend on reaching out to and establishing contact withpotential donors who might identify with their specific objectives. This, along withfrictions in the flow of information across donors and a wide variety of donor-specificfactors, implies that in course of the campaign, contributors may “arrive” and maketheir contributions at different points of time. One important practical question thatarises then is whether a contributor should be informed about actual contributions made(or, the funds raised) till that point of time in the campaign. This question acquiressignificance in view of the fact that if donors observe past contributions before makingtheir own contribution, then there is an incentive for early contributors to free ride:by making low contributions and pre-committing to not contribute later, early moverscan shift the burden to late movers. In other words, revealing information about pastcontributions can create a dynamic free-riding effect if donors can pre-commit to notcontribute in the future.

This dynamic free-riding effect was formalized by Varian (1994) in a completeinformation game of voluntary contribution to a public good where it was shownthat if agents contribute sequentially i.e., each agent contributes after observing thecontributions made by the earlier agents in an exogenous order of moves where eachagent contributes only once, the total contribution generated often falls short of, andnever exceeds, the total contribution if the agents make their contribution decisionssimultaneously (i.e., without observing the contribution made by any other agent). Forinstance, if there are two agents with quasi-linear utility and their marginal valuationsof the public good are ordered, then in a simultaneous move game, the agent with thehigher valuation is the sole contributor and the public good is provided at a level that isindividually optimal for this agent (which is inefficient). In a sequential contributiongame, it is possible that the higher valuation agent moves first, contributes zero andthe lower valuation agent then contributes her individually optimal level so that thepublic good is provided at even a lower level.

The theoretical argument outlined above implies that fundraisers or charities shouldnot announce or reveal contributions during the campaign (perhaps announce only atthe end of the campaign, to generate snob value or publicity for donors).1 This is,however, extensively contradicted by real world evidence that information about pastcontributions are made available to prospective new contributors. Much of this evi-dence comes from fundraising by charities where major donations are announcedduring the fundraising campaign (see, among others, the discussion on capital cam-paigns in Andreoni (2006)). A number of field studies and experimental works onpublic goods also demonstrate the merits of sequential contribution with announce-ment of contributions (over simultaneous contribution) (see Silverman et al. 1984;List and Lucking-Reiley 2002; Potters et al. 2005; Coats et al. 2009). One way toreconcile the real world observations with the theoretical result outlined above is toargue that the latter requires that the order of moves of contributors be exogenous, andthat each agent contribute only once; both of these assumptions may not be satisfied

1 Glazer and Konrad (1996) and Harbaugh (1998) respectively consider wealth-signaling and prestigemotive of donations. They do not analyze the strategic timing of announcements. Charities may announcedonations after completion of the fund-drive to confer the donors their due recognition.

123

Page 3: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 121

in real world fundraising situations where donors may decide on their order of movesendogenously and may not be able to commit to contribute only once. If either ofthese hold, then in Varian’s framework the sequential and simultaneous move gamesgenerate identical outcomes and, in particular, revealing past contributions is no worsethan not revealing them.

However, it is also arguable that in many real world situations, the order of arrivalof major donors is to a significant extent determined by exogenous factors such asthe advertising and solicitation strategy of the fundraising agency, the flow of infor-mation across social networks, fluctuations in wealth of donors, news shocks and soon. To that extent, contributors may often be sharply constrained in their ability tochoose their order of moves. Further, in actual fundraising or voluntary contributionprocesses, it is not possible for outsiders to observe whether major donors can committo not contribute in the future; however, it is certainly true that in many of these funddrives, major donors actually contribute only once.

In many cases, the very structure of contribution may also limit the possibility of adonor contributing more than once. For example, in some fundraising events donorsare called upon sequentially to make their pledges. There are instances of fundrais-ing in churches and other social gatherings where, at the end of the service or themain social event, donors put their money in a box or basket—if the box or basket istransparent (as it is in many cases) they can observe the contributions made by others.There is some evidence that in such events, being able to observe the contributionsmade by others does actually increase total contribution.2 To reconcile these with thetheoretical result in Varian (1994), one needs additional arguments.

In recent years, a significant theoretical literature has developed to explain the realworld practice of using sequential fundraising schemes and revealing contributions toprospective donors. One strand of this literature has shown that the sequential formatmay generate higher total contribution (than the simultaneous move case) even whenagents have only one chance to contribute, i.e., exactly under the conditions that gen-erate lower provision of the public good through the dynamic incentive to free ridein Varian’s framework. This paper forms a part of this strand of the literature. Weargue that the reason why revealing previous contributions to prospective donors maymake sense even when donors contribute only once (and therefore, can free ride onfuture donors) is because the true willingness of a contributor to pay for the publicgood is her private information that is, at least to a significant extent, unknown toother contributors. In the incomplete information structure generated by independentprivate preferences for the public good, when donors contribute without observingthe actual contributions or types of other donors, they base their own contributionson the expected contribution of other donors, which implies that a higher valuationdonor tends to reduce her contribution and free ride on the possibility that other donorsmay turn out to have relatively higher valuation; further, a contributor with fairly low

2 For example, Soetevent (2005) compares “closed bag” and “open basket” methods of Baptist churchcollections in the Netherlands (at the end of the day’s service). With traditional closed bag collectionsmembers of the congregation do not observe the donations made by others, whereas with open basket (thatis passed around from person to person in the church) they have information about earlier contributions.Soetevent finds that offerings for charitable purposes external to the parish were significantly higher whenopen basket collections were used.

123

Page 4: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

122 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

valuation may contribute very little as she gambles on the event that other contributorshave much higher valuations and will contribute generously. The net effect is that instates of the world where a large proportion of contributors are actually ones with rel-atively low valuations, the total contribution may be excessively small relative to whatthese low valuation contributors would have provided under complete information.When contributions are made sequentially and past contributions are observed, thisproblem is partially redressed because later contributors make their donations knowingwhat the earlier ones have contributed, and do not need to guess their valuations orcontributions. Thus, when the early contributors have low valuations, higher valuationlate movers can make up for their low contributions; on the other hand, when the earlymovers have higher valuation, they may find it too risky to free ride on late movers asthe latter may seriously underprovide the public good if they happen to be of lowervaluation type. The net effect can result in an improvement in the expected provisionof the public good relative to a situation where donors do not observe the actions ofany other donor.

Existing theoretical papers that contain results about the efficacy of sequential con-tribution schemes with announcement of contributions even when donors contributeonly once, are as follows. (Some of these papers also analyze the outcome where earlydonors may contribute a second time.)

Andreoni (1998) analyzes fundraising for big-value public projects with thresholdsintroducing non-convexity in production. The fundraising team may cultivate a fewleading donors in the early stages, secure their pledges and then announce them tolaunch the public fund-drive of the campaign when the rest of the potential donorscontribute. The knowledge that the threshold funds have been raised improves the mar-ginal productivity of follower contributions, thus creating advantages for a sequentialcontribution format.3 In contrast to this paper, our results are derived in a convexframework (as in Varian 1994) with no threshold effect in the production technologyof the public good.

Romano and Yildirim (2001) consider warm-glow and snob effects in the utilityfunction of donors; each donor not only cares about the total contribution or the totalprovision of the public good, but also the individual contribution levels of other donors.Using complementarities between individual contributions, they show that being ableto observe past contributions can raise the total contribution. Our results, in contrast,are based on a more conventional formulation where contributors care only about thetotal provision of the public good and the cost of their own contribution.

Vesterlund (2003) considers a model where donors have common valuation of thecharity but are uncertain about the quality of the charity. More generous gifts from

3 One may view discrete public goods (such as a 0–1 public good that is either provided or not provided)as special cases of such threshold technology. Admati and Perry (1991) and Marx and Matthews (2000)respectively analyze the provision of discrete public goods (under complete information) in an alternatingoffer voluntary contribution format and an unrestricted repeated contribution format. Menezes et al. (2001)analyze simultaneous contribution to discrete public goods under incomplete information about privatevaluations, while Agastya et al. (2007) study how pre-play cheap talk communication indicating whetherone would like to contribute to a discrete joint project or not, followed by simultaneous contributions, canimprove outcomes relative to a simultaneous contribution, incomplete information game without the cheaptalk.

123

Page 5: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 123

early donors, who may have privately acquired information about quality, prompts laterstage donors to give higher donations and this, in turn, motivates high quality charitiesto publicly announce contributions. In contrast to Vesterlund’s paper, donors in ourpaper have independent private valuation for the public good and there is no questionof contributions revealing private information about the charity. Indeed, our resultsare not based on any informational advantage or signaling value of announcement ofcontributions.4

Finally, a recent literature on joint projects in teams and competitive races in inno-vations (especially in softwares) with public good features focuses on the sequentialcontribution format with exogenous order of moves (Winter 2006; Bessen and Maskin2009). In these models, it is natural to focus on production functions that allow forsome complementarity in individual contributions or inputs. These papers do not com-pare sequential and simultaneous mechanisms, but instead take sequential settings asgiven. It is intuitive that in team problems with complementary technologies, sequen-tial voluntary contributions may outperform simultaneous contributions.5 Our resultssuggest that even when individual contributions are perfect substitutes, incompleteinformation (say, arising from uncertainty about the input cost of individual teammembers) can lead to superiority of sequential design.

Specifically, we analyze a conventional model of voluntary contribution to a pub-lic good where agents have quasi-linear utility. The model is a direct extension ofthe one in Varian (1994) to a Bayesian setting where contributors have (independent)private information about their valuation of the public good. We allow for arbitrarynumber of agents and fairly general distribution of types. We show that under certainsufficient conditions that include concavity of the marginal utility from the publicgood, the expected total contribution generated in a perfect Bayesian equilibrium ofa sequential move contribution game is at least as large as that in a Bayes-Nash equi-librium of the simultaneous move contribution game if the agent who moves last inthe sequential game is one who makes a strictly positive contribution in the simulta-neous move game for every possible realization of her type. We obtain this result, eventhough each agent has only one chance to contribute and can therefore pre-committo contributions. Further, if the equilibrium in the sequential game is one where some

4 In an earlier paper (Bag and Roy 2008), we consider a multistage game of contribution to a public goodwith all agents having the option to contribute in all stages. There we show that under incomplete informa-tion about the agents’ (independent private) valuations of the public good, the expected total contribution ishigher if the contributions made at each stage are observed before the next stage; the economic reasoningbehind this is based on the possibility of revelation of the private preferences of contributors through theiractions and the incentive of higher valuation contributors to hide information about their true preferencesas it may make them more vulnerable to free-riding by other agents in subsequent stages of the game. Suchincentives are not important in voluntary contribution processes where agents cannot contribute repeatedly;the current paper focuses on these environments by assuming that agents move sequentially with eachagent having only one turn to contribute so that later movers cannot free ride on earlier contributors, andcontributors have no incentive to either hide or reveal their private valuation of the public good.5 Intuitively, with sequential contribution, agents might be able to better coordinate their costly activities(i.e., efforts or contributions) towards improved collective outcome than under simultaneous contributions.In fact, Agastya (2009) shows, in a joint project setting similar to one in Agastya et al. (2007) (see foot-note 3), that sequential contribution would yield a better chance of project completion than simultaneouscontribution. But this ranking is then reversed if one adds cheap talk possibilities prior to the contributionstage.

123

Page 6: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

124 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

contributor who moves prior to the last mover, makes a strictly positive contributionwith strictly positive probability or alternatively, if the marginal utility from the publicgood is strictly concave, then the sequential game generates strictly higher expectedtotal contribution. In an example with two agents and two types, we show that someof these sufficient conditions are not necessary for the sequential game to generatehigher contribution.

The sequential move game considered in this paper is one where every agent per-fectly observes the individual contributions made by earlier contributors before makingher own contribution decision. However, as we argue informally at the end of Sect. 4,our results are equally valid for a modified version of the sequential move game whereeach contributor observes only the sum of contributions made by earlier contributors,but not necessarily their individual contributions.

There is a substantial literature on voluntary provision of public goods under incom-plete information that focus on inefficiencies that arise due to incompleteness of infor-mation.6 We do not concern with the efficiency or normative issues7; instead, we offeran incomplete information based explanation of why sequential contribution schemesmay be better for the total provision of the public good.

The next section presents the model. In Sect. 3 we analyze the simultaneous contri-bution game, followed by an analysis of the sequential contribution game in Sect. 4. InSect. 5, we state our main results comparing the expected contributions in the sequen-tial and simultaneous move games; in particular, we outline general conditions underwhich the sequential form generates higher expected total contribution. Section 6 elab-orates further on these conditions. Section 7 discusses the two-agents, two-types case.The Appendix contains some proofs not included in the main text.

2 The model

N > 1 agents contribute voluntarily to a public good. Each agent i ∈ {1, . . . , N } hasa budget constraint wi > 0. Agent i’s payoff depends on the total contribution of allagents, her own contribution and her own type, and is given by

ui (gi , g−i , τi ) = τi Vi (gi + g−i ) + wi − gi ,

where gi ≥ 0 is i’s contribution, g−i is the total contribution of all other agents j �= i ,and τi is a private preference parameter of agent i that affects her marginal utility fromconsumption of the public good, is known only to agent i and is interpreted as the“type” of agent i . It is common knowledge that each agent i’s type τi is an independentrandom draw from a probability distribution with distribution function Fi and compactsupport Ai ⊂ R++. Let τ i and τ i be the lowest and highest possible types of agent i

6 See Bliss and Nalebuff (1984), Palfrey and Rosenthal (1988), Fershtman and Nitzan (1991), Gradstein(1992), Vega-Redondo (1995) etc.7 Implementation of efficient provision in public good games through clever mechanism constructions waspart of an early approach; see, for instance, Jackson and Moulin (1992). Cremer and Riordan (1985) employ aStackelberg mechanism (players declare their preferences sequentially) in an incomplete information publicgood setting to induce efficiency along with truth-telling and budget balance.

123

Page 7: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 125

defined by

τ i = min{τ : τ ∈ Ai }, τ i = max{τ : τ ∈ Ai }.

Assumption 1 ∀i ∈ {1, . . . , N }, Vi (.) is continuously differentiable, concave andnon-decreasing on R+, with Vi (0) = 0, τ i V ′

i (0) > 1 and τ i V ′i (wi ) < 1.

Define ∀i :

zi = sup{x ≥ 0 : τ i V ′i (x) = 1}.

Under Assumption 1, 0 < zi < wi . It is easy to check that agent i would never con-tribute in excess of zi in any contribution game, whatever be her type. This allows usto drop wi and write agent i’s payoff function simply as

ui = τi Vi (gi + g−i ) − gi .

Define

G =N∑

i=1

zi > 0.

Assumption 2 Vi (.) is strictly concave on [0, G], ∀i ∈ {1, . . . , N }.Under Assumptions 1 and 2, every agent i of every possible type τi ∈ Ai has a

unique standalone contribution xi (τi ) ∈ (0, wi ) defined by:

xi (τi ) = arg maxgi

ui (gi , 0, τi ),

(1)satisfying τi V ′

i (xi (τi )) = 1.

It is easy to check that xi (τi ) is strictly increasing in τi , implying:

zi = xi (τ i ).

The expected standalone contribution of agent i , denoted hereafter by θi , is given by:

θi =∫

Ai

xi (τi ) dFi (τi ).

Also, since Vi (.) is non-decreasing, V ′i (.) ≥ 0. Assumption 2 therefore implies that

V ′i (G) > 0 on [0, G). Finally, we impose:

Assumption 3 V ′i (.) is concave on [0, G].

123

Page 8: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

126 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

Assumption 3 is an important technical restriction that will be useful in comparingexpected total contributions under sequential and simultaneous move games.8 Notethat we do not require that the function V ′

i (.) be concave or strictly decreasing on theentire positive real line.

While our analysis is presented for a continuously variable public good, by settingVi (G) = V (G) for all i and interpreting V (G) as the ‘probability of success’ of apublic project with binary outcomes (success or failure) that depends on total invest-ment G, the analysis can be easily applied to a discrete public good setting9; in thatcase, τi > 0 is agent i’s deterministic utility if the project succeeds, while the utilityobtained when the project fails is normalized to zero.

We will compare two game forms—an N -stage sequential contribution game anda simultaneous contribution game—and the solution concepts are Perfect BayesianEquilibrium and Bayesian-Nash Equilibrium, respectively. In the sequential contribu-tion game, the agents contribute in an exogenous order and the contribution amountsbecome known as and when they are made. Each agent is allowed to contribute onlyonce, and is not allowed to add to her contribution at a later stage. In the simultaneouscontribution game, each agent contributes without any knowledge of other agents’contributions. We confine attention to pure strategy equilibria.

The contribution games are compared according to the (ex ante) expected totalcontributions made by all N agents, i.e., the expected provision of public good.

3 Simultaneous contribution game

First, we analyze the simultaneous contribution game. Let yi (τi )denote the equilibriumcontribution of agent i of type τi ∈ Ai , i ∈ {1, . . . , N } and y−i (τ−i ) =∑ j �=i y j (τ j )

where τ−i ∈∏ j �=i A j is the vector of types for agents other than agent i . Then, yi (τi )

is a solution to the following expected utility maximization problem:

maxy≥0

τi Eτ−i [Vi (y + y−i (τ−i ))] − y. (2)

In what follows, we denote by F−i (τ−i ) the joint distribution of τ−i . We start with asimple observation that follows directly from the definitions of xi (τi ) and G:

8 A simple example that satisfies all of the above assumptions is the situation where all agents have identicalutility functions and distribution of types and for all i = 1, . . . , N , Vi (.) is the quadratic function

Vi (G) ={

αG − 12 G2, 0 ≤ G ≤ α, α > 0

12 α2, G > α,

with the additional restrictions that τ i = τ , τ i = τ satisfy

1

ατ< 1,

1

ατ≥ 1 − 1

N.

9 Consider any density function h(z) with support on the positive real line that is weakly decreasing and is,in addition, strictly decreasing and concave over [0, G]. Then, taking V (x) = ∫ x

0 h(z) dz as the probabilityof success of the project satisfies our assumptions.

123

Page 9: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 127

Lemma 1 Consider any Bayesian-Nash equilibrium of the simultaneous move con-tribution game where yi (τi ) is the contribution made by agent i of type τi . Then,yi (τi ) ≤ xi (τi ) ∀τi ∈ Ai , ∀i ∈ {1, . . . , N }, and the total contribution generated

N∑

i=1

yi (τi ) ≤ G with probability one.

Below we derive a much sharper bound for the expected total contribution, but firstthe following technical result should be noted (see the Appendix for the proof).

Lemma 2 Consider the simultaneous move game and fix an agent index i . If for somej �= i , Pr{τ j : y j (τ j ) > 0} > 0, then the probability distribution of the randomvariable y−i =∑ j �=i y j is non-degenerate.

Lemma 3 (An upper-bound on expected total contribution) Consider any Bayesian-Nash equilibrium of the simultaneous move contribution game where for some agenti , yi (τi ), the equilibrium contribution of agent i , is strictly positive τi -almost surelyi.e., Pr{τi : yi (τi ) > 0} = 1.

(i) Then,

N∑

k=1

{∫yk(τk) dFk(τk)

}≤ θi (3)

i.e., the expected total contribution by all agents generated in this equilibriumdoes not exceed the expected standalone contribution of agent i .

(ii) If, in addition, V ′i (G) is strictly concave on [0, G], and there exists some agent

j �= i such that Pr{τ j : y j (τ j ) > 0} > 0, then the inequality in (3) holds strictlyi.e., the expected total contribution by all agents generated in this equilibriumis strictly less than the expected standalone contribution of agent i .

Proof Using the first-order condition of the maximization problem (2) faced by agenti of type τi and the hypothesis that yi (τi ) > 0 τi -almost surely, we have:

τi

∫V ′

i (yi (τi ) + y−i (τ−i )) dF−i (τ−i )

= τi Eτ−i [V ′i (yi (τi ) + y−i (τ−i ))]

= 1, τi -almost surely. (4)

First, we establish (i). Since (using Assumption 3) V ′i (.) is concave on [0, G], and from

Lemma 1, yi (τi ) + y−i (τ−i ) ∈ [0, G] almost surely, we have by Jensen’s inequality

τi V ′i (yi (τi ) + Eτ−i {y−i (τ−i )}) ≥ 1, τi -almost surely,

so that using (Assumption 2) concavity of Vi (.) and (2), it follows that

yi (τi ) + Eτ−i {y−i (τ−i )} ≤ xi (τi ), τi -almost surely,

123

Page 10: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

128 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

and integrating with respect to the distribution of agent i’s type we have:

Eτi {yi (τi )} + Eτ−i {y−i (τ−i )} ≤ Eτi {xi (τi )} = θi ,

establishing part (i) of the lemma.Now, consider part (ii) of the lemma. It is easy to check from the first-order con-

ditions of agent j’s maximization problem that given y− j (τ− j ), the equilibrium con-tribution y j (τ j ) of agent j is non-decreasing in the type τ j of agent j . Thus, if τ <

τ ′, τ, τ ′ ∈ A j and y j (τ ) > 0, then y j (τ′) > 0. Further, using (4),

1 = τ

∫V ′

j (y j (τ ) + y− j (τ− j )) dF− j (τ− j )

< τ ′∫

V ′j (y j (τ ) + y− j (τ− j )) dF− j (τ− j )

so that y j (τ′) > y j (τ ). Since Pr{τ j : y j (τ j ) > 0} > 0 for some j �= i , the total con-

tribution of agents other than agent i , y−i (τ−i ), is a non-degenerate random variable(by Lemma 2). Therefore, using strict concavity of V ′

i (.) on [0, G] (assumed in part(ii) of the lemma), the fact that y j (τ j )+ y− j (τ− j ) ∈ [0, G] almost surely (Lemma 1),and Jensen’s inequality, we have from (4)

τi V ′i (yi (τi ) + Eτ−i {y−i (τ−i )}) > 1, τi -almost surely,

so that using strict concavity of Vi (.) on [0, G] (Assumption 2) and (1) it follows that

yi (τi ) + Eτ−i {y−i (τ−i )} < xi (τi ), τi -almost surely

and integrating with respect to the distribution of agent i’s type we have:

Eτi {yi (τi )} + Eτ−i {y−i (τ−i )} < Eτi {xi (τi )} = θi ,

establishing part (ii) of the lemma. The next result follows immediately from Lemma 3:

Corollary 1 Suppose there is a Bayesian-Nash equilibrium of the simultaneous movecontribution game where for all i ∈ {1, . . . , N }, yi (τi ), the equilibrium contributionof agent i of type τi , satisfies yi (τi ) > 0, τi -almost surely. Then, the expected totalcontribution in this equilibrium does not exceed min{θi : i = 1, . . . , N }. If, further,V ′

i (G) is strictly concave on [0, G] for all i ∈ {1, . . . , N }, then the expected totalcontribution in this equilibrium is strictly less than min{θi : i = 1, . . . , N }.

4 Sequential contribution game

In this section, we analyze the sequential contribution games where agents contributein an exogenous order of moves with each agent contributing only once.

123

Page 11: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 129

Let

P = {p = (p1, . . . , pN ) : (p1, . . . , pN ) is a permutation of (1, . . . , N )}.

For each p = (p1, . . . , pN ) ∈ P , we can define an N -stage sequential contribu-tion game �(p) where agent pi contributes (only) in the i-th stage after observingcontributions made in all previous stages 1, . . . , i − 1.

We first specify a lower bound on the total contribution that depends on the lastmover’s type:

Lemma 4 In any perfect Bayesian equilibrium of �(p), for each possible realizationτ of the type of the last mover pN , the total contribution generated is at least as largeas x pN (τ ), her standalone contribution for type τ , and the expected total contributiongenerated in the game is at least as large as θpN , the expected standalone contributionof agent pN .

Proof The proof follows from the fact that if z ≥ 0 is the total contribution of agentsin the first (N −1) stages, then in the last stage of the game, the unique optimal actionof agent pN of type τ is to contribute max{0, x pN (τ ) − z}.

Next, we argue that as long as the total contribution generated in the first (N − 1)

stages is strictly positive with some probability, the expected total contribution gener-ated in the sequential game is strictly higher than the expected standalone contributionof the last mover. The main argument here is that earlier contributors know that evenif they contribute zero, the last mover will ensure that the total contribution is at leastas large as her standalone contribution (depending on her realized true type). If thetotal contribution on the equilibrium path in the first (N −1) stages is below the stand-alone level for the lowest type of the contributor in stage N , then the last contributorwho contributes strictly positive amount (for some realization of her type) among thefirst (N − 1) movers will always be better off deviating and contributing zero withprobability one. Therefore, on an equilibrium path where total contribution in first(N − 1) stages is strictly positive (with strictly positive probability), it must exceedthe standalone level of the N -th contributor for the very low realizations of her type.

Lemma 5 In any perfect Bayesian equilibrium of �(p) where the total contributiongenerated in the first (N − 1) stages is strictly positive with strictly positive probabil-ity, the expected total contribution is strictly higher than θpN , the expected standalonecontribution of agent pN .

Proof In view of Lemma 4, it is sufficient to show that for an event (i.e., a set oftype profiles for N agents) of strictly positive probability measure, the generated totalcontributions must strictly exceed the standalone contributions of agent pN (corre-sponding to her realized types in those type profiles).

For each realization of types of the first (N −1) contributors ω ∈∏N−1i=1 Ai , let z(ω)

be the total contribution generated in the first (N − 1) stages. Observe that the uniqueoptimal action of agent pN of type τ in stage N is to contribute max{0, x pN (τ ) − z},

123

Page 12: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

130 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

if the total contribution in the first (N − 1) stages is z. We claim that since z(ω) > 0with strictly positive probability, it must be the case that

z(ω) > x pN (τ pN) with strictly positive probability. (5)

Suppose, to the contrary, that z(ω) ≤ x pN (τ pN) almost surely. Then, given the optimal

strategy of agent pN , the total contribution generated at the end of the game is exactlyidentical to that generated if every agent contributes zero with probability one in thefirst (N − 1) stages. In particular, let

k = max{1 ≤ n ≤ N − 1: agent pn makes strictly positive contribution

with strictly positive probability}.

By definition, for all n lying strictly between k and N , no contribution occurs (almostsurely) on the equilibrium path in stage n. Consider a unilateral deviation where agentpk contributes zero almost surely and independent of history. The distribution of totalcontribution generated at the end of the game remains unchanged (as the last movermakes up the difference). Therefore, this deviation is strictly beneficial for agent pN−k .This establishes (5). From (5), it follows that there exists ε > 0 small enough suchthat

Pr

{ω ∈

N−1∏

i=1

Ai : z(ω) > x pN (τ pN) + ε

}> 0. (6)

Let τ > τ pNbe defined by:

τ V ′pN

(x pN (τ pN) + ε) = 1.

Choose τ ∈ (τ pN, τ ). Since τ pN

= min{τ : τ ∈ ApN } and ApN is the support of theprobability distribution of τpN , it follows that FpN (τ ) > 0. Also note that

x pN (τ ) < x pN (τ pN) + ε,∀τ ∈ ApN ∩ [τ pN

, τ ], (7)

as xi (τi ) is strictly increasing in τi for all i. Let

B1 ={

ω ∈N−1∏

i=1

Ai : z(ω) > x pN (τ ), τ ∈ ApN ∩ [τ pN, τ ]}

.

Then, using (6),

Pr(B1) > 0.

Let B be the event:

B = {(τp1 , . . . , τpN−1) ∈ B1, τpN ≤ τ }.

123

Page 13: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 131

Since Pr(B1) > 0 and FpN (τ ) > 0, it follows that Pr(B) > 0. Further, using (6) and(7), for realizations of type profiles (of all players) in the set B, the generated totalcontributions strictly exceed the standalone contributions of agent pN . The proof iscomplete.

Finally, note that the set of perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcomes of the sequentialgame �(p) is identical to the set of perfect Bayesian equilibrium outcomes generatedwhen the extensive form is modified so that in stage i , i = 2, . . . , N , agent pi observesperfectly the sum of the actual contributions made by agents p1, . . . , pi−1, but nottheir individual contributions. Note that the payoff of each agent depends only on thetotal contribution generated at the end of the game (and not on individual contributionlevels) and further, each agent contributes only once so that any information about theprivate preferences of an agent inferred from her individual contribution level is ofno relevance to agents who move later. The strategy sets of players in the modifiedsequential game is a subset of that in �(p). However, sequential rationality ensuresthat in any perfect Bayesian equilibrium of �(p), at each stage of the game and for eachrealized history, the strategy of the player of any type who moves at that stage mustspecify an action that is also optimal if the player observes only the total contributiongenerated (at the end of the previous stage for that realized history). Therefore, forany perfect Bayesian equilibrium of �(p), working backwards from the last stage andsubstituting strategies of players that possibly depend on individual past contributionsby ones that depend only on the sum of previous contributions, one can construct aperfect Bayesian equilibrium of the modified sequential game that is outcome equiva-lent. Our results in the subsequent sections comparing the expected total contributionsgenerated in the sequential and simultaneous move games are therefore equally validfor versions of the sequential move game where individual contributions are observedimperfectly but the cumulative contribution generated before each stage is observedperfectly.

5 Comparison of contributions

We now present the paper’s main results comparing the expected total contributionsgenerated in the simultaneous and sequential move contribution games.

First, we provide sufficient conditions under which sequential move games thatsatisfy a certain restriction on the order of moves (specifically, in terms of who movesin the last stage) generate weakly greater expected total contributions compared to thesimultaneous move game.

Proposition 1 Consider any Bayesian-Nash equilibrium E of the simultaneous movecontribution game where some agent i makes a strictly positive contribution τi -almostsurely. Then, every perfect Bayesian equilibrium of the N-stage sequential move game�(p) where p = (p1, . . . , pN ) and pN = i , generates at least as much expected totalcontribution as in the Bayesian-Nash equilibrium E of the simultaneous move game.

Proof Follows immediately from Lemma 3 and Lemma 4. Next, we state sufficient conditions under which a sequential move game generates

strictly higher expected total contributions compared to the simultaneous move game.

123

Page 14: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

132 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

Proposition 2 Consider any Bayesian-Nash equilibrium E of the simultaneous movecontribution game where some agent i makes a strictly positive contribution τi -almostsurely. Consider any perfect Bayesian equilibrium E of the sequential move contribu-tion game �(p) where p = (p1, . . . , pN ) and pN = i . Suppose, further, that at leastone of the following hold:

(a) Imperfect Free-Riding: In equilibrium E of the sequential game �(p), ∃� �= i(i.e., some agent who moves in one of the first (N − 1) stages) who contributesstrictly positive amount with strictly positive probability;

(b) V ′i (G) is strictly concave on [0, G] and there exists some agent j �= i such

that in the equilibrium E of the simultaneous move contribution game Pr{τ j :y j (τ j ) > 0} > 0.

Then, equilibrium E of the sequential move contribution game �(p) generates strictlyhigher expected total contribution than equilibrium E of the simultaneous move game.

Proof If (a) holds, then the result follows from Lemma 3(i) and Lemma 5. If (b) holds,then the result follows from Lemma 3(ii) and Lemma 4.

The conditions in Proposition 1 and Proposition 2 are strong sufficient conditions;in particular, the conclusions of Proposition 1 and Proposition 2 may hold even ifthe last mover in the sequential move game is one who contributes zero with positiveprobability in the simultaneous move game and in fact, even if all players contributezero with positive probability in the simultaneous move game. We will illustrate thesepossibilities in examples in Sect. 7.

The next result follows immediately from Proposition 1 and Corollary 1:

Corollary 2 Consider any Bayesian-Nash equilibrium E of the simultaneous movecontribution game where every agent makes strictly positive contribution almost surely.Then, for every p ∈ P, every perfect Bayesian equilibrium of the N-stage sequen-tial move game �(p) generates at least as much expected total contribution as inequilibrium E of the simultaneous move game.

Corollary 2 clarifies that if the equilibrium of the simultaneous move game (towhich one compares the outcomes of the sequential games) is an “interior equilib-rium” where all agents of “almost” all types contribute strictly positive amounts, thenthere is no need to impose any restriction on the order of moves in the sequential gameto ensure that it generates weakly higher expected total contributions.

Similarly, using Proposition 2 and Corollary 1, we have immediately:

Corollary 3 Consider any Bayesian-Nash equilibrium E of the simultaneous movecontribution game where every agent makes strictly positive contribution almost surely.Suppose, further, that at least one of the following holds:

(a) ∀p ∈ P, in every perfect Bayesian equilibrium of the N-stage sequential movegame �(p), some agent who moves in the first (N −1) stages contributes strictlypositive amount with strictly positive probability;

(b) V ′i (G) is strictly concave on [0, G], ∀i ∈ {1, . . . , N }.

123

Page 15: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 133

Then, for every p ∈ P, every perfect Bayesian equilibrium of the N-stage sequentialmove game �(p) generates strictly higher expected total contribution than equilibriumE of the simultaneous move game.

Corollary 3 indicates that if the equilibrium of the simultaneous move game is an“interior equilibrium” then, under certain additional conditions, the sequential movegame generates strictly higher expected total contributions independent of the orderof moves.

The results outlined in this section indicate that the sequential contribution gamegenerates at least as much expected total contribution as in any equilibrium of thesimultaneous contribution game where the agent who moves last in the sequentialgame contributes a strictly positive amount with probability one. Showing that thesequential game generates strictly higher expected contribution requires that eitherthe marginal utility from the public good is strictly concave or, that the equilibrium ofthe sequential game is one where the last mover is not the only one that contributes(imperfect free riding).

One implication of this is that we are not able to say anything in general about thecomparison of the contributions generated in the sequential game to that in a non-interior equilibrium of the simultaneous move game where, for example, every agentcontributes zero for certain realization of types (that occur with strictly positive proba-bility); the technical difficulty here is that the first-order conditions no longer hold withequality for all realizations of types (of a player) and this makes it difficult to obtaina useful bound on the equilibrium expected total contribution. In the next section, weprovide explicit verifiable conditions on the payoff function and the distribution oftypes that ensure that no equilibrium of simultaneous move game is non-interior, andanother set of conditions to ensure that in the sequential game, the last mover is notthe only one who contributes. Under these conditions, our results on comparison ofcontributions in this section can be applied independent of which equilibrium we selectfor each extensive form. Finally, in Sect. 7, we show that for the special case of twoagents and two types, the sequential move game may generate strictly higher expectedtotal contribution even if all agents contribute zero with strictly positive probability(equilibrium is non-interior) in the simultaneous move game. Thus, the conditionsoutlined in this section should be seen as sufficient conditions that are by no meansnecessary for the superiority of the sequential contribution scheme.

6 Further conditions

In the previous section, we outlined some conditions under which the expected totalvoluntary contribution generated in a sequential move game exceeds (weakly orstrictly) that generated in a simultaneous move game. One restriction that is required inall of the results outlined in the previous section is that in the Bayesian-Nash equilib-rium of the simultaneous move game, a certain agent (in particular, the one who moveslast in the sequential game) must contribute strictly positive amount for almost everypossible realization of her type. Another condition that ensures that the sequentialgame generates strictly higher expected total contribution requires that in the perfectBayesian equilibrium of the N -stage sequential game, free-riding is imperfect, i.e.,

123

Page 16: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

134 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

some agent moving in the first (N −1) stages contributes strictly positive amount withstrictly positive probability.

In this section, we outline some sufficient and verifiable conditions on the exoge-nous preferences and distributions of types that ensure that the equilibria of the relevantgames satisfy the two properties noted above. It is worth emphasizing that the condi-tions to be stated are by no means tight. One should view them as merely illustrative ofhow the antecedents of the main propositions (and corollaries) in the previous sectionmay hold and as indicating that, in particular, the propositions are not vacuous.

While the conditions can be easily written for the general version of the modeloutlined in Sect. 2, for ease of exposition we will assume that:

Assumption 4 Vi (G) = V (G), ∀i ∈ {1, . . . , N }.Note that Assumption 4 allows for the possibility that agents differ in the distri-

bution of types (i.e., the distribution function Fi need not be identical) so that somedegree of asymmetry between players is allowed for. However, preferences now onlydepend on the type of the agent and not on her identity.

First, we provide an easily verifiable condition under which there exists an agentwho contributes strictly positive amount with probability one in the simultaneous movegame. The condition, however, requires that the distribution of types assigns strictlypositive mass to the lowest type of each player.

Lemma 6 Let μ−k = ∏j �=k

Pr{τ j = τ j }, and i ∈ argmaxk∈{1,...,n} τ kμ−k .10 Suppose

that

minj=1,...,N

Pr{τ j = τ j } > 0,

and V ′(0) >1

τ iμ−i. (8)

Then, in any equilibrium of the simultaneous move game, at least one player contrib-utes strictly positive amount with probability one.

Proof Suppose there is an equilibrium of the simultaneous move game where everyplayer contributes zero with strictly positive probability. Consider player i of type τ iwho contributes zero. Then, the total contribution of all other players is zero withprobability μ−i and is bounded above by (N − 1)x(τ ) with probability 1 − μ−i ,where τ = max j=1,...,N τ j . The marginal expected payoff of player i of type τ i (atzero contribution) is

≥ τ i [μ−i V ′(0) + (1 − μ−i )V ′((N − 1)x(τ ))] − 1.

10 Here the notation,∏

, denotes multiplication.

123

Page 17: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 135

So, if

τ [μ−i V ′(0) + (1 − μ−i )V ′((N − 1)x(τ ))] > 1, (9)

which is implied by (8), then we immediately obtain a contradiction. It should be clear that condition (8) is significantly more stringent than what is

required, and that interior contribution by some player does not really require strictlypositive mass point at the lowest type (though an easily verifiable sufficient conditionmay be more difficult to specify for a continuous distribution function). For specificpreferences, one can provide much weaker conditions under which all players makestrictly positive contributions with probability one in a simultaneous move game. Thefollowing example considers a symmetric two-players game with quadratic utility forthe public good.

Example 1 Let N = 2 and

V (G) ={ [1 − (1 − G)2], 0 ≤ G ≤ 1

1, G > 1.

Let F1 = F2 = F where the support of F is the interval [τ , τ ]. We do not require anyprobability mass point at τ . We assume:

1

2< τ < τ < 1

and,

τ >2

2 + m, where m = E

(1

τ

).

Check that x(τ ) = 1 − 1/(2τ) ∈ (0, 1), τ ∈ [τ , τ ]. It is easy to check that Assump-tions 1–4 are satisfied.11 Consider the simultaneous move contribution game. Thefollowing is a symmetric Bayesian-Nash equilibrium: each player of type τ ∈ [τ , τ ]contributes:

y(τ ) = 1

2

(1 − 1

τ+ m

2

).

Observe that since τ > 22+m ,

y(τ ) > 0, ∀τ ∈ [τ , τ ].

11 Also note that V ′(.) is linear (hence, concave) and strictly decreasing (V (.) is strictly concave) on [0, 1].Here, set G = 2 − 1

τ.

123

Page 18: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

136 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

To see that this is an equilibrium, suppose agent 2 contributes according to strategyy(τ ). Then, consider agent 1’s first-order condition for an interior solution to hermaximization problem when she is of type τ :

2τ Eτ2 [(1 − y1 − y(τ2))] = 1

i.e.,1

2τ= (1 − y1) − Eτ2 [y(τ2)] = (1 − y1) − 1

2

(1 − m

2

),

which yields

y1 = 1

2

(1 − 1

τ+ m

2

)= y(τ ).

Thus, both players playing according to the strategy y(τ ) is a Bayesian-Nash equilib-rium.

Next, we outline a condition under which the total contribution generated in thefirst (N − 1) stages of the sequential move game is strictly positive with strictlypositive probability so that the antecedent of Lemma 5 and one of the conditions inProposition 2(b) and Corollary 3 hold.

To begin, let

τ = min{τ i : i = 1, . . . , N }τ = max{τ i : i = 1, . . . , N }.

Define the function x(τ ) on the entire interval [τ , τ ] by:

x(τ ) = argmaxx τ V (x) − x, τ ∈ [τ , τ ].

Under Assumption 1,

1 < τ i V ′i (0) = τ i V ′(0), i = 1, . . . , N ,

so that x(τ ) ∈ (0, G],∀τ ∈ [τ , τ ], and

τ V ′(x(τ )) = 1.

Note that x(τ ) is the optimal “standalone” contribution of any player of type τ i.e.,xi (τi ) = x(τi ), ∀τi ∈ Ai , ∀i = 1, . . . , N , where xi (τi ) is as defined in Sect. 2. Also,note that x(τ ) is continuous and strictly increasing on [τ , τ ].Lemma 7 Consider any sequential contribution game �(p) where p = (p1, . . . , pN )

and pN = i . Let j ∈ {p1, . . . , pN−1} be an agent such that

τ j ≥ τ p�, � = 1, . . . , N − 1. (10)

123

Page 19: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 137

If

1

τ

τ∫

τ i

(1 − x(τ )

x (τ )) dFi (τ ) >

1

τ j(11)

for some τ ∈ (τ i , τ i ) , then in any perfect Bayesian equilibrium of �(p), some agentwho moves in the first (N − 1) stages contributes strictly positive amount with strictlypositive probability i.e., free-riding is necessarily imperfect.

Proof Suppose, to the contrary, that there exists a perfect Bayesian equilibrium of �

where the total contribution generated in the first (N − 1) stages is zero almost surely.It is easy to check that in that case, the contribution generated at the end of the game isexactly the standalone contribution x(τ ) of the last mover i , depending on her realizedtype τ ∈ Ai .

Consider agent j (as defined in (10)) who moves in one of the first N − 1 stages.We will show that it is strictly gainful for agent j of type τ j to deviate and contributea strictly positive amount. The smoothness of the payoff function in τ then impliesthat there exists ε > 0 such that deviation is strictly gainful for all types τ j of playerj lying in [τ j − ε, τ j ]. As τ j = sup{τ : τ ∈ A j } where A j is the support of thedistribution function Fj , it follows that

Pr{τ j ∈ [τ j − ε, τ j ]} > 0

which would be a contradiction.In the rest of this proof we will show that it is strictly gainful for agent j of type

τ j to deviate and contribute an amount equal to x (τ ) > 0 where τ is as defined in theproposition.

Following such a deviation by agent j of type τ j , the total contribution at the endof the game is at least as large as x (τ ) if the last player’s (player i’s) type τi ≤ τ , whileif τi > τ then the total contribution is at least as large as x(τi ). Thus, the expectedutility of the deviating agent j of type τ j is:

≥ τ j

⎢⎣τ∫

τ i

V (x (τ )) dFi (τi ) +τi∫

τ

V (x(τi )) dFi (τi )

⎥⎦− x (τ ),

and so this deviation is gainful as long as:

τ j

τ i∫

τ i

V (x(τi )) dFi (τi ) < τ j

⎢⎣τ∫

τ i

V (x (τ )) dFi (τi ) +τi∫

τ

V (x(τi )) dFi (τi )

⎥⎦− x (τ ),

123

Page 20: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

138 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

which is equivalent to:

τ j

⎢⎣τ∫

τ i

{V (x (τ )) − V (x(τi ))} dFi (τi )

⎥⎦ > x (τ ). (12)

We want to derive a sufficient condition such that (12) holds for some τ ∈ (τ i , τ i ).As V is concave,

V (x (τ )) − V (x(τi )) ≥ V ′(x (τ ))(x (τ ) − x(τi )) = 1

ττ V ′(x (τ ))(x (τ ) − x(τi ))

= 1

τ(x (τ ) − x(τi )).

Therefore, (12) holds as long as

τ j

τ

⎢⎣τ∫

τ i

(x (τ ) − x(τi )) dFi (τi )

⎥⎦ > x (τ )

i.e.,1

τ

τ∫

τ i

(1 − x(τi )

x (τ )

)dFi (τi ) >

1

τ j

which follows from (11).

Since∫ τ

τ i

(1 − x(τi )

x (τ )

)dFi (τi ) > 0, condition (11) is likely to be satisfied for some

τ ∈ (τ i , τ i ) if τ j is large enough. Further, larger the probability mass of the distribu-tion of types in a neighborhood of τ i , the easier it is for this condition to hold.

The economic intuition is that greater the likelihood that the last mover has verylow valuation for the public good, greater the risk faced by an early mover with highvaluation for the public good when she tries to fully free ride on the last mover becausethat may, in certain states of nature, lead to very low provision of the public good. Thiscreates incentive for an early mover with high valuation to make a strictly positivecontribution. It is easy to see that (11) is more likely to hold if an early mover hassignificantly “higher” distribution of valuations (types) than the last mover. Indeed,even under complete information, an early mover may not free ride on the last mover,and may contribute a strictly positive amount if her valuation of the public good issignificantly higher than the last mover.

If agents are identical, then under complete information, early movers always freeride fully on the last mover. With incomplete information however, even if all agentshave identical distribution of types, early movers may not fully free ride on the lastmover—this, in fact, is a crucial difference between the complete and incompleteinformation sequential games. We illustrate this in the next example where all agentshave identical distribution of types and for a specific class of distribution functions,

123

Page 21: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 139

we show that (11) can be satisfied (so that some early mover contributes a strictlypositive amount with strictly positive probability).

Example 2 Suppose that Fi = F,∀i ∈ {1, . . . , N }, where the support of F is theinterval [τ , τ ] and F has the following structure:

F(τ ) ={

(1 − ε)G(τ ), τ ≤ τ ≤ τ

(1 − ε) + εH(τ ), τ ≤ τ ≤ τ ,

where 0 < ε < 1, τ ∈ (τ , τ ), G(τ ) is any probability distribution function withsupport [τ , τ ] satisfying

0 ≤ G(τ ) < G (τ ) = 1,

and H(τ ) is a probability distribution function with support [τ , τ ], satisfyingH (τ ) = 0.

Then, (11) reduces to the requirement that:

1 <τ

τ

⎢⎣τ∫

τ

(1 − x(τ )

x (τ )

)dF(τ )

⎥⎦

= τ

⎧⎪⎨

⎪⎩1 − ε

τ

⎢⎣τ∫

τ

(1 − x(τ )

x (τ )

)dG(τ )

⎥⎦

⎫⎪⎬

⎪⎭

= τ

⎧⎪⎨

⎪⎩1 − ε

τ

⎢⎣1 − 1

x (τ )

τ∫

τ

x(τ ) dG(τ )

⎥⎦

⎫⎪⎬

⎪⎭. (13)

As∫ τ

τx(τ ) dG(τ ) < x (τ ),

⎢⎣1 − 1

x (τ )

τ∫

τ

x(τ ) dG(τ )

⎥⎦ > 0.

Since H, τ are independent of the distribution function G whose support is [τ , τ ],⎧⎪⎨

⎪⎩1 − ε

τ

⎢⎣1 − 1

x (τ )

τ∫

τ

x(τ ) dG(τ )

⎥⎦

⎫⎪⎬

⎪⎭

is independent of H and τ in particular, so (13) holds if τ is large enough.

123

Page 22: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

140 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

Finally, we note that condition (13) that ensures strictly positive contribution bysome early mover in the sequential game is consistent with the last mover of the sequen-tial game making strictly positive contribution with probability one in the simultaneousmove game (as required in some of the results of the previous section). To illustratethis, consider Example 2 above. The sufficient condition (8) in Lemma 6 that ensuresthat some player contributes strictly positive amount almost surely is satisfied as longas:

η = limτ↓τ

G(τ ) > 0

and V ′(0) >1

τ((1 − ε)η)N−1 ,

and these are perfectly consistent with τ being large enough so that (13) holds.

7 A special case: two agents, two types

In this section, we discuss a special case of our model with two agents (N = 2) andtwo potential types. We use this to make two important points.

First, though our general results in Sect. 5 require that at least some agent contrib-utes strictly positive amount with probability one in the simultaneous move game (inorder to obtain weakly or strictly higher expected total contribution in the sequentialmove game), this is by no means necessary. We show that even if all agents contributezero with strictly positive probability in the simultaneous move game, the sequentialmove game may still generate strictly higher expected total contribution.

Second, our general results in Sect. 5 show that when the last mover is the one whocontributes strictly positive amount almost surely in the simultaneous move game,the sequential game generates weakly higher expected total contribution (and underadditional conditions, strictly higher contributions). We show that even if the agentwho contributes strictly positive amount with probability one in the simultaneousmove game moves early in the sequential game and the last mover is an agent whocontributes zero with strictly positive probability in the simultaneous move game, thesequential game may still generate strictly higher expected total contribution.

In this section, we assume that Assumptions 1–4 hold so that

Vi (G) = V (G), i = 1, 2,

and further restrict:

Ai = {τL , τH }, with 0 < πi = Pr[τi = τH ] < 1, i = 1, 2.

Proposition 1 shows that there is a sequential game that generates weakly higherexpected total contribution than the simultaneous move game as long as there is atleast one agent who contributes strictly positive amount in the simultaneous movegame for (almost) every realization of her type. If, in addition, the requirements ofProposition 2 are satisfied, then the sequential game generates strictly higher expected

123

Page 23: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 141

total contributions. If the simultaneous move game is such that every agent contrib-utes zero with positive probability, then the results outlined in the previous section nolonger apply. However, for the special case considered in this section, we can show thatunder certain conditions, the sequential contribution game generates higher expectedtotal contribution even though the equilibrium in the simultaneous move game is onewhere both agents contribute zero when their realized type is τL . Thus, the interiorityof equilibrium contributions (for some agent) is not necessary for higher contributionsunder the sequential form of the contribution game.

Recall that x(τ ) is the “standalone” contribution of type τ as defined earlier.

Proposition 3 Suppose that

x(τH )

x(τL)< min

{1

πi, 2πk + 1 − πk

πi

}, (14)

where

πk = max{π1, π2}, and i �= k.

Then, the expected total contribution generated in any perfect Bayesian equilibriumof the sequential game �(p), where p = (p1, p2) and p2 = k, is strictly greater thanthat generated in any Bayesian-Nash equilibrium of the simultaneous contributiongame where both agents contribute zero when their realized type is τL .

The proof appears in the Appendix.For π1 = π2 = 1

2 , (14) reduces to the requirement that x(τH ) < 2x(τL), which isquite easily satisfied as long as τL and τH are not too far apart.

Next, we point out that even if the sequential move game is such that the agent (oragents) who contribute strictly positive amount for all realization of types in the simul-taneous move game move earlier than other agents, the sequential move game maystill generate higher expected total contribution than the simultaneous move game.We illustrate this in the example (summarized) below where within the framework oftwo agents and two types considered in this section, we choose a specific quadraticfunctional form for the V (.) function.

Example 3 Let

V (G) ={ [1 − (1 − G)2], 0 ≤ G ≤ 1

1, G > 1.

Here, x(τ ) = 1 − 1/(2τ), τ = τH , τL . Note that V ′(.) is linear (hence, concave) andstrictly decreasing (V (.) is strictly concave) on [0, 1]. Here, G = 2 − 1

τH. Assump-

tions 1–4 are satisfied as long as τL > 12 , τH < 1.

Suppose π j > πi . Consider the sequential move game �(p) where p = ( j, i) i.e.,player j moves first and player i moves next. It can be checked that if

πi ≤ max

{0, 1 − τL

τH

[2τL +

√4τ 2

L − 1

]}, (15)

123

Page 24: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

142 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

then the first-mover (player j) of τH -type makes a strictly positive contribution in the(unique perfect Bayesian equilibrium of the) sequential move game and the expectedtotal contribution generated is:

z = (πi + π j )x(τH ) + (1 − πi )(1 − π j )x(τL) − πiπ j .

In the simultaneous move game, it can be shown that there is a unique Bayesian-Nash equilibrium and in this equilibrium, agent j makes a strictly positive con-tribution for both realization of types, while agent i makes a strictly positivecontribution y only if it is of τH -type. The expected total contribution in the simulta-neous move game is exactly equal to the expected standalone contribution of agent j

i.e., y = π j x(τH ) + (1 − π j )x(τL). Observe that z − y =[

1−π jτL

− 1τH

] [πi2

]> 0 if

π j < 1 − τL

τH. (16)

Thus, even though the agent who has strictly higher probability of being τH -typeand contributes strictly positive amount almost surely in the simultaneous move gamemoves first in the sequential move game and the agent who does not contribute strictlypositive amount almost surely in the simultaneous move game is the last mover in thesequential move game, the sequential game generates (strictly) higher expected totalcontribution relative to the simultaneous move game if (15) and (16) hold.

Appendix

Proof of Lemma 2 First, observe that in any equilibrium of the simultaneous movegame, the first-order condition for any player j of type τ is given by:

E

⎣τ j V ′j

⎝y j (τ j ) +∑

k �= j

yk

⎦ = 1, if y j (τ j ) > 0

≤ 1, if y j (τ j ) = 0

(where the expectation is taken with respect to the distribution of∑

k �= j yk). Usingthe strict concavity of Vj (.) in the relevant range, it is easy to check that each playerj’s equilibrium contribution is weakly increasing in his type τ j and, further, strictlyincreasing over the range of types τ j where y j (τ j ) > 0. Therefore, for any fixed playeri , the lower bound (infimum) of the support of the distribution of y−i =∑ j �=i y j , thetotal equilibrium contributions of all players other than i (whether or not they contrib-ute a strictly positive amount), is given by their total contribution in the state whereτ j = τ ,∀ j �= i , and the upper bound (supremum) of the support of the distribution ofy−i is given by their total contribution in the state where τ j = τ ,∀ j �= i . These twobounds cannot be identical unless all players other than player i contribute zero withprobability one, and the latter is not possible given that Pr{τ j : y j (τ j ) > 0} for somej �= i .

123

Page 25: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 143

Proof of Proposition 3 Let y1(τ ), y2(τ ), τ = τH , τL , denote the equilibrium contri-butions of the two agents in the simultaneous move game where

y1(τL) = y2(τL) = 0.

The first-order condition of maximization for agent i of type τL yields for i, j =1, 2, j �= i,

π jτL V ′(y j (τH )) + (1 − π j )τL V ′(0) ≤ 1. (17)

Using Assumption 2,

π jτL V ′(x(τL)) + (1 − π j )τL V ′(0) > 1, (18)

which implies that (comparing (17) and (18))

y j (τH ) > x(τL) > 0, j = 1, 2.

From the first-order condition for agent i of type τH we have for i, j = 1, 2, j �= i ,

π jτH V ′(yi (τH ) + y j (τH )) + (1 − π j )τH V ′(yi (τH )) = 1 (19)

so that

τH V ′(yi (τH )) > 1, i = 1, 2 (20)

and therefore yi (τH ) < x(τH ), i = 1, 2. Thus,

x(τL) < y j (τH ) < x(τH ), j = 1, 2. (21)

The expected total contribution generated in this game is

[π1 y1(τH ) + π2 y2(τH )].

Further, from the first-order conditions:

π1V ′(y1(τH ) + y2(τH )) + (1 − π1)V ′(y2(τH )) = 1

τH= V ′(x(τH )) (22)

π2V ′(y1(τH ) + y2(τH )) + (1 − π2)V ′(y1(τH )) = 1

τH= V ′(x(τH )) (23)

and using the concavity of V ′(.) on [0, G] and Jensen’s inequality we have:

π1 y1(τH ) + y2(τH ) ≤ x(τH ) (24)

π2 y2(τH ) + y1(τH ) ≤ x(τH ). (25)

123

Page 26: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

144 P. K. Bag, S. Roy

Also, from (22) and (23), V ′(y1(τH ) + y2(τH )) < V ′(x(τH )) so that

y1(τH ) + y2(τH ) > x(τH ). (26)

From (21) and (26),

y1(τH ) + y2(τH ) > max{x(τH ), 2x(τL)}. (27)

Multiply (24) by π2 and (25) by π1 and add to obtain

π1π2 y1(τH ) + π2 y2(τH ) + π1π2 y2(τH ) + π1 y1(τH ) ≤ (π1 + π2)x(τH ),

implying

π1 y1(τH ) + π2 y2(τH )

≤ (π1 + π2)x(τH ) − π1π2[y1(τH ) + y2(τH )]= [πk x(τH ) + (1 − πk)x(τL)] + [πi {x(τH ) − πk[yi (τH ) + yk(τH )]}]

−(1 − πk)x(τL), i �= k

<︸︷︷︸using (27)

πk x(τH ) + (1 − πk)x(τL) + [πi {x(τH ) − πk · max{x(τH ), 2x(τL)}}]

−(1 − πk)x(τL)

< πk x(τH ) + (1 − πk)x(τL). (using (14))

Therefore, the expected total contribution in this equilibrium of the simultaneous movegame π1 y1(τH ) + π2 y2(τH ) < πk x(τH ) + (1 − πk)x(τL), the expected standalonecontribution of agent k. Finally, from Lemma 4, we know that in the sequential movegame �(p) where p = (p1, p2), p2 = k i.e., agent k is the last mover, the expectedtotal contribution generated is at least as large as the expected standalone contribution[πk x(τH ) + (1 − πk)x(τL)] of agent k. The proposition follows. Acknowledgments We thank two anonymous referees, William Thomson (editor of IJGT), MuraliAgastya and Rajiv Sethi for helpful suggestions and discussions. An earlier version of this work was pre-sented at the APET-Singapore Workshop (2008), Jadavpur University (India) Annual Conference (2008),and the Royal Economic Society Conference (2009). For errors or omissions, we remain responsible.

References

Admati A, Perry M (1991) Joint projects without commitment. Rev Econ Stud 58:259–276Agastya M (2009) Transparency of peer activities confounds cheap talk in joint projects. University of

Sydney (Economics) Working paperAgastya M, Menezes F, Sengupta K (2007) Cheap talk, efficiency and egalitarian cost sharing in joint

projects. Games Econ Behav 60:1–19Andreoni J (1998) Toward a theory of charitable fund-raising. J Polit Econ 106:1186–1213Andreoni J (2006) Philanthropy. In: Kolm S-C, Mercier Ythier J (eds) Handbook of giving, reciprocity and

altruism. North Holland, Amsterdam pp 1201–1269Bag PK, Roy S (2008) Repeated charitable contributions under incomplete information. Econ J 118:60–91

123

Page 27: On sequential and simultaneous contributions under ...faculty.smu.edu/sroy/Seqcontr_IJGT_article.pdfDallas, TX 75275-0496, USA e-mail: sroy@smu.edu 123. 120 P. K. Bag, S. Roy ... movers

On sequential and simultaneous contributions under incomplete information 145

Bessen J, Maskin E (2009) Sequential innovation, patents and imitation. Rand J Econ 40:611–635Bliss C, Nalebuff B (1984) Dragon-slaying and ballroom dancing. J Public Econ 25:1–12Coats JC, Gronberg TJ, Grosskopf B (2009) Simultaneous versus sequential public good provision and the

role of refunds—an experimental study. J Public Econ 93:326–335Cremer J, Riordan MH (1985) A sequential solution to the public goods problem. Econometrica 53:77–84Fershtman C, Nitzan S (1991) Dynamic voluntary provision of public goods. Eur Econ Rev 35:1057–1067Glazer A, Konrad KC (1996) A signaling explanation for charity. Am Econ Rev 86:1019–1028Gradstein M (1992) Time dynamics and incomplete information in the private provision of public goods.

J Polit Econ 100:581–597Harbaugh W (1998) What do donations buy? A model of philanthropy based on prestige and warm glow.

J Public Econ 67:269–284Jackson MO, Moulin H (1992) Implementing a public project and distributing its cost. J Econ Theory

57:125–140List J, Lucking-Reiley D (2002) The effects of seed money and refunds on charitable giving: Experimental

evidence from a university capital campaign. J Polit Econ 110:215–233Marx LM, Matthews SA (2000) Dynamic voluntary contribution to a public project. Rev Econ Stud 67:

327–358Menezes F, Monteiro PK, Temimi A (2001) Private provision of discrete public goods with incomplete

information. J Math Econ 35:493–514Palfrey TR, Rosenthal H (1988) Private incentives in social dilemmas: the effects of incomplete information

and altruism. J Public Econ 35:309–332Potters J, Sefton M, Vesterlund L (2005) After you—endogenous sequencing in voluntary contribution

games. J Public Econ 89:1399–1419Romano R, Yildirim H (2001) Why charities announce donations: a positive perspective. J Public Econ

81:423–447Silverman WK, Robertson SJ, Middlebrook JL, Drabman RS (1984) An investigation of pledging behaviour

to a national charitable telethon. Behav Ther 15:304–311Soetevent AR (2005) Anonymity in giving in a natural context—a field experiment in thirty churches.

J Public Econ 89:2301–2323Varian HR (1994) Sequential contributions to public goods. J Public Econ 53:165–186Vega-Redondo F (1995) Public subscriptions and private contributions. Soc Choice Welfare 12:193–212Vesterlund L (2003) The informational value of sequential fundraising. J Public Econ 87:627–657Winter E (2006) Optimal incentives for sequential production processes. Rand J Econ 37:376–390

123