marxism and the postcolonial world

18
C r i t i c a l E n c o u n t e r s a f o r u m o f c r i t i c a l t h o u g h t f r o m t h e g l o b a l s o u t h s t a y u p d a t e d v i a r s s M a r x i s m A n d T h e P o s t c o l o n i a l W o r l d : F o o t n o t e s t o a L o n g M a r c h P o s t e d : 0 1 / 1 0 / 2 0 0 7 b y A d i t y a N i g a m i n I d e n t i t y , M a r x i s m , R e l i g i o n T a g s : i n d o n e s i a , m a o t s e t u n g , m u z a f f a r a h m e d , s a r e k a t i s l a m , t h i r d w o r l d 0 B y A d i t y a N i g a m I n t r o d u c t i o n T h i s p a p e r i s a s m u c h a b o u t t h e p o s t c o l o n i a l w o r l d a s i t i s a b o u t m a r x i s m . M o r e i m p o r t a n t l y , i t i s a b o u t t h e r e l a t i o n s h i p a b o u t t h e t w o . I u s e t h e t e r m p o s t c o l o n i a l h e r e t o r e f e r t o s o m e t h i n g m o r e t h a n a m e r e t e m p o r a l m a r k e r a s m o r e t h a n s o m e t h i n g t h a t c o m e s a f t e r t h e e n d o f c o l o n i a l i s m . R a t h e r , i t r e f e r s t o t h e e n t i r e r e g i o n o f t h e T h r e e C o n t i n e n t s ( A b d e l - M a l i k 1 9 8 1 ) s i n c e t h e b e g i n n i n g o f i t s e n c o u n t e r w i t h c o l o n i a l i s m , a n d t h r o u g h i t , t h e i r e n c o u n t e r w i t h m o d e r n i t y ; i t t h e r e f o r e p o i n t s t o w a r d s a w h o l e r a n g e o f c o n d i t i o n s t h a t m a r k i t o u t a s d i s t i n c t f r o m t h e f i r s t w o r l d p o l i t i c a l , e c o n o m i c , p s y c h o l o g i c a l a n d c u l t u r a l . I f c o l o n i a l i s m w a s t h e d o m i n a n t a g e n t o f m o d e r n i t y i n t h e s e s o c i e t i e s , i t w a s c e r t a i n l y n o t h e o n l y o n e . A c e r t a i n m a r x i s m , p a r t i c u l a r l y a f t e r t h e R u s s i a n r e v o l u t i o n o f 1 9 1 7 , b e c a m e a p o t e n t f o r c e t h r o u g h w h i c h t h e e m a n c i p a t o r y i d e a l s o f t h e s e c u l a r - m o d e r n i m a g i n a t i o n e n t e r e d t h i s w o r l d . A n d y e t t h e r e r e m a i n s a c o n t i n u o u s t e n s i o n b e t w e e n t h e h i g h d i s c o u r s e o f m o d e r n i t y e n t a i l e d i n i t a n d t h e e x i s t e n t i a l s i t u a t i o n o f t h i s w o r l d , w h i c h b e c o m e s c o m p l i c a t e d b y t h e d a y . T h e e n d o f t h e t w e n t i e t h c e n t u r y m a r k s t h e e n d o f a g i g a n t i c e m a n c i p a t o r y p r o j e c t , p r o b a b l y t h e l a r g e s t e v e r i n h i s t o r y t h a t w a s c a r r i e d o u t i n t h e n a m e o f t h a t m a r x i s m , w h i c h m e t i t s e n d w i t h t h e c o l l a p s e o f a c t u a l l y e x i s t i n g s o c i a l i s m . I w i l l r e f e r t o t h i s m a r x i s m a s c a n o n i c a l m a r x i s m w h i c h r a p i d l y d e g e n e r a t e d f r o m a v i s i o n o f f r e e d o m i n t o a m a s s i v e p r o j e c t o f s o c i a l e n g i n e e r i n g , o f t r y i n g t o f i t t h e w h o l e w o r l d i n t o O n e P a s t a n d O n e F u t u r e . I n i t s e n t i r e l y m i s p l a c e d e f f o r t t o e f f a c e a l l d i f f e r e n c e , i t e n d e d u p , i n t h e p r o c e s s , e f f a c i n g i t s e l f . T h e p r o j e c t o f e r a s i n g d i f f e r e n c e b e g a n f r o m w i t h i n . I n o r d e r t o b e a b l e t o c a s t t h e w o r l d i n t h e s i n g l e m o u l d o f t h e v i s i o n o f t h e T h i r d I n t e r n a t i o n a l a n d i t s i n h e r i t o r s , i t w a s f i r s t n e c e s s a r y t o e r a s e d i f f e r e n c e f r o m w i t h i n i t s o w n r a n k s : i t s o w n s e l f h a d t o b e r e c o n s t i t u t e d , i n a m a n n e r o f s p e a k i n g . W h a t I c a l l t h e f o o t n o t e s t o m a r x i s m a r e p r e c i s e l y t h o s e e l e m e n t s o f i t s s e l f , t h o s e c u r r e n t s o f t h o u g h t t h a t c o m p r i s e d i t s r i c h v a r i e t y b e f o r e t h e o n s e t o f o r t h o d o x y , t h a t w e r e w a y l a i d a n d p u s h e d t o t h e m a r g i n s .

Upload: sandipkluis

Post on 06-May-2017

219 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

Critical Encounters

a forum of critical thought from the global southstay updated via rss

Marxism And The Postcolonial World: Footnotes to aLong March

Posted: 01/10/2007 by Aditya Nigam in Identity, Marxism, Religion Tags: indonesia, mao tsetung, muzaffar ahmed, sarekat islam, third world

0By Aditya Nigam

Introduction

This paper is as much about the postcolonial world as it is about marxism. More importantly, it is aboutthe relationship about the two. I use the term ‘postcolonial’ here to refer to something more than a meretemporal marker – as more than something that comes after the end of colonialism. Rather, it refers tothe entire region of the Three Continents (Abdel-Malik 1981) since the beginning of its encounter withcolonialism, and through it, their encounter with modernity; it therefore points towards a whole rangeof conditions that mark it out as distinct from the first world – political, economic, psychological andcultural. If colonialism was the dominant agent of modernity in these societies, it was certainly no theonly one. A certain marxism, particularly after the Russian revolution of 1917, became a potent forcethrough which the emancipatory ideals of the secular-modern imagination entered this world. And yetthere remains a continuous tension between the high discourse of modernity entailed in it and theexistential situation of this world, which becomes complicated by the day.

The end of the twentieth century marks the end of a gigantic emancipatory project, probably thelargest ever in history that was carried out in the name of that marxism, which met its end with thecollapse of “actually existing socialism”. I will refer to this marxism as “canonical marxism” whichrapidly degenerated from a vision of freedom into a massive project of social engineering, of trying tofit the whole world into One Past and One Future. In its entirely misplaced effort to efface all difference,it ended up, in the process, effacing itself.

The project of erasing difference began from within. In order to be able to cast the world in the singlemould of the vision of the Third International and its inheritors, it was first necessary to erase differencefrom within its own ranks: its own ‘self’ had to be reconstituted, in a manner of speaking. What I callthe “footnotes” to marxism are precisely those elements of its self, those currents of thought thatcomprised its rich variety before the onset of orthodoxy, that were waylaid and pushed to the margins.

Page 2: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

They are what Javeed Alam has, in the context of the philosophical traditions of modernity, called the“unembodied surplus” of the tradition (Alam 1999). The communist/marxist self that was expungedand thus pushed outside the text, as it were, has kept re-appearing in different ways in different timesand places, occasionally, disguised in conventional modes of appearance. Even after the collapse, theidea of a communist future continues to survive in very different ways and continues to inspirestruggles in large parts of the world, especially the Three Continents, including India – often outside theapparatuses of mainstream communist parties.

In this essay, I wish to open up the space for a reconstruction of a new emancipatory vision for the“Third world”, which cannot but draw heavily on marxism, even if it is marxism reincarnated for apostmarxist conjuncture. I am aware that the search for the “real” Marx is a futile one. For one thing,he is inaccessible. For another, the world that has traversed a century and a half since then demandsmuch more than he can offer. After all, it was Marx who constantly reminded us that ideas can neverhave transhistorical validity; that they arise within given socio-historical contexts and becomemeaningful within them.

At one level, just like the “original Marx” is lost to us, so is the “pre-marx” era of human thought. Thetradition of Marx permeates the very world we live in and the very air we breathe, to borrow anexpression from Castoriadis (1987). Any new vision can only arise by passing through the multifariouspractices of “actually existing marxism” – by way of a theoretical encounter with that legacy.

In this paper, I explore through an investigation of the fate of Marx’s doctrine, two inter-related sets ofquestions. The first set of questions relates to the problem of the specificity of the postcolonial world andthe problems of simply “applying” theory born in the West to conditions so very different. Thisproblem is further complicated, I will argue, because underlying the theory there was always theEurocentric assumption of the invincibility of the West, thanks to its ‘higher level of development’/‘advanced mode of production’ and its being possessed of the magical wand of Science and Reason –that is History ( Future History?) embodied.

The second set of questions has to do with the ways in which marxism’s canonization itself led to thedestruction of the emancipatory potential – both in its theory and in the organizational formsmediating its practice.

Also related to the first set of questions is the entire Indian debate on secularism and modernity. I willnot go into that debate here, but suffice it to note that so far it has been framed in terms of thestate/community and tradition/modernity dichotomies. While the Indian debate provides rich insightsinto the questions at issue, it remains caught within its own terms. So for instance, the entire body ofwritings deals with secularism (and modernity) being colonial impositions and therefore state-centric –for critics and supprters alike. The question then really hinges on the nature of colonial interventions inIndian society. Many critics of secularism would argue that the fact of colonial imposition should alertus to its inherent limitations, while many secularists have been arguing that as the colonial state merelybuilt on processes (and resources) within precolonial society, it did not really introduce a fundamentalrupture. I shall merely point out here that there was at least one more route through which the secular-modern imaginary entered societies like India’s: this was the route of marxism which had neither theburden of the state nor the colonial legacy to shoulder and which should therefore have made it

Page 3: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

different in its approach form that other secualrism. As it happens, the fate of left-secularism and state-secularism actually converged as the going became tough. This, I will argue, had something to do withthe profound rupture – an epistemic rupture – introduced by the canonized versions of marxism.

There is one more problem that lies somewhere between the first and the second. Marxism travelledeastwards through the agency of the Comintern – the codified canon embodied – or through itsconstituent “sections” like the Communist Party of Great Britain (CPGB), in the case of countries likeIndia. There is therefore, a complicated dynamic in the way the first problem is itself mediated by thesecond circumstance. One of the problems of “applying theory” in this fashion is that not merely thecultural but also the politico-historical context and specificity of the countries where the “application” isintended gets ignored. What happens if the application is undertaken through the mediation of ahighly centralized and rigid structure like the Comintern, therefore, will form a part of the followingdiscussion.

I

On the hundred and fiftieth anniversary of The Communist Manifesto, there is one fundamentalquestion that needs to be asked. Let us pose the question through the words of a ‘Tricontinentalmarxist’. Anouar Abdel-malek refers to a book by Argentine historian Gustavo Beyhaut concerning theproblem of race in Latin America, which contains ‘a number of interesting references to Engels amongothers’. He refers to a series of articles published by Engels in 1848 and 1849 where he discusses the warof 1847 between the United States and Mexico. “He refers quite unambiguously , to the positivecharacter of American expansion in Mexico, in so far as it represents the expansion of an advancedcivilization…This could be extended even, let us say, to cover Vietnam a century later.”(Abdel-Malek1981: 81-82)

Abdel-Malek’s ironic remark pointing to the fact that a century later the same could under nocircumstances be extended to Vietnam says something about the profound change, the radicalalteration of the terms of discourse, that had already taken place in marxism during the interveningcentury. Was this simply because the nature of capitalism’s expansion underwent a qualitative changewith the appearance of imperialism? Or was it the case that with the appearance of Lenin’sImperialism, The Highest Stage of Capitalism, the basis was laid for the complete transformation ofmarxist discourse? There are any number of quotations that can be marshalled from the writings of thefounders of marxism and Abdel-Malek has furnished some of them to show how nineteenth centurymarxism shared a common ground with Orientalist discourse – in fact was largely located within it.What is relatively uninvestigated is the transformation referred to above.

We know the famous (?) passages from the The Communist Manifesto (1848) where it was proclaimedthat the subjection of the villages to the rule of the bourgeoisie ‘rescued a considerable part of thepopulation from the idiocy of rural life’. “Just as it made the country dependent on the towns, so it hasmade barbarian and semi-barbarian countries dependent on the civilized ones, nations of peasants onthe nations of bourgeois, the East on the West” (Marx and Engels 1982: 39).

The terms ‘rural population’, ‘country’ ‘barbaric and semi-barbaric countries’ and the ‘East’ are allanalogous categories – repositories of idiocy (the lack of Reason?), embodiments of a past that wasunproblematically and unadulteratedly ‘barbaric’. Since then, things have changed significantly, andtoday, if at all marxism survives anywhere, it is in these ‘Three Continents’. Its long march has

Page 4: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

traversed not merely one and a half centuries, it has moved from the West where it was born, to theEast which it saw as the habitat of the barbarians and the irrational, and where it found its mostenduring residence.

If in the 2000s, the only hope of all shades of marxists resides in the mountains of Chiapas or theindigeous coca growing peasantry of Bolivia or the peasant base of the Nepal Maoists, I shall suggestonce again taking the cue from Abdel-Malek, that what happened in this period to marxist theory,crucially, was the displacement of the historical/economic determinist problematic and the centralityacquired by the “specificity of the political”. If the celebratory tone of the Manifesto was predicatedupon the “higher technological and cultural/civilizational levels” of capitalism (that made it the“unconscious tool of history”), the Leninist-Maoist moment of marxism’s development privileged thepolitical – the revolutionary potential of the oppressed peoples and the peasantry of the colonial worldand, in its later form, of the ‘Third World’. There are major tensions on this point in the writings ofLenin, whose initial faith rested on the West and subsequent to the October revolution, specifically onthe European proletariat which would be the standard-bearer of world revolution.

The Maoist moment, on the other hand, in the enunciation of the contradiction between “nationalliberation struggles and imperialism” as the central and focal contradiction of the epoch, (at the time ofthe Great Proletarian Cultural Revolution), represents the complete displacement of the economisticproblematic. The fact that the Chinese people were “poor and blank” became the virtue, the source oftheir revolutionary energy. The subsequent, completely bizarre form in which this expressed itself inthe so-called Three-Worlds Theory, also represents to an extent the extension of the same dynamic –though that has a lot to do with the specific nature of power-struggle within China and externally, withChina’s battle for supremacy within the international communist movement with the Soviet Union.The populism of the postulate of the “convergence of interests of the USA and the USSR” was probablymeant to rally the movements in the Three Continents with pure rhetoric, unable as China was tocompete with the USSR in supplying arms to them. That should not however, detract us from assessingthe theoretical significance of that rhetoric. Nor need that lead us to any concession in assessing thedisaster that was the Cultural Revolution.

II

In 1848, when the Manifesto was published, the West was the centre of the world and the worldrevolution, and the East figured in the document – as in many other pronouncements of the founders ofmarxism – as a mere remnant of the past. I have already quoted some of the relevant passages above.Not only are they steeped in Orientalist common sense, they are also fully in line with the metaphor ofdarkness and light that is the central organizing principle of the Enlightenment. I have however,quoted these passages not to say that Marx was an Orientalist or racist. The point is precisely thereverse: Even for a revolutionary like Marx, it was not possible to apprehend these forms/formations bystepping outside the discursive horizon of his times. What were different societies, different culturalconfigurations located outside the physical space of the Enlightenment, became transformed andconstituted as temporally prior – as relics of the past whose dissolution had to be welcomed as theyrepresented backwardness. The East was backward because of its superstitious beliefs in religion,magic, sorcery and the like; never mind if mathematics, print technology and gun powder – the threemajor powers of modernity and colonialism were discovered/ invented in the East. It had to wait for theWest to civilize it, to bring it to light.

Page 5: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

[Andre Gunder Frank had since responded to this argument quite forcefully by claiming that Marx, farfrom simply being limited by the discursive horizon of his times, is in fact constitutive of that momentin Western thought that relegated the Orient to its marginal position.]

Fernando Claudin (1975) has, in his studied and extremely well documented account of the Communistmovement, pointed to the degeneration of the marxist doctrine under Stalin. He has shown how, incountry after country, it was the needs of the Soviet state and Stalin, that were responsible for turningthe defense of marxism and the internal revolutionary struggles into a subordinate position to thedefense of the Centre of World Revolution. This centre, according to him was once the Comintern thathad already become the instrument of Soviet foreign policy interests but the problem was that eventhat entailed some mediatory forms like consultations with leaders of some of the important parties,particularly those who were represented in the Executive Committee of the Comintern (ECCI). Claudinargues convincingly that it was the need to do away with these minimum impediments to the completeannexation of the communist movements in different countries to Soviet interests that led to theComintern’s dissolution and its replacement by the Soviet state as the new Centre.

In the history of the Comintern, he shows how the problematic category of the “East” appeared as acrucial one through successive struggles within. He shows that Lenin himself was till as late as 1912, aEuropean at heart. In his article on the “Awakening of Asia”, written in the wake of Sun Yatsen’srevolution in China, Lenin wrote welcoming the revolution:

“Does that mean…that the materialist West has hopelessly decayed and that the light shines only fromthe mystic, religious East? No, quite the opposite. It means that the East has definitely taken theWestern path, that new hundreds of millions of people will from now on share in the struggle for theideals which the West has already worked out for itself” (Claudin: 50).

There is a long history to the way in which Lenin came to reappraise the situation and theorize the riseof imperialism, especially after the revolution and the formation of the Comintern, when he actuallyhad to deal with the question of the “backward nationalities” within Soviet Union and in the world atlarge. We need not recount that history here. However some critical moments need to be revisited.Claudin’s account clearly maps the changes in the attitude of the Comintern. He claims that the FirstCongress almost completely ignored the question of the colonies and

“expressed very clearly the traditional ideas that were strongly rooted in the minds of the marxists: ‘Theemancipation of the colonies is possible only in conjunction with the emancipation of the metropolitanworking class. The workers and peasants not only of Annam, Algiers and Bengal, but also of Persia andArmenia, will gain the opportunity of independent existence only when the workers of England andFrance have overthrown Lloyd George and Clemenceau…’ ”(Caludin 246)

Claudin argues that three things happened between the First and the Second Congresses that put the“national and colonial question” on the agenda. First, the ebbing of the proletarian revolutionary tidein the West. Second the upsurge in the colonies and Third, the sharp rise of the national and colonialquestion inside the Soviet Union (Claudin: 246).

The Second Congress, which was attended by many delegates from the colonies, saw the almostcomplete reversal of the above position in the stand taken by these representatives like M.N.Roy.Claudin quotes the report of the Congress Commission on the National and Colonial Question, which

Page 6: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

said that “Comrade Roy defends the idea that the fate of the revolutionary movement in Europedepends entirely on the course of the revolution in the East” (Caludin: 247). Roy was, of course, basinghis argument on the idea that as long as the imperialist powers continued to extract super-profits fromthe colonies they would never enter into a terminal crisis of capitalism. Lenin countered Roy byreferring to the fact that “(I)n spite of the fact that the proletariat in India numbers five million andthere are 37 million landless peasants, the Indian communists have not succeeded in creating acommunist party…This fact alone shows that Com. Roy’s views are to a large extentunfounded.”(Caludin: 248). Clearly Lenin was hitting below the belt by putting forward this entirelynon-theoretical argument. This fact really showed nothing so far as the question at issue was concerned.

The Third Congress, held a year later, completely bypassed the issue due to certain strategicrequirements of the USSR. I will not go inot the details of these requirements but suffice it to note thatRoy had to protest against it while making his report on India, where the mass movement was reachingunprecedented heights. I quote: “I have been allowed five minutes for my report. As this theme cannotbe dealt with adequately even in an hour, I wish to employ these five minutes for an energetic protest.”He went on to remark that the way in which the Eastern question has been dealt with at this Congressis purely opportunist and is worthy rather of a Congress of the Second International” (Caludin: 249). Inthe Fifth Congress, the issue was raised forcefully by the Japanese Communist Party delegate SenKatayama and Ho Chi Minh (then Nguyen Ai Quoc).

It is interesting in this context, to note that at the Fourth Congress, Tan Malaka of the Indonesian CPnarrated the story of the CP’s collaboration with an oraganization called the Sarekat Islam. He said:

“…We collaborate with the Islamists…Between 1912 and 1916, this union had one million members,perhaps it had three or even four million. It was a very large proletarian union which sprang upspontaneously and was very revolutionary. Until 1920 we collaborated with this union…In 1921 wesucceeded in making Sarekat Islam adopt our programme and it went into the villages agitating forcontrol of production and for the watchword: ‘All power to the poor peasants and to the proletariat.However, a split occurred in 1921, owing to the tactless criticism of the leaders of the Sarekat Islam. Thegovernment and its agents made use of this split, and also of the decisions of the Second Congress ofthe Comintern, to fight against Pan-Islamism.”

In the midst of this narration Marchlewski, who was at the Chair, interrupted: “Your time is up”. Tothis Malaka replied, “I have come from India, it took me forty days to come here” and continuedamidst applause, to express what can only be described as the most crucial existential crisis of acommunist of the colonial world: “they (the Sarekat Islamists) are with us ‘with their stomach’ (to use apopular expression) but with their hearts they remain with the Sarekat Islam – with their heaven whichwe cannot give them.”(Claudin: note 87, ch, 4))

If this was the situation in the colonies in the rest of the world, the situation inside the USSR was nodifferent – in fact, it was more complicated. Claudin writes of the Muslim peoples of Central Asia:“Tsarist colonization had taken in these regions…an ‘Algerian’ form: settlement by Russian colonists[peasants and also some workers], who inevitably acqired a colonialist mentality. When Bolshevikpower was established in the heartland of Russia, this Russian minority…at once became ‘Soviet’ and

Page 7: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

from its ranks were recruited many of the ‘Bolsheviks’ who were to take over the leading functions inthe new institutions.” In 1920, Lenin sent one of his closest collaborators, Safarov, to study the problemand Claudin remarks that Safarov was to write some years later that,

“It was inevitable that the Russian revolution should have a colonialist character in Turkestan. TheTurkestani working class, numerically small, had neither leader, programme, party nor revolutionarytradition…Under Tsarist colonialism, it was the privilege of the Russians to belong to the industrialproletariat. For this reason, the dictatorship of the proletariat took on a typically colonialist character.”(Caludin: 256-7)

At the famous Baku Congress of the Peoples of the East, Narbutabekov from Turkestan made thefollowing impassioned plea:

“We…have faith in our…leaders of the world proletariat – comrades Lenin, Trotsky, Zinoviev andothers, but all the same we must state…what we want, and the voice of the Muslim workers and thepeoples of the East must be heard…Everyone knows that the East is utterly different from the Westand its interests are different – thus, rigid application of the ideas of Communism will meet withresistance in the East…They [the leaders] should come and see for themselves what is happening in ourcountry, what exactly the local authorities, whose policies drive the working masses away from theSoviet power, are up to…(I)n shedding our blood on the Turkestan fronts against the enemies of Sovietpower, we bound up our lives closely with the working masses of the whole of Russia and theaccusations of chauvinist tendencies made against Turkestani leaders must be dropped…I tell youcomrades, that our Turkestani masses have to fight on two fronts. On the one hand, against the evilmullahs at home, and on the other against the narrow nationalist inclinations of localEuropeans.”(Caludin: note 85, ch.4)

Notice the use of terms like “our country” and “local Europeans”. Notice also the fact that already thecomplexity of conflict between local cultures and high theory was being played out – the latter talkingthe language of universalism while the former were asserting their ineradicable difference. In fact,Narbutaketov’s speech shows how their idea of universalism was predicated precisely on therecognition of difference – otherwise the fear was that in the name of universalism, local Europeannationalism would ride roughshod over them. Hence the fight on two fronts. Between him and TanMalaka, we see the really repressed voices of marxism, the traces of which we would find difficult toretrieve. The long history of marxism’s sojourn in the East in fact, can be seen as one of continuousstruggle between these two imperatives, between the dictates of a theory which talked an abstractlanguage but was steeped in European traditions and therefore dismissive of other traditions and, theimperatives of making their own revolution which could not afford to adopt an instrumentalist attitude,let alone be self-deprecatory about their own cultures.

Most of the time however, as Abdel-Malek rightly observes, the communists from the colonies “wereless concerned to expound theses than to say: we exist.”(Abdel-Malek: 86). To some extent, Roy did tryto theorize but then, in his theoretical predelictions he was more European than most other colonialmarxists. His theorizations therefore, were mainly confined to asserting the importance of the Easternquestion and to demonstrate that it could not be made politically subordinate to the tasks of the

Page 8: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

communists in the West. Of all the Tricontinental marxists, it was Mao Tsetung who went furthest inhis effort to theorize though, as we shall see these efforts too fell far short of the requirements. It may beuseful then to look at some of his forays into theory.

IV

Three concepts seem to be of crucial importance to Mao Tsetung’s attempt at dealing with theapplication of marxism’s predominantly European theoretical paraphernalia and the rigid impositionof the Comintern’s code. First, the “law of uneven development” as an absolute law. “Nothing in theworld develops absolutely evenly”, he proclaims (Mao 1977a: 336). Through this assertion, Mao almostinstinctively, subverts the metaphysical positivist desire of finding laws and regularities governinghuman societies – much of which baggage marxism had itself inherited through the Second and theThird Internationals. Second, he makes what is his central conceptual move through his enunciation ofthe “particularity and universality of contradiction.” The universality of the contradiction is simply theidea that “contradiction exists in the development of all things”; that “it is precisely in the particularityof the contradiction that the universality resides.” (Mao 1977a: 316). Universality, says Mao, is easier tounderstand because “it has been widely recognized” since Marx, Engels, Lenin and Stalin, but “theparticularity of contradiction is still not clearly understood by many comrades, especially thedogmatists.”(Mao 1977a: 315-6).

Notice here the second major subversion: If universality of contradiction was to a certain marxism, theUniversal appearing, a la a certain marxist Hegel, in each particular and each particular representing amere moment of the Universal, Mao in one stroke, completely reverses its meaning. The particular nowbecomes the only way in which the Universal can appear. This is Mao’s famous law of contradiction.This notion is the second universal truth. The two statements together constitute what Mao calls “theuniversal truths” of Marxism, thus holding on the idea in words but interpreting it in a way thatpractically denies its universality. In his rendering then, this is universality, but one which has noattribute of its own; it acquires everywhere the attributes of the particularity. That is why Mao can ask:“Why is it that the Chinese revolution can avoid a capitalist future and be directly linked withsocialism, without taking the old historical road of Western countries…?” and answer: “The sole reasonis the concrete conditions of the time.”(Mao 1977a: 341).

By making these moves Mao is further able to complicate notions of subjectivity and agency handeddown by the Internationals. Contradictions exist, according to him, not only between the exploiters andthe exploited, but equally importantly, “among the people”. In the concrete conditions of China, herefers to “contradictions within the working class, contradictions within the peasantry, thecontradictions within the intelligentsia, the contradictions between the working class and thepeasantry” etc. (Mao 1977b: 385).

It is true that Mao never theoretically follows through and works out the ideas of subjectivity andagency in the light of these formulations but all through his practice we can see that he is acutely awareof the implications of the above. It is easy to see that, put this way, simplistic notions like a “class-in-itself” turning into a “class-for-itself” – another specifically 19th century Europeanism – becomeimpossible to conceive. For, having already posited the contradiction within the class, it is neither

Page 9: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

possible to simply derive class consciousness from class position, nor think of a single unified will of aclass – expressed through a single party. Needless to say, attributing a telos of History to that is well-nigh impossible.

In case we had any doubts, Mao goes further. True, he does put “contradictions among the people” inthe category of “nonantagonistic contradictions” as opposed to “antagonistic” ones among theexploiters and the exploited. Yet, these are not fixed categories which can only be resolved in oneparticular way, consonant with the larger telos. So he argues that one can easily turn into the other.“(T)his contradiction between the two classes (the national bourgeoisie and the working class), ifproperly handled can be transformed into a nonantagonistic one and be resolved by peacefulmethods.” (Mao 1977b: 386). On the other hand, “(I)n ordinary circumstances, contradictions amongthe people are not antagonistic…but if they are not handled properly…antagonism may arise.”(Ibid:391).

The phrase “if handled properly” then leads us to the third concept of Mao’s: politics in command.Nothing but the limiting conditions are provided by the economy and the logic of production. The restdepends upon politics, upon how forces are rallied, how alliances are struck, how struggles areconducted and what organizational forms mediate each of these.

We must however, be cautious while understanding the use to which Mao puts these concepts. Hewanted to puncture the rigidly structured and codified canon of the Comintern and create the space forhis own activity. The political task of accomplishing the Chinese revolution demanded a partialrejection of that canon but in the balance of world forces then existing he could not afford to becomeanother Tito – excommunicated by the communist world. It was to create this space that the idea of aparticularity that not just expressed the essence of the Universal but was an entity in its own right,becme important. The theoretical/philosophical task that followed from Mao’s initiative, at once bolderand more conservative than Lenin’s, was never undertaken, either by him or by his successors. Inmany ways therefore, Mao remained a believer in “the universal truths of Marxism-Leninism” eventhough he often enough chose to define them in the above manner. Today, we surely can read theseconceptual moves made by him in a more radical way.

This caution is necessary in order to understand that because the theoretical/philosophical implicationswere never followed through into an alternative theorization of the specificities of the colonialworld/East, marxism even its Maoist incarnation, remained within the larger framework of post-Enlightenment, often positivist, thought. It was therefore easy for it to slip back into the canon and inthe case of China, into the high modernist paradigm that rules it in the post-Mao phase.

It is important therefore to underline here that to create a space for a different practice and analternative theorization is no substitute for an alternative theory. In order to accomplish that latter task,a further step is required: It is not enough to say that “our history” is different from theirs; we mustmove towards a reconstruction of this history on its own terms. However, that is not our concern in thepresent essay, but I wish to state here that when I say “on its own terms” it is not once again a searchfor the pristine, precolonial histories that I am suggesting. Nor am I suggesting that all responses of thenationalist leaders and intelligentsia to colonial modernity that were based on some sort of dialoguewith it, were a priori illegitimate. The search, on the contrary, must be based on an effort to understandwhy they related to colonialism in the way that they did.

Page 10: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

V

In this section I will briefly look at the formative history of the Indian communist movement, whichpresents an interesting counterpoint to the Chinese case, for it is a movement that remains essentiallyhegemonized by the Comintern and the classical paradigm. Yet, in a peculiar way Indian communismtoo reveals the existential angst of other colonial communists.

It needs to be underlined that by the time marxism came to India, it had already undergone its firstmajor metamorphosis. To the hundreds of youth who joined the communist movement in the countryin the second and third decades of this century, marxism was an anti-imperialist doctrine of liberationfrom colonialism. That much was already self-evident. Its hostility to colonialism was a logical extensionof it hostility to capitalism as such. On this issue Eastern marxism did not seem to suffer from anyinternal contradiction. Many of the youth who felt attracted towards the communist movement werenationalists to begin with, driven by a passion for a new, free India. Others were believers in Islam andanti-British, who wanted to fight for the Khilafat. For many of them though, their religiosity does notseem to have been articulated with their nationalism. These are points that are often overlooked when,all too easily the communists today are accused of having been the carriers of an alienated, Westernoriented way of thinking. There seem to be many more layers of complication than are visible at firstsight, as we shall see later. There was certainly something internal to communism too, that happened inlater years that also transformed Indian communism to its subsequent alienated form.

The first generation of Muslim youth who went and joined M.N. Roy and became the co-founders ofthe communist party in Tahskent, were in fact muhajirs – self-exiled or on hijrat. Roy writes of themthat “they were not even nationalists”. He then goes on to add:

“My preliminary efforts with the educated minority produced greater results than I expected andwanted. Most of them transferred their fanatical allegiance from Islam to Communism(emphasisadded). I had not spoken to them at all about Communism. I had only told them that driving theBritish out of India would be no revolution, if it was succeeded by replacing foreign exploiters by nativeones. I had to explain the social significance of a revolution: that, to be worthwhile, a revolution shouldliberate the toiling masses of India from their present economic position. Instinctively idealists, theyreadily agreed with my opinion and jumped to the conclusion that if the revolution had to liberate thetoiling masses, it would have to be a Communist revolution.”(Roy 1984: 464).

Note the significant expession here: The mohajirs “transferred their fanatical allegiance tocommunism”. Let us just dwell on this for a moment. Their being idealist does not fully explain theirconversion. For we know that religion was a central concern to the Muslim youth who joined theKhilafat movement. Could it be that to these early youth, conversion to communism did not stand incontradiction to their religion? Could it be then that they saw in communism, primarily a politicalimaginary that did not demand a subordination of their spiritual world to the political? The idea of acommunist revolution was in the air; it was there already in the stories that were told in hushed tones,that narrated how the hated landowners and rulers had been overthrown in Russia, led by a larger-than-life messiah called Lenin. Only further scholarship can reveal the extent to which the story of therevolution was acquiring a mythological character. One thing seems certain: the stories of these earlyyears did not yet reveal communism to be a godless, irreligious creed. And for the believers of Islam, towhom the world – the Creation – was greater than any nation, the idea of a revolution that sought to

Page 11: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

transcend national boundaries may have really seemed very attractive. How else do we make sense ofthe wholesale transfer of allegiance that Roy talks of? The story of Tan Malaka, of the initialcollaboration between the Sarekat Islam and the communists, the tale of Narbutabekov – all of thempoint in the direction of a conclusion that at least in the early years, conversion to communism did notinvolve anything more than the adoption of a new political vision of how to recast the world. Itcertainly did not entail the epistemological rupture, the abandonment of old ways of making sense ofthe world and th adoption of the standpoint of High Rationalism.

If this was the frame of mind of the muhajir-turned-communists, those at home were not from“Western educated elite” either. Muzaffar Ahmed, one of the founders of the CPI at home, hasdescribed his own situation in his pre-communist days, in his autobiography:

“I would be suppressing the truth if I were to say that I was never involved in anything communal. Iused to participate in meetings and organizations raising the specific demands of Muslims. I was also areligious Muslim at that time. Even if I did not offer namaz five times a day, I did fast throughout theentire month of Ramzan.” (Ahmed 1987: 7).

In fact, Muzaffar Ahmed further explains that later, during the 1920s, given his “the state of mind…and the thrill that was associated with the terrorist movement” it was not entirely impossible that hejoined a terrorist revolutionary group.

“But there were major hurdles in the way. The terrorist revolutionaries drew their inspiration fromBankimchandra’s Anandamath. This book was full of communal hatred from the beginning to the end.Its basic mantra was the song Bandemataram… How could a monotheistic Islamic youth recite thismantra?”(Ahmed 1987: 9).

Ahmed says this even as he records his deepest respect for the terrorists (this is the term he consciouslyuses). Notice here that even though the monotheistic Muslim youth found it difficult to chant theHindu mantra, he did eventually become a communist subsequently – Islam did not stand in the way.I suspect that for leaders and political activists like him, communism would have been the first stationin the route to Rationalism and atheism.

Saroj Mukherjee, one of the stalwarts of the Bengal communists who joined the CPI in the thirties, alsobegins his autobiography with the concerns that animated some of the youth who joined thecommunist movement at that time.

“We wanted the freedom of the country. We wanted to usher in an arrangement wherein the peoplecould live in happiness after driving out the British rulers. In what misery do the workers, peasants, thepeople of the villages and industrial areas live! We wanted an end to that state of affairs and to build ahappy and prosperous country…This was the thought that we were obsessed with.” (Mukhopadhyay1985: 7).

Clearly, the concerns that brought these youth of diverse persuasions to the communist movementwere similar. They were nationalists in a different way – in the sense that they wanted the happiness ofthe people who constituted the majority of the “nation”, namely the poor, toilng people. Theirnationalism had nothing to with any prior “Indian essence”. And a precondition to this happiness wasthe freedom from foreign rule. Alternatively, they were religiousy inclined “internationalists” – the

Page 12: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

Khilafatists – who once again wanted the “revolution of the toiling masses” and therefore managed tofree themselves of the narrow religious concerns for the sake of the larger cause. In other words, to themalso, their Islamic allegiance presented no barrier in the transition to communism.

How do we understand this transformation – an epistemological leap – from nationalism/religiosity tocommunism? I would suggest that in the early years, the transition from nationalism and religion didnot involve any rupture. The rupture is located precisely in the transition from communism toRationalism. As a political imaginary, communism provided the buffer between two worlds; as a self-proclaimed weltanschauung, it became the agent of High Reason and of the ideology of Progress. Forthe moment I shall use ‘communism’ (with lower case c) to denote the former and ‘Communism’ (withcapital C) to denote the philosophy.

I do not think that the straightforward dichotomy of tradition/modernity is very helpful here. For, aslate as the turn of the twentieth century, colonial modernity was already the condition of existence andeverything, nationalism and religion included, was marked by its presence. There was no longer any“innocent precolonial-self” in existence any more. And yet there is a crucial leap involved here. Thecommunist (that is, pre-Communist) ideas of nationalism and religiosity were deeply engaged in adialogue with tradition and the past. In a manner of speaking, they represented attempts to cope withcolonial modernity from within the ground of a tradition that was already ineradicably lodged within itand therefore conditioned by it. The rupture or leap to Communism meant a closure of that dialogue –a move to a ground that was firmly located within the epistemological world of Western, post-Enlightenment rationalism. The communists in India, probably, did not just encounter the shift in theComintern’s position that Tan Malaka had experienced with all his being. To them the exciting story ofthe workers’ revolution in Russia presented a picture that was very different from the one that the“backward peoples” of Turkestan and Soviet Central Asia were beginning to experience. The meaningof the revolution was differently felt within and without. I am not suggesting that to the people ofSoviet Central Asia the revolution brought only disaster. Far from it. I am only suggesting that thedifferent story that was beginning to unfold there was at that time not accessible to those who laterbecame communists in India. To them the dream of a happy, prosperous and exploitation-free nationwas at hand and the USSR showed them the way to it. Since the question of Pan-Islamism had alreadybeen “resolved” by the comintern, to the Indian communists it – and the religious question in general –was already handed down as received wisdom, unlike Malaka, for whom it remained an open questionhaving the backing of a different experience. The leap for the Indian communists therefore, was oneinto this worldview – not the one being defended by Malaka or Narbutabekov. How this leap becamepossible is a matter of further research and investigation.

I will tentatively suggest that a part of the explanation may be rooted in the ontological condition of thecolonial subject – a condition shaped by a colonial modernity that was both oppressor as well as themirror that revealed to him/her the pathologies of the precolonial past. It is within that generalontological condition that we can situate the immense appeal of a modern emancipatory project likesocialism or communism which simultaneously declared its hostility to colonialism/imperialism and tothe oppressions of the past. It is probably within this larger canvas that the transition to the comintern-led Communism becomes possible, even though the actualization of that possibility is a more complexprocess.

Page 13: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

According to Tunisian writer Albert Memmi (1965), the constitution of colonial subjectivity is markedby (a) the social and historical mutiliation of the colonized and (b) what I will call after him, her culturalschizophrenia. He delineates two moments of the constitution of this subject, when he talks of twohistorically possible ways of realizing this subjectivity. The first moment of this constitution is mimetic,for the colonized native here mimics and emulates the colonial master. For Memmi, of course, themimicry is of a different kind, taking place as it does in the violent context of the assimilation ofcolonized populations under French colonialism. This may also happen, I will suggest, by way of thecolonized subject defining her political project of emancipation in terms of the larger theoretical andepistemological criteria of the West, in terms of its philosophy and its achievements as the embodimentof progress and modernity – what Partha Chatterjee has called the Thematic of nationalism. It mayalso happen in a second, more subtle way of the native/colonized subject recasting her/his ownreligious/spiritual apparatus in order to summon it to provide the ethical and therefore epistemic,justifications for redefinitions of Selfhood and enable it to play a new political role.

The second moment of this constitution is actually already beginning to emerge in the abovedescription – that of the assertion of their difference. For, this could never be based on the completerejection of the Self. Even the former category of responses, represented by the modernists whocelebrated the idea of the eventual triumph of Reason and Science, were responses from the sameground as that of those who seemed to entirely reject the West. What attracted them to ideas ofsocialism/liberalism was the idea of a modern India that was not merely politically independent butalso free of social oppression. Where the two differed and parted ways was the way in which theyassessed the strengths of the colonial power and what they considered crucial to their sense of Selfhood– in other words, what they considered the indispensable and the relatively discardable aspects of theirtradition. For those who privileged the West’s achievements in material, scientific and modern terms,the road to salvation lay to a large extent, in the first option pointed out by Memmi. The communistsclearly, would fall in this category. On the other hand, those who thought that the West’s political andarmed might was the key to its strength, also sought to masculinize and militarize their own “religion”(like a Vivekananda or in a different way, a Savarkar or a Golwalkar), while holding on to the notionthat it was still spiritually superior to the Europeans. The reasons why different social groups andsections made different choices have deeper historical reasons, which we can hardly go into here.Suffice it to note that there was no essential Indian Self and different people understood their“Indianness” in radically different ways. One of the key mediating factors was the attitude the playersheld towards the violence and oppression of the old order and the stake each of them had in precolonialsocial arrangements. The caste oppression of the brahminical order for instance, ensured that the entirerange of backward caste and dalit leaders did not take the second option. To them the old order was anunmitigated evil that had to go. This circumstance itself was what made all the difference. In Europeand the West, the ideas of the philosophes of the Enlightenment were rooted in the struggles withintheir respective societies and so the choice was a more straightforward one between the old and thenew. In India and much of the colonial world, the rejections of past violences went along with the needto redefine the Self in relation to a set of new ideas that were tied to the West that was actuallycolonizing it.

In the context of Indian communism, it is this that provides the key link. The assertion of the universalcondition – “All men [without markers] are born free and equal”- becomes the basis for challenging theindigenists/revivalists who claim a special status in the name of their difference and who seem to bewanting the freedom to revive a hated past. The transition from communism to Communism takes

Page 14: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

place in this context. It may be worthwhile to study the specific contexts in which the earlycommunists, much like the early social reformers and the leaders of the “backward classes”, found amore secure ally in the modern liberal/socialist doctrines coming from the west.

What further complicated the situation in the context of the Indian communist movement was that itbecame totally unreflexive by virtue of its complete dependence on the Comintern and the SovietUnion, not merely for its ideological-theoretical nourishment but also its organizational coordination.The problem, it seems, is not where a particular idea is born but whether it has the capability to adaptto different conditions which, I have been arguing so far, was the case with marxism but which wasprecisely the casualty of its canonization.

Muzaffar Ahmed narrates how the work of the CPI began at four different places – Calcutta, Madras,Bombay and Lahore – in the country around the same time. “It was not as if the initiators met anddecided to start work…In each place it started independently. They did not even know each other”. Hegoes on to explain how in these circumstances, and given the large distances within India, each of thesefour groups maintained separate/independent contact with the Comintern (Ahmed 1987: 62).

Symptomatic of the control of the Comintern over the Indian Communist Party was the first Manifestoof the Party – titled “Manifesto to The Delegates of the XXXVI Indian National Congress”. Thedocument was written and printed in Moscow by M.N. Roy and approved by Lenin and Stalin. It isinteresting that the people who drafted and approved the document had no day to day touch with themovement in the country. Mikhail Borodin had gone to Madrid to attend a conference and broughtwith him a pile of Indian papers for Roy, who the submerged himself in them to eventually produce thedocument. The Manifesto is full of unsought advice to the Congress. It further displays the mostelementary lack of political sense in that it shows no appreciation of the dynamics of political dialogue:why should the delegate to the Congress session take this unasked for bit of advice seriously when theydo not even know, let alone trust those who are handing it out? The tone of the advise is often derisivein the extreme. For instance, it says: “Several thousand of noisy, irresponsible students and a number ofmiddle class intellectuals followed by an ignorant mob momentarily incited by fanaticism, cannot bethe social basis of the political organ of a nation.”(Reproduced in Ahmed 1987).

On the positive side, the document does try to expose the “freedom first” argument by emphasizingthat there can be no genuine freedom without the toiling people and their demands figuring centrallyin the movement. But then the document proceeds:

“How can the Congress expect to arouse lasting popular enthusiasm in the name of the Khilafat and bydemanding the revision of the treaty of Sivres? The high politics behind such slogans may be easy forthe learned intellectuals…but it is beyond the comprehension of the masses of the Indian people whohave been steeped in ignorance not only by the foreign ruler, but by our own religious and socialinstitutions…Their consciousness must be aroused first of all. They must know what they are fightingfor”.

In the event, of course, it was clear what the masses understood and what they did not, who in theirperception, was talking “high politics” and who was not? The document is therefore, more importantbecause it completely failed to understand the meaning of what it called “high politics” and “abstractidealism”. For instance, it says:

Page 15: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

“The programme of the Congress has to be denuded of all sentimental trimmings; it has to be draggeddown from the height of abstract idealism; it must talk of the things indispensable for mortal life of thecommon human being…the object for which the Indian people will fight should not be looked forsomewhere in the unknown regions of Mesopotamia or Arabia or Constantinople…”.

Recall Malaka’s lament that “with their hearts they remain with the Sarekat Islam – with their heavenwhich we cannot give them”. The inability to understand the meaning of the peoples’ heaven, theconstrual of all spirituality/religiosity as ignorance is centrally linked to the epistemological leap into theworld of post-enlightenment rationalism. I must emphasize that I am not talking of communists notbeing religious but simply of being unable to understand the world of those who are religious. In otherwords, I am talking of the closure, the diremption entailed in this leap. If they could not understand thereligious mind, nor could they understand the force of nationalism. I will not go into the details of thataspect as that has been written about in fair amount of detail. It is also idle to argue about whetherinvolving the Khilafat sentiment was a correct or an incorrect move on Gandhi’s part. Surely itscorrectness or otherwise cannot be judged on the basis of purported outcomes. In any case, what I amunderlining is the crossing of a particular epistemological threshold on the part of the communists.

That the influence of the Comintern was not simply ideological, made matters worse. The minimumautonomy that the Indian communists displayed was also repeatedly undermined. Muzaffar Ahmed, adevoted follower of the Comintern line narrates an incident which is illustrative. In a conference held in1926, one of the items on the agenda was the change in name of the Labour Swaraj Party. In his words:“ It was decided in the deliberations of the conference that the name of the Labour Swaraj Party wouldbe changed to ‘The Bengal Peasants’ and Workers’ Party’. Some of us present in the KrishnanagarConference did not however, raise the issue that as a class the workers’ name should come first. Therewould have been no use raising the issue before the praja and krishak [tenant and peasant]representatives. We said that in the tradition of usage of words in English, Workers’ should come first,as there are less letters in this word….Our argument was not accepted by a majority of the delegates.”(Ahmed 1987: 340). The frivolity of the argument reveals the pathetic state of mind in which thisproposal may have been put forward. In the third conference of the PWP of Bengal, held in Bhatparain March 1928, the Communists managed to get the English name of the party changed to Workers’and Peasants’ Party but the Bengali name remained what it was. (Ahmed 1987: 348).

There can be no other explanation for this desperate behaviour except fear – the fear of ridicule anddisciplinary action by the Comintern. If Ahmed himself did not feel compelled to press for a change ofname at the Krishnanagar conference because it would not have cut ice with the peasant delegates,what else was the desperation about? Marxist orthodoxy decreed that there could be only one party toa class. Only the communist party could represent the working class and only one class could berepresented by any party. What then was this business of two-class parties? The mystery is uncoveredmany many years later, in 1960, when Muzaffar Ahmed writes to Clemens Palme Dutt, through hisbrother, Rajni Palme Dutt to seek some clarification regarding the expulsion of M.N. Roy from theComintern. “As regards Roy’s expulsion…” replies C.P. Dutt, “(B)y the end of 1927, Roy had alreadycome under heavy criticism for his policy in China…Then came his discrediting in connection withIndia. Apart from the decolonization theory, he was attacked, firstly because he had given exxageratedreports about the strength of the Communist Party of India and his influence there and, secondly,because he was attempting to build a Workers and Peasants Party as a kind of alternative to the

Page 16: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

Communist Party…Roy answered the criticism that it was wrong to form a political party on a 2-classbasis by saying that what was required in India was not merely a 2-class party but a multi-class party.”(Ahmed 1987: 402).

Characteristically, Ahmed, even while publishing this damning letter refused to draw the conclusionthat he ought to have in his memoirs. After all, it is abundantly clear from his accounts that theformation of the PWPs and the WPPs were no conspiracies hatched by Roy; all of them, includingAhmed believed in the need for forming them and in my view, rightly so. The subsequent dissolution ofthe WPPs can now be seen in perspective. It may not be entirely out of place to mention that with theaccession to power by Hitler and the turn in the Comintern’s line in 1935, in its Seventh Congress,when the worldwide tactical shift was towards formation of United Fronts, Indian communists were tosee sermonizing in a very different direction. The well-known “Dutt-Bradley Thesis” authored by R. P.Dutt and Ben Bradley of the CPGB, directed the formation of a mass anti-imperialist front – in fact ofthe transformation of the Congress itself into a multi-class party!

The glimpse of the Indian communist movement that we see here gives a diametrically opposite picturefrom the Chinese one, particularly the phase after the ascent of Mao. The history of the ChineseCommunist Party before that phase is also of course replete with instances of sharp struggle against thedisastrous attempts to impose the Comintern’s line. The struggle against what was known as the groupof twenty-eight Bolsheviks or the “Returned students” [i.e. returned from Moscow] has been officiallyrecognized by the CCP. Mao himself has said on occasion that the CCP could make the Chineserevolution successful by going against the wishes of Stalin.

What the above discussion highlights then is something more than mere centralization of commandwithin the Comintern. The suppression of local initiative goes hand in hand with the hard choice thatthe communists of the colonial world were presented with: a choice between two epistemologicalworlds. It was a choice within which is located the final leap of Indian communists. It would however,be an oversimplification to say that force alone was responsible for this transformation. There is anelaborate mythology through which the hegemony of the Comintern is established. This mythologyhas a peculiarly theological structure where the world is divided between believers and non-believers:“Those who are not with us are against us”. The fear of excommunication is as strong within this worldas it is in any other religion. In the event, the canonization of faith has all the other attributes that gowith religion: a set of sacred texts, a pantheon of gods, a Papal authority and the mythology thatsustains the faith. Reason is finally sublated into its opposite and in a typically Hegelian auhfebung, ifthere ever was any, a synthesis of the rationalist religion occurs. It is the stranglehold of this mythologyto which even Mao submits in the end, when he makes his existential choice of remaining within thefold of believers – his constant fear of becoming another Tito, recurrent in so many of his writings andspeeches ensures this choice.

VI

In conclusion, I would like to draw attention to one of the first footnotes of Marx’s doctrine – written byMarx himself and all but erased by his followers. I am referring to Marx’s correspondence with VeraZasulich – the Russian Narodnik-turned-Marxist. In 1881, Teodor Shanin tells us, Marx spent threeweeks agonizing over a reply to Zasulich’s letter, during which he wrote four drafts puzzling over theissue of the Russian peasant communes. He tried to understand the decline of the peasant commune

Page 17: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

not as an absolute law of history but as a historical contingency. (Shanin 1983: 13-4). Recovered afterhis death, it was sent by Engels to the Group for the Emancipation of Labour (of which luminaries likePlekhanov and Zasulich were members) for publication. After a long silence of seven months, theyreplied to Engels saying that they would publish it once they got it translated into Russian. They neverdid. Finally it was published in 1886, in Vestnik Norodnoi Voli (Vol 5). The only positive response to theletter, the Japanese scholar Haruki Wada informs us, was from among the Populists (Narodniks). Theywere discovered, according to Wada, in 1911 by D.B. Riazanov who with Bukharin’s help managed todecipher them in 1913. One full decade later they were again discovered accidentally by a Menshevikcalled B.I. Nikolaevskii and published in 1924. In 1926, Riazanov published them separately.(Shanin:41-2). Writing as the defender of what was already a canon, Riazanov said that the letter and its draftsrepresented a decline in Marx’s scholastic capability. (Shanin: 42). Both Wada and Shanin havedocumented in detail, the turmoil that Marx was undergoing and the small but significant changes hewas making in fresh editions of his earlier writings. In the French edition of Capital published in 1875,for instance, he deletes one paragraph on primitive accumulation that says that in different ways, thesame process is going on in different countries everywhere. The new passage restricts the scope of histheoretical generalizations to Western Europe. (Shanin: 48-9).

It is this passage from the French edition that Marx quotes from in the letter to Zasulich and remarks:“Hence the ‘historical inevitability’ of this movement is expressly limited to the countries of WesternEurope.” (Marx 1977: 576). Following the outbreak of the Russo-Turkish War sometime in 1877, Marxwrote to F.A. Sorge:

“This crisis is a new turning point for the history of Europe. Russia…has for a long period been on thebrink of revolution. All the factors for this are already present…The revolution this time starts from theEast, that same East which we have so far regarded as the invincible support and reserve of counter-revolution”. (Wada in Shanin 1983: 55-6).

In other words, the canonization of Marx deprived later marxists of the most crucial insights that couldbe had from the way in which he was grappling with “the problem of the East” – for which we had towait for the Leninist and Maoist moments of reformulation of theory. The critical spirit of Marx that isrepeatedly in evidence throughout his life and seen in this dramatic episode, was the first to be killed. Inorder to preserve the canon and the icon Marx, the critical philosopher had to be killed first. Thereconstitution of the communist self began with the (re)construction of Marx.

An earlier version of this essay was published in the Economic and Political Weekly, 9 January 1999,Vol 34, Nos 1&2.

REFERENCES

Abdel-Malek, Anouar (1981) Nation and Revolution. Volume 2 of Social Dialecics. The MacmillanPress, London and Basingstoke.

Ahmed, Muzaffar (1981), Amar Jibon O Bharater Communist Party, National Book Agency.

Alam, Javeed (1999), India: Living with Modernity, Oxford University Press, Delhi

Page 18: Marxism and the Postcolonial World

Carr`e re d’Encausse, Helene and Stuart Schram (1965) Marxism and Asia, Allen Lane The PenguinPress.

Castoriadis, Cornelius (1987), The Imaginary Institution of Society , Polity Press, UK.

Claudin, Fernando (1975), The Communist Movement: From Comintern to Cominform, in two parts.Monthly Review Press, New York and London

Mao Tsetung (1977a), Selected Works Vol. I, Foreign Languages Press, Peking.

—————–(1977b), Selected Works Vol. V, Foreign Languages Press, Peking

Marx, K. (1973), Grundrisse. Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy. Vintage Books, NewYork.

Marx, Karl (1977), Selected Writings, Ed. David McLellan, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

Marx, Karl and Engels, Friedrich (1982), Selected Works, Progress Publishers, Moscow.

Memmi, Albert (1965), The Colonizer and the Colonized, Souvenir Press Ltd.

Mukhopadhyay, Saroj (1985), Bharater Communist Party O Amra, Vol. I, National Book Agency.

Roy, M. N. (1984), Memoirs, Ajanta Publications, India.

Shanin, Teodor (1983), Late Marx and the Russian Road – Marx and ‘the Peripheries of Capitalism’Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.

<!–[if !supportEmptyParas]–> <!–[endif]–>

Blog at WordPress.com. | The Greyzed Theme.Follow

Follow “Critical Encounters”

Powered by WordPress.com