(jurists_ profiles in legal theory ) hugh baxter-habermas_ the discourse theory of law and democracy...

349

Upload: arnaldo-b-s-neto

Post on 14-Aug-2015

102 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)
Page 2: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Habermas

Page 3: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Jurists: Profiles in Legal Theory

William Twining, General Editor

Page 4: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

HabermastHe discourse tHeory

of law and democr acy

Hugh Baxter

stanford law books

An Imprint of Stanford University Press

Stanford, California

Page 5: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Stanford University PressStanford, California© 2011 by the Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University. All rights reserved.

No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system without the prior written permission of Stanford University Press.

Printed in the United States of America on acid-free, archival-quality paper

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Baxter, Hugh. Habermas : the discourse theory of law and democracy / Hugh Baxter. p. cm. — (Jurists—profiles in legal theory) Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 978-0-8047-6912-9 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Habermas, Jürgen. 2. Law—Philosophy. 3. Sociological jurisprudence. 4. Democracy—Philosophy.   5. Discourse analysis. I. Title. II. Series: Jurists—profiles in legal theory.

k230.h332b39 2011

340'.1—dc22

2010039808

Typeset by Thompson Type in 10/13 Galliard

Page 6: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Contents

Acknowledgments vii

Introduction 1

1. Basic Concepts in Habermas’s Theory of Communicative Action 9

2. Habermas’s “Reconstruction” of Modern Law 60

3. Discourse Theory and the Theory and Practice of Adjudication 106

4. System, Lifeworld, and Habermas’s “Communication Theory of Society” 148

5. After Between Facts and Norms: Religion in the Public Square, Multiculturalism, and the “Postnational Constellation” 192

Notes 255 Bibliography 311 Index 323

Page 7: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)
Page 8: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Acknowledgments

This work has been underwritten in part by summer research grants from Boston University. Thanks to the School of Law for that support.

I’ve presented prior versions of parts of this book at the following venues: faculty workshops at the University of Illinois, the University of Texas, Northeastern University, and Boston University; the 2007 and 2008 annual meetings of the Law and Society Association; and the 2000 meet-ing of the Working Group on Law, Culture, and the Humanities. Thanks to the participants at those sessions.

Special thanks to friends and colleagues who read and commented on preliminary versions: David Lyons, Pnina Lahav, Richard McAdams, Manuel Utset, and Daniela Caruso. I have benefited also from communi-cations with Cristina Lafont and John Victor Peterson.

Thanks to the anonymous reviewers at Stanford University Press, par-ticularly Anonymous Reviewer #3.

Heartfelt thanks for the guidance I received over the years from Rhoda Greenspan, Michael Caplan, Kevin Lyons, Bonnie Teitelman, Peg Baim, Sharon Cardamone, and Rachel Bairstow.

In memory of my friend, Francis Tomasic, who introduced me to Habermas’s work.

Deepest appreciation to my parents, Cynthia Lewis Baxter and Mau-rice Baxter, for their love and support throughout my life.

For my wife, Marina Leslie—with gratitude, much love, and great an-ticipation of our future years together.

Page 9: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)
Page 10: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Habermas

Page 11: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)
Page 12: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Introduction

The work you have in front of you is a critical analysis of the complex the-ory of law and democracy developed by celebrated German philosopher and sociologist, Jürgen Habermas (1929– ). It presumes no prior familiar-ity with Habermas’s work and is designed to be understood by those with little prior acquaintance with law and legal theory. As with other volumes in the “Jurists” series, I begin with a brief biographical sketch of my cho-sen figure,1 which I integrate with a brief outline of the book’s plan and central arguments.

Habermas was born on June 18, 1929, in the German town of Gum-mersbach, located in North Rhine-Westphalia about forty miles from Düsseldorf. His grandfather was a Protestant minister and seminary direc-tor, and his father served as a district director of the Bureau of Trade and Industry.2 Habermas describes his father as having been a “passive sym-pathizer” with the Nazi regime.3 According to Habermas’s recollection, “The political climate in our family home was probably not unusual for the time, . . . marked by a bourgeois adaptation to a political situation with which one did not fully identify but which one didn’t seriously criticize either.”4 Near the end of the war, Habermas joined Hitler Youth, and he soon was sent, with other boys apparently as young as twelve, to “man the Western defenses.”5 Habermas recalls that, at the end of the war, when he was just short of sixteen years old, “the radio was reporting the Nuremberg trials, movie theatres were showing the first documentary films, the con-centration camp films. . . . All at once we saw that we had been living in a politically criminal system. I had never imagined that before.”6 The experi-ence was shattering for Habermas, and undoubtedly it was fundamental in

Page 13: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Introduction 2

developing the left-wing political convictions that underlie both his rela-tively mandarin academic interests and also his numerous interventions into political controversies as, by the late 1980s, Germany’s leading public intellectual.7

Between 1945 and 1949, Habermas studied at gymnasium, and be-tween 1949 and 1954 he pursued university studies at Göttingen, Bonn, and Zurich. In 1954, he completed his PhD at the University of Bonn, writing his dissertation on Schelling’s concept of nature. After serving as assistant to first-generation Frankfurt School philosopher Theodor Adorno at the Institute for Social Research, Habermas completed a second doctorate in Marburg. His dissertation (or Habilitationsschrift) is much read today (although not translated into English until 1989): The Struc-tural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Investigation into a Category of Bourgeois Society (1962).8 After serving as a professor at the University of Heidelberg, Habermas succeeded first-generation Frankfurt School figure Max Horkheimer as professor of philosophy and sociology at the Johann Wolfgang Goethe-University in Frankfurt (am Main).9

Habermas’s inaugural lecture at Frankfurt, “Erkenntnis und Interesse,” formed the basis for his 1968 book of the same title, translated into English as Knowledge and Human Interests. Habermas’s argument in that work was that the natural and human sciences are related to fundamental cognitive or “knowledge-constitutive” (erkenntnisleitende) interests, rooted in our species life: interests in, respectively, the control of nature (the “technical” interest) and the establishment of mutual social relations (the “practical” interest). More speculatively still, Habermas argued for a third “emancipatory” in-terest in the elimination of repression, both individual-psychological and social, with psychoanalysis and Marxian ideology critique as the scientific models. While the theory was subjected to intensive criticism,10 leading to Habermas’s backing away from some of its central arguments, the underly-ing distinction between “labor” and “interaction” informed his later work. And Habermas continued to pursue the idea of a critical theory of society that had inspired his speculation as to an emancipatory cognitive interest.

After Knowledge and Human Interests, Habermas began to expand the already extensive theoretical influences on his work. In one line of inquiry, he investigated social systems theory, beginning a more-than-twenty-five-year debate with German sociologist Niklas Luhmann that lasted until the latter’s death in 1998. Habermas and Luhmann coauthored a 1971 book that contained their first but hardly last critical exchange.11 Habermas fol-lowed that work with a more influential 1973 study, Legitimation Crisis.

Page 14: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Introduction 3

Two aspects of that book are especially noteworthy. The first is method-ological: Habermas began his career-long quest of integrating insights from social systems theory, on the one hand, with more standard social theory that begins from the perspective of the acting subject. The idea, as Habermas put in Legitimation Crisis, was to develop a “two-level theory of society,” one that sees society both as system and as “symbolically struc-tured” “lifeworld” of everyday action. “Both paradigms, life-world and sys-tem, are important,” Habermas argued. “The problem is to demonstrate their interconnection.”12 The idea of integrating these two sociological perspectives has been a key concern for Habermas throughout his career.

The second significant development in Legitimation Crisis was substan-tive. The book represents Habermas’s attempt to update Marx’s theory of crisis tendencies in capitalism. Marx’s theory of the tendency toward eco-nomic crisis in capitalist systems depended on a theoretical premise—the labor theory of value—that Habermas rejects. While Habermas allows for the possibility of economic crisis, he argued that it was not beyond possibility that tendencies in that direction could be successfully man-aged by political intervention. Accordingly, his interest shifted more to-ward tendencies toward “rationality crisis” (essentially, overburdening of political planning capacity) and “legitimation crisis” (the inability of an expertocratic and planned state to secure the conditions of its own legiti-macy). The latter form of crisis depends in turn upon tendencies toward “motivation crisis”—the possibility that the post-1960s generation would continue a path of questioning and rejecting the values and motivations presupposed by a capitalist economic system and a liberal democracy. This emphasis on social crisis theory went together with Habermas’s method-ological focus on developing a “two-level” theory of society. Both themes, substantive and methodological, have been central parts of Habermas’s work, particularly up until his turn toward direct consideration of law and legal issues in 1992.

Another weapon in Habermas’s expanding methodological arsenal came from his encounters with Anglo-American analytic philosophy of language, particularly the speech-act theory of (among others) J. L. Austin and John Searle. The focus of speech-act theory on “pragmatics,” or the study of language in use, rather than (from Habermas’s perspective) the more abstract approach of formal semantics, was congenial to Habermas’s attempt to develop a theory of “communicative action” that could ground, ultimately, a new conception of rationality in action: one that he called, not surprisingly, “communicative rationality.” Around this time—the early

Page 15: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Introduction 4

and mid-1970s—Habermas was studying, finally, theories of social evolu-tion as keys to his continuing attempt to recast Marxian understandings of social transformation.

All of these lines of inquiry converged in Habermas’s 1981 magnum opus, Theory of Communicative Action. This two-volume treatise alternated between readings of leading figures in social theory—Max Weber, Georg Lukács, Frankfurt School figures Horkheimer and Adorno, George Her-bert Mead, Emile Durkheim, Talcott Parsons, and finally Marx—with more systematic development of his new two-level theory of society. The action-theoretical or “lifeworld” side of that theory was centered on his understanding of communicative action. The “system” side of that theory developed a Parsons-inspired theory of societies as evolving, input-output related networks of differentiated subsystems—the economic and admin-istrative systems, on Habermas’s account. The “lifeworld,” he argued, was “socially integrated” by shared norms and values. With the development of capitalism, Habermas argued, economic and administrative systems historically evolved from the social lifeworld. These systems are character-ized by mechanisms of “systems integration,” like the market, that bind together patterns of largely self-interested action through the often coun-terintuitive consequences of action rather than the actors’ intentions.

Habermas presented this complex, two-level evolutionary theory of society as a recasting of Weber’s idea of the “rationalization” of Western societies—that is, the incorporation of various forms of rationality and rational action into a variety of social settings. What Habermas tries to capture is what neo-Marxist but Weber-influenced theorists Georg Lu- kács, Max Horkheimer, and Theodor Adorno saw as a distorted form of rationalization, a development they called (and criticized as) “reification.” Habermas sees his task as rescuing this neo-Marxist appropriation of We-ber’s theory of rationalization from Lukács’s lapse into apotheosis of the Communist Party and Adorno’s indulgence of self-conscious paradox in which a critical standard is literally inconceivable. While Habermas argues that the process Weber called “rationalization” had left unexhausted ratio-nal potential that could be exploited by, in particular, more radical democ-ratization, his central theme is a more defensive crisis theory—a revision of the argument of Legitimation Crisis that now sees tendencies toward the “colonization of the lifeworld.” Leaving aside the Marxian question whether advanced capitalist societies might be headed toward economic crisis or “crisis in material reproduction,” Habermas focuses instead on tendencies toward crises in “symbolic reproduction.” By that he means

Page 16: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Introduction 5

an incompatibility between the “functional imperatives” of reproducing (primarily) the economic system and the requirements of society seen as “lifeworld”—social integration, socialization of persons, and cultural re-production. The framework Habermas develops in Theory of Communica-tive Action still informs his work today, including his understanding of law and democracy. Accordingly, in Chapter One of the present book I provide a critical analysis of that framework.

Habermas wrote Legitimation Crisis and Theory of Communicative Ac-tion during his eleven-year stay as director of the Max-Planck Institute for social research in Starnberg, West Germany. In 1982, he returned to Frank-furt. His academic writing for the first few years back at Frankfurt cen-tered around developing a communicative or “discourse” theory of ethics from his theory of communicative action13 and responding to the debate over modernity and postmodernity. With respect to the latter, Habermas maintained his position that the critical and rational potential of moder-nity had been realized only selectively in the development of a capitalist economy and bureaucratic state apparatus. Modernity is thus, in Haber-mas’s view, an “unfinished project.”14 His Philosophical Discourse of Moder-nity (1985) was notable for his engagement (though disappointing in my view) with Michel Foucault and Jacques Derrida, considered at the time as perhaps Habermas’s top theoretical rivals.

Habermas’s political interests became more sharply engaged with the debate, beginning in 1986, over West German revisionist historians’ ac-count of the Nazi period. In this public political debate, carried out in the pages of Die Zeit and Die Frankfurter allgemeine Zeitung, Habermas argued that his conservative opponents had minimized German responsi-bility for the Holocaust. Against the conservative alternative of “national pride,” Habermas began to develop the idea of “constitutional patriotism” as the only form of national attachment that could do justice to univer-salistic principles of morality and political democracy. This idea of consti-tutional patriotism has remained important in Habermas’s recent work, emerging as his idea of responsible political attachment in increasingly multicultural societies.

Around the same time, and inspired by his ongoing encounter with Weber, Habermas began to turn his attention systematically, for the first time, to law and legal theory. His 1986 Tanner Lectures, “Law and Moral-ity,”15 took their departure from Weber’s sociology of law and his concep-tion of political legitimacy. The next year Habermas convened a five-year working group on legal theory that involved several German colleagues

Page 17: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Introduction 6

trained in the field. By 1992, Habermas had completed his monumental Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy.16 My critical analysis of Between Facts and Norms is the core of the present book: Chapters Two, Three, and Four.

Habermas’s project in Between Facts and Norms has two parts. The first is the “discourse theory of law and democracy” proper, which Habermas describes as a “reconstruction” of the “normative self-understanding of . . . modern legal orders.”17 The central theme of this part of the project is that legitimate law and radical democracy mutually presuppose one another. Habermas’s normatively ambitious discourse theory first develops an ac-count of the “system of rights” that must be recognized, in one form or another, for a legal order to be legitimate. He then turns to the “principles of the constitutional state” that would be required to secure those rights. Habermas next “test[s] and elaborate[s] the discourse concept of law and democracy” against, first, contemporary discussions in legal theory, and, second, contemporary controversies in constitutional practice and theory.18

The second main part of Habermas’s project locates this discourse the-ory in a model of modern complex societies. Habermas has two purposes here. First, he wants to examine whether the discourse theory, developed through normative “reconstruction,” actually has a purchase on factually existing social conditions. Second, elaborating his theory of law and de-mocracy through social-theoretical concepts allows him to deepen, and to make more concrete, his normative theory.

The plan of the present study is as follows. I begin, in Chapter One, by setting out the basic concepts of social action and social theory that Habermas incorporates from his work of the late 1970s and 1980s. Here my main focus is on the argument of Habermas’s two-volume Theory of Communicative Action (1981). In Chapters Two and Three I address the first part of Habermas’s work on law and democracy—the normative “discourse theory” proper.

Chapter Two considers Habermas’s “reconstruction” of modern law’s “normative self-understanding.” I discuss in the first part of that chapter Habermas’s account of the basic problematic of modern law—the risk of dissensus that has increased with social modernization—and I analyze the tension between law’s “facticity” and law’s “validity” that organizes Habermas’s entire theory of law and democracy. With that as background, I critically examine in Habermas’s analysis of the “system of rights.” Af-ter a section comparing Habermas’s derivation of that system with Rawls’s better-known generation of principles of justice from the original posi-

Page 18: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Introduction 7

tion, I go on to suggest some skepticism about Habermas’s largest claims for the system of rights: that it reconciles longstanding tensions between “private” and “public autonomy” and between the idea of basic rights and the idea of popular sovereignty. I then criticize Habermas’s account of the constitutional state, particularly his reliance on what he calls “the discourse principle.” This principle is the basis for Habermas’s theory of law and de-mocracy, but I argue that it cannot bear the full weight that Habermas places on it.

In Chapter Three, I turn to Habermas’s “testing” of the discourse theory against recent developments in the theory and practice of adjudica-tion. The first part of Chapter Three addresses the general theory of ad-judication that Habermas develops in dialogue with Dworkin’s theory of “constructive interpretation.” The second part of Chapter Three considers the special case of constitutional adjudication. In both parts, I am critical of the uses to which Habermas puts the notion of judicial “discourses of application”—a notion that is central to Habermas’s idea of courts’ appro-priate role in a separation-of-powers scheme. An additional difficulty in Habermas’s theory is its inability to account for—and Habermas’s under-standable unwillingness to exclude as illegitimate—the common-law ad-judication process that is basic to Anglo-American law. I criticize also the distinction Habermas tries to establish between his “proceduralist” theory of constitutional adjudication and the “neorepublican” theory of Frank Michelman. Finally, I consider the implications that Habermas’s proce-duralist theory might have for constitutional law and democratic politics. Here I engage some recent developments in American constitutional law: Supreme Court decisions in the last few years that concern how electoral districts are to be drawn and whether corporate speech may be permitted to dominate public discussion surrounding elections.

Chapter Four focuses on the second part of Habermas’s theory of law and democracy: the “communications theory of society” and, in particular, the social-theoretical model of “system” and “lifeworld” that Habermas uses to organize that theory. My contentions will be that while Habermas appropriately chooses to revise the model presented in Theory of Communicative Action, and while the strategy of argument is a refreshingly prodemocratic conception rather than politically defensive crisis theory, the revised model nonetheless introduces some difficulties. I suggest in the last section of Chapter Four that Habermas might improve that model by selectively incorporating ideas from his long-time theoretical adversary, systems-theorist Niklas Luhmann.

Page 19: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Introduction 8

During the time Habermas was writing Between Facts and Norms, the Soviet Union collapsed, and Germany was reunified. As the nation’s lead-ing public intellectual, Habermas turned his attention to the new political situation, publishing (to speak for the moment only of books) Die nach-holende Revolution (1991), focusing on the political developments in East-ern Europe and particularly East Germany; A Berlin Republic: Writings on Germany (1995); and The Inclusion of the Other (1996). The last collection is particularly rich, as it contains Habermas’s side of his much-anticipated 1995 debate with preeminent American political philosopher John Rawls as well as Habermas’s first systematic attempts to consider the possibilities for democracy beyond the nation-state. Inclusion of the Other also features Habermas’s taking up of the Kantian political project of “perpetual peace” under the heading “the constitutionalization of international law.”

Habermas since has pursued the idea of (what he calls) the “postna-tional constellation,” particularly concerning the possibilities for democracy beyond the nation state, and he has pressed severe criticism of American intervention in Iraq under the second Bush administration. During these years Habermas has become a prominent advocate of European integra-tion, though in his most recent discussions he has sharply criticized what he takes to be the undemocratic means through which that integration, after the failure of the proposed European constitution, has been pursued.

Finally, and particularly in his Between Naturalism and Religion (2005), Habermas has sought to understand the worldwide resurgence of reli-gion.19 He has weighed in on the debate over multiculturalism and the discussion over the role of religious argument in the sphere of democratic public debate. Along these lines, Habermas has jointly published a dia-logue with Pope Benedict XVI, and he has sought to engage the moral and ethical questions surrounding new biotechnologies.20

In Chapter Five I consider this spate of writing since Between Facts and Norms. In keeping with the present book’s focus on Habermas’s theory of law and democracy, I explore in particular three of Habermas’s main themes: the role of religion in the public square, political-philosophical issues surrounding multiculturalism, and the possibilities of democracy beyond the nation-state (with special attention to the European Union).

Page 20: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

chapter one

Basic Concepts in Habermas’s Theory of Communicative Action

Habermas begins his construction of the theoretical framework he devel-ops in Theory of Communicative Action with a theory of action. He aims to go beyond standard conceptions of rational action to generate a theory of “communicative action.” In this form of action—or, more properly, interaction—participants pursue their goals either on the basis of an exist-ing consensual understanding or with the aim of developing that kind of understanding (see section 1.1). Habermas sets his concept of communica-tive action within a concept of society: a concept that, following the phe-nomenological tradition in philosophy and social theory, Habermas calls society as “lifeworld” (see section 1.2).

Both in Theory of Communicative Action and later in Between Facts and Norms, Habermas takes the notion of the “lifeworld” as the basic concep-tion of society, to be amended or supplemented only for cause. As I sug-gested in the Introduction, Habermas argues that in the course of social evolution—specifically, with the rise of a capitalist economy and a bureau-cratic state—systems of economic and political action develop in which ac-tion is coordinated not by consensual understanding by the consequences of self-interested action. I consider in section 1.3 Habermas’s idea of such “systems.” Habermas’s thinking here is inspired by his reading of Talcott Parsons, the preeminent American sociologist from the early 1950s until perhaps the early 1970s. In section 1.4, I consider how Habermas puts the lifeworld and system concepts together in his model of system/lifeworld interchange. This model is the basis of Habermas’s critical theory, from its development in 1981 at least until Habermas revised it in his 1992 work Between Facts and Norms.

Page 21: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 10

My argument will be that in elaborating each of these basic concepts, and particularly in his account of system/lifeworld interchange, Habermas tends toward polar distinctions that cannot be maintained. Communi-cative action is not so clearly demarcated from other forms of action as Habermas suggests, and because Habermas constructs his notion of the lifeworld around communicative action the distinction between system and lifeworld similarly is too sharply drawn. This tendency toward stylized oppositions, I contend, ultimately undermines the system/lifeworld model Habermas develops in Theory of Communicative Action. And thus to the ex-tent Habermas relies on that model in Between Facts and Norms, his account of law is correspondingly weakened. Further, I argue, the critical model Habermas develops in Theory of Communicative Action is more functionalist than straightforwardly normative. Habermas argues that the overextension of economic and bureaucratic forms of rationality threaten the “symbolic reproduction of the lifeworld,” inducing forms of social crisis that he calls collectively “the colonization of the lifeworld.” I will argue in subsequent chapters that Habermas revises this politically defensive strategy by argu-ing, more positively, that the idea of legitimate modern law and more radi-cally democratic political practice mutually imply one another.

1.1 com mu nicati v e action

Habermas distinguishes among three types of rational action1: instrumen-tal action, strategic action, and communicative action. Typically he marks the differences among these types with a pair of crosscutting distinctions.2 One distinction is between two “orientations” of action, toward “success” or toward an “understanding” between the actor and others. The other dis-tinction tracks Max Weber’s notions of “social” and “nonsocial” action—where “social action” means action in which the actor “takes account of the behavior of others” and orients her action accordingly.3

Both instrumental action and strategic action are oriented toward suc-cess rather than mutual understanding. They differ, however, along the lines of Habermas’s second distinction. Instrumental action is essentially the soli-tary performance of a task, according to “technical rules.” As such, instru-mental action is “nonsocial,” in Habermas’s typology. Strategic action, by contrast, is designed to “influenc[e] the decisions of a rational opponent,” according to “rules of rational choice.” Instrumental actions may be ele-

Page 22: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 11

ments of a pattern of social action—either communicative or strategic—but they do not themselves comprise a distinct type of social action.4

1.1.1 The Distinction between Communicative and Strategic Action

More difficult is the distinction between communicative and strate-gic action. The general distinction Habermas draws between these two forms of action—orientation toward success versus orientation toward understanding—is not by itself very helpful. As Habermas allows, com-municative action as well as strategic action is goal directed, and the goals of communicative action are not necessarily reducible to the aim of reach-ing understanding. Orientation to “success” versus orientation toward “understanding,” then, does not seem a promising basis for distinguish-ing between strategic and communicative action—at least not without ad-ditional explanation. Nor does the term communicative by itself mark the difference: Habermas acknowledges both that communicative action does not consist wholly in speech acts5 and also that strategic action, too, may include the use of speech.6

The picture becomes clearer, however, when one considers the pur-pose of Habermas’s typology. As a social theorist, Habermas is interested primarily in how individual actions can be coordinated into patterns of interaction.7 For this reason, Habermas generally uses the terms commu-nicative and strategic to refer to types of interaction rather than to discrete individual actions. The problem Habermas sets himself—and the basis for his distinction between communicative and strategic action—is to identify the mechanisms that coordinate these two types of interaction.8

This task Habermas approaches through his “formal pragmatics.” With the term pragmatics, Habermas signals his focus on language in use—on utterances or “speech acts”—as opposed to a semantic focus on the mean-ing of isolated sentences or propositions. By “formal,” Habermas means that he seeks not to describe and classify the “communicative practice of everyday life”9 as it operates within a particular language—that would be the approach Habermas calls “empirical” pragmatics—but instead to “rationally reconstruct” the necessary presuppositions of communicative practice.10 What Habermas pursues in his formal pragmatics is a theory of the unreflectively mastered, pretheoretical communicative capacities of or-dinary competent speakers. This theory focuses, in particular, on the way speakers may use speech acts to establish, maintain, or transform social relationships with other persons.

Page 23: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 12

The central idea in Habermas’s formal pragmatics, and the basis for his conception of communicative action, is the notion of a speech act’s “validity.” Habermas distinguishes among three forms of validity to which speech acts may lay claim: propositional truth,11 normative right-ness (Richtigkeit), and sincerity (Wahrhaftigkeit).12 Typically, Habermas observes, just one of these validity claims is thematic in a particular speech act: In a confession, for example, the claim to sincerity is thematic, as is the claim to truth in a factual assertion.13 Habermas’s formulation of the main categories of speech acts reflects this insight: In “constative,” “regulative,” and “expressive” utterances, the claims to truth, rightness, and sincerity are (respectively) thematic.14

Nonetheless, Habermas contends, any speech act in communica-tive action raises simultaneously all three claims, even if (ordinarily) the speaker raises only one directly or thematically.15 Here perhaps Habermas stretches the notion of “raising a claim” too far. We would not ordinar-ily say, for example, that a speaker’s request for a glass of water “raises a truth claim”—that she claims it to be true that a glass of water can be ob-tained and brought in a reasonable amount of time. More likely we would say that she presupposes these factual circumstances. A weaker but more plausible formulation of Habermas’s position might therefore be that every utterance constitutive for communicative action raises a claim to or presup-poses validity in the three respects Habermas identifies. An alternative (and also weaker) formulation is that, at least in principle, any speech act can be criticized along any of the three dimensions of validity.16 For example, a statement that the argument of a colleague’s book depends on five identi-fied factual errors would be a constative speech act in which propositional truth is the thematic claim. But if one were to make such a statement at a party celebrating the book’s publication, a hearer might respond by saying that such a criticism, even if true, is normatively inappropriate in the con-text of its utterance. Or the hearer might reply by challenging the speaker’s sincerity—by, for example, suggesting that the criticism arises more from the speaker’s jealousy than from a serious evaluation of the book’s merits. In this second revision of Habermas’s thesis, every speech act constitutive for communicative action involves all three claims in that, in principle, a hearer can challenge the utterance in each of the three different ways.

Either of these two weaker versions of Habermas’s thesis would suf-fice for his purposes. And the second of the two, emphasizing the role of a hearer’s criticism, connects to an important theme in Habermas’s no-tion of communicative action. Validity claims, Habermas maintains, are

Page 24: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 13

essentially criticizable.17 By “criticizable,” Habermas means that in com-municative action the hearer may respond to the claims by taking a “yes or no position”—either accepting the speech act’s claims or opposing them with criticism or requests for justification.18 And at least to the extent the interaction between speaker and hearer is to remain communicative,19 the speaker assumes the obligation of providing such justification if neces-sary.20 Further, particularly in the case of regulative speech acts (such as a promise), mutual acceptance of a validity claim may impose future obliga-tions.21 In these senses, acceptance of validity claims, or further discussion between speaker and hearer aimed at consensus concerning those claims, is the “mechanism of understanding [Verständigung]” that coordinates communicative action.

Because the point often has been misunderstood, it is worth under-scoring that Habermas does not equate communicative action with the speech acts that coordinate it. In communicative action, as in all rational action, the participants pursue goals and plans of action, based on their interpretations of the situation.22 But communicative action is action pro-ceeding from or directed toward achieving a consensus. In communicative action, Habermas says, actors “coordinate their individual plans . . . on the basis of communicatively achieved agreement.”23

The mechanism coordinating strategic action, on Habermas’s scheme, is not “consensus”—mutual acceptance of validity claims—but “influence” (Einflußsnahme).24 The term influence requires explication. In one sense of the word, communicative actors may seek to influence each other. In dis-cussing a problematic claim, one may try to persuade the other that his po-sition is correct, and the other may try to convince the one of her criticism. But by “influence,” Habermas says, he means “exert a causal influence,”25 independent of the convincing force of reasons that could support claims to validity. So far, however, the characterization of “influence,” and thus the characterization of strategic action, is only negative—influence oper-ates in some way other than mutual recognition of validity claims.

Habermas tries to characterize the mechanism of influence more pre-cisely by distinguishing between two subtypes, “open” and “concealed” strategic action. Of these two subtypes, Habermas has given far more at-tention to concealed strategic action. The kind of “influence” characteristic of concealed strategic action is, in effect, deception26—primarily conscious deception.27 The more technical criterion Habermas adopts for concealed strategic action concerns the “avowability” of the parties’ intentions or aims. In concealed strategic interaction, at least one participant pursues

Page 25: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 14

aims that he knows could not be avowed without jeopardizing that par-ticipant’s success, while at least one participant assumes that all are acting communicatively. A simple example: One person requests a loan from an-other person without disclosing that the money will be used for a criminal purpose. Assuming that the person from whom the loan is requested has no reason to endorse the criminal purpose, the aim is nonavowable, in Habermas’s sense, because to declare it is to make tender of the loan un-likely. This kind of action is parasitic on communicative action, Habermas believes, because the success of the coordinating speech act depends on the hearer’s belief that the speaker could redeem the claim to have spoken his intentions sincerely or truthfully.28

Habermas has given less attention to the notion of openly strategic ac-tion. From his general characterization of strategic action—that it operates through “influence” rather than “consensus”—we can assume that stra-tegic actors do not presuppose or seek a consensus in plans or goals or at least not one resting on mutual acceptance of validity claims. But how can it be characterized positively?

In Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas attempted to specify open strategic action with formal-pragmatic analysis. Focusing on the variant of open strategic action most difficult to distinguish from commu-nicative action—the sort that, like communicative action, is coordinated by speech acts—Habermas assumed that the characteristic kind of coor-dinating speech act is the “simple” or “pure imperative.” By “simple” or “pure” imperative, Habermas meant a command that is a sheer assertion of power. To these simple imperatives Habermas contrasted speech acts that are similar in form—involving a command or order—but that, on Haber-mas’s analysis, belong to communicative action. These sorts of commands or orders Habermas called “normatively authorized requests.” Habermas’s example of such a request was a flight attendant’s instruction to a passen-ger to extinguish a cigarette.

These two kinds of speech act differ, Habermas argued, in their “ac-ceptability conditions,”29 by which Habermas meant the speaker’s basis for expecting compliance and the addressee’s basis for complying. In the case of pure imperatives, the basis for compliance is only the addressee’s fear of negative sanctions (or interest in positive sanctions) over which the speaker has disposal. This motivation Habermas characterized as “merely empirical.” In the case of normatively authorized requests, by contrast, the speaker expects compliance not just because she can deploy sanctions but because compliance is normatively required. If the addressee accepts

Page 26: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 15

the speaker’s claim that compliance is normatively required—required, in Habermas’s example, by a valid safety regulation—then the interaction is coordinated by mutual acceptance of a claim to normative rightness. Because the claim to normative validity is criticizable, Habermas argued, it must be supported or opposed with reasons, not simply with reference to potential sanctions. Accordingly, Habermas argued, the hearer’s accep-tance of the speaker’s claim may be motivated rationally, not just empiri-cally.30 Habermas thus characterized the opposition between communi-cative and open strategic action through a series of further oppositions: between normatively authorized requests and simple imperatives, between validity claims and power claims, between reasons and sanctions, and be-tween rational and empirical motivation.

Habermas since has disavowed this way of distinguishing between communicative and open strategic action. In particular, he has acknowl-edged the untenability of any “sharp distinction between normatively au-thorized [requests] and simple imperatives.”31 Instead, Habermas now ar-gues, from a sociological perspective we see a “continuum” between purely “de facto” power and “power transformed into normative authority.”32 While at one end of the continuum is the pure or simple imperative—his standard example is the bank robber’s “hands up” demand—Habermas now admits that such an imperative is only an “extreme case” or “limit case.”33 Rather than a “categorial” difference between pure imperatives and normatively authorized requests, Habermas maintains, there is only a “difference of degree.”34

With this concession, Habermas must abandon the idea that pure imper-atives exemplify open strategic action generally. If the bank robber’s com-mand were the paradigm case, then open strategic action would be a socially marginal form of action. And that would be inconsistent with the main line of Habermas’s work. A prominent feature of modern societies, Habermas argues, is the development of “spheres of strategic action”—preeminently the market.35 The category of open strategic action must be understood more broadly than the “pure imperative” model would suggest.

Habermas has not much elaborated on how we are to conceive of open strategic action, if not along the lines of the pure imperative. But from Habermas’s preliminary specification of strategic action, together with other remarks scattered throughout his work, we can construct at least a sketch. The paradigmatic case of open strategic action seems to be compe-tition among rational opponents, each pursuing self-interested goals ac-cording to rules of rational choice. Each tries to influence or steer each

Page 27: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 16

other’s choices, and each is aware that the other is operating in this way. The choices of each are conditioned by their respective predictions of the other’s choices as well as by the consequences of their interaction. Game theory, rational choice theory, and decision theory, Habermas sometimes suggests, formalize this paradigmatic case of open strategic action.36

But even this paradigmatic case differs in important ways from the norm-free, purely power-driven form of action that the “pure imperative” model described. Strategic competition, Habermas acknowledges, typically takes place against a normative backdrop.37 Strategic action in the mar-ketplace, for example, presupposes general acceptance of a variety of legal norms—such as criminal-law norms that forbid some tactics or strategies and permit others, norms of property law that outfit some with more mar-ket power than their opponents, rules that define the possibilities for dif-ferent kinds of transaction, and the like. These legal norms structure the participants’ choices among strategies and tactics. Further, apart from state-enforced law, informal social norms may shape strategic interactions in par-ticular spheres of economic activity. Even paradigmatic cases of strategic action, then, may involve the mutual recognition of legal and social norms.

Habermas’s recognition that the pure imperative is only the “limit case” of open strategic action, not the paradigmatic case, has further conse-quences. In rejecting the “pure imperative” model, Habermas recognized a “continuum” along which power relations are more or less underwritten by social norms. This recognition suggests a corresponding continuum within the concept of strategic action, according to which instances of strategic action may be more or less structured and coordinated by binding social norms that the participants mutually recognize. If this is so, then strategic interaction may shade more or less toward communicative action. Open stra-tegic action, in short, cannot be as “norm free,” or as sharply distinguished from communicative action, as the “pure imperative” model suggested.38

Similar observations apply on the other side of the communicative/strategic distinction. In many actual instances of communicative action, the sanctions Habermas considers characteristic of strategic action may be ready to hand. Habermas’s own example of the flight attendant’s “no smoking” request to the passenger illustrates this point. While this request raises a claim to normative validity, the passenger likely will not get far by treating that claim as if it were readily criticizable. The sanctions available to the flight attendant—even if never invoked or even referred to—likely will limit the extent to which the normative claim, criticizable in principle, actually may be criticized. This is not to deny the difference between the

Page 28: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 17

flight attendant’s normatively authorized request and the bank robber’s demand. But it is to suggest that, just as actual instances of strategic action are not norm free, so too are many actual instances of communicative ac-tion far from power or sanction free. (Interactions in the workplace are a good example.) Habermas’s point about the continuum of power relations suggests a continuum between the “pure types” of communicative and strategic action.

Habermas appears to have come to this conclusion. He now describes interactions as “fall[ing] along a continuum” between purely communica-tive and purely strategic action, with most actual situations presenting a “mélange” of these types.39 In fact, Habermas’s “discourse theory of law” preserves an important place for action that reflects elements of both pure types, regulated bargaining and fair compromise. What Habermas insists on is not an on-or-off distinction among actual interactions in the world but a difference between two approaches to the dimensions of validity he distinguishes. Habermas expresses this difference as one between the “per-formative” attitude, constitutive for communicative action, and the “ob-jectivating” attitude that is constitutive for strategic action.

By “performative,” Habermas means (in this context) something like “oriented toward validity.” Within the performative attitude, social norms are criticizable and in need of justification.40 By “objectivating,” Habermas means that social norms appear not so much as potentially justifiable or criticizable but simply as social facts, with more or less calculable conse-quences attaching to their violation or obedience. Within this objectivat-ing attitude, norms are primarily conditions for, or obstacles impeding, the success of the actor’s self-interested pursuits.41 (Think here of Holmes’s “bad man.”42) Increasingly, Habermas has come to rely on this opposition between “performative” and “objectivating,” not just to distinguish be-tween communicative and strategic action but also to mark the difference between different methodological approaches to social theory.43 And the opposition between the corresponding understandings of social norms—seen, respectively under the aspects of “validity” (Geltung) and “facticity” (Faktizität)—underlies Habermas’s theory of law and democracy.44

This distinction between the performative and objectivating attitudes, like the other distinctions Habermas has invoked to differentiate commu-nicative and open strategic action,45 does not unequivocally and uncontro-versially classify actual interactions as purely communicative or purely stra-tegic. The existence of intermediate and borderline cases is unsurprising, however, and it does not pose a fatal objection to Habermas’s typology. The

Page 29: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 18

real questions are whether Habermas’s characterizations of communicative and strategic action mark an intelligible alternative—whether the pure types are sufficiently distinguishable—and more important, whether the distinc-tion and typology mark useful differences for theoretical purposes.

This last question is the one I want to address. Habermas’s typology of rational action is not just an abstract classificatory scheme for placing ac-tual interactions in one box or the other or between boxes (though Haber-mas insists that it must be able to do that too46). The distinction between communicative and strategic action is designed with further purposes of social theory in mind.

1.1.2 Communicative Rationality and Discourse

One such purpose is to provide an account of the ways modern socie-ties manage conflict and dissensus. As will become clearer in the following discussion, a central premise of Habermas’s theory of modernity is that the risk of dissensus—disagreement as to plans of action or as to claims about the world—increased with the demise of traditional forms of authority and traditional worldviews.47 Habermas distinguishes three basic alternatives for handling dissensus in simple interactions: attempting to resolve the disagreement communicatively, continuing the interaction under prem-ises of strategic action, and breaking off the interaction entirely.48 Law, it will turn out, institutionalizes all three possibilities. It creates spheres of action in which individuals may pursue their interests without securing the agreement of others—whether by refusing to interact or by opting to interact strategically. And law also establishes procedures through which disagreements can be resolved more or less communicatively. The mecha-nisms of action coordination Habermas distinguishes in his typology of social action find analogues in his social theory of law.

A second purpose of Habermas’s action theory is to rethink and ex-pand the idea of rationality. Most familiar accounts of rationality—such as those found in economic theory, game theory, decision theory and ra-tional choice theory—are keyed toward the problematics of instrumental or strategic action. Beginning from the notion of communicative action, Habermas hopes to develop a new conception of rationality, which he calls, unsurprisingly, “communicative rationality.” The idea of communi-cative rationality, like the idea of communicative action, depends centrally on the notion of criticizability. Claims to validity are essentially criticizable, and they may be supported or opposed with reasons and argument. The

Page 30: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 19

criticizability of validity claims creates the rational potential of communi-cative action—the possibility of communicative rationality.

One way to develop the dimensions of Habermas’s notion of commu-nicative rationality is to distinguish between everyday and more reflective forms of communicative action.49 Habermas’s example of the flight atten-dant’s request to the passenger is an example of everyday communicative action. If the passenger responds to the request by demanding reasons, the flight attendant likely will invoke the relevant federal regulation and explain that he has authority to enforce it. Should the passenger demand more justification than that—by, for example, questioning the FAA’s au-thority to pass such a regulation or by invoking a putative constitutional right to smoke at will—the flight attendant likely will switch over to strate-gic action, mentioning the sanctions for failure to comply and, if necessary, deploying those sanctions. And so, while the regulation offers a reason for compliance, and one not entirely reducible to the mere fact of potential sanctions, the role of rational criticism and justification is sharply circum-scribed. The fact that a claim is criticizable in principle does not mean that criticisms and demands for justification always are in place. In everyday contexts, the pressures of action often limit the rational potential of com-municative action.

When removed from the pressures of immediate action, however, this rational potential may be developed more fully. Habermas refers to various forms of “argumentation” or “discourse,”50 in which participants pursue more methodically the task of criticizing and defending the claims to va-lidity Habermas has identified. Here validity claims serve less as a means of coordinating participants’ goal-directed plans of action—as in everyday communicative action—and more as an explicit theme of communication and debate.

Habermas introduces the idea of discourse through various “idealiza-tions.” Participants in discourse must have equal opportunities to raise topics, arguments, and criticisms.51 The situation must exclude all force “except the force of the better argument,” and it must exclude “all mo-tives except a cooperative search for the truth.”52 Habermas sometimes has referred to these idealizations as describing an “ideal speech situation,”53 or alternatively, an “ideal communication community.”54 While Habermas describes these conditions as “general pragmatic presuppositions” of dis-course,55 he is aware that they are never completely fulfilled. Here it is a matter of more and less, and Habermas is willing to speak of “discourse” when these demanding conditions are “sufficiently fulfilled.”56 The ideal

Page 31: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 20

conditions are “presupposed” in actual communicative practice to the ex-tent that significant deviations are a prima facie reason to question an ap-parent consensus that is reached—though these deviations are of course not sufficient to refute definitively a claim on which the participants have reached agreement.

Discourses, Habermas says, are exceptional forms of communicative action—“islands in the sea of practice.”57 Nonetheless, Habermas claims, the institutionalization of discursive practices—in contexts such as scien-tific research, democratic procedure, and legal procedure—is a characteris-tic feature of modern societies. These developments Habermas interprets as a progressive realization of the rational potential implicit in communica-tive action. In this way Habermas recasts Max Weber’s theory of “rational-ization,” focusing on the realization—though only a partial and selective realization—of communicative rationality.

But for this task, Habermas needs a concept of society to supplement his typology of social action. The first “level” of his “two-level” theory pre-sents society as the “lifeworld” of social groups and communicative actors.

1.2 lifewor ld

One would not choose the ungainly term lifeworld unless one wanted to mark a contrast with some other way of understanding the world. The term originated in the later work of the philosopher Edmund Husserl, who opposed it to the world as constructed by the “objective sciences.”58 The lifeworld, for Husserl, was the everyday, pretheoretical world of taken-for-granted certainties. This “realm of original self-evidences”59 provides the “grounding soil” for all human activities, including the scientific ac-tivity of constructing the “objective-scientific” world.60 Consistent with his method of transcendental phenomenology, Husserl sought to map the “formal,” “general,” and “invariant” structures of the lifeworld as such.61

This “ontology of the lifeworld,”62 left largely unpublished at Husserl’s death in 1938,63 speaks more directly to the concerns of transcendental phe-nomenology than to those of substantive social theorizing. But it offered a starting point for the work of Alfred Schutz, a social theorist and philoso-pher who was much influenced by Max Weber as well as Husserl.64 Schutz, who was more interested than Husserl in the methodology of the social sciences—and better informed as well65—attempted to describe the general structures of the everyday, prescientific world in a way that would be fruit-

Page 32: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 21

ful for social theory. Schutz, following Husserl, came to call this world of everyday action and experience the “lifeworld.”66

1.2.1 The “Structural Components” of the Lifeworld

Habermas’s initial presentation of the lifeworld concept largely tracks Schutz’s analysis.67 The lifeworld is the unproblematic, taken-for-granted setting in which actors are located spatially, temporally, and socially. Ac-tors encounter both an objective or natural world of things and a social world of other human beings. Their encounters with those worlds are shaped by their past experiences. But this lifeworld is essentially shared or “intersubjective,” not the creation or private preserve of individual sub-jects. The “segment of the lifeworld” in which particular actions or interac-tions take place is the “situation” of action. The situation is a “context of relevance” circumscribed by a “horizon” rather than by fixed boundaries: What is within the horizon of relevance, and thus included in the situation of action, depends on the “theme” of action and the actors’ “plans.” Actors interpret and define their situation, and formulate their plans, in reliance upon a “stock of knowledge”—socially conditioned and transmitted and differentially distributed among a society’s members. Action, on this view, is the “mastery of a situation,” or the realization of a plan.68

But even in this preliminary sketch of the lifeworld concept, Habermas introduces an important variation on Schutz’s account. Schutz links the lifeworld to the problematic of action in general—in fact, to the problem-atic of “subjective experience” in general, including (for example) imag-ining, dreaming, and fantasy, as well as action.69 Habermas, by contrast, introduces the lifeworld as the background not to experience in general, nor even to action in general, but as the background and “horizon” for specifically communicative action.70 The concept of the lifeworld, Haber-mas says, is “complementary to that of communicative action.”71

Accordingly, Habermas develops his concept of the lifeworld in terms familiar from his theory of communicative action. In interpreting their situations and pursuing their plans, he says, actors in “lifeworld” situations proceed consensually. Their actions presuppose, or are directed toward establishing, “common situation definitions.” On the basis of these com-mon situation definitions, they seek to harmonize their plans of action. The mechanism for this cooperative process of interpretation and action is the mechanism of communicative action: mutual acceptance of claims to validity. With perhaps unnecessary flourish, Habermas describes the

Page 33: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 22

lifeworld as “so to speak, the transcendental site where speaker and hearer meet, where they can reciprocally raise claims . . . , and where they can criticize and confirm those validity claims, settle their disagreements, and arrive at agreements.”72

This “communicative-theoretical” recasting of Schutz’s lifeworld concept leads Habermas to further revisions. A main target is Schutz’s notion of the “stock of knowledge,” which Habermas interprets as the “cultural patterns of interpretation, evaluation, and expression” on which communicative ac-tors rely “to negotiate a common definition of a situation” and compatible plans of action.73 Even understood in this communication-theoretical way, Habermas argues, the cultural “stock of knowledge” cannot be the only re-source on which communicative actors rely. According to Habermas,

the one-sidedness of the culturalistic concept of the lifeworld becomes clear when we consider that communicative action is not only a process of reaching understanding; in coming to an understanding about something in the world, actors are at the same time taking part in interactions through which they de-velop, confirm, and renew their memberships in social groups and their own identities. Communicative actions are not only processes of interpretation in which cultural knowledge is “tested against the world”; they are at the same time processes of social integration and of socialization.74

Thus, the lifeworld resources on which communicative actors rely, in inter-preting their situations and harmonizing their plans, include group mem-berships and personal identities, as well as the cultural stock of knowledge.75

The items on this list are not drawn out of thin air. They correspond to the culture/society/personality schema that Talcott Parsons developed in American sociology.76 According to Habermas, culture, society, and personality are “the structural components of the lifeworld.”77 He defines these “components” as follows:

I use the term culture for the stock of knowledge from which participants in communication supply themselves with interpretations as they come to an understanding about something in the world. I use the term society for the legitimate orders through which participants regulate their memberships in social groups and thereby secure solidarity. By personality I understand the competences that make a subject capable of speaking and acting, that put him in a position to take part in processes of reaching understanding and thereby assert his own identity.78

These initial definitions require some explication. First, with respect to the “society” component, Habermas’s terminological choice is confusing. He is, at this point, analyzing society as lifeworld, and thus it is peculiar

Page 34: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 23

to use the term society to designate a mere component of the lifeworld. The term institutional component79 might better express Habermas’s intention. The component “society,” Habermas says, is the system of social institu-tions80 that define group memberships and coordinate interaction through binding norms and institutionalized values. Generally Habermas includes within the societal component items such as the constitutional framework of state offices and central “legal institutions” like contract and property,81 as well as “the bases of constitutional law, the principles of criminal law and penal procedure, and all regulation of punishable offenses close to morality.”82 We will see, however, that for Habermas both the state and the law occupy a double status—he analyzes each in “system” as well as “lifeworld” terms.

The “personality” component includes not just the speech- and action-related competences that Habermas mentions in the above definition but also motivations.83 Habermas, of course, is working at a high level of ab-straction when he refers to competences and motivations as a structural component of the lifeworld, not just attributes of individual persons. What he has in mind is something like a social stock of typical personal compe-tences and motivations, some subset of which individuals develop through processes of socialization and continuing social interaction. As with the distribution of knowledge, the distribution of these competences and mo-tivations is far from uniform.

1.2.2 The Symbolic Reproduction of the Lifeworld

This account of culture, society, and personality as structural compo-nents of the lifeworld is not just an abstract classification of the resources on which communicative actors rely. Habermas uses it to address the basic social-theoretical question of how a society reproduces itself—how, that is, it maintains itself through time, despite (or rather, through) changes in the content of cultural tradition, institutional structure, and personal competences.84 He distinguishes two aspects of social reproduction. The “symbolic reproduction” of society as lifeworld is the reproduction of the different components he has distinguished—culture, society, and per-sonality. The “material reproduction” of society as lifeworld involves the “maintenance of the material substratum of the lifeworld.”85 Material re-production implicates the “purposive” aspect of communicative action—“goal-directed interventions into the objective world”—while symbolic reproduction depends more on the aspect of mutual understanding.86

Page 35: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 24

To each of the components of society-seen-as-lifeworld, Habermas at-tributes a particular function in symbolic reproduction. “Cultural repro-duction” consists in the transmission and renewal of cultural knowledge, so as to “secur[e] a continuity of tradition and coherence of knowledge sufficient for daily practice.” “Social integration” establishes social soli-darity through shared norms and institutionalized values. In so doing, it coordinates interaction and “stabilizes the identity of groups to an extent sufficient for everyday practice.” “Socialization” operates to develop per-sonal identities, “secur[ing] for succeeding generations the acquisition of generalized competences for action and see[ing] to it that individual life histories are in harmony with collective forms of life.”87 Unsurprisingly—because Habermas defines the lifeworld as the background for commu-nicative action—these reproductive processes operate primarily through communicative action.88

Habermas’s typology of reproductive processes makes clear that the lifeworld components he distinguishes—culture, society, and personality—are interrelated. The reproduction of any one component, he says, contrib-utes to the reproduction of the other two as well.89 And further, Habermas argues, any particular communicative interaction both draws on and helps reproduce each of the lifeworld’s components:

In coming to an understanding with one another about their situation, par-ticipants in interaction stand in a cultural tradition that they at once use and renew; in coordinating their actions by way of intersubjectively recognizing validity claims, they are at once relying on membership in social groups and strengthening the integration of those same groups; through participating in interactions with competently acting reference persons, the growing child in-ternalizes the value orientations of his social group and acquires generalized capacities for action.90

Nothing guarantees that the reproduction of culture, society, and person-ality will be successful. For that reason, Habermas’s typology addresses also the “manifestations of crisis” that appear with “disturbances” in the various reproductive processes. Here, too, Habermas sees the various life-world components as interrelated. Just as successful reproduction of one component contributes to the reproduction of the other two, Habermas argues, so does disturbance in any one of the reproductive processes im-pinge upon the other two.91

More important than the names Habermas assigns these nine crisis ten-dencies is the place that they collectively occupy in his critical social theory. They operate as indices for the “pathological” developments he diagnoses

Page 36: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 25

in contemporary societies. As we will see, the general thesis of Theory of Communicative Action is that the “rationalization of the lifeworld”—the re-alization of communicative rationality in culture, society, and personality—makes possible and necessary the development of economic and adminis-trative systems that are “uncoupled” from the action-coordinating, socially integrating mechanism of communicative action. The “hypertrophic” de-velopment of these systems, Habermas argues, causes “the penetration of forms of economic and administrative rationality”92 into “communicatively structured areas of life,”93 with resulting disturbances in cultural repro-duction, social integration, and socialization. These crisis tendencies in the “symbolic reproduction of the lifeworld,” then, are the criteria by which Habermas identifies social pathologies.

I will later suggest difficulties in Habermas’s argument for this thesis. For now, it is enough to note why Habermas might be attracted to this strategy of argument. The thesis’s premises seem normatively minimalist: He appeals not to freedom or justice or democracy or autonomy or some other value, but to functional necessity.94 And who can argue with func-tional necessity?

The answer is that everyone can. As Habermas pointed out almost forty years ago, against then-dominant biological conceptions of social systems theory, it is extremely difficult to define, in an uncontroversial way, the equilibrium state and reproductive parameters for sociocultural systems.95 This observation calls into question whether Habermas’s strategy can be as normatively parsimonious as it first seems. To determine, for example, whether a process of cultural reproduction has been successful or path-ological, one would have to decide (in Habermas’s terms) whether “the transmission and renewal of cultural knowledge” has “secured a continuity of tradition and coherence of knowledge sufficient for daily practice.” And to make this determination, one would have to take a position on some of the normative issues that, at first glance, were avoided by recourse to “functional necessity.” For example: Is a cultural tradition best “contin-ued” when it has been preserved without substantial change or when it has been subjected to rigorous critical examination and transformation? One’s answer to this question will influence whether one sees, for example, re-vision of the literary canon as consistent with successful cultural repro-duction or as pathological. Similarly, the question whether knowledge has been transmitted to a degree “sufficient for daily practice” may require the theorist to decide whose daily practice matters, or matters most, and what that daily practice should look like. How much does the ordinary citizen

Page 37: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 26

need to know about politics? About high culture? Whether one sees the present distribution of knowledge as normal or pathological is a matter of political controversy. Similar observations would apply to the other two reproductive processes Habermas identifies.96

Habermas, of course, is aware that diagnoses of social crisis cannot be uncontroversial. He would resist the suggestion, however, that the matter is simply a matter of the observing theorist’s politics. Instead, he suggests, one can speak of crisis to the extent that—and only to the extent that—a society’s members experience their situation as such.97 As Habermas ac-knowledges, this question of how members of a society experience social change requires empirical research.98 His own efforts, however, tend in a more strongly theoretical direction—toward formulating a hypothesis that could guide this empirical research.99 The hypothesis is based on what he takes to be a tension between the requirements of a “rational-ized lifeworld” and the “imperatives” of the economic and administrative “systems.” Habermas’s argument thus depends on how he specifies the “ra-tionalization of the lifeworld.”

1.2.3 The Rationalization of the Lifeworld

In the history of social theory,100 the notion of “rationalization” is most closely associated with Max Weber. Weber’s introduction to his studies of the world religions101 mentions the following historical developments under the heading of “Occidental rationalism”: modern empirical and ex-perimental science; systematic theology; a systematized, formalized, and predictable law; various developments in music, including Western sys-tems of harmony, written notation, and innovations in instrumentation; the Gothic vault and dome in architecture; the technique of perspective in painting; the development and market circulation of printed literature; the modern university; specifically Western forms of bureaucratic admin-istration, with technically and legally trained officials; periodically elected parliaments connected to a party system; the capitalist enterprise with its rational organization of wage labor; rationalized forms of economic calcu-lation and action; capital markets; technological employment of scientific knowledge; and a rational vocational ethic (the Protestant ethic).102 The breadth of this list indicates the comprehensiveness of Weber’s notion of rationalization. But it raises questions as to how this list is to be ordered and whether “rationalization” bears the same sense throughout.

Habermas imposes order on this list of developments by reading We-ber through Parsons’s culture/society/personality schema103—the schema

Page 38: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 27

that organizes Habermas’s own account of the structures of society as life-world. He distinguishes, accordingly, among rationalization of the cul-tural tradition, rationalization of basic social institutions, and the rational-ity of personal motivations, competences, and dispositions.

Following Weber, Habermas sees the rationalization of culture as a process of differentiation among “spheres of value”: science in the “cogni-tive” sphere, law and morality in the “evaluative” dimension, and autono-mous art in the “expressive” dimension.104 This conception of the different cultural spheres corresponds closely to Habermas’s account of the various validity claims raised in communicative action. The correspondence is par-ticularly apparent with respect to the cognitive and evaluative spheres: Sci-ence, Habermas notes, focuses on questions of propositional truth, and law and morality focus on questions of normative rightness. With respect to art, the fit is looser. Whereas the third validity claim Habermas attrib-uted to communicative action was “sincerity,” the value standard he con-nects to art is “authenticity.”105 By “authenticity,” Habermas seems to mean authenticity in the expression of an artist’s subjectivity.106 In this way there is at least an analogical connection between the validity claims of “sin-cerity” and “authenticity.” Further, and again following Weber, Haber-mas finds in each of these dimensions, at the transition to modernity, a “cultural system of action” that institutionalizes discourse with respect to the relevant claim. The “scientific enterprise,” connected in large part with universities, professionalizes scientific inquiry. The “artistic enterprise” produces, distributes, and criticizes artistic and literary works. Religious associations specialize in questions of morality. Finally, with respect to le-gal questions, Habermas locates “the legal system,” which he understands to include “specialized juridical training,” professionalized scholarly dis-cussion of legal issues,107 as well as “public justice.” In these ways, cultural rationalization realizes the rational potential in communicative action.

Habermas approaches more warily Weber’s account of the rationaliza-tion of personality and society. For Weber, what a theory of rationaliza-tion must explain is the development of the modern bureaucratic state and capitalist economy, together with the methodically rational pattern of life conduct—the Protestant ethic of labor in one’s calling—that served the rationalizing developments in state and economy. According to Habermas, this explanatory strategy focuses too narrowly on the path modernization actually took and not enough on the rational potential left unexhausted. One reason Weber took this tack concerns his postulate of social-scientific value-freedom, which prevents him from giving systematic significance to his occasional comments that “rationalization,” as it actually has played

Page 39: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 28

out, has led to pathological and irrational consequences.108 Habermas, as a critical social theorist, is not burdened by that postulate. The other reason, according to Habermas, concerns limitations in Weber’s theory of action, and accordingly, in his theory of rationality. Weber lacked a concept of communicative action and communicative rationality. Both of these fea-tures of Weber’s approach, Habermas claims, led Weber to miss some of the senses in which modern societies have been rationalized and to pass over the question whether the project of rationalization, as it actually has unfolded, has been selective or incomplete.109

Three conditions must be satisfied, according to Habermas, before the reproduction of the lifeworld can be called its rationalization. The first builds on the idea of differentiation with which Weber approached the problem of cultural rationalization. Habermas presents the initial point of this rationalization process as one in which a mythically based cultural tradition reigns supreme, not only underwriting the interpretive schemes of a society’s members but determining social roles and group member-ships, fixing a relatively concrete moral code, prescribing procedures and standards for political institutions, fixing the division of labor and limit-ing the extent of individual economic initiative, and determining from the outset who will be able to acquire which competences and skills.110 Just as the rationalization of culture involves the differentiation of three spheres of value, so the rationalization of the lifeworld as a whole involves the dif-ferentiation of the “components” culture, society, and personality. Society, or, the institutional order, differentiates itself from the cultural tradition through a “gradual uncoupling of the institutional system from world-views,” with the result that “formal procedures for positing and justifying norms,” rather than mythic tradition, establishes the legitimacy of social institutions. The differentiation of the personality component appears in the “extension of the scope of contingency for establishing interpersonal relations”—that is, the greater possibilities for individual initiative in estab-lishing social relations and acquiring competences and motivations. And to the extent the cultural tradition is disentangled from the operation of social institutions, “the renewal of traditions depends more and more on individ-uals’ readiness to criticize and their ability to innovate.” What Habermas means with this sketchy account is that the cultural tradition loses much of its prejudicial power over the course of social interaction:

These trends can establish themselves only insofar as the yes/no decisions that carry everyday communicative practice no longer go back to an ascribed nor-mative consensus, but issue from the cooperative interpretation processes of

Page 40: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 29

participants themselves. Thus they signal a release of the rationality potential inherent in communicative action.111

The other two conditions Habermas sets for the rationalization of the lifeworld—a differentiation between form and content and an increasing “reflexivity” in the lifeworld’s symbolic reproduction—can be considered together in their effects on each of the three lifeworld components. For cul-ture, the differentiation between form and content means that the “core, identity-securing traditions” lose the concreteness of mythical worldviews and develop into abstract basic values (such as autonomy, liberty, and the like) as well as formal procedures and structures for communication and argumentation. The increased “reflexivity” of cultural reproduction arises with the institutionalization of the cultural systems of action Weber men-tioned: the academy and scientific laboratory, institutions of professional legal training and scholarship, religious associations, and the community of artistic creation and criticism. These institutions and practices subject the cultural tradition to ongoing criticism and revision. Culture is not merely reproduced, in the sense of being carried forward unchanged; it is critically appropriated and discursively transformed.

In the institutional order, the trend toward a differentiation between form and content brings general moral and legal principles that are “less and less tailored to concrete forms of life.”112 Here Habermas might have in mind conceptions of the moral agent and legal person that increasingly abstract from particular characteristics, such as status, class, religious af-filiation, ancestry, and eventually race and sex, as well as the sense that particular norms need to be justified not just traditionally but in terms of more general principles. Here, too, Habermas emphasizes the development of formal procedures for creating and justifying norms, with democratic procedures figuring as particularly important. With an implicit contrast to Weber’s more sober assessment of modern democracy,113 Habermas writes:

Mead and Durkheim . . . stress the evolutionary significance of democracy: democratic forms of political will-formation are not only the result of a power shift in favor of the carrier strata of the capitalist economic system; forms of discursive will-formation are established in them. And these affect the quasi-naturalness of traditionally legitimated domination in a similar way, even as modern natural science, jurisprudence with specialized training, and autono-mous art break down the quasi-naturalness of ecclesiastical traditions.114

The democratic process is “reflexive,” in two senses. First, the creation and justification of norms is itself normatively regulated. Second, the

Page 41: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 30

democratic institutionalization of political discourse allows for a reflec-tive, or critical, attitude toward traditional norms and institutions.

In the “personality” component of the lifeworld, the separation be-tween form and content brings an increasing emphasis on “formal com-petences.” With the universalization of at least basic formal education, individuals acquire generalized competences—reading and quantitative skills, for example—that are applicable in many different settings, not just in a particular task or craft. The professionalization of formal education, together with the development of social-scientific disciplines surround-ing child rearing and education, counts as an increased “reflexivity” in the socialization process. Here, too, traditional patterns increasingly are sub-jected to critical scrutiny and revision.115

In all these ways, according to Habermas, the symbolic reproduction of the lifeworld’s “structural components” has brought a communica-tive rationalization, or, the “release of the rationality potential in com-municative action.”116 Running through this account is an emphasis on three related points. First, with the communicative rationalization of the lifeworld, social interaction comes to depend more on communicatively achieved consensus, as opposed to consensus prescribed in advance by tra-dition. Second, this rationalization has meant an increasing importance of discourse and not just naive or unreflective communicative action. Third, the rationalization of the lifeworld has brought the institutionalization of discourse, not just its episodic eruption.

1.2.4 The Material Reproduction of the Lifeworld and the Limits of the Lifeworld Perspective

Habermas’s account of society as lifeworld is not yet complete. The no-tion of communicative rationalization is part of the more general notion of the lifeworld’s “symbolic reproduction.” In introducing the notion of sym-bolic reproduction, however, I mentioned that Habermas distinguishes it from the “material reproduction” of society viewed as lifeworld. By the latter, Habermas means chiefly the organized production, distribution, and consumption of goods and services, as well as the society’s external and internal defense.117 He has argued that symbolic reproduction oper-ates through communicative action, and particularly, through the “com-municative acts” that coordinate communicative action—paradigmatically, speech acts that raise, criticize, defend, accept, or reject claims to truth, rightness, or truthfulness. Material reproduction, he says, implicates the

Page 42: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 31

“purposiveness”—the realization of plans through interventions in the world—that is the other aspect of communicative action, beyond reaching mutual understanding.118 Material reproduction, then, may involve com-municative action, particularly in the form of coordinated, cooperative social labor,119 but not necessarily or exclusively. It may involve, also, the success-oriented conduct he called “strategic action.”120

This connection between strategic action and material reproduction raises an obvious question. Habermas, we saw, has defined the lifeworld in terms of specifically communicative action. Thus to the extent that mate-rial reproduction depends on strategic action, it would seem to be inacces-sible, as a matter of definition, from the “lifeworld” perspective Habermas has been developing.

Habermas, however, does not move quite so quickly. The theoretical approach that sees society as lifeworld does not “simply filter[] out” ques-tions concerning material reproduction.121 Further, despite Habermas’s definition of the lifeworld in terms of communicative action, he allows in a number of passages—albeit usually in the form of an afterthought or an admission—that strategic action, too, can be analyzed in “lifeworld” terms.122 The concession is wise, although underplayed. Strategic action draws on the same “lifeworld” resources as does communicative action. As Habermas has acknowledged, except for the “limit case” of a crimi-nal demand, even strategic interaction presupposes the parties’ acceptance of legal norms that exclude some strategies or tactics and permit others, and often strategic competitors recognize extralegal norms as well. “Self-interested action,” Habermas says, “has always been fused with, or limited by, a normative order”123—the normative order that Habermas calls the “societal component” of the lifeworld. Equally evident is the fact that in interpreting their situations and formulating their plans, strategic actors rely on the “stock of knowledge” that Habermas describes as the cultural tradition. Certainly, also, strategic action both relies on and develops the competences and motivations Habermas analyzes under the heading of “personality.” None of this is surprising. As Schutz suggested, the “life-world perspective” refers us to the problematic of action in general—even if Habermas is right that communicative action carries the main burden in reproducing what he calls the symbolic structures of the lifeworld.

Habermas ultimately does conclude that the analysis of material repro-duction calls for a different kind of approach, based on a modified version of Talcott Parsons’s social systems theory. But the argument is not simply a matter of drawing a conclusion from a definition of the lifeworld that

Page 43: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 32

excludes strategic action. Habermas in fact presents two sets of arguments for why the “lifeworld” or action-theoretical perspective must be supple-mented with a systems-theoretical approach. The first concerns what he calls “the fictions of hermeneutic idealism.” The second (and more persua-sive) addresses more directly the organization and operation of modern complex societies.

A theoretical approach that confines itself to the lifeworld concept, Habermas says, falls prey to three “fictions.” The first is the idea that ac-tors are autonomous in a very strong sense: They control their situations of action and the consequences of their actions. In this picture, society consists in relations fashioned “with the will and consciousness of adult members” and fashioned in that way only. The second fiction is that “culture is independent of external constraints.” From the perspective of a “member[]” of a lifeworld, Habermas says, culture is so fundamental to the interpretation of situations and the formulation of plans that “it is strictly meaningless . . . to inquire whether the culture in whose light they deal . . . is dependent on anything else.” The third fiction is that commu-nicative actors “encounter one another in a horizon of unrestricted pos-sibilities of mutual understanding,” assuming necessarily “that they could, in principle, arrive at an understanding about anything and everything.” From this perspective—“the internal perspective of participants [in] a so-ciocultural lifeworld”—the process of reaching understanding is “basically transparent,” and “no force can gain a footing.” These three “fictions”—the autonomy of actors, the independence of culture, and the transpar-ency of communication—are according to Habermas built into the self-understanding of both everyday actors and social theorists who examine the world from everyday actors’ perspective. And because they are fictions, some approach must be developed to supplement the action-theoretical analysis of society as lifeworld.124

Perhaps these arguments might be telling against some versions of in-terpretive sociology but not against the approach Habermas has developed. The idea that actors are purely autonomous and fashion their own world conflicts with Habermas’s initial account of the lifeworld as the taken-for-granted, pregiven background of action that remains largely invisible to so-cial actors. It conflicts also with his admissions elsewhere that we can com-prehend unintended consequences within the “lifeworld” approach.125 The idea that culture is independent of everything else conflicts with Haber-mas’s account of the way in which the three “structural components” of the lifeworld are interrelated, both in their capacity as resources for social

Page 44: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 33

action and in their reproduction. And finally, the idea that communication is transparent and forceless conflicts with Habermas’s account of strate-gic action—particularly his account of the deception or self-deception he classifies as concealed strategic action—together with his admission that strategic action is not excluded from the lifeworld. Habermas’s account of these “fictions of hermeneutic idealism” suggests a thinker eager to move on with a systems-theoretical approach—for reasons we still have not discovered—not real difficulties in the theoretical approach we have con-sidered so far.

The other set of arguments for supplementing the lifeworld approach centers around the problem of social complexity. The communicative ra-tionalization of the lifeworld is part of a trend toward greater complexity. If agreement is not secured in advance by tradition, but depends on the interpretive and discursive achievements of participants, then the possibil-ity of agreement becomes more burdensome and risky.126 The problem of coordinating action becomes correspondingly more difficult. One way in which modern societies have managed this greater risk of dissensus, ac-cording to Habermas, is through the development of generalized “media” such as money and power.127 The systems that develop around these media, Habermas argues, coordinate action and integrate society in a way funda-mentally different from the way those functions are fulfilled through com-municative action and consensus concerning validity claims.

The usual way Habermas introduces this difference is through the distinction between action orientations and action consequences.128 Com-municative action, with its “mechanism of mutual understanding,” “har-monizes the action orientations of participants.”129 By this he means that communicative actors are oriented toward reaching agreement with each other, or (if an agreement already has been reached) they are oriented to-ward that agreement. The interaction is coordinated through this agree-ment. And at a more encompassing level, society itself is integrated through a general consensus about institutionalized norms and values. So it ap-pears, at least, from the perspective of a theory of communicative action.

According to Habermas, interactions steered by the “media” around which the economic and administrative systems develop—money and power—are coordinated through action consequences. By this he means that actors in, for example, a monetary transaction may be indifferent whether they share some mutual commitment to norms or values. Each participant is oriented toward her own success. In that sense, then, the actors’ orienta-tions are not, as in the case of communicative action, congruent or even

Page 45: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 34

necessarily complementary. What coordinates interaction in this situation, and particularly what binds together a network of market transactions, is the “functional[] intermeshing of action consequences.”130 Habermas calls this form of societal cohesion “system integration,” as opposed to the “so-cial integration” that binds a social lifeworld together through normative consensus.131 To understand the way in which system integration operates through “nonintended interconnections” of action,132 Habermas argues, we need some version of systems theory.

Surely Habermas is right that we cannot understand the operations of a complex society if we see it entirely from the perspective of actors, their intentions, and their orientations. As he suggests, markets, and perhaps other mechanisms as well, coordinate interaction and integrate a society in a way irreducible to communicative agreement and a consensus about norms and values. Two difficulties remain, however.

First, even at this point, an abstractly polarizing tendency appears in Habermas’s conception of the relation between the lifeworld, on one hand, and the “media-steered” economic and administrative systems, on the other. He describes the market as “norm free,”133 as contrasted with the normatively dense contexts of the lifeworld. In the market, to be sure, one is free of various normative restrictions that would be binding in a friend-ship or family relation. But the idea that markets (and also, we will see, the “administrative system”) are norm free is simply wrong—as Habermas implicitly acknowledges when he describes market relations, and the mar-ket as a sphere of interaction, as “first generated by”134 or “first constituted in”135 formal law. Habermas will try to incorporate this acknowledgment by arguing that the media of money and power must be “anchored in the lifeworld”—secured, that is, by positive law. But this solution understates the extent to which economic and political processes are not describable, on their own terms, as “norm free.” This difficulty, I will argue, under-mines Habermas’s model of the system/lifeworld relation that he takes to characterize modern societies.

Second, the fact that Habermas’s “lifeworld” model needs to be sup-plemented does not determine what approach should supplement it. It is hardly obvious that social systems theory, rather than more standard ap-proaches in economic theory and political science, offers the key that can unlock the workings of the economic and administrative systems.136 For purposes of presenting Habermas’s basic concepts, however, I will concede that point. Still, this concession settles very little. Habermas sometimes understands the term systems theory very broadly, to the point of classify-

Page 46: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 35

ing Marx, Adam Smith, and even Hobbes as systems theorists.137 Neither are matters settled if we focus on more contemporary versions of social systems theory. Habermas relies on the version articulated by Talcott Par-sons, the dominant figure in American sociology from at least the 1950s until his death in 1978. As I will suggest in the final section, however, an-other and more powerful variant of social systems theory recently has been developed—Niklas Luhmann’s “autopoietic” theory.138 Habermas’s devel-opment of a systems-theoretical approach is thus selective, and I will argue in Chapter Four that he could avoid some of the difficulties in which his reliance on Parsons places him. In this respect, my argument goes beyond earlier criticisms of Habermas’s system/lifeworld model that focused (as did Habermas) only on Parsonsian systems theory.139

1.3 system

1.3.1 Open Systems Theory and Parsons’s “Interchange Paradigm”

The best-known version of social systems theory—and the one from which Habermas borrows—is the “open systems” approach, first devel-oped during the 1960s under the influence of advances in cybernetics and information theory. This approach conceives of systems as adaptive and open to their changing environments. System and environment are engaged in ongoing “exchange” or “interchange,”140 through which the system receives inputs from its environment, processes them, and con-verts them into outputs that are fed back to the environment. Information about the outputs’ effects on the environment and the system flows back into the system, completing the “feedback loop.”141

This model becomes more complex when we consider that a system’s environment typically includes other organized systems. The functionalist sociological systems theories of the 1960s and early 1970s incorporated this insight, presenting modern societies as differentiated into a plurality of subsystems142—such as the political system or the economic system—each of which performs some particular social function. Accounting for the in-put and output relations among the various social subsystems has been a basic problem for functionalist systems theory.

The most highly developed and influential version of this approach ap-pears in the later work of Talcott Parsons. Parsons argues that any system of action must fulfill precisely four functions: “adaptation” (A), “goal-attainment” (G), “integration” (I), and “latent pattern-maintenance” (L).

Page 47: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 36

The functions listed in this “four-function paradigm,” or “AGIL” schema, correspond to what Parsons’s earlier work had characterized as the four basic elements of action: means or resources, goals, norms, and values, respectively.143 To each of the four functions corresponds a social subsys-tem. The economy, on Parsons’s account, serves the adaptive function (A); the “polity” serves the goal-attainment function (G); the “societal commu-nity” serves the integrative function (I); and (for lack of a better term) the “pattern maintenance subsystem” serves the function that its name sug-gests (L).144

Parsons’s “interchange paradigm” addresses the issue of how these functional subsystems are interrelated. To each subsystem he attributes a “generalized medium of interchange”145 that both structures the subsys-tem’s “internal” operations and controls its input/output relations with other subsystems. Parsons’s strategy was to begin with the idea of money as the medium for the economy. Then, working largely by analogy to the case of money, he identified media for the other three social subsystems: “power” for the polity, “influence” for the societal community, and “value-commitment” for the pattern-maintenance subsystem. Each interchange between subsystems involves, according to Parsons, a “double” exchange, with an input and an output accomplished through each of the two sys-tem’s respective media. Thus, for example, the interchange between econ-omy and polity involves four boundary-crossing inputs and outputs, two mediated by money and two by power. The same pattern obtains with respect to the other five intersystem relations, generating a total of twenty-four media-controlled interchanges.146

This interchange model of functional subsystems and media-controlled exchange is not, to most, an intuitive way of looking at the social world. In particular, it is not a map of society, as if seen from the air, on which we could locate particular organizations or institutions by placing them se-curely in one subsystem or another. Particular organizations, like business firms, may be specialized with respect to one of the four functions. But none belongs exclusively to any one subsystem. As the Parsons-influenced theorist Jeffrey Alexander puts it, “There are economic aspects of churches and political aspects of factories.”147 The same point holds at the level of the subsystems themselves. The political system, on Parsons’s scheme, is specialized with respect to the function of realizing collective goals.148 But in fulfilling this function, it draws on “inputs” from the other social sub-systems. What the interchange paradigm is designed to convey is the “di-mensional pressures” that societies face and the functions they must fulfill.

Page 48: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 37

Understood in that way, Alexander concludes, the model “encompasses the full multidimensional complexity of real social causality” because “the analysis of any single subsystem . . . cannot be isolated from the analysis of any other.”149

Parsons’s further development of the interchange model was still more ambitious in scope. The account considered so far covers only the inter-change among subsystems of the social system. The social system, how-ever, is itself a subsystem of a more encompassing system that Parsons calls the “general action system.” An obvious question is whether the same principles developed at the level of the social system apply at the level of the general action system. Parsons concludes that they do. According to Par-sons, the four-function paradigm, connected as it is to the elements of ac-tion in general, applies to any system of action. In fact, Parsons generalizes the four-function paradigm still more ambitiously. Properly understood, he argues, a system of action is just a special case of a living system.150 And according to Parsons, the four-function “AGIL” paradigm is grounded in “the essential nature of living systems at all levels of organization and evolutionary development, from the unicellular organism to the highest human civilization.”151 On that basis, Parsons came to consider the four-function paradigm, as well as the interchange paradigm that accompanies it, wholly general in its application.

Parsons and his followers set about applying the four-function para-digm at various levels of generality. The subsystems of the “general ac-tion system” include, besides the social system (I), the cultural system (L), the personality system (G), and the (oddly named) “behavioral organism” (A).152 At this level, too, Parsons gave names to the various media, charted the various double interchanges, and blocked out the other categories that the four-function paradigm requires.153 In his last years Parsons ascended another level of generality to address the so-called human condition, where the general action system (I) takes its place alongside the “physico-chemical system” (A), the “human organic system” (G), and (the crypti-cally named) “telic system” (L).154 Here too, Parsons named the media, charted the “double interchanges,” and so forth.155 But if the four-function paradigm is wholly general in its application, then it must operate in the other direction as well—at the level of subsystems for the social system’s subsystems, and then at the level of the subsystems of those subsystems, and so on. The AGIL schema is endlessly self-replicating, and the proj-ect of naming functional subsystems, generalized interchange media, and media-controlled interchange relations could go on forever.156 At some

Page 49: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 38

point, however, it becomes a senseless exercise—as even some of those strongly influenced by Parsons have concluded.157 And one has to wonder about the formalism of a theory in which the same four-part differentia-tion appears, and the same principles apply, whatever the level of analysis.

Habermas’s response to Parsons’s systems theory is generally critical. He has no particular use for the AGIL schema, nor does he follow Parsons in his ascent from the social system to the general system of action—let alone the level of the “human condition.”158 The problem with Parsons’s “general system of action,” according to Habermas, is that it presents cul-ture, society, and personality—Habermas’s “structural components of the lifeworld”—as media-steered, boundary-maintaining systems, analo-gous in structure to state and economy. Parsons totalizes systems theory. Habermas argues that its explanatory potential is limited. The question for him is how to determine the relative rights of the systems-theoretical and “lifeworld” perspectives.

Habermas pursues this question by examining Parsons’s theory of “generalized interchange media.” He focuses on Parsons’s discussion of the four media at the level of the social system—money, power, influence, and value-commitment. Habermas follows Parsons in taking money to be the exemplary case of a medium and in then considering whether the other proposed media are sufficiently similar in their structure and op-eration. For reasons we will soon explore, Habermas ultimately concludes that only money and power are genuine interchange media—or, to use his preferred (if peculiar) term, genuine “steering media” (Steurungsmedien).159 For this reason, he will conclude that only the economic and administra-tive systems are “media-steered” systems.

This will leave him with the question of how to understand the rela-tion between the open, adaptive, media-steered, functionally differenti-ated economic and administrative systems, on one hand, and the lifeworld, on the other. That will be the most serious difficulty in Habermas’s “two-level” theory of society.

1.3.2 “Steering Media”

Parsons first developed the idea of money as the economy’s interchange medium in his collaborative work with Neil Smelser, Economy and Society (1956). In a series of essays published between 1963 and 1968, he extended the notion to the other three subsystems of the social system.160 Through-out these essays, money remained the paradigmatic interchange medium,

Page 50: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 39

with language emerging as a point of further comparison. Habermas’s ac-count of Parsons’s medium concept distills from these essays four aspects of the money medium that Parsons emphasizes: its “structural features,” its “structure of claim and redemption,” its “qualitative properties,” and its “system-forming effects.” Habermas takes these aspects of money to be defining criteria for his notion of a “steering medium”—his version of Par-sons’s “generalized interchange medium.” For our immediate purposes, the first two features are most relevant.

By the “structural features” of a medium, Habermas is referring, in the first instance, to what Parsons calls the medium’s “code.” Parsons conceives of media codes by analogy to ordinary language: They allow the transmis-sion of semantic content, governed by syntactical rules for the medium’s use. In fact, Parsons says, money as a medium “is a very specialized language.”161 A medium’s code symbolizes a “generalized value” that can be presumed meaningful for all who will deal with the medium in “standard situations.” For money, the standard situation is the buying and selling of economic goods, with actors pursuing their own interests.162 The generalized value, of which money is both expression and measure, is “utility.”163 Parsons con-ceives of money’s circulation as the sending of “messages,” meaningful in terms of the medium’s code, that are designed to motivate the recipient to accept an “offer.” The motivating force is the prospect of sanctions, whether positive or negative, that will affect the recipient’s relevant interest. Money, Parsons says, operates through “inducement,”164—the prospect of positive sanctions connected to the generalized value of utility.165

Like ordinary language as a medium, Parsons observes, money as a medium has no intrinsic value. Instead, it presents a “nominal value” (exchange-value) that can be “redeemed” for a “real value” or “intrinsic sat-isfier” (typically, the use-value of a good or service). Ultimately the mon-etary medium is “backed by reserves”—whether by gold or other precious metals, as in bygone days, or by other means, as at present.166 Similarly, Habermas notes, linguistic utterances may “express knowledge,” but they are not themselves “knowledge.” They are the medium through which participants reach communicative agreement, and the claims raised in ut-terances are the “measure” of achieved agreements. Likewise, Habermas contends, communicative agreements are “backed by potential reasons” that can be adduced, if necessary, to “redeem” claims raised in communi-cative action.167

Habermas emphasizes, however, the differences between ordinary lan-guage and money as media. Two are particularly important for his further

Page 51: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 40

argument. First, the redemption of a claim in communicative action involves the giving of reasons that can withstand rational criticism. The redemption of a monetary claim or offer does not. The acceptance of a claim in com-municative action, therefore, may be “rationally motivated”—in the sense of “communicatively rationally motivated”—whereas the acceptance of a claim or offer in a money-mediated interaction is motivated, in Habermas’s ter-minology, only “empirically,” by the desire for a positive sanction. Money thus allows actors to circumvent the process of reaching agreement about contested claims to validity. Their interaction is coordinated not by com-municative consensus but by the consequences of their respective success-oriented calculations and their mutual strategic influence. Habermas relies on the distinction between rational and empirical motivation, and the no-tion of media as “replacing” the process of reaching understanding, as his main criteria for “steering medium” status. The idea that steering media re-place communicative consensus formation will be part of his argument that system and lifeworld in modern societies are “uncoupled.”

Second, as Parsons notes, money and the process of exchange must be “institutionalized” if they are to enjoy a secure basis of trust. The “backing” of the monetary medium itself occurs through the guarantees of national and international governmental and financial institutions. Contract law and property law institutionalize and regulate the process of exchange.168 No such institutional or legal guarantees are necessary for the medium of ordinary language. Habermas sees this difference as indicating that while ordinary-language communication is always already located in a lifeworld context, the medium of money must be institutionally “anchored in the lifeworld”—specifically in the institutional and legal complex Habermas calls the “society” component of the lifeworld.169 This point also will be significant to Habermas’s understanding of the relation between system and lifeworld.

The other “features” Habermas discerns in Parsons’s account of money concern its “qualitative properties” and its “system-building effects.” Mon-ey’s relevant qualitative properties are that it is precisely measurable, alien-able in specific amounts, and capable of being stored. The first two proper-ties allow money to operate as an objective, context-independent measure of value in rationally calculated action. Money’s alienability allows it to serve as a circulating medium.170 Its capacity for being stored increases ac-tors’ freedom to pursue their economic interests rationally by shopping around, waiting for favorable terms, and saving or investing.171 Under the heading of “system-building effects,” Habermas has in mind Parsons’s re-

Page 52: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 41

marks about media inflation and deflation—changes in the relation be-tween nominal and real value—and money’s “self-referential extension,” in the form of markets for money (that is, capital markets).172

The question Habermas now poses is whether, based on the model of money as medium, any of Parsons’s other candidates—power, influence, or value commitment—qualify as genuine “steering media.” According to Habermas, power qualifies, but the others do not.

With the concept of power, as with the concept of money, Habermas follows Parsons’s lead in the first instance. Parsons sees parallels between power and money in terms of their “structural features.” Like the money code, the power code represents a “generalized value,” which Parsons calls “effectiveness” in attaining collective goals. It operates in a “standard situ-ation” of “following imperatives.” As with the parties to a monetary trans-action, the issuer of the imperative and the person to whom it is directed are understood to take an “objectivating” or “success-oriented” attitude toward one another.173 The “message” or “offer” associated with power is, as was the case with money, connected to a characteristic sanction that is to motivate the hearer in the interaction. The difference here is that while the sanction associated with money’s “inducement” was positive, the sanc-tion associated with power’s “deterrence” is negative—the threat of un-pleasant consequences in case of disobedience.174

Habermas sees parallels also in the “structure of claim and redemp-tion” associated with the two media. Like money, Parsons says, power has no intrinsic value.175 The real value for which the power code stands is the attainment of collective goals. The ultimate “backing” for power is dis-posal over the means of force. In these respects, Habermas claims, Parsons is right to see power and money as analogous.176

In other respects, Habermas acknowledges dissimilarities between power and money. Power is less calculable than money. There simply is no power-related equivalent for the price system, and in fact, Habermas allows, “It is impossible to quantify power.” Although power can circu-late, it “cannot circulate in so unrestricted a manner as money.” Habermas thinks this is so because power, which in a modern political system is sup-posed to attach to offices rather than persons, nevertheless tends to “get bound up symbiotically with the person of the powerful”—thus, for exam-ple, the advantage of incumbency. Actually, and more to the point, even if power attaches only to offices rather than persons, it is in that respect also considerably less alienable than money. Political power may not be sold or disposed of or given away, in the same way that one may sell a piece

Page 53: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 42

of property. Nor, Habermas points out, is there a reliable way to deposit power—even if we can interpret an election as, in some sense, a deposit of power from which the incoming administration may draw. Power cannot be stored, without use, to the same extent and with the same security as money. Nor can one speak of power inflation or deflation to the same de-gree, or with the same precision, as with respect to the money medium.177

Habermas emphasizes, finally, a relevant difference between the ways in which money and power are, as he puts it, “anchored in the lifeworld.” Like money, power must be legally institutionalized, although through public law rather than private law. Public law organizes a hierarchy of of-fices that prescribes the terms of access to political power and channels the flow of political decisions. The difference, according to Habermas, is that for power, something more than this legal institutionalization and the “backing” of physical force is required. Power must be “legitimated,” and that means that its exercise remains connected to “the recognition of nor-mative validity claims.” This “anchoring” of the power medium is “more demanding” than the anchoring of money, which needs no legitimation beyond its legal institutionalization.178

The reason for this asymmetry in “normative anchoring,” according to Habermas, concerns a difference in the “standard situations” of the two media. In the case of money, parties in the “ideal-typical exchange rela-tion” meet each other on equal terms. Neither has the power of command over the other, and neither can insist upon the other’s participation. In the case of power, by contrast, the standard situation is one in which one party both commands and has disposal over the means necessary to enforce com-pliance. Parsons sees that, for power to serve as a stable medium, it must be directed toward collective goals. And yet, Habermas observes, if the power holder is able to define “which goals are going to count as collective,” that determination must be contestable by those subject to power. Seemingly on the verge of declaring that the medium of power implies democracy, Habermas pulls back, allowing for the possibility that a tradition-based consensus rather than democratic procedures might provide the requisite legitimation.179 Still, Habermas sees the significance of his insistence that power must be legitimated. He invokes the distinction between “simple imperatives” and “normatively authorized requests” that he made in dif-ferentiating communicative from strategic action. And, aware that he has classified “normatively authorized requests” as cases of communicative ac-tion, Habermas nevertheless suggests that “power as a medium evidently retains something of ” the normatively authorized request. Here Habermas

Page 54: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 43

comes very close to describing “power-mediated” interaction as communi-cative action.

But Habermas stops short of this description. And despite the fact that so many of his comparisons between money and power produce more differences than similarities, he pronounces power a “steering medium” alongside money. This judgment is somewhat surprising. What it indicates is that the various factors Habermas mentions as criteria for media status are not equal in importance.

Habermas seems to rely most heavily on two general similarities be-tween money and power. The first is that power, like money, needs to be legally institutionalized for the medium to enjoy a secure basis of trust. That factor was the reason he resisted describing language as a “medium” in the sense that money is a medium, and as noted below, it is one of the main reasons he rejects Parsons’s two other proposed media, influence and value commitment.

The second parallel between money and power on which Habermas relies concerns the “standard situations” for each medium’s operation. In both cases, Habermas describes the standard situation as involving more or less calculating, success-oriented interaction that allows actors to cir-cumvent the process of reaching consensus over contested validity claims. In the standard situation of power’s exercise, the directly relevant reasons for compliance are the potential sanctions over which the power holder has disposal. The fact that power ultimately refers back to a legitimating consensus does not mean that the motivation for compliance, in particu-lar instances of power’s exercise, is “rational” rather than “empirical.” The system as a whole must be legitimate for power to be a stable medium. The actual exercise of power, however, often operates without detailed norma-tive justification being given or requested.

Habermas’s classification of power as “steering medium” seems to me doubtful. But rather than belabor the similarities and differences between money and power, it makes sense to see what he can make of his deci-sion to classify power as medium and to see what effects his reservations about this decision have on his account of the system that develops around the power medium. These matters will become apparent when I turn to Habermas’s model of the relation between system and lifeworld.

Parsons’s remaining two media for the subsystems of the social system—influence and value commitment—can be handled more briefly. Habermas concedes that we can find names for these proposed media’s “standard situations,” “generalized values,” “nominal claims,” “real values,” “reserve

Page 55: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 44

backing,” and the like, that formally will parallel the account Parsons gives of money and power. But the dissimilarities to money, and also to power, weigh against conceiving influence and value commitment as “steering media.” Both influence and value commitment are less susceptible than ei-ther money or power to calculation, alienation, and storing. Both “remain strongly tied to persons and particular contexts,” and thus neither seems well described as a circulating medium. Further, the “reserve backing” Par-sons designates for these proposed media—cultural tradition and values—are, in Habermas’s view, better understood from a “lifeworld” perspective than from a systems-theoretical angle. Habermas, in fact, has classified the cultural tradition as a component of the lifeworld, and he has described values as relevant to both the culture and personality components of the lifeworld. The same is true of the “real values” Parsons nominates for influ-ence and value commitment: “reasons for convictions” and “justifications for obligations.”180

Habermas, in short, argues that both influence and value commitment are better analyzed through a theory of communicative action rather than through systems theory. Unlike money and power, influence and value commitment do not replace the coordinating mechanism of communica-tive consensus. Both influence and value commitment, on Parsons’s ac-count, implicate reasons and justifications, not just sanctions, and thus for each we can speak of (communicatively) rational rather than empirical motivation. Finally, Habermas notes, the forms of institutionalization Par-sons proposes—“prestige orderings” and “moral leadership”—are not le-gally secured, and in fact they are not really institutions at all.181 For these reasons, Habermas maintains, we have no reason to posit either influence or value commitment as “steering media.”

Still, Habermas allows, both influence and value commitment represent “special cases of consensus formation in language.” In the standard situa-tion of each—“giving advice” and “moral appeals,” respectively—one party has special competence or authority. The other party trusts that the specially competent or authoritative party could provide reasons sufficient to justify the relevant claim, without demanding the reasons or subjecting them to criticism. In this way, “influence and value commitment are . . . forms of generalized communication that bring about a reduction in the expenditure of energy and in the risks attending mutual understanding.” They do not replace mutual understanding in its coordinating role “but only provide it with relief through abstraction from lifeworld complexity.”182

Page 56: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 45

Such is Habermas’s account of “steering media.” Money and power, and these only, are media around which “systems,” in Habermas’s sense, can be differentiated. It should be clear, however, that we still do not know what “systems” are “in Habermas’s sense.” We need to know more about the “internal” structure of the systems he identifies, as well as much more about how Habermas hopes to link his “lifeworld” account of society and his systems-theoretical account. He addresses both issues in his account of the “uncoupling of system and lifeworld,” to which I now turn.

1.3.3 Uncoupling of System and Lifeworld

Each of the two methodological approaches I have considered so far describes the development of modern societies as a process of differentia-tion. From the perspective of the theory of communicative action, Haber-mas sees the differentiation of the lifeworld’s “structural components” as an essential aspect of the lifeworld’s rationalization. From the perspective of systems theory, Habermas describes the operation of two “steering me-dia” around which the economic and administrative systems differenti-ate. But from what do these systems “differentiate,” other than from each other? Habermas describes the “anchoring” of the steering media “in the lifeworld,” and so presumably system and lifeworld are differentiated. But beyond this vague notion of “anchoring,” what relation might obtain be-tween society seen as lifeworld and society seen from the point of view of systems theory?

So far I have presented the two methodological approaches almost en-tirely separately. Each, in Habermas’s view, accounts for some aspects of a modern society, but if we try to think of either as a model of society as a whole, we see that in each account Habermas leaves a blank spot that needs to be filled in by the other approach. The “lifeworld” perspective, Habermas says, is inadequate to account for society’s “material reproduc-tion,” which he sees as carried out through the economic and administra-tive systems. To understand the structure and operation of these systems, Habermas claims, we need a systems-theoretical approach.183 But that systems-theoretical approach, Habermas maintains, cannot adequately grasp the “symbolic structures of the lifeworld.” To understand those symbolic structures, we need the notion of communicative action and its complementary concept of the lifeworld. Habermas has set up his accounts of the two approaches so that they appear to be mutually complementing.

Page 57: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 46

With the notion of the “uncoupling of system and lifeworld,” he tries to bring them together into a single model of society.

Habermas describes the “uncoupling of system and lifeworld” as a “second-order process of differentiation.”184 By this he means that his ac-count of this uncoupling treats the differentiation of the economic and administrative systems, and the differentiation of the lifeworld’s structural components, as at the same time a further process of differentiation—the differentiation of system from lifeworld.185 This notion of differentiation of system from lifeworld may seem an obvious consequence of characterizing state and economy as “systems” that, qua systems, are differentiated from their environments. And, as I suggested, it seems to bring together two different but complementing theoretical paradigms. But what Habermas accomplishes through his notion of “uncoupling” is not so much the in-tegration of the two paradigms as the marking of a boundary between system and lifeworld that gives each approach its own turf. To the systems-theoretical approach, Habermas assigns the domains he calls “systems”—the economy, and also the state administration. To the approach that is based in a theory of communicative action, he grants the domain that he calls “the lifeworld.” And finally, it will become clear, Habermas analyzes the relations between these domains within a systems-theoretical frame of reference.

Habermas locates the uncoupling of system and lifeworld within an ambitious theory of social evolution. His sketch of this theory traces the development of exchange and power relations from simple “tribal” societies to modern societies.186 At the initial point of this evolutionary process—“small, prestate societies” in which kinship is “something like a total institution”—Habermas discerns an “interweaving of system inte-gration and social integration.” As we travel along the social-evolutionary path, however, the two forms of integration pull apart. Described systems-theoretically, each stage is marked by a new “mechanism of system differen-tiation” that increases the society’s complexity.187 Described in “lifeworld” terms, the transition to each stage depends on the institutionalization of these mechanisms of systems differentiation.188 Particularly important in this evolutionary process is the development of law and morality, which Habermas analyzes as a transition from “preconventional” to “conven-tional” to “postconventional levels.”189

The details of this evolutionary theory are not important for my pur-poses. What matters is the account Habermas gives of modern society, in which, he claims, system and lifeworld are largely “uncoupled.” Two

Page 58: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 47

features of this account are particularly important. The first concerns the relations between systems and the relations between system and lifeworld. The second concerns the “internal” structure of system and lifeworld.

Habermas has described the economic and administrative systems as differentiated out around the steering media of money and power. Fol-lowing Parsons’s account of a generalized interchange medium, Habermas takes steering media to operate in two ways: They both coordinate interac-tion within the relevant system and regulate the system’s “external” inter-change with its environments. Money and power were hardly unknown in precapitalist societies, Habermas allows, but neither operated as a genu-ine “steering medium.”190 What is decisive for the formation of “media-steered” subsystems, Habermas maintains, is that the medium comes to control the relations between system and environment.191 In the case of money, Habermas argues, this occurred with the widespread institutional-ization of wage labor and the development of markets for consumer goods. With these developments, the relations between the economic system and its environment of the “private household” came to be mediated by money. I point to Habermas’s account of this relation because, for him, it is a rela-tion between system and lifeworld: The “private household”—that is, the family, viewed from the perspective of the economic system—belongs to the societal component of the lifeworld.192

This point has more general significance. Habermas’s account of the “uncoupling of system and lifeworld” presents system and lifeworld as so-cial spheres that are in actual interrelation with one another, not just as one-sided or partial constructions of society seen from two different theo-retical perspectives. And the interrelation is regulated by steering media—at least from the side of the economic and administrative subsystems.193 The framework in which Habermas locates this interchange between sys-tem and lifeworld is thus systems-theoretical. And within this framework the lifeworld becomes “one subsystem among others”—albeit the one in which “systemic mechanisms have to be anchored.”194

The second aspect of Habermas’s account of the uncoupling of system and lifeworld concerns the “internal” structure of both domains. Habermas has described money and power as media that address a basic problem created by the rationalization of society as lifeworld: the greater danger of dissensus, to the extent consensus is no longer prescribed in advance by tradition, and the resulting burden on interpretive energies required to reach agreement communicatively. Money and power, he has said, address this problem by circumventing the process of reaching communicative understanding.195

Page 59: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 48

With his account of system and lifeworld as uncoupled, however, Habermas goes further. To his notion of steering media as regulators of systems’ internal operations, he adds the notion of “formal organizations.” By “formal organizations” Habermas means, essentially, bureaucratic or-ganizations, whether governmental agencies or business firms, with hier-archical structures of command, defined roles and tasks, and defined be-havioral expectations whose fulfillment is a condition for membership.196 Formal organizations are first constituted in positive law.197 Habermas speaks also of “formally organized domains of action [Handlungsbereiche],” by which he sometimes means “formal organizations” and sometimes means entire systems of action—the economic and administrative sys-tems.198 The two terms go together: He tends to conceive of the economic and administrative systems as networks of formal organizations.

Habermas presents formally organized domains of action as coordi-nated and integrated by money and power only. In these domains, Haber-mas claims, system and lifeworld are “uncoupled” not just in the sense that new mechanisms for coordinating action develop that are irreducible to the mechanism of communicative understanding. Rather, system and lifeworld are uncoupled in the further sense that the lifeworld’s resources become essentially irrelevant for the operation of the economic and ad-ministrative systems. These formally organized, media-steered subsys-tems, Habermas writes, are

consolidated and objectified into norm-free structures. Members behave to-ward formally organized action systems, steered via processes of exchange and power, as toward a block of quasi-natural reality; within these media-steered subsystems society congeals into a second nature. Actors have always been able to shear off from an orientation to mutual understanding, adopt a strategic attitude, and objectify normative contexts into something in the objective world, but in modern societies, economic and bureaucratic spheres emerge in which social relations are regulated only via money and power. Norm- conformative attitudes and identity-forming social memberships are neither necessary nor possible in these spheres; they are made peripheral instead.199

Habermas goes on to argue even more explicitly that “formal organiza-tions” in both subsystems have become indifferent to each of the struc-tures of the lifeworld—personality, culture, and society. Through their ability to prescribe membership conditions, formal organizations manage the personal dispositions, capacities, and motivations of their members. Further, Habermas maintains, with more than a little hyperbole: “Just as persons are, as members, stripped of personality structures and neutral-

Page 60: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 49

ized into bearers of certain performances, so too cultural traditions . . . are robbed of their binding power and converted into raw material for purposes of ideology planning, that is, for an administrative processing of meaning constellations.” Finally, with respect to the society component, organizations “make themselves independent from lifeworld contexts” by “neutralizing the normative background of informal, customary, morally regulated contexts of action.”200

System and lifeworld are thus uncoupled in a radical sense. The de-velopment of money and power as media, together with the rise of for-mal organizations, fundamentally transforms the nature of interaction in what become the differentiated economic and administrative systems. Habermas refers in this connection to “an uncoupling of interaction from lifeworld contexts.” In these formally organized, media-steered systems, “the lifeworld contexts in which processes of reaching understanding are always embedded are devalued in favor of media-steered interactions; the lifeworld is no longer needed for the coordination of action.”201 Taken lit-erally, this would mean that all of the lifeworld resources Habermas has identified—norms, values, institutions, interpretive schemes, personal competences and motivations—are irrelevant for the coordination of inter-action in the economic and administrative spheres.

This claim is plainly false. I have argued above that strategic action, not just communicative action, draws on what Habermas calls the life-world’s resources. The same is true of the subtype of strategic action called “media-steered” interaction, and it is true also of interaction within formal organizations. Interaction in general, not just communicative action in particular, is informed and channeled by the interpretive schemes Haber-mas associates with culture, the legal (at least) institutions and norms he associates with society, and the personal competences and motivations he associates with personality. To be sure, monetary transactions, for exam-ple, are less moralized than interaction with one’s friends or family. And further, the norms and behavioral expectations imposed by formal orga-nizations may be organization specific, not general social norms. Finally, formal organizations may not permit discursive challenges to their rules or expectations. But only if we equate “norms” with “informal norms” and “moral norms”—excluding legal norms and organizationally imposed norms—do either of Habermas’s two systems, or formal organizations, ap-pear to be norm free.

In one sense, the problem is the same one I have been noting in analyz-ing each of Habermas’s basic concepts. His initial account of communicative

Page 61: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 50

action, before the amendments I discussed, tended toward an indefensibly sharp opposition between communicative and strategic action. His account of “lifeworld” interaction focuses almost exclusively on communicative ac-tion, with strategic action appearing only as an afterthought. And in the course of arguing that a systems-theoretical perspective must supplement his lifeworld perspective, he presented a polarizing account of the lifeworld as normatively dense and systems as “norm free.” At these points, Haber-mas stylizes his distinctions between communicative and strategic, validity and power, lifeworld and system.202

The problem becomes more acute, however, with Habermas’s account of the uncoupling of system and lifeworld. There the notion of lifeworld as the resources on which actors rely shifts to a conception of the lifeworld as itself a domain of action—as the informally organized and communica-tively structured contexts of action203 that stand opposed to the formally organized and media-steered spheres of action Habermas calls “systems.” This shift in the concept of the lifeworld is essential to Habermas’s “un-coupling” thesis, and it is the source of a good bit of his difficulties. It is a baffling shift as well. While perhaps the institutional complex at the core of the lifeworld’s “societal” component can be seen as a domain of action, the cultural tradition and the social stock of motivations and competences cannot. Habermas simply does not explain how the lifeworld, with these “structural components,” constitutes a system or network of action that can be placed in a systems-theoretical interchange model opposite the eco-nomic and administrative systems. In his model of the system/lifeworld relation, Habermas implicitly acknowledges this point by presenting the interchange between system and lifeworld as channeled through the insti-tutional component only.204 As a result, however, he has no way to explain how interaction in the economic and administrative systems might draw on the interpretive schemes of culture and the motivations and compe-tences of personality. The ultimate consequence of Habermas’s shifting conception of the lifeworld is an untenably stylized account: The lifeworld is the informal, customary, normatively rich home of communicative ac-tion, and systems are the strategic, calculating, formalized, normatively empty worlds of money and power.205

In various passages of Theory of Communicative Action unrelated to the uncoupling thesis, Habermas recognizes the points I am making. For ex-ample, as I have noted, he acknowledges that the media of money and power must be institutionalized, and that means, in Habermas’s terminol-ogy, a “recoupling” of system and lifeworld. The domains of economic and

Page 62: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 51

administrative action are legally constituted, and the processes of exchange and command are legally regulated through the basic “legal institutions” of private and public law. Formal organizations impose normative require-ments and behavioral expectations on their members—not, perhaps, infor-mal or moral requirements, but normative requirements notwithstanding. These points, of which Habermas is well aware, are obscured by the shift in his notion of the lifeworld and his hyperbolic notion of “uncoupling.”

Further, Habermas acknowledges the stylization of his conception of formal organizations as steered only by money and power. Underneath the formal organization, he argues, is an informal organization, and organi-zations could not attain their goals if communicative action were entirely set out of play.206 This recognition is consistent with his statement that the “material reproduction of the lifeworld” is accomplished through com-municative as well as strategic action. The original reason for adopting a systems-theoretical perspective was not that interaction in the systems responsible for material reproduction is entirely strategic (or, by extension, media steered). Instead, the reason had to do with the counterintuitive consequences of economic and administrative processes that are irreduc-ible to the actor’s intentions or plans and inaccessible to a theory that con-fines itself to an interpretive perspective. Here, too, Habermas’s decision to see system differentiation as an uncoupling from the lifeworld—and the polarizing sense he gives this notion of “uncoupling”—has obscured in-sights available elsewhere in his work.

Unfortunately, the model he develops to analyze the system/lifeworld relation reproduces the errors of his “uncoupling” analysis. That model is the topic of the next section.

1.4 the system/lifewor ld model in theory of com mu nicati v e action

Habermas’s working model of the relation between system and lifeworld is systems-theoretical: It presents media-steered interchange processes between the economic and administrative systems, on one side, and the lifeworld on the other. As I mentioned, Habermas conceives of this inter-change as channeled, on the side of the lifeworld, through the institutional component. He distinguishes two “institutional orders” of the lifeworld that participate in this interchange. The “private sphere” is in interchange with the economic system, and the “public sphere” is in interchange with

Page 63: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 52

the administrative system. He presents these private and public spheres from a double perspective—first from the perspective of the lifeworld and then from the perspective of the relevant system. (In Table 1.1 I present most of the information contained in the next few paragraphs.)207

According to Habermas, the “institutional core” of the private sphere is the “nuclear family.” Oddly, given its location in the societal component rather than personality, Habermas describes the primary function of the fam-ily as socialization. From the perspective of the economic system, the family, as private-sphere environment, appears as the “private household.” Habermas focuses on two “roles” that have “crystallized” around the interchange rela-tion between private sphere and economic system: the roles of employee and consumer. The employee role, he says, is “organization dependent” and arises in legal form. The consumer role is not legally constituted, and although it may be “defined with reference to formally organized domains of action,” it is not “dependent upon them.” These are the channels through which the interchange between economy and private sphere operates.

table 1.1Habermas’s model of system/lifeworld interchange

Lifeworld “institutional Lifeworld Factor/ order” role product Medium System

labor power — P’ —➤

1) employee income from

Private sphere employment — M —

Economic goods and — M — 2) consumer services

demand — M’ —➤

taxes — M’ —➤

1a) client organizational

Public sphere accomplishments — P —

Administrative

2a) citizen political decisions — P —

mass loyalty — P’ —➤M = money medium; P = power medium. The apostrophes following the P or M that designate contri-butions from the lifeworld are Habermas’s; they acknowledge that neither the money medium nor the power medium is proper to the lifeworld.

source: From The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol.  1, by Jurgen Habermas. Translator’s preface and translation Copyright © 1987 by Beacon Press. Originally published as Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, Band 2: Zur Kritik der funktionalistischen Vernunft, Copyright © 1981 by Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main. Reprinted by permission of Beacon Press, Boston.

Page 64: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 53

Habermas follows this same pattern in describing the interchange be-tween public sphere and administrative system. The “institutional core” of the public sphere consists in “communicative networks amplified by a cultural complex, a press, and later, mass media.” Habermas notes that the public sphere is really two public spheres—an artistic/literary sphere and a political public sphere. Only the latter enters the model. In this politi-cal public sphere, Habermas maintains, “a public of citizens” engages in political participation. Viewed from the perspective of the administrative system, however, the public sphere is “the environment relevant to gener-ating legitimation.” The relevant roles are “client” of government services and “citizen of the state.” The client role, like the employee role, is “organi-zation dependent.” The citizen role, like the consumer role, is defined with respect to, but is not “dependent upon,” the formally organized domain of the state administration.

Because Habermas has selected a systems-theoretical interchange model, he presents the relations between system and lifeworld as regulated by steering media. Parsons presented the relation between systems as in-volving a “double interchange,” mediated by both media proper to the re-lated systems. Habermas, however, has to improvise here. The only media he has identified are money and power, and so the interchange between system and lifeworld can be regulated only by these two media. This puts Habermas in a difficult position. On one hand, he cannot consistently at-tribute either the money or the power medium to the lifeworld. On the other hand, the model of interchange he borrows from Parsons requires him to do just that.

The interchange relations Habermas identifies are as follows. The pri-vate sphere, via the employee role and the power medium, contributes la-bor power to the economic system. In exchange, the economic system pro-vides income via the money medium. The private sphere, via the consumer role and the money medium, contributes demand for goods and services. In exchange, the economic system provides those goods and services by the money medium.

In the interchange between public sphere and administrative system, the public sphere, via the client role and the money medium, contributes taxes to the administrative system. In exchange, the administrative system provides “organizational accomplishments” via the power medium. The public sphere, via the citizen’s role and the power medium, contributes “mass loyalty” to the administrative system. In exchange that system pro-vides political decisions via the power medium.

Page 65: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 54

Habermas describes the process by which lifeworld processes become cognizable in terms of steering media as “real abstractions.” This term, which Habermas attributes to Marx,208 is significant in both its parts. With the word abstraction, Habermas means to highlight a certain conversion process of concrete “lifeworld” values into abstract “system” values that will be comprehensible within the system’s code. Following Marx, Habermas describes, as one of the processes of abstraction, the commodification of wage labor—the conversion of concrete, individual capacities for labor into quantities of abstract labor-power, comparable along the scale of money prices.209 A similar process of abstraction operates through the consumer role, in the conversion of “use-value orientations” into abstract demand, expressed in terms of willingness and ability to pay. So, too, with the con-version, in the citizen’s role, of “publicly articulated opinions and collective expressions of will” into “mass loyalty.”210 By the word real in the expres-sion real abstractions, Habermas means to signal that these processes are not “abstractions” in a purely intellectual sense but are real social processes.

Habermas sees his project in Theory of Communicative Action as a refor-mulation of the critique of capitalist societies, as presented first by Marx, then by Georg Lukács, and then by Habermas’s “Frankfurt School” pre-decessors (principally Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno).211 One sig-nificant distinction between Habermas’s approach and the approaches of his various predecessors is that Habermas believes these processes of “real abstraction” are not necessarily pathological. Neither the organization of media-steered subsystems as such, nor the processes of “abstraction” as such, count as social pathologies.212 But Habermas designs his model as a framework for analyzing developments that would count as crises or social pathologies.

Habermas identifies a number of different types of crisis or social pa-thology. Two to which he pays little attention in Theory of Communica-tive Action are what he calls “steering crises”—“internal” crises of the two media-steered subsystems, whether in the form of “economic” crisis or “planning crisis.”213 In contrast to orthodox Marxist approaches, Haber-mas maintains that, with welfare-state attempts to regulate the business cycle, tendencies toward economic crisis largely have been displaced into the administrative system.214 Of greater interest to Habermas are crises in symbolic reproduction. He mentions the possibility that these may be “in-ternally” induced: For example, the “cultural impoverishment of everyday communicative practice” may arise with the “elitist splitting-off of expert cultures from contexts of communicative action in daily life.”215 But he

Page 66: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 55

focuses more intensively on the crises of symbolic reproduction that are “externally” induced, through incompatibility between the forms of orga-nization and rationality proper to system and lifeworld.

Habermas refers to this last kind of crisis as “inner colonization,” or, the “colonization of the lifeworld.” This social pathology arises when crises in the economic and administrative systems “can be avoided only at the cost of disturbances in the symbolic reproduction of the lifeworld.”216 Or, in Habermas’s more colorful description of this social pathology: “The im-peratives of autonomous subsystems make their way into the lifeworld from the outside—like colonial masters coming into a tribal society—and force a process of assimilation upon it.”217 Thus, the term colonization. Habermas’s idea is that “colonization” occurs when the informally organized, commu-nicatively structured domains of action that Habermas has come to call the lifeworld—the domains of action that are primarily responsible for cultural reproduction, social integration, and socialization—are disrupted by the penetration of “alien,” systemic forms of organization and rationality.218

According to Habermas, tendencies toward colonization are channeled through the interchange relations his model has identified. The roles of employee, consumer, citizen, and client are the points of incursion. Haber-mas is particularly interested in two of those roles: consumer and client. The reason for focusing on these roles, according to Habermas, is that with the pacification of class conflict and the depoliticization of the citi-zen’s role, the consumer and client roles are the more likely sites of conflict. These roles, Habermas claims, have been “upgraded” under recent condi-tions, as a sort of “compensation” for employees’ relative lack of power in the workplace and the “neutralized citizen’s role.”219 And thus in these roles, Habermas maintains, the “privatized hopes for self-actualization and self-determination are located.”220

Of these two roles, Habermas spends most of his energy on the “cli-ent” role. He calls the colonization tendency in the relation between ad-ministrative system and client of welfare-state services “juridification”—the extension of formal law to areas previously regulated only informally and the increasing density of legal regulation.221 The term juridification does not by itself signify pathological tendencies, Habermas cautions. The development of the constitutional state (as in the nineteenth-century Ger-man Rechtsstaat) and the institution of the democratic constitutional state also count as “juridification,” and the institutions established then were, compared to their predecessor institutions, “unambiguously freedom-guaranteeing.”222

Page 67: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 56

With respect to these criteria of “freedom-guaranteeing” and “freedom- depriving,” however, Habermas discerns an ambivalence in the most recent “wave” of juridification. On one hand, welfare-state programs compensate for risks by creating legal entitlements to income in case of need or inabil-ity to work. But on the other hand, this “historical progress” has costs that Habermas emphasizes. The bureaucratic structure of the administrative system requires “a centralized and computerized handling of social exigen-cies by large, distant organizations.” The individualizing and bureaucratic form in which assistance is offered “affects the self-image of the person concerned,” Habermas maintains, and the availability of governmental aid weakens the “readiness of solidar[y] communities to provide subsidiary assistance.” And government-provided therapeutic procedures only repro-duce “the contradictions of welfare-state intervention . . . at a higher level”: The bureaucratic form of aid, Habermas claims, is inconsistent with the therapeutic aim of establishing “independence and self-reliance.”223 Haber-mas thus identifies a “dilemmatic structure” to welfare-state juridification:

While the welfare-state guarantees are intended to serve the goal of social in-tegration, they nevertheless promote the disintegration of life-relations when these are separated, through legalized social intervention, from the consensual mechanisms that coordinate action and are transferred over to media such as money and power.224

Habermas sketches the lines of this thesis through examination of (then) recent empirical research in social-welfare law, school law, and family law.225 This research, however, is by now dated, and it was directed more to a German than an American audience. And in any event, for present purposes the details of Habermas’s argument are less interesting than the position he assigns to law in this process of juridification. A legally oriented reader will have detected that my account of Habermas’s basic concepts, as they stood prior to Habermas’s most recent work, says little directly about law. We know that developments in law are, for Habermas, important to the rationalization of the lifeworld and the development of media-steered systems. Law is one of the “cultural systems of action” es-tablished, in early modernity, with the rationalization of culture. The ba-sic “legal institutions” of private and public law institutionalize the media of money and power. And the media-steered subsystems, as well as their constitutive “formal organizations,” are created and regulated by law. But law is, in Habermas’s scheme, neither its own subsystem nor a structural component of the lifeworld. The position it occupies with respect to the system/lifeworld division is thus unclear.

Page 68: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 57

In his account of “juridification,” Habermas suggests that law may operate as a steering medium. In “most areas of economic, commercial, business, and administrative law,” he says, “the law is combined with the media of power and money in such a way that it takes on the role of a steer-ing medium itself.” Like the other steering media, he says, law-as-steering-medium must be secured by the basic “legal institutions” he has identified. But because of its connection to the media of money and power, law as medium is “technicized and demoralized,” and it can be evaluated not sub-stantively but only according to its functionality or instrumental success.226 Further, as concerns the juridification thesis, Habermas argues that law, as a steering medium, has been an instrument of the welfare-state project of taming “modern relations of power and dependence that arose with the capitalist enterprise [and] the bureaucratic apparatus of domination.” His classification of law as a steering medium in this project, too, is part of his diagnosis that welfare-state interventionism has tended to disrupt the com-municatively structured, informally organized domains it regulates.

Habermas did not work out the concept of law as a medium in the way that his system/lifeworld model would demand—with a separate sys-tem it steers, and an account of its code, standard situation, generalized value, and other medium-defining characteristics. And in his most recent work, Habermas repudiates the idea of law as steering medium.227 We are still left, then, with the question of law’s position in Habermas’s system/lifeworld model. The account he has given suggests that law is relevant to both system and lifeworld and that in that respect its significance is ambiv-alent. But law finds no particular place in Habermas’s model. It appears, variously, as a “cultural system of action” alongside science and art, as part of the societal component of the lifeworld (or, at least, the fundamental principles of private and public law appear there as “legal institutions”), and as a mechanism that regulates media-steered interaction in the eco-nomic and administrative systems. In Habermas’s recent work on law, he retains the mood of ambivalence, but with a much fuller and more coher-ent treatment of law’s structure and operation.

The problems in Theory of Communicative Action’s treatment of law are paralleled in its treatment of politics. As with his account of law, Haber-mas’s account of political institutions and processes stretches across the divide between system and lifeworld. One would think, at first, that the state would count as part of the “institutional complex” that Habermas calls the societal component of the lifeworld. And Habermas does describe the constitutionally established framework of state offices as part of the

Page 69: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 58

societal component—though he does not make clear whether he means the legal framework that organizes those offices or the political framework of offices themselves. Habermas notes also that the exercise of political power must be legitimated, and by “legitimated” he means not only legally institutionalized but also normatively justified. But once Habermas has introduced the systems-theoretical conception of political power, he ana-lyzes what one might call the “political system” almost exclusively as the formally organized, media-steered “administrative system” that stands on the “system” side of the system/lifeworld divide.228

No doubt this classification of political institutions as both system and lifeworld, like Habermas’s similar treatment of law, reflects his am-bivalence about the state. It reflects, also, his determination to think about democracy in a way that takes account of modern complexity. Yet Haber-mas’s discussion of political institutions, rather than genuinely reconciling complexity and democracy, puts democracy on one side of the divide and complexity on the other. Habermas’s account of the lifeworld’s rationaliza-tion presents democracy, and the idea of the discursive production and justification of political and legal norms, as one of the West’s foremost accomplishments. But his systems-theoretical account presents an admin-istration that operates through the steering medium of power, with the “standard situation” of power’s operation described as the “following of imperatives.” And the model of the relation between public sphere and administrative system describes a process of abstraction—not necessar-ily pathological—in which democratic impulses are transformed, via the power medium, into “mass loyalty.” Habermas’s more recent work, we will see, relies on a more complex notion of power that is not reducible, in its entirety, to imperative command.229 And this more recent work, also, is more attentive to what Habermas calls the political public sphere, as well as the relations between that sphere and formal governmental institutions. These changes mark a substantial improvement over the account given in Theory of Communicative Action.

I have suggested that Habermas’s analysis of the uncoupling of system and lifeworld unnecessarily stylizes and polarizes what he wants to describe under the two aspects. The interchange model Habermas uses to bring to-gether the two stylized accounts does not correct this problem. And the problem is not just that the model is incomplete—addressing, as Habermas acknowledges, only the relation between the societal component of the lifeworld and the two media-steered subsystems.230 The problem is one of principle, not just coverage. The interchange model is systems-theoretical,

Page 70: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Theory of Communicative Action 59

not neutral between the systems and lifeworld perspectives. On that mod-el’s premises, the interchange among social spheres can be understood only as media steered. Thus, Habermas’s difficulty in accounting for the rela-tion between system and lifeworld: The model demands media for the var-ious lifeworld components, and Habermas denies that any are to be found. And thus, Habermas unconvincingly imputes money and power to the public and private spheres in their interchange with the administrative and economic systems, respectively. This ad hoc solution leads Habermas to claim, for example, that the input of labor power to the economic system operates through the power medium. Power is the more plausible choice, given the alternative between money and power, but the sale of one’s labor power is not best understood as the giving of a command. These appar-ently technical slips and inconsistencies are symptoms of a more serious problem: the failure to reconcile Habermas’s “lifeworld” approach with his Parsons-inspired notions of systems theory.

Page 71: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

chapter two

Habermas’s “Reconstruction” of Modern Law

2 .1 the t wo aspects of lega l va lidit y a nd h a ber m as’s method of r econstruction

The premise of Habermas’s analysis of modern law is the social condition he has described as the “rationalization of the lifeworld.” Through this process of rationalization, Habermas has argued, the cultural tradition has been largely secularized and has lost much of its power to prescribe in ad-vance the division of labor and social roles. Action must be coordinated less through an unproblematic background consensus and more through the achievements of participants themselves. Interest positions are more sharply differentiated, and the possibility of dissensus and conflict accord-ingly has increased. Communicative action, Habermas has said, offers one mechanism for coordinating action and integrating society. But attempts to secure communicative agreement are burdensome and risky, Habermas has maintained, and, further, modern societies are characterized by the development of spheres of strategic (or “media-steered”) interaction. Ac-cordingly, communicative agreement cannot be the only mechanism by which action is coordinated and modern societies integrated.

Modern law addresses these difficulties. On one hand, law enforces compliance by strategic actors (and those otherwise uncommitted to the law’s normative claims) through sanctions. On the other hand, if a legal order is to provide a stable basis for social integration, it must be accepted as generally legitimate. According to Habermas, modern law is character-ized by these two aspects: its steering of actors’ choices through sanctions and its claim to legitimacy. Both are essential. Law, on Habermas’s anal-

Page 72: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 61

ysis, “leave[s] the choice of action orientation up to the addressees.”1 In other words, it offers the alternative between two forms of compliance: one motivated by a concern for the sanctions that the norm’s enforcement would impose and the other motivated by a belief that the legal norm is legitimate. Law, then, is tailored to both the “objectivating” and “perfor-mative” attitudes that Habermas used to distinguish between strategic and communicative action.

The idea that a legal order’s legitimacy buttresses its long-run stabil-ity is a staple of social theory. As Habermas notes, it features particularly prominently in Max Weber’s sociology of law.2 Habermas parts company with Weber, however, as to exactly how social theory should understand the notion of legitimacy. For his part, Weber distinguished between social (or de facto) validity and “ideal” validity.3 With the notion of social valid-ity, Weber meant to address the issue whether, as a matter of sociological fact, members of a society generally believe that the society’s legal order and its norms are obligatory. With the notion of ideal validity, by contrast, Weber meant to refer to the question whether, as a matter of legal or politi-cal theory, a society’s legal order and norms are legitimate—whether, that is, a legal order’s socially accepted claim to validity genuinely may be re-deemed. Weber’s sociology of law, and with it his notion of a legal order’s legitimacy, addresses only the matter of social validity. A legal order’s ideal validity, Weber says, is a question for legal theory or jurisprudence or the philosophy of law, not for sociology.4

Habermas’s “reconstructive” approach does not so quickly exile the question of ideal validity. His perspective on legitimacy is more abstract than Weber’s focus on actors’ actual beliefs about legal norms and the legal order. Habermas’s reconstruction of “the self-understanding of . . . mod-ern legal orders”5 focuses on the presuppositions that underlie modern practices of legal justification. Because the process of rationalization has undermined the social order’s religious and metaphysical support, Haber-mas argues, the only plausible form of justification is through discourse.6 An important part of Habermas’s reconstructive analysis of law, therefore, is to analyze the various kinds of discourse involved in making and apply-ing legitimate law. At the same time, Habermas argues, the emphasis on discourse does not mean that he is concerned only with law’s “ideal valid-ity.” Instead, Habermas intends his discourse theory of law to reconstruct the presuppositions characteristic of modern societies, not to survey law from a perspective generated solely through an extrinsic ideal theory. As with his notion of “rationalization,” Habermas’s reconstructive analysis of

Page 73: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 62

a modern legal order is designed to capture its unexhausted rational poten-tial but from a perspective more or less immanent to the legal order, not a utopian perspective.

The tensions Habermas identifies at the outset of his theory of law—tensions between ideal and empirical validity, and between legitimacy and enforcement—exemplify a more general theoretical logic underlying Be-tween Facts and Norms. The German title of that book is Faktizität und Geltung which, translated literally, means “facticity and validity.” This dis-tinction between “facticity”7 and “validity” organizes the argument of Be-tween Facts and Norms at every level. With “facticity,” Habermas associates ideas such as law’s positivity, certainty or predictability, institutional con-nections, and coercive enforcement.8 With “validity” he associates law’s (ideal) legitimacy and “rational acceptability”9—that is, its claim to be nor-matively worthy of obedience. As suggested above, Habermas considers both moments essential. So, too, is the tension between them.

It may be worth a moment to make the architectonic of Habermas’s project more clear. Between Facts and Norms divides into two main parts, each paired with one side of the most comprehensive facticity/validity dis-tinction Habermas identifies. The first part, on the “validity” side, is the reconstructive and normative theory: the “discourse theory of law” proper, established through a reconstructive account of modern legal orders’ “self-understanding.”10 The second part, on the “facticity” side, is the “commu-nication theory of society,” in which Habermas examines, from the point of view of social theory, whether the reconstructive discourse theory is plausible under factually obtaining conditions of modern social complexity.

In this first division—between discourse theory proper and the com-munication theory of society—the tension between facticity and validity is, Habermas says, “external.” By this he means that he is concerned, in that aspect of his project, with the tension between officially legitimate democratic and legal procedures, on one hand, and, on the other hand, the systems of “social power” that may displace or otherwise influence those procedures “externally.”11

But the tension between facticity and validity, Habermas argues, in-habits also the very notion of legal validity itself.12 And so even in Haber-mas’s discourse theory proper—which occupies the “validity” side in the “external” tension between facticity and validity—the tension between facticity and validity reappears, this time as an “internal” tension, or as a tension immanent in the “validity dimension” of modern law itself.13 The basic figure of Habermas’s work on law is the nesting of tensions between

Page 74: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 63

facticity and validity. That is the architectonic of Habermas’s reconstruc-tive theory of law and democracy.14

The structure of chapters in Between Facts and Norms reflects this ar-chitectonic. After the first two chapters, which sketch basic concepts in Habermas’s earlier work and introduce the facticity/validity distinction, Chapters Three and Four present the core of the discourse theory proper—the “validity” side of the most comprehensive facticity/validity division. Chapters Seven and Eight address the “communication theory of society” that occupies the “facticity” side of that distinction. The intervening Chap-ters Five and Six “test” the discourse theory, Habermas says, by addressing adjudication-related issues in legal theory and constitutional law.

Chapters Three and Four, devoted to the “validity” side of the most general facticity/validity distinction, seem in turn to divide along the lines of that same distinction.15 In Chapter Three, Habermas addresses, first, what he calls “the system of rights,” by which he means the categories of basic rights (five, according to Habermas) that any modern system of law must recognize if it is to count as legitimate. He turns then in Chapter Four to an account of “the principles of the constitutional state,” address-ing the institutional mechanisms and procedures required to implement the basic rights that he has set out abstractly, under the heading of “the sys- tem of rights,” as conditions of any legal system’s legitimacy. The account of the system of rights thus seems to track the “validity” side of Habermas’s basic distinction, while the account of the constitutional state develops the institutional and positive dimension of law that Habermas connects with “facticity.” Yet Habermas’s argument—a characteristic argument through-out his work on law and democracy—will be that the two moments, ana-lytically distinguishable, mutually presuppose and complete one another.

In section 2.2, I examine Habermas’s account of the system of rights. In section 2.3, I will take up Habermas’s account of the principles of the constitutional state.

2 .2 the system of r ights

The task of Habermas’s “system of rights” is to mediate two related ten-sions: between private and public autonomy and between basic rights and popular sovereignty. Here, too, Habermas sees these tensions as expres-sion of a more general tension between facticity and validity.16 Basic indi-vidual rights create spheres of morally neutralized action, thus securing

Page 75: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 64

individuals’ private autonomy. But these rights must be justified and made legitimate through a legislative procedure that is based on the “principle of popular sovereignty.”17 The idea of Habermas’s system of rights is to show that these two aspects of modern law are not only compatible but “co-original.”18

First, however, Habermas must show that modern legal orders’ “self-understanding” manifests the tension that he proposes to mediate.

2.2.1 The Grounds of Law’s Legitimacy

Habermas’s reconstruction of modern legal orders’ “self-understanding” begins with readings of two traditions: nineteenth-century German civil-law theory and the social contract theory of Rousseau and Kant. Habermas draws two conclusions from these readings. First, the ideas of human rights and popular sovereignty are “the sole ideas that can justify modern law.”19 Second, neither tradition succeeded in reconciling the two ideas. This ac-count is the background for Habermas’s own attempt to mediate the ten-sion between human rights and popular sovereignty, private autonomy and civic autonomy.

In German private-law theory, Habermas sees the primacy of in-dividual private-law rights to property and free contract. For the mid-nineteenth century authors in this tradition, these rights presupposed an equality among legal persons and were based in the mutual recogni-tion of all. But this mutual recognition was independent of authorization by a democratic legislature. The justification for these private-law rights was that they created and maintained a zone of personal sovereignty and private autonomy. This moral grounding of private-law rights gave way, according to Habermas, with the ascent of positivist theories of the late nineteenth century—theories that traced the validity of law not to its cor-respondence with moral notions but to the binding will of a sovereign. And according to Habermas, subsequent developments in German civil-law theory—efforts to restore the moral grounding of private-law rights, to add “social rights” to the negative liberties of private law, or to explain the connection between private autonomy and democratic lawmaking—have been unsuccessful.20

In Rousseau, Habermas finds the ideas of political autonomy and pop-ular sovereignty that are absent in classical civil-law jurisprudence. And with Rousseau’s link between democratic lawmaking and the general will, the exercise of political autonomy seems to guarantee the equal liberties of

Page 76: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 65

all. In that sense, Habermas says, Rousseau’s emphasis on civic autonomy establishes “an internal connection between popular sovereignty and hu-man rights.” But Rousseau places demanding preconditions on this ex-ercise of civic autonomy. If the legal order is not to be a coercive order, the political community must be small and already integrated through a shared cultural tradition, and its members must possess extraordinary civic virtue. In Habermas’s view, however, these conditions amount to a de-nial of the basic problematic of modern law: the differentiation of interest positions, the pluralization of groups and conceptions of the good, and the increasing importance of self-interested action. And thus, according to Habermas, the promised reconciliation of private and civic autonomy remains fictive—at least with respect to a recognizably modern society.21

Finally, in Kant Habermas finds both a notion of political autonomy and an emphasis upon private individual liberties. The grounding for these private rights is, as in German civil-law jurisprudence, a moral no-tion of autonomy and the mutual recognition of rights among equals. These particular rights are for Kant the specification of a more general right to equal liberties. The requirement that these rights be specified in positive law seems to link Kant’s system of rights to the idea of popular sovereignty. But, according to Habermas, the status of these individual rights as prepolitical natural rights creates an “unacknowledged competi-tion between morally grounded human rights and the principle of popular sovereignty.”22 The morally grounded system of rights operates as a limit on democratic legislation. Thus, rather than reconciling the idea of human rights with the principle of popular sovereignty, Habermas claims, Kant subordinates the latter to the former.23

Habermas incorporates into his preliminary notion of law several points on which his three readings converge. Modern law, in all three, cen-ters around a “system of rights.” These rights take the form of equally dis-tributed, mutually recognized individual liberties that define the legal per-son as rights-bearer. Following Kant and the German civil-law tradition, Habermas sees these individual rights as the basis for private autonomy—the sphere of individual decision making that must be preserved if law is to be legitimate. Further, from Rousseau and Kant, Habermas incorporates the idea of popular sovereignty or democratic lawmaking as a source of legitimacy. The idea here is that a legal order is legitimate to the extent that its norms are authored by their addressees. Habermas refers to this idea, interchangeably, as “civic autonomy,” “public autonomy,” or “politi-cal autonomy.” And, according to Habermas, Rousseau and Kant saw also

Page 77: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 66

that these two sources of legitimacy needed to be genuinely reconciled— popular sovereignty with individual rights, or, put differently, private auton-omy with civic autonomy. But the reconciliations failed in each case, accord-ing to Habermas, because each tacitly ranks one term in these conceptual pairs over the other. Kant, Habermas maintains, emphasizes a “moral read-ing of human rights” that subordinates popular sovereignty and civic auton-omy. Rousseau provides an “ethical reading of popular sovereignty”—where, by “ethical,” Habermas means “pertaining to a particular community’s form of life.” Kant and the early German civil-law theorists thus grounded law in morality. Rousseau grounded it in the shared life of a unified and virtuous ethical community. In both cases, law’s legitimacy is established extralegally, by virtue of the postulated correspondence between the legal order and some other order—whether moral or (in Habermas’s sense) ethical.

According to Habermas, the subordination of law to morality or ethi-cal life misunderstands the place of law in modern society. Legal norms are not just imperfect copies of universal moral norms, nor are they simply em-anations of an existing, prepolitical consensus. Habermas sees the relation between law and morality as complementary, and he understands both as differentiated from particular forms of life belonging to ethically unified communities.24 He makes these points in the first instance through his theory of rationalization.

The process Habermas calls the “rationalization of the lifeworld” brings an increasing pluralism of forms of life, with the customary norms and practices of each “devalued to mere conventions.”25 This allows the differentiation of both morality and law from traditional norms based in particular homogenous communities. On Habermas’s reading, morality becomes increasingly universalistic—Habermas focuses on Kant’s moral theory, but utilitarianism would qualify as well—and moral norms are to be justified not simply by their coherence with particular traditions but impartially, through universalistic moral discourses.26 With the positiviza-tion of law, legal norms come to be generated through legally prescribed procedures.27 The process of rationalization, then, weakens the connec-tions between legal and moral norms, on one hand, and the customs of particular communities, on the other.

The positivization of law—the generation of legal norms through le-gally prescribed procedures—differentiates legal from moral norms.28 So too does the internal link between the validity of a legal norm, but not a moral norm, and the norm’s enforcement.29 And so too do the different references of the two kinds of norms—to members of a legal community,

Page 78: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 67

in the case of legal norms, and (on Habermas’s view) to “humanity or a presupposed republic of world citizens,” in the case of moral norms.30 But Habermas sees the relation between law and morality not just as differ-entiation: The two kinds of norms, he says, are “complementary.”31 Law, according to Habermas, compensates for the heavy burdens that univer-salistic, postconventional moralities place on individuals. Some of these burdens Habermas classifies as “cognitive.” Postconventional moralities consist not in a list of concrete duties but primarily in a universalization principle and an idea of discursive justification. Because they require auton-omous determinations, postconventional moralities require the individual to make difficult judgments in justifying general principles, in deciding which of several potentially applicable principles should apply, and in ap-plying an abstract principle to a factual situation.32 Legal norms ease this burden with their relative concreteness.33 And through their employment of sanctions to induce compliance, legal norms address also the “weakness of the will” problems that are exacerbated in postconventional moralities.34 From a functional point of view, then, law supplements morality in regu-lating interpersonal relations, and it does so through institutionally bound, coercive mechanisms that are absent from postconventional morality.

Habermas thus rejects the idea that law is subordinate to morality or the prepolitical customs and norms of a particular homogenous commu-nity. And although he sees legal and moral norms as complementary, he re-jects the idea that law’s legitimacy can be established solely through moral theory: The institutional dimension of law and its coercive mechanisms are sufficient to differentiate law, and the basis of its legitimacy, from moral-ity. Thus, if human rights and popular sovereignty are to be the grounds of law’s legitimacy, they need to be understood not in a moral or ethical sense, but directly as legal rights and legal procedures.35

Habermas’s reconstruction of the system of rights aims at an account that “gives equal weight to both the private and the public autonomy of the citizen.”36 In accounting for civic or political autonomy, Habermas says, he must incorporate the sense in which a legal order can be said to be authored by the members of a legal community who are also the address-ees of legal norms.37 Here he must make room for democratic procedures of lawmaking—or, as Habermas puts it, for the “discursive processes of opinion- and will-formation in which the sovereignty of the people as-sumes a binding character.”38 And in accounting for private autonomy, Habermas claims, he must leave room for individuals not to exercise this very “communicative freedom.” Legally protected private liberties involve

Page 79: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 68

actors’ freedom to “withdraw from the public space . . . to a position of mutual observation and influence.”39 In terms of Habermas’s action the-ory, these liberties “entitle one to drop out of communicative action”40 and to act strategically with respect to individual interests. In these respects, private liberties are basic to the creation of morally neutralized spheres of strategic action—spheres of action that Habermas’s earlier work analyzed as the economic and administrative systems.

But Habermas has in mind here more than just the freedom to act stra-tegically in pursuit of economic gain or power. He speaks also of a right to “privacy” that consists in an actor’s refusal “to give others an account or give publicly acceptable reasons for her action plans.”41 This freedom to withdraw from the exercise of “communicative freedom”—that is, the free-dom to refuse to exercise one’s public or political autonomy—is a necessary condition of that communicative freedom itself.42 In that respect, public autonomy already could be said to presuppose private autonomy.

2.2.2 The “Discourse Principle” and the Categories of Basic Rights

Habermas’s categories of basic rights are designed further to reconcile the tension between private and public autonomy—a tension that appears also in the relation between human rights and popular sovereignty. Haber-mas approaches this reconciliation project with what he calls “the discourse principle.” In its general form, this principle is neutral between law and mo-rality.43 As Habermas puts it, the discourse principle “merely expresses the meaning of postconventional requirements of justification”44—that is, the requirements of justification in a rationalized “lifeworld,” where tradition and religious or metaphysical worldviews are no longer sufficient to legiti-mate social norms or institutions. Habermas states the principle as follows:

D: Just those action norms are valid to which all possibly affected persons could agree as participants in rational discourses.45

I will examine later the ambiguity of “could” in the expression “could agree.” For now, clarification of the other terms—all of which are expressly defined46—will suffice. By “action norms,” Habermas means “temporally, socially, and substantively generalized behavioral expectations.” By “af-fected persons” he means “anyone whose interests are touched by the fore-seeable consequences of a general practice regulated by the norms at issue.” And with the term rational discourse, he refers to “any attempt to reach an understanding over problematic validity claims,” provided that conditions

Page 80: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 69

permit “free processing of topics and contributions, information and rea-sons.” Habermas adds a rider that will turn out to be important: The term “rational discourse” also “refers indirectly to bargaining processes insofar as these are regulated by discursively grounded procedures.”47 This rider allows him to include also processes of “compromise,” where discursive agreement is impossible to obtain—provided that the bargaining condi-tions underlying the compromise are fair.48 Such compromises will turn out to be important in his account of the Rechtsstaat, or constitutional state.

The other conceptual tool Habermas introduces is the idea of “the legal form.” Habermas seems to mean by this term the formal characteristics of legal norms that make them specifically legal rather than moral.49 Haber-mas also refers in this context to “the legal medium.” The terms legal form and legal medium seem to be synonymous for Habermas.50 But his use of the word medium, together with the unclear relation between “legal form” and “legal medium,” gets Habermas into some conceptual difficulties.

The problem with the term medium is that Habermas’s prior writings, as well as a number of passages in Between Facts and Norms, use the term medium as shorthand for “steering medium.” As I mentioned in section 1.4, the term steering medium is part of Habermas’s social-theoretical vocabu-lary, and it refers to money and power as “system” mechanisms that co-ordinate action by circumventing the process of reaching communicative agreement. As Habermas explains, his idea of a “steering medium” is a more restrictive version of what Talcott Parsons called “generalized sym-bolic media,” or specialized languages for particular social subsystems (such as the economy and polity). In referring to “the legal medium,” Habermas probably means something more like Parsons’s “generalized symbolic medium” than his own “steering medium.” If that is so, then law is not a “steering medium” analogous to money and power,51 but instead, a “language” with a specialized vocabulary and conceptual structure that “circulates” throughout society.52 And if we understand the term legal me-dium in that way, then the term legal form should mean that which marks the legal medium as legal—the particular structure and characteristics of law that make it what it is.

Even with this conceptual clarification, Habermas’s argument is dif-ficult to follow. His initial claim is that “the legal medium as such [or the legal form] presupposes rights that define the status of legal persons as bearers of rights.”53 Habermas has in mind, in the first instance, the sort of liberties he analyzes under the heading of private autonomy.54 But he does not mean that the legal form (or legal medium) by itself necessarily implies

Page 81: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 70

the panoply of rights recognized in German civil-law theory or in any par-ticular existing legal system. What he means, instead, is that the legal form (and legal medium) presupposes a concept of legal personhood and that the concept of legal person is one of rights-bearer, whatever the particular content of those rights might be.

Habermas’s perspective here is of course abstract, but it is nonetheless familiar. American status law historically has denied full legal personhood to members of various groups by limiting or denying outright the rights available to others—whether private-law rights or rights of political partici-pation. Those who lack the full complement of rights ordinarily granted to legal persons are, to that extent, not full legal persons. So what Habermas means is that, whatever the precise content of rights in a given legal sys-tem, the idea of modern law uses the idea of rights to define the status of persons, and legal personhood is a necessary condition for participation in legal communication. In that sense the form or medium of law implies a system of rights.

But what sort of rights? This is the point at which Habermas invokes the discourse principle. He describes three “categories” of rights that are generated “simply from the application of the discourse principle to the medium of law as such.”55 The first category of rights he mentions is:

1. Basic rights that result from the politically autonomous elaboration of the right to the greatest possible measure of equal individual liberties.56

This category needs some parsing to be intelligible. Two aspects of Haber-mas’s formulation particularly need explanation. The first concerns the words greatest possible measure of equal, just before the words individual lib-erties. Habermas has said that the legal medium—or (he sometimes says) the legal form—implies the idea of individual liberties that define the sta-tus of legal persons. Here, however, we have the proviso that there must be “the greatest possible measure of equal” individual liberties. The lan-guage in quotation marks, according to Habermas, is the contribution of the discourse principle.57 While he does not explain this point, he likely means that we could not expect “all possibly affected persons” to “agree as participants in [a] rational discourse[],”58 as the discourse principle would require, to a system of unequal liberties.59 And if equal liberties were the outcome of this discourse, then the participants would opt for the max-imum of liberties compatible with the liberties of all. That, at any rate, must be Habermas’s argument.60

Page 82: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 71

The other part of this formulation that needs explanation is the phrase politically autonomous elaboration of the right to equal liberties. Just as Kant saw the right to equal liberties as a general principle that needed to be par-ticularized, so Habermas would require “elaboration” of this same right.61 This first category of rights, and the categories that follow, are just “un-saturated placeholders”62 rather than lists of actual rights. And the words politically autonomous before elaboration suggest that the elaboration of this category is for citizens to perform rather than for the theorist. The reason is Habermas’s idea of political autonomy. If the system of rights is to give adequate weight to citizens’ political autonomy, then the precise content of those rights must be left up to citizens’ discursive exercise of their political autonomy. The theorist is a “nonparticipant”63 in this politically autono-mous elaboration of the right to equal liberties, and it is not for her to de-termine precisely what rights citizens should accord one another—unless, perhaps, the theorist is intervening in an ongoing debate in an existing society, and in that case the theorist is operating in a different phase of Habermas’s project.64

The second and third categories of rights—relating to membership in a legal community and to the “actionability” of rights—are, according to Habermas, “necessary corollaries” of the first category of rights. Corollaries may not be the right word. But Habermas seems right that the concept of legal personhood implies both membership in a legal community and—at least as a general matter, and in modern societies—the “actionability” of rights. Here, too, Habermas includes the qualification that each category refers to rights that arise only through an exercise of citizens’ political au-tonomy. For that reason these second and third categories, like the first, are only “unsaturated placeholders.” Habermas formulates these two cat-egories as follows:

2. Basic rights that result from the politically autonomous elaboration of the status of a member in a voluntary association of consociates under law.

3. Basic rights that result immediately from the actionability of rights and from the politically autonomous elaboration of individual legal protection.65

Habermas describes briefly the sorts of rights that these second and third categories implicate. The category of membership rights establishes the distinction between those who belong and those who do not belong to the legal community. The general subject matter concerns citizenship rules,

Page 83: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 72

immigration, and emigration. Habermas suggests that the right to emi-grate must be guaranteed and voluntary, and, as to immigration matters, there must be “a regulation in the equal interest of members and appli-cants.”66 Habermas does not explain these conclusions, and at first they sound surprisingly substantive. But the first conclusion, concerning the right to emigrate, follows from the idea of a legal community as voluntary rather than compulsory. One cannot be said to “consent” to a legal or po-litical order if one is not free to leave it. The requirement that immigration regulation be “in the equal interest of members and applicants” follows, presumably, from the discourse principle. Habermas has formulated that principle to provide not that all members of a community be able to agree to a particular norm but instead that the norm be agreeable to all those af-fected. And regulations concerning immigration surely affect those who would choose to immigrate. Here, too, the discourse principle implies an equality of treatment.

The third category of rights, covering the “actionability” of rights and availability of “individual legal protection,” requires that legal remedies be available for violations of legal rights—again, whatever those particu-lar rights might be. Habermas has argued already that the idea of a legal norm’s validity implies its adequate enforcement. The requirement of en-forcement implies, in turn, that legal persons have access to independent courts that will decide disputes “impartially and authoritatively according to the law.” Here, too, Habermas takes the discourse principle to impose further requirements—in this instance, procedural rights consistent with basic norms of due process and equal treatment.67

These three categories of rights, Habermas says, define the private au-tonomy of citizens. But each category requires legal institutionalization if the rights they describe are to be effective legal rights. Habermas’s descrip-tion of each category has indicated that this legal institutionalization, or “elaboration” of the abstract category, must engage the political autonomy of citizens. Thus the fourth category of rights comes as no surprise:

4. Basic rights to equal opportunities to participate in processes of opinion- and will-formation in which citizens exercise their political autonomy and through which they generate legitimate law.68

Habermas describes this fourth category of rights as applying “reflexively” to each of the four categories, including the fourth category itself.69 What he means is that through the processes described in the fourth category, the rights indicated in each of the four categories can be specified, and

Page 84: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 73

legal norms can be generated. In this way, Habermas links political au-tonomy and private autonomy. Only through citizens’ exercise of their po-litical autonomy, he argues, can citizens legitimately secure their private autonomy by law. And exercise of that political autonomy in lawmaking must “orient” itself by the rights, described in the first three categories, that establish the private autonomy of a legal community’s members. Pri-vate and public autonomy, as well as basic rights and popular sovereignty, are thus “co-original.”70 Each presupposes the other, and neither may be ranked above the other in analyzing the idea of legitimate law.

This reconciliation between private and public autonomy—and be-tween basic rights and popular sovereignty—is located at an extraordi-narily abstract level. At this point in Habermas’s presentation, we do not yet have the institutions of a constitutional state. Rather, what Habermas is describing is the sorts of rights that persons must accord one another if they are to establish themselves as a legal community with (and through) the medium of legitimate law.71 At this level of abstraction, the tension be-tween basic rights and popular sovereignty is easy to harmonize. Our idea of legitimate law includes both terms. Exercise of popular sovereignty does not necessarily imperil basic rights, and basic rights are not necessarily an external limit on the exercise of that sovereignty.

The harmoniousness of Habermas’s reconciliation, however, does not necessarily carry over when the system of rights is institutionalized in a constitutional state. Imagine a legislative body on the brink of enacting a statute that unquestionably would infringe on some group’s basic rights. It would be implausible to say that enactment of this statute would not be an exercise of sovereignty. Habermas might contend, sensibly enough, that such a statute would not be legitimate law, in that it would offend a basic right. But in that case, basic rights would operate as a constraint on the exercise of sovereignty. As Robert Alexy has shown, similar arguments ap-ply if we imagine the legislators to be framing a constitution rather than a statute.72 The tension between basic rights and popular sovereignty, easily mediated in an abstract account of the “system of rights,” reappears once we imagine actual legislation, whether constitution making or enactment of ordinary statutes.

I would not expect Habermas to disagree with the above analysis.73 His point, I think, is not that his account of the system of rights has utterly re-solved the tension between popular sovereignty and basic rights. That would be inconsistent with the main theme of his discourse theory of law: an in-escapable and ongoing tension between facticity and validity. Habermas in

Page 85: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 74

fact understands this tension to be an achievement of, and criterion for, the very rationalization processes that make the discourse principle, in his view, the only persuasive principle of justification.74 What Habermas is arguing, instead, is that conceptual accounts of law that privilege basic rights over democracy, or democracy over basic rights, are misguided. The two terms, rightly understood, mutually presuppose one another in the idea of legiti-mate law.

The fourth category of rights, concerning citizens’ exercise of political autonomy, marks a shift in perspective. The first three categories describe, from the perspective of a “nonparticipant,”75 the “principles” by which the authors of law must “orient themselves . . . insofar as they make use of the legal medium at all.” But beginning with the political participation rights described in the fourth category, we shift, Habermas says, from the stand-point of a nonparticipant to that of a participant in democratic lawmaking processes. And here we need to speak not of the general discourse principle but of the principle of democracy.

Habermas’s “principle of democracy” (or “democratic principle”) is a particularization of the discourse principle. Whereas the discourse prin-ciple addresses the justification of action norms in general, the democratic principle concerns only the justification of the legal norms that are to gov-ern a particular community.76 Habermas’s formulation of this principle is extraordinarily strong: “The democratic principle states that only those laws may claim legitimacy that can meet with the assent of all citizens in a discursive process of legislation that in turn has been legally constituted.”77

If Habermas means that legislation must receive universal assent to be legitimate, then that requirement would be excessively demanding in any world, especially the pluralistic worlds of modern societies. But Habermas qualifies and weakens this apparent requirement of universal assent. For one thing, the word can in his statement of the democracy principle leaves him room to maneuver. He does not say that the only legitimate laws are those that have received the citizenry’s universal assent in some factually occurring “discursive process.” Instead, he says only that if a statute is to “claim legitimacy,” then it must be one that “can” claim the assent of all in a discursive process. We need to know more about the discursive pro-cess Habermas has in mind. We know that it must be an idealized and counterfactual process; otherwise, all existing law would be illegitimate. But what outcomes could we expect in an idealized and counterfactual discourse? The answer depends on how much we idealize the counterfac-

Page 86: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 75

tual discourse. It would take considerable idealization, however, for the outcome to be universal assent with respect to any law—unless, that is, we understand “assent” to mean something more like “willingness to live with” rather than univocal endorsement.78

Habermas, even at this point in the development of his theory, has sig-naled that he might intend assent to mean something weaker than univo-cal endorsement. Recall that in stating the discourse principle, Habermas includes the possibility of bargaining and compromise. A compromise may be valid, Habermas allows, even if the parties reach agreement for different reasons.79 It will turn out, in his discussion of the constitutional state, that Habermas leaves considerable room for these options—to the point of ac-knowledging that “compromises make up the bulk of political decisionmak-ing.”80 We will see that many of the arrangements Habermas approves in his account of the constitutional state are inconsistent with any strong reading of the “universal assent” requirement. What Habermas does with his ac-count of the constitutional state is to displace the problem of “universal as-sent” from legislative outcomes to lawmaking procedures. The question will be whether that solution is compelling, or whether, instead, the formulation of the democracy principle should be weakened from the outset.

One more category in Habermas’s system of rights remains to be men-tioned. I will have more to say about this category in the concluding sec-tion of Chapter Three, but for now I will only introduce it. While the first four categories correspond to familiar liberal rights,81 the fifth category takes up the “social and ecological rights” commonly associated with the welfare state.82 And while the first four categories are “absolutely justi-fied,” the fifth category is justified only “relatively”—that is, only so far as social and ecological rights are necessary to guarantee exercise of the rights described in the first four categories.83 Habermas formulates this category as follows:

5. Basic rights to the provision of living conditions that are socially, technologically, and ecologically safeguarded, insofar as the current circumstances make this necessary if citizens are to have equal op-portunities to utilize the civil rights listed in (1) through (4).84

One question will concern how far this “relative justification” extends. Another will be whether these social and ecological rights fairly could be called “basic” to modern legal orders generally, when they are not recog-nized as such in American constitutional law.

Page 87: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 76

2 .3 a compa r ison w ith r aw ls

2.3.1 Similarities and Points of Connection

Habermas’s derivation of the system of rights will perhaps be more clear to some readers if contrasted with Rawls’s use of the “original posi-tion” device.85 Both Habermas and Rawls produce their basic principles through a hypothetical and counterfactual inquiry that is designed to ensure impartial and universalistic judgment. Rawls’s “original position” models impartiality through situational constraints on the parties who ne-gotiate the social contract: Behind the “veil of ignorance,” none knows the social position, race or ethnicity, gender, natural endowments, or compre-hensive moral/political doctrine of the citizens he represents.86 For Haber-mas, the impartiality and universalism constraints are built into the idea of rational discourse. Both theorists, then, consider what principles would be adopted if certain specified counterfactual conditions were satisfied. And both impose a unanimity criterion—in Rawls’s case, unanimity among parties in the original position and, in Habermas’s case, unanimity among members of his hypothetically self-constituting legal community.

Further, both hypothetical devices are produced through generous con-sideration of circumstances in a modern democratic society. The considered convictions on which Rawls relies come from the fund of publicly acknowl-edged insights in a modern democratic culture.87 The “medium” or “form of law” on which Habermas relies—as well as the discourse principle— is generated through “rational reconstruction” of norms and practices in specifically modern and democratic societies. So, too, is Habermas’s idea that “private” and “public autonomy”—and the liberties of moderns and ancients, respectively—are to receive equal weight.

The content of the basic principles that Habermas and Rawls generate is similar.88 Rawls’s first principle of justice prescribes that “each person has an equal claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic rights and liberties.”89 Similarly, the first category of Habermas’s system of rights is recognition of “basic rights that result from the politically autonomous elaboration of the right to the greatest possible measure of equal individ-ual liberties.”90 Habermas’s formulation, requiring maximization, recalls Rawls’s original formulation in Theory of Justice, which referred to “the most extensive total system” of equal basic liberties.91

Further, both Habermas and Rawls give special solicitude to citizens’ political liberties. Habermas presents his first three categories of basic

Page 88: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 77

rights—essentially, private rights—as defined through a “politically au-tonomous elaboration” of a relevant principle.92 That indicates that these rights are effective only if recognized through a suitably democratic pro-cess. Habermas’s fourth category gives content to the phrase politically au-tonomous elaboration, by mandating broad rights of political participation. In Habermas’s thinking, then, the political liberties not only receive pro-tection as basic rights; they condition the concretization of the nonpoliti-cal liberties. As we will see in considering his account of the principles of the constitutional state, Habermas makes clear that he means something more than just formal equality for political participation.

For his part, Rawls argues that the political liberties—and those only—must be guaranteed their “fair value.”93 In the course of discussing “stages” beyond the original position, Rawls indicates that his principles of justice require legislation that would seek to equalize what otherwise would be substantively unequal rights of political participation.94 Rawls, like Haber-mas, recognizes that unconditional private rights, particularly with respect to the ownership of property, would compromise formally equal rights of political participation.95 For Rawls as for Habermas, a prime task for con-stitutional courts is to maintain the fair value of political liberties.96

An additional parallel in content concerns the status that each theorist gives social-welfare rights. Habermas’s fifth category of rights—only “rela-tively justified,” unlike the four “absolutely justified” categories—guarantees “basic rights to the provision of living conditions that are socially, tech- nologically, and ecologically safeguarded, insofar as the current circum-stances make this necessary if citizens are to have equal opportunities to utilize the civil rights” of the other four categories. According to Habermas, then, social-welfare rights count as basic only to the extent that they may be instrumental for exercise of the other categories of rights. Rawls, too, gives welfare rights decidedly secondary status. True, he recognizes that so-cial and economic inequality requires justification. That, of course, is the import of his difference principle. But the principle of equal basic liberties is lexically prior to the difference principle, and Rawls is clear that the dif- ference principle does not count as a constitutional essential.97 Both Haber-mas and Rawls, then, tend to see material inequality as constitutionally problematic only so far as it affects the exercise of more basic (and primarily political) liberties.98 Rawls, however, differs from Habermas in that he more clearly pronounces satisfaction of citizens’ “basic needs” to be a “constitu-tional essential.”99

Page 89: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 78

Apart from similarities in content, Rawls and Habermas give similar status to the basic principles that they develop. Habermas describes his five categories of basic rights as “unsaturated.” The descriptions are place-holders, only anticipatory of their elaboration and concretization through actual political discourse. Rawls, too, distinguishes between the two prin-ciples that would be selected in the original position, on one hand, and the principles and rules that develop in the successive stages he describes (constitutional, legislative, and judicial).100 Both thus see constitutionalism as an ongoing project rather than something accomplished and completed with the ratification of a founding document.

2.3.2 The 1995 Rawls/Habermas Debate

Habermas’s Between Facts and Norms was published in 1992; Rawls’s Political Liberalism in 1993. Two years after that latter date, the two theo-rists engaged in a much-anticipated debate on the pages of the Journal of Philosophy. Habermas began his discussion of Rawls’s work by stating: “I admire this project, share its intentions, and regard its essential results as correct.” The “dissent” Habermas went on to express was, he said, “within the bounds of a familial dispute.”101

Two points of apparent disagreement emerged that are relevant here. The first concerns Habermas’s charge that Rawls’s theory is insufficiently proceduralist in design. The original position, Rawls explains, models a pure procedural conception of justice: Whatever the parties select is just, with no independent criterion beyond the agreement itself. According to Habermas, however, Rawls’s theory relies, implicitly and improperly, on substantive conceptions. He has in mind Rawls’s idea of society as a sys-tem of cooperation, his idea of the well-ordered society, and particularly his conception of the person. These ideas, Habermas says, “introduce[] normative contents into the very procedure of justification,” and they are themselves “in need of a prior justification.” Further, Habermas argues, Rawls owes us a demonstration that these conceptions are “neutral toward conflicting worldviews and remai[n] uncontroversial after the veil of igno-rance has been lifted.”102

Rawls, of course, makes clear from the outset that his conception of the person is normative. That conception—like the other fundamental “com-panion” conceptions—he finds “implicit in the public political culture of a democratic society.”103 The theory, Rawls makes clear, “starts from within a certain political tradition”104 and seeks to work out a theory of justice

Page 90: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 79

on that basis. The idea of persons as “free and equal” may not be neutral with respect to all “worldviews”—in the sense that many would reject that conception—but that seems to tax Rawls with failing to achieve a sort of neutrality to which he never aspired. Rawls distinguishes between neutral-ity of aim and neutrality of effect. While state institutions must not be “in-tended to favor any comprehensive doctrine,” inevitably they will produce, for the various such doctrines, differential “effects and influences.”105

The odd feature of Habermas’s objection here is that it seems to ap-ply equally well to his own “proceduralist” theory. Rawls makes this ob-servation, though sometimes in the course of suggesting that Habermas’s discourse theory, a “comprehensive view,” is a sort of Hegelian logic from which unfolds “all the allegedly substantial elements of religious and meta-physical doctrines.”106 The observation can be made more cogently (and fairly) than that (and Rawls does so elsewhere in his reply).

Habermas generates his five categories of rights by applying “the dis-course principle” to “the medium [or form] of law.” Both notions fairly could be called substantive—or, at least, both rest on assumptions that could be characterized in that way. Discourse, as Habermas conceives of it, unfolds among persons who, like Rawls’s “person,” are free and equal. The situation must exclude all force other than the force of the better argu-ment, and all must have equal opportunities to raise topics, to offer infor-mation, arguments, and criticisms and to question the very terms of the discussion. The idea of discourse thus incorporates, in a thoroughgoing way, egalitarian premises. So does the discourse principle, under which a norm is justified only if it would meet with universal agreement in uncon-strained discourse among all those affected. Neither could be called “neu-tral toward conflicting worldviews” or “uncontroversial.”107 Further, as Charles Larmore points out, the professedly “postmetaphysical” character of Habermas’s theory means that “rational belief ” in the truth of religious and metaphysical world views “is no longer possible.”108 In this sense, too, Habermas’s theory is substantive and, in Rawls’s sense, “comprehensive.”

Has Habermas given a “prior justification” of his idea of discourse? Not in any sense that Rawls has failed to do. Habermas, in fact, developed the idea of discourse and the discourse principle through a rational recon-struction of specifically modern and (in Habermas’s sense) “rationalized” practices of justification. So, too, did his conception of the “medium of law” come from an analysis of specifically modern forms of law, with (for example) the characteristic separation between law and morality and char-acteristic conception of person as rights-bearer. If Rawls’s conception of the

Page 91: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 80

person is substantive and not uncontroversial, the same is true of Haber-mas’s notions of discourse and the medium of law. Habermas’s method of rational reconstruction seems not fundamentally different from Rawls’s way of working up the “person” conception.109

A second objection Habermas raises to Rawls’s political liberalism con-cerns the co-originality of the “liberties of the moderns” and the “liber-ties of the ancients.” By this distinction Rawls understands, as belonging to the moderns, “freedom of thought and conscience, certain basic rights of the person and of property, and the rule of law,” and as belonging to the ancients, “equal political liberties and the values of public life.”110 The distinction maps out closely against Habermas’s own distinction between private and public autonomy.111 The central theme of Habermas’s “system of rights” is that private and public (or, political) autonomy must be co-equal and seen as mutually implicative. In this way he seeks to distinguish his proceduralist theory from liberalism and republicanism (as he under-stands them). Liberals, according to Habermas, have subordinated rights of political participation to (the other) basic liberal rights, and republicans have reversed that ranking. He tells the same story of Kant and Rousseau, despite the intention of both thinkers to perform a genuine reconciliation.

Habermas acknowledges Rawls’s intention to reconcile and balance the liberties of the moderns with the liberties of the ancients.112 But accord-ing to Habermas, Rawls has failed, for reasons built into Rawls’s theo-retical design. The principles of justice selected in the original position, Habermas maintains, are already justified. And so in the successive stages of the theory that Rawls describes, with the progressive lifting of the veil of ignorance, Rawls’s citizens “find themselves subject to principles and norms that have been anticipated in theory and have already become in-stitutionalized beyond their control.” The constitution for them is not an ongoing “project” to be realized through exercise of political autonomy—Habermas’s position—but instead a fait accompli. The “essential discourses of legitimation have already taken place within the theory,” Habermas as-serts, and so the task of Rawls’s citizens is not the “present exercise of po-litical autonomy” but instead, only “preservation of political stability.”113 Further, Habermas (mis)reads Rawls as saying explicitly that participatory rights are largely instrumental for the protection of other basic rights.114

I find Habermas’s argument unconvincing. To begin with, Rawls in-cludes “the political liberties and freedom of association” in his list of basic liberties alongside the others.115 He does not there suggest any ranking. Moreover, in his discussion of how to handle conflicts among basic liber-

Page 92: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 81

ties, his criterion is that the “central range of application” must be main-tained for each of these liberties. Again, Rawls provides no ranking, and he makes no suggestion that the political liberties must give way.116 Fur-ther, Rawls places, in his first principle of justice, the requirement that the fair value of political liberties—and those alone—be guaranteed.117 That hardly suggests that these liberties are disfavored. If anything, it might be thought (incorrectly, but more reasonably) to mean the opposite.

Habermas’s point seems to be that Rawls’s theory, by pronouncing the two principles justified before any actual discourses among flesh-and-blood persons, presents Rawls’s citizens as constrained.118 To use one of Habermas’s favorite motifs, they are the addressees but not the authors of the principles of justice. But first, even if the basic principles are taken as fixed and unalterable, still (as Rawls explains) much work needs to be done in concretizing and specifying them—and in enacting them into valid law. This is the work of the constitutional convention, legislative stage, and judicial stage.119 Moreover, Habermas is forgetting that, for Rawls, the theory is fully justified only when publicly justified and accepted.

And here again, the objection Habermas raises would apply equally to his own theory. Habermas works up the five categories of rights through his own hypothetical procedure. The question he answers with his system of rights is: What sorts of rights must persons accord one another if they are to establish themselves as a legal community with (and through) the medium of legitimate law? The first four categories of rights Habermas takes to be “absolutely justified,” and the fifth category “relatively justi-fied” (that is, justified so far as necessary to guarantee the other categories of rights). Do these categories of rights, generated through the counter-factual device of Habermas’s theory, then confront Habermas’s citizens as pregiven, stripping them of their political autonomy? Habermas’s position seems completely parallel to the position he criticizes in Rawls.120

With respect to his own theory, Habermas argues that even though he has pronounced four categories of rights to be absolutely justified, those rights do not operate as a constraint on citizens or legislators’ political autonomy. The reason why not is essentially a matter of definition. The basic rights Habermas identifies are, he says, generated by applying the discourse principle to the medium of law. As conditions necessary for the production of legitimate law, they cannot be seen as constraints on the political autonomy that they enable.121 Perhaps for this reason, Haber-mas suggests that Rawls would have done better to ground his theory not in the original position but in the idea of legitimate law and the discourse

Page 93: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 82

principle.122 He then would have the same escape that Habermas thinks is open to him.

But as I have argued in section 2.2.2, the escape works only to reconcile abstractly the ideas of basic rights and popular sovereignty. Rawls, too, can make that claim—or, put in terms of his own theory, he can claim to have conceptually reconciled, without subordinating either, the political liberties with other basic liberties. But, outside the bounds of the theory, and from the perspective of a contrary-minded legislator, basic liberties do appear to be a constraint on lawmaking—so long as we don’t simply define lawmak-ing as the making of law consistent with the recognition of basic rights.

In short, I see more agreement than disagreement between Habermas and Rawls as to the political liberties’ status. Habermas’s criticism on this point is not telling.

2 .4 the constit u tiona l state

Habermas’s reconstructive theory of the Rechtsstaat or “constitutional state,” like his reconstructive account as a whole, is keyed to the issue of modern legal orders’ legitimacy. But the reconstructive theory itself incor-porates the more general tension between facticity and validity, and so it, too, has a side that corresponds to “validity” and a side that corresponds to “facticity.” The system of rights occupies the former position in Habermas’s theory, setting out the normative conditions required for any modern sys-tem of law to count as legitimate. The rights set forth in that part of Haber-mas’s theory are “unsaturated placeholders,” not concrete legal rights. That is, they are seen as the conditions that orient legitimate lawmaking, not as elements of positive law. With the transition to the principles of the con-stitutional state, however, Habermas considers the sorts of arrangements that would have to be set forth in positive law for a legal order to count as legitimate. And so, at this point, with the idea of law’s positivity before us, we move to the “facticity” side of Habermas’s organizing distinction—even as we still consider the more general issue of legal legitimacy. Habermas’s account of the constitutional state addresses the institutions, procedures, and mechanisms that are required if the abstract categories of rights he has described are to be implemented concretely through positive law.

The term Rechtsstaat, translated in Between Facts and Norms as “consti-tutional state” or “rule of law,” compounds the German words for “law” and “state.” Habermas’s theory of the Rechtsstaat first explores the implied

Page 94: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 83

connection—Habermas says an “internal connection”123—between law and political power. Then, by way of explaining the link between the dem-ocratic idea that legitimates law and the operation of political power, he develops a distinction between “communicative power” and “administra-tive power.” The idea of the democratic Rechtsstaat, or constitutional state, Habermas claims, is that citizens’ communicative power is the source of le-gitimate law, and administrative power—or, power as a steering medium—should remain “tied” to that lawmaking power124 in both the generation and application of administrative power. Habermas sees the separation of powers as a mechanism that guards against the illegitimate use of adminis-trative power. He explicates that notion by distinguishing among different kinds of discourse appropriate to the various governmental powers.

2.4.1 The Internal Link between Law and Political Power

Habermas has said that the validity of a legal norm implies its ad-equate enforcement. To that extent, law and the exercise of power are conceptually—or, as Habermas likes to say, “internally”125—linked. This connection of law and political power appears in the enforcement of rights through state-organized courts, with state personnel imposing sanctions to enforce courts’ judgments where necessary. Habermas’s reconstructive theory of the constitutional state goes further. Law and political power are linked not just through enforcement but in the legislative process as well. Legitimate lawmaking requires democratic procedure that is established with the “help of governmental power.” And the executive power imple-ments enacted legal norms through the “organized offices of a public ad-ministration.”126 In all these ways, Habermas says, “Political power is not externally juxtaposed to law but is rather presupposed by law.”127

The relation between law and political power is reciprocal. Not only does law presuppose political power; political power, at least in a consti-tutional state, presupposes law. The system of state offices, through which political power is exercised, is organized through law. And political power is exercised largely through the form of law. Political decisions, Habermas maintains, “owe their collective bindingness to the legal form in which they are clad.”128 Law and political power thus reciprocally perform func-tions for one another.

Seen from a systems-theoretical point of view, Habermas says, law and politics mutually constitute one another’s “codes.” Here Habermas is flirt-ing with Niklas Luhmann’s autopoietic theory—a surprising move, given

Page 95: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 84

Habermas’s frequently expressed distaste for the autopoietic (rather than Parsonsian) variant of systems theory.129 According to Luhmann, modern societies are differentiated into a plurality of functional subsystems, such as the economy, politics, law, and science, each of which is a self-producing and self-reproducing network of communication. Each subsystem’s com-munication is organized by a binary “code,” or distinction between op-posed values, that demarcates the subsystem from its environment. Haber-mas follows Luhmann in taking law’s binary code to be the distinction between legal and illegal.130 This distinction, Habermas observes, is ap-plied to particular cases in state-organized courts and enforced through governmental power. In this way, political power is constitutive for law’s binary code of legal and illegal.131 Habermas—like Luhmann—is much less clear on what the binary “code” for politics might be.132 Recalling his dis-cussion in Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas describes the politi-cal “power code” in terms of the giving of commands.133 Apparently, then, the binary power code is the distinction between giving and following commands. And it is law, Habermas argues, that specifies who has the power of command and who has the obligation to follow.134

Habermas’s apparent reliance on this aspect of Luhmann’s theory is pe-culiar for at least three reasons. First, a system’s binary code, Luhmann ar-gues, is what “closes” the system’s network of communication, and this idea of system closure is, elsewhere in Between Facts and Norms, the main target of Habermas’s anti-Luhmann polemics. As I suggest at the end of Chapter Four, I believe that Habermas’s polemics mischaracterize Luhmann’s work generally and the idea of system closure in particular. Nevertheless, Haber-mas seems to be appropriating an idea that, in his view, has pernicious theoretical consequences. This inclination is difficult to explain. Second, because Luhmann takes the binary code to be what defines both a system’s unity and its distinction from other systems,135 Habermas’s account of the different system codes for law and politics would commit him—if he were serious about the idea of the binary code—to the position that law and poli-tics are distinct (though closely linked) systems of communication. While Habermas does not make his view on this point entirely clear, he seems on the whole to favor treating law as part of a more general political sys-tem, not as a separate system.136 Appropriation of “binary coding,” then is not easy to reconcile with Habermas’s main line of argument. Third, while much in Luhmann’s autopoietic theory is well worth considering—even for Habermas’s purposes—the idea of the binary code is, for reasons I explain at the end of Chapter Four, not the most attractive aspect of Luhmann’s work.

Page 96: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 85

In fact, however, Habermas does not make systematic use of Luh-mann’s “binary coding” idea. It appears intermittently,137 but, in each in-stance, it can be translated into more familiar conceptions. In the passage we are now considering, the point is that law and political power recipro-cally perform functions for one another. That point does not presuppose that legal or political communication is organized by a binary code.

Still, even with the notion of binary coding excised, the idea of political power needs further analysis. As Habermas points out, not all exercises of political power are legitimate—not even when they are presented in legal form.138 And so the idea of democracy, basic to law’s legitimacy, requires a differentiation in the notion of power that can help distinguish between the legitimate and illegitimate exercise of power. That differentiation in the notion of power is between “communicative” and “administrative” power.

2.4.2 Communicative and Administrative Power

In contrast to his interpretation of power as command in Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas had developed four years earlier a notion that he called a “communications concept of power.”139 What Habermas meant then, and what he means now by “communicative power,” is the “motivating force” of common convictions reached through unconstrained communicative action.140 Here Habermas draws on the notion of “rational motivation” that he developed in his account of the way that mutual rec-ognition of validity claims coordinates communicative action. Habermas sees the communicative power of citizens as “jurisgenerative,” that is, as a way of “influenc[ing] the production of legitimate law.”141 The precondi-tion for this “jurisgenerative” power is the existence of “undeformed public spheres”142 of political discussion that are linked to the formal institutions in which law is made.143 In turn, the precondition for undeformed public spheres is a “vibrant” civil society,144 or, network of voluntary associations that are autonomous from state control.145 These associations, Habermas maintains, are the social basis for the political public sphere.146 Habermas’s idea of democracy, then, involves much more than formal governmental institutions and periodic voting rituals. It requires broad, active, and ongo-ing participation by the citizenry. In this sense, Habermas’s theory of law and democracy is not purely state centered.147 It depends heavily on com-munication outside of formal governmental channels—communication that, if it is to be “jurisgenerative,” must influence official governmental decision making.148

Page 97: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 86

This notion of communicative power is the basis for Habermas’s rein-terpretation of popular sovereignty. From a discourse-theoretical point of view, popular sovereignty means that “all political power derives from the communicative power of citizens.” Understood at full strength, this idea of popular sovereignty would require all exercises of power to be “oriented and legitimated by the laws citizens give themselves in a discursively struc-tured opinion- and will-formation.” And ideally, all relevant questions would be “processed in discourses and negotiations on the basis of the best available information and arguments.”149

Despite the reference to “laws” that “citizens give themselves,” how-ever, Habermas acknowledges that in political communities of any size, there can be no convocation of all the citizenry. Parliamentary bodies are indispensable. But what Habermas insists on is that these bodies “must re-main anchored in the informal streams of communication emerging from public spheres that are open to all political parties, associations, and citi-zens.”150 Only in this way can the communicative power of public discus-sions among citizens influence the production of legitimate law.

Habermas acknowledges further that the idea of communicative power addresses only the generation of political power, not the exercise of exist-ing power. And even if communicative power is the source of legitimate law, and thus the source of legitimate political power, Habermas has said that the idea of a legal norm’s validity implies that the norm is adequately enforced through sanctions. The exercise of power in the form of sanc-tions, however, does not itself conform to the model of communicative power. Moreover, Habermas acknowledges that the idea of power as com-mand, not power as collective will-formation, is essential to the organi-zation and operation of governmental entities. Politics, then, cannot be reduced to the jurisgenerative operation of communicative power. “The concept of the political in its full sense,” Habermas says, “also includes the use of administrative power within the political system, as well as the com-petition for access to that system.”151

“Administrative power,” the counterconcept to communicative power, is the notion of power as the “steering medium” of a self-regulating admin-istrative system.152 This systems-theoretical conception of power appeared front and center in Theory of Communicative Action. To recall that notion: Power, conceived of as official command backed by sanctions, allows actors to circumvent the process of reaching communicative agreement over con-tested claims to validity. Communicative power, then, develops through communicative action and discourse; administrative power circumvents

Page 98: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 87

both. The form of communicative power that is constitutive for democ-racy emerges outside the formal bureaucratic organizations; administra-tive power develops within those bureaucracies. The relation between ad-ministrative and communicative power is a central problem for democracy. In Habermas’s terms, how can the bureaucratic exercise of administrative power be linked to, and constrained by, citizens’ communicative power?

That is one of the questions Habermas’s theory as a whole is designed to address. His preliminary answer is general and equivocal. The idea of the Rechtsstaat, he says, is that the administrative system must be “tied to the lawmaking communicative power. . . . Administrative power should not reproduce itself only on its own terms but should only be permitted to regenerate from the conversion of communicative power.” At the same time, however, the constitutional state must avoid “disrupting the power code by interfering with the self-steering mechanism of the administrative system.”153 This preliminary answer moves in two directions. The first part suggests that the administrative system may not legitimately become inde-pendent of citizens’ communicative power. But Habermas adds immedi-ately that the administrative system is “self-steering” and its “power code” must not be “interfer[ed]” with. The two prescriptions are not compatible.

The problem is that Habermas’s systems-theoretical concepts are in-compatible with his present project: a normative theory of democracy. The concepts of “systems” and “steering media” developed in Theory of Com-municative Action were part of a more general model of modern societ-ies in which genuine democracy, as Habermas understands it, was literally inconceivable. The axis of that model is the distinction between system and lifeworld. On one side are the economic and administrative systems, operating through the steering media of money and power. On the other is the “lifeworld,” with its “structural components” of culture, society, and personality—or, as Habermas alternatively conceives of the lifeworld, the “communicatively structured contexts of action” that are distinct from the money- and power-driven economic and administrative systems.154 Theory of Communicative Action presents the relation between system and lifeworld systems-theoretically, as “interchange” controlled by “steering media.” But because, according to Habermas, only the economic and administrative systems have such steering media, the interchange model presents the rela-tion between system and lifeworld as steered only by money and power.

On this conception, the lifeworld’s contribution to the administrative system cannot be the “communicative power” of a normative consensus among citizens; instead, it must be assimilated to the “steering media” of

Page 99: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 88

money and power. And so in Habermas’s systems-theoretical model of in-terchange, the lifeworld’s inputs to the administrative system are “mass loyalty” and taxes, with the administrative system outputting, in ex-change, political decisions and “organizational accomplishments.”155 This austere model of system/lifeworld interchange has no place for the “juris-generative” communicative power Habermas now attributes to citizens’ discussions in the political public sphere.

The passage from Between Facts and Norms that I quoted two paragraphs above—noting that systems are “self-steering,” with their own “codes” that cannot be “interfer[ed] with”—carries over the idea of systems’ impervious-ness to normative influences. The passage is typical of Habermas’s official professions of commitment to the system/lifeworld model of society. But in fact, as I argue in Chapter Four, the social-theoretical model Habermas develops toward the end of Between Facts and Norms is inconsistent with the system/lifeworld model. It had to be. Otherwise, Habermas could not maintain that communicative power may influence and constrain the exer-cise of administrative power.

This is not to deny that bureaucracies tend to insulate themselves from democratic influences, nor is it to deny that there sometimes may be good reasons to limit the extent of such influences. My point instead is that to de-scribe systems as “self-steering,” with “codes” that cannot be “interfer[ed] with,” presents a tension as if it were a contradiction. Further—although this claim takes me beyond the scope of the present chapter—the concep-tion of the political system that Habermas presents in Between Facts and Norms is superior to the notion of the administrative system he defended in Theory of Communicative Action. The more recent idea of a “system,” while incompletely theorized, allows a more nuanced and balanced account of legal and political processes.

In any event, the administrative system cannot be entirely “self-steering,” on Habermas’s premises, because its “power code” is the product of law. Legitimate law, on Habermas’s view, is both the product of democratic law-making and the mechanism that defines the structures of official command and obedience that Habermas calls “administrative power.” Law, in other words, is a mechanism for effecting, and regulating, what Habermas calls the “conversion of communicative into administrative power.”156

The particular legal techniques for constraining the official use of power that Habermas mentions are familiar: an independent and impartial judiciary bound by the rule of law, legal controls over the state adminis-tration, and the separation of powers. What is interesting in Habermas’s

Page 100: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 89

account, however, is his explication of these familiar ideas, practices, insti-tutions and norms through discourse theory—and in particular, through a typology of the different forms of discourse and their relation to the dif-ferent forms in which political power is exercised. In section 2.4.3, I ana-lyze Habermas’s typology of discourses, as well as the idea of bargaining that sits uneasily at the boundary of Habermas’s discourse theory. Then, in section 2.4.4, I consider Habermas’s recasting of the ways in which the constitutional state binds administrative power to communicative power.

2.4.3 The Typology of Discourse and Bargaining

I noted earlier the “discourse principle” Habermas takes to govern the process of justifying norms of action. That principle, he said, is neutral with respect to different kinds of norms (moral and legal, for example). Haber-mas further suggested that the general discourse principle operates differ-ently in different kinds of discourse. Specifically, he noted in distinguishing between the “democracy principle” and “the moral principle” the different “reference systems” for legal and moral discourse—the legal community and “humanity or a presupposed republic of world citizens,” respectively.

This idea of a “reference system” is one basis for Habermas’s distinc-tions among the various kinds of discourse related to norms and social action. A second concerns the kinds of reasons that are acceptable in the various forms of discourse. Before his recent work on law, Habermas had settled on a tripartite division of discourses in which “practical reason” may be employed: moral, ethical, and pragmatic.157 Habermas’s work on law now understands legal discourse—or rather, the various kinds of le-gal discourse appropriate to different legal institutions and practices—as drawing on, but irreducible to, each of these three types.

Pragmatic issues concern the selection of appropriate means for achiev-ing given goals, or, should the goals become problematic, then the weigh-ing of possible goals against accepted preference standards, such as ef-ficiency, or against accepted values.158 Pragmatic discourses are directed toward justifying “technical and strategic recommendations.”159 The valid-ity of these recommendations is determined by the accuracy of the empiri-cal knowledge on which they depend.160 Habermas refers to the “purpo-sive” employment of practical reason in pragmatic discourses.161

Ethical issues arise when pragmatic preference standards or value- orientations become questionable.162 Habermas distinguishes between two kinds of ethical deliberation, one at the individual level and the other

Page 101: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 90

at the social level. Individual ethical deliberation, which Habermas refers to as “existential” or “clinical” deliberation, concerns the significance of a choice to a particular life-project or to “the kind of person one is and would like to be.”163 This decision is not purely individual but depends to a considerable extent on one’s social circumstances and the collective form of life one inhabits.164 Nonetheless, the ethical deliberation that takes place at the collective level—concerning not individual but collective identity—has a “different meaning.” Habermas speaks in this connection of “ethical- political questions.”165 Discourse aimed at establishing an “authentic” understanding of the collectivity’s identity—and realizing that identity through collective decisions and courses of action—is “ethical-political discourse.”166 The reference system here is a “shared form of life,” and the standard is what is “good for us,” the reflecting community.167

This hyphenated conjunction of “ethical” with “political,” however, tends to obscure a basic problem for modern multicultural societies. Haber-mas ordinarily conceives of “ethical,” unmodified, as referring to a particu-lar community that shares a form of life and a deep consensus over substan-tive values.168 But as Habermas notes in his criticism of “civic republican” theorists from Rousseau to Frank Michelman, one cannot conceive of mod-ern pluralistic societies as if they were this kind of close-knit community.169 The “we” who are (on Habermas’s theory) authors and addressees of legal norms are a legal community, not an ethically homogenous group.170

This point has significant implications for Habermas’s notion of “ethical-political discourse.” Despite Habermas’s statement that the standard for such discourse is what is “good for us,” differences among conceptions of the good in multicultural societies likely prevent consensus—in the sense of substantive agreement on the merits—as to at least many matters Haber-mas deems ethical. Further, if consensus must be the universal (or near- universal) agreement that Habermas’s discourse principle seems to require, then the problem for Habermas is more difficult still. What Habermas must develop, then, is a way in which, consistent with the discourse principle, modern societies can deal with the problem of “ethical” disagreement.

One option Habermas rejects would be to exclude, or at least radically devalue, all contributions to political discussion that presuppose the supe-riority of the speaker’s conception of the good.171 That option, Habermas claims, would bracket out ethical questions from politics and advantage the “inherited background of settled traditions.” Further, it would elimi-nate the possibility that discursive engagement might produce consensus as to ethical matters.172

Page 102: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 91

But what kind of consensus could be expected about ethical matters? To the extent that these matters are deeply rooted in competing concep-tions of the good, and to the extent that these conceptions constitute the identity of communities and their members, then, as Thomas McCarthy has argued, “persistent ethical disagreements” are likely.173 The standard that the discourse principle sets—requiring, with respect to norms, that “all possibly affected persons could agree as participants in [a] rational dis-course[]”174—seems unattainable. And Habermas realizes that it is.

For that reason, his response—on this issue and elsewhere—will be to reinterpret the discourse principle to require not consensus as to the substantive norm in question but, instead, consensus as to the lawmaking procedures through which discourse is to take place.175 This is one sense in which Habermas’s theory is, as he likes to say, “proceduralist.” A recurring issue throughout my argument, however, will be whether this procedural-ist move is consistent with the discourse principle or whether, if it is not, Habermas’s statement of the discourse principle must be modified. We are not quite yet in a position to address that issue. We need the rest of Haber-mas’s account of the various forms of discourse.

The third form of discourse in Habermas’s typology is “moral dis-course.” Just as Habermas’s use of the word ethical required explanation, so does his use of the word moral. Unlike ethical (or ethical-political) dis-course, moral discourse refers not to a particular community or shared form of life, but to an unlimited communication community.176 Moral norms, thus, are to be justified not in terms of their coherence with this or that collective form of life, but according to their consistency with “jus-tice,” where the term justice is to be understood in a strongly universalistic sense. On Habermas’s interpretation of moral discourse, a norm is mor-ally justified only if it expresses a “categorical” rather than “conditional” or “hypothetical” imperative.177 In other words, a moral norm is justified only if all those potentially affected—not just all members of a particular collectivity—could agree to it in a rational discourse.178 It must, then, ex-press an entirely general interest.179

As Habermas acknowledges, one consequence of conceiving of moral-ity in this way is that norms will be justifiable only if they are extraor-dinarily abstract.180 And that raises the question as to how such abstract principles could possibly be applied. Here Habermas follows the lead of Klaus Günther in distinguishing between discourses of justification and discourses of application. While a moral norm is justified only if it passes the discourse principle’s universalization test, its application is regulated

Page 103: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 92

instead by a “principle of appropriateness.” Determining which of various valid norms is “appropriate” to a particular situation, and how it applies to that situation, requires, Habermas allows, consideration of “all the rel-evant features of the situation conceived as exhaustively as possible.”181 We will return to this matter in considering Habermas’s analysis of adjudica-tion. For now it is sufficient to note that Habermas distinguishes between the justification and application of moral norms and that he makes a paral-lel distinction with respect to legal norms as well.

Alongside these forms of discourse, Habermas places the idea of bar-gaining. With this notion, he begins to address some of the issues I have raised above. “In complex societies,” Habermas contends—that is, in so-cieties marked by stratification, differentiation of interest positions, and a priority on self-interested action—“it is often the case that” neither moral nor ethical discourse will result in consensus. This is so, he says, “when-ever it turns out that . . . the proposed regulations touch on . . . diverse interests . . . without any generalizable interest or clear priority of some one value being able to vindicate itself.” In such cases, he observes, “there remains the alternative of bargaining, that is, negotiation between success-oriented parties who are willing to cooperate.” The aim of bargaining is to resolve conflicts not resolvable through discourse. And that means that the compromise the parties negotiate (1) must be preferable to no agree-ment at all; (2) must address the problem of free riders; and (3) must exclude exploitation, or, a situation in which some parties “contribute more to the cooperative arrangement than they gain from it.”182

Habermas does not make entirely clear whether these three conditions are simply an explication of what we mean by a legitimate compromise reached through bargaining, or instead, criteria that are to be applied to evaluate whether a given compromise is legitimate or illegitimate. My sense is that he means the former. Supporting this interpretation is the fact that Habermas turns immediately to the question whether bargain-ing is inconsistent with the discourse principle. And that, for Habermas’s discourse theory, is the question whether bargaining could be considered legitimate. “The discursive chain of a rational will-formation would snap at such points of compromise,” Habermas says, “if the discourse principle could not be brought to bear at least indirectly on bargaining processes.”183

Habermas already has signaled the conclusion he will reach. In stat-ing the discourse principle, Habermas said that the term rational discourse “refers indirectly to bargaining processes insofar as these are regulated by discursively grounded procedures.”184

Page 104: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 93

The relation Habermas forges between discourse and bargaining is in-direct at best. Discourse, he has said, imposes “symmetry conditions”: The participants must have equal opportunities to raise topics, arguments, and criticisms. The parallel in the bargaining situation is that the parties must have “equal opportunity for pressure,” that is, equal bargaining power. Because generally this condition is not satisfied at the outset, procedures must be devised that will equalize the parties’ opportunity for pressure. “To the extent that” these conditions are satisfied, Habermas maintains, compromises that result from bargaining are presumptively fair. But whether the procedures are adequate is according to Habermas a ques-tion for moral discourse. And so is the matter whether a given question is amenable to bargaining or whether, instead, it is a question in which gen-eralizable interests are at stake.185 In these ways, procedures for bargaining must be “discursively grounded,” as Habermas states in announcing the discourse principle. And thus although bargaining involves pressure and appeal to interests rather than to rational conviction, it is governed “indi-rectly” by the discourse principle.

As a general matter, this concession to bargaining rather than dis-course is wise. Habermas, after all, is “reconstructing” the idea of the con-stitutional state. And because, as he acknowledges, the bulk of political decision making involves compromise rather than purely discursive agree-ment,186 an interpretation of the constitutional state that branded bargain-ing as per se illegitimate would not be a plausible reconstruction.

But the reconciliation between bargaining and discourse that Haber-mas tries to establish raises two questions. First, the idea of bargaining suggests a refinement in the theory of action underlying Habermas’s dis-course theory. The basic distinction in Habermas’s typology of social ac-tion, I said in Chapter One, is between communicative and strategic ac-tion. Habermas’s difficulties in characterizing open strategic action led him to allow that most actual interactions are a “mélange” of the two types. Bargaining seems a clear example of this “mélange.” Habermas describes it as “success-oriented” and designed to exert influence on one’s opposite number through pressure. In these respects, as Habermas says, it can be characterized as strategic interaction.187 But on the other hand, bargain-ing seeks to coordinate the bargainers’ respective plans of action through a communicatively achieved agreement. In that respect, it resembles com-municative action. Habermas, of course, could reply that bargainers do not necessarily act communicatively without reserve—in colloquial terms, they do not necessarily place all their cards on the table. Moreover, to the extent

Page 105: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 94

that bargainers pursue different interests, they do not reach agreement for the same reasons, as Habermas’s notion of discursive agreement requires.188 But still, bargaining, to the extent it seeks cooperation and a common plan, is distinct from other forms of strategic action. Given its social significance, as well as the place it occupies in Habermas’s discourse theory of law and democracy, Habermas likely should recognize bargaining as a distinct type of rational action, irreducible either to communicative action or to strategic action in which cooperation and common action are not envisioned.189

The second question Habermas’s account of bargaining raises is whether he can plausibly claim that specifically moral discourse must ground and legitimate bargaining procedures. The procedural rules gov-erning bargaining are, in fact, legal rather than moral norms—that is, they bind members of a legal community, not humanity as such. While legal norms “may not contradict moral norms,”190 rules governing bargaining would have to be far more concrete and detailed than abstract moral prin-ciples. And so for that reason, their justification would not be possible in purely moral discourse. Perhaps Habermas means that bargaining-related rules are applications of moral principles. But that seems inconsistent with the way Habermas has presented the idea of “application discourses.” Such discourses apply general norms to particular circumstances. Bargaining rules of course apply to particular circumstances, but as legal rules they must be of general applicability.

The likely reason for this slip is Habermas’s anxiety about allowing com-promise procedures to be governed by rules that themselves are likely the products of compromise. If that were so, then “the discursive chain of a ra-tional will-formation would snap at such points of compromise.”191 Thus his statement that, while bargaining and compromise are not themselves forms of discourse, they are “indirectly governed” by the discourse principle.

The problem, however, is that these practices are indirectly governed by the discourse principle only in the sense that the governing rules pre-sumably are the product of a discursive lawmaking process. But that is true of any legally regulated activity, on Habermas’s scheme: All legal rules, if legitimate, must be the product of discursive lawmaking. Habermas’s recourse to moral discourse as the alleged source of bargaining rules is designed to avoid the conclusion that bargaining has no special connection to the discourse principle. But his argument cannot be sustained. Bargain-ing is not itself discourse, nor is it governed by rules that are products of moral discourse alone, nor is it “indirectly governed” by the discourse principle in any special way.

Page 106: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 95

2.4.4 Binding Administrative Power to Communicative Power

This typology of discourse and bargaining is the basis for Habermas’s reading of the way that the constitutional state binds administrative to communicative power. While he speaks of “legal discourse” in the singu-lar, it turns out that the permissible scope of this discourse varies, depend-ing on whether we are speaking of democratic lawmaking, adjudication, or the “administration” of law more narrowly conceived. These activities differ in their legitimate access to the “different sorts of reasons” and to the “corresponding forms of communication.”192 Habermas’s reinterpretation of the separation of powers incorporates this insight.

It is easiest to begin with the function of democratic lawmaking, be-cause lawmakers on Habermas’s theory have access to the “full range” of reasons.193 Here, despite his lapse with respect to the grounding of bargain-ing and compromise, Habermas is particularly attentive to the differences between legal and moral norms that entail differences in the respective modes of justification. Moral arguments are relevant to the justification of legal norms, Habermas says,194 but they do not exhaust the range of permissible arguments. Legal norms govern a particular legal community, not humanity as such. They are teleological, not purely justice oriented (in Habermas’s deontological sense of justice), involving “the cooperative pur-suit of collective goals and the safeguarding of collective goods.” For that reason the justification of legal norms must be open to “ethical-political” concerns. Further, as compared to moral norms (as Habermas conceives of them), legal norms are much more concrete in content. Some legal norms respond only to the need for legal certainty. The American rule of driv-ing on the right is the most obvious example, but other norms respond primarily to the need for certainty. Even beyond these norms, the matters law regulates are not necessarily ones on which one could expect univer-sal agreement, and for reasons Habermas has suggested, the possibility of compromises that balance interests cannot be excluded altogether from the legislative process. Finally, because the validity of legal norms presupposes their adequate enforcement, “pragmatic” issues may enter into legitimate lawmaking in this way as well.195

In short, lawmaking implicates the various kinds of issues Habermas has distinguished—moral, ethical, and pragmatic—and, accordingly, the corre-sponding forms of discourse all may be permissible. To mark the special character of legal justification, as well as the differences between legal and moral validity, Habermas amends slightly the tripartite division of validity

Page 107: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 96

claims that he introduced with the concept of communicative action. The validity claim relevant to legal norms is “legitimacy,” in distinction from the claim to “rightness” proper to moral norms. The standard Habermas suggests for measuring this legitimacy is whether the norm expresses “a rea-sonable consensus in view of all [the various] aspects and problem types.”196

The fact that Habermas selects a new name for law’s validity claim—legitimacy, rather than rightness—is significant. So, too, is his choice of name. We might take many legal rules to be “legitimate” but still believe they are unwise or suboptimal compared to alternatives. The term legiti-macy suggests greater focus on procedure and origins than on substantive merit. This proceduralist turn responds to the strength with which Haber-mas has formulated the discourse principle. That principle, again, requires universal assent in a discursive process. Even if we understand universal assent in a somewhat relaxed manner—emphasizing the “could” in the phrase “could agree as participants in rational discourses”—the require-ment still seems excessive. To name just two barriers to discursive consen-sus: Habermas has allowed the possibility (even necessity) of compromise over pragmatic issues, and he has said that “ethical” matters may not be susceptible either of discursive consensus or compromise. And so Haber-mas has to reinterpret the discourse principle, taking it to apply not so much to the substance of legal norms as to the procedure through which such norms are justified and enacted. The new term, then, is legitimacy rather than rightness, and the burden of legitimacy, here as elsewhere in Habermas’s theory, is borne by democratic procedure.197

One aspect of democratic procedure concerns the process of lawmak-ing within formally organized legislative bodies. As the idea of the consti-tutional state requires, this lawmaking process is itself legally regulated. Habermas mentions the standard issues here—periodic and secret elec-tions with equal representation, competition among political parties, com-mittee organization, generally public deliberations, and various legislative formalities. He does not argue that there is some uniquely correct way to address these issues. He says, instead, that these procedural matters must be “regulated in the light of the discourse principle,” to ensure that “the necessary communicative presuppositions of pragmatic, ethical, and moral discourses, on one hand, and the conditions for fair bargaining, on the other, can be sufficiently fulfilled.”198

In using the word sufficiently, Habermas is acknowledging that the ide-alized version of rational discourse never will be fully realized within leg-islative bodies. The principle of majority rule, for example, is an important

Page 108: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 97

limit. The pressures of time and the need for action require decision rather than endless discourse. Habermas suggests that a majority vote does not necessarily mean the end of discourse, just perhaps a “caesura in an ongo-ing discussion” or “the interim result of a discursive opinion-forming pro-cess.” But he acknowledges that legislative decisions, if revisable through new legislation, are less revisable than discursive conclusions on which col-lective action does not immediately depend.199

What Habermas is wrestling with here is the tension between two things he wants to affirm: his discourse principle, with its requirement of universal assent among all those affected, and the requirements of any imaginably functioning political system. Habermas wants both to argue that his discourse principle has been institutionalized, in the form of the democracy principle, and also to claim that he has “reconstructed,” from a nonutopian point of view, the “self-understanding” of existing Western constitutional democracies.

This problem has come up in four contexts: (1) Habermas’s acknowl-edgment that lawmaking requires representative government, not a dis-course among all the citizenry that by itself would produce binding law; (2) his recognition that “ethical” disagreement may make discursive con-sensus impossible; (3) his acknowledgment that the detailed nature of legislated norms, together with the connection between legislation and interests, makes bargaining and compromise unavoidable; and (4) his rec-ognition that the legislative procedures that are to cure the problems men-tioned in (1) through (3) above are themselves not entirely consistent with an idealized notion of discourse. In short, Habermas has to rely on an ide-alized notion of discourse to support his “universal assent” requirement, but that idealized notion of discourse is inconsistent with the requirements of any imaginably existing political system. In (1) through (3), Habermas has retreated from arguing that legislative outcomes must be “legitimate” in his original sense—capable of receiving the citizenry’s universal assent in discourse—to arguing that democratic procedure must carry the weight of legitimation. With (4), however, he now has to confront that existing democratic procedures are themselves far from what an idealized notion of discourse would prescribe. But he cannot reject the idealized notion of discourse without rejecting the idea of universal assent that is at the heart of the discourse and democracy principles.

Ultimately, the shift to a procedural focus cannot save Habermas’s discourse principle. Procedural norms are positive legal norms, and as such, they are within the scope of the discourse principle. The democracy

Page 109: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 98

principle—the version of the discourse principle applicable to specifically legal norms—provides that “only those [laws] may claim legitimacy that can meet with the assent of all citizens in a discursive process of legislation that in turn has been legally constituted.”200 Nothing in this statement ex-empts procedural norms, and for good reason. If procedure is to bear the weight of legal and political legitimacy, then procedural norms, above all, would have to qualify as legitimate. Given the discourse and democracy principles, that seems to require that the legal norms that constitute and regulate the democratic lawmaking process must themselves be capable of receiving the citizenry’s universal assent.201

We have here the same problem that prompted Habermas to retreat to procedural justification in the first place. The nuts and bolts of demo-cratic procedure—whether to have a bicameral or unicameral legislature, the number of representatives, procedures for committee and leadership assignment, and so on—hardly seem susceptible of universal agreement in any nonidealized discourse. The maze of procedural detail, like the maze of detail in substantive legal norms, resists universal discursive consensus and calls, instead, for compromise at any number of points. Habermas seems to recognize this point when he notes that discourse theory can-not prescribe any set of uniquely correct procedures. He does not seem to recognize, however, that because procedural rules, too, are positive legal norms, they would be subject to the universal assent requirement of the discourse and democracy principles.

Habermas might try to stave off this conclusion by arguing that only the most general procedural arrangements are susceptible of universal agreement (even in idealized discourse) but that these arrangements suffice to get the legislative machine in motion. This argument has two problems. First, even the most basic constitutional provisions for legislative process in-volve considerable detail—the number of representatives, for example—and, for reasons stated, universal discursive consensus on these matters seems unlikely. Habermas perhaps recognizes this point implicitly when he ac-knowledges that the “system of rights”—the basis for any legitimate consti-tutional project, and a system that includes democratic procedures within its ambit—could be realized in a number of permissible ways. The second problem with the argument that I am considering is that it demonstrates further just how little can be justified directly by Habermas’s discourse principle. Only the most general procedural arrangements could be sub-stantively justified; all other legal norms would enjoy merely a presumption of rationality, so far as their generation was procedurally proper.

Page 110: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 99

This raises the question why Habermas makes such strong claims for the discourse and democracy principles. I mean that in two senses. First, why does he formulate these principles so strongly, so that norms can be substantively justified only if they could command universal assent in dis-course? Second, why does he take the discourse and democracy principles, so formulated, to be so central to modern law, given how few legal norms can meet the demanding standard of universal assent?

As to the first question, Habermas takes “our” practices of justification to aim at universal assent, at least as a regulative ideal. Possibly this might be so with respect to scientific discourse, although I think there is much room for doubt even there. And those who, like Habermas, are commit-ted to strict universalism in “moral” matters will perhaps be sympathetic to the idea that moral norms must be susceptible of universal assent in an ideal discourse—though, as Habermas notes, the consequence of this posi-tion is a dramatic shrinking of the moral domain, with an equally strong trend toward increasing the abstractness of “moral” norms. But with re-spect to the kind of discourse that is the stuff of democratic lawmaking, the universal assent requirement seems not even to be a regulative ideal. As Habermas notes, legal norms touch on interests that may conflict sharply in modern societies, as well as group identities and forms of life that cannot be unified through law without strenuous dissent.202 The reasons Haber-mas has given for why universal consensus on substantive lawmaking is-sues likely cannot be expected suggest that the “democracy principle,” as Habermas has formulated it, is external to lawmaking discourse, not im-manent within it. Habermas’s account purports to be a “reconstruction” of modern law and democracy, but conspicuously absent from political and legal discourses in modern societies is the idea that a norm is justified only if all could assent in an ideal discourse. The few instances in which una-nimity is required in actual political discourses—such as the requirement of “unanimous consent” to revise and extend lawmakers’ remarks or oth-erwise to depart from prescribed procedure—are taken to be the subject of bargain and compromise. Such unanimity norms work, to the extent that they do, only because each knows that the other can sanction a refusal to assent by denying similar requests for unanimous consent in the future. Any resulting unanimous agreement is the result not so much of convic-tion with respect to a normative validity claim as it is recognition that the game is better played by withholding one’s objection.

The second question—why does Habermas cling to the idea of univer-sal assent, even as his account of legislative discourse undermines it?—likely

Page 111: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 100

finds its answer in Habermas’s account of the “system of rights.” The cri-terion Habermas sets for a reconstruction of law and democracy is that it must account for how the addressees of law are also its authors. The univer-sal assent requirement is a particularly strong way of accounting for iden-tity. If all legal norms could receive universal assent in an ideal discourse, then no one could complain that the legal order is coercive.

But Habermas’s own shift to indirect or procedural legitimation, rather than direct or substantive legitimation, suggests that this defense of the “universal assent” requirement is untenable. If laws are presumptively legitimate because of their procedural pedigree, then they may well be substantively coercive—in the sense that at least some members of society would not assent to them in discourse. In shifting to procedural legitima-tion, Habermas recognized that as to many legislative matters, universal substantive agreement is unavailable. After that shift, the sense in which law’s addressees are also its authors is that they, because of fidelity to rec-ognized procedure, have reason to accept legislative outcomes, even if they cannot endorse them substantively. This sense in which law’s addressees are also its authors doubtless is more modest than Habermas’s original formulation of the discourse and democracy principles seemed to promise. But it is the most that can be sustained, given Habermas’s (wise) conces-sions to the realities of the legislative process. The addressee/author iden-tity, like the scope of the discourse and democracy principles themselves, has to be reassessed and reformulated to reflect Habermas’s concessions about “ethical” disagreement and the necessity of bargaining and com-promise in lawmaking. That identity between addressee and author is not an independent reason for supporting the excessively strong version of the discourse and democracy principles. Universal substantive assent really has no place in Habermas’s theory after the proceduralist turn.203

The contribution of Habermas’s “discourse theory of law and de-mocracy” thus is not the idea of universal discursive assent. Instead, it is Habermas’s recognition that discourse—not “the discourse principle” as originally formulated—is institutionalized in the lawmaking process through legally prescribed procedures. The most novel aspect of Haber-mas’s account is the connection between deliberation and decision in formal governmental institutions, on one hand, and informal discussion among ordinary citizens, on the other. Popular sovereignty, reinterpreted discourse-theoretically, is consistent with legislative decision making in representative bodies, but subject to an important caveat: If the citizens’ communicative power is to influence lawmaking, legislative bodies must

Page 112: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 101

remain “porous, sensitive, and receptive to the suggestions, issues and contributions, information and arguments that flow in from a discursively structured public sphere.”204 In part this, too, is a matter of legal regula-tion. Public spheres must be constitutionally protected.205 Habermas sug-gests, also, that the procedures for selecting representatives must “provide for the broadest possible spectrum of interpretive perspectives, including the views and voices of marginal groups.”206

With this latter suggestion, Habermas likely implies a criticism of the American system, in which the two-party framework tends to limit the range of represented views. But much of the work in ensuring that citizens’ communicative power influences representative bodies depends on the cit-izenry itself, not the actions of representatives.207 Whether political public spheres are vibrant or moribund depends in substantial part on the soci-ety’s traditions and political culture.208 Habermas’s theory of democracy places great weight on the importance of active political public spheres and on their connection to the network of voluntary associations that Haber-mas calls “civil society.”

Habermas’s account of law and democracy, then, departs from an ex-clusive focus on state institutions. As Habermas recognizes, however, the claims he makes for the importance of public spheres and civil society need to be substantiated through social theory. That is a central task of Haber-mas’s “communication theory of society,” which, as I have explained, is the supplement in Habermas’s larger project to the discourse theory proper.

Here again, a contrast with Rawls’s political liberalism may be in-structive. The purpose for which Habermas develops his elaborate social- theoretical model of modern complex societies is to determine whether the discourse theory, developed through normative “reconstruction,” actually has a purchase on existing social conditions. The motivation for this exer-cise thus may at first seem similar to Rawls’s motivation in developing the idea of the “overlapping consensus.” Rawls asks: “How is political liberal-ism possible?”209 and in particular, how can it provide a stable basis for a just society?210 Habermas asks: How is it “plausible that the reconstructed normative self-understanding of modern legal orders does not hang in mid-air,” but instead “connects with the social reality of highly complex societies”?211 I would not go so far as Habermas’s suggestion that Rawls misses the “institutional dimension” of law.212 But Habermas’s reliance on substantive social theorizing in this second part of his project, as a supple-ment to and check on the philosophical analysis of the first part, seems to me a great advantage of his theory.

Page 113: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 102

As a result of his excursion into social and legal theory, Habermas has a richer account of the way that democracy operates—and might operate— than Rawls can provide with his more narrow focus on public reason. Rawls’s requirements of public reason apply only to constitutional essen- tials and matters of basic justice.213 But, as Rawls acknowledges, much or-dinary political discussion in a democratic society—among citizens and among officials—concerns other matters.214 Political Liberalism, however, has comparatively little to say about that kind of discussion.

The focus on public reason also leads Rawls to understate the impor-tance of voluntary associations in civil society for the workings of democ-racy. Such associations, for Rawls, count as part of the background politi-cal culture.215 Habermas, too, distinguishes between civil society and the political public sphere, but his more complete account of the link between civil-social associations and the operation of the public sphere emphasizes the former’s role in generating impulses for democratic practice. The idea of democracy, according to Habermas, is that (what Habermas calls) the citizenry’s “communicative power” emerges in the public sphere as a re-sponse to impulses from civil society, then flows through what Habermas calls the “sluices of democratic and constitutional procedures situated at the entrance to the parliamentary complex.”216 Civil society, to the extent that it is autonomous from both the state, is a source of “counterknowledge”—counter, that is, to official conceptions in the political system’s formal decision-making institutions.217

Such is Habermas’s account of the ways in which administrative power is bound to communicative power with respect to legislation. This account, based in a discourse-theoretical understanding of separation-of-powers norms, extends also to the other two familiar branches of government.

Lawmaking, Habermas has said, may rely on the full range of reasons and discourses—moral, ethical, and pragmatic—in discursively justifying and enacting legal norms. Adjudication, by contrast, is limited on Haber-mas’s theory to the application of existing norms. Habermas seems to ap-proach adjudication according to a civil-law model. The “cornerstone” of modern law is the statute,218 enacted by representative bodies. Habermas emphasizes the requirement of a “democratic genesis” for statutes more than did the earlier German tradition.219 But still, he sees the statute as “the foun-dation for individual legal claims”220 taken up in adjudication. Judicial deci-sion, he says, involves “the application of legal statutes to individual cases.”221

The obvious question for American readers is whether this idea of ad-judication is a plausible “reconstruction” (in Habermas’s sense) of Ameri-

Page 114: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 103

can practice. Common-law decision making involves the application of judge-made rules, not just statutes, and further, it involves the justifica-tion of new judge-made rules, not just the application of existing rules as pregiven premises. Habermas, oddly, does not systematically discuss the idea of common-law adjudication.222 As we will see, Habermas takes up Dworkin’s “constructive interpretation” approach in his “testing” of the discourse theory of law against legal theory proper. That will allow Haber-mas to argue that, in interpreting and applying existing law, judges are at the same time developing the law. But that does not adequately address the problem that judge-made rules, even if pregiven from the individual judge’s point of view, do not have the democratic pedigree that Haber-mas’s theory apparently would require.

Habermas’s reconstructive account of the constitutional state focuses on what he calls “normative” and “systematic” arguments why adjudica-tion must be limited to the application of existing legal norms rather than the justification and announcement of new norms.223 In terms of discourse theory, Habermas says, justification and application involve “different log-ics of argumentation.” To the extent this argument is not simply circular— assuming that adjudication involves only the application of pregiven norms—it is difficult to decipher. Habermas observes that adjudication re-lies on party presentation, with the judge as “impartial representative of the legal community,” whereas “in discourses of justification there are . . . only participants.”224 That may be so, but its significance is not immedi-ately clear. What Habermas seems to be saying is that adjudication can-not involve the justification of norms because the only participants are the interested parties and the disinterested judge. The justification and enact-ment of legal norms, Habermas has argued, require the participation of the citizenry through discussion in the public sphere. Adjudication, therefore, lacks the democratic warrant Habermas’s theory would require. For that reason, it cannot involve the genesis of new norms, and it must confine itself to “a discourse of application aimed at decisions consistent over time”225—or, consistent until the appropriate lawmaking power has changed the law.

Habermas’s second argument sounds similar themes. The judiciary has the coercive power of the state at its disposal to enforce its judgments. If judges were free to act as lawmakers, then they would be able to wield administrative power without connection to the communicative power of democratic discussion. The separation of lawmaking and law-applying power is a corollary of Habermas’s discourse theory of law and democracy. The conclusion is not novel—a basic argument against judge-made law

Page 115: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 104

always has been that it is undemocratic. What remains to be seen, though, is whether Habermas’s inflection of this standard point through discourse theory solves the standard difficulties. Is the distinction between justifica-tion and application any less manipulable and unsatisfying than the dis-tinction between making and finding the law? Is it an improvement on Dworkin’s attempt to escape this choice with the notion of constructive interpretation? I will take up these issues in Chapter Three, where I con-sider Habermas’s “testing” of his theory against legal theory proper and also against the theory and practice of constitutional decision making.

As should be apparent by now, Habermas intends his discourse theory as a recasting of separation-of-powers notions. One branch of government remains to be discussed—the executive branch, or as Habermas refers to it, “the administration” (Verwaltung). As one would expect, Habermas ar-gues that there must be legal controls over the administration to prevent it from deploying administrative power in a way disconnected from com-municative power.226 He mentions the usual such controls—the require-ment of statutory authorization, ongoing legislative oversight, and judicial review. The administration may not substitute itself for the lawmaking power.227 That much is obvious. More difficult is Habermas’s distinction between adjudication and administration, both of which seem to involve the application of democratically enacted law. Habermas admits a fur-ther difficulty: Given increasing legislative reliance on general clauses and goal-oriented programs, the administration is left “considerable room for discretion.” These recent developments, Habermas suggests, undermine traditional conceptions of administrative tasks as merely the technical im-plementation of norms established elsewhere.228

Discourse theory, according to Habermas, offers a way to account for the separation of administration from both legislative and judicial deci-sion making. Legislatures have access to the full range of “normative, prag-matic, and empirical reasons, including those constituted through the re-sults of fair compromises,” provided that they access these reasons “within the framework of a democratic procedure designed for the justification of norms.”229 The judiciary engages in discourses of application, in the context of particular cases, and it is bound to apply enacted law. A court is not free to “make whatever use it likes of the reasons packaged in, and linked to, stat-utes.” Anticipating his discussion of Dworkin, however, Habermas implies that in applying law, courts may engage in constructive interpretation—or, as he later puts it, that they may “justify the individual decision by its coher-ence with a rationally reconstructed history of existing law.”230 The adminis-

Page 116: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Reconstruction” of Modern Law 105

tration, however, is limited to “pragmatic discourses,” where the normative premises are “pregiven.” It is “not permitted to deal with normative reasons in either a constructive or reconstructive manner,” nor is it free to “follow [its] own interests or premises.” What it is to contribute is “empirically in-formed, purposive-rational decision making” in pragmatic issues.231

Habermas’s general idea here is to account for the separation of powers not so much in terms of differences among functional tasks, or in terms of a logic of general and specific,232 as in terms of differences in access to reasons and kinds of discourse. From this point of view, the significance of the separation of powers is that it is “a way to secure both the priority of democratic legislation and the recoupling of administrative power with communicative power.”233

This general sketch, developed through Habermas’s “reconstructive” analysis of law and democracy, is of course no substitute for detailed analy-sis of particular legal and political systems. Presumably Habermas would allow—as he has with respect to earlier work—that its merit depends on whether, in the future, it proves fruitful for more empirically oriented re-search.234 In fact, the rest of Habermas’s work on law seeks to bring the ideas developed reconstructively into closer contact with ideas generated through different approaches. The “communication theory of society,” which I discuss in Chapter Four, situates the discourse theory’s conclu-sions in a model of contemporary societies, testing whether those conclu-sions “connect[] with the social reality of highly complex societies.”235 And before developing that theory of society, Habermas seeks to “test and elaborate the discourse concept of law and democracy” against, first, con-temporary discussions in legal theory, and second, contemporary contro-versies in constitutional law.236

Page 117: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

chapter three

Discourse Theory and the Theory and Practice of Adjudication

With his “testing” of the reconstructively developed discourse theory, Habermas shifts from a “philosophical” standpoint to “the perspective of legal theory proper.” From this latter standpoint, the focus is on adjudica-tion and, in particular, on adjudication as seen from “the judge’s perspec-tive.” Certainly, as Habermas notes, this is the dominant perspective in legal scholarship. According to Habermas, this is not simply a matter of parochialism or traditionalism but a legitimate theoretical decision. His stated reason is as follows: “Because all legal communications refer to ac-tionable claims, court decisions provide the perspective from which the legal system is analyzed.”1

That reason does not sufficiently support a methodological commit-ment to court-centered legal theory. Habermas’s strategy is particularly strange given his statement, in the same general discussion, that on his ap-proach “political legislation” is “central” and his acknowledgment that one can analyze political legislation from the standpoint of legislators, agen-cies, citizens, and interest groups.2 Certainly one also could investigate law’s effects (or lack of effects) outside the courtroom, even if one sees law primarily as creating “actionable claims.”

But Habermas is correct that if discourse theory is to “prove itself ” as a theory of law, then it must provide an account of adjudication. To be sure, adjudication need not be understood only from “the judge’s perspective.” The perspectives of lawyers, the parties, and jurors are obvious alterna-tives, or better, supplements. But Habermas is right that one basic ques-tion of legal theory concerns how judges do and should decide cases. That

Page 118: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 107

question is indeed one against which a legal theory must prove itself, even if it is not obviously and necessarily the central question of legal theory.3

Habermas considers, first, the general nature of adjudication, ap-proaching it through a critical reading of familiar perspectives that is in-formed by his own guiding distinction between facticity and validity. He turns, then, to the special case of constitutional adjudication.

3.1 discourse theory a nd dwor k in’s “constructi v e inter pr etation”

In the context of adjudication, the tension between facticity and valid-ity appears as a tension between “certainty” and “legitimacy.” With the “certainty” requirement, Habermas connects not just the general need for adequate and predictable enforcement of legal standards but also the more particular need for consistency in judicial decision making. With “le-gitimacy,” Habermas associates the need for judicial decisions to be nor-matively justifiable and thus worthy of respect apart from the presence of sanctions.4 Habermas describes the basic problem of adjudication as fol-lows: “How can the application of a contingently emergent law be carried out with both internal consistency and rational external justification, so as to guarantee simultaneously the certainty of law and its rightness?”5

Two aspects of this formulation deserve comment. First, the word appli-cation reflects Habermas’s position, developed in his analysis of the separa-tion of powers, that adjudication is about the application of legal norms, not their creation and justification.6 The words external justification express the same idea. The justification for the norms applied in judicial decisions must come from without—from the reasons “packaged in, and linked to, stat-utes.”7 Second, the references to “internal consistency” and “emergent law” express the idea that present judicial decisions link to a past and future of le-gal decision making. The certainty requirement thus mandates consistency with past institutional history and, at the same time, prescribes that present judicial decisions must be points of connection for future judicial decisions.

With this idea of the double requirement for judicial decision making as the backdrop, Habermas distinguishes his discourse-theoretical ap-proach from three prominent theories of judicial decision making. As one by now might expect, Habermas maintains that each of these theories fails to reconcile the certainty and legitimacy requirements.

Page 119: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 108

According to Habermas, legal realism8 revokes the certainty require-ment by denying that past decisions are sufficiently determinate to con-strain present decision. This denial would, in effect, negate “the very function of law,” which is “to stabilize expectations.” Further, Habermas argues, realism pursues the legitimacy goal only by assimilating judicial decision making to other kinds of political decision. On this view, cases are correctly decided only if the judge wisely uses her discretion to pursue utilitarian or social-welfare goals. In both respects, Habermas thinks, real-ists skeptically reject the necessary “idealizing suppositions” of participants in the judicial process.9

Legal positivists, Habermas thinks, commit a symmetrical error. Ac-cording to Habermas, positivists see law as a closed system of norms, with legitimation coming only through fidelity to legally prescribed proce-dures. The basic norm—whether Hart’s “rule of recognition” or Kelsen’s Grundnorm—bears the weight of legitimation but “without itself being ca-pable of rational justification.” Instead, “as part of a historical form of life, it must be factually accepted as settled custom.” The emphasis on identify-ing unambiguously what is or is not law, and the concern with “pedigree” rather than rational justification, promotes the certainty guarantee at the expense of the legitimacy or “rightness” guarantee. Positivism’s treatment of “hard cases,” Habermas argues, reflects this “priority of legal certainty.” In such cases, Habermas maintains with Hart in mind, positivists claim that law has run out and commit the decision to judicial discretion. Here the “rightness” standard is extrinsic to law.10

“Legal hermeneutics” fares somewhat better in Habermas’s assess-ment. The insight here is that a “case” is defined by the relevant norm, whose relevance criteria select some aspects of the factual situation and exclude others. The decision reached by applying the rule counts as a fur-ther development of the rule. A decision’s legitimacy derives from the ethi-cal tradition that shapes both the judge’s “preunderstanding” of the case and the interpretive maxims that aid in application. But this connection of legitimacy to a particular tradition is insufficient in a pluralistic society, Habermas argues.11

The encounters Habermas stages with these three theories of law do not amount to much of a “test” for discourse theory. All three sketches are too brief to develop the theory in question, and the account of “real-ist” thinkers—attributing to them “a flat revocation of any guarantees of legal certainty”—is particularly crude.12 The characterization of positivism as pursuing the “priority of certainty” through judicial discretion, also, is

Page 120: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 109

problematic. Further, each of the three general approaches has considerable internal diversity, with many variants and subvariants. Habermas would have done better either to encounter the three theories in a less cartoonish version or to omit the discussion entirely.13 The purpose of his encounter, however, probably is not so much a “testing” of his own theory as a setup for a theory he will consider at some length: the theory of adjudication Ronald Dworkin developed in work up to and including Law’s Empire.

The connections between Dworkin’s account of adjudication and Habermas’s ideas are easy to see. Both focus on the decision of legal rather than factual issues, and both assume the “internal” perspective of the judge.14 Both see judicial decision making as bound by the certainty and legitimacy guarantees.15 Both emphasize the requirement of principled ju-dicial decision.

Habermas, in fact, could make more of the connection between his own approach and Dworkin’s theory of “constructive interpretation.” The linkage is easiest to see if we consider first the “chain novel” device that Dworkin uses to illustrate judicial decision making. A new chapter for a chain novel, Dworkin observes, must “fit” the prior chapters that other authors have crafted.16 Further, among the possible ways of continuing the story that survive some threshold test of “fit,” the author must consider which “makes the work in progress best, all things considered.” Dworkin, of course, notes that the two “dimensions” of interpretation—“fit” and “justification,” he called them in his 1986 work, Law’s Empire17—are not entirely separable. Questions of fit are relevant also in the second dimen-sion of interpretation, both in the chain novel example and in the practice of judicial decision making that the example illustrates.18

Put in terms of judicial decision making, the “fit” requirement means that a present decision must sufficiently cohere with relevant past deci-sions. Habermas, perhaps oddly, describes this only as a matter of justifi-cation, maintaining that Dworkin would “justify the individual decision by its coherence with a rationally reconstructed history of existing law.”19 Perhaps he is trying to say only that, on Dworkin’s theory, the degree of fit is relevant to the matter of justification. In any event, the requirement of coherence with past decisions is part of what Habermas means by adjudi-cation’s “certainty” requirement.20 Dworkin’s second dimension of inter-pretation, referring to the decision’s justifiability, corresponds to Haber-mas’s “legitimacy” or “rightness” requirement. Put in terms of Habermas’s overarching distinction between facticity and validity: Dworkin’s “fit” requirement treats past decisions as authoritative (“facticity”), but, at the

Page 121: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 110

same time, he sees the present decision’s justifiability (“validity”) as not entirely reducible to its degree of fit. Neither the interpretive dimensions of fit and justification, nor the guarantees of certainty and legitimacy, col-lapse into one another.

Habermas is more critical, however, of Dworkin’s decision to elaborate “constructive interpretation” through the device of Hercules, the idealized judge with “superhuman intellectual power and patience” whose cogita-tions and decisions we witness throughout the second half of Law’s Em-pire. Habermas asks the obvious questions. Does Dworkin’s reliance on an idealized judicial figure indicate that the interpretive tasks he sets for ordinary judges are excessively demanding? If no judge, by definition, can equal Hercules’ capacities, then can the theory Dworkin is defending serve as even a regulative ideal?21

Habermas approaches these issues by way of Dworkin’s reception in critical legal studies. Accordingly—and because of his own views about the central issues in adjudication—Habermas takes the basic problem to be one of indeterminacy. What reason, he asks, do we have for thinking that Dworkin-style judging would not simply substitute the political prejudices of flesh-and-blood judges, and unacknowledged influences in the judicial system’s environment, for determination by law?22 And if the law is “shot through with contradictory principles and policies,” then could Dworkin’s judge possibly complete the “rational reconstruction” that his interpretive method requires?23

To some extent, Habermas defends Dworkin against these charges. He notes Dworkin’s own reply, to the effect that the objections confuse rules with principles.24 Rules, understood as concrete norms that apply directly to particular fact-situations, cannot conflict without either invalidating one of the rules or requiring an exception. Principles, by contrast, may “compete” within a coherent normative theory without the competition being a theory-defeating “contradiction.”25 This reply is correct as far as it goes, Habermas thinks, but it can be deepened by considering Haber-mas’s own distinction, borrowed from Klaus Günther, between discourses of justification and discourses of application. “[A]ll norms” except for the most rulelike rules, Habermas claims, “are inherently indeterminate” in their application.26 This is because most norms do not specify, in detail and in advance, the factual situations to which they do and do not apply. And so in many cases, more than one norm may be potentially applicable. A discourse of application, according to Günther and Habermas, is required to determine which valid norm is “appropriately” applied in the particu-

Page 122: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 111

lar context, after consideration of all potentially applicable norms and all relevant facts and circumstances.27 But because the relevance of facts and circumstances depends on which norm one is considering, discourses of application require one to work back and forth between the norm and its situation of application. This uncertainty of application, however, does not affect the norms’ validity.28 And so the “indeterminacy” objection Haber-mas attributes to critical legal studies confuses justification with applica-tion, not just principles with rules.29 In this analysis Habermas follows closely Günther’s account of the logic of application discourses.30

As Habermas acknowledges, however, this reply to the indeterminacy objection does not sufficiently address the requirement of legal certainty. He makes this acknowledgment in the context of evaluating Dworkin’s theory,31 but it applies equally to his own. As Robert Alexy has argued, the standard of “appropriateness” in discourses of application, together with the subsidiary requirement of a “complete description of the situation,” is empty.32 It does not assist the judge either in selecting a governing norm or in applying the norm to the factual situations that the norm illuminates.33 It simply tells the judge to decide the case correctly. “Appropriateness” is a term of praise rather than a criterion or instruction that can guide decision making and promote certainty of outcome.

Habermas’s responses to this problem are surprising. He suggests, first, that “legal certainty” is “itself a principle that must be weighed against other principles in the case at hand.”34 This response seems, first, to misstate the logical status Habermas has given to “certainty.” It is not a “principle,” in the sense of a general norm that, in particular cases, helps specify the justification for decision. Instead, it is one of two basic func-tional requirements that a legal system as a whole must satisfy: The course of decision must be sufficiently certain (that is, predictable in view of past institutional history, with adequate enforcement), and decisions must be sufficiently justified to count as correct. Doubtless the point Habermas is trying to make is that these two requirements, which he has identified as in tension,35 may be traded off against each other. What he suggests is a reinterpretation of the certainty requirement that trims back its demands to a more manageable level. Again, his recourse is to procedure. Instead of focusing on the certainty of outcome, Habermas says, we should focus on the certainty of procedures. Sound procedures, he contends:

guarante[e] the certainty of law at a different level. Procedural rights guarantee each legal person the claim to a fair procedure that in turn guarantees not cer-tainty of outcome but a discursive clarification of the pertinent facts and legal

Page 123: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 112

questions. Thus affected parties can be confident that in procedures issuing in judicial decisions only relevant reasons will be decisive, and not arbitrary ones.36

This reinterpretation and relocation, however, responds to neither of the reasons that motivated Habermas to postulate “certainty” as a require-ment for adjudication. The “very function of law,” he said, was to “stabilize expectations.”37 That function requires predictability of outcome, not just predictability that litigation procedures will be fair. Nor does the fairness of procedures by itself guarantee continuity in a legal system’s institutional history. While good procedures may help produce more consistent out-comes, the more salient factor seems to be the character of legal norms ap-plied in a particular system. As we have known at least since legal process theory: “Rules,” which specify their applicability and application relatively precisely, are generally more certain in their outcome than open-ended “standards” or “principles.” It may be, as Habermas suggests in the final chapter of Between Facts and Norms, that contemporary conditions make classical ideas of legal certainty unrealizable.38 But then why does Haber-mas not make that clear at the outset of his discussion of adjudication? Why is certainty (of outcome) a basic function of law, and why is realism faulted for “revoking” the (classical) guarantee of legal certainty?

Habermas’s further response to the “indeterminacy of application” problem is no more satisfying. Apparently following Klaus Günther’s lead, he suggests that legal “paradigms” can operate to limit the indeterminacy of adjudication.39 What Habermas means by this term is not at first clear. His most common usage of this term—beginning with the opening of his first chapter on adjudication and continuing throughout Between Facts and Norms—presents “paradigms” as highly abstract interpretations of a legal system as a whole. Borrowing from systems theory, he describes a legal paradigm as “something like the implicit social theory of the legal system, and hence the image this system forms of its social environment.”40 Under-stood in this way, Habermas claims, “the legal paradigm determines how basic rights and constitutional principles are to be understood and how they can be realized in the context of contemporary society.”41 Habermas usually identifies these paradigms in a trio of competing conceptions—with his own conception drawing from but superseding the other two. In order of historical occurrence, these are the “liberal” (or “bourgeois formal-law”) paradigm, the “social-welfare” (or “welfarist” paradigm), and his own “proceduralist” paradigm.42

Page 124: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 113

If Habermas has these paradigms in mind, then he has no solution to the problem of indeterminacy in application. They are far too abstract to provide guidance in concrete cases.43 Further, as Habermas acknowledges, these paradigms presently compete with one another, and so even if any one of them provided clear guidance in a particular question, the ques-tion of paradigm selection would remain.44 Habermas’s usual trio of para-digms, then, are more indeterminate in application than the legal norms they purportedly clarify.

As Habermas acknowledges in another context, the complexity of ju-dicial decision making may be reduced with less abstract “paradigms.” In discussing Cass Sunstein’s proposed seven “canons” for interpreting regu-latory statutes, Habermas first remarks that the proposal is an “exemplary contribution to the paradigm discussion,” largely because the canons co-here with the discourse theory’s “radical-democratic meaning of the sys-tem of rights.”45 But while Habermas agrees that “background norms” are necessary for judicial interpretation (at least in cases of ambiguity), and while he approves of Sunstein’s proposal on the merits, he draws back from endorsing fully this kind of solution to the problem of indeterminacy. These canons at least verge on “a politically inspired ‘creation of law,’ ” and in that respect they offend the requirement that judicial activity be limited to discourses of application, not justification.46 Further, canons of construction, and interpretive norms more generally, tend to be the prop-erty of legal experts, and so they may become ideological and resistant to change.47 Habermas should add that typically they are contested, both in the abstract and in their application to particular cases. Because they are contested, professionalized rules, Habermas could add further, interpre-tive canons may not materially assist in producing legal certainty: They do not guarantee substantive consistency with past cases, nor do they provide much guidance for law-conforming primary conduct.48

Ultimately, Habermas addresses the indeterminacy problem through a “theory of legal discourse” that, as one by now would expect, gives pride of place to procedure. He begins this theory by renewing his objections to Dworkin’s “Hercules” device. The theory is “monological,” Habermas observes (following Frank Michelman), meaning that Hercules develops his interpretations not in discourse with others—whether attorneys in the case, his fellow judges, or both—but through his own solitary cognitive ef-forts. Monological is a term of opprobrium in a discourse theory that relies on “dialogue” (or discursive engagement) in the search for “appropriate” applications of legal norms. And so rather than “anchor the ideal demands

Page 125: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 114

on legal theory in . . . the ideal personality of a judge who is distinguished by her virtue and her privileged access to the truth,” Habermas suggests, better to have recourse to “the political ideal of an ‘open society of inter-preters of the constitution.’ ”49

This move, however, has little to do with promoting legal certainty or reducing indeterminacy in the law’s application. If the law, as applied, were what an “open society of interpreters” decided after some discursive pro-cedure, then the distinction between adjudication and legislation in fact would be leveled out. Habermas will put the idea of the “open society” to other uses—and I will come back to them—but his invocation of that idea in addressing the indeterminacy problem is unhelpful.50

Besides, what Habermas addresses under the heading of “legal proce-dures” involves, for the most part, something other than democratic influ-ence on legal outcomes. His aim is to show how legal procedures, especially litigation procedures, incorporate—more or less—the discourse principle.

The “more or less” qualification is important. As with legislative pro-cedures, judicial procedures impose time and relevance constraints. Pre-trial procedures, and rulings during trial, limit the issues that may be raised and the time that may be devoted to them. The parties, Habermas acknowledges, pursue interests strategically—that is, their contribution to courtroom discourse is not disinterested pursuit of the right answer but advocacy. The burden of proof asymmetrically distributes discursive roles. Habermas sees the role of the judge as compensation for these di-vergences from the discourse model. “The legal discourse of the court,” Habermas writes, “is played out in a procedural-legal vacuum, so that reaching a judgment is left up to the judge’s professional ability.” In the German system, Habermas points out, the judge is required to set out the reasons for decision. In Anglo-American trials, however, jury decisions may be simply answers as to ultimate issues, with no explanation and no real checks to see whether the conclusions are discursively warranted. And as to factual matters, as Habermas notes, appellate review is sharply lim-ited.51 The same is true of most ordinary trial rulings on (for example) the admission of evidence. Moreover, voting procedures in multimember decision-making bodies, whether judge or jury, may further deviate from the discourse model. This is less true in jury cases, perhaps, to the extent that the law requires unanimity or at least a strong supermajority. In cases with multimember judicial panels, however, a simple majority will suffice. As with rules establishing legislative majority rule, “consensus” among de-

Page 126: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 115

cision makers is a less stringent requirement than Habermas’s statement of the discourse principle first would suggest.

To this list of limits that legal procedure imposes on the discourse principle, one should consider also the overwhelming percentage of cases that are settled or (in criminal cases) plea-bargained. In such cases, we see bargaining rather than something that meets the general requirements of discourse. True, as I mentioned above, Habermas’s account of the con-stitutional state’s principles leaves room for bargaining and compromise. But it requires that the conditions of bargaining be fair, with power more or less symmetrically distributed. Do the conditions of legal bargaining meet this requirement? Certainly there is an imbalance of power in most criminal cases between prosecution and defense, and the same is true in many civil cases. The requirement of appointed counsel in criminal cases is partial compensation for the imbalance of power, but, given the realities of at least many American systems of criminal justice, doubtless it is not full compensation.

One accomplishment of legal procedure is, as Habermas claims, the structuring of a space in which arguments can be exchanged and relevant information brought forward. The requirement of judicial impartiality, and such requirements as there may be for reasoned explanation of judg-ments, compensate in part for divergences from the discourse principle’s usual requirements. But the differences between actual judicial procedures and the idealized requirements of discourse are as important as the simi-larities. Here, as with similar restrictions on discourse in legislative mat-ters, Habermas sensibly realizes that the discourse principle, taken full-strength, would be unworkable. The question remains, however, whether a discourse theory can make those concessions without systematically re-vising the original statement of the discourse principle.

Habermas sees his recourse to procedure as a reformulation of Dwor-kin’s theory of judicial interpretation. Rather than place “idealizing de-mands” on the judge, with the rhetorical device of Hercules as superhuman intellect, Habermas locates those demands in “the necessary pragmatic presuppositions of legal discourse.”52 But just as Dworkin concedes that ordinary judges do not match but can only emulate Hercules, so the pro-cedures actually applied in adjudication can only partially realize the de-mands of the full-strength discourse principle.

There is a further difference. More is not always better when it comes to realization of the discourse principle. Adjudicative procedures necessarily,

Page 127: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 116

and wisely, stop far short of fully institutionalizing ideal discourse require-ments. Competing with the demands of the discourse principle (“validity” or “legitimacy”) are the pragmatic requirements of decision making (“fac-ticity”). Habermas is right that these are in tension. But these pragmatic requirements are not just a moment of “facticity” that limits the discourse principle. They are conditions without which no attempt to institutional-ize discourse even could be made.

One further aspect of Habermas’s general theory of adjudication re-mains to be discussed: the status of common-law decision making. A significant part of Dworkin’s account of “constructive interpretation” in Law’s Empire is devoted to common-law adjudication,53 and Habermas takes Dworkin’s idea of constructive interpretation as inspiration. But throughout the course of Between Facts and Norms, Habermas rarely men-tions the topic of common-law decision and never considers it systemati-cally.54 One reason, likely, is Habermas’s greater familiarity with the civil-law tradition. Still, Habermas has had significant contact with American legal scholars over the years, and his account of constitutional adjudication refers frequently to American constitutional practice and theory. Further, the common-law tradition is hardly unknown to German sociology of law. Max Weber discussed it,55 and Niklas Luhmann, Habermas’s long-time theoretical rival, begins his autopoietic study of law by noting that he learned much from considering common-law systems.56

Habermas’s account of law in fact invites consideration of common-law adjudication. As noted in Chapter Two, the core principle of Haber-mas’s theory of the constitutional state is that administrative power must be bound to the communicative power that originates in discussion among the citizenry and “circulates” through legislative bodies. Habermas rec-ognizes that courts wield administrative power.57 In cases of statutory or constitutional interpretation—Habermas’s paradigm cases of judicial interpretation—the connection to the citizenry’s communicative activ-ity and its legislative product is apparent. Not so, however, in the case of common-law decision making, where law is made by judges (though sub-ject to legislative correction). While some state-court judges in the United States are elected (federal judges are not), the process by which they reach decisions and make new law does not feature significant popular partici-pation. In highly visible cases, interested groups may be allowed to file friend-of-the-court or amicus curiae briefs, but adjudication typically de-pends exclusively or almost exclusively on presentation by the litigating parties. Their interests may not be widely shared, and certainly they are

Page 128: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 117

shaped by the case’s litigation posture. Adjudication does not offer oppor-tunities for public input and participation that are remotely comparable to legislative hearings, town-hall meetings, petition drives, and the like. The administrative power that issues from lawmaking common-law court decisions, then, has at best an uncertain relationship to the communicative power of the citizenry.

The problem of squaring common-law adjudication with democratic theory is of course not unique to Habermas. But some of the usual escapes available to other thinkers are not open to Habermas. It is not enough, on his principles, to argue that the people and the legislature tacitly have approved common-law decision making, retaining and occasionally exer-cising the power to override such judicial decisions. Further, even if a ju-risdiction had a statute that generally bestowed this power on courts, the delegation of lawmaking power to courts still would be problematic for Habermas. Despite Habermas’s references to an “open society” of inter-preters, and despite his statements that a critical public needs to develop to evaluate court decisions,58 the fact remains that common-law courts have few if any of the procedures that ensure public participation in legislative decision making. It does not seem to me enough, in other words, for the people and their legislative representatives to tolerate common-law deci-sion making, or even to authorize it once and for all. Habermas’s theory of lawmaking requires popular participation in the genesis of law, not just tacit authorization or after-the-fact criticism.59

Nor can Habermas escape the problem by noting that, in each case, judges do not make law afresh but only apply and develop the work of their judicial predecessors. The first difficulty with this reply is that, as I argue in the following pages, in discussing Habermas’s theory of con-stitutional adjudication, the distinction between justification and applica-tion is elusive. Moreover, if we were to acknowledge that common-law courts engage in justification discourses as well as application discourses, or that application discourses may include some elements of norm justifi-cation, the problem remains that judicial proceedings don’t offer the kind of opportunities for public participation available in the legislative process. Further, if we were to try to argue that common-law courts only apply precedents reached by their judicial predecessors, the problem is that at an earlier point in this chain of common-law decisions, courts have en-gaged in lawmaking. And here, too, the problem is that the citizenry’s communicative power has (and has had) little if anything to do with that

Page 129: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 118

lawmaking. The “web”60 of law that common-law courts make and apply is relatively unconnected to citizens’ communicative power.

Victor Peterson tries to defend Habermas by noting that his theory of separation-of-powers norms is based on a distinction among kinds of discourse and that it rejects the “classical” sharp separations among law-making, law-applying, and law-implementing operations of government.61 Habermas, at the end of his separation-of-powers discussion, certainly does criticize the classical “liberal” conception:

The classical scheme for separate branches of government becomes less ten-able the more laws lose the form of conditional programs [akin to “rules,” as opposed to “standards”] and assume instead the shape of goal-oriented programs. As a rule, these “materialized” laws, too, appear as general norms formulated without proper nouns and directed to an indeterminate number of addressees. However, they contain general clauses and vague statutory lan-guage, or set concrete policies (analogous to special legislation) that leave the administration considerable room for discretion.62

Habermas sees these developments in both the United States and Ger-many and in “comparable countries” as well. They require, he maintains, “new structures” if the legitimacy of administrative action is to be main-tained, such as “corresponding forms of participation or . . . quasi-judicial and parliamentary procedures, procedures for compromise formation, and the like.”63 The implications of these developments directly concern the executive rather than the judiciary. But in the final chapter of Between Facts and Norms, Habermas argues that in contemporary societies even the discourse-theoretical understanding of separated powers must be relativ-ized. This relativization affects the judiciary as well as the executive:

To the extent that legal programs are in need of further specification by the courts—because decisions in the gray area between legislation and adjudica-tion tend to devolve on the judiciary, all provisos notwithstanding—juristic discourses of application must be visibly supplemented by elements taken from discourses of justification.64

And here Habermas recognizes the need for new forms of legitimation:

Naturally these elements of a quasi-legislative opinion- and will-formation require another kind of legitimation than does adjudication proper. The ad-ditional burden of legitimation could be partly satisfied by additional obliga-tions for courts to justify opinions before an enlarged critical forum specific to the judiciary. This requires the institutionalization of a legal public sphere that goes beyond the existing culture of experts and is sufficiently sensitive to make important court decisions the focus of public controversy.65

Page 130: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 119

This development would seem democratically desirable for instances in which courts must, with some sort of necessity, take on new lawmaking or quasi-lawmaking functions. But does the whole system of common-law adjudication fit this description? Would it not be possible for norms pres-ently developed by common-law courts instead to be the subject of legisla-tion rather than judicial lawmaking? Habermas is not in these passages arguing that the common-law system of adjudication, as practiced in, for example, the United States, fits the model of separated powers he has de-fended. Nor could he, it would seem, if there is indeed a democratically preferable alternative.66

One option for Habermas might be to argue, straightforwardly, that common-law decision making is simply illegitimate. Courts inevitably fill gaps, clarify ambiguity, and correct vaguenesses in statutes and constitu-tions, the argument might go, but they may not take the lead in creat-ing legal norms. This would be a straightforward application of Haber-mas’s distinction between justification and application, together with his separation-of-powers contention that the courts may do only the latter and not the former.

The problem, however, is that Habermas is purporting to “recon-struct” the “normative self-understanding” of modern legal orders. Some of those legal orders take common-law decision making to be basic. Treat-ing this as a “mistake”—an option in Dworkin’s theory of constructive interpretation on which Habermas remarks67—might seem impermissible for a reconstructive rather than purely normative theory. Is the practice of common-law decision making simply too basic to Anglo-American ju-risprudence for Habermas to treat it as needlessly undemocratic and thus a misapplication of the constitutional state’s recognized principles?68 Or could he occupy something of a middle ground—recognizing its entrench-ment yet still criticizing it as a deviation from democratic principles?

Common-law adjudication, in short, is a topic Habermas needs to ad-dress more directly. It seems inconsistent with his theory of adjudication and the idea of democratic power, yet difficult simply to dismiss within a reconstructive theory.

3.2 constit u tiona l a djudication

Habermas’s theory of constitutional adjudication rests heavily on the dis-tinction between discourses of justification and discourses of application.

Page 131: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 120

The critical side of his account is directed toward the “value jurisprudence” he discerns in German constitutional practice and the paternalism he sees in some constitutional theories (especially those of the “civic republican” variety). The positive side of his discussion is to develop a “proceduralist” account of constitutional courts’ legitimate role, which he develops through his critique of “liberal” and “republican” models.

3.2.1 Value Jurisprudence in Constitutional Practice

Habermas makes clear that the separation of powers does not, in his view, necessarily preclude constitutional review of legislation or settling of intragovernmental disputes.69 Nor, he says, does he take the “liberal” model of constitutional-court adjudication to be incontestably binding—where by “the liberal model” he means the idea that the only enforceable individual constitutional rights are “negative” rights against the state.70

This latter position follows from Habermas’s account of the “system of rights.” He introduces his five categories of basic rights prior to consider-ing the principles of the constitutional state, taking these categories to be necessary conditions for any legal community’s attempt to constitute itself through legitimate law. Nothing in Habermas’s formulation implies that his categories of basic rights, when “saturated” and enacted as binding le-gal norms, apply only as against the state. The fourth and fifth categories, particularly—involving rights to participation in democratic lawmaking and (relatively justified) rights to “social and ecological” security—clearly envision “positive” rights. Further, the abstractness with which Habermas specifies his categories of basic rights means, as he says, that there are many different ways in which they might legitimately be implemented. The “lib-eral” model of the constitution is one possibility, but it is not uniquely legitimate.71

Habermas argues, further, that the social conditions that made the liberal model attractive have eroded. The assumptions about “economic society” that underlie the liberal model, Habermas states, “no longer hold for developed, postindustrial societies in the West.” The first category of rights—taking, from Kant, the idea that law must ensure “the compatibil-ity of each one’s liberty with an equal liberty for all”—shrinks in the liberal model to a picture of negative rights against the state. And so, “measured against Kant’s principle of law, it is only the shift to the social-welfare para-digm that again brings out the objective legal contents of individual liber-ties that have always already been implicit in the system of rights.”72

Page 132: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 121

The question, though, is how a constitutional court can legitimately enforce the system of rights—or, more properly put, enforce the version of that system that has been implemented through positive law. We know, from Habermas’s conception of the separation of powers, that the court must apply constitutional provisions rather than create law. Habermas ar-gues, however, that the German constitutional court has tended toward the latter and thereby has overstepped its legitimate authority.

The catchphrase Habermas uses to designate the problem is “value ju-risprudence.” By that term (which he borrows from critics of the German constitutional court),73 Habermas means the idea that the constitution is “not so much . . . a system of rules structured by principles, but . . . a ‘concrete order of values.’ ” On this view, principles express values, and where principles compete, the problem of application should be resolved by weighing and balancing the underlying values. This is a “conceptual” error, according to Habermas. He catalogues various differences between values and principles. Values are “teleological,” reflect “intersubjectively shared preferences,” and are only “relatively binding,” while principles are “deontological” and “absolutely binding.” Values “recommend,” while principles “command.” These conceptual differences notwithstand-ing, Habermas has to tread lightly here. He has, after all, allowed that through pragmatic and ethical-political discourses, values and preferences legitimately may be incorporated into legislation. So too might they be incorporated into constitutional provisions. Still, according to Habermas, “No doubt values or teleological contents also find their way into law, but law defined through a system of rights domesticates, as it were, the policy goals and value orientations of the legislator through the strict priority of normative points of view.”74

One basis for Habermas’s critique is thus a fundamental distinction between justification and application discourses. But the distinction be-tween justification and application is less sharp and more malleable than he allows. This problem is particularly difficult with respect to the most general constitutional norms, such as “due process” or “equal protection,” and particularly difficult also in cases of first impression. Suppose, for ex-ample, that a court is deciding, as a matter of first impression, whether due process requires a government agency to grant a hearing before issuing a particular kind of adverse decision. Certainly one can say that the court must apply the due process clause rather than simply weigh and balance values or interests or equities. But in this case, it is unclear what it means to “apply the law.” One way to accomplish this task—and a standard way

Page 133: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 122

for the U.S. Supreme Court—is for the court to fashion a subordinate rule or standard that not only will decide the present case but will govern a relevant category of cases in the future. The court will need to provide justifications for its choice of an auxiliary rule or standard. Its justification will be convincing as legal argument only if it marshals evidence of text, history, structure, or purpose that demonstrably connects to the more gen-eral norm or principle the court is interpreting.

A good example of this interplay between application and justification is the Court’s decision in Kyllo v. United States.75 The question in that case was whether warrantless use of a “thermal-imaging device” to detect un-usual heat patterns emanating from a residence—probative of the resident’s use of high-intensity lamps to cultivate marijuana—violated the Fourth Amendment. In an opinion written by Justice Scalia,76 the Court began its analysis by quoting the relevant portion of the Fourth Amendment’s text: “The right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers, and effects, against unreasonable searches and seizures shall not be violated.” By itself, of course, the language does not obviously require a decision either way. The Court proceeded to justify its decision—that the police activity was unconstitutional—by relying on subordinate or auxiliary rules that are not stated explicitly in the constitutional text. The first, found in the Court’s prior cases, was that “with few exceptions,” a “warrantless search of a home” is unreasonable and hence unconstitutional. The Court explained that prior decisions had treated privacy interests in the home as “ ‘at the very core’ of the Fourth Amendment.”77

That left open, however, the question whether what had occurred in this case was a “search” or, instead, simply observation constitutionally indistinguishable from the instances of warrantless visual surveillance that had been permitted in prior cases. The Court’s analysis considers four pos-sible auxiliary rules, none explicit in constitutional text, that might de-termine whether a search had occurred. The first—common-law trespass doctrine—had been used “well into the 20th century,” the Court noted, but recent cases had “decoupled” the Fourth Amendment meaning of “search” from traditional “trespass” notions. A second was the govern-ment’s proposed rule, endorsed by the Kyllo dissenters, that the distinction should be between observations (whether technologically aided or not) of a building’s exterior surface, on one hand, and “through-the-wall surveil-lance” on the other. The Court rejected this proposed rule as inconsistent with prior cases and as “leav[ing] the homeowner at the mercy of advanc-ing technology.” A third possible auxiliary rule, also rejected by the Court,

Page 134: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 123

would have distinguished between observation of “intimate details” or “private activities in private areas,” on one hand, and the observation of (for example) heat emissions as measured on the building’s surface. The Court explained: “In the home, our cases show, all details are intimate de-tails, because the entire area is held safe from prying government eyes.”78

Noting the significance that prior cases had given actual “physical ‘in-trusion into a constitutionally protected area,’ ” the Court selected a fourth possible auxiliary rule to define whether a “search” has occurred: “Where, as here, the Government uses a device that is not in general public use, to explore details of a home that would previously have been unknowable without physical intrusion, the surveillance is a ‘search’ and is presump-tively unreasonable without a warrant.” The Court relied not just on the idea that the Fourth Amendment gives special “sanctity” to the home, and to “details” therein, but on two further considerations. The first was the idea that the Fourth Amendment must be understood to “assure[] pres-ervation of that degree of privacy against government that existed when the Fourth Amendment was adopted.” While the Court noted cases that had applied this “criterion,” it seems to come also from a more general interpretive principle. One version of such a principle might be the follow-ing: The purpose of protecting liberties with a written constitution is to ensure that those liberties, as understood at the time the Constitution was adopted, are not eroded.79 The Court’s second consideration in selecting its “criterion” was the need to provide advance guidance to law enforce-ment officials as to which techniques are permitted and which are forbid-den (at least without a warrant).80

Kyllo, in other words, illustrates how applying a constitutional standard such as the Fourth Amendment may require constructing and justifying a new rule or standard that not only decides the present case but will gov-ern future cases as well. Important for present purposes is that the rule constructed, justified, and adopted in Kyllo did not previously have the status of an authoritative norm of any kind. For that reason, the process of generating and adopting that rule seems hard to describe simply as an “application discourse” in which we choose among conflicting norms that we presuppose as valid (and hence have no need to justify). As Christopher Zurn has argued, “Justification discourses . . . inevitably refer to applica-tion discourses,” and “Application discourses . . . inevitably refer back to justification discourses.” This “general reflexive reciprocity between justi-fication and application will result in the inevitable transmutation of con-stitutional protection into constitutional elaboration.”81

Page 135: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 124

My point is not that decisions like Kyllo involve “discourses of justifi-cation” rather than “discourses of application.” The point, instead, is that in the application of abstract principles or other general norms, the func-tions of justification and application, as Habermas (following Klaus Gün-ther) has described them, are not entirely distinguishable. One result of the decision is a singular judgment that affects the parties to the case.82 In this respect, the Court is engaged in the application of a relatively abstract and authoritative norm. But the other result of the case is the generation of a new and more specific rule that will govern future cases as well. In this respect, justification is required. As Robert Alexy points out, we can distinguish between the functions of justification and application without positing two different kinds of discourse:

For discourses of application the question what is the correct solution in a cer-tain situation is constitutive, for discourses of justification, the question which universal norm is right. But from the fact that those two questions have to be distinguished it does not follow that there exist two essentially different kinds of discourse.83

Even if one agrees with Habermas and Günther and distinguishes be-tween two kinds of discourse, both kinds seem present in ordinary constitutional-law decisions like Kyllo.

Habermas seems to recognize, at least in one passage of Between Facts and Norms, that the distinction between justification and application dis-courses, with the judiciary limited to the latter, may not be so simple to maintain. Writing in terms not limited to constitutional adjudication, Habermas acknowledges:

To the extent that legal programs are in need of further specification by the courts—because decisions in the gray area between legislation and adjudica-tion tend to devolve on the judiciary, all provisos notwithstanding—juristic discourses of application must be visibly supplemented by elements taken from discourses of justification.84

This point, however, seems to be more generally significant than Haber-mas usually allows. On this one point (though not more generally in mat-ters of constitutional theory), Habermas might have followed Dworkin, from whom he borrows the idea of “constructive interpretation.”85 “Law as integrity,” Dworkin writes, “rejects as unhelpful the ancient question whether judges find or invent law; we understand legal reasoning, it sug-gests, only by seeing the sense in which they do both and neither.”86 The

Page 136: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 125

same may be said of the closely parallel distinction between applying and justifying legal norms.87

To be sure, Habermas is right that—as he praises Dworkin for recognizing—courts are not in the same position as legislatures.88 This of course is the real purpose in “binding” courts, constitutional or otherwise, “to existing law”89 and confining them to “discourses of application.” Habermas’s main argument is that legal principles may not be treated as if they were mere values and straightforwardly balanced—as if the court were a legislative body resolving conflicts among the various values and preferences in a pluralistic society. This distinction between values and principles is the other basis, besides the justification/application distinc-tion, for Habermas’s critique of the German constitutional court.

One way to understand what Habermas is criticizing is through the work of Robert Alexy. In A Theory of Constitutional Rights (2002) (origi-nally published in 1986), Alexy undertakes a “rehabilitation of the much-despised theory of values” announced in the German court’s Lüth decision of 195890—the theory to which Habermas objects. The core of Alexy’s reha-bilitation is a theory of principles.

Alexy sees the distinction between rule and principle as “the basis for a theory of constitutional justification.” Rules are “always either fulfilled or not,” and their conflict is “played out at the level of validity.” By that Alexy means that, if rules conflict, then either one must be invalidated or one must be amended (perhaps with an exception clause). Principles, by con-trast, are “optimization requirements”; that is, they “require that some-thing be realized to the greatest extent possible given the legal and factual possibilities.”91 Their conflict is not one of validity but of “weight.”92 The metaphor Alexy uses for how one resolves a conflict between or among principles is “balancing.”93 Alexy refers sometimes to balancing interests and sometimes to balancing the principles themselves. His more formal statements refer to establishing a “relation of precedence” among the rea-sons that the principles represent.94 The German constitutional court, by contrast, has spoken of weighing values.

This last idiom, as mentioned, is what provokes Habermas’s criticism. But Alexy sees the Lüth court’s statement about the Basic Law as an “objec-tive order of values,” centered on human dignity,95 as capable of translation into the language of principles. The court itself has referred alternatively to “the principles . . . that are expressed by the constitutional rights.”96 The move from values to principles is possible, according to Alexy, because

Page 137: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 126

the two “have basically the same conceptual structure,”97 as each refers to “gradated satisfaction.”98 Yet—and here Alexy’s analysis coincides with Habermas’s—they occupy different “fields.”99 As optimization require-ments, principles “belong to the deontological realm.”100 Values, by contrast, concern “the Good” and thus “are located on the axiological plane.”101 Still, Alexy notes, neither the possibility of translating value-talk into principle-talk nor the deontological/axiological distinction provides an easy escape from objections to the German court’s value jurisprudence. “Objections raised to a theory of constitutional rights as values apply equally to a theory of constitutional rights as principles.”102 And so those objections must be answered.

The objection that most concerns Alexy is that balancing defies “ratio-nal control,” leading to “judicial subjectivism and decisionism.” His answer is that he presents a “justification model.” Balancing, he has said, produces a conditional relation of precedence among reasons—“conditional,” that is, with respect to the relevant circumstances of the case. To justify this rela-tion of precedence, he says, “one can use all the arguments available in con-stitutional argumentation generally.”103 Balancing, then, is no more or less “subjective” or “decisionist” than legal reasoning more generally.

And balancing, according to Alexy, is inescapable in a system of consti-tutional rights that includes principles. That is because no principle, he ar-gues, can be absolute. For this proposition Alexy offers a “proof.” Suppose, he says, that a principle is absolute. Then it must protect either a collective interest or an individual right. But if an absolute principle were to protect a collective interest, then there would be no individual rights “for as far as the absolute principle reaches.” The absoluteness of the principle, then, would be inconsistent with the idea of individual rights. On the other hand, if the absolute principle were to protect an individual right, then all conflicting similar rights would have to “give way, which is inconsistent” (inconsistent because similar rights would be treated differently). Alexy’s conclusion: “Absolute principles are either incompatible with constitutional rights or can only apply where the rights they create benefit just one person.”104

The argument is unconvincing to the extent that one individual consti-tutional right might be thought to be incommensurable with and superior to all others—and also one whose particular instantiations are not in com-petition with one another. Alexy addresses that possibility. The usual candi-date for such a right in German law, he suggests, is the Basic Law’s principle of “inviolable” human dignity.105 While the constitutional language may suggest an absolute principle, according to Alexy the court’s cases establish

Page 138: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 127

only that there is a “core area of private autonomy,” protected by a rule, with a periphery where intrusions on private autonomy are permitted when the reasons are deemed sufficiently important.106 Here, too, it is a matter of considering the precedence among reasons in accommodating the right to human dignity with collective interests or (perhaps) other competing rights.

For his part, perhaps due to the relative emptiness of his notion of “ap-propriateness” in application discourses, Habermas seems to allow courts to do what seems practically indistinguishable from Alexy’s proposal. He describes legal norms as a “package” of reasons107 that constitutional courts may unpackage for purposes of applying the norm, so long as they do not assume the position of a legislator:

The legitimating reasons available from the constitution are given to the con-stitutional court in advance from the perspective of the application of law. . . . The court reopens the package of reasons that legitimated legislative decisions so that it might mobilize them for a coherent ruling on the individual case in agreement with existing principles of law; it may not, however, use these rea-sons in an implicitly legislative manner that directly elaborates and develops the system of rights.108

Perhaps Habermas intends a distinction between “reasons,” on one hand, and “purposes,” “goals,” or “values,” on the other. But it is difficult to see what meaning general principles have if one bars consideration of the pur-poses, goals, or values these principles could be said to advance (or, on another view, were thought by their authors, or contemporaries of their au-thors, to advance). Further, the idea that a “firewall” separates norms and values perhaps makes sense for “moral” norms, at least as Habermas con-ceives of them. Those norms are to be justified not through their coherence with a particular collective form of life but through a strict universalization test that takes humanity as such to be the “reference system.” Legal norms, by contrast, are justified not just in universalistic moral discourse, Haber-mas has said, but also through pragmatic and ethical-political discourse. As Habermas has explained, interests, values, and collective goals all are rel-evant, even dominant, in pragmatic and ethical-political discourse. Given this conception of legal norms’ “validity basis,” then, it seems peculiar to exclude, in an “application discourse” that interprets a legal norm, the very considerations that were relevant to its justification.109

Apart from his critique of value jurisprudence, Habermas recognizes this point. As I have noted, Habermas argues at least intermittently that courts must work with, and interpret, the “package” of reasons relevant to a legal norm’s justification. He also has acknowledged the point in outlining

Page 139: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 128

his distinction between legal and moral norms. There Habermas states that legal “discourses of justification and application” cannot focus only on the “justice” considerations of moral discourse, but “also have to be open to a pragmatic and ethical-political use of practical reason.”110 Habermas is right that legal principles are not themselves values, goods, or collective goals. But surely the values, goods, and collective goals relevant to a principle’s justifi-cation are relevant in concretizing it for application to a particular case or in resolving a competition among competing principles.111

Habermas presents his critique of value jurisprudence as a critique of the German constitutional court’s “methodological” error.112 In my view, nothing much separates Habermas from Alexy in method, and because Alexy offers his approach as an interpretation of German constitutional court practice, nothing much evidently separates Habermas’s proposed method from the German court’s method. Habermas’s critique of the Ger-man court seems to me properly substantive, not methodological. His ar-gument, I believe, should be not that the German court has committed a category mistake by confusing principles and values but that it has “un-packaged” the principles improperly in particular cases—following its own normative purposes and not those marked by the constitution. That cri-tique would require Habermas both to offer a substantive theory of what the German constitution means and to document the ways in which the German court, in its particular cases, has departed from that meaning. But Habermas does not follow that path in Between Facts and Norms.

A substantive critique—however undeveloped in Habermas’s exposition—would be consistent with Habermas’s general aims. The ac-count of judicial methodology is only part of Habermas’s more general separation-of-powers theory. The basic principle of the constitutional state, Habermas has said, is that the connection between communicative and administrative power must be maintained—or, more specifically, that the priority of democratic legislation, understood to include constitu-tional provisions along with ordinary statutes, must be preserved. From that point of view, judicial rulings that decisively change the meaning of statutes or constitutional provisions amount, in Habermas’s terminology, to the triumph of judges’ administrative power over democratically legiti-mate expressions of citizens’ communicative power. That concern is what animates Habermas’s claim that courts must be bound “to existing law” and his statement that a court may not “make whatever use it likes” of the reasons that are “packaged in, and linked to, statutes.”113

Page 140: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 129

3.2.2 The Proceduralist Model of Constitutional Courts’ Legitimate Role

Habermas develops his “proceduralist” account of constitutional courts’ role in contrast to what he characterizes as “liberal” and “republi-can” models of law and politics. His idea is to appropriate from each what is useful. This strategy is unsurprising: It relies on contrasts developed throughout his discourse theory of law. His account of the two “ideas that can justify modern law” connects “human rights” with liberalism and “popular sovereignty” with republicanism.114 In his system of rights, the categories of rights devoted to private autonomy respond to the “liberal” side of the liberal/republican divide, and the categories of rights that se-cure public or civic autonomy respond to the “republican” side. Critical as Habermas is of republican theories—and, I will argue, not always fairly critical—his sympathies lie closer to that side than to the liberal model.

The sketches that Between Facts and Norms offers of both the liberal and republican models are, as Habermas says, “stylized.”115 In the liberal model, he has said, basic individual rights obtain only as negative rights against state interference.116 These rights create a sphere in which individu-als may pursue private ends.117 The political process involves a competitive struggle for power among strategically acting groups,118 with citizen par-ticipation through voting necessary primarily as a check on government and primarily for the sake of protecting citizens’ private ends.119 The mea-sure of legitimacy is quantitative—votes, understood as the aggregation of preferences.120 In terms of Habermas’s system of rights, the emphasis is much more strongly on private autonomy, with citizens’ public autonomy figuring primarily as an instrument for securing private autonomy.

Given this characterization of the “liberal” model, we see immediately that Habermas cannot accept it as his own. Habermas designed his “system of rights” so that private and public autonomy would be “co-original” and would receive equal weight. If the “liberal” view is that public autonomy has value only as an instrument for securing private autonomy, then Habermas cannot accept that view. Further, Habermas’s conception of citizen participa-tion involves considerably more than just voting. He emphasizes the consti-tutive role of citizens’ discussion in the political public sphere—constitutive for the generation of legitimate law but constitutive also for personal and group identities. Within formal governmental institutions, Habermas has emphasized the importance of discourse, not just bargaining and compro-mise. The separation-of-powers theory Habermas has urged is designed not

Page 141: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 130

just to protect private interests from government encroachment but also to bind administrative power to citizens’ communicative power.

Partly for these conceptual reasons, but partly because of changing so-cial conditions, Habermas argues against a “liberal” conception of basic rights and their enforcement. The “classical scheme for the separation and interdependence of government branches,” he says, “no longer corresponds to” the constitutional court’s mission of “keep[ing] watch over just that system of rights that makes citizens’ private and public autonomy equally possible.” The most pertinent change in social circumstances that Haber-mas describes is a tendency toward greater concentration of power. And so while “liberal” models see the danger to private autonomy exclusively (or at least primarily) in government intervention, for Habermas the danger to private autonomy comes as much from “positions of economic and so-cial power” as from the state. From his perspective, the “liberal” prescrip-tion of formally equal freedoms to vote and otherwise participate cannot be sufficient. The effective exercise of “communicative and participatory rights”—public autonomy—is threatened, according to Habermas, by un-equal social power.121 Thus the task of “keep[ing] watch over” the system of rights cannot mean that the constitutional court should be attentive only to threats from the state and the infringement of formally equal liber-ties. In ways we will soon consider, Habermas argues that the constitu-tional court must be attentive to the danger that concentrated social and economic power poses to both private and public autonomy.

Here Habermas’s thinking reflects the German more than the Ameri-can constitutional tradition. For the most part, the American system protects basic rights, such as the right of equality or the freedom of ex-pression, only against state action, not private action. The German con-stitutional court, however, has held that constitutional rights norms have a “radiating effect” that “affect[s] the relations between citizens” to pro-duce a “third party or horizontal effect.”122 Habermas recognizes similar effects specifically in the area of social-welfare rights.123 As Robert Alexy explains, the idea of horizontal effect may mean different things. On one interpretation favored by the German court, it amounts to an interpretive mandate that private-law norms must be interpreted in light of constitu-tional rights (“indirect effect”).124 Alexy discerns also two other senses of “horizontal effect.” According to the idea of “direct effect,” “certain rights and no-rights, liberties and no-liberties, powers and disabilities” exist be-tween citizens “on the basis of constitutional reasons, which would not exist in the absence of these reasons.”125 And according to the idea of “in-

Page 142: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 131

direct effect,” the state must have regard for constitutional rights norms, as “objective principles,” “both in legislating in the private law field and also in private law adjudication.” Each of these three “models,” Alexy argues, “correctly highlights some aspects of . . . horizontal effect cases.”126 With this possibility that constitutional rights may affect private-law norms—with respect to both judicial interpretation and legislative duties in enactment—the German system is more attuned than the American sys-tem to Habermas’s concern for concentrated social and economic power’s constitutional dangers.

Habermas acknowledges similarities between the modern republi-can model—particularly Michelman’s—and his own conception. As does Habermas, modern republicans emphasize the “procedural conditions” of modern democracy that include deliberation within formal political insti-tutions. But more characteristically, and in common with Habermas, neo-republicans see democracy’s basic operations outside those formal institu-tions. They emphasize, Habermas notes, the importance of citizens’ public autonomy, with communication and participation rights “preeminent[]” among civil rights.127 The link between the democratic process and law’s legitimacy depends on robust, potentially preference-changing, political discussion among citizens in the political public sphere. And, with Haber-mas, Michelman sees the social basis of this public sphere in the voluntary associations of civil society.128 These civil-social organizations occupy the “margins” of the officially organized political system. By virtue of that location, they are ideally situated to produce novel “initiatives, issues and contributions, problems and proposals.”129 A prime role for constitutional courts, according to the neorepublican essays of Michelman and Sunstein, is the promotion of deliberative democracy, conceived as operating inside and outside formal political institutions.130

These similarities between Habermas’s theory of democracy and neo-republican theory—especially Michelman’s version—are striking. In dis-tancing his “proceduralist” conception from the republican view, however, Habermas works up and in my view exaggerates two differences. First, Habermas asserts repeatedly in Between Facts and Norms, neorepublican theory à la Michelman assumes a deep “ethical” consensus that “does not sit well with the conditions of cultural and societal pluralism that distin-guish modern societies.”131 For that reason, Habermas argues, neorepub-lican theory operates with an idealized and even premodern conception of politics.132 According to Habermas, neorepublican theory therefore tends to see actual politics as “fallen” and defective. And therefore, Habermas

Page 143: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 132

claims, republicans resort, necessarily, either to an activist constitutional court as substitute for the absent people or to a romanticized but ritualized “symbolic politics.”133

The first part of this diagnosis depends on largely overlooking the “neo” in “neorepublican.” Habermas places great emphasis on republican-ism, unmodified, as a theory of ethically unified communities, with full exercise of citizenship to be expected from only the most virtuous members of those communities.134 He reads Michelman to continue this presupposi-tion of strong ethical consensus.135 This reading is mistaken, in my view. Michelman explicitly poses, as a central problem for any neorepublican the-ory, the tension between, on one hand, traditional republicanism’s assump-tions of deep consensus among members of an ethically integrated elite of a small community and, on the other hand, the modern American reali-ties of ethical and cultural plurality.136 He inquires whether, starting from modern conditions, his revised version of republicanism could account for how an ethically plural and interest-divided public of citizens might demo-cratically produce law, such that each could accept that law.137 One might not like Michelman’s answer to that question. Or one might, as I do, take the question concerning universal acceptance to be the wrong one. But Habermas is not in any position to make that latter objection. The question is exactly the one that he asks. And Habermas’s accusation that Michelman assumes deep ethical consensus from the outset unfairly chains Michelman to elements of the republican tradition that he is attempting to revise.138

The idea that Michelman resorts to “symbolic politics,” on the order of “bicentennial celebrations of the Declaration of Independence,”139 is particularly mistaken. In making this charge, Habermas refers specifi-cally to Michelman’s statement that a modern, large-scale, democratic po-litical community’s identity—made, by the way, not found—depends on “remembrance” of the community’s origins “in public acts of deliberate creation.”140 But what Michelman is talking about, I think, is something closely akin to Habermas’s own “reconstructive” account of how a legal community constitutes itself as a self-governing legal community, under law, with both private and public autonomy secured. Michelman’s inquiry is, to be sure, historical in a way that Habermas’s is not: He speaks of the origins of specifically American constitutionalism, not the principles of the constitutional state in general. But the idea of politics as periodic return to origins is not Michelman’s conception. After noting that the founding of the American republic was an act of “popular self-creation,” Michelman adds, with respect to the idea of self-governance: “Once, however, is hardly

Page 144: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 133

enough.” He goes on to criticize the “myth of the Founder” in “classical re-publican” thinking, in which politics is a cycle between forgetting and rec-ollecting the founder’s unique virtue.141 Democratic politics for Michelman is an ongoing and uncertain matter, with a tension between the original act of popular self-creation and subsequent developments of the constitutional project. It is hardly a matter either of ritually celebrating origins and found-ers or of returning, without mediation, to the founders’ wisdom. The no-tion of deliberative politics with which Michelman operates is, to be sure, idealized. But certainly the same is true for Habermas’s own discourse-theoretical account of the connections between citizens’ communicative power and the administrative power of the state apparatus.142

That leaves the question of the constitutional court’s legitimate author-ity. According to Habermas, Michelman, perhaps more than other neo-republicans, sees the danger of “constitutional-court paternalism.”143 But given Habermas’s interpretation of Michelman—the assumption of a deep ethical consensus and an understanding of politics only as “symbolic” politics—Habermas has to conclude that Michelman tends toward the pa-ternalism he tries to resist. That conclusion, after all, was what was sup-posed to follow from Michelman’s misunderstanding of ethical consensus and politics. Habermas’s claim was that neorepublican theory, including Michelman’s work, leaves a vacuum in the idea of deliberative democracy that requires substitution of courts for the people.

Habermas is on somewhat firmer ground with this conclusion than he was with the premises of his argument. As Habermas notes, Michelman recognizes that constitutional-court “activism” is suspect on his premises. In fact, Michelman sees also that any form of judicial review is difficult for him to justify.144 That difficulty motivates and structures his essay Law’s Republic. Michelman begins with an account of the Supreme Court’s decision in Bowers v. Hardwick, which relied on notions of deference to democratic legislation and “majority sentiments about . . . morality” to sustain application of an antisodomy criminal statute to same-sex sexual conduct.145 Classical republicanism, Michelman observes, would seem to speak in favor of the Bowers decision. And so, given Michelman’s commit-ment to opposing Bowers, he needs to find resources in neorepublican the-ory that amend the classical republican emphasis on “normative unity.”146 Even in his last paragraph of the essay, however—after he has presented his constitutional argument for a different result in Bowers—Michelman notes that “the difficulty remains of explaining how it can be right to address such a non-demonstrative argument about the impermanent meaning of

Page 145: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 134

the people’s law to any body other than the People.” Michelman’s answer to this difficulty is tentative, relying in the first instance on the idea that judges “perhaps” have some special cognitive or normative advantage:

Judges perhaps enjoy a situational advantage over the people at large in listen-ing for voices from the margins. Judges are perhaps better situated to conduct a sympathetic inquiry into how, if at all, the readings of history upon which those voices base their complaint can count as interpretations of that history—interpretations which, however re-collective or even transformative, remain true to that history’s informing commitment to the pursuit of political free-dom through jurisgenerative politics.147

As Michelman recognizes, however, this kind of answer raises serious questions for a theory that, at its core, presents popular political engage-ment as jurisgenerative and the source of legal legitimacy. “[A] judicial constitutional convention,” Michelman admits, “is not equivalent—indeed it is contrary—to actual democracy.” Michelman’s ultimate answer is “pragmatic.” “Actual democracy is not all there is to political freedom,” he says in the essay’s final sentence, “and Hardwick is before us, appealing to law’s republic.”148

This passage, together with a related passage that Habermas quotes,149 makes the best case for Michelman’s slippage into “constitutional-court pa-ternalism.” But if he is guilty of that offense, he is not driven to it for the reason Habermas thinks. The passages show that Michelman precisely does not assume a deep ethical consensus that is binding on all interpret-ers of law. Part of his idea of “political freedom,” invoked in the last lines, is freedom from a political community’s consensus, and the passage that Habermas quotes assigns judges the task of “challeng[ing] ‘the people’s’ self- enclosing tendency to assume their own moral completion as they now are.”150

Further, Michelman hesitates to rely on “actual democracy,” in the context of Bowers, not because he has a premodern notion of politics that both demands total engagement from a virtuous people and, for that rea-son, cannot be realized under modern conditions. Instead, Michelman’s concern—that “voices from the margins” will go unheeded—identifies a structural problem in majoritarian political institutions that is recognized in both American constitutional law and constitutional theory.151 Whether or not Michelman is right that the Georgia statute unconstitutionally de-nies rights of privacy and equal citizenship is an interpretive question that can be answered only by addressing the substantive merits of Michelman’s constitutional argument.152

Page 146: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 135

To be sure, Michelman’s final paragraph betrays considerable anxiety about his constitutional argument. Voices heard from the margin are not necessarily to be given authority, and majoritarian democracy is not always to be distrusted. But Michelman is not alone in trying to sort out these difficulties. He has, in fact, the company of Habermas. Consider Haber-mas’s initial characterization of legitimate judicial review:

Judicial review should refer primarily to the conditions for the democratic gen-esis of laws. More specifically, it must start by examining the communication structures of a public sphere subverted by the power of the mass media; go on to consider the actual chances that divergent and marginal voices will be heard and that formally equal rights of participation will be effectively exercised; and conclude with the equal parliamentary representation of all the currently rel-evant groups, interest positions, and value orientations. Here it must also refer to the range of issues, arguments and problems, values and interests that find their way into parliamentary deliberation and are considered in the justifica-tion of approved norms.153

This passage is surprising in a number of respects. Perhaps most sur- prising is that Habermas offers it as an endorsing interpretation of John Hart Ely’s theory of judicial review. While the main themes of Ely’s “representation-reinforcing” theory come through—“clearing the channels of political change” and “facilitating the representation of minorities”154—William Forbath is right that Ely “might be amazed” to see his theory characterized in this way.155 Conclusions about exactly what Habermas would have the Supreme Court do are difficult to draw, from this or any of Habermas’s other discussions of a constitutional court’s legitimate pow-ers.156 But the picture that emerges suggests, in Habermas’s own character-ization, a “rather bold constitutional adjudication”157 that would make not just Ely but perhaps even Michelman uncomfortable.

In developing Ely’s themes of representation reinforcement, Habermas suggests that the “power of the mass media” operates to “subvert[]” the political public sphere. Elsewhere in Between Facts and Norms he explains what he means by this charge. Concentration of editorial control in the hands of a few induces a centrist bias that does not facilitate the representa-tion of “divergent and marginal voices.” Habermas criticizes also the frag-mentation of issues and the presentation of politics as entertainment, as well as the accommodating response among party and political leaders to these very developments. While Habermas notes research suggesting that the public’s critical capacity may not be as low as often is alleged,158 he sees

Page 147: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 136

the “social power” of large media organizations as a threat to “nullify[]” the “constitutionally regulated system of power”—and thus as a threat to the legitimacy of the political system and its decisions.159 Habermas does not make clear what a constitutional court is supposed to do about these problems, and in part his criticisms are directed to media organizations themselves. But Habermas also notes that in Germany one finds the be-ginnings of “constitutional regulation” that would reduce the social power of media organizations and, presumably, diminish their agenda-setting ca-pacity. Mentioning both media self-regulation and mass-communications law, Habermas endorses the proposal that

political and social actors would be allowed to “use” the public sphere only insofar as they make convincing contributions to the solution of problems that have been perceived by the public or have been put on the public agenda with the public’s consent. In a similar vein, political parties would have to partici-pate in the opinion- and will-formation from the public’s own perspective, rather than patronizing the public and extracting mass loyalty from the public sphere for the purposes of maintaining their own power.160

This proposal, however, would seem to outfit government officials with the power of selecting among speakers and the content of speech. Even with the aim of ensuring “convincing contributions” and upgrading the level of political discourse, the constitutional problem here is obvious—especially in the American context, where government selection among speakers is re-garded as perhaps the chief evil addressed by the Constitution’s free-speech and free-press clauses.161 Certainly one can imagine a constitutional argu-ment that would support the proposals Habermas is discussing. Whether that argument connects with the body of free-expression doctrine in this country, however, is doubtful.162

Habermas, of course, does not err simply by rejecting implicitly the re-ceived wisdom of American constitutional doctrine, and Between Facts and Norms is not intended as a treatise on American constitutional law. But the tension between mass-media-dominated political discussion and delibera-tive democracy is relatively easy to identify. What would be helpful would be consideration, also, of the other side of the free-expression question. Habermas’s proposal raises obvious problems, and not just under prevailing American doctrine. His own theory suggests that civil-social organizations and the political public sphere need to be constitutionally protected and not dominated by government.163 It is hardly obvious, however, that his pro-posal would not undermine the public sphere, albeit through state adminis-trative power rather than through the social power of media organizations.

Page 148: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 137

Habermas sounds also the second theme of Ely’s “representation- reinforcing” theory. A constitutional court’s judicial review, he says, must “consider the actual chances that divergent and marginal voices will be heard and that formally equal rights of participation will be effectively exercised.”164 This kind of position follows from Habermas’s rejection of the “liberal” paradigm and its emphasis on purely formal equality. Dis-parities of social and economic power, Habermas has said, threaten full and effective participation in the democratic process, and, accordingly, these disparities threaten the legitimacy of official decision making. But Habermas, understandably in the general-theoretical work Between Facts and Norms, is short on details. How should the divergence between full and actual participation be taken into account? Presumably the court is not free to rewrite legislative norms, reasoning that they would have been different had the political process been genuinely and effectively open on equal terms. But under what circumstances may it invalidate, or refuse to enforce, legislation on those grounds? Should it, instead, remand the is-sue to the legislature?165 Given that social and economic power always is unequally distributed in some measure, how serious must the imbalance be to justify the court’s solicitude? The answers to these questions would help explain just how assertive Habermas’s constitutional court would be.

Most interesting in Habermas’s account of judicial review is his ref-erence to “equal parliamentary representation” for all “currently relevant groups, interest positions, and value orientations.”166 By “equal” he means, presumably, equal in proportion to their influence in the public sphere. But how is that influence to be measured? If, as in this country, the po-litical system operates under a “first past the post” scheme of districted elections, then voting outcomes will be biased against smaller parties,167 and even public opinion polls likely will reflect that bias. It seems that the proportional representation system must already be in place for there to be measures adequate for implementation.

Further, and more fundamental, how should the court go about ensur-ing that all currently relevant groups and positions receive parliamentary representation? Habermas doubtless is thinking here of European systems in which his ideas already are reflected in present political organization.168 Whether he could make the same recommendation in the very different con-text of American politics is doubtful. Legislation, such as the Voting Rights Act, goes some small way toward Habermas’s proposal. But it is difficult to imagine an American court, on its own, mandating proportional parlia-mentary representation for all “currently relevant groups, interest positions

Page 149: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 138

and value orientations.” The connection between this kind of representation and a laudable system of democracy is evident—though hardly indisputable. But without any firm basis in politics as it now is practiced, the power of a court to mandate this kind of change, even in the name of sound democratic procedure, seems at least doubtful. It is a long way from Reynolds v. Sims’s “one person, one vote”169 ruling to a constitutionally mandated system of proportional representation for groups, interests, and value orientations.

Two current issues in American constitutional law demonstrate the gap between what Habermas envisions for judicial review and what the U.S. Supreme Court is prepared to deliver. The first is campaign finance, and it indicates primarily substantive differences between Habermas and the Court. The second concerns “gerrymandered” electoral districts, and it il-lustrates primarily a difference with respect to the limits of legitimate judi-cial activity. My account of the gap is not intended as criticism of Haber-mas’s account. Instead, Habermas’s work can generate both criticism of American political reality and also support for reform outside of the courts.

The issue of how to finance political campaigns clearly is a central is-sue for democratic and constitutional politics, and deliberative democratic theorists tend to support equalizing political spending. Rawls, for exam-ple, sees public funding of campaigns, together with limits on private con-tributions, as essential to establishing and maintaining the “fair value” of equal political liberties.170 He supports, also, an egalitarian regulation of expenditures on campaign speech. Writing even before the Court’s 2010 decision in Citizens United v. FEC, which invalidated congressional limits on corporate campaign expenditures, Rawls observes that “what is dismay-ing is that the present Court seems to reject altogether the idea that Con-gress may try to establish the fair value of the political liberties.”171 Dwor-kin, too, argues that deliberative-democratic ideals require much stronger regulation of campaign contributions and even speech itself. “Money is the enemy not just of fairness but of real argument,”172 he maintains. Going well beyond the kind of regulation that Citizens United invalidated, Dwor-kin advocates, for example, that campaign advertisements

in the familiar form should be forbidden on all networks except subject to the following regulations: the advertisement must run for a minimum of three minutes, of which at least two minutes must consist in a candidate for office or an officer of an organization that has paid for the advertisement speaking directly to the camera.173

While Habermas seems not to have commented directly on campaign-finance issues, that might reflect the fact that German political campaigns

Page 150: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 139

are much shorter, cheaper, and heavily subsidized by public funds. Were he to attend to the American context, Habermas likely would see campaign-finance regulation to be an essential part of maintaining a democratic and egalitarian political process. Accordingly, he likely would take its support to be a central part of American judicial review.

After the Citizens United case, however, regulation of campaign fi-nance seems constitutionally blocked. In that decision, the Court invali-dated limits on corporations’ and unions’ use of general-treasury money to engage in what federal law called “electioneering communication.” By that term, Congress meant “ ‘any broadcast, cable, or satellite communica-tion’ that ‘refers to a clearly identified candidate for Federal office’ and is made within 30 days of a primary or 60 days of a general election.”174 The challenged statute itself (the 2002 Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act or “BCRA,” informally known as “McCain-Feingold”) had left open many channels for corporate electoral speech. Unlimited expenditures from the general treasury were permissible at any time other than the thirty- or sixty-day windows, and within those windows corporations still were per-mitted to spend freely on speech through their PACs, or “political action committees,” which are segregated funds whose money is raised from em-ployees or stockholders expressly for political purposes. (The amount of money in a PAC, the theory goes, reflects support for its sponsor’s political ideas, whereas the amount of money in a corporation’s general treasury reflects only the relative popularity of its goods and services.) Further, cor-porations were free to use general-treasury money at any time so long as the funded speech addressed only issues and not candidates. Finally, cor-porations’ speech in print or through the Internet was wholly unregulated. Yet the Court ruled in Citizens United that the First Amendment prohib-ited the distinction Congress had made between speech by corporations and speech by individuals and other noncorporate organizations.

The Court’s ruling may endanger the other limit Congress imposed in the BCRA. That limit was on the political parties’ ability to raise so-called soft money, that is, money raised in unlimited amounts that then could be used for political speech that was formally—although often not really—independent of political campaigns.175 In banning soft-money donations, Congress’s objective was to block what had been a way around limits on direct contributions to candidates. One effect of that regulation, however, was to shift money away from the political parties and toward (typically) more sharply ideological independent groups known as “527s” (after the provision of the Internal Revenue Code under which they organize).176

Page 151: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 140

And at the oral argument in Citizens United, the question emerged whether invalidating BCRA’s regulation of electioneering communications would, by now encouraging money to move toward corporations and unions and again away from political parties, create pressure to repeal BCRA’s ban on soft money.177 Some experts predict that the Court itself is likely to overturn the soft-money ban,178 and given the 5-4 vote on that issue the first time around—a breakdown that, like the alignment on electioneering communications, has shifted with the Court’s changing composition—the prediction seems cogent. The result of such a decision would be to leave the place of money in politics less regulated than it was before the 2002 BCRA, with the opportunity for corporations, unions, and wealthy in-dividuals to exercise outsized influence in public-sphere electoral debates.

Given Habermas’s conception of the constitutional court as guard-ian of (to borrow Rawls’s phrase) the “fair value” of the equal political liberties, American observers inspired by Habermas’s work could press criticisms of the U.S. Supreme Court’s present course. And Habermas’s emphasis on procedural approaches could support the kinds of campaign-finance regulation left open by Citizens United: requirements that cor-porate (as well as other) expenditures on electioneering communication must be disclosed and “disclaimer” requirements that those responsible for funding broadcast ads must clearly identify themselves. As the Court noted in Citizens United, these requirements increase the transparency of corporation-funded speech and “enable[] the electorate to make informed decisions and give proper weight to different speakers and messages.”179 As the Court noted further, internet publication makes the disclosed informa-tion readily accessible to ordinary persons, both voters and shareholders.

The problem, however, is that disclosure and disclaimer requirements by themselves seem insufficient to fill the gap that Citizens United created. Accordingly, a Habermasian response to the campaign-finance situation at present would be to join those who, like Harvard law professor Lawrence Lessig, are pressing for a constitutional amendment that would authorize the kinds of campaign-finance regulation just invalidated.180 Indeed, the Habermasian likely would want to go much further here in limiting the effect of unequal social power on the value of formally equal political lib-erties. The people acting through constitutional amendment would not be subject to limitations conventionally thought to bind reviewing constitu-tional courts.

A second issue that shows the gap between Habermasian constitutional ideals and current American constitutional reality—and the potential for

Page 152: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 141

Habermasian criticism—is the issue of partisan gerrymandering in draw-ing electoral districts. As the early nineteenth-century referent of the term indicates,181 gerrymandering has been part of American politics since the establishment of a party system,182 and those in office long have drawn the boundaries of electoral districts to favor themselves and their allies. But only in the past thirty or so years, once advanced computer technology be-gan to become cheaply available to process detailed, block-by-block voting-registration information, did the art of partisan gerrymandering become almost an exact science. When outfitted with the power to draw district lines, each major party tends to protect its incumbents with “safe” seats and to minimize the electoral prospects of its opponents by “cracking” (splitting the party’s stronghold with a district-dividing line) or “packing” (placing a large supermajority of the party’s supporters in a single district, thus preventing it from winning two seats rather than one).183 Since the 2000 election cycle, a parallel trend has been the “bipartisan” or “sweet-heart gerrymander,” a sort of “non-aggression pact between the two par-ties” designed to protect incumbents of each party.184 The result has been an increase in the number of safe seats with a corresponding decline in electoral competitiveness. A common hypothesis is that further results are a decrease in representatives’ accountability to the electorate and an in-crease in sharp-edged partisanship.185 While one might dispute whether sharper partisanship necessarily is a vice for a political system, a decline in accountability surely is.

Since the 1980s, the Supreme Court has considered constitutional chal-lenges to partisan gerrymanders but, so far, ultimately has denied relief. When it first considered the issue in 1986, a majority of the Court’s mem-bers recognized the possibility of a successful challenge but failed to unite on a constitutional standard.186 Eighteen years later, the Court emerged in more or less the same place: Five members of the Court believed that parti-san gerrymanders could violate the Constitution and perhaps, in some fu-ture case, be amenable to judicial relief, but a majority of the Court found no violation in the case before them, and no majority coalesced around a single constitutional standard.187 The issue of partisan gerrymandering be-came more difficult still when the Supreme Court permitted Texas’s 2006 partisan gerrymander, notwithstanding prior convention that redistricting would occur only immediately after each decennial census. And in that case, too, the Court failed to agree on a standard for evaluating the consti-tutionality of partisan gerrymanders.188

Page 153: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 142

But that this democracy-endangering practice189 evades judicial re-dress hardly exhausts the avenue for constitutional politics. The question whether partisan gerrymanders may violate the Constitution is, for the Supreme Court, only one of justiciability. Even Justice Scalia, writing for three other Justices to find the issue nonjusticiable, seemed willing to grant that “an excessive injection of politics” into redistricting “is unlawful.”190 And Scalia’s argument for nonjusticiability relied heavily on the availability of congressional rather than judicial relief. While the Constitution confers on states the responsibility for congressional districting in the first instance, it reserves to Congress the power to “check partisan manipulation of the election process by the states.”191 Legislation to that effect has been intro-duced in the House and Senate, after similar bills died in both houses dur-ing the last Congress.192

It may be unrealistic to expect Congress to correct the practice that seats its members but, as popular discontent with the practices of partisan and bipartisan gerrymandering increases, perhaps not. In any event, and besides also the possibility of federal constitutional amendment or state constitutional litigation, legislative action at the state level is both pos-sible and underway. A small but increasing number of states have taken redistricting—for both congressional and state legislative office—out of the hands of state legislatures and put it in the hands of independent and presumably neutral commissions. Other states use commissions in an ad-visory capacity or as backup in case of legislative deadlock. Other mecha-nisms, such as more or less purely computer-generated districting, have been proposed.193

While the future of this reform movement is of course uncertain, it nicely illustrates Habermas’s idea that the constitution is an ongoing project—one that should engage citizens and legislatures, not just courts. In this area, unlike others, the Supreme Court has recognized that nonju-dicial actors have a role in constitutional development.194

Two final points about Habermas and the role of constitutional courts are appropriate. First, his discussion of the “rather bold” approach courts should take when considering the democratic political process should not obscure the more deferential approach he commends in other areas. For Habermas, the constitution is a project whose elaboration involves not just the courts but the legislature and the people as well. In this re-spect his thinking converges with recent work in American constitutional theory that focuses on the “constitution outside the courts” and “popular constitutionalism.”

Page 154: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 143

Building on work by Paul Brest and Sanford Levinson,195 Mark Tush-net has analyzed the role of Congress—and, taking a comparative per-spective, other national legislatures196—as constitutional interpreter. Like Habermas, Tushnet is moved by the tension between judicial review and democratic self-governance. The greater danger, he argues, is posed by “strong-form,” as opposed to “weak-form,” judicial review. This distinc-tion between “strong-” and “weak-form” review is illuminating and, in my opinion, would much enrich Habermas’s analysis. By “strong-form” review, Tushnet means a system, like the American system, in which “ju-dicial interpretations of the Constitution are final and unrevisable by ordi-nary legislative majorities.”197 “Weak-form” review, by contrast, “provides mechanisms for the people to respond to decisions that they reasonably believe are mistaken”—mechanisms that “can be deployed more rapidly than the constitutional amendment or judicial appointment processes.”198 Examples of weak-form review that Tushnet discusses include the variants found in New Zealand, the United Kingdom, and Canada. In each vari-ant, the national legislature, rather than the constitutional court, has the last word in at least some areas of judicial review.199

American observers tend to be skeptical of weak-form review and dis-trustful of the very idea of legislatures as constitutional interpreters. Tush-net argues that one reason for the distrust—and for some of the poor con-gressional performances that fuel that distrust—is what he calls “the judicial overhang”: Congress “know[s] the courts are available to correct (some) of their constitutional errors,” and for that reason “legislators have little incentive to expend great effort in enacting only constitutionally permis-sible statutes.” As an example of the overhang, Tushnet cites Senator Arlen Specter’s explanation for his vote in favor of the Military Commissions Act of 2006. While Specter believed that part of the act was unconstitutional (his amendment to correct the problem had failed), he justified his vote for the act by noting that the Supreme Court would “clean it up.”200 And the Court did.201 The example illustrates, first, that the judicial overhang complicates our ability to evaluate Congress’s capacity for congressional interpretation: While, according to the Court, Congress got the Constitu-tion wrong in the Military Commissions Act, Specter’s remark indicates that in that instance congressional interpretive capacity was not necessarily lacking.202 The example illustrates, further, that the judicial overhang likely inhibits Congress from developing its constitution-interpreting capacity.

The judicial overhang problem in strong-form systems demonstrates the need for a comparative perspective. Are legislatures in weak-form

Page 155: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 144

systems actually better constitutional interpreters than their counterparts in strong-form systems? In particular, are they better protectors of basic rights? Answering those questions requires both substantive interpretation of the respective constitutions and a substantive theory about the appropri-ate level of basic rights protection. Further, to the extent that legislatures in weak-form system perform better than strong-form counterparts, what institutions, practices, and procedures are responsible? If strong-from re-view is firmly rooted, does local culture allow selective borrowing from, or at least learning from, exemplary weak-form institutions, practices, or procedures?

Habermas does not draw the distinction between strong-form and weak-form review, but, given his separation-of-powers ideas and em-phasis on legislative generation of law, some version of weak-form review would seem congenial to him. He might further be attracted to the idea of “popular constitutionalism” defended by Stanford Law School Dean Larry Kramer.203 Like Tushnet, Kramer attacks the idea of “judicial supremacy”—the notion that the Supreme Court has “the final word on constitutional interpretation.”204 While his argument is steeped in the specifically American history of judicial review, in contrast to Tushnet’s com-parative and present-day approach, Kramer’s account adds an historical di-mension to the Habermasian idea of the Constitution as an ongoing project that is not the property of a lawyerly and judicial elite. Kramer and Tushnet are hardly alone in contemporary American constitutional thought. From the direction of history and political science, Keith Whittington too has prominently attacked the idea of judicial supremacy.205 Within the legal acad-emy, Robert Post and Reva Siegel have explored the connection between the making of constitutional law and social movements. Their position, how-ever, which they call “democratic constitutionalism,” resists Kramer’s sharp alternative between judicial supremacy and democratic self-governance.206 Habermas’s social-theoretical and philosophical explanation of legitimate law’s necessarily democratic generation seems naturally to supplement this developing new literature in American constitutional theory and history. American progressives’ romance with courts seems to be ending.

Writing from the direction of legal philosophy, Christopher Zurn re-cently has published an important study of judicial review from the point of view of Habermasian deliberative-democratic theory. As with propo-nents of popular or democratic constitutionalism, Zurn argues for a mul-tiplication of the sites of constitutional interpretation and politics. Consti-tutional review is a “function,” he points out, that is not reducible to the

Page 156: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 145

specific “institution” of judicial review. After critically reviewing promi-nent American legal-theoretical justifications for judicial review, Zurn concludes with

specific institutional proposals [that] best comport with the ideals of delibera-tive democratic constitutionalism: proceduralist judicial review located in an independent constitutional court . . . , constitutional self-review panels in the legislative and executive branches, mechanisms for dispersing decisional au-thority concerning constitutional elaboration across the branches of national government, easing overly obdurate amendability requirements, and civic con-stitutional fora for both democratic deliberation about constitutional matters and as alternative mechanisms for constitutional amendment.207

Although as Zurn acknowledges, not all of his proposals translate into likely reform of American institutions (such as the proposal for a specifi-cally constitutional court rather than the comparatively more generalist U.S. Supreme Court), Zurn’s attention to questions of institutional de-sign, as well as Habermasian deliberative-democratic theory, is a welcome addition to American constitutional theorizing.

The final point about Habermas’s theory of constitutional courts’ le-gitimate role is signaled by his most general statement: that the constitu-tional court must “keep watch over just that system of rights that makes citizens’ private and public autonomy equally possible.”208 This statement raises the issue that has been at least implicitly present in some of the pre-ceding discussion. Habermas’s reconstruction of the “system of rights” develops general categories of rights that, he says, a modern legal system must recognize if it is to be legitimate. He acknowledges, however, that there is more than one way to implement those categories of rights, and he emphasizes that the abstract categories are not enforceable legal rights un-til they have been “saturated” through democratic lawmaking. That means that even if we retain the idea that the “reconstruction” has some criti-cal potential—it allows us to evaluate the relative legitimacy of particular implementations—still, Habermas cannot expect courts to do anything other than enforce the legal norms that in fact have been enacted. On Habermas’s theory, courts are “bound to existing law.” While a recon-structive account of the system of rights and constitutional state might be instructive in interpreting a particular legal system’s legal norms, none-theless, courts must tether their decisions not directly to that account but directly to the governing legal norms.

Thus the role of judicial review is not, strictly speaking, to “keep watch over just that system of rights that makes citizens’ private and public

Page 157: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 146

autonomy equally possible.” The role of judicial review, instead, is to keep watch over the version of the system of rights that govern in a particular legal community. The discourse theory of law is not itself a charter that is to be enforced directly. A critical account of how courts have fulfilled their mission cannot content itself with references to a reconstructive theory. Instead, it must engage directly the texts that authoritatively govern in a particular legal community. Understandably, Habermas saw that as be-yond the scope of his project in Between Facts and Norms. But even on the premises of that project, critical evaluation of existing legal systems can-not avoid engaging the particular ways that—in authoritative legal texts—those systems have implemented the “system of rights” and “principles of the constitutional state.”

That raises, at least in the American context, the problem of Haber-mas’s fifth category of basic rights, consideration of which I deferred in Chapter Two. This category consists of “basic rights to the provision of living conditions that are socially, technologically, and ecologically safe-guarded, insofar as the current circumstances make this necessary if citi-zens are to have equal opportunities to” exercise their private and public autonomy.209 Even the statement of this category of rights raises a problem discussed earlier: How equal must the opportunities be made? And, given the “relative” rather than “absolute” justification of this category of rights, Habermas has to face an additional question: How close a connection should be required between new social and ecological rights, on one hand, and private and public autonomy, on the other? These questions are par-ticularly pressing in the context of judicial review. If a court is convinced that the legislature has not done enough to implement social or ecological protection, what remedy should it order? The question is difficult because the legislative programs implementing these sorts of rights typically are detailed, with complex enforcement schemes.

A more fundamental question, however, is whether Habermas can claim plausibly to have reconstructed modern legal systems generally when the American system offers so little in the way of basic protection—that is, constitutional protection—for social and ecological rights. True, Haber-mas assigns a significant role to legislatures in implementing the system of rights.210 He also recognizes that the German constitutional court has found a “radiating effect” of social-welfare guarantees so that they not only establish entitlements with respect to the government but also in-fluence the content of private-law norms.211 But the near total absence of specific protection for these rights in American constitutional law poses a

Page 158: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Discourse Theory and Adjudication 147

challenge to Habermas’s reconstructive theory. Perhaps American courts simply have made a mistake by failing to recognize deeper commitments implied by the system of law that we have. But if so, then that argument would need to be made.212

One might find the beginnings of that argument in comparative analy-sis of other nations’ attempts to recognize social and ecological rights. Most recently written constitutions, after all, offer explicit guarantees, al-beit of various strengths, for these categories of rights. A growing English- language literature addresses these new forms of constitutional protection that rely on a variable mix of legislative and judicial institutional involvement.213

In sum, it is difficult to know exactly what to make of Habermas’s ac-count of the constitutional court’s legitimate role. His positive statements on the subject are both brief and general. A strong reading of these state-ments would give the constitutional court considerable latitude to remake the democratic process. Further, because Habermas sees the democratic process as threatened by inequality in social and economic power, his pro-ceduralist theory could be understood to authorize large-scale redistribu-tion of power. On the other hand, however, his critique of “value jurispru-dence,” while not strictly applicable in this context, suggests a conception of judicial restraint.

Part of the difficulty in interpreting his views may be the difference be-tween American and German constitutional law, particularly with respect to issues of free expression and the constitutional basis for social-welfare rights. The commitments of the “proceduralist paradigm” would be easier to discern if Habermas left the level of reconstructive theorizing and, in his “testing” of the discourse theory against the world of adjudication, encoun-tered more concretely the particular ways in which the “system of rights” and “principles of the constitutional state” have been institutionalized.214

Page 159: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

chapter four

System, Lifeworld, and Habermas’s “Communication Theory of Society”

In the previous chapter, I considered Habermas’s attempt to “test” the “discourse concept of law and democracy” by immersing it into leading discussions of legal theory. That was the occupation of Chapters Five and Six in Between Facts and Norms. In the succeeding chapters of that work, Habermas takes up another test, this time against social theory. His aim, he has said later, was to develop a “reconstructive social theory which employs a ‘dual perspective’ ”—the perspective, first explored in his 1981 monumental work Theory of Communication Action, of “system” and “life-world.” The purpose of developing what he now calls a “communication theory of society” is “to make it plausible that the reconstructed norma-tive self-understanding of modern legal orders does not hang in mid-air.” Instead, Habermas says, his proposed model “should explain how this [normative] self-understanding connects with the social reality of highly complex societies.”1 The idea is to ensure that the normative theory is not “utopian” in a pejorative sense.

While in Theory of Communicative Action Habermas meticulously devel-oped the concepts of system and lifeworld and the model of “interchange” between the two, Between Facts and Norms does not so much explain the basic concepts of his earlier theory as invoke them. But as I explain in sec-tion 4.1, such conceptual explication as he provides of “system” and “life-world” is generally consistent with the analysis provided in Theory of Com-municative Action.

Still, in developing the “communication theory of society” in which his “discourse theory of law” is to be situated, Habermas departs from his

Page 160: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 149

earlier understanding of the relation between system and lifeworld. One reason is that Habermas, for the first time, is giving systematic attention to law, and it turns out that law does not fit neatly into either the “sys-tem” or “lifeworld” category. To some extent this was true even in Theory of Communicative Action—recall Habermas’s distinction between “law as medium” (system) and “law as institution” (lifeworld). But Between Facts and Norms repudiates that distinction. And in placing law on center stage, the question of law’s relation to the system/lifeworld distinction becomes more pressing. Habermas’s initial solution to this difficulty is a prolifera-tion of metaphors: Law, he says, “mediates” between system and lifeworld or operates as a “transformer” or “hinge” between system and lifeworld.

In section 4.2, I discuss Habermas’s attempt to give these metaphors more precise content. As I noted at the opening to Chapter Two, Haber-mas’s general aim in the “communication theory of society” is to explain how the “communicative power” developed in citizens’ public-sphere dis-cussion might influence and check state “administrative power”—and also how it might not. The theoretical construction Habermas develops here is the “model of the circulation of political power.”2

To some extent, I argue, the model of the circulation of power can be understood as consistent with the distinction between system and life-world. The model provides greater detail concerning the political public sphere, the “lifeworld environment” to the administrative system in Theory of Communicative Action. It presents, also, the idea of “civil society” as an elaboration of the lifeworld’s “private sphere.” Many of the innovations in Between Facts and Norms, then, can be understood as attempts to flesh out, or to adjust, the framework presented in Theory of Communicative Action.

But despite Habermas’s continued allegiance to the system/lifeworld distinction, I argue in section 4.3, the model of the circulation of power in fact reworks the notions of system and lifeworld so substantially that Haber-mas’s official conceptions no longer apply. Power, even as it operates in the political system’s core, no longer can be understood as simply the “steering medium” Habermas described. The relation Habermas describes as one be-tween “system” and “lifeworld” no longer is channeled exclusively through steering media, as the old interchange model prescribes. Law (or, the legal system) straddles the distinction that was supposed to constitute the theo-ry’s axis. And on the “lifeworld” side, Habermas’s continued reference to the three “structural components” (culture, society, and personality) does not work for him. As the reader might guess, I think these developments in

Page 161: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 150

Habermas’s model of society are for the best, but, in moving away from the older notions of system and lifeworld, Habermas leaves basic conceptions in his model essentially untheorized.

I argue that Habermas’s revised model can be shored up on both the “system” and “lifeworld” side of his basic distinction. On the system side, I suggest in section 4.4 that Habermas’s conception in fact approaches the post-Parsons “autopoietic” systems theory of Niklas Luhmann—even as Habermas generally polemicizes against that theory. Further but selective appropriation of autopoietic concepts, I argue, would improve Habermas’s social theory. On the other side of Habermas’s basic distinction, I argue that the concept of lifeworld as separate social sphere should be discarded.

4.1 the offici a l accou nt of “lifewor ld” a nd “system”

Habermas’s explication of the lifeworld concept, though abbreviated, tracks the account given in Theory of Communicative Action. As before, he presents the lifeworld first in Husserlian and Schutzian terms, as the unproblem-atic, taken-for-granted background of human action. But also as before, the idea of the “rationalization of the lifeworld” leads Habermas quickly to a different conception. In the course of that rationalization, Habermas claims, the lifeworld’s “structural components,” still fused in “archaic” societies,3 differentiate into culture, society, and personality.4 And, with that rationalization, social formations’ “symbolic reproduction”—cultural reproduction, social integration and socialization—comes to depend more heavily on participants’ communicative achievements.5

This account, like the parallel account in Theory of Communicative Ac-tion, works two changes on the original phenomenological conception of the lifeworld. First, Habermas’s emphasis on communicative action as mechanism for symbolic reproduction leads him to see the lifeworld as centered around specifically communicative action, not so much as the background to all social action. “The lifeworld,” Habermas writes in Be-tween Facts and Norms, “is constituted from a network of communicative actions.”6 Second, Habermas’s discussion of the lifeworld’s rationalization turns the notion into a concept of society—a concept that takes on substantive theoretical significance. Social formations, conceived as lifeworlds, have “structural components.”7 In the course of historical development, they

Page 162: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 151

have been “rationalized,” in the sense that their cultural traditions, social institutions, and patterns of socialization have come to depend increas-ingly on specifically communicative action, and particularly on rational criticism. This revised conception of the lifeworld is, in the first instance, a conception of whole social formations as lifeworlds.

But again following the path marked in Theory of Communicative Ac-tion, the term lifeworld soon comes to refer not to whole social formations but to only certain social spheres. As before, this redefinition depends on two premises: the centering of the lifeworld concept around communica-tive action and the idea that system and lifeworld have become uncoupled.

Habermas’s account of the uncoupling of system and lifeworld is consistent with his account in Theory of Communicative Action. With the rationalization of society as lifeworld, he argues, “the risk of dissension increases with the scope for taking yes/no positions on criticizable valid-ity claims.” At the same time, the potential for social conflict increases with the differentiation of interest positions and the “unshackl[ing]” of “self-interested pursuit of one’s own success.” The burden of social integra-tion, then, shifts to the achievements of communicative action, while at the same time that very integration is endangered by the strategic pursuit of individual interests.8

Money and power, Habermas confirms, operate as “steering media” that can relieve the burden on communicative action. They are mechanisms of “system integration,” not (as with “values, norms, and mutual under-standings”) “social integration.”9 These media deploy “special codes” that abstract from ordinary language and permit users to circumvent the pro-cess of reaching communicative agreement (that is, consensus over claims to validity). Although Habermas omits the lengthy discussion of system differentiation he provided in Theory of Communicative Action, he charac-terizes the end result of that process in the same terms. The economic and administrative system differentiate out from the lifeworld’s societal com-ponent10 and “separate[] from the lifeworld.”11 These systems, which op-erate through “markets and governmental bodies,” respectively, “become “independent vis-à-vis socially integrated spheres of action, that is, spheres integrated through values, norms, and mutual understanding.”12

Thus, for Habermas, the lifeworld concept ultimately is a partial con-ception of society, referring to “socially integrated spheres of action” that are distinct from the economic and administrative systems. As in Theory of Communicative Action, the methodological distinction between systems

Page 163: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 152

theory and action theory becomes a substantive distinction that divides the social turf. And, as before, the question arises: What is the relation between system and lifeworld?

A complete answer to this question will require examination of Haber-mas’s “circulation of power” model. The preliminary answer, however, begins with Habermas’s claim, consistent with Theory of Communicative Action, that the “steering media” of money and power must be “anchored in the society component of the lifeworld” through “legal institutionaliza-tion.”13 Habermas embellishes on this “anchoring” idea by describing law as a “hinge between system and lifeworld”14 or, alternatively, as a “trans-former in the society-wide communication circulating between system and lifeworld.”15

What Habermas means by these catchphrases is two things. First, mod-ern law can be analyzed in both system and lifeworld terms. Viewed from the “system” side of the system/lifeworld distinction, law institutionalizes the power medium by establishing the framework of offices and specifying rules of official command. It institutionalizes the money medium not just by establishing and maintaining a currency, but also by promulgating and enforcing private-law rules for money-mediated transactions.16 From the “lifeworld” side, legal rules and legal institutions “belong[] to the societal component of the lifeworld.”17 In developing his “discourse theory of law,” with its emphasis on participatory democratic lawmaking as the source of legal legitimacy, Habermas makes clear that law, to the extent that it is ac-cepted as legitimate, is a source of social integration.18 The production and reproduction of legitimate law, then, is part of the symbolic reproduction of the lifeworld. Finally, in Habermas’s analysis of the democratic lawmak-ing process, the production of legitimate law connects the “communica-tive power” of citizens’ public-sphere discussion with the “administrative power” that operates within the differentiated administrative system. In these ways, law operates as “hinge” between system and lifeworld.

The second sense of Habermas’s metaphors is signaled more clearly in the “transformer” than the “hinge” metaphor. Habermas, both in Theory of Communicative Action and in Between Facts and Norms, presents the media of money and power as specialized languages, differentiated from ordi-nary language. To the extent that the democratic lawmaking process suc-cessfully produces valid law, Habermas suggests, it mediates between the ordinary-language communication of the political public sphere and the specialized languages of (administrative) power and money.19 Habermas’s

Page 164: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 153

idea here is that legal validity has two sides. On one hand, modern law claims to be legitimate—that is, to be worthy of citizens’ rational assent—and to that extent it is related to the “normatively substantive messages” of citizens’ political communication in the public sphere. On the other hand, modern law leaves open the possibility of a different attitude—obedience rooted not in normative conviction but in the fear of sanctions for non-compliance. According to Habermas, this second aspect of legal validity is tailored to the strategic pursuit of economic interests and the exercise of administrative power (which is, essentially, the power of command). In this sense, Habermas claims, law “accepts” the normative “messages” that originate in lifeworld political communication among citizens and “puts these into a form that is comprehensible to the special codes of the power-steered administration and the money-steered economy.” And thus “the language of law . . . can function as a transformer in the society-wide com-munication circulating between system and lifeworld.”20

I will consider in the next section Habermas’s attempt, with his “model of the circulation of power,” to give the “hinge” and “transformer” meta-phors more precise content. For the moment, it is enough to note that the image of law as “hinge” or “transformer” raises questions for Haber-mas’s understanding of the system/lifeworld relation. The first question concerns Habermas’s location of “legal institutions” in the lifeworld’s soci-etal component. In Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas seemed to understand “legal institutions” as basic legal principles, especially those of contract and property law. But what of “legal institutions” such as courts? How are they to be understood? Do they have a double status, such that they belong to both system and lifeworld? Or, as the “hinge” and “trans-former” metaphors suggest, are they somehow intermediate between sys-tem and lifeworld or astride the system/lifeworld distinction?

Second, how is it that a lifeworld sphere—the political public sphere—can send “normatively substantive messages” to the administrative system? The system/lifeworld model developed in Theory of Communicative Action required that interchange between system and lifeworld be channeled by system “steering media.” Habermas’s idea of “administrative power” con-forms to the conception of a “steering medium,” but “communicative power” does not. How, then, does this communication between system and lifeworld occur? The question is difficult because Habermas’s conceptual explication of “lifeworld,” “system,” and “steering medium” tracks without explicitly revising the accounts given in Theory of Communicative Action.

Page 165: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 154

4.2 the model of the circul ation of pow er

In attempting to situate his discourse theory of democracy social- theoretically, Habermas introduces what he calls a model of the “constitu-tionally regulated circulation of power.”21 In some ways, this model can be understood as specifying more precisely Theory of Communicative Action’s account of “interchange” between lifeworld and administrative system. Habermas prefaces his introduction of the model with a quick run-through of the distinction between system and lifeworld,22 and he provides an ex-panded analysis of the public sphere and “private sphere”—the lifeworld en-vironments to the administrative system in Theory of Communicative Action.

But Habermas borrows the model from Bernhard Peters,23 and Peters is critical of the “dualistic conception of system and lifeworld.”24 Unsur-prisingly, then, the new model conceives of the “circulation of power” in a way that avoids some of the difficulties of Habermas’s earlier system/lifeworld model. The changes are necessary, given the objectives Habermas pursues in his work on law and democracy—objectives that are fundamen-tally different from those pursued in Theory of Communicative Action.

Habermas’s earlier system/lifeworld model was the centerpiece of a po-litically defensive crisis theory. Apparently skeptical about the possibility of genuine democracy, Habermas argued in Theory of Communicative Ac-tion that the “colonizing” tendencies of the economic and (especially) ad-ministrative systems faced structural limits: limits rooted in the functional necessities of symbolic reproduction. Between Facts and Norms, by contrast, pursues a more “offensive” strategy.25 The “reconstructive” part of Haber-mas’s discourse theory of law and democracy investigates not so much the functional necessities of “symbolic reproduction” as the explicitly norma-tive principles of the constitutional state. The leading principle, according to Habermas, is that the state’s exercise of “administrative power” must be linked to citizens’ articulation of communicative power in the politi-cal public sphere. And thus, rather than see the role of the political public sphere as the production of only “mass loyalty”—the picture developed in Theory of Communicative Action’s system/lifeworld interchange model—Habermas now sees the political public sphere as normatively influencing the course of official decision and as productive of law. To be sure, the point of the “communication theory of society” is to discover the “iner-tial moments” that resist the realization of democratic ideals.26 But the emphatically prodemocratic thrust of Habermas’s project makes the old system/lifeworld model inappropriate.

Page 166: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 155

The idea of the new “circulation of power” model, then, is to show more precisely how citizens’ communicative power may be converted into administrative power—power as a steering medium—and how the lat-ter can be checked by the former. At the very outset, four changes from the older system/lifeworld model are apparent (the significance of which will be discussed below). First, Habermas now refers to “the political sys-tem” rather than to “the administrative system.” Second, only the politi-cal system, and not the economic system, appears in the model. (To be sure, Theory of Communicative Action is not exactly exemplary in its analysis of the economic system,27 but it does include that system in the model.) Third, Habermas presents the political system not as a single administra-tive apparatus but as internally differentiated into regions of “center” (or “core”), “inner periphery,” and “outer periphery.”28 And fourth, in his ac-count of these regions, Habermas refers much more forthrightly to politi-cal institutions and associations—such as legislatures, courts, and political parties—in partial replacement of more shadowy references to anonymous workings of the system.

Habermas’s model is easiest to understand if we approach it first through the center/periphery map.

4.2.1 The Political System’s Center

The “center” or “core area” of the political system, Habermas explains, is “formed by the familiar complexes of administration.” Each of the three branches of government is represented here. Habermas mentions “the incumbent Government,” by which presumably he means the executive branch. Included, also, are “parliamentary bodies,” understood in their connection with a party system that competes for election. More gener-ally, Habermas refers here to “democratic opinion- and will-formation,” which “includes” parliaments, elections, and party competition. Finally, Habermas includes the “judicial system” in the center or “core area” of the political system.29

Inclusion of the executive branch is unsurprising. Habermas’s account of the other two branches, however, requires comment. First, Habermas’s location of “democratic opinion- and will-formation,” through processes of election and legislation, marks a significant change in his conception of “systems.” One prominent characteristic of “systems,” as defined in Theory of Communicative Action, was that both their internal operations and their relations to their environments are steered by “media” that circumvent the

Page 167: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 156

process of reaching understanding through communicative action. For the administrative system (now known as the political system), the me-dium was power, understood as command. But Habermas now speaks of “democratic opinion- and will-formation” in the “core area” of the political system. The political system’s internal operations, then, seem to be com-municatively organized and dependent on the rational discourse Haber-mas connects to communicative action. Already at this point, then, the distinction between system and lifeworld is attenuated in the new model.

The second aspect of the political system’s center that requires com-ment is Habermas’s decision to place the judicial system there rather than in a separate legal system. In some respects, this choice is not surprising. Courts are (at least typically) politically organized and staffed by state personnel; further, as Habermas notes in his general account of law, their decisions presuppose and rely on political enforcement. Moreover, Haber-mas’s earlier account of the lifeworld’s “colonization” saw family and juve-nile courts as part of the administrative system.30

But Habermas since has repudiated the idea of “law as medium” that underwrote his treatment of family and juvenile courts as part of the welfare-state bureaucracy. And various passages in Between Facts and Norms affirmatively suggest a distinction between legal and political sys-tems. Some of these passages seem to use the term legal system to refer to what Habermas’s model calls “the political system.”31 But others seem to point more strongly toward positing the legal system as a distinct system—though one linked to the operations of the political system.

In some of these passages, Habermas flirts with the ideas of Niklas Luhmann, the late (but still preeminent) systems theorist. This flirtation is surprising, given Habermas’s frequent polemics, in Between Facts and Norms and elsewhere, against Luhmann’s work. As Habermas notes, Luhmann’s brand of systems theory—the theory of “autopoietic” systems32—relies on the idea of a system’s “code” as the basis for the system’s identity and unity (and thus also the system’s distinction from its environment).33 A code, for Luhmann, is a binary distinction basic to the system’s communications—for the legal system, the distinction between legal and illegal. Habermas picks up this idea of the binary legal code,34 and he suggests also that the political system has its own binary code. While Habermas, like Luhmann, does not make entirely clear what this latter binary code is, it appears to be the distinction between command and obedience.35 Habermas’s positing of separate system codes would seem to commit him to a distinction be-tween the legal and political systems.36

Page 168: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 157

Despite Habermas’s flirtation with the idea of binary codes, however, he seems content to understand the judicial system as part of a more com-prehensive political system.37 One reason, likely, is that he still sees “sys-tems” as defined through steering media, not so much through binary codes. And law, he has now decided, is not a steering medium. Further, Habermas’s discourse theory of law accounts for the distinctiveness of ju-dicial communication—its differences from legislative or administrative communication—through the notion of separation of powers. The differ-ent branches of government represented in the political system’s “center,” Habermas claims, have access to different kinds of reasons and are permit-ted different sorts of discourse.38 Habermas, then, can place the judicial system within a more general “political system” without denying the dif-ferences that make argumentation in the judicial system distinctive. That allows him to avoid a reduction of “law”—judicial discourse—to (ordinary or party) “politics.” Finally—and this is a point yet to be developed—Habermas’s “circulation of power” model distinguishes between center and periphery according to the degree of formal organization and insti-tutionalization. The “center” of the political system is formally organized, that is, created by positive law, and whether one looks at courts, legislatures or agencies, the center is the locus of official decision. Habermas identifies the periphery, by contrast, in terms of informal organization and separa-tion from official channels of decision.

4.2.2 The Political System’s Periphery

Beyond the political system’s “center” of decision-making institutions, Habermas identifies an “inner periphery” and an “outer periphery.” The inner periphery, he suggests, includes institutions with “rights of self- governance or . . . other kinds of oversight and lawmaking functions del-egated by the state” (for example, “universities, public insurance systems, professional agencies and associations, charitable organizations, foun-dations, etc.”).39 This assemblage of groups is an odd collection. Public insurance systems would seem more naturally to fit into the state ad-ministration, particularly given Habermas’s prior treatment of welfare bureaucracies as power-wielding, “lifeworld-colonizing” arms of the state apparatus. Further, whether universities should be seen as exercising pow-ers “delegated by the state” would seem to depend on whether they are public or private institutions. Presumably, however, Habermas is thinking of, for example, the extensive government sponsorship of university-based

Page 169: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 158

scientific research, especially in the medical and defense sectors. And so even private universities might be seen as quasi-state institutions, albeit generally not ones that make official governmental decisions. Professional associations—such as, in this country, the AMA and ABA—perform regu-latory functions that might well have been considered the province of of-ficial government institutions. While “charitable associations and founda-tions” fit less naturally into this picture, the “inner periphery” thus seems to consist mostly in institutions and associations that perform quasi-state functions without exercising official state decision-making power.

Habermas gives much more attention to the political system’s “outer periphery.” In classifying the organizations and associations one finds there, Habermas distinguishes between “customers” and “suppliers.” By “customers,” Habermas means various organizations, such as “business associations, labor unions, [and] interest groups,” which are linked in a network of ongoing communication with “public agencies.”40 Habermas seems to see these “customers” as representatives, of a sort, of the eco-nomic system.41 With respect to the political system, their activity seems to consist largely in bargaining on behalf of their respective constituencies.42 They are “customers” in the sense that their encounters with the political system are directed primarily toward obtaining governmental largesse and favors for their clients.

The “suppliers” are driven less by directly economic interests and more by ideological objectives. They are “associations, and organizations, that, before parliaments and through the courts, give voice to social problems, make broad demands, articulate public interests or needs, and thus attempt to influence the political process more from normative points of view than from the standpoint of particular interests.” These groups include: (1) “or-ganizations representing clearly defined group interests”; (2) associations with “goals recognizably defined by party politics”; (3) “cultural estab-lishments” (such as “academics, writers’ associations, and ‘radical profes-sionals’ ”); and (4) “public-interest groups” (for example, environmentalist groups and animal-protection associations, but also “churches or chari-table organizations”).43

As Habermas is aware, the distinction between customers and suppli-ers is not entirely easy to draw.44 Labor unions and industry associations, for example, seem to be both customers and suppliers: They seek both to lobby official decision makers for economically favorable outcomes and also to participate more generally in public debate. But in any event, to the extent that a group counts as “supplier,” it appears in three places in

Page 170: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 159

Habermas’s topography of the “circulation of power.” Besides populat-ing the political system’s outer periphery, “suppliers” are key players in the public sphere of political discussion, and they help constitute the network of voluntary associations that Habermas calls “civil society.”

4.2.3 The Public Sphere and Civil Society

The public sphere, Habermas tells us, is not a system, institution, or-ganization, or “framework of norms.” His positive descriptions tend to be highly metaphorical—and the metaphors sometimes mix indiscriminately. It is a “network” of communications with respect to public issues. The po-litical public sphere is a “sounding board for problems,” a “warning system with sensors that, though unspecialized, are sensitive throughout soci-ety.” The political public sphere “filter[s],” “synthesize[s],” and “bundle[s]” “streams of communication.” Reviewing the usual metaphors of space and stage and forum—“architectural metaphors of structured spaces”— Habermas argues that they do not adequately convey the nature of the po-litical public sphere. While these metaphors may describe limited publics, the political public sphere is detached from physical presence and simple interactions; it becomes “extend[ed] to the virtual presence of scattered readers, listeners, or viewers linked by public media.”45 And as detached from concrete presences and interactions, the political public sphere is, in Habermas’s formulation, a circuit of “as it were, ‘subjectless’ forms of communication”46—or, in an alternative formulation, an “anonymous cir-cuit[] of communication.”47

This array of metaphors may be daunting,48 but what Habermas is try-ing to do with them can be made reasonably clear. One aim is to char-acterize the relation between the public sphere and the political system’s center—the sphere of official decision making (and lawmaking in particu-lar). The other is to account for the relation between the political public sphere and the “private sphere” of the lifeworld.

Consider, first, the relation between political public sphere and political center. The political public sphere is the source of citizens’ “communicative power”—the power of common convictions that arises through rational debate. Deliberative decision making in the political system’s “center” is an-other locus of communicative power. The idea of the constitutional state, Habermas has argued, is that citizens’ communicative power must influ-ence the communicative power developed in officials’ deliberations. Or, to use another of Habermas’s favorite metaphors: Citizens’ communicative

Page 171: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 160

power must be able to pass through the “sluice” of official deliberative pro-cedures and “penetrate[] the constitutionally organized political system.”49

Habermas’s reconstruction of the constitutional state notes that de-mocracy cannot, under modern conditions, mean the assembly of all the citizens.50 And thus the political public sphere, for Habermas, is not a physical space in which the citizenry as a whole is present and interacts. Instead, the political public sphere relies on mass-communications media that establish “virtual” presence—communication among those who never will meet face-to-face and know nothing or very little of one another’s lives. That is the meaning of his emphasis on “anonymous” and “subject-less circuits of communication.”

The various contributions in these circuits of opinion influence official decision making only if they are “bundled” to form what Habermas calls “public opinion.” Habermas resists the usual idea that public opinion is the statistical average of what people think. Nor does he simply weight the average to reflect the likelihood of voting, the degree of influence of the respective opinion holders, or anything of the sort. Oddly—because his concern here seems to be mainly whether public opinion will influence decision making in the political system’s center—Habermas insists on a qualitative appraisal of public opinion. And so opinion polls, in Haber-mas’s view, reflect public opinion “only if they have been preceded by a focused public debate and a corresponding opinion-formation in a mobi-lized public sphere.” Relevant factors here include the “discursive level of opinion-formation” and its inclusiveness—or, more generally, the “proce-dural properties of its process of generation.”51

As a descriptive definition of public opinion, or even the influence of public opinion, this conception seems inapt. But it may be more plausible if understood as a “basis for measuring the legitimacy of the influence that public opinion has on the political system.”52 Viewed in this way, Haber-mas is suggesting that public discussion has an appropriate democratic influence only to the extent that the conditions of public debate meet certain discursive criteria. I will discuss below Habermas’s account of the obstacles that may prevent the public sphere from producing the requisite “influence” on the political system’s center.

The second aim of Habermas’s account of the public sphere—captured in the “sounding board” and “sensors” metaphor—is to explain how prob-lems and issues make it onto the agenda of public discussion. The connec-tion is through the lifeworld sphere he calls “civil society.”

Page 172: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 161

The appearance of civil society in Habermas’s model is connected with the shift in his theoretical and political objectives since Theory of Commu-nicative Action.53 The place that civil society now occupies is the lifeworld’s “private sphere.”54 In Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas saw the private sphere as centered around the nuclear family—or, from the per-spective of the economic system to which it was “lifeworld environment,” centered around the “private household.” The roles of “employee” and “consumer,” Habermas said, were the relevant roles for money-steered in-terchange between the economic system and private sphere. Habermas did not consider in Theory of Communicative Action the relation between the private sphere and the political system.55

In Between Facts and Norms, by contrast, Habermas is interested pre-cisely in the relation between private sphere and the political system. Habermas’s focus on “civil society,” rather than the employee and con-sumer roles, reflects this new interest. What he is investigating is the po-litical significance of the private sphere. How, he asks, is it related to the public sphere of political discussion, and how in turn is it related to formal political decision making?

Habermas’s understanding of “civil society” is consistent with that term’s common usage in recent political discussion. His most usual defini-tion presents civil society as a “network of voluntary associations,”56 al-though he includes also family relations.57 The voluntary associations that constitute civil society, Habermas emphasizes, are “noneconomic,”58 “in-formal,”59 and generally egalitarian.60 Civil society, so conceived, is thus distinct from both the economic and political systems.61 Habermas makes clear that civil society is a “lifeworld” sphere.62

Civil society’s “lifeworld” location is the source of its strategic role in Habermas’s theory. The problems, concerns, and issues of everyday life, he suggests, are discussed in civil-social associations before they become items of public-sphere discussion.63 Participants in public-sphere discussion are, Habermas says, “recruited” from civil society’s voluntary associations.64 And so these associations may “distill and transmit” responses to lifeworld problems “in amplified form to the public sphere.”65 Civil society, to the extent that it is autonomous from both the state and political systems, is in this way a source of “counterknowledge”—counter, that is, to official conceptions in the political system’s formal decision-making institutions.66

Together, then, civil society and the political public sphere establish a link between system and lifeworld. This link, on Habermas’s view, is what

Page 173: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 162

makes genuine democracy possible. At the same time, Habermas empha-sizes a number of preconditions.

4.2.4 The Circulation of Power and the Possibility of Democracy

One set of preconditions for democracy, according to Habermas, has to do with the “culture” and “personality” components of the lifeworld—not just the “society” component in which voluntary associations are rooted. Democracy, he claims, presupposes “a liberal political culture supported by corresponding patterns of political socialization.”67 In other words, the society in question must have a tradition of inclusive and broad po-litical participation, and individuals must be both able and disposed to take advantage of the possibilities that the culture presents. “Otherwise,” Habermas suggests at one point, doubtless with an eye on post–Cold War Eastern Europe and Russia, “populist movements arise that blindly defend the frozen traditions of a lifeworld endangered by capitalist moderniza-tion.”68 More generally: Public debate otherwise would cordon off some topics from rational discussion, or it would fail to include all whose inter-ests are potentially affected, or both. And that would offend the principle of democracy, as Habermas understands it.

Second, both civil society and the political public sphere must be le-gally protected to ensure their autonomy. Basic rights of free speech, press, association, and assembly are necessary not just for the political public sphere but for civil society as well. In fact, Habermas claims, civil society is constituted through these basic rights, as well as through legal protections of “privacy”—where this last is understood as the protection of autono-mous choice in matters of lifestyle and judgment. These legal protections, if effective, safeguard both the political public sphere and civil society from state domination.69

Third, both civil society and the political public sphere must be in-sulated also from the effects of unequal “social power”—that is, unequal “possibilities . . . in social relationships to assert [one’s] own will and in-terests, even against the opposition of others.”70 While the power to as-sert one’s will and interests is essential to political participation,71 gross inequalities in the distribution of social power mean that some may “in-fluence the political process in such a way that their interests acquire a priority not in accord with equal civil rights.” Habermas suggests that the egalitarian structures of voluntary associations may, to some extent, “ab-sorb and neutralize” differences in social power. But, at the same time,

Page 174: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 163

the democratic potential of civil society itself depends on a more or less equal distribution of power.72 And so does the democratic potential of the political public sphere.73 Of course the problem is that the redistribution of unequal social power is extraordinarily unlikely if that very inequal-ity renders both civil society and the political public sphere democratically ineffective. Perhaps in confession of the difficulty of this dilemma, Haber-mas suggests at one point that genuine democracy would be possible “only in an egalitarian public of citizens that has emerged from the confines of class and thrown off the millennia-old shackles of social stratification and exploitation.”74 That, however, does not seem to be our situation.

Fourth, a precondition for modern democracy is an appropriate role for the mass communications media. As Habermas recognizes, the mod-ern political public sphere requires these media, if political communication and debate is to extend beyond simple (and generally ineffective) face-to-face interaction. But at the same time, the expense of many forms of com-munication, together with dominance of print and television by power-ful organizations, means a centralization of control over the selection of “topics, contributions, and authors into the mass-media-dominated public sphere.” Habermas notes also the economic incentives toward dumbing-down of political reporting and commentary (or, for that matter, minimiz-ing it in favor of purer forms of entertainment).75

Habermas noted these dangers in 1992, and so he was unable to con-sider at that time whether the Internet could, in some measure, counter the trends toward centralized control. (His present assessment, discussed in Chapter Five, is less positive than one might expect.) The diagnosis he presents in Between Facts and Norms is threefold. First, he notes studies that find audiences not so passive as the sharpest media critics believe. Second, he presents a normative argument that “the mass media ought to under-stand themselves as the mandatary of an enlightened public whose willing-ness to learn and capacity for criticism they at once presuppose, demand, and reinforce.” Third, he suggests that government regulate the mass media to require broader access and presentation of noncentrist points of view.76 The obvious difficulty with this last idea—and one that Habermas acknowledges—is that using state administrative power to select among speakers raises substantial free-speech concerns.

Habermas notes, also, an additional obstacle to genuine democracy: the tendency of governmental institutions in the political system’s center to short-circuit the “official” or “constitutional” circulation of power. The “official” pattern of circulation, reconstructed in Habermas’s discourse

Page 175: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 164

theory of democracy, prescribes that legislative initiatives are to come from the citizens’ exercise of “communicative power.” Set out social- theoretically, in terms of Habermas’s center/periphery model of the po-litical system, communicative power, emerging in the public sphere as a response to the impulses from civil society, must flow through the “sluices of democratic and constitutional procedures situated at the entrance to the parliamentary complex.”77 But in practice, Habermas acknowledges, much “normal business” crosscuts this official flow. And this, he says, is unavoidable. Most operations of the core “proceed according to routines” that are not necessarily linked to popular initiatives:

From a normative standpoint, the only decisive question concerns which power constellations these patterns reflect and how the latter can be changed. This in turn depends on whether the settled routines remain open to reno-vative impulses from the periphery. In cases of conflict, that is, processing matters according to the usual conventions is eclipsed by another mode of operation.

Habermas calls this other mode “problematization.” Here “the attention span of the citizenry enlarges,” and “the pressure of public opinion” com-pels the core institutions to switch over to “constitutional channels for the circulation of power.”78

Habermas is not altogether optimistic about the possibilities here. “Under certain circumstances,” he says, “civil society can acquire influence in the public sphere, have an effect on the parliamentary complex (and the courts) through its own public opinions, and compel the political system to switch over to the official circulation of power.”79 But in addition to the obstacles noted above—the effects of unequal social power and the nor-malizing power of the mass media—Habermas acknowledges that political parties and leaders, too, have ways of managing public opinion.80 While political parties are essential to the operation of the political system’s cen-ter,81 their function of recruiting and disciplining officeholders may well interfere with the development of sufficiently discursive public debate.82

Habermas does note, however, that many of the important movements in the last two decades—antinuclear movements, environmental move-ments, feminism, and multiculturalism, to name a few of his examples—have originated in civil society, eventually making it onto the “agenda” of the public sphere. And only much later, after a long period of public opin-ion formation, did they gain official attention.83 Civil society, then, has for Habermas an innovating role in the democratic lawmaking process.

Page 176: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 165

4.3 the stat us of the system/lifewor ld model

With the preceding sketch of Habermas’s “circulation of power” model in mind, the question becomes: What has happened to the system/lifeworld model that Habermas defended earlier? As I showed in section 4.1, Between Facts and Norms officially presents the concepts of system and lifeworld more or less as Habermas developed them, with considerable fanfare, in Theory of Communicative Action. But immediately after concluding one of these official presentations,84 Habermas presents the “circulation of power” model, and that model on its face expresses differences from Habermas’s earlier system/lifeworld theory. In this part of my argument, I will be con-sidering whether or not Habermas’s new model effectively abandons many of the central assumptions of the earlier system/lifeworld scheme. I look at this matter as someone who has argued that the original system/lifeworld model is untenable.

4.3.1 Mapping Center/Periphery against System/Lifeworld

Habermas’s “circulation of power” model speaks more of the political system’s “center” and “periphery” than it speaks of system and lifeworld. Habermas does not make clear how the center/periphery schema maps out against the distinction between system and lifeworld. Does the periphery—especially the “outer periphery”—belong to system or lifeworld? And what effect does the notion of “periphery” have? If, as it seems, the concept of “periphery” blurs the boundary between system and lifeworld, then does the distinction between system and lifeworld still have significance?

The changes that the notion of “periphery” might effect are easiest to see when one examines the position the two models assign to the political public sphere. Habermas’s earlier system/lifeworld model made clear that the political public sphere belongs to the “societal component” of the life-world, as the administrative system’s environment. The public sphere was not “in” the administrative system; instead, it was related externally to that system through media-steered, input/output interchange relations.

The newer model, however, speaks of “the political system” rather than the administrative system, and it presents the relevant system as dif-ferentiated into center and periphery. One would think that the “center” of the political system might be the same as the old, undifferentiated ad-ministrative system. Not so. While “the incumbent Government” seems

Page 177: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 166

to correspond at least roughly to the old administrative system, Haber-mas includes at the political system’s center legislative bodies and courts—institutions not clearly accounted for in the old system/lifeworld model and difficult (as Habermas now acknowledges) to see entirely in terms of administrative power (or the steering medium of “power as command”). Even the “center” of the new “political” system seems more expansive than the old administrative system, and Habermas makes clear that its workings cannot be accounted for solely in terms of “power as command.”

Introduction of the political system’s “periphery” complicates mat-ters further. The term periphery is ambiguous. Does it include the pub-lic sphere? Civil society? Does it refer to the outer reaches of the political system—distant regions that still are within the system’s boundaries? Or does it refer instead only to those “peripheral” regions that are beyond the system’s perimeter?

Much of Habermas’s initial account of the periphery is a list and de-scription of the various players that populate that region—the quasi-state organizations and associations of the “inner periphery,” and the “custom-ers” and “suppliers” of the outer periphery.85 The public sphere is emphati-cally not an organization, association, or system. For that reason, it is dif-ficult to place on the system’s “periphery.” Habermas, however, states that the political public sphere is the political system’s “real periphery.”86 Other statements are to similar effect.87 Still other statements are more equivo-cal,88 but on balance, Habermas seems to suggest that the political system’s “periphery” includes the political public sphere. In fact, Habermas sug-gests that the political system’s periphery includes also the sphere he calls “civil society.”89

That leaves the question whether the periphery is part of the political system—that is, within the system’s boundaries—or whether, instead, it is a region “peripheral” to the system in the sense of lying beyond the sys-tem’s outer limit. Habermas cannot avoid the question because the system/lifeworld distinction, even as formulated in Between Facts and Norms, sees systems as differentiated and separate from their environments. Systems theory depends on the distinction between system and environment. And so if systems-theoretical concepts still have meaning to Habermas—as he says they do—then he has to answer the “boundary” question.

Habermas does not make his answer altogether explicit, but if he is retaining his system/lifeworld distinction, the answer has to be that the periphery lies outside the political system’s boundary.90 The political pub-lic sphere, he says, is not organized as a system.91 And further, Habermas

Page 178: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 167

makes clear that “civil society” belongs to the lifeworld—with the usual specific address being the lifeworld’s “societal component.”92 Thus the pe-riphery, conceived as including both the political public sphere and civil society, must not be within the political system’s boundaries.

But while this answer resolves the “mapping” issue, it also raises fur-ther problems. One difficulty is at least terminological and possibly con-ceptual. If the “periphery” is not properly part of the political system, then why does Habermas describe the political system as differentiated into center and periphery? Instead of referring to governmental decision mak-ing institutions as the political system’s “center,” it would be enough to refer to them as, simply, “the political system.” Only if the periphery were part of the system would we need the distinction between center and pe-riphery. Otherwise, we should speak more simply of system and environ-ment, or system and not-system.

Two other difficulties will be the subject of separate sections. First, if the periphery is beyond the political system’s boundaries—lying in the do-main Habermas calls the lifeworld—then Habermas must account for the interchange between system and lifeworld. The account he has given in Be-tween Facts and Norms is full of terms like “influence,” “communication of normative messages,” and the like. These notions are impossible to square with the austere “media theory” announced in Theory of Communicative Action. Habermas’s “circulation of power” model, I will suggest, confirms the criticisms I made of the earlier “interchange model.”

A second difficulty is that the reasons why the public sphere and civil society cannot be part of the political system—why they must be assigned to the lifeworld—also suggest that the center is not a “system,” either. Very little of the Parsons-inspired systems theory actually animates Habermas’s current work—notwithstanding his formal allegiance to the earlier “sys-tems” concept.

4.3.2 The Two Models and Interchange among Social Spheres

The model of system/lifeworld interchange presented in Theory of Com-municative Action is a systems-theoretical model. According to Habermas’s critical appropriation of Parsons’s media theory, interchange between sys-tems operates through the media proper to the related systems. The me-dia proper to the economic and political systems, Habermas claimed, are money and political power. Habermas recognizes only money and power as “steering media.” As I noted in Chapter One, Habermas specifically

Page 179: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 168

rejects Parsons’s suggestions that “influence” and “value-commitment” qualify as media analogous to money. And as I have argued, that makes the model of system/lifeworld interchange asymmetric. The lifeworld spheres Habermas presents as operating in media-controlled interchange with the two systems—the public and private sphere—have no media of their own to contribute to the interchange. And so their “inputs” into the two sys-tems must be assimilated to the media of money and power. The irony of this conceptual strategy is that, while designed to preserve the integrity of the lifeworld in all its normative richness, the strategy requires Habermas to conclude that the public sphere contributes only “taxes” and “mass loy-alty” to the administrative system, in exchange for “organizational perfor-mances” and “binding decisions.” The system-theoretical frame of Haber-mas’s interchange model, together with the assumptions he makes about the nature of interchange and steering media, leads him in Theory of Com-municative Action to a hollowed-out conception of democracy’s workings.

As I have argued, Habermas likely chose this conceptual strategy to make his argument normatively minimalist. The argument of Theory of Communicative Action is not a normative exhortation for more democracy or greater economic justice. While Habermas’s account of the lifeworld’s “rationalization” is designed to demonstrate the unexhausted “rational potential” in modern societies—the only selective and partial realization of “communicative rationality”—his diagnosis of modern “social patholo-gies” takes the form of a crisis theory. Independent of the political will to resist the “colonizing” tendencies of economic and bureaucratic systems, he argues, those tendencies face unavoidable limits—limits rooted in the functional necessity of “symbolically reproducing” the lifeworld. The fo-cus of Habermas’s system/lifeworld model, then, was on the effects that systems have on the lifeworld, not so much the influence that the lifeworld might have on systems.

Between Facts and Norms is a very different project. The argument is much more strongly normative. Legal norms are legitimate, he claims, only if they conform to the principle of democracy. And that means that they must be able to “meet with the . . . assent of all citizens in a discursive process of legislation that in turn has been legally constituted”93 (though, with due regard for fair compromise). Habermas’s recourse to social theory is designed as a “translation” of the strongly normative principles of the discourse theory of democracy. Accordingly, the “circulation of power” model focuses on the conditions necessary for the production of legitimate law: (1) A “vibrant” civil society94 must transmit “impulses” to the political

Page 180: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 169

public sphere that express unresolved social problems that are susceptible of political solution; (2) a “robust”95 and “unsubverted”96 political public sphere must discursively process these impulses to generate “public opin-ion”; (3) this public opinion must “influence”97 the deliberations of official decision makers (primarily legislative bodies) in the political system’s cen-ter; and (4) the administration’s exercise of “administrative power” must be bound by the normative premises of legal rules and principles whose existence ultimately depends on citizens’ “jurisgenerative” communicative power. The focus, then, is on how lifeworld structures peripheral to the political system—civil society and the public sphere—may “influence” the operation of the political system that is differentiated from the lifeworld.98

Notice the term influence. Habermas’s argument in Between Facts and Norms uses the idea of “influence” to characterize the relation between spheres constituted through communicative action—civil society and public sphere—and the “system” that, Habermas still claims, is qua sys-tem organized around a “steering medium.” No longer must system and lifeworld be related only through money and power. Instead, the “input” from lifeworld to system operates through “influence,” and Theory of Com-municative Action specifically concludes that “influence” is not the name of a steering medium.99 Without acknowledging the point, Habermas ef-fectively has abandoned the premises of his systems-theoretical conception of “interchange” between system and lifeworld.

My argument does not depend on Habermas’s having chosen the term influence to describe the effect of the political system’s periphery (read: life-world) on the system’s center. The very premise of Habermas’s project is to account for how informally organized spheres, constituted by and cen-tered around communicative action, may send “normatively substantive messages” to spheres that, supposedly, are differentiated as “systems” that operate and communicate only through steering media. This conception is impossible to reconcile with the media theory that Habermas embraced in Theory of Communicative Action.

4.3.3 “System” Revisited

Habermas’s media theory was supposed to account not just for the rela-tions among systems but for the “internal” operations of systems as well. Here, too, the concept of “steering medium” is central for Habermas. A defining characteristic of a steering medium is that it allows calculating, strategic actors to circumvent the process of reaching understanding over

Page 181: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 170

contested validity claims. Habermas in effect defines “systems” as spheres of action in which steering media, not linguistic consensus, play the cen-tral coordinating role. Habermas refers to systems as “media-steered,” as opposed to “communicatively organized.”

A second feature of Theory of Communicative Action’s “system” concep-tion is the notion of formal organization. By “formally organized,” Haber-mas means “created by positive law.” Habermas makes clear, first, that the economic and administrative systems as a whole are created by positive law: The media of money and power, he says, must be “legally institu-tionalized” for the media to operate as stable systems media. And further, Habermas extends the notion of formal organization to include the entities and associations that populate the economic and administrative systems. Here he is thinking of bureaucratic organizations—both business firms and government agencies—that are structured hierarchically and have de-fined expectations for membership that are enforced through command.

Combining these two features, I noted in Chapter One, Theory of Com-municative Action develops a hyperbolic conception of these systems as “norm-free structures” in which “the lifeworld”—understood as the cul-tural tradition, social norms, and personal competences and dispositions—is irrelevant for the coordination of action. I argued strenuously against this conception.

In Between Facts and Norms, Habermas’s explications of the “systems” concept do not explicitly revise his earlier account. While he does not re-peat the more hyperbolic claims about “norm-free structures,” he does make clear that a defining characteristic of a “system,” and what renders it “independent” from the lifeworld, is its development of a steering medium that allows users to circumvent the process of communicative agreement.

That understanding of a “system” was what made clear—despite ini-tial ambiguity—that the “peripheral” spheres of civil society and the public sphere could not be systems or part of the political system proper. They have no steering media of their own, operating instead through “influence”—which, again, is not a steering medium on Habermas’s view. They reproduce themselves through communicative action and are “com-municatively organized,” which for Habermas indicates “lifeworld” rather than “system” status.

But now consider Habermas’s account of the political system’s center. Legislatures, he claims, operate deliberatively, and while they have spe-cial procedures that structure and (because of time constraints) sometimes terminate discourse,100 they do not operate simply through the power of

Page 182: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 171

command. Instead, they are part of the process of “democratic opinion- and will-formation.”101 Similarly, Habermas understands the adjudicative structure as consistent with the “discourse principle,” even if time and rel-evance constraints limit the scope of available arguments and even if the participating lawyers—though not the judge—present arguments strategi-cally.102 Further, even the “administration” operates through discourse as well as through command.103

Communicative action and discourse, then, are not peculiar to the life-world. Habermas’s expansion of the idea of political power to include com-municative as well as administrative power, and his ready admission that communicative power is generated through discourse in the political sys-tem’s center, suggest a move away from the earlier conception of “systems.” The notion of a “steering medium”—power as command, in the case of the political system—is too crude a tool for Habermas’s theory of democracy. And so although his official explications of the “system” concept still insist that systems are differentiated out around steering media, Habermas’s ac-tual analysis of the political system is more sophisticated. And it has to be, given Habermas’s objectives in Between Facts and Norms.

Here, as with the unacknowledged revisions of the “interchange” con-cept, the developments seem to me clear improvements. But in what sense is the political system now a “system”? And, with respect to the notion of interchange, are we limited to the “electronics metaphors”104 of “impulse,” “amplifier,” “transformer,” along with the water metaphor of “sluices”? Is Habermas’s mixing of these metaphors the best theoretical (let alone liter-ary) strategy?

In section 4.4, I will suggest that a better conception of social “sys-tems,” and a better account of the relations among social spheres, might be available through a selective appropriation of more recent systems theory. I have in mind here the “autopoietic” theory of the late Niklas Luhmann, Habermas’s longtime partner in debate and probably Habermas’s equal in eminence among continental social theorists. As I have noted in passing already, Habermas’s encounters with Luhmann’s “autopoietic” theory are almost entirely polemical, and his interpretation of autopoietic theory is, for the most part, a caricature. But oddly, at the same time that Habermas blisters the idea of autopoiesis, he states offhandedly that the political and legal systems are “autopoietic.”105 Habermas appropriates what is in my judgment a less attractive idea in Luhmann’s work—the idea of the binary code, already discussed briefly and to be discussed somewhat more expan-sively in the following pages.106 A more accurate reading of Luhmann’s

Page 183: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 172

work, and a more judicious borrowing from it, could rehabilitate Haber-mas’s collapsed notion of social systems.

4.3.4 “Lifeworld” Revisited

I have described the successive shifts in Habermas’s notion of the life-world: from (1) the phenomenological concept of lifeworld as the unprob-lematic, naively relied on set of resources on which social interaction draws; to (2) the idea that society as a whole can be conceived as “lifeworld,” with the “structural components” of culture, society, and personality; to (3) the notion of the lifeworld as a separate (because communicatively orga-nized) social sphere, involved in interchange with the systemically inte-grated economy and administration. These shifts are particularly apparent in Theory and Communicative Action, but they appear also in the official lifeworld-explicating passages of Between Facts and Norms.

In my view, both (2) and (3) in the preceding paragraph are problem-atic in principle, and neither idea fits well with the line of argument fol-lowed in Between Facts and Norms.

Consider, first, the “components” idea. This idea begins to emerge in Theory of Communicative Action when Habermas is criticizing, from within, the phenomenological conception of the lifeworld. If we under-stand the lifeworld as the background of social interaction, and as the stock of resources on which actors draw, then we see that actors rely on culturally transmitted knowledge, group memberships, and personal iden-tities (including skills, dispositions, and motivations), not just the cultural “stock of knowledge” that Schutz emphasized. As I pointed out, and as Habermas acknowledges, this list corresponds closely to Parsons’s culture/society/personality schema. These resources of action, however, become lifeworld “components” only when Habermas makes a methodological shift. He is interested, he says, in developing the “lifeworld” concept not just as a means for analyzing this or that particular context of action, or even the problematic of social action in general. Instead, his focus is on the lifeworld “as a whole,” and in particular, how the lifeworld reproduces itself through time.107 Not social action so much as society becomes his object of investigation. And at this point, we have the idea that society as a whole can be seen as lifeworld. Habermas quickly converts the resources of “action”—“culture,” “society,” and “personality”—into “structural com-ponents of the lifeworld,” or rather, structural components of society seen as lifeworld.

Page 184: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 173

This last move is puzzling. Why would we necessarily think that soci-ety has “components,” if that term has the ordinary meaning of “parts”? And why would we assume that culture, society, and personality are the appropriate parts?

As Habermas has explained, his interest is in accounting for how socie-ties reproduce themselves through time. Certainly he is right that a soci-ety’s continued existence—as recognizably the same society—depends on its ability to maintain, even through change, a cultural tradition. Clearly, also, a society needs to be able to maintain (again, even through change) its basic social institutions, and equally clearly, it needs to transmit appropri-ate skills, dispositions, and motivations to its members. What Habermas calls cultural reproduction, social integration, and socialization all seem to be necessary functions for a society’s reproduction. But to say that is not to commit ourselves to the idea that the society has “components” and that the components are culture, society, and personality. We can speak of re-productive functions without localizing them in a particular “component” of society. Nor is the “component” idea necessary for Habermas’s ultimate use of the “symbolic reproduction” schema—his account of systems’ ten-dencies to “colonize” the lifeworld and thus to impair the symbolic repro-ductive functions. Here, too, we can speak of functions without localizing them in a “component.”

Similar arguments apply to Habermas’s use of the “components” idea to organize and reformulate Weber’s theory of “rationalization.” As de-scribed in Chapter One, Habermas presents the lifeworld’s rationalization as leading to the differentiation of the various components from one an-other, and second, to the increased importance of discourse in reproduc-ing each component. But the idea that the “society” component has dif-ferentiated from the “culture” component can be expressed more directly: Tradition is less likely to suffice as justification for social institutions or norms. The differentiation of the “personality” component from the “cul-ture” component amounts to the weakening of traditional role limitations that prescribed in advance who would acquire which skills, competences, and dispositions. Habermas’s account of course is more complex than this, but the “component” idea seems to add nothing to the picture.

In my view, the “components” idea is not just unnecessary but posi-tively disadvantageous. It suggests that society has parts, and if the first-order division of lifeworld is into culture, society, and personality, then one naturally wonders where to place more particular social phenomena. The problem, though, is that one-to-one assignment generally is impossible.

Page 185: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 174

Consider, for example, Habermas’s account of the “anchoring” of sys-tems’ steering media. Money and power, Habermas says repeatedly, must be “anchored in the lifeworld,” by which he means “legally institution-alized.” Money is “anchored” through basic principles of private law (es-pecially property and contract), and power is “anchored” through public (especially constitutional) law. But in what component of the lifeworld? Habermas picks the societal component, on the theory that these basic principles are “institutions,” and he uses the term institutional component as a synonym for “societal component.” To me, it seems odd to describe legal principles as “institutions.” Further, as Habermas points out in Between Facts and Norms, legal principles constitute bodies of knowledge, and so they could be considered part of the “culture” component. Or, insofar as legal principles encourage the development of certain motivations, compe-tences, and dispositions, they could be said to belong to the “personality” component.108 Once one starts elaborating on what it means for a medium to be “legally institutionalized,” it becomes clear that very little is accom-plished by selecting a “component” in which the medium is “anchored.” A full explanation of how money and power are legally secured could use the terms culture, society, and personality, but nothing more would be gained by claiming that the medium is “anchored in” “components of the lifeworld” that bear these names.

Or (to borrow again Jeffrey Alexander’s illustration109) consider an organization such as a church. Is it located in the cultural component, the societal component, or the socialization component? Pretty clearly it performs all three functions that Habermas attributes to those “compo-nents”: It transmits and reproduces a cultural tradition; it integrates the members of the church through shared norms and values and through common experiences; and it socializes the members, encouraging them to develop their personal identities in particular ways. Showing how the church fulfills these reproductive functions would be a significant part of explaining the church’s social significance. But claiming that the church is “in” a “component” called “culture,” “society,” or “personality”—or “in” all three—would add nothing to the explanation.

Consider, finally, Habermas’s notions of the political public sphere and civil society. In Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas tried to locate the public sphere within the societal component. But, as he acknowledges in Between Facts and Norms, the public sphere is not an “institution,” “orga-nization,” or “framework of norms.” The public sphere, then, seems diffi-cult to place in the “society” component. Probably for this reason, Between

Page 186: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 175

Facts and Norms does not specify a lifeworld “component” as the public sphere’s location. Civil society, which receives significant discussion only in Between Facts and Norms, generally is assigned an address in the “so-ciety” component. But the network of voluntary associations—more so, even than the particular association of a church—performs the functions of cultural reproduction and socialization that Habermas attributes to the “culture” and “personality” components, not just the “social integration” function he assigns to the “societal” component.

All this is to say that it is fruitless to try to place social phenomena in one or the other lifeworld “component.” But Habermas himself seems to understand the component scheme as inviting that exercise. And if the “components” of the lifeworld are not to be understood as containing sub-parts, then their purpose is unclear. Habermas would do better simply to speak of the reproductive functions—cultural reproduction, social integra-tion, and socialization—and not of the lifeworld “components” to which they ostensibly correspond.

This would be consistent with his suggestion in Between Facts and Norms—not always faithfully followed—that “the communicative concept of the lifeworld breaks with the idea of a whole composed of parts.”110 It would be consistent, also, with the approach of his “circulation of power model.” In that model, the elements of his explanation are civil society, the public sphere, and the various official decision-making political institu-tions. Only as an afterthought does Habermas connect civil society to one of the “components,” and it does not occur to him to find a “component” to house the public sphere.

At the beginning of this section I identified as a second target of criti-cism Habermas’s idea of the lifeworld as a separate sphere of society, differ-entiated from the economic and administrative systems. This conception is the effect of Habermas’s distinction between system and lifeworld.

In Chapter One, I criticized the account of systems’ “uncoupling” from the lifeworld that Habermas gave in Theory of Communicative Action. In that work, Habermas understood “uncoupling” in a radical sense. It meant more than just that new mechanisms of societal integration had developed, allowing action to be coordinated without communicative agreement. Un-coupling meant, also, that the lifeworld’s resources were unnecessary in coordinating media-steered interaction and that the differentiated systems were formally organized, “norm-free” contexts of action. This stylized contrast between the normatively rich lifeworld and the normatively empty systems, I argued, is untenable.

Page 187: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 176

As I have suggested, Between Facts and Norms tacitly revises the sys-tem side of the system/lifeworld distinction. No longer is the political system, at least, “norm free.”111 In fact it is both the recipient of “norma-tively substantive messages” from the public sphere and also, in legislatures and courts, the transmitter and even generator of communicative power through institutionalized discourse. This revised conception of “system” suggests to me that the system/lifeworld distinction itself is unnecessary. The difference between “system” and “lifeworld”—between political cen-ter and periphery—now is not a sharp distinction between the presence and absence of communicative action (or even discourse). Instead, we can speak only of more or less reliance on communicative action versus reliance on command.112

I am not denying all distinctions between the political system, the eco-nomic system, and the rest of the social world. The question, however, is how to account for that rest of the social world. I have argued above against conceiving it as divided into the “structural components” of cul-ture, society, and personality. My suggestion now is that the covering term, lifeworld, also should be dropped.

My argument is based, in the first instance, on the history of the term lifeworld. As I explained in Chapter One, the term originated in Husserl’s later work to mark a contrast between the world of everyday, pretheoreti-cal, taken-for-granted certainties, on one hand, and the world as under-stood by “objectifying” sciences, on the other. Schutz continued this focus on the “mundane,” everyday world, as subjectively experienced. Without that focus, and its implied contrast to other ways of apprehending the so-cial world, it would be difficult to see why one would choose the term lifeworld. Indeed, the term lifeworld seems to me linked to a particular methodological approach in the social sciences—one that investigates the ordinary, everyday world and how human beings experience it.

This approach can be practiced in any sort of setting. It need not be limited to an especially “informal” or “communicatively organized” set-ting. One could analyze the “lifeworld” of the New York diamond busi-ness, or a Mafia family, or floor traders on the New York Stock Exchange, or a conference among social systems theorists. Habermas is right that one would not fully understand the workings of an economy through the “life-world” perspective. But at the same time, the “lifeworld” perspective would disclose insights, relevant to the workings of an economy, that would be unavailable to social systems theory, or for that matter economic theory.

Page 188: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 177

My guess is that the term lifeworld appealed to Habermas because it marked, sharply, the difference between the two theoretical methods he wanted to reconcile and also the difference between the conceptions of social life that those methods disclose. These latter differences were rhe-torically important for Habermas’s “colonization” argument in Theory of Communicative Action: The mechanical systems, born of the living life-world, turn back on the parent to devour it.113 As I have argued, that ver-sion of the system–lifeworld distinction was not defensible, and the story line of Between Facts and Norms requires a different conception: one in which “lifeworld” and “system” do not operate on utterly different prem-ises and principles. The conception of the political system in Between Facts and Norms is not systems-theoretical in any sense that Habermas has in-troduced and defended, nor is the distinction between the “inside” and the “outside” of the political system dramatically different in the respects Habermas’s distinction deems relevant. The term lifeworld—as a reference to a separate sphere of the social world rather than the name of a social-scientific approach—should in my view be dropped.

4.4 au topoietic theory a nd the r efor mul ation of h a ber m as’s soci a l-theor etica l model

I proceed from the conclusions of the preceding section: (1) Theory of Com-municative Action’s system-lifeworld interchange model is untenable, par-ticularly when the objective is to develop a theory of law and democracy; (2) Habermas’s model of the circulation of power is inconsistent with the interchange model, especially in its conception of “systems” and the rela-tion between systems and their environments; and (3) the shift in Haber-mas’s concept of “system” makes his notion of the lifeworld dispensable. But the collapse of Habermas’s media-theoretical conception of systems raises the question: What exactly is Habermas’s conception of a system? And further, how are systems related to their environments?

The first question arises because Habermas’s “circulation of power” model introduces the idea of “the political system” casually. The political system, he says, is differentiated into center and periphery. The character-izations of center and “inner periphery,” however, have the quality of lists rather than concepts. Habermas’s account of the center (or core area) is as follows:

Page 189: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 178

The core area of the political system is formed by the familiar institutional complexes of administration (including the incumbent Government), judicial system, and democratic opinion- and will-formation (which includes parlia-mentary bodies, political elections, and party competition).114

The three branches of government all are represented here, but not in a parallel way. With the “administration” (Verwaltung), Habermas seems to include all the personnel who operate it (“the incumbent Government,” or Regierung).115 With the judicial system, he seems to mean just the sys-tem of courts, not necessarily the judges themselves. For the third branch, one would expect Habermas to say, simply, “legislatures” (or “parliamen-tary bodies”), or perhaps “legislatures (including the elected representa-tives).” Instead, he uses a term for a process rather than an institution—“democratic opinion- and will-formation”—and he explains that the process “includes” institutions (“parliamentary bodies”) and two mecha-nisms or procedures (“political elections, and party competition”).

Thus the “center” includes a mix of institutions, personnel, and proce-dures, all described generally (and misleadingly) as “familiar institutional complexes.” Not only are the items on the list not all of the same type; they do not all have the same function. Legislatures have a lawmaking function. Courts and the administration, Habermas’s “discourse theory” makes clear, have a law-applying function. Nor are all the items on the list official state decision-making entities. Courts and the “administration” are, but “political elections” are decisions, or decision procedures, and se-lection is made by the people rather than by state officials. Similarly, “party competition” does not name a state decision-making entity. Obviously, such competition is relevant to the course of official decision making—it organizes the electoral process and communication within legislative bodies—but it is not itself a state decision-making institution or procedure. In short, Habermas’s characterization of the political system’s center seems ad hoc—a listing of institutions, personnel, and procedures that bear on official decision making but without a clear concept that adequately con-nects the items on the list.

Perhaps the preceding discussion makes too much of the casual way Habermas first characterizes the political system’s “center.” But even if so, what makes the center, so described, a system? Habermas’s earlier concep-tion of “system” emphasized that systems are characterized by steering media tailored to strategic action, with the mechanism of communica-tive agreement generally set aside as a basis for coordinating action. While Habermas still recites this official explication of “system,” the political sys-

Page 190: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 179

tem, for reasons already explained, does not conform to this conception. What, then, makes the political system’s center a “system”?

Similar observations apply to Habermas’s account of the periphery. The inner periphery consists in a collection of institutions and associations per-forming quasi-state functions. There, at least, we have a common theme that connects the items on the list. At the outer periphery, we have first an-other collection of associations and institutions—“customers” and “suppli-ers,” who are linked in ongoing communication with state decision-making entities. We have, further, a network of voluntary associations called “civil society.” But the pattern is broken with Habermas’s inclusion of the politi-cal public sphere in the outer periphery. That sphere, he says, is a network of communication, or a social space, not an association, institution, or collec-tion of associations and institutions.

Habermas, then, has an inconsistent conception of the periphery. It is neither purely a network of communications nor purely a network or col-lection of associations. Nor are the associations he places at the outer pe-riphery necessarily communicating in the (outer peripheral) public sphere. These associations, he says, are rooted in the “core private structures” of the “lifeworld,” and whether they participate in the political public sphere is contingent.116 The civic-social associations probably are better described, as Habermas sometimes does, as the “social basis” of the communication that occurs in the political public sphere.117

Habermas’s account of the outer periphery faces a second and more serious problem. As I have already noted, Habermas does not make clear whether civil society and the political public sphere, as “peripheral” net-works or sites of communication, are inside or outside the system’s bor-ders. I suggested that his theory would require him to place both net-works outside the system’s borders, but only because he stated both that the public sphere is not organized as a “system” and that civil society is a “lifeworld” sphere. Once we see that Habermas’s model of the circulation of power undercuts his prior definitions of system and lifeworld, and in the process undermines the distinction between the two, the question is again open. Should the “peripheral” networks of political communication count as “inside” or “outside” the political system? Or should the term political system be taken to include only official decision-making channels (legislatures, courts, agencies, and the like)? Either way, what establishes the system’s boundaries? If we treat the periphery as “outside,” then the system’s boundaries are determined by whether the communication, or the communicating entity, has official decision-making power. If we treat

Page 191: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 180

the periphery as “inside” the political system, then the system’s boundaries are determined—for the most part—by the character of the communica-tion. (Is it “political” communication or not?)

As Habermas notes, Niklas Luhmann’s theory of law as an “autopoi-etic” system addresses this question of a communicative system’s scope.118 Luhmann’s answer is worth considering to see whether it might provide the beginning for a more rigorous conception of Habermas’s “systems.”

Luhmann defines social “systems” as networks of communication. Communications, as the “elements” and “operations” of a system, establish the system’s boundaries. For Luhmann, then, the legal system is the total-ity of all legal communications. By itself, of course, that does not explain what a “legal communication” is. For that purpose, Luhmann relies on the notion of a system’s code. As already briefly discussed, Luhmann sees a system code as a binary opposition between values—in the case of the legal system, the distinction between legal and illegal (Recht and Unrecht). And so for Luhmann, all communications that invoke the code values “legal” or “illegal” count as operations and elements of the legal system. That means, for example, that the utterance “get off my property,” made by one private citizen to another, would be a communication within the legal system to the extent that it asserts an owner’s legal right to exclude.119 So, too, does the writing of a will or the formation of a contract count as an operation of the legal system. Luhmann thus sees the boundaries of communicative systems expansively. Any communication that invokes the system’s code is an operation of that system.

But Luhmann quickly introduces two distinctions that make this conception of the legal system—the totality of all communication that invokes the legal code—more manageable. First, Luhmann distinguishes between communications that are “decisions” and those that are not. By “legal decisions” he means communications that “change the situation of the law.” Court decisions are obvious examples, but the category of deci-sions includes also “statutes, treaties, administrative acts, wills, land regis-try entries,” and contracts.120 (Notice that even private persons, according to Luhmann, can make law.121) Second, Luhmann sees the legal system as internally differentiated. The axis of differentiation—as in Habermas’s analysis of the political system—is the distinction between center and pe-riphery. Luhmann—as does Habermas, in those passages of Between Facts and Norms that speak of a separate “legal system”—places communication by and to courts at the legal system’s center.122

Page 192: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 181

One parallel, then, is that both Luhmann and Habermas place the relevant decision-making institution at the system’s “center,” with system-relevant communication of other sorts at the periphery. A second parallel is in their respective treatments of the periphery. Habermas, we have seen, emphasizes the role of political and legal communication outside official state decision-making institutions—in the public sphere, and also in civil society. This “informal” communication is important to the system’s self-reproduction, according to Habermas’s model of the circulation of power. Civil society, as a source of “counterknowledge,” may stimulate discus-sion in the public sphere and generate ideas that, one day, may influence the course of lawmaking or other official decision. For his part, Luhmann emphasizes that the “peripheral” status of communication outside the courts—the most important forms of which are legislation and contract—does not mean that such communication is any less important to the sys-tem’s self-reproduction. Instead, the periphery is the source of the system’s “real dynamism.”123 It is the “contact zone[] to other functional systems of society”—much as, for Habermas, the political public sphere is linked to civil society, and civil society is “attuned to how societal problems resonate in the private life spheres.”124 “Peripheral” for both authors thus does not mean unimportant. Instead, it means potential openness to the world be-yond the system’s boundaries.

Let me return to the two problems I raised with Habermas’s revised model. The first problem was that Habermas lacks a coherent concept of “system” once we reject, as both implausible and inconsistent with his pres-ent work, the earlier account with its focus on “steering media.” The sec-ond problem concerned the scope of a system’s boundaries. Do they extend beyond the “central” decision-making body to include the “periphery”?

One way of reconstructing Habermas’s collapsed “system” concept would be to follow Luhmann. By “system,” we then would mean a net-work of communication, not (at least not in the first instance) institutions or personnel. The political system then would include all system-relevant communication. For reasons I have explained in prior work (and here rel-egate to the margins),125 I would not use Luhmann’s idea of the binary code as the means for identifying which communications count as system-relevant. Instead, I would follow an alternative way Luhmann suggests for identifying a system’s unity: the idea of a “circulating symbol,” or (nonbi-nary) communicative theme. “Legal validity” was Luhmann’s example of a “circulating symbol,”126 and it seems to me that communication oriented

Page 193: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 182

toward the theme of legal validity (or invalidity) could be said to be legal communication.

With respect to the political system, Habermas emphasizes the cen-trality of political power, though in more than one sense. Some communi-cation is about the production of legitimate law, a process he describes as the conversion of communicative power into administrative power. Some is about the exercise of administrative power. And some (particularly with respect to elections) is about access to offices with political decision-making power. A good criterion for the political system’s communication, then, might be: “communication related to the generation of, exercise of, or access to political power,”127 where “political power” could be defined further along the lines of Habermas’s distinction between communicative and administrative power.128 All such communication is within the politi-cal system’s boundaries, and other communication is not. This conception of the political system’s boundaries is expansive: It would include politi-cal discussion in the political public sphere, to the extent that it relates sufficiently to the theme of political power. Still, following Habermas’s center/periphery scheme, this communication would be “peripheral,” as compared to communication at the system’s decision-making center.

On this understanding of the political system, however, most com-munication in what Habermas calls “civil society” would be beyond the system’s boundaries. Likely, also, civil society would not count as a system—at least not a differentiated system with a unifying communica-tive theme—because its communication, as Habermas describes it, is too diffuse. In Luhmann’s terms, civil-social communication would be in the political system’s environment. But that raises the question: What is the nature of that system/environment relation? How is communication oc-curring in the voluntary associations of civil society relevant to the po-litical system as we now are conceiving of it? The same sort of question arises also with respect to the political public sphere. If we see the political system as differentiated into center and periphery, how do the two spheres relate to one another?

This question of system/environment relations is the focus of Haber-mas’s polemics against autopoietic theory. According to Habermas, by de-nying relations of input and output among the systems it distinguishes,129 autopoietic theory sees each system as “narcissistically marginalized,”130 “autis[tic],”131 and autopoietically “encapsulate[d]” in “its own shell,”132 speaking its own language and only to itself.133 This “mutual indifference” among systems, Habermas says, is inconsistent with “empirically observed

Page 194: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 183

interdependencies.” And the postulated indifference of systems to their en-vironments makes the democratic process inconceivable. On Luhmann’s premises, says Habermas, “the political process, the public sphere, and po-litical culture present environments whose language the legal system can-not understand.”134

This reading of Luhmann is the occasion for Habermas’s metaphors of law as “hinge” or “transformer” between system and lifeworld. Law, he suggests, operates not as a special “code” or system language, as au-topoietic theory would have it. Instead, law is the translator between the ordinary-language communication of the lifeworld and the system-specific codes of the economic and administrative systems. Because law has the capacity to “communicate[] with the steering media of money and admin-istrative power,” Habermas claims, it is capable of sending “normatively substantive messages” from lifeworld to system.135

Habermas’s account of autopoietic theory, however, is a caricature that exaggerates the distance between his views and Luhmann’s. The feature of autopoietic theory Habermas is reacting to is the idea of systems’ “op-erative closure.” This is the feature that makes systems “autopoietic,” or, self-producing, and in fact it is a tautological consequence of Luhmann’s notion of “system.” If a system’s operations consist in all and only those communications that invoke the system’s code, as Luhmann stipulates, then it is “closed” with respect to those operations. The system’s opera-tions establish the system’s boundaries, and the system is in fact coexten-sive with its constituent operations.136

What Luhmann is rejecting here is the idea that information can cross system boundaries unproblematically. Communications have system- specific meaning, he says, and so a communication proper to one system is in the first instance just “noise” to another system.137 Further, to the extent that systems “observe” each other—that is, to the extent that communica-tion in one system refers to another system—the observation is framed by the standards and procedures of the observing system.138 External refer-ence is in that way at the same time self-reference.

These are the claims to which Habermas’s polemic attaches. Closure with respect to a code means, for Habermas, that each system is “encapsu-lated in its own shell,” with its own “semantics” and unintelligible to other systems. The impossibility of direct communication between systems means, for Habermas, that the systems are “autistic,” speaking only to themselves. The connection between self-reference and external reference means, for Habermas, that systems are “narcissistically marginalized.” If

Page 195: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 184

operative closure, as previously described, were the whole story for auto-poietic theory, then Habermas’s reading might be justified.

But operative closure is only part of the story. With that idea Luhmann pairs the idea of “cognitive openness.” Systems are operatively closed, in the sense that their operations do not cross system boundaries. By definition, they establish the system’s boundaries, and the system is coextensive with the communications that are the system’s operations. But these communica-tions may, and ordinarily do, refer to events, processes, and the like, in the system’s environment. In that sense, systems are “cognitively open” to their environments. Luhmann thus does not deny the possibility of “external ref-erence.” Instead, his point is simply that such reference is not a neutral mir-roring of the world. To the extent that communicative systems have differen-tiated from one another, they have developed distinctive standards, criteria, and procedures and thus distinctive ways of apprehending the world.139 Law is not science, and science is not art. Luhmann’s point is simply that we can-not presume identity of meaning across system boundaries.

But how, on Luhmann’s view, is one system “cognitively open” to an-other, when in the first instance the systems’ respective streams of com-munication present not “information” to one another but just “noise”? Luhmann’s answer is in terms of the notions of “irritation” (or “perturba-tion”) and structural coupling. Communication in one system may “ir-ritate” another system’s communication to the extent that it “registers” or “resonates” in the irritated system’s structures, categories, or criteria. The meaning of the communication, however, will be different in the two systems. To the extent that the irritating communication can be neither screened out as irrelevant nor easily processed within the irritated system’s categories, Luhmann maintains, it may stimulate change in those catego-ries. This possibility is the autopoietic equivalent for what more standard versions of social systems theory call “adaptation to the environment.” Au-topoietic theory, however, emphasizes more strongly that the change is not simply induced from without but generated from within.

Through “structural coupling,” Luhmann says, this process of mutual irritation can be made more systematic, making systems more responsive to one another. One meaning Luhmann gives “structural coupling” is that one system “presupposes specific states or changes” in another system and “relies on them.”140 Courts, for example, presuppose that their deci-sions will be enforced by the political system, and thus legal and political discourse are “structurally coupled” in this sense. This “coupling” seems consistent with Habermas’s notion of the reciprocal functions that law and

Page 196: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 185

political power perform for one another. Another meaning Luhmann gives “structural coupling” is that a structure or central category might be com-mon to, though understood differently in, two systems. For Luhmann, leg-islation is a mechanism that structurally couples the legal and political sys-tems, with different “prehistories” and “possibilities for connection” in the two systems.141 From the perspective of the political system, a statute’s “pre-history” is the political maneuvering that led to its enactment. By shifting (even if slightly) the balance of power between government and opposition, the statute’s enactment creates fresh possibilities for future political maneu-vering. From the perspective of the legal system, by contrast, the statute’s “prehistory” is in the dutiful following of legally prescribed legislative pro-cedures. As for new “possibilities for connection,” the statute’s enactment creates new valid law that changes the legal position for future cases.142

Law is full of concepts and categories that have this sort of “double significance”143—one meaning in legal communication and a related but not identical meaning in the communication of another system. A good example is the idea of property. Probably the dominant legal conception of property is expressed in the familiar “bundle of rights” formula.144 With the reference to “rights,” the formula refers “internally,” to the legal sys-tem’s own categories and procedures. But the rights in the bundle—to use, exclusive possession, disposition, profit—correspond to economic inter-ests. The legal concept of property thus also refers externally and allows (in Luhmann’s term) “observation” of the economic system. But despite the reference to economic “interests,” the legal meaning of property does not coincide with its economic meaning—as I have argued elsewhere, with reference to “takings” law.145

Consider two further examples of this kind of structural coupling. First, the concept of “insanity” in criminal law is informed by its counter-part in psychiatry. But as the Supreme Court has noted, the two concepts “vary substantially,” given the different senses of “individual responsibility and competency” with which the two disciplines operate.146 Second, the use of experts in litigation allows incorporation of scientific knowledge into litigation, and part of the federal admissibility standard is whether the “reasoning or methodology underlying the testimony is scientifically valid.” The other part of the standard, however, refers to whether the in-formation in question would “assist the trier of fact to understand or de-termine a fact in issue.” In announcing this standard, the Supreme Court noted differences between legal and scientific inquiry—specifically, in fi-nality or revisability of conclusions, time constraints on the proceedings,

Page 197: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 186

and the purposes for which knowledge is to be used.147 To this list one might add the different standards of proof and the different capacities of the relevant inquirers.

The idea of structural coupling suggests an important set of problems. The goal of improving the system’s “openness”—its ability to incorporate insights from other systems of communication—must be accomplished through mechanisms, procedures, and standards of the “observing” sys-tem. These of course can be modified, but they are not infinitely plastic. Improving a system’s “external” reference always is, at the same time, a problem of the system’s self-reference.

Much more could be said about the idea of structural coupling, but this quick sketch will have to suffice.148 It shows, I think, that Habermas is wrong to dismiss autopoietic theory so quickly as a theory of “autistic,” “narcissistically marginalized” systems, “encapsulated in their own shells” and speaking only to themselves.

At the same time, however, I think there is substance to a criticism of autopoietic theory that Habermas made five years before Between Facts and Norms: that Luhmann errs in conceiving of systems as observing, com-municating subjects. Habermas argues that autopoietic theory is, in effect, an appropriation of (what Habermas calls and condemns as) the “philoso-phy of the subject.”149 Whether or not that is so, I agree that Luhmann is wrong to present systems—for example, the legal system—as unitary observers and communicators. In my view, the conception is inconsistent with Luhmann’s acknowledgment that systems like the legal system are themselves differentiated—in the case of the legal system, differentiated into “central” and “peripheral” circuits of communication. Further, in distinguishing between decision and argument, Luhmann understands legal communications to have different effects and different possibilities for connection to future communications. These differences among com-munications are flattened out by statements that present “the legal system” as communicator and observer.

Luhmann’s account of the center/periphery distinction suggests, fur-ther, that some of the totalizing claims he makes for systems theory need to be trimmed back. Like Habermas, Luhmann distinguishes between “cen-ter” and “periphery” by looking to communications’ institutional site. Le-gal communication in the courts, he says, is central; communication in leg-islatures is peripheral. Courts and legislatures, however, are not elements of autopoietic theory. That theory conceives of society as the system of all communications, of the legal system as the totality of all legal communica-

Page 198: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 187

tions, and so forth. Only communications are elements and operations of a system. But when Luhmann begins to analyze the legal system, he needs more than elements and operations. He draws on a more conventional sort of social theory that speaks not just of systems and their elements but also of institutions—like legislatures and courts. Underneath the purity of auto-poietic theory is a much more ordinary way of looking at the social world.

What I am suggesting is a double focus. The networks of commu-nication that Luhmann calls “systems” present possibilities for ongoing communication. Such networks make some possibilities more likely and tend to close off others. But which selections will be made depends on the “place” in the system at which the communication occurs—by which I mean the social site of communication, as identified by a more conven-tional theory that speaks of agents and institutions. It depends also on the nature of those agents, individual or collective, who are communicating. This is not to say that “systems,” as Luhmann conceives of them, are not both constraining and enabling. What one can say, and whether one will say it, is not simply a matter of purely free agency. But neither is it best described simply as an operation of the system.

Instead of systems, then, we might better speak of “discourses” (or, al-ternatively, “communicative networks”). In addition to those “discourses,” we need an account of both the sites of discourse and those who discourse. Luhmann probably would not have accepted these suggestions as friendly amendments. But they strike me as improvements on an already powerful as well as brilliantly creative theory.

Others have argued that while autopoietic insights are promising for le-gal theory, Luhmann’s work requires modification or supplementation. My suggestion that we see systems as discourses draws on some of the work of Gunther Teubner, Luhmann’s ambassador to the English-speaking world and important legal theorist in his own right. Teubner’s essay “Rethinking Legal Pluralism,” for example,150 takes the key concepts of autopoietic legal theory to be “perturbation” (or, “irritation” as described above), “struc-tural coupling, and coevolution.” The special case of law’s relation to soci-ety, however, requires in Teubner’s view a recasting of the idea of structural coupling. Because law and other social fields belong to the same society, Teubner argues, they cannot be conceived simply as two independent au-topoietic systems. And the idea of an autopoietic system within a broader autopoietic system

presses for modifications of the general concept: Is not law, in relation to other cultural provinces like politics, science, economy, religion, culture, much more

Page 199: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 188

“open” than the general concept of structural coupling would permit? Is not “interdiscursivity” in law and society much more dense than mere transitory perturbations could ever produce? And do we not find in the coevolution of law and society significantly more elective affinities than the mere coexistence of structural drift would provide for? To use our metaphor as a theme with variations: “order from music” instead of “order from noise”?151

Teubner goes on to conceive of the relations among systems as “interdis-cursivity” and the latter in terms of “a clear-cut separation of autonomous (not semiautonomous) discourses” that, “at the same time,” are structur-ally coupled. Not the details of Teubner’s proposal but its general strategy of seeing systems as discourses or communicative networks is what inter-ests me here.152

A second figure who, like Teubner, defends a critical and selective ap-preciation of Luhmann’s work is more central to Anglo-American think-ing about law: the late Sir Neil MacCormick. Throughout his Institutions of Law (2007), MacCormick praises Luhmann’s work, particularly the idea of the binary code and the notion of structural coupling.153 Yet in the same paragraph that he endorses these autopoietic concepts, MacCormick eclecti-cally uses ideas of system “input” and “output” that would horrify purist autopoietic theorists.154 MacCormick explains that “to accept system-theory for the light it sheds . . . does not require one to abandon critical judgment in respect of some less convincing parts of the theory.”155 He thus rejects the totalizing quality of Luhmann’s thought, where the same basic autopoietic concepts and principles apply to any attempt to understand reality, whether natural or social.156 MacCormick distances himself in particular from the idea that “individual human beings enter sociology as ‘psychic systems.’ ” I agree with MacCormick that the totalizing aspect of systems theory is to be avoided—though, for my part, I would join Luhmann in avoiding the input/output metaphor. Something like MacCormick’s “institutional” ap-proach to law seems to me an important supplement to autopoietic theory.157

Particularly as amended, this conception of systems as discourses is consistent with what Habermas is trying to accomplish with his model of the circulation of power and his idea of law as translator among discourses. The main goal of Habermas’s “communications theory of society” is to show, in social-theoretical terms, how the “informal” discourses of the po-litical public sphere can influence the institutionalized discourses of deci-sion at the political system’s center. The possibility of this influence, he says, depends in turn on the openness of the political public sphere to the “impulses” of civil society.

Page 200: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 189

Autopoietic theory, particularly as revised, provides a way for Haber-mas to account for these connections among different circuits of commu-nication. The “center” of the political system institutionalizes official dis-courses that are directed toward decision. Habermas distinguishes from that network of communication the political public sphere. This network of communication is “peripheral,” on Habermas’s account, but if we see his “political system” as a communicative network whose theme is political power, then the political public sphere is within the boundaries of the polit-ical system. “Civil society,” by contrast, does not name a circuit or network of communication that is closed by a single theme. Rather, “civil society” is the collective name for voluntary associations in which communication, but not just a single specialized sort of communication, can take place. In terms of autopoietic theory, civil society is an environment to the political system, though not one organized as a system or particular discourse.

What Habermas’s account of democracy prescribes is, in effect, irrita-tion and structural coupling among the three communicative networks he distinguishes. Recall, first, his account of the relation between civil society and the political public sphere. The voluntary associations of civil soci-ety are “attuned to how societal problems resonate in private life spheres.” Moreover, Habermas says, “the great issues of the last decades” were first discussed in these voluntary associations—and as examples of these issues he mentions the nuclear-arms race, the risks of nuclear power and genetic engineering, ecological issues, the “dramatically progressing impoverish-ment of the Third World and problems of the world economic order,” feminism, immigration, and multiculturalism. When first raised in civil-social organizations, none of these issues was on the agenda of the politi-cal public sphere. But the members of the “public”—by which Habermas means those who participate in the political public sphere—are “recruited” from these voluntary associations. The process of getting general public attention to these issues required, both literally and in terms of autopoietic theory, irritation: “dramatize[d] presentations” that capture the attention of the mass media. “Only through their controversial presentation in the media,” Habermas says, “do such topics reach the larger public and subse-quently gain a place on the ‘public agenda.’ ”158

This “irritation” of the political public sphere’s communicative network thus required strategic choices by concerned individuals and groups. For that reason, it is not readily explained simply as an operation of a “system”—autopoietic theory unamended. But unsatisfying, too, is the mixed meta-phor Habermas uses to describe the process of agenda making: Civil-social

Page 201: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 190

organizations, he says, “distill and transmit” responses to social problems “in amplified form to the public sphere.”159 What the metaphor obscures is what autopoietic theory suggests: A communicative network is capable of screening out, as “noise,” a communication that does not conform to generally prevailing standards and assumptions. Irritation may, but hardly is guaranteed to, transform the network’s prevailing patterns.

The relation between political public sphere (“periphery”) and decision-making institutions (“center”) is, from the point of view of autopoietic theory, a relation between subsystems of the political system.160 In other words, the two communicative networks are distinct. Habermas would not disagree. He distinguishes between informal public discourse and in-stitutionalized discourses of decision-making institutions. The problem is to ensure that the political public sphere “influences” the course of official decision.

Habermas’s reconstructive account of the “constitutional state” identi-fies a number of mechanisms that are designed to link the informal and formal discourses. These mechanisms are, in autopoietic terms, mecha-nisms of structural coupling. The most obvious is the requirement of periodic democratic elections. Like the other mechanisms of structural coupling, elections do not require that a particular communication have the same meaning in the communicative networks they link. Votes, if in-tended by voters as a statement of personal commitment, may “irritate” the official network of communication as threats to or confirmations of the balance of political power and the terms of access to power. Elections organize and focus these irritations and make outcomes legally binding.

Similarly, guarantees of free speech, association, press, and assembly, “provide a continuous influx”161 of irritations into the communicative networks that operate through official decision-making institutions. So does the requirement that official debate and decision making be public. And so do mechanisms that provide for public hearings and participation in administrative decision making. None of these mechanisms guarantees that “normatively substantive messages” will resonate in official political decision making just as they do in the political public sphere. But they do establish and organize the (partial) openness of the political “center” to its “periphery.”

I think, in short, that Habermas’s new account of law and democracy has more in common with autopoietic theory than with his earlier concep-tions of system and lifeworld. The peculiar thing about the “communica-tion theory of society,” however, is that Habermas ritually invokes those

Page 202: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

“Communication Theory of Society” 191

earlier conceptions, even as his “circulation of power” model implicitly transforms them. Given the flaws that the system/lifeworld model had from the start, and given its incompatibility with a normative theory of radi-cal democracy, Habermas would do well to abandon it explicitly—but also to theorize more rigorously the replacement model of the “circulation of power.” This chapter has made suggestions in that direction. My consider-ation of Habermas’s thinking in Between Facts and Norms is now complete.

Page 203: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

chapter five

After Between Facts and Norms: Religion in the Public Square,

Multiculturalism, and the “Postnational Constellation”

In the years since Between Facts and Norms, Habermas has extended his project in three directions. First, prompted in part by his 1995 debate with John Rawls, he has joined the growing discussion about religion’s place in public political discourse. Second, probably motivated both by the Rawls debate and by immigration-related developments, Habermas has sought to come to terms with multiculturalism. Third, and in contrast to the im-plicitly nation-state–based model of Between Facts and Norms, Habermas has considered the possibilities of democracy in what he now calls “the postnational constellation,” with particular attention to the integration project of the European Union. In this line of his work, Habermas has suggested a partial reformulation of the “circulation of power” model that occupied my attention in the last chapter. Moreover, his discussion of the postnational constellation extends to a reformulation of Kant’s program of “perpetual peace”—a reformulation that Habermas calls, alternatively, the “constitutionalization of international law” and the idea of “world society without a world government.”

This chapter considers, in turn, each of these extensions of Habermas’s project.

Page 204: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 193

5.1 r eligion in the public squa r e

5.1.1 Background: The Rawls/Audi Restrictive View and Its Critics

The publication of Rawls’s Political Liberalism in 1993 prompted an ex-tensive debate about the role of religion in politics and particularly about the role of religion in public political discussion among citizens. His views, together with those later expressed by Robert Audi, have been taken to define one side of the controversy: the side arguing that citizens in liberal democracies should exercise restraint on public employment of religious reasons. Among those on the other side of the controversy, the views of Robert Wolterstorff and Paul J. Weithman have stood out. For his part, Habermas himself takes these thinkers to define his starting point, and I follow his strategy here.

The central premise of Rawls’s political liberalism is what he calls “rea-sonable pluralism”: that free societies are necessarily divided by “incompat-ible yet reasonable comprehensive doctrines.”1 By “comprehensive” doc-trines, Rawls means those that “include conceptions of what is of value in human life, and ideals of personal character, as well as ideals of friend-ship and familial and associational relationships, and much else that is to inform our conduct, and in the limit to our life as a whole.”2 Religious conceptions are clear (though not the only) examples.3 Rawls assumes that each citizen holds some comprehensive doctrine.4 Rawls’s strategy of deal-ing with reasonable pluralism is to require that the political conception he develops be “freestanding,” that is, not dependent on any particular comprehensive doctrine.5 In Rawls’s metaphor, this freestanding political conception can fit like a “module” into the comprehensive doctrine of each citizen.6 The political conception as module thus “in different ways fits into and can be supported by various reasonable comprehensive doctrines that endure in the society regulated by it.”7 In this way, Rawls argues, we can attain an “overlapping consensus” over a political conception of justice despite enduring and reasonable disagreement over comprehensive views.8

Rawls defines the “reason” of a political society as its way of “formulat-ing its plans, of putting its ends in an order of priority and of making its decisions accordingly.” This “public reason” organizes and regulates public political debate. Although Rawls also discusses the positive elements of pub-lic reason—he refers, for example, to the facilitative “guidelines and rules” of “public inquiry”9—he emphasizes the constraints it places on the kinds of reasons to be offered in public debate. With regard to “constitutional

Page 205: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 194

essentials” and “matters of basic justice,”10 Rawls maintains, “political values alone” are to be invoked.11 These “limits of public reason” do not apply ei-ther to personal deliberation about politics or to political discussion within voluntary associations but only to “citizens when they engage in political advocacy in the public forum” or to citizens when they vote on fundamental matters, as well as to “political parties,” candidates, and “other groups who support them.”12

But why these limits, particularly on the discussion of citizens? Rawls assumes that liberal democracy implies relatively deep commonality. His “ideal of democratic citizenship” requires that citizens “should be ready to explain the basis of their actions to one another in terms each could reasonably expect that others might endorse as consistent with their free-dom and equality.”13 On one view of the matter, this requirement would exclude religious reasons—and other reasons drawn from comprehensive doctrines—from being offered in citizens’ discussion of constitutional es-sentials or issues of basic justice: These are not the kind of reasons that, under conditions of reasonable pluralism, all can be expected to endorse.

Rawls calls this understanding of public reason “the exclusive view.”14 This view, Rawls suggests, might be the most appropriate one for the ideal case: a “more or less well ordered”15 society in which “members recognize a firm overlapping consensus of reasonable doctrines” and are “not stirred by any deep disputes.” There, “invoking only political values is the obvious and the most direct way for citizens to honor the ideal of public reason and to meet their duty of civility.”16

In other sets of circumstances, however, what Rawls calls the “inclu-sive view” is more appropriate. In one such set of circumstances, society is “nearly well-ordered” but faces a “serious dispute . . . in applying one of its principles of justice”—serious enough for “those of different faiths . . . to doubt the sincerity of one another’s allegiance to fundamental political val-ues.”17 Here, according to Rawls, the dispute might be resolved if members of the contending groups were to explain to one another how their com-prehensive views “affirm” shared political values. In this way, the break in trust could be repaired. Invoking comprehensive doctrines in these cir-cumstances, and to this limited degree, would be a way of “honor[ing] the ideal of public reason.”18

Deeper reliance on comprehensive doctrines, Rawls suggests, would be appropriate in the case of a society that is not well ordered and faces “a profound division about constitutional essentials.” Rawls’s examples here come from the abolitionist and civil rights movements. In arguing that

Page 206: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 195

slavery was contrary to God’s law, Rawls maintains, the “nonpublic rea-son” that abolitionists invoked “supported the clear conclusions of pub-lic reason.” In so doing, they might well “have seen their actions as the best way to bring about a well-ordered and just society in which the ideal of public reason could eventually be honored.” Similar analysis, Rawls thinks, applies to Martin Luther King Jr.’s advocacy. Here too, the inclu-sive view of public reason would be appropriate.

In his 1997 essay, “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,”19 Rawls re-considers this case-by-case approach to the question whether citizens may invoke reasons from their comprehensive doctrines in discussion of con-stitutional essentials or matters of basic justice. Rather than the “inclu-sive view of public reason,” Rawls now refers instead to “the wide view of public political culture,” but under this latter heading he again invokes the two special sets of circumstances justifying reliance upon comprehensive doctrines.20 In addition, and most important, Rawls now states a general “proviso” that marks out a much more religion-friendly position:

Reasonable comprehensive doctrines, religious or nonreligious, may be intro-duced in public political discussion at any time, provided that in due course proper political reasons—and not reasons given solely by comprehensive doctrines—are presented that are sufficient to support whatever the compre-hensive doctrines are said to support.21

The difficult issues of how, how soon, and by whom political reasons must be provided “must be worked out in practice” and are governed “by the nature of the public political culture.”22

For most recent discussion of religion’s role in the public square, Rawls’s notion of the proviso has been a basic point of reference. In this debate, on the side of restraining religious reasons, Robert Audi is perhaps best known. Like Rawls, Audi considers not what citizens have a legal right to say in public political debate but instead what a proper “ethics of citi-zenship” requires.23 And like Rawls, Audi sees democratic discussion as tending to require citizens to address each other with reasons to which all might agree.24 But the scope of political debate in which religious reasons are problematic is broader for Audi than for Rawls: Whereas Rawls consid-ers restrictions only with respect to constitutional essentials and matters of basic justice, Audi considers, more generally, all citizen advocacy of coercive laws or public policies.25

Audi announces two principles restrictive of religious reasons.26 Ac-cording to the first, the principle of “secular rationale”:

Page 207: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 196

One has a prima facie obligation not to advocate or support any law or public policy that restricts human conduct, unless one has, and is willing to offer, adequate secular reason for this advocacy or support (say for one’s vote).27

By “secular reason,” Audi means “one whose normative force . . . does not evidentially depend on the existence of God (or on denying it), or on theo-logical considerations, or on the pronouncements of a person or institution qua religious authority.”28 According to Audi, only in “special contexts,” where “candor or other considerations require laying out all of one’s main reasons,” should a citizen’s advocacy for a coercive law or policy invoke religious reasons.29 While Audi does not give an example of such a “special context,” he seems to mean something like what Rawls calls “declaration”: a form of discourse in which the speaker shows how a political position or conception of justice is consistent with, and even emerges from, the speaker’s comprehensive doctrine.30 Even here, however, the speaker (on Rawls’s analysis as well as Audi’s) must present a secular argument suf-ficient to justify the position.

The second principle is the “principle of secular motivation.” In Audi’s formulation:

One has a (prima facie) obligation to abstain from advocacy or support of a law or public policy that restricts human conduct, unless one is sufficiently motivated by (normatively) adequate secular reason.31

A motivation is “sufficient,” Audi explains, if (1) the reason explains the action and (2) “one would act on it even if, other things remaining equal, one’s other reasons were eliminated.” It follows that the presence of a reli-gious motivation is not necessarily impermissible, provided that it is accom-panied by a secular motivation that would by itself be sufficient to generate the action.32 Indeed, Audi allows, religious convictions may be “genetically basic,” “motivationally primary,” and “evidentially adequate.”33

Audi maintains that his restrictions on religious reasons neither make religion “purely private” nor “marginalize” it.34 His opponents disagree. The opponents of the reason-restrictive position to whom Habermas most attends are Paul Weithman and Nicholas Wolterstorff.

Weithman opposes his position to what he calls “the standard ap-proach,” an approach for which he sees Rawls and Audi as the key propo-nents. This standard approach, Weithman argues, errs in its requirement that reasons in political debate must be, in a special sense, “accessible,” “intelligible,” or “comprehensible” to all.35 Against (in particular) Audi’s position that only secular reasons meet this requirement, Weithman asks:

Page 208: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 197

“Why think that adequately informed, rational adults cannot see the reason-giving force of religious reasons?”36 The question is apt with respect to secularly minded as well as religious citizens. As Weithman observes: “I may reject utilitarianism, but I can still see utilitarian considerations as reasons of a sort. I can still see the people who offer them as not unrea-sonable, even when they offer them as the basis for settling fundamental political questions.”37 Why are matters different with religious rather than utilitarian reasons?

In addition to questioning the basic premise of the Rawls/Audi “stan-dard approach,” Weithman presents an empirical argument that institution-alized religion, and religious argument, play an important role in promot-ing American democracy.38 The argument has two parts. First, according to Weithman, churches39 contribute to what he calls “realized citizenship,” particularly among the poor and minorities. Second, Weithman maintains, specifically religious argument contributes a distinctive and valuable moral vocabulary and set of concerns to democratic political discourse.

By “realized citizenship,” Weithman means that one has both “real op-portunities” as well as “legally guaranteed opportunities to participate” and that implies in turn that one has “the resources of information, skills, networks and influence to take advantage of ” citizenship’s opportunities.40 Weithman mentions churches’ contribution, through social services, to “the material conditions associated with democratic equality.”41 Further, he observes, membership in a church provides a locus for political informa-tion, discussion, and recruitment; exposes the citizen to encouragement to vote or otherwise as participate (twice as likely, Weithman’s study sug-gests, as in the workplace setting); and offers opportunities for volunteer service that both develops politically relevant skills and suggests a con-nection between moral and political issues.42 Weithman emphasizes par-ticularly the importance of church organizations for political participation among African Americans, especially “low status” African Americans, and the poor.43 Without the activity of churches, Weithman maintains, these “segments” of the population would be largely excluded from, or at least less represented in, the political process.44

In the second part of his argument that religion contributes impor-tantly to American political life, Weithman is particularly interested to combat the assumption that its influence is either illiberal in its mode of preference-formation45 or (a slightly different point) politically conservative in content. On the second score, Weithman emphasizes the arguments, for example by the Catholic Church, for greater economic equality,46 as well as

Page 209: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 198

the arguments by Martin Luther King Jr. and other theologians for racial equality.47 Since 1995, the Catholic Church has pressed arguments against the death penalty.48 Weithman notes that significant advocacy efforts, by the Catholic Church and other churches, have been devoted to the pro-motion of children’s health, the protection of refugees and immigrants, campaign finance reform, affirmative action, food stamps, health care for the poor, and humanitarian aid to Africa.49 These church efforts have been reflected in the views, reasons, and arguments presented by individual church members.50 These issues and concerns, of course, are more com-monly associated with the left end of the political spectrum than with the right. Weithman acknowledges that the Catholic Church (and of course some Protestant denominations) engages in religious advocacy against abortion as well as against assisted suicide. But it is a “stereotype” of re-ligious argument, Weithman says, to focus on “pro-life” positions and ig-nore the many other issues on which religious advocacy assumes a more politically “liberal” position.51 This stereotype, Weithman suggests, likely accounts for some of the appeal, to some political liberals, of restrictions on religious arguments in politics.52 Finally, Weithman argues with respect to the content of religious advocacy, religious argument may in comparison to standard political speech use different and more striking terminology and metaphor, thereby casting political issues in a new light and encourag-ing “sustained reflection on the moral dimensions of public policy.”53

On the basis of his argument against the foundational Rawls/Audi no-tion of accessibility (or comprehensibility, or intelligibility), as well as his “empirical” argument for the contribution religious organizations and in-dividuals make to American democracy, Weithman defends the position that “citizens may offer exclusively religious arguments in public debate and . . . they may rely on religious reasons when they cast their votes.”54 Specifically, against Audi’s principle of secular rationale, Weithman argues that Audi overestimates the danger of civil strife that otherwise would be unleashed; against both that principle and Audi’s principle of secular moti-vation, Weithman contends that Audi undervalues religious contributions to democracy.55 But missing from Weithman’s argument, in my opinion, is an argument against Rawls and the proviso. Why is it impermissible to require religious citizens to provide “in due course” a secular argument in addition to their religious argument?

Nicholas Wolterstorff, like Rawls and Audi, considers “the role of citi-zen in a liberal democracy.”56 His central question is whether religious rea-sons may be determinative in debating or deciding political issues. Like

Page 210: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 199

Weithman, Wolterstorff concludes that a proper ethics of citizenship places no restraint on the use of religious arguments in citizens’ political debate or voting.57 He goes beyond Weithman, perhaps, in arguing against any general restraint on religious reasons by officeholders.58

Wolterstorff, correctly in my opinion, sees that he opposes not a uni-fied “liberal” or “standard” approach but a “family of positions,” with a common element being some form of restraint on religious reasons.59 He begins his discussion by noting what, at first glance, would be (in his view) a “flagrant conflict” between restraints on reasons and the idea of liberal democracy.60 And why, he asks, a restraint on religious reasons in particu-lar? The answer, he thinks, cannot be that such a restraint is necessary for social peace. While that contention was “cogent” in seventeenth-century Europe, we “now have behind us a long history of religious tolerance,” and “American society at the end of the twentieth century is a different mat-ter.” Further, Wolterstorff observes—citing American abolitionism, as well as political resistance movements in Nazi Germany, communist Europe, and apartheid South Africa—“Many of the social movements in the mod-ern world that have moved societies in the direction of liberal democracy have been deeply and explicitly religious in their orientation.” And secular systems such as communism or fascism, Wolterstorff says, have been the forms in which most brutality has been carried out.61

This first argument, like Weithman’s argument about the contribu-tions religious organizations and citizens make to American democracy, could be called “empirical.” Wolterstorff also engages the theoretical logic behind the positions of his opponents, both Rawls and Audi.

Against Rawls, Wolterstorff argues that basing a political position on a comprehensive doctrine, including a religious doctrine, is consistent with treating others as free and equal citizens with equal political voice. While democracy requires a certain amount of agreement about conclusions, fair majority-vote procedures are sufficient.62 According to Wolterstorff, Rawls overemphasizes the likelihood63 and need for agreement on prin-ciples or reasons. “If I can defend a policy I accept with reasons that you find cogent,” he asks, “what difference does it make to you whether those were also for me the determinative reasons?”64 In an interesting argument, Wolterstorff further suggests that “the liberal”—prototypically Rawls but also Audi—is a communitarian of sorts, based however on common rea-sons rather than shared values:

What is striking about our contemporary proponents of the liberal position is that they are still looking for a politics that is the politics of a community with

Page 211: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 200

a shared perspective. They see that that perspective cannot, in our societies, be a comprehensive perspective. . . . So they propose scaling down our expecta-tions. Take a society that is more or less a liberal democracy, and then consider a single aspect of that society, a single dimension: the political. . . . The per-spective which it embodies will be the shared political culture of the society. The liberal is not willing to live with a politics of multiple communities. He still wants communitarian politics. He is trying to discover, and to form, the relevant community. He thinks we need a shared political basis; he is trying to discover and nourish that basis. For the reasons given, I think that the attempt is hopeless and misguided. We must learn to live with a politics of multiple communities.65

According to Wolterstorff, citizenship in a liberal democracy requires honor-ing others in their particularity, not just their abstract freedom and equality. That means listening to others in political discourse, even when the message comes from what might be called a “comprehensive doctrine.” This, Wol-terstorff argues, is the proper duty of civility: “listening to the other person with a willingness to learn and to let one’s mind be changed.” And that means without restriction of the kind of reasons that may be offered. 66

Finally—and this is the argument that most engages Habermas— Wolterstorff argues that restriction on religious reasons, even if presented in an ethics of citizenship and not a legal code, unfairly burdens the free exercise of religion. He would find this unfairness particularly clear in Audi’s position, according to which restrictions are required only for reli-gious reasons, not for reasons derived from other comprehensive positions. But he notes that the same discrimination is likely under Rawls’s position: While the use of religious reasons is easily detectable, reliance on secular comprehensive doctrines (such as utilitarianism or nationalisms) is less ap-parent. And more fundamental, Wolterstorff argues, the religious convic-tions of “a good many” prescribe that

they ought to base their decisions concerning fundamental issues of justice on their religious convictions. They do not view it as an option whether or not to do so. . . . Accordingly, to require of them that they not base their decisions and discussions concerning political issues on their religion is to infringe, in-equitably, on the free exercise of their religion.67

This point is part of the motivation behind Habermas’s criticisms of Rawls and Audi.

5.1.2 Habermas and the “Institutional Translation Proviso”

Habermas entered this controversy with his 2005 book Between Nat-uralism and Religion (translated into English in 2008). He gives Rawls

Page 212: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 201

“immense credit” for launching the debate68 but notes (and this will be his view as well) that Rawls’s position has been criticized as “overly nar-row”69 and “rather restrictive.”70 While Habermas acknowledges the force of Weithman’s “empirical” and “functional” argument that religious or-ganizations have contributed much to American democracy,71 he sees the “central objection” to Rawls as Wolterstorff ’s. As Habermas characterizes that objection: “A state cannot encumber its citizens, to whom it guaran-tees freedom of religion, with duties that are incompatible with pursuing a devout life—it cannot expect something impossible of them.”72 On the issue of whether citizens may rely exclusively on religious reasons in pub-lic political discourse, Habermas’s position turns out to be much closer to Weithman and Wolterstorff than to Rawls and (especially) Audi. But Habermas’s “institutional translation proviso,” presented as an alternative to Rawls’s proviso, emphasizes against Weithman and Wolterstorff that the world of discussion among officeholders and candidates must be a world of secular reasons only.

Habermas presents his argument as part of “postmetaphysical think-ing.” What Habermas particularly means by “postmetaphysical” in this context is a refusal either to affirm or deny the truth of religious claims—either of which, he seems to believe, would itself be a metaphysical asser-tion. Habermas describes his position as

an agnostic, but nonreductionist form of postmetaphysical thinking. It re-frains, on the one hand, from passing judgment on religious truth, while in-sisting (in a non-polemical fashion) on making a strict demarcation between faith and knowledge. On the other hand, it rejects a scientistically truncated conception of reason and the exclusion of religious doctrines from the geneal-ogy of reason.73

Postmetaphysical thinking, he says, “refrains from making ontological pronouncements on the constitution of being as such.”74

Habermas also characterizes his position as “secular” rather than “secu-larist.”75 By “secular,” Habermas means that he does not affirm the truth of religious claims. That is consistent with his description of postmetaphysical thinking as “agnostic.”76 By “secularist” (or “laicist”77), on the other hand, Habermas means one who “adopts a polemical stance towards religious doctrines.”78 The secularist views religion as a retrograde position that, at least ideally, “will ultimately dissolve in the acid of scientific criticism.” For the secularist, religious thinking has nothing positive to contribute to political discussion, and a refusal to take it seriously is consistent with democratic citizenship.79 But for Habermas, this kind of secularist thinking may be “just as unappetizing” for democracy as religious fundamentalism.

Page 213: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 202

Indeed, he asks, “Don’t the very same normative expectations that we have of an inclusive civil society forbid a secularistic devaluation of religion as much as, for example, the religious rejection of the equal status of men and women?”80

Habermas’s argument in fact ranges across four distinct positions, each progressively more favorable to religious thought:

1. As a matter of postmetaphysical epistemological thinking, we can-not say there is no cognitive content to religion.

2. We must as citizens acknowledge that there may be “cognitive sub-stance” in religious claims81 and that religious positions may be sus-ceptible of truth.82

3. Secular citizens have something to learn by attending to religious thought.83

4. Religious thinking historically has made contributions to democ-racy, and it has at least the potential to do so at present.84

In Habermas’s most positive formulations, “religious traditions have the power to provide convincing articulations of moral sensitivities and soli-daristic intuitions,”85 and they “have a special power to articulate moral intuitions, especially with regard to vulnerable forms of communal life.”86 Habermas identifies a number of current political issues on which reli-gious communities may contribute “convincing moral intuitions”: eutha-nasia, “bioethical issues in reproductive medicine,” animal protection, and climate change.87

Rawls’s position, according to Habermas, would suppress these reli-gious contributions to democratic debate. The point is not obvious, how-ever: Recall that Rawls permits citizens to express purely religious (or oth-erwise “comprehensive”) views in public political debate, so long as “in due course” they provide secular and “proper political” reasons.88 Haber-mas therefore must attack Rawls’s proviso directly.

Habermas reads Rawls’s proviso through the metaphor of transla-tion: The religious citizen has an obligation “in due course” to provide a “proper political” translation for her religious reasons. Although Rawls imposes a similar obligation on a citizen who relies on a secular compre-hensive doctrine, Habermas perceives an unfair asymmetry.89 His idea must be that secular reasons deriving from a comprehensive view are more easily translated into Rawls’s “proper political” reasons than are religious reasons. And here we come back to Wolterstorff ’s objection to Rawls: “A good many religious people” believe that

Page 214: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 203

they ought to base their decisions concerning fundamental issues of justice on their religious convictions. They do not view it as an option whether or not to do so. . . . Accordingly, to require of them that they not base their decisions and discussions concerning political issues on their religion is to infringe, in-equitably, on the free exercise of their religion.90

For these religious citizens, Rawls’s required translation is not available, and in that sense, the burden of translation is asymmetrical.

Habermas’s argument against this asymmetrical burden is conceptual:

The liberal state contradicts itself if it demands that all citizens conform to a political ethos that imposes unequal burdens on them. The translation proviso for religious reasons and the institutional precedence of secular over religious reasons demand that religious citizens make an effort to learn and adapt that secular citizens are spared.91

But why does the “liberal state contradict[] itself ”—or, more accurate, why does Rawls’s proposal contradict the idea of the liberal state? As Habermas suggests elsewhere, Rawls rightly focuses on neutrality of aim rather than neutrality of effect: “Individual norms and measures” always have differen-tial effects on “different cultural groups.”92 This is true even if the norm is “in the equal interest of all.”93 And so the mere fact of a differential burden on religious and secular citizens is not conceptually inconsistent with the idea of the liberal state.

Nonetheless, Habermas’s alternative to Rawls’s proviso targets this unequal burden on religious and secular citizens. The basic idea of this alternative is that while religious reasons presented in the informal pub-lic political sphere must be translated before they may enter the political system’s institutional core,94 the burden of translation should be mutual—that is, shared by religious and secular citizens. Habermas formulates his “institutional translation proviso” as follows:

The liberal state must not transform the necessary institutional separation be-tween religion and politics into an unreasonable mental and psychological bur-den for its religious citizens. It must, however, expect them to recognize the principle that exercise of political authority must be neutral toward compet-ing worldviews. Every citizen must know and accept that only secular reasons count beyond the institutional threshold separating the informal public sphere from parliaments, courts, ministries, and administrations. . . . Religious citi-zens can certainly acknowledge this “institutional translation proviso” with-out having to split their identity into public and private parts the moment they participate in public discourses. They should therefore also be allowed to express and justify their convictions in a religious language even when they cannot find secular “translations” for them.95

Page 215: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 204

And yet the burden Habermas imposes on religious citizens is far from trivial. As part of accepting the exclusivity of secular reasons in the politi-cal system’s institutional core, they must accept the “institutionalized mo-nopoly on knowledge of modern scientific experts.”96 Religious citizens must also “reasonably reckon with the persistence of disagreement in their dealings with non-believers and members of other faiths.”97 This latter in-junction amounts to the requirement that religious citizens accept Rawls’s idea of reasonable pluralism: While the religious citizen of course may hold to his own comprehensive view, he must recognize the reasonableness and permissibility of others. Along these lines, and in a somewhat surprising development, Habermas accepts and adopts Rawls’s idea of “political con-ception as module” (despite his criticism, in his 1995 debate with Rawls, of Rawls’s more general theory of a political conception’s justification):

The major world religions must reappropriate the normative foundations of the liberal state on their own premises. . . . Rawls chose the image of a module to represent how the morality of human rights is “embedded” within different religious comprehensive doctrines. The module fits into the various orthodox contexts of justification even though it is constructed exclusively on the basis of reasons that are neutral with respect to worldviews.98

While mainstream Protestant churches and (since Vatican II) the Catho-lic Church have reached this institutional accommodation with the liberal democratic state, Habermas notes that “many Muslim churches still have to undergo this painful learning process.”99 One might add that this pro-cess remains outstanding for many nonmainstream Christian churches, as well as for individual believers within mainstream Protestantism and Catholicism. The burden of accepting a liberal democratic political con-ception from “within” a religious comprehensive view—and not merely reaching a “modus vivendi”100 with it—is significant indeed. And finally—although Habermas does not make the point explicit—religious citizens presumably must make the effort to provide secular translations of their religious reasons if they want these reasons to have influence on the politi-cal system’s secular institutional core. This remains so even if, according to Habermas, religious citizens must be free to participate in the informal political public sphere even if they cannot find available secular transla-tions for their religiously inspired views.101

Habermas has suggested that the burden on secular citizens should be no less than the burden on religious citizens. In addition to relieving some of the obligations Rawls assigns to religious citizens, Habermas tries to equalize the burdens by imposing additional requirements on secular

Page 216: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 205

citizens. Habermas mentions three requirements specially applicable to the secular—or, as Habermas sometimes says, to the “religiously tone-deaf.”102

First, in their capacity as citizens—that is, as participants in political discussion—they must not take the position that religious views are irra-tional or not susceptible of truth.103 Second, they must “rationally reckon with the fact of continuing disagreement”104—that is, expect religion to continue as a presence in modern life, including political life.105 Third, they may not question the right of believers to “couch their contributions to public discussions in religious language.”106 And finally, they must “par-ticipate in efforts to translate relevant contributions from the religious lan-guage into a publicly accessible language.”107

At first glance, and at least from the side of religious citizens, Haber-mas’s proposal might seem less restrictive on reason giving in public de-bate than Rawls’s proviso. He addresses solicitously the religious citizen who can find no “translation” into public reasons for her religiously based political view. Such a citizen, according to Habermas, does not violate the ethic of democratic citizenship by offering only religious reasons.

But Cristina Lafont has perceptively argued that Habermas’s proposal places unjustified burdens on both religious and secular citizens. This point is particularly clear with respect to secular citizens. According to Haber-mas, secular citizens may not present what he has called a “secularist” ar-gument in public debate, that is, an argument that religiously grounded views are historically retrograde. While Habermas may (or may not) be correct that this position is, on the merits, unjustified, it is a separate ques-tion whether that position should be banned from public discourse. And on that point Habermas provides no argument. It is not simply a matter, on Habermas’s part, of suggesting that secular citizens refrain, for reasons of civility, from expressing disrespect for their religious co-citizens’ views. Habermas goes beyond that to require that secular citizens acknowledge the possible truth of religious beliefs. As Lafont asks: Why is that “a pre-condition of democracy or rationality?”108 One might question, further, why secular citizens should be required to assist religious citizens in find-ing “translations” of religious reasons into public reasons—the only kind of reasons that, on Habermas’s position, may count in forming policy or reaching political decisions. It might indicate an excellence of character—a special democratic generosity—but it seems excessive to expect this solici-tude from secular citizens as a matter of course.

Lafont further questions Habermas’s requirement that religious citizens must, for purposes of democratic debate, accept the cognitive authority of

Page 217: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 206

science109—or, as Habermas puts it even more strongly, the “institutional-ized monopoly on knowledge of scientific experts.”110 Here too, she ob-serves, Habermas provides no justification.111 And because the authority vel non of science is itself a contested political issue—for example, in the teaching of evolution in public schools—the requirement seems to me in-consistent with Habermas’s solicitude for religious citizens’ freedom to par-ticipate in public debate.112 In this way, too, Habermas’s proposal is more reason-restrictive than it might first seem.

Lafont’s proposed revision of Habermas’s “institutional translation proviso” would, she says, “recognize the right of all democratic citizens to take their own cognitive stance in public deliberation.”113 Secular citi-zens would be free to question the “cognitive substance”114 of religion, and religious citizens would be free to question the epistemological and po-litical authority of science. But this freedom would not, in Lafont’s terms, “include[] an additional right to the protection of the integrity of such cognitive stances.”115 What Lafont means is that while in advocating “co-ercive policies” citizens would be free to present their arguments initially in whatever form they choose—whether in terms of public reasons, in a secular but “comprehensive” idiom, or in religious language—they must be “prepared to address any objections based on reasons generally accept-able to democratic citizens that other participants may advance against such policies.”116 In Lafont’s full statement of what she calls (in lieu of Rawls’s “proviso” and Habermas’s “institutional translation proviso”) the “accountability proviso”:

Citizens have no obligation to provide either public reasons or translations in terms of public reasons for each policy proposal they support or criticize, but they do have the obligation to address any such reason that is introduced by others against their proposals. Whenever citizens manage to cast their objec-tions to a proposed policy in terms of reasons generally acceptable to demo-cratic citizens (i.e. reasons based on basic democratic principles of freedom and equality, etc.), other citizens have the obligation to address and to defeat them with compelling reasons before such a coercive policy can be enforced.117

But how different is Lafont’s “accountability proviso” from Rawls’s pro-viso? Although free in the first instance to present purely religious argu-ments on any political issue—including constitutional essentials and mat-ters of basic justice—Lafont’s religious citizen must be prepared to address objections that are framed in terms of public reasons.118 And while La-font’s essay does not make the point entirely clear, it seems that the reply must be in terms of public reasons. I make this inference because Lafont

Page 218: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 207

assigns citizens who are faced with public-reasons-based objections “the obligation to address and to defeat [those objections] with compelling rea-sons.”119 And for Lafont, as for Rawls and Habermas, legitimately winning arguments must be based on “reasons generally acceptable to democratic citizens.” That, she says, is required by “any serious commitment to de-liberative democracy.”120 In short, Lafont’s proposal, like Rawls’s, seems to be that citizens may present arguments in any form, including purely religious form, provided that they then address, with public reasons, any objections that are based on public reasons. Indeed, Lafont’s proposal may be more restrictive than Rawls’s because (as with Audi’s proposal) it ex-tends to any advocacy of a coercive policy, not just issues of constitutional essentials or matters of basic justice.

Lafont has well articulated the core difficulty of (what Weithman would call) the “standard approach” to religious argument in deliberative democratic theory. On one hand, theorists like Rawls, Audi, and Lafont believe that deliberative democracy entails in public debate an “obligation to provide reasons acceptable to everyone that justify coercive policies to which all must comply.” Under conditions of reasonable pluralism, reli-gious reasons cannot meet this standard. But, on the other hand, as Lafont argues, deliberative democracy seems to require that each citizen freely be able to “judge the policies under discussion strictly on their merits,” and this requires in turn that they be “allowed to adopt their own cognitive stance, whatever it may be.” As Lafont formulates the difficulty:

The challenge for a defense of deliberative democracy under pluralistic condi-tions is to come up with a design of political deliberation in the public sphere that recognizes the right of all democratic citizens to adopt their own cogni-tive stance in deliberation, whether religious or secular, without giving up on the obligation to provide reasons acceptable to everyone that justify coercive policies to which all must comply.121

Lafont is correct that Habermas, without remarking on the point, has given up the idea that each participant in democratic debate must “provide reasons acceptable to everyone.” Religious citizens, he has said, may ex-press purely religious views without providing secular translations. In tak-ing this position, Habermas is siding with Weithman, in particular, on the side opposite Rawls in the debate about religion’s role in the public sphere. If secular citizens are able, as Habermas suggests they are, to provide secular translations for religious reasons, then they are able to see them as reasons and to grasp the force that they have for the believer.122 Why does the notion of deliberative democracy require more? Here Weithman’s

Page 219: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 208

observation, quoted earlier in the chapter, seems to me pertinent: “I may reject utilitarianism, but I can still see utilitarian considerations as reasons of a sort. I can still see the people who offer them as not unreasonable, even when they offer them as the basis for settling fundamental political questions.”123 Whether or not one agrees with Wolterstorff ’s diagnosis—that liberals like Rawls are like disappointed communitarians in a plural-ist world, prescribing that although we are divided by values we must be united in offering the same kind of reasons—it seems more basic to democ-racy, “deliberative” or otherwise, to allow all citizens to maintain their own “cognitive stance” than to require all to employ the same kind of reason. Habermas, it seems to me, needs to acknowledge explicitly that he has in effect fully repudiated the Rawls/Audi view that citizens must place special restrictions on their use of religious reasons in public political discourse. (But the position of officials, again, is different: In the halls of political decision, Habermas says, only secular reasons may count.)

5.2 multicult ur a lism a nd constit u tiona l patr iotism

Habermas’s recent discussions of religion and the future of Europe have led him to enter debates over multiculturalism more generally. As with his dis-cussion of religion, Habermas’s treatment of multiculturalism invokes, and positions him in relation to, the work of others. For purposes of presenting Habermas’s views, two figures in the multicultural debate are particularly useful to discuss: Will Kymlicka, an influential liberal multiculturalist, and Brian Barry, a liberal and sharp critic of multiculturalism. The focus will be on the nature of rights in multiculturalist societies. Because Habermas’s treatment is sometimes more allusive than systematic, my sketch of Kym-licka’s and Barry’s positions will need to fill in the gaps.

5.2.1 Background: Kymlicka and Barry

Kymlicka’s Multicultural Citizenship (1995) defends the idea of “group-differentiated citizenship” with “group-differentiated” (or “group-specific”) rights. The latter term is in Kymlicka’s view preferable to the term collective rights that is commonly associated with multiculturalist theories. This is so, he says for several reasons. First, the term collective rights is too broad because, if taken literally, it would extend to include rights held by unions,

Page 220: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 209

corporations, and the public. Those rights, however, are not what is con-troversial about multiculturalism. Second, the term collective rights suggests an opposition to individual rights. But, in fact, many of the rights associ-ated with Kymlicka’s version of multiculturalism are to be exercised by in-dividuals, with individual legal claims available for their violation.124 Third, Kymlicka notes, the term collective rights suggests ideas of collectivism or communitarianism, as opposed to individualism, and the communitarian/individualist debate is in Kymlicka’s view not helpful for his purposes.125

Kymlicka identifies three kinds of group-differentiated rights. The first, self-government rights, includes rights to “some form of political autonomy or territorial jurisdiction” accorded to component nations in multination states. Mechanisms for extending such rights include federal-ist governmental structures and reserved territory. As an example of the first mechanism, Kymlicka refers to Canadian federalist arrangements that were designed to ensure Francophone control over matters related to edu-cation, language, and culture. Examples of the second mechanism include the “reservations” (U.S.) and “reserves” (Canada) allocated to tribes or bands of indigenous peoples.126

The second form of group-differentiated rights Kymlicka calls “poly-ethnic rights.” Characteristic measures to secure those rights concern pub-lic support for group-specific cultural or linguistic practices and—here Habermas is generally approving—exemptions from general laws that bear heavily on particular groups’ characteristic religious practices. Taken as a whole, Kymlicka says, these polyethnic rights are “intended to help eth-nic groups and religious minorities express their cultural particularity and pride without . . . hampering their success in the economic and political institutions of the dominant society.”127

The final category of group-differentiated rights that Kymlicka identi-fies comprises “special representation rights.” Proportional representation, Kymlicka observes, is one mechanism for securing such rights,128 but in the American context, at least, such electoral schemes are comparatively rare. The most prominent form of special representation rights in American law, as Kymlicka notes, is race-conscious legislative districting, pursuant to the Voting Rights Act of 1965.129 American law currently permits some such race-conscious districting practices if the group in question is “suffi-ciently large and geographically compact to constitute a majority in a [par-ticular] district” and voting patterns are racially polarized.130 Under these conditions, the U.S. Supreme Court has held, a specially drawn “majority- minority” district may be necessary to ensure that “the political processes

Page 221: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 210

leading to nomination or election . . . are . . . equally open to participation by members of ” the group in question.131 But race-conscious districting has been controversial from the beginning, and, in a series of cases that Kymlicka notes, the Court has ruled that the Constitution may be offended if “race for its own sake, and not other districting principles, was the legis-lature’s dominant and controlling rationale in drawing its district lines.”132 Still, at present, and subject to these limitations, race-conscious districting is an example in American law of Kymlicka’s “special representation rights.”

The basis for extending group-differentiated rights that Kymlicka em-phasizes most strongly is equality. The theory behind race-conscious dis-tricting, for example, is that, in a race-polarized society, the votes of racial and ethnic minorities otherwise will be “diluted” and (after the election) their interests unfairly neglected. With respect to polyethnic rights, Kym-licka argues that equality may require explicit recognition and protection of minority cultural practices. Against the objection that a liberal principle of state neutrality would be offended, Kymlicka maintains that govern-ment neutrality with respect to ethnic and national groups is in fact impos-sible. According to Kymlicka, “Government decisions on languages, in-ternal boundaries, public holidays, and state symbols unavoidably involve recognizing, accommodating, and supporting the needs and identities of particular ethnic and national groups.” And so “the state unavoidably pro-motes certain cultural identities, and thereby disadvantages others.”133 For this reason, Kymlicka argues, the principle of equality may require special support for minority cultural practices, including in some cases exemption from generally applicable laws.

Kymlicka defends these three kinds of group-differentiated rights as “external protections” for cultural minorities that may be consistent with liberalism. Sharply in tension with liberalism, however, are what Kymlicka calls “internal restrictions,” or, putative “right[s] of a group to limit the liberty of its own individual members in the name of group solidarity or cultural purity.”134 As examples of illiberal internal restrictions that might be asserted in the name of polyethnic rights, Kymlicka cites requests that the state permit (1) group-based exemptions from (for example) public schooling (designed to keep children in the traditional religious commu-nity), (2) traditional cultural practices of genital mutilation or compul-sory arranged marriage, and (3) a “cultural defense” to charges of spousal abuse.135 On Kymlicka’s analysis, the second and third sorts of internal re-strictions would be impermissible in a liberal society. But matters may be more “complicated,” Kymlicka suggests, with respect to the first. He notes

Page 222: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 211

that certain ethnic groups—he mentions the Amish, Mennonites, Hasidic Jews, and (in Canada) the Hutterites—have been “allowed to maintain certain illiberal institutions for many years, even many generations.” Al-though past permission does not now have dispositive weight, Kymlicka indicates that long-established groups at least “have a stronger claim to maintain internal restrictions than newly arriving immigrants.”136 He dis-cusses, but does not clearly indicate a conclusion concerning, the Amish practice of ending children’s schooling before age sixteen and the Hutterite practice of denying compensation to those ousted from the community and common lands for the sin of apostasy.137

Kymlicka distinguishes, finally, between voluntary immigrants and national minorities. The latter, he says, typically seek integration into the larger society, while the former may demand to remain “distinct societies alongside the majority culture” with “various forms of autonomy or self-government to ensure their survival as distinct societies.” National minori-ties, Kymlicka indicates, are those groups whose territory has been invol-untarily incorporated into the larger society. In the American context, he identifies American Indians, Puerto Ricans, the descendants of Mexicans whose territory was annexed after the Mexican war of 1846–1848, “native Hawaiians, the Chamorros of Guam, and various other Pacific Islanders.” Canadian national minorities include the Québécois and “Aboriginal com-munities.”138 Kymlicka would reserve self-government rights for national minorities. Voluntary immigrants, he says, are entitled to government as-sistance aimed at fighting prejudice and discrimination as well as language training; in addition, and depending on the situation, some group-specific polyethnic rights, such as religiously based exemptions, may be appropriate. Kymlicka acknowledges that refugees fleeing persecution, and economic refugees, represent intermediate cases, as their immigration is not entirely voluntary. Yet Kymlicka suggests that, with respect to these groups, the gov-ernment of the receiving country is not obliged to allow the groups to estab-lish themselves as national minorities with self-government rights. “The best that refugees can realistically expect is to be treated as immigrants, with the corresponding polyethnic rights, and hope to return to their homeland as quickly as possible.” With respect to economic refugees, the government of the receiving country has an obligation to pursue economic redistribution among nations as the “only long-term solution.”139

Perhaps the foremost liberal critic of multiculturalism was the late Brian Barry. His Culture and Equality (2001) is a sometimes polemical140 exami-nation of various multiculturalist positions, with Kymlicka a chief target.

Page 223: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 212

Habermas suggests at one point agreement with Barry and disagreement with Kymlicka, but I will argue that the picture is more complicated.

At the outset, Barry sets aside certain group-based programs that his liberalism would countenance, “such as ‘affirmative action’ in relation to jobs, or special funding for education, to help groups whose members suf-fer systematic disadvantage”—provided that “ ‘disadvantage’ is defined in universal [rather than culturally specific] terms.”141 Further, Barry does not challenge “multiculturalist” education to the extent that it requires only “ ‘a greater degree of attention to minorities and women and their role in American history and social studies and literature classes in schools.’ ”142 It will turn out, also, that Barry is willing to permit, or at least consider per-mitting, some of the accommodations that Kymlicka describes as “poly-ethnic rights”—although as a matter of prudential cost/benefit judgment, not as a matter of equality right.

But Barry suggests that some of the practices multiculturalists see as re-ligiously mandated, and thus deserving of liberal accommodation, are only traditional practices “packag[ed]” as if they were religiously mandated. If no exemption is given from generally applicable laws, those who engage in the practice, he says, may well reevaluate it. Such has been the case, Barry argues, in some countries that have denied exemptions from humane treat-ment laws for ritual slaughter.143 Further, the characteristic argument Barry makes against religion-backed arguments for exemptions is that the chal-lenged rule constrains not religious exercise but only the conduct directly burdened by the rule. He contends, for example, that humane slaughter-ing requirements do not restrict believers’ religious liberty but “only the ability to eat meat,” and eating meat, his argument goes, is not religiously required.144 Similarly, he interprets a motorcycle helmet requirement as restricting not religious liberty for Sikhs who assert a religious mandate that they wear turbans, but only the riding of motorcycles—a practice not required by the Sikh religion. As Barry summarizes the argument:

[W]e must insist on the crucial difference between a denial of equal opportu-nities to some group (for example, a law forbidding Sikhs to ride motorcycles) and a choice some people make out of that from a set of equal opportunities (for example, a choice not to ride a motorcycle) as a result of certain beliefs.145

As I indicated, however, Barry is not entirely as oblivious to the burden on believers as these passages would suggest. While he uses the above argu-ments to oppose the idea that justice, equality, or religious liberty requires exemptions, he allows that “balance-of-interest” or “balance-of-advantage”

Page 224: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 213

arguments might support the believers’ cause. With respect to the helmet law, for example, he notes that “if not being able to ride a motorcycle ruled out a significant proportion of all the jobs in an area open to somebody with a certain level of trained ability, that would be relevant.” And further:

It would also be a matter of specific concern if the inability to ride a motor-cycle prevented Sikhs from joining the police force, because it is important that the police force be open to all, and should in fact contain representatives of all minorities. This is not so much a matter of doing a favor to Sikhs as one of pursuing a benefit to all of us. But there is nothing to prevent police forces from organizing themselves so that Sikh members are not assigned to duties that entail riding a motorcycle. (The police already, quite rightly, permit Sikhs to wear turbans.)146

Moreover, Barry argues, for the many Sikhs in the construction indus-try, where protective headgear also is generally required, “the particular circumstances make the balance-of-advantage argument for an exemp-tion rather powerful.”147 Similarly, Barry states that an employer’s ban on headscarves “is rightly to be regarded as a denial of equal opportunity,” even as he questions the strength of any firm religious requirement of headscarves for Muslim women.148 Whether the wearing of headscarves is a requirement or only a custom, he reasons, “to abandon a long-established custom” is “no trivial matter,” and “there is no non-trivial reason in sup-port of a ban on headscarves.” The general principle Barry defends is that “culturally derived characteristics that do not demonstrably interfere with the ability to do the job cannot be accepted as a basis for job discrimina-tion.”149 And Barry reaches a similar conclusion in his consideration of the 1989 French controversy over whether Muslim girls might wear a headscarf in school (the affaire du foulard): here, too, the “rule-and-exemption” ap-proach may best reconcile the interests at stake.

This pattern of pragmatic support for religiously (or at least culturally) asserted exemptions is striking. It seems to me as important as Barry’s re-fusal to credit the arguments as successfully invoking equality or religious liberty. Even if, as Barry says, a pragmatic “rule and exemption” approach is not “the panacea that it is commonly represented as by multiculturalists,” there seems reason to question his assertion that there may not be “too many other[]” cases in which the balance of advantages requires an exemption. 150

Yet Barry, in my opinion appropriately, is more reluctant to support ex-emptions when children’s welfare is at stake. He criticizes the U.S. Supreme Court’s 1971 Yoder decision, in which Amish parents sought exemption

Page 225: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 214

from compulsory school education beyond the eighth grade. According to Chief Justice Burger’s opinion for the Court, the parents argued that

their children’s attendance at high school, public or private, was contrary to the Amish religion and way of life. They believed that, by sending their chil-dren to high school, they would not only expose themselves to the danger of the censure of the church community, but . . . also endanger their own salva-tion and that of their children.151

The Court held that compelling the children to attend a public or private high school would unconstitutionally prohibit the parents’ (not the chil-dren’s) free exercise of religion and the parents’ right to direct the upbring-ing of their children.152 Barry identifies a “mismatch” between the ratio-nale, which focuses on the parents’ rights, and “the content of the decision, which concerns children.” Other cases, Barry notes, have held that parental rights must sometimes yield to considerations of children’s welfare.153 Edu-cation should be such an area, Barry argues, with private schools and home schooling subject to “vigilant” state supervision.154 The error in the Yoder decision, according to Barry, is that it “assumes that Amish children need education only to become Amish.”155 But with twenty percent of Amish children leaving the group, Barry observes, this premise is mistaken.

Similarly, while Barry sees some form of bilingual education as per-haps a sensible transitional system for immigrant children, he believes that existing programs of bilingual education may serve the interests of those who create and run them more than those of the children they are to serve. For example, New York responded to a court decision requiring the state to adopt some program in bilingual education, and the state’s response was to require bilingual education for all those whose English test scores were below the fortieth percentile, regardless of whether or not they were native English speakers.156 Although these programs are styled as transi-tional, Barry sees them as traps that lock students into inferior educational opportunities. He speculates:

Rather than conceiving of [bilingual/bicultural education] as one possible mode of transition, to be compared for efficacy with ESL or “immersion” (of either the old-fashioned “cold turkey” kind or sophisticated recently de-veloped programmes), it may be seen instead as a way of fostering Hispanic identity . . . . What happens to these children may be seen . . . as a way of restoring members of the ethnically defined community to their “roots” in their language and culture, and thereby stabilizing their identity as Hispanics.

In this way, Barry believes, government-sponsored multiculturalist pro-grams tend to serve their designers’ interests in cultural preservation more than the interests of their putative beneficiaries.

Page 226: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 215

Barry’s broadest criticism of multiculturalism is that, as a “politics of difference,” it stands opposed to his preferred “politics of redistribu-tion.”157 Against Kymlicka, he notes that American blacks stand entirely outside the organizing distinction between national minorities and vol-untary immigrants; the difficulties they face receive only two pages of discussion in Kymlicka’s Multicultural Citizenship. And their “oppression,” Barry argues, principally concerns unequal access to material resources; it is not primarily cultural.158 Multiculturalism, Barry contends, both diverts focus from the problem of unequal material resources and undermines the conditions necessary for a successful coalition. By engaging in “turf wars,” multiculturalists “dissipate” the resources needed for “more broad-based causes.” “Not only does [multiculturalism] do nothing to change the structure of unequal opportunities and outcomes,” Barry concludes, “it actually entrenches it by embroiling those in the lower reaches of the distribution in internecine warfare.”159

Barry does not provide strong evidence for these broadest claims.160 And as mentioned, he is willing to countenance some of Kymlicka’s rec-ommended exemptions from generally applicable requirements, on “prag-matic” grounds, when those requirements impose special hardship on par-ticular groups. He seems to think that these concessions, however, should not be understood as statements of rights. In his view, there is a sharp dif-ference between Kymlicka’s “group-differentiated citizenship” and his own idea of a “unitary republican citizenship.” “There should be only one status of citizen,” Barry says, “so that everybody enjoys the same legal and political rights.” And, underscoring: There should be no “special rights (or disabili-ties) accorded to some and not others on the basis of group membership.”161

5.2.2 Habermas on Multiculturalism

Habermas positions himself in the debate as opposed to “extreme” or “radical” multiculturalism, echoing Barry’s objection that some strands of multiculturalist theory are improperly preservationist rather than poten-tially critical in their approach to cultures. A consequence of this view, Habermas argues, would be to “curtail the right of their individual mem-bers to choose a life of their own.”162

But exactly what he means to reject as “extreme” or “radical,” and ex-actly what in multiculturalism he intends to approve, is made more dif-ficult by Habermas’s imprecise and sometimes inconsistent use of terms. For example, he speaks of both collective rights and cultural rights. Based on a position he defended in Facts and Norms—that rights in modern legal

Page 227: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 216

orders are necessarily individual rights163—one would assume that he would either deny that cultural rights are collective rights or reject cultural rights as inconsistent with the nature of modern law. His position, how-ever, is not so straightforward.

In some passages of his recent work, Habermas does reject the idea of collective rights while identifying them with multiculturalist positions. The “introduction of collective cultural rights,” he writes in a 2007 lecture, is a position of “extremist multiculturalists.” It is “a form of species protec-tion for entire cultural groups” that “would in fact curtail the right of their individual members to choose a way of life of their own.”164 Here Haber-mas approvingly cites Brian Barry’s Culture and Equality.165 Elsewhere, Habermas characterizes “group rights” as both unnecessary and “norma-tively questionable.”166

But, in other passages, Habermas seems to argue that collective rights are necessary elements of a just multicultural society. He writes, for example:

The aim of guaranteeing free access to the cultural background, social net-work, and communicative web of identity groups also accounts for the intro-duction of collective rights. Such rights strengthen the organizations respon-sible for the self-assertion of endangered cultures. Collective rights empower cultural groups to preserve and make available the resources on which their members draw in forming and stabilizing their personal identities.167

Habermas does not make clear here what kind of collective rights—or, better, to use Kymlicka’s term, group-differentiated rights—he has in mind. But, by referring to the strengthening of “organizations responsible for the self-assertion of endangered cultures,” Habermas seems to have in mind what Kymlicka calls self-government rights, or perhaps special representa-tion rights. Yet in the next paragraph, Habermas seems to mean by “collec-tive rights” the full spectrum of what Kymlicka calls “group-differentiated rights.” That is because one of the four conflicts that Habermas attrib-utes to the “the introduction of collective rights” likely concerns what is called in the American context “affirmative action,”168 and two of the other conflicts seem to concern what Kymlicka calls “polyethnic rights.”169 But whatever Habermas means to include under the heading of “collective rights,” he seems in this discussion to treat them as necessary elements of a just multicultural society, albeit productive of certain characteristic con-flicts. In other words, Habermas here emphasizes the ambivalence of “col-lective rights,” not their inconsistency with a liberal democratic order. In related passages, Habermas seems to relax his earlier assumption that the modern legal medium requires individual rather than collective rights.170

Page 228: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 217

And in still other discussions, Habermas suggests that “cultural rights” are the issue in multicultural societies, and they are not necessarily collective rights.171

Let us follow this last suggestion that we focus in the first instance on the idea of cultural rather than collective rights and try to make more precise what Habermas means. Cultural rights are, he says, to be distin-guished from “social” rights,172 or rights of distributive justice. Violation of a cultural right is not discrimination, but instead, exclusion173 or denial of recognition.174 Incorporation of cultural rights, he says, involves a logic different from the social rights of the welfare state.175 Whereas resources can be redistributed through political use of the legal medium, by contrast “relations of recognition, extending across subcultural divides, can only be promoted indirectly, but cannot be directly produced, by means of politics and law.”176 In this sense cultural rights, while not necessarily inconsistent with the logic of modern legal orders, “run[] up against the structural lim-its of the legal medium.”177

So much, however, is primarily a negative definition. Habermas of-fers a general—and daunting—account of the purpose or point of cultural rights: “the guarantee of equal access to the patterns of communication, social relations, traditions, and relations of recognition that are required or desired for developing, reproducing, and renewing . . . personal identi-ties.”178 By this Habermas means to invoke his account, developed in The-ory of Communicative Action, of how personal identities are formed through communicative action, with communicative action understood as drawing on the “resources” of culture, society, and personality. Whereas this pro-cess may be relatively unproblematic for members of dominant groups, the same cannot necessarily be said for members of minority identity groups. Habermas mentions a couple of different ways in which cultural rights might assist this process of identity formation.

First, and in Habermas’s view less problematic, is the granting of ex-ceptions to generally applicable rules. As examples, Habermas mentions the following cases:

Sikhs are permitted to wear their turbans on motorcycles and to carry their rit-ual daggers in public; Muslim women and girls may wear their “headscarves” in the workplace and in school; Jewish butchers are permitted to slaughter livestock and poultry according to kosher methods; and so forth.179

This sort of exception-granting, Habermas says, is “not a matter of a mys-terious ‘inversion of the universal into the particular,’ only trivial instances

Page 229: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 218

of basic rights taking priority over ordinary laws or public safety regula-tions.”180 With this sympathy for the rule-and-exemption approach to what Kymlicka calls “polyethnic rights,” Habermas parts ways with Barry, argu-ing that exemptions are required by a principle of equality—and not just as a matter of pragmatic “balance of interests” argument. For example, he sides with the French Muslim schoolgirls in l’affaire du foulard, maintain-ing that by forbidding headscarves “on the secular ground that religion must be treated as a private matter to be kept out of the public domain,” the French officials offended an “imperative of impartiality.” Although he does not elaborate in detail, he seems to suggest that the rights at stake were not just those of the individual schoolgirls: The state, he says, in-truded on “the legitimate claim to self-representation and public recog-nition of a religious minority.”181 Habermas appears also to endorse, as a matter of “neutrality” and “excluding intolerant conduct,” exemptions “from generally binding safety regulations” that permit Sikhs to “wear turbans and carry ceremonial daggers.”182 But he lists, as open questions for the courts as to “whose ethos” should be accepted and “when,” a vari-ety of other claims that fit Kymlicka’s description of polyethnic rights.183

The second sort of cultural right—and one Habermas discusses at more length—involves collective rights. With “self-assertion rights,” Habermas says, “representatives of identity groups” are granted “enhanced author-ity to organize and administer themselves.” Habermas is less clear on ex-amples of this kind of right, but he seems to mean roughly what Kymlicka means by “self-government rights.” Habermas mentions, as problematic cases of this kind of right, instances in which “religious law supplements or even replaces civil law, especially within the family”—and in which the re-ligious law “is guarded and interpreted literally by guardians of orthodoxy (as it is in Islamic countries and in Israel, for example).”184

Although such rights may be problematic for Habermas, the reason is not a simple inconsistency of collective rights with a modern legal or-der. Habermas suggests an analogy between collective rights of group “self-assertion” and ordinary delegations of authority under a demo-cratic constitution to “local authorities, provincial governments, or semi- public institutions.”185 As Habermas notes, however, standard delegations of constitutional authority are limited by constitutionally specified indi-vidual liberties, and so such delegations “cannot conflict with citizens’ basic rights”—that is, they may not permissibly be allowed so to conflict.

Problems arise, however—and the analogy breaks down—when the groups whose self-assertion is buttressed by collective cultural rights do

Page 230: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 219

not “have an internal organization that satisfies liberal standards.” Here, conflicts may arise between constitutionally guaranteed basic liberties and cultural rights of “self-assertion.” Habermas characterizes the problem as arising “when the liberal state fulfills the conditions required to enable the reproduction of a cultural minority whose very existence would otherwise be threatened, and when it as a consequence accepts in return the viola-tion of the basic rights of individual members.”186 Habermas seems to have in mind here what Kymlicka called an “internal restriction,” that is, the limitation of a group member’s liberty “in the name of group solidarity or cultural purity.”187

Habermas’s prime example of problematic “self-assertion” rights is the American Yoder case, discussed also by Kymlicka and Barry. As Habermas describes the case, “Amish parents were . . . allowed to withdraw their children from the ninth and tenth grades because they would otherwise be familiarized with subjects judged to be incompatible with the survival of the worldview and way of life of the religious community.”188

One might object that Yoder seems an example of Habermas’s first category of cultural rights, not the second—that is, a case in which the parents seek a religiously based exemption from generally applicable laws, not the outfitting of a community with collective rights of “self-assertion.” But Habermas is correct at least in pointing out the possible divergence in interest between the parents, who are seeking to maintain a traditional way of life against state interference, and the children, who might, if given the choice and sufficient information to make it, seek to find another way.

Habermas does not make entirely clear whether he rejects the result in Yoder or whether he simply finds it a difficult and problematic case. But his discussion in another context makes clear his general approach to cases of collective rights of self-assertion:

The Catholic Church has the right to exclude women from the priesthood, even though the equality of men and women has constitutional standing and is implemented in other sectors of society. The Church explains this employ-ment policy by appealing to an essential element of the doctrine to which its pastoral mission is devoted. From the perspective of the liberal state, the principle of equality is not violated as long as members are not barred from expressing their dissent by leaving the group or by mobilizing counterforces within the organization itself.189

Realistic right of exit and the possibility of expressing dissent within the group seem to be Habermas’s minimum conditions for recognizing a col-lective right that is in tension with a basic individual right.

Page 231: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 220

In the Yoder case, of course, children lacked the realistic possibility of exiting the group—and the group, by controlling their access to educa-tion, was limiting their ability to determine whether children ever would wish eventually to exit the group. But in upholding the parents’ claim, the Supreme Court stated that, in addition to the right of free exercise of religion, it considered the “right of parents to direct the religious upbring-ing of their children.”190 The Court, in other words, did not assume chil-dren’s exit from parental and communal authority as a background right that children enjoy. For the Court, then, the tension Habermas identifies between individual and collective right disappears. For this reason, too, Yoder is a difficult case for illustrating Habermas’s view of cultural collec-tive “self-assertion” rights.

It would have been helpful if Habermas, in the work I have been dis-cussing, had been able to consider with greater particularity more of the “countless cases” of tension between communal rights and basic individual rights. Instead, his attention seems to be less on the merits of particular conflicting claims and more on the general question whether collective rights imply a “contradiction in the idea of civic equality as such.”191 That he answers that general question in the negative indicates that Habermas has some sympathy for a multiculturalist position. What is difficult to as-sess is the strength of Habermas’s sympathy.

As I suggested above, Habermas does distinguish his position from “strong multiculturalism.” By “strong multiculturalism,” Habermas seems to mean the idea that cultures are akin to legal subjects and that the state is obliged to ensure that cultures have the resources necessary for their sur-vival. Against this position, Habermas argues that the survival of cultural groups depends primarily on individual members’ ongoing appropriation and reproduction of that tradition in their communicative interaction with others. For that reason, he maintains, the state is not in the position of ensuring that cultural groups are able to survive—or, as he puts it, “the survival of identity groups and the continued existence of their cultural background cannot be guaranteed by collective rights at all.”192 This analy-sis grounds Habermas’s insistence on the realistic possibility of exit and the possibility of internal dissent as minimum conditions for cultural collec-tive rights of self-assertion:

Collective rights can strengthen the cultural self-assertion of a group only if they also accord the individual members the latitude to use them realistically in deciding on reflection between critical appropriation, revision, or rejection. Freedom of association certainly already safeguards the voluntary nature of

Page 232: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 221

group membership. But it is only the seal on a realistic right to exit. The guar-antee of the internal latitude necessary to assimilate a tradition under condi-tions of dissent is decisive for the survival of cultural groups. A dogmatically protected culture will not be able to reproduce itself, especially not in a social environment replete with alternatives.193

In her work The Claims of Culture (2002), Seyla Benhabib defends a Haber-masian approach to multiculturalism with more clarity than Habermas himself. Benhabib welcomes multicultural movements “to the degree to which they are movements for democratic inclusion, greater social and po-litical justice, and cultural fluidity.” But she opposes attempts—by Kymlicka and others, she suggests194—to “maintain[] the purity or distinctiveness of cultures.”195 This is the “preservationist” impulse of some multiculturalists that Habermas rejects. Indeed, Benhabib rejects the idea, which she attrib-utes to Kymlicka (and others), that cultures are “clearly delineable wholes” that are “congruent with population groups” and uncontroversially de-scribable.196 Cultures, she writes, are “constant creations, recreations, and negotiations of imaginary boundaries between ‘we’ and the ‘other[s].’ ”197

The central point in Benhabib’s defense of a Habermasian approach is her emphasis not so much on formal political institutions as on “the politi-cal activities and struggles of social movements, associations, and groups in civil society.”198 The role of cultural rights, Habermas means to argue, is to create space for this political activity, and in the process to make pos-sible critical encounter with one’s own tradition. Habermas, together with Benhabib, insists on intracultural dialogue in civil society and the infor-mal public sphere, not the closing off of cultures to one another199—or, to use Habermas’s other term, not the segmentation of cultures.200 Notwith-standing the plurality of cultures in a given society, Habermas insists that there be a single political community. He understands the unity of this community to be established by the constitutional norms, such as equal-ity and dignity of the person, that underwrite and justify the group-based exemptions from general rules that are part of Kymlicka’s “polyethnic rights.” In Habermas’s clearest formulation:

Multiculturalism that understands itself in the right way is not a one-way street to the cultural self-assertion of groups with their own collective identities. The equal coexistence of different forms of life must not lead to segmentation. It calls for the integration of all citizens and the mutual recognition of their subcultural memberships within the framework of a shared political culture. The citizens as members of society may legitimately cultivate their distinctive cultures only under the condition that they all understand themselves, across subcultural divides, as citizens of one and the same political community. The

Page 233: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 222

same constitutional basic norms in terms of which cultural exemptions and authorizations are justified also define their limits.201

Here as elsewhere, Habermas’s approach could be called “procedural” rather than “substantive.” In his remarks on multiculturalism he warns of the danger that a majority culture would infuse “cultural substance” into an essentially procedural constitution. That is Habermas’s diagnosis of the French headscarf case. There, he suggests, a “republican” and “secularist interpretation of the constitution” (Habermas elsewhere uses the term la-icist) “violate[d] the required neutrality of the state.”202 At the same time, he insists on a need for “liberalization” of subcultures to allow all individu-als to engage in full participation.

The consensus required for a liberal democratic order is no longer for Habermas the relatively thick consensus of Theory of Communicative Action, where a society is integrated by shared substantive norms and values. The catchphrase Habermas uses for the needed basis of social integration is constitutional patriotism.

5.2.3 Constitutional Patriotism

While constitutional patriotism is a key term in Habermas’s recent work, his explication of the idea is relatively sparse. As a way into what Habermas means by the term, I rely on Jan-Werner Müller’s insightful Constititional Patriotism (2007), then look briefly at Habermas’s debate with Frank Mi-chelman. In the next section, I turn to how Habermas puts the concept of constitutional patriotism to work in his account of the possibilities for democracy beyond the nation-state.

As Müller explains, the idea of constitutional patriotism first devel-oped in West Germany and assumed prominence during the “historians’ debate” of 1986—a debate over how to understand National Socialism and the Holocaust both in German history and, more broadly, in Euro-pean history. Habermas was a central participant in that debate, arguing against what he saw as an attempt by conservative historians to restore a “conventional form of national pride” in place of more critical understand-ings of the German past.203 The main idea of constitutional patriotism, in Müller’s formulation, is “that political attachment ought to center on the norms, the values, and, more indirectly, the procedures of a liberal demo-cratic constitution” rather than shared ethical values or a particular na-tional tradition.204 While this conception obviously speaks to the concerns of a liberal democratic constitutionalist in postwar Germany, Habermas

Page 234: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 223

defends it as a conception attractive to multicultural and “postnational” societies more generally.

One standard criticism of constitutional patriotism is that it is “blood-less,” a sort of “professor’s dream.”205 If the constitutional principles and values that are to be a basis for the social bond are universal, how can constitutional patriotism account for attachment to a particular polity?206

Müller addresses this challenge forthrightly, acknowledging that con-stitutional patriotism always requires “supplements of particularity” to universalist principles.207 The supplements Müller identifies in constitu-tional patriotism’s West German origins are “memory” with respect to the Nazi past and “militancy” with respect to present-day “enemies of democ-racy.”208 And constitutional patriotism in general—not just its early West German instantiation—requires supplementation in two additional senses.

First, Müller observes, constitutional patriotism in general depends on a background theory of justice. The theory Müller identifies is “centered on the idea of sharing political space on fair terms.”209 Second, Müller con-cedes, to meet a requirement of specificity—to answer, that is, the question why we should be attached to one polity rather than another if the prin-ciples are universal210—constitutional patriotism largely depends on exist-ing political boundaries. As Müller puts it: Constitutional patriotism is “not a free-standing theory of political boundary formation.”211 In both these ways, constitutional patriotism is inherently dependent on concep-tions and sources of motivation outside itself—although as to the problem of presupposing political boundaries, constitutional patriotism is in the same position as are other liberal theories.212

In analyzing the structure of constitutional patriotism, Müller usefully distinguishes among the “object of attachment,” the “mode of attach-ment,” and the “reasons for attachment.” In this section, I want to focus only on the object of attachment. One would first assume that the object of attachment for a theory of constitutional patriotism would be, simply, the constitution. And given the “requirement of specificity”—the require-ment that a theory of constitutional patriotism explain why we should be attached to one polity rather than another—one would think that the object of attachment would be similarly specific: the constitution of this rather than that country.

But Müller’s formulations of the object of attachment are more ab-stract. Rather than tracking a particular constitution, Müller’s formula-tions seem to track instead the abstract background theory of justice earlier identified. Constitutional patriotism’s object of attachment, Müller says, is

Page 235: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 224

“the idea of individuals recognizing each other as free and equal and find-ing fair terms of living together.”213 Following Frank Michelman, Müller holds that given inevitable interpretive disagreement about constitutional meaning, only the idea of the constitution, and not a concrete, particular, historical constitution, can be the object of attachment for constitutional patriotism.214 And Michelman attributes this idea to Habermas.215

Michelman’s formulation—that attachment must be to “the idea of the constitution as opposed to the thing itself ”—seems to me misleading. Im-mediately after stating that attachment must be to the idea of the constitu-tion rather than “the thing itself,” Michelman hastens to add that neither he nor Habermas can be “speaking only of people’s attachment to some purely abstract, ideal notion of a constitution.”216 The two formulations, appearing as they do on a single page, are difficult to reconcile.

Michelman and Müller are right that if the idea of constitutional pa-triotism is to explain the integration of modern pluralist, multicultural societies—societies divided by great ideological and interpretive (as well as material) differences—then that idea must have some way of accounting for disagreement, even profound disagreement. As both Müller and Mi-chelman note, one function of “constitutional patriotism” is to provide the losers in those disagreements “with a genuinely moral motivation to main-tain the constitutional regime as a whole”—or, less abstract, with a reason to consent to their particular defeat.217 But Habermas’s idea of procedural legitimation seems designed to address exactly that problem: We accept outcomes we substantively disfavor, provided that procedures we accept as legitimate have been followed. Those procedures are the ones specified in the constitution we have, not a more abstract idea of the constitution. Constitutional patriotism, it would seem, need not posit attachment to the idea of the constitution rather than “the thing itself ” to explain and justify losers’ consent—at least not in ordinary cases.

But Michelman and Müller are concerned with something deeper than disagreement in ordinary cases of constitutional application. Both ques-tion (as did I in Chapter Three) the sharp distinction Habermas would draw between application and justification. As Michelman explains, dis-agreement over how to interpret a fundamental constitutional principle, such as due process or equal protection, may be so basic that we cannot plausibly say that the two sides accept the same principle.218 The contend-ing parties may agree on the words to be interpreted, but for them the words designate different principles.219 The problem deepens when we re-alize that procedural principles—even Habermas’s basic democracy- and

Page 236: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 225

justification-defining principles—are not immune from such fundamen-tal disagreement. The strategy of legitimation through procedure, then, cannot offer an unproblematic escape from this problem of “reasonable interpretive pluralism”220—or, as Habermas puts it, “radical interpretative pluralism.”221

In saying that constitutional patriotism requires attachment to the “idea” of the constitution rather than “the thing itself,” Michelman and Müller mean that full and deep substantive consensus about constitutional principles cannot be expected in modern multicultural, pluralistic socie-ties. For each, the solution to the problem of radical pluralism must lie elsewhere.

For his part, Michelman refers to “constitutional identity,” and in my view his proposed solution is surprising. Different countries, Michelman says, may have different constitutional identities that explain disagreement over the same principle. In the United States, for example, “constitutional law strongly protects freedom to utter racist hate speech while in Canada it does not.” According to Michelman, the difference indicates not a differ-ence in constitutional principles between the two countries but only “that the two countries have somewhat differing constitutional identities.” And this point, he says, is at “the core of ‘constitutional patriotism’ ”:

“Constitutional patriotism,” it appears, is the morally necessitated readiness of a country’s people to accept disagreement over the application of core con-stitutional principles of respect for everyone as free and equal, without loss of confidence in the univocal content of the principles, because and as long as they can understand the disagreement as strictly tied to struggles over constitu-tional identity.222

With respect to Habermas’s proposed procedural consensus, Michelman remarks that “Habermasian procedure, it appears, is very much a matter of what we sometimes call substance.” Habermas, Michelman points out, has argued that basic human rights are a precondition for the legal institu-tionalization of citizens’ democratic practice, and of the “discourse ideal” of democratic willingness to justify norms to one another Michelman asks, “Is that ideal not a value?” The “convergence” underlying a commitment to democratic procedure is, in Michelman’s characterization, essentially ethical and not merely “procedural.”223

I say that Michelman’s proposed solution is surprising because it seems to rely on the very terms Michelman has challenged in Habermas’s account. After arguing that radical interpretive pluralism means disagreement not just about application but about constitutional essentials themselves,

Page 237: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 226

Michelman uses the notion of constitutional identity to reinstate the dis-tinction between application and content that he has just questioned. In place of procedural consensus, Michelman sees constitutional patriotism as rooted in a substantive consensus over shared ethical values.

More persuasive, in my opinion, is Müller’s explication of constitu-tional patriotism as rooted in a “constitutional culture.” He notes the common usage of “constitutional identity” but instead opts explicitly for “constitutional culture” to “underline[] that we’re not dealing with some-thing homogeneous or even harmonious.” Rather than conceive of consti-tutional patriotism in terms of consensus over values or principles, Müller sees instead in constitutions the possibility of a space or “site for intense and yet reasonable moral and political contestation.” In these cases of rea-sonable disagreement, Müller writes, a constitutional culture provides a “language to contest majority decisions” and “a genuinely moral motiva-tion to maintain the constitutional regime as a whole.” Under conditions of radical interpretive pluralism, a constitutional culture characterized by constitutional patriotism can both enable and contain disagreement. This “contained conflict,” Müller writes, “can in fact also have an integrating and stabilizing effect.”224

In his brief comments on the problem of radical interpretive plural-ism, Habermas sides more with Müller than with Michelman. Habermas criticizes Michelman’s “recourse to a kind of communitarian solution”225 that presupposes consensus about “a set of ‘thick’ ethical beliefs.” “Even if the classical European nation-state had fitted this image,” Habermas writes, “in view of the present pluralism of our more or less multicultural and deeply divided societies, it is no longer plausible to adhere to such a requirement of a strong value consensus.”226 While Habermas notes his agreement with Michelman that “a common practice” is required to han-dle the problem of radical interpretive pluralism,227 he resists—as he did in Between Facts and Norms—a Michelmanian solution that he reads as inap-propriately “ethical” and insufficiently “procedural.”228

Müller uses the idea of a constitutional culture to explain how Haber-masian constitutional patriotism can answer the “specificity” question—the question of how, if the constitutional patriot’s principles are univer-salist, she or he should be committed to one polity rather than another. Constitutional cultures are individuated, Müller suggests, in that “the kinds of conversations and disagreements that characterize” them “are necessarily related to particular national and historical contexts.”229 To some extent, of course, this is correct: Recall, for example, Michelman’s

Page 238: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 227

observation about the different American and Canadian understandings of whether and how far racist speech should be constitutionally protected. But of course, despite the different answers the two countries’ high courts have given, one finds similar arguments pro and con on either side of the border. Still, Müller’s point is that different institutional systems, taken together with different constitutional texts and histories, support different constitutional conversations. In that sense,

Even constitutional patriots . . . do not come from nowhere. They find them-selves entangled in—and hopefully thriving on—particular cultures, and above all, face, sustain, and re-work particular constitutional cultures which are trying to express universal norms of justice and fairness in specific con-texts. The best means to be faithful to universal norms and to render them actionable is to enter and enrich the ongoing conversation about a given politi-cal culture; and constitutional patriots remain faithful to the conversation not least by keeping faith with the ongoing disagreements which might character-ize that conversation.230

In constitutional patriotism, Habermas says, “citizens make the principles of the constitution their own not merely in an abstract sense but also in the concrete historical context of their respective national histories.”231 In the next section, I examine Habermas’s discussion of the possibilities for constitution making and democracy beyond the nation-state. As Pablo de Grieff observes, Habermas’s notion of constitutional patriotism is de-signed to account for integration not just of existing nation-states (address-ing the circumstance of multiculturalism) but also for integration in a con-stitutional democratic system beyond the nation-state. This latter project of integration will be easier to the extent that existing national constitu-tions share common principles and commitments.232

5.3 democr acy a nd the “post nationa l constell ation”

The analysis of Between Facts and Norms was implicitly keyed to the frame-work of nation-states.233 In the years since the 1992 publication of that book, Habermas has begun to consider how that framework might be ex-tended, going so far as to speak of the “postnational constellation.”234 This section examines Habermas’s various post-1992 essays235 with a focus on two strands of his thought. The first concerns the possibilities for democ-racy beyond the nation-state, particularly in the European Union (EU).

Page 239: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 228

Especially on the question whether the EU should adopt a constitution— and, after that attempt failed, whether the Lisbon Treaty is a proper substitute—Habermas has been very much a public voice. The second strand of thought I consider is Habermas’s attempt to appropriate and transform the project Kant established in his 1795 essay Perpetual Peace. The catchwords for this line of thought are “the constitutionalization of international law” and “politically constituted world society without a world government.”

5.3.1 Democracy beyond the Nation-State: The European Union

The starting point for Habermas’s venturing beyond the nation-state model of Between Facts and Norms is his coming to terms with globaliza-tion. Habermas understands globalization as, in the first instance, a specifi-cally capitalist economic process236 (albeit one created by “deliberate politi-cal decisions”237), characterized by expanding trade, increasingly influential transnational corporations with worldwide production capacities, increased direct foreign investment, expanded and intensified networks of commu-nication, and “the growing autonomy of financial circulatory processes, which assume a dynamic of their own distinct from the real economy.”238 If ever there was such a thing as a purely national economy, Haber-mas argues, there is not one now.239 With the “denationalization of the economy”—and by that Habermas means “the increasing global intercon-nection of financial markets and industrial production itself ”—“national politics loses its control over the general conditions of production and with it any leverage for maintaining [a nation’s] standard of living.”240 Habermas observes, of European economies in particular, that this denationalization and “locational competition” is producing high unemployment and “the marginalization of a growing minority for the sake of international com-petitiveness.”241 Only transnational or supranational institutions, according to Habermas, could preserve the “essentials” of the European welfare state and prevent formation of a more or less permanent underclass.242

In each of his treatments of the issue, Habermas identifies a list of new “border-crossing” problems that defy national regulation, including “risks of high technology and arms trafficking”; international drug traf-ficking; “worldwide organized crime and the new decentralized terrorist networks”; transnational environmental problems, including acid rain,243 climate change, and water supply; “the pressure of the massive streams of migration”; “the distribution of scarce energy resources”;244 and world-wide financial crisis.245 In light of “the growing interdependencies of a

Page 240: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 229

world society,” Habermas suggests, we must question the basic premise underlying traditional notions of sovereignty: “that national politics, cir-cumscribed within a determinate national territory, is still adequate to ad-dress the actual facts of individual nation-states.”246

Some of the reasons Habermas presents for exploring governance be-yond the nation-state are primarily functional. “Continental regimes,” like the EU, can serve as a “counterweight” to the sole global superpower and, in Habermas’s view, the misguided and destructive foreign policy ventures it has pursued, particularly under the second President Bush.247 Haber-mas invokes the “counterweight” idea also in connection with processes of economic globalization:248 Continental regimes are necessary, he says, to avoid destructive races to the bottom in battles of locational compe-tition.249 More generally, continental regimes could fulfill coordination functions not suitable for the United Nations.250

But the crisis tendencies Habermas identifies are not just economic and environmental. He sees also a crisis in the solidarity among citizens251 that sustained the democratic constitutional state.252 No analogous solidar-ity, in his view, yet can be drawn on at the transnational or supranational levels. Such transnational or supranational regulation as now operates is accordingly largely nondemocratic. The prime challenge in Habermas’s view is thus to produce forms of democratic governance beyond the nation-state, even though at present the sustaining forms of solidarity are undeveloped. Notwithstanding the difficulties inherent in that project, in Habermas’s view there is no other palatable possibility:

The postnational constellation confronts us with an uncomfortable alterna-tive: either we must abandon the demanding idea of the constitution as a self-administering association of free and equal citizens and resign ourselves to a sociologically disillusioned interpretation of constitutional democracies which have been reduced to mere facades; or we must detach the fading idea of a democratic constitution from its roots in the nation-state and revive it in the postnational guise of a constitutionalized world society.253

Habermas, of course, is unwilling to abandon the idea of the democratic constitution. And so he must investigate the possibilities for democracy beyond the nation-state. While he repeatedly makes clear that he does not place his democratic hopes in the possibility of a world government, he sees in the development of continental regimes “the genuinely utopian mo-ment of a ‘cosmopolitan condition.’ ”254

The presently most advanced venture toward democracy beyond the nation-state is the European Union. In the political essays he has published

Page 241: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 230

in book collections since Between Facts and Norms, and in newspaper ar-ticles and public addresses, Habermas has devoted a great deal of attention to the EU project, particularly with an eye toward addressing its much-discussed “democratic deficit.”255

One widely perceived obstacle to the EU’s democratization has been the lack of a European “demos.” Habermas has expended considerable energy in combating this position. One of his lines of argument attacks the idea that national identities, as opposed to a European identity, are natural, prepolitical entities defined simply by commonalities of language and descent. Instead, Habermas contends, they are partly the product of considerable mythmaking and tradition construction by intellectuals and popular social movements.256 With respect particularly to the case of the German language, he argues, “There is nothing originary about the ho-mogeneity of the linguistic community; it [has] require[d] a leveling of different dialects in favor of a written language imposed by administrative means.”257 And “the idea of national history,” he writes, “was an academic construct made possible by historians, folklorists, linguists, and literary critics.”258 “Collective identities,” he says, “are made, not found.”259

The idea that national identities are prepolitical, Habermas argues, obscures the fact that they have developed partly as the products of constitution-making and constitution-developing processes.260 The “nub of republicanism,” he contends, lies “in the fact that the forms and proce-dures of the constitutional state, together with the democratic mode of le-gitimation, simultaneously forge a new level of social integration.”261 This process was behind the development of the nation-state,262 and Habermas reasons that there is no “necessary socio-ontological reason why solidarity between citizens and the regulatory capacity of the constitution should stop at national borders.”263 In fact, Habermas goes further to suggest that development of a constitutional state that transcends existing nation-state borders is an imperative rooted in both multiculturalism and globaliza-tion. And this state must be democratic:

The challenges of “multiculturalism” and “individualization” both . . . de-mand the end of the symbiosis between the constitutional state and “the na-tion” as a community of shared descent, and a renewal of a more abstract form of civil solidarity. . . . Politics has to catch up with globalized markets, and has to do so in institutional forms that do not regress below the legitimacy condi-tions for democratic self-determination.264

These republican and functionalist lines of reasoning gave Habermas hope that a European constitution, if adopted, would have a “catalytic effect.”265 In 1995 he wrote:

Page 242: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 231

Europe has been integrating economically, socially, and administratively for some time and in addition can base itself on a common cultural background and the shared historical experience of having happily overcome nationalism. Given the political will, there is no a priori reason it cannot create the po-litically necessary communicative context [for European democracy] once the constitutional basis for such a context has been laid down.266

Habermas was among the most prominent advocates of the Treaty Es-tablishing a Constitution for Europe.267 But in 2005 the Treaty failed to receive the required unanimous member-state approval when French and Dutch voters rejected it in separate referenda.

After a two-year official “period of reflection,” and after negotiations among the member states, the Treaty of Lisbon was presented as a substi-tute. The language of “constitution” was dropped (as were the flag and national anthem); the document was considerably shorter; and concessions (particularly to Poland and the United Kingdom)268 were made. This time twenty-six of the twenty-seven member states opted to proceed by parlia-mentary vote rather than referendum. Parliamentary votes went more or less smoothly,269 but in June 2008 the voters in Ireland—the sole country employing the referendum—rejected the Treaty. After a series of negotia-tions and concessions from the EU, the Treaty was put before Irish voters again, and this time they approved. The Treaty went into effect on Decem-ber 1, 2009.

Habermas has criticized sharply the process by which the Treaty of Lis-bon was ratified. As he had suggested with respect to the failed Constitu-tion, Habermas pressed for the Treaty of Lisbon to be put before national voters rather than the political elites in each nation.270 His proposal, in a November 2007 lecture, was to present to voters in each of the member states a referendum, conducted under uniform law, in which “the ques-tion to be decided would be whether they want a politically constituted Europe with a directly elected president, its own foreign minister, a stron-ger harmonization of tax policy, and an alignment of their respective so-cial policies.” Unlike the actual ratification process, Habermas’s proposal would not have required unanimity among member states before any legal change could be effected. At the same time, he would not have imposed change on any member state whose electorate voted “no” in the referen-dum. Instead, “the proposal would be deemed accepted if it succeeded in winning the ‘double majority’ of the states and of the votes of the citizens,” but “the referendum would be binding only on those member states in which a majority of the citizens voted for the reform.”271

Page 243: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 232

The process actually followed for ratification, both with the Treaty Establishing a Constitution for Europe and with the Treaty of Lisbon, exemplified a “convoy” model “in which the slowest vehicle determines the speed.”272 By contrast, Habermas’s proposal of “graduated integration” or “a Europe of different speeds” would have allowed that at least for a period of transition there might develop a “Europe of core and periphery.” He ex-pressed confidence that the referendum would attain the required double majority, and in his prediction voters in the more reluctant nations would feel pressure to join the core: Faced with the “unpalatable alternative” of remaining outside the reformed Union, he predicted, they “would also be inclined to align themselves with the center.”273

Habermas’s language criticizing the undemocratic character of the Lis-bon ratification process is extraordinarily strong. While the “intention” of both the Constitution and the Lisbon Treaty was “to promote a higher level of participation from citizens across national frontiers,” he observes, there was no “mobilization of citizens during the constitution-founding process”:

Instead of this, the slimmed-down reform treaty now definitively sets the seal on the elitist character of a political process which is remote from the popula-tions. The negotiation procedure, the failure to conduct referenda even where they are actually called for, the bizarre rejection of the already established communal symbols (such as the flag and the anthem), finally the national ex-clusion clauses and the deflationary publicity campaigns employed by some of the governments to sell the result of Lisbon at home—all of this reinforces the established political modus operandi and renders conclusive the fearful decoupling of the European project from the formation of opinion and will by the citizens. Never before, at turning points in the unification process, has European politics been conducted in such a blatantly elitist and bureaucratic manner as on this occasion. In this way the political class is sending the signal that it is the privilege of the governments to decide the future destiny of Europe behind closed doors.274

As to the substance of the Lisbon Treaty, Habermas is far from fully sat-isfied. He praises, as an appropriate efficiency-creating measure, the in-troduction of qualified-majority legislative voting procedures (rather than unanimity) in the Council of Ministers.275 While Habermas has not to my knowledge commented explicitly, likely he would approve of the new mechanism that allows member-state parliaments, whose democratic cre-dentials are presently stronger than those of EU institutions, to participate on a consultative basis in EU legislation.276 Further, Habermas has stated that he approves in principle the strengthened powers of the European

Page 244: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 233

Parliament. But even there, he complains that citizens will “derive no ben-efit from a formally strengthened status of the Parliament” without deeper political change in the Union. The political change Habermas envisions, it would seem, could not be accomplished solely and directly by treaty modi-fication or even a formal constitution. What is required, he writes, is that “the usual spectrum of opinions and relevant issues within the national public spheres [must be] broadened and . . . the public spheres [must] be-come responsive to one another.”277

Habermas has been making similar suggestions since before the Eu-ropean Constitution was proposed. They come straight from the “model of the circulation of power” that Habermas proposed in Between Facts and Norms. There, Habermas specified the following necessary conditions for genuine (rather than merely formal) democracy: (1) links between the formal decisionmaking institutions of the political system’s core, on one side, with the peripheral political public sphere; (2) a social basis for the political public sphere in “vibrant” voluntary associations of civil society; and (3) a common democratic political culture that meets the political system halfway.

The first problem Habermas faces is that presently each of these pre-suppositions is lacking. There is at present, he allows, no global or even European political public sphere.278 Nor is there yet a network of voluntary associations that could be called world or even European civil society.279 Further, Habermas admits (though with less emphasis than skeptics of the European Union) there is no strongly developed European political iden-tity or consciousness280—at least not in any form comparable to national political identity and consciousness.

A second problem is that each of these presuppositions of democ-racy seems to presuppose the others—and Habermas admits the problem forthrightly. Development of a European political public sphere depends upon a social basis in Europe-wide civil society, he says,281 but, at the same time, a pan-European civil society requires a Europe-wide political pub-lic sphere.282 A developed European common political identity, Habermas allows, presupposes both a working European public sphere and a pan-European civil society,283 but the relation of presupposition is mutual.284 Habermas, recall, had supported a European constitution as a “catalyst” for dealing with these difficulties. But the constitution died in 2005, and, in view of his critical comments about the ratification process, Habermas does not seem to see the Lisbon Treaty as likely “catalytic.”

With respect to the absence of a specifically European public sphere, Habermas has repeatedly noted that it is not as though one needs to be

Page 245: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 234

built from scratch. What is required, instead, is that existing national pub-lic spheres be mutually open to one another in the right way.285 Habermas uses various metaphors to describe this relation. In the first, he speaks of “interlinked national public spheres” in which discussion can be “synchro-nized.”286 He makes the electronic undertones of the metaphor explicit when he writes that a European public sphere “can arise only insofar as the circuits of communication within the national arenas open themselves up to one another while themselves remaining intact.”287 In different meta-phors, he suggests that there must be “mutually translated processes of communication within the national spheres” and an “osmotic[]” absorp-tion of issues. He rejects what he calls the “multilayered cake” conception in which the European public sphere would constitute “a higher level of communication, with its own European-wide media operating in a second language.”288 Existing national public spheres could become more mutu-ally responsive, he says, without somehow “constructing a supranational public sphere” and without “drastic changes in the existing infrastruc-ture.”289 His most extended diagnosis of the problem makes clear that the key features are an explicit focus on all-European issues, as opposed to their approach through the proxy of national issues and figures, and a syn-chronized set of discussions:

Major hurdles undoubtedly remain. A constitution will not be enough. It can only initiate the democratic processes in which it must then take root. Since agreements between member-states will remain a factor even in a politically constituted Union, a federal European state will, in any case, be of a different calibre than national federal states; it cannot simply copy their legitimation processes. A European party system will come about only to the extent that the existing parties, in national arenas at first, debate the future of Europe, discovering in the process interests that transcend borders. This discussion must be synchronized throughout Europe in interlinked national public spheres; that is, the same issues must be discussed at the same time, so as to foster the emergence of a European civil society with its interest groups, non-governmental organizations, civic initiatives, and so forth.290

Habermas recently has given extended consideration to the idea of the public sphere in his essay “Political Communication in Media Society: Does Democracy Still Have an Epistemic Dimension? The Impact of Nor-mative Theory on Empirical Research.”291 This account develops and in some ways refines the analysis of the public sphere presented in Between Facts and Norms. Unfortunately, its prime focus is on “the political role played by national public spheres in the liberal constitutional states of the West,”292 with a few suggestions at the end as to how the idea he develops

Page 246: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 235

could be transposed to the Europe-wide and global levels. Nonetheless, his new account of the public sphere is worth considering.

Whereas Habermas’s tripartite schema of Between Facts and Norms dis-tinguished among liberal, republican, and procedural models, this recent essay uses a schema of liberal, republican, and deliberative theories of de-mocracy.293 As before, he associates the liberal model with an emphasis on private autonomy and the republican model with an emphasis on pub-lic autonomy; the deliberative model, as he said of the procedural model, comprehends both. And the deliberative model is in his view uniquely qualified to comprehend present-day societies. Interestingly, given the widely held perception that deliberative conceptions are unrealistic and out of touch with present social complexity, Habermas claims that deliberative theory excels in its ability to “relat[e] . . . strong normative ideas to present-day social complexity.” This is so, he says, because of “the revolution in electronic communication.”294 His idea seems to be that (for reasons ex-plained in the following pages) the deliberative model is well attuned to communication that does not take place face-to-face.

As before, Habermas understands the public sphere as intermediary in a number of ways: between state and voters,295 between state and so-ciety,296 and (as periphery of the political system) between the “core” of state institutions and the political system’s environment of civil society.297 He uses also some of the same metaphors that he used in Between Facts and Norms: The public sphere is a “sounding board” for “society-wide” problems first discussed in civil-social associations298 and a “filter”299 or “filter-bed” from which emerge “the reasonable elements of opinion for-mation” in “the murky streams of political communication.”300 The pub-lic sphere, he emphasizes, is “reflexive.”301 The “elites” who participate in public-sphere communication “absorb impulses” from civil-social commu-nication and “send them back in, a reworked form, to the public of voters.” In this way the public sphere produces “reflected public opinions”302 that come both from “above” (from political elites) and from “below” (from civil society).303 Participants in public-sphere discussion observe and com-ment on “what they perceive as ‘public opinion’ ”—and, in so doing, par-ticipate in the process of generating public opinion.

The public sphere is thus a central part of Habermas’s revised model of the democratic process—a model corresponding to what Between Facts and Norms called “the model of the circulation of power.” He now describes the public sphere as approached from three different “angles”: from the political system’s “center” (the state’s “system of offices”), from “functional

Page 247: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 236

systems” (the economy, of course, but Habermas does not specify another “functional system”), and from “civil society.” Different actors enter the public sphere from these directions: From the political system’s center, we see politicians and political parties, from the functional systems we see “lobbyists and special interest groups” as “representatives” of the systems, and from civil society we see “advocates, public interest groups, churches, intellectuals, and non-governmental organizations.”304 Also in the public-sphere mix are journalists—with the direction from which they enter left unspecified. The difference from Habermas’s prior model is that in the earlier rendition Habermas saw two groups of the above personnel as oc-cupying the outer periphery of the political system—not specifically the public sphere—with the functional systems’ representatives described as political-system “customers” (presumably of government largesse) and the civil-social figures as political-system “suppliers” (presumably of ideas or normative insights). Politicians and political parties occupied the political system’s center, not the public sphere.

The various public-sphere actors that Habermas identifies all must op-erate through the mass communications media if their efforts are to have influence. Habermas calls the mass media the “infrastructure of the public sphere.”305 From one point of view, media-based communication suffers from two “deficits” or “defects” that are relevant to a theory of democracy. First, it “lacks the procedural constraints to which face-to-face negotiations in political institutions such as courts or parliamentary committees are subject.” It lacks, according to Habermas, “standards of discursive qual-ity, or even representativeness.” Second, it lacks the two-way, reciprocal exchange that is part of Habermas’s idea of discourse and communicative rationality. In media-based communication we do not find “an egalitarian exchange of opinions and claims.”306 Self-consciously invoking a theatrical metaphor and analogy, Habermas writes that the media experts and the politicians dominate in “the dramaturgy of the public sphere.”307 Thus, in the public sphere, Habermas sees forms of communication that hardly seem to fit his discourse theory or the deliberative model of politics. He will have to provide reasons, nonetheless, that a deliberative form of de-mocracy can take hold.

He approaches this task by, first, extending the notion of power he developed in earlier work. For present purposes, he sets out four differ-ent types.308 “Political power,” he says, “inherently requires legitimation,” and in the constitutional state an especially “demanding form” is required: “the reasonable agreement of all citizens to the principles and procedures

Page 248: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 237

of the political decision-making process.”309 This formulation, in my view is too strong: It confuses, or at least threatens to confuse, the hypotheti-cal unanimity Habermas has required in the past with actual unanimous agreement. (I have already criticized even the requirement of hypotheti-cal unanimous agreement.) As before, Habermas identifies also “social power,” which “rests on status within a stratified society and is generally attached to positions within functional systems.” A special form of so-cial power, and “the dominant form in capitalist societies,” is “economic power.”310 A central concern of democracy is to control the conversion of social (particularly economic) power into political power (though adminis-trative power might be the better term here).

The preceding three types of power echo Habermas’s earlier analysis. The innovation in Habermas’s typology is the notion of “media power.” This form of power is “based on the technology and infrastructure of mass communication” and exercised by “reporters, columnists, editors, publish-ers, directors, and producers.” It operates through the selection and fram-ing of content in media presentations. Habermas suggests that its magni-tude can be “measured by the resonance which a program generates in the public sphere.”311

So described, the notion of media power is not an inherently critical or even normative concept. All content must be presented and framed. And the idea of “resonance” is neutral as to the normative desirability of that resonance. Habermas begins to introduce a critical dimension with the re-quirement that the media be editorially independent “from pressure exer-cised by politically, economically, and socially powerful actors.”312 Second, “civil society must also enable its citizens to participate in an inclusive pro-cess of public opinion formation.”313 In other words, media power must not overwhelm the communicative power that emerges from civil-social discussion and citizen participation in the public sphere.

As one example of insufficient media independence, Habermas cites the general failure of the American media, including the New York Times and other members of the “quality press,” to examine critically the government-provided “information” during the 2002–2003 buildup to the Iraq invasion. Because politicians and political parties are “the most important suppliers” of “political events, news, and commentaries,” the danger of improper gov-ernment influence on coverage is ever present. Habermas identifies also as a form of insufficient independence “the media’s lack of distance from associations and organizations representing economic or other special in-terests.” This undue influence, Habermas writes, is “less spectacular but

Page 249: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 238

more frequent.”314A special case here is when media barons develop politi-cal ambitions. (Habermas names both Rupert Murdoch and Silvio Ber-lusconi.) While Habermas identifies as a danger the “colonization of the public sphere by market imperatives,”315 he cautions that not just any link-age between the market and communications media is to be criticized. In the eighteenth century, Habermas maintains, “the reorientation of the pro-duction and distribution of cultural products to the conditions of market exchange” had at least in part an “emancipatory effect.” The phenomena Habermas criticizes are the “redefinition of political questions in terms of the categories of advertising,” “the personalization of serious debates, the dramatization of events, the crude simplification of complex matters, and a polarizing exaggeration of conflicts.” In this “infotainment,” Habermas argues, we have a confusion between modes of communication. The critical standard Habermas suggests is the following:

It is only when the functional imperatives of the market interfere with the “in-ternal logic” of the production and presentation of messages and programs in broadcasting that one mode of communication is surreptitiously replaced by another. Infotainment is one of the catchwords for the adjustment of political discussion to the style and substance of entertainment.316

One would think that the Internet would at least begin to address two problems Habermas identifies in the media system. The first is “selective access to, and uneven participation in, media-based political communica-tion.”317 The second is the “asymmetric structure” of non-Internet media that doesn’t allow users to “talk back”318—or, to use a more usual Haber-masian term, exchange roles of speaker and addressee. (As to a third prob-lem Habermas mentions—the lack of face-to-face interaction, with an accompanying absence of “standards of discursive quality, or even repre-sentativeness”319—the Internet scores less well.)

After early dismissal of the Internet’s democratic possibilities,320 Habermas more recently has recognized that Internet communication “seems to counterbalance the weaknesses associated with the anonymous and asymmetrical character of mass communication.” It allows “unregu-lated exchange between partners who communicate with one another as equals, if only virtually.” In Internet use Habermas sees not just “inquisi-tive surfers” but also the revival of an “egalitarian public of reading and writing conversational partners and correspondents.”321

But at this point Habermas begins to reverse field. Internet communi-cation, he says, has “unequivocal democratic merit” only with respect to authoritarian societies, where “it undermines censorship by authoritarian

Page 250: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 239

regimes which try to control and suppress spontaneous public opinions.” Matters are different in “liberal regimes”:

Here the emergence of millions of “chat rooms” scattered throughout the world and of globally networked “issue publics” tends rather to fragment the huge mass public, which in the public sphere is centered on the same issues at the same time in spite of its size.

And here Habermas revives his earlier diagnosis and decries the Internet-caused disintegration into “fragmented groups.” With the “centrifugal tendencies” of the Internet, he says, “The existing national publics seem to be undermined rather than reinforced.” This is because one problem he identifies with Internet communication is the same one he attributes to the insufficiently linked national public spheres of Europe: a lack of syn-chronization, which if present would have speakers and audiences address-ing the same issues at the same time. This problem, he seems to think, is addressed only during times such as “election campaigns,” when “interest and support” can be mobilized and focused. Only at such times, he says with evident exaggeration, can “political communication within national publics see[m] at present to be able to benefit from online debates.” And thus, he concludes, “appealing to the Internet cannot dispel the prima facie doubt over the potentially positive contribution of mass communication to deliberative politics.”322

This diagnosis of the Internet’s possibilities seems to me too abbreviated to be very convincing. I say that as someone skeptical of many of the largest claims made for the Internet’s democratic political possibilities. Habermas needs to address the question more systematically and at greater length.323

Notwithstanding his judgment of the Internet’s democratic potential, Habermas’s overall judgment of the public sphere’s present possibilities for democracy is relatively positive. He relies on recent empirical studies that suggest confirmation for the “truth-tracking” power of deliberation. For example, he reports that Michael Neblo has found that group deliberation “tended to promote a convergence rather than a polarization of opinions”; this evidence Habermas interprets as a group “learning process[].”324 James Fishkin’s well-known “deliberative polling” experiments have indicated, Habermas notes, that group deliberation increases participants’ substantive knowledge and allows them to “counter unreflective framing effects.”325 In a study conducted just about the time Habermas’s essay went to press, Fishkin conducted a deliberative poll with EU voters and found, as effects of deliberation, both increase in knowledge and tendencies toward conver-gence in opinion.326 Habermas discusses other studies to similar effect.327

Page 251: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 240

He does not acknowledge, however, that other studies have come to con-flicting results. Most notably, Cass Sunstein has found that deliberation, at least among the like-minded, may tend to produce polarization of opinion and, rather than changing minds, it may tend to confirm participants’ ini-tial points of view.328 And of course also there are difficult questions of institutional design that must be answered before small-group techniques could be adapted for use in mass democratic processes—although propos-als certainly are being made.329

Thus, despite his recognition of the media’s lapses of independence, his acknowledgment of “infotainment” and other “media effects,” and his identification of structural differences between media-based communica-tion and his model of discourse, Habermas concludes that his deliberative model of democracy can be sufficiently realized “under favorable conditions” in the “media-dominated public sphere.”330 Perhaps more important than this conclusion, which as noted is still controversial, is Habermas’s effort to make his deliberative model empirically testable. This effort is what has made Habermas’s recent essay on democracy in “media society” one that is “particularly close to [his] heart.”331

As Habermas acknowledges, however, his theoretical account of the public sphere in media society is keyed to national rather than transna-tional societies.332 For the foreseeable future, he recognizes, Europe-wide political democracy will have something of a derivative character, depend-ing to a considerable extent upon parallel processes within the member states. Habermas writes:

[A Europe-wide “cosmopolitan condition”] must receive indirect “backing” from the kinds of democratic processes of opinion- and will-formation that can only be fully institutionalized within constitutional states, regardless of how complex federal states on a continental scale may become. This weak form of constitutionalization beyond the nation-state remains reliant on continual provisions of legitimacy from within state-centered systems. Only within states does the organizational part of the constitution secure citizens equal access to the politically binding decisions of the government through insti-tutionalized publics, elections, parliaments, and other forms of participation. Only within constitutional states do administrative mechanisms exist to in-sure the equal inclusion of citizens in the legislative process.333

Two important consequences follow from this analysis. First, despite Habermas’s reference to the “postnational constellation,” nation-states will retain a vital and even preeminent role in the project of democratic consti-tutionalism.334 To the extent that the future realizes Habermas’s hope of “links” between national and transnational public spheres and civil societ-

Page 252: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 241

ies, as well as between national and supranational political institutions,335 the “model of the circulation of power” with which Habermas’s Between Facts and Norms sought to capture the democratic political process would have to be amended and complicated.

Second, consider Habermas’s admission that “democratic processes of opinion- and will-formation . . . can only be fully institutionalized within constitutional states, regardless of how complex federal states on a conti-nental scale may become.”336 This does not seem consistent with Haber-mas’s suggestion that we must “detach the fading idea of a democratic con-stitution from its roots in the nation-state and revive it in the postnational guise of a constitutionalized world society.”337 Habermas’s admission also seems to suggest that the idea of “constitutional patriotism,” which he has defended as a basis for integrating increasingly multicultural states, might not serve to integrate new “postnational” forms of political society.338 Moreover, if political institutions beyond the nation-state cannot satisfy the public sphere/civil society/parliament model of democracy that Haber-mas has defended in Between Facts and Norms, might we need to rethink the idea of democracy?339

While Habermas’s model of Between Facts and Norms focuses on parlia-ments as the key form of governance, an assumption of many contempo-rary EU scholars is that the days of twentieth-century parliamentarianism are gone.340 Some scholars, largely sympathetic to Habermas’s normative aims, have tried to describe the new policy-making developments charac-terized as “comitology” as consistent with at least some aspects of Haber-mas’s understanding of democracy.

Comprehensive review and assessment of the comitology literature is beyond the scope of this book. But briefly, “comitology” refers to a pro-cess by which the European Commission—the executive body of the EU—implements legislation adopted by the European Council or Parliament. In the structure of committees, “European and national officials interact with various private and semipublic players (e.g. administrations, depart-ments, private and public associations, and certain, mainly corporate, inter-est groups).”341 Advocates of comitology laud its deliberative qualities, its mobilization of “experts and counter-experts,”342 and its inclusion of those most directly affected by the policy in question.343 In these respects, one sees connections to Habermas’s discourse theory of democracy.344 But ad-vocates for the comitology model see it as involving norm creation as well as the implementation of legislatively prescribed norms.345 To that extent, the model is in tension with Habermas’s understanding of the separation of

Page 253: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 242

powers, according to which the administration must be limited to “prag-matic discourses” with “pregiven” normative premises.346

To be sure, even those sympathetic to the comitology model acknowl-edge its defects. Formally, its constitutionality is questionable,347 and both parliamentary oversight and judicial review still are lacking.348 Comito-logical operations are not altogether transparent to citizens.349 Access to committees is unequal, measured both across EU member states350 and across social strata.351 The comitological process clearly is incompletely democratic.

But the comitological model is only one possible form of new insti-tutional design for political democracy beyond the nation-state. While Habermas’s discussion of EU developments would be stronger if he had engaged this specific and well-known proposal, his arguments typically operate at a higher level of abstraction than that occupied by questions of institutional design. Still, Habermas’s writings still might be taken to inform discussions of institutional design. Further, some of his remarks about “transnational negotiation systems” (see section 5.3.2) would seem to apply to, or at least have implications for, the EU committee structure.352

5.3.2 The Constitutionalization of International Law: Politically Constituted World Society without a World Government

A final dimension of Habermas’s recent political writings is his consid-eration and transformation of Kant’s project of “perpetual peace.” Haber-mas’s catchphrases here are “politically constituted world society without world government,”353 and “the constitutionalization of international law.”

Habermas first systematically addresses Kant’s project in a 1995 essay “Kant’s Idea of Perpetual Peace: At Two Hundred Years Removed.”354 He reads Kant as aiming to establish a cosmopolitan law “alongside state law and international law.” The end point of the historical process was to be “a global legal order that unites all peoples and abolishes war.” The principles of cosmopolitan law were to be those already “implemented within single states.”355 Kant distinguished sharply between the “federation of nations” (Völkerbund) that he envisioned and a “state of all peoples” (Völkerstaat). The original states were to retain their independence. In contrast to the so-cial contract that models existing states, the basis for the world federation would be the treaty. In this sense, the basis for cosmopolitan law differs from existing international law only in its projected permanence.356

Page 254: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 243

But what is the foundation for this projected permanence, Habermas asks? If the federation, unlike the state, lacks a constitution that authorizes coercive authority, and if in general it provides no actionable legal rights to federation members, then the obligation to respect the federation and maintain the peace lacks a legal basis. According to Habermas, Kant’s “so-berly realistic descriptions of the politics of his time” make belief in an effective moral obligation difficult to credit. And so, Habermas maintains, Kant “glosses over” the problem “with a mere appeal to reason.” Enter the philosophy of history, in which “a hidden ‘purpose of nature’ ” is to bring about “the improbable ‘agreement between politics and morality.’ ”357

Habermas points to three features of the historical situation that, in Kant’s account, were to align reason with self-interest. In each instance, Habermas seeks not just to discern what disappointed Kant’s hopes but to discover whether there might be reason to expect different results in the present and future. Two of the developments are worth mentioning.

The first concerns globalization. Kant had hoped that trade among members of the federation would provide sufficient incentive to deter war. The actual developments, according to Habermas, are much more ambiva-lent. “Nongovernmental actors such as multinational corporations and in-ternationally influential private banks undermine the formal sovereignty of nation-states,” Habermas writes. And with the “denationalization” of econo-mies, the ability of nations to “profit from their economies” by benefiting from trade is diminished. Accordingly, the incentives toward peace that Kant had hoped for are diminished, even as trade among nations has increased.358

The second development concerns the public sphere. According to Habermas, Kant saw philosophers as monitors of republican principles, and, while he foresaw the dangers of censorship, he did not anticipate the systematic manipulation of public opinion. I have already discussed Haber-mas’s view of these developments. What is interesting here is that Haber-mas sees the potential development of a “global public sphere.” It first be-gan to emerge, according to Habermas, around events such as the Vietnam War and the first Gulf War, then around global summit meetings. The possibilities of a more permanent worldwide public sphere are uncertain:

To be sure one should not overlook the fact that this temporary, issue-specific public attention is still channeled through the established structures of national public spheres. Supporting structures are needed to institute permanent com-munication between geographically distant participants who simultaneously exchange contributions on the same themes with the same relevance. In this

Page 255: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 244

sense, there is not yet a global public sphere, nor even the urgently needed Eu-ropean public sphere.

One supportive trend that Habermas discerns is the development of an international civil society: a network of nongovernmental organizations from which public-sphere communication might draw. Habermas men-tions Amnesty International and Greenpeace as specific examples, but more generally he sees “at least an indication of the growing impact on the press and media of actors who confront states from within the network of an international civil society.”359

According to Habermas, a reformulation of Kant’s project must re-construct the ideas of external and internal sovereignty that the Westpha-lian system of nation-states presupposes. If a cosmopolitan legal order is to be binding, it requires a legal code with sanctions for violations. The U.N. charter’s ban on offensive war making and its peacekeeping ventures, however, are only a beginning. In his 1995 “Perpetual Peace” essay and elsewhere, Habermas mentions as obstacles the Security Council single-power veto,360 with resulting limits on peacekeeping interventions, and the absence of binding judgments against nonconsenting states from the International Court of Justice.361 He cites also, though less clearly by way of criticism, the circumstance that the United Nations does not itself have a military force but must instead rely on troops supplied by the member nations.362

From the side of internal sovereignty, Habermas rejects Kant’s idea that only states and not individuals count as members of citizens of the envisioned cosmopolitan community. With the development of interna-tional human rights law, the beginning steps have been made toward a cosmopolitan legal order. While the law requires states to respect the basic human rights of their citizens, it at the same time “bypasses the collec-tive subjects of international law and directly establishes the legal status of the individual subject” with “unmediated membership in the associa-tion of free and equal world citizens.” As an institutional framework in which these cosmopolitan human rights are to be developed and enforced, Habermas mentions the U.N. Human Rights Commission as monitor and reporter of violations, together with what has become the new Interna-tional Criminal Court (ICC). Habermas endorses the idea of personal li-ability for human rights crimes as a positive development, and he applauds the move away from only ad hoc human rights tribunals. The ICC’s pow-ers, however, are limited by the refusal of several key nations, including the United States, to participate as party states. Enforcement of human rights

Page 256: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 245

guarantees, Habermas observes, is weakened further by the absence of an international executive power.363

As steps toward the constitutionalization of international law, Haber-mas’s 1995 Kant essay, together with more recent articles,364 emphasizes U.N. reforms. In his first set of proposals, Habermas recommends con-verting the General Assembly into “a kind of upper House” (analogous to the U.S. Senate), with the establishment of a parliament of directly represented citizens. Countries that refuse democratic elections “could be represented in the interim by the World Parliament itself as the representa-tives of oppressed populations.”365 The Security Council’s unanimity rule would be abolished, and regional regimes would be granted representa-tion. Habermas’s model here is the Council of the European Union.366

But how would a constitutionalization of international law, with the institutional reforms mentioned above, stop short of a world state? And why would a world state be undesirable?

As to the second question, Habermas sees a world state as at least po-tentially “normalizing,” that is, overly assimilative of national difference.367 In addition, the idea is for Habermas utopian in a pejorative sense. To saddle a supranational organization with general rights-protecting respon-sibilities would require securing at the same time “the ‘empowering’ mate-rial conditions” needed for effective exercise of those rights. This responsi-bility, Habermas believes, would “overtax the capacities and political will of the international community.”368 Networks and nonstate organizations at the transnational level, intermediate between the territorial states and the United Nations, are required to address these matters.

The difference between the constitutionalization of international law and the development of a world state is more difficult to explain.369 Haber-mas distinguishes conceptually between constitution and state: The former effects a horizontal association of citizens, and the latter implies vertical relations of authority. But his description of the power a world state would enjoy—“a supranational power above competing states that would equip the international community with the executive and sanctioning powers required to implement and enforce its rules and decisions”—is difficult to distinguish from his proposed U.N. reforms.370 The difference Habermas has in mind seems to lie in the limited number of functions he would as-sign to the world organization: peacekeeping (albeit of a more ambitious scope than originally recognized)371 and the enforcement of basic human rights if territorial states refuse or are unable to enforce them.372 There is no “structural analogy,” Habermas says, between an organization assigned

Page 257: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 246

few and limited functions by territorial states and “the constitution of a sovereign state that can determine what political competences it claims for itself (and hence possesses supreme constitutional authority).”373

The U.N. reforms concern the supranational level. At the “transna-tional” level, Habermas emphasizes the importance of “regional” or “con-tinental regimes” on the model of the European Union.374 The “world do-mestic policy” Habermas envisions would be made largely at this level. He has in mind organizations—or, as he often says, “negotiation systems”—that are separate from the World Trade Organization, International Mon-etary Fund, and World Bank. Habermas’s list of problems to be addressed at this level is lengthy. He mentions, in various essays: “extreme disparities in wealth within the stratified world society, . . . ecological imbalances, and . . . collective threats,”375 “global energy and . . . environmental, finan-cial, and economic policy.”376 Habermas describes the task here as politics “ ‘catching up’ with globalized markets.”377 While markets already are ef-fectively globalized, the political organization needed for the transnational regulation Habermas envisions lags far behind: “With the exception of the United States,” he writes, “there are at present no viable actors at the in-termediate or transnational level.”378 If constitutional patriotism is a chal-lenge at the level of the nation-state, its transnational analogue may be more difficult still. What is needed, Habermas says, is the “rais[ing]” of “international consciousness” “to an ever higher level of abstraction in the process of integrating nation-states into continental regimes.”379

As one might expect, Habermas emphasizes the need for legitimation of any new transnational organizations and greater legitimation for the expanding scope of activity by the existing supranational organization, the United Nations. Despite his distinction between state constitutions and the constitution of trans- or supranational organizations, Habermas asserts repeatedly that there is no a priori reason to limit democratic prin-ciples to the national level at which they were first institutionalized. Their universalistic meaning points beyond the nation-state. To quote again Habermas’s most striking formulation: “We must detach the fading idea of a democratic constitution from its roots in the nation-state and revive it in the postnational guise of a constitutionalized world society.”380 But the question remains how to implement democratic constitutional prin-ciples. I have discussed above Habermas’s suggestions with respect to the European Union; I consider here briefly his other ideas for the trans- and supranational levels.

Page 258: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 247

The proposed second legislative chamber for the United Nations would be an instance of directly democratic implementation. And to the extent that it induces member states to set up genuinely democratic elec-tions for U.N. deputies—the unattractive alternative Habermas provides is U.N.-appointed representation for nondemocratic nations’ “oppressed populations”—one might hope for democratic spillover into national poli-tics. For the United Nations, Habermas suggests indirectly democratic le-gitimating strategies as well. He proposes: “Opinion- and will-formation within the world organization should be connected back to the circuits of communication within national parliaments and should be subject to more effective monitoring by NGOs and other representatives of a mobilized world public.”381

For transnational negotiation systems, Habermas requires that there be a fair balance of power,382 suggested by his idea of bargaining as the sometimes necessary substitute for discourse.383 One apparent difficulty, however, is that while a balance of bargaining power may be established at the national level through law—either directly or by adjusting background entitlements—similar possibilities for adjusting power differentials seem lacking when the bargaining partners are states. Beyond a fair balance of power, Habermas mentions the need for “public criticism, deliberation, and political reaction by affected citizens in their respective national are-nas.”384 Here as elsewhere, the involvement of nongovernmental organiza-tions is essential. But for Habermas, the needed legitimation for transna-tional networks and bargaining systems must be primarily indirect, that is, dependent on the democratic political processes in the territorial states. He is emphatic on this point:

Transnational negotiation systems . . . must receive indirect “backing” from the kinds of democratic processes of opinion- and will-formation that can only be fully institutionalized within constitutional states, regardless of how com-plex federal states on a continental scale may become. This weak form of con-stitutionalization beyond the nation-state remains reliant on continual pro-visions of legitimacy from within state-centered systems. Only within states does the organizational part of the constitution secure citizens equal access to the politically binding decisions of the government through institutionalized publics, elections, parliaments, and other forms of participation. Only within constitutional states do administrative mechanisms exist to insure the equal inclusion of citizens in the legislative process.385

The burden of legitimation would seem much greater for transnational organizations than for the supranational U.N. organization. The latter’s

Page 259: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 248

functions, Habermas has emphasized, are limited; transnational organi-zations are assigned more far-reaching responsibilities of global domes-tic politics. While Habermas allows that with respect to securing peace and protecting basic human rights, “the requisite solidarity among world citizens need not reach the level of implicit consensus on thick political value-orientations that is necessary for the familiar kind of civic solidar-ity among fellow-nationals,” a different conclusion seems required at the transnational level.386

The preceding analysis of needed transnational and supranational de-velopments comes mostly from essays Habermas published in 2005 and 2006. In 2008, he published a lecture that addresses criticisms of his pro-posals. Again he insists on the conceptual difference between a world con-stitution and the constitution of a nation-state. There is no prepolitical global civil society, he suggests, that could be the basis for a social con-tract. Instead, Habermas argues, the development of a world constitution must reckon not just with individuals as subjects but with states as subjects as well: Individuals and states “constitut[e] the two categories of founding subjects of a world constitution.”387

Habermas’s most recent proposal modifies slightly his suggestion for U.N. reorganization. While the twin functions of securing peace and protecting human rights would remain the same, the U.N. Charter now would “play the role of a cosmopolitan constitution.” Habermas proposes two possible institutional arrangements. In the first, there would be a one-chamber General Assembly with representatives of “the cosmopoli-tan citizens” and also delegates from member states’ democratically elected parliaments. The other possibility would be (as in his earlier suggestion) a two-chamber parliament with representation for individuals and states, respectively. According to Habermas’s proposal, this supranational legisla-tive body would “initially convene as a Constituent Assembly” but subse-quently assume the form of a “World Parliament.” The “legislative func-tion” of this world parliament “would be confined to the interpretation and elaboration of the Charter.”388

As before, transnational organizations would have to address issues beyond the U.N. peacekeeping and (secondary) basic-rights-protecting mission. The boundary between national and transnational competence would be a recurring issue. Even if we could expect greater cooperation among states and peoples, national governments would retain much of their authority. As Habermas frames the question: When must national

Page 260: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 249

governments’ duties to their own citizens “take a back seat to the legal ob-ligations which the states incur towards all cosmopolitan citizens equally as members of the international community?”389

Habermas is frank about the difficulties his proposal would face. The means for enforcement of supranational decisions would have to come from “able and willing members.” Habermas can only hope that those able and willing members would adopt a more global and less nationally self-interested perspective than the United States so far has done. And as to the possibility of using transnational organizations to implement a global domestic politics, Habermas acknowledges that “we lack at present the necessary institutions and procedures to decide upon programs and to implement them on a broad scale.”390 As noted, the requirement of fair compromise would seem to presuppose a more equal balance of power (economic as well as military) than presently exists or could be expected to be established in the foreseeable future.

Further, Habermas again acknowledges that a politically constituted world society would face legitimation difficulties. The general idea, Habermas says, is to “connect up with the existing, though inadequate, modes of legitimation of the constitutional state, while at the same time supplementing them with” new means of legitimation.391 Prospects seem brighter with respect to the supranational U.N. organization than with the transnational negotiating regimes. As Habermas notes, the idea of a duty not to commit wars of aggression is “anchored in all cultures.” And thus the development of “judicially elaborated standards” at the suprana-tional level can to that extent draw on “a ‘credit’ of legitimation.”392 At the transnational level, by contrast, the more encompassing political issues would require that the participating states themselves be democratic. As Habermas allows, “This extension of the chain of legitimation of dem-ocratic procedures beyond national borders is . . . an immensely ambi-tious requirement.” The development of a requisite global public sphere would require that national public spheres be mutually “responsive to one another”—and that means that nationally organized publics would have to consider the same issues at the same time. This deliberation would have to be democratic. As Habermas’s projection of a European public sphere indicates, that prospect is presently unrealized even at a level more mod-est than the global public sphere. Habermas speaks of necessary “learning processes” both for states and for peoples.393

Page 261: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 250

concluding questions

At age 81, Habermas has not yet slowed his pace of scholarly and public-political production. Indeed, as this chapter indicates, he has extended his project ambitiously to consider prospects for democracy and human rights beyond the nation-state. This extension, I think understandably, leaves open key questions for further analysis. In closing this book, I mention only a few such questions.

First, although it may be plausible in “reconstructing” Western liberal democracies to identify legitimate law with democratically produced law, that choice is more problematic in the case of nonliberal and nondemo-cratic societies. While Habermas’s discourse theory of law and democracy could provide an external critical standard for such societies, it would lack the immanence that makes it attractive and nonutopian in the case of liberal democratic societies. What adaptations (if any) are necessary to make the theory normatively appropriate outside its original range of application?

Second, Habermas specifies his discourse theory of law social- theoretically with his “model of the circulation of power.” (See Chapter Four.) That model focuses on the generation of legitimate law through, first, “lifeworld” civil-social communication that, second, emerges into the sphere of public-political discussion and then, third, passes through the “sluices” at the entry to the formal political system. Does this model have applica-tion to nonliberal and nondemocratic societies? And further: How could it be adapted for application beyond the nation-state? Is parliamentary- democratic origin still so essential for the creation of legitimate trans- and supranational law? How precisely should we theorize the relation between national public spheres and emerging trans- and supranational public spheres? Is there a similar relation between national and trans- and suprana-tional civil societies? Luhmann’s systems theory has, since at least the early 1970s, maintained that “society” must be understood as world society. How can Habermas’s theory, now attentive to operations and developments be-yond the nation-state, be similarly understood? In short, Habermas’s “com-munications theory of society” needs to be updated to take account of his now continental and global frames of reference.

Third, and most challenging, is the set of questions that emerged at the end of this final chapter. If legitimate law is democratically produced law, how are we to understand the production of law through transnational bargaining systems in a world without a fair balance of bargaining power? If legitimation of that law depends upon conditions in national systems,

Page 262: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

After Between Facts and Norms 251

how do we answer the objection that most of those systems are neither liberal nor democratic? How more precisely could there come to develop something like a global civil society and a global public sphere? Is there any possible equivalent for “constitutional patriotism” beyond the national level? Can we really conceive of a “global domestic politics” that does not develop through a world state?

It soon will be fifty years since Habermas’s first important book, Struc-tural Transformation of the Public Sphere. It is remarkable that he is still so pro-lific and so vital—and especially remarkable that he has at each stage of his career continued to rethink and expand his intellectual and political project.

Page 263: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)
Page 264: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Reference Matter

Page 265: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)
Page 266: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes

introduction

1. For a book-length English-language philosophical and political biography of Habermas, see Matustik (2001); for a shorter German-language biography, see Wiggershaus (2004).

2. Habermas (1986a), 73.3. Matustik (2001), 3–4.4. Habermas (1986a), 73.5. Habermas (1986a), 74; Matustik (2001), xxx.6. Habermas (1986a), 73–74.7. For another brief autobiographical reflection on Habermas’s experiences at

the end of World War II, see Habermas (2008f), 17–18.8. A recent example of a work that holds Structural Transformation in high

esteem is MacCormick (2007).9. Matustik (2001), 41.10. See, above all, McCarthy (1979), 53–125.11. Habermas and Luhmann (1971).12. Habermas (1975), 4.13. See, for example, Habermas (1991b) (originally published 1982).14. The term unfinished project comes from Habermas’s 1980 essay “Die

Moderne—ein unvollendetes Projekt.” The essay is reprinted in d’Entreves and Benhabib (1997), 38–57.

15. Habermas (1988b).16. The book’s German title is Faktizität und Geltung—literally, “Facticity and

Validity.” It was translated into English four years after its German publication.17. Habermas (1996), 82 (emphasis omitted).18. Ibid., 7.19. See also Habermas (2002). 20. See Habermas (2003a).

Page 267: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 256

1. basic concepts in habermas’s theory of communicative action

Portions of this chapter were adapted from “System and Lifeworld in Haber-mas’s Theory of Law,” Cardozo Law Review 23: 473–615 (2002).

1. One might wonder why Habermas’s action theory focuses only on rational action. His explanation has two parts. First, he constructs his typology of action for purposes of social theory, not for other classificatory purposes. See Habermas (1984c), 273–274, 278–279. And the particular project Habermas has pursued in-volves a reconstruction and reformulation of Max Weber’s theory of “occidental ra-tionalism.” Habermas accordingly privileges rational action in his typology. For a critique of Habermas’s decision to focus on rational action, see Joas (1991), 99–101.

2. For examples of this strategy, see Habermas (1984c), 285; Habermas (1982), 263–264.

3. Weber (1978) (Vol. I), 4.4. See Habermas (1984c), 285. 5. See ibid., 101.6. See Habermas (1982), 264.7. See, for example, Habermas (1984c), 298; ibid., 273–274. 8. See ibid., 101. Hans Joas argues that Habermas needs to distinguish more

clearly between a typology of social action and a typology of how social action is coordinated (Joas (1991), 101).

9. Habermas (1984c), 328. 10. For an excellent account of Habermas’s method of reconstruction, see

Power (1998).11. Or at least the claim that the utterance’s “existential presuppositions” are

satisfied. See Habermas (1984c), 99, 306–307. This qualification is necessary to account for speech acts that do not directly assert matters of fact.

12. See, for example, ibid., 75, 99. One might ask: Why these three and only these three forms of validity? While Habermas does not pretend to a transcen-dental deduction of the three categories of validity (see ibid., 38), he does attempt to justify his choice systematically. Truth, rightness, and sincerity, he argues, cor-respond to the three “worlds” to which utterances may refer: the “objective” world of “existing states of affairs,” the “social” world of norms, and the “subjective” world of “desires or feelings.” See ibid., 51, 91–92; see also ibid., 70.

I avoid this terminology because I find it potentially misleading. It seems, first, to suggest that the theory of communicative action depends on some deep ontological claim about the number and nature of “worlds.” Further, the distinc-tions between the “objective world” and “subjective world” and among the various “subjective worlds” to which individual speakers have “privileged access” (ibid., 91, 100) could be thought to recreate what Habermas elsewhere criticizes as the “philosophy of consciousness,” with its sharp division between subject and object and among subjects.

In fact, however, formal pragmatics is a “rational reconstruction” of commu-nicative practice, not a revelation of timeless truths. As a rational reconstruction, Habermas tells us, it is hypothetical, revisable in principle, and subject to empiri-

Page 268: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 257

cal check. See, for example, Habermas (1991c), 32. Moreover, the theory is explic-itly historical: Only in modern communicative practice, we are told, are the three worlds and validity claims clearly distinguished. See Habermas (1984c), 48–51, 235–36; Habermas (1987b), 133, 159. Nor does Habermas conceive of communicat-ing human beings as monadic subjects, isolated in their own “subjective worlds.” Validity claims are raised, criticized, and defended publicly, with respect to shared standards and criteria.

Habermas’s tripartite division of validity claims has received significant criti-cism. See Cooke (1994), 51–94. For present purposes, however, I am willing to accept Habermas’s choice of truth, rightness, and sincerity as plausible enough for an initial theoretical decision.

13. See Habermas (1984c), 308–309.14. See Habermas (1992), 57, 77; Habermas (1984c), 325–326. Habermas distin-

guishes also “communicative” and “operative” speech acts (see ibid., 326), but the definitions of those classes are unimportant for present purposes.

15. See Cooke (1994), 59.16. See ibid.; see also Habermas (1992), 76–77. Accord Cooke (1994), 60–61.17. See, for example, Habermas (1984c), 301.18. See, for example, ibid., 38–39, 101, 305–307.19. Habermas is not always careful to include this qualification expressly, but

it follows from his position. The alternatives to providing a requested justifica-tion are either breaking off interaction or switching over to strategic action. See Habermas (1979), 3–4.

20. See Habermas (1984c), 99.21. See ibid., 303–304.22. See, for example, Habermas (1984c), 101; Habermas (1991d), 241; Haber-

mas (1984b), 154.23. Habermas (1984c), 305; see also ibid., 86.24. See, for example, ibid., 286; Habermas (1991c), 242; Habermas (1991a), 58;

Habermas (1984a), 572–573.25. See Habermas (1992), 79; Habermas (1984b), 153.26. See Habermas (1984c), 332–333.27. He mentions also the possibility of unconscious deception, which he calls

“systematically distorted communication.” See Habermas (1984c), 333. In this form of interaction, the parties believe that they are acting communicatively, but at least one party is in the grip of an individual psychopathology or powerful so-cial ideology that distorts, and in distorting subverts, the process of reaching un-derstanding about claims to validity. This notion once occupied a prominent place in Habermas’s work, with a reconstructed version of psychoanalysis providing a methodological model for critical social theory. See Habermas (1970); Habermas (1971). With Habermas’s turn in the mid-1970s toward substantive social theoriz-ing and away from epistemological concerns and ideology critique, the importance of this concept in Habermas’s work has receded.

28. The discussion in text short-circuits Habermas’s usual characterization of concealed strategic action. Since 1981, in The Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas has explicated concealed strategic action by modifying the notion of

Page 269: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 258

“perlocutions,” borrowed from J. L. Austin’s speech-act theory. See Austin (1962), 101–131; see also Habermas (1984c), 288–295. Habermas’s initial formulation at-tracted significant criticism, on two scores: Habermas’s analysis of “perlocution” bore little resemblance to what Austin meant by that term, and, further, Austin’s notion of perlocution had little connection to what Habermas meant by concealed strategic action. See, for example, Wood (1985), 157–162; Culler (1985), 136; Baxter (1987), 41, 81 n.8 (1987); Tugendhat (1991), 180. Habermas since has acknowledged that his usage of the term perlocution is idiosyncratic and “leads to misunderstand-ings” (Habermas [(1991d]), 23; see also Habermas [(1986b]), 201). He has proposed a revised theory in which (this time explicitly) only some perlocutions count as constitutive for concealed strategic action. See ibid., 239–240; see also Cooke (1994), 22–24 (analyzing Habermas’s present position).

We need not retrace Habermas’s journey. The criterion of concealed strategic action is essentially the same after as before Habermas’s revisions (see Habermas (1991d), 240), and it can be explicated without reference to any conception of “per-locution.” See Cooke (1994), 23.

29. Habermas constructs his formal-pragmatic analysis by analogy to formal semantics. A prominent approach in formal semantic theory analyzes the meaning of a sentence or proposition in terms of its truth conditions—the conditions under which the sentence or proposition would be true. Habermas analyzes the meaning of an utterance—the basic element of pragmatic theory—in terms of the conditions under which it would be acceptable. See Habermas (1984c), 297–298. “Acceptable” is broader than “true” in two senses. First, it covers claims to rightness and sincer-ity as well as claims to truth. Second, it addresses the issue of whether the utter-ance is normatively appropriate when made in a particular context, not just the question of whether it is abstractly valid.

30. See ibid., 301–302.31. See Habermas (1985), 112.32. See Habermas (1992), 83.33. See ibid., 84; Habermas (1991d), 239; Habermas (1986b), 201.34. Habermas (1991d), 239.35. Habermas (1996), 26–27.36. See, for example, Habermas (1991d), 242–243.37. See, for example, Habermas (1996), 25.38. My argument here is compatible with the argument in Johnson (1991): that

strategic action need not be so “egoistic” or “atomistic” as Habermas’s account implies. The same is true for Habermas’s account of game theory.

39. See Habermas (1996), 139.40. See Habermas (1992), 80.41. See Habermas (1996), 524 n. 18; see also ibid., 121, 448.42. See Holmes (1897).43. See, for example, Habermas (1996), 26–29.44. The title of Habermas’s 1992 book on law and democracy is Faktizität und

Geltung—literally, Facticity and Validity—but rendered in the English translation as Between Facts and Norms.

Page 270: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 259

45. Those other distinctions include: consensus and influence, validity and power, reasons and sanctions, rational and empirical motivation, cooperation and pursuit of self-interest.

46. See, for example, Habermas (1992), 81. 47. See, for example, Habermas (1996), 25–27.48. See Habermas (1979), 3-4. Sometimes Habermas mentions other possibili-

ties, such as “carrying out straightforward repair work” or continuing the interac-tion but avoiding the controversial issue. See Habermas (1996), 21.

49. See Habermas (1984c), 25; Habermas (1991b), 158; see also Habermas (1982), 235.

50. Sometimes Habermas has given the term discourse a more narrow meaning than “argumentation.” See Habermas (1984c), 23, 41–42. In more recent writings, however, the terms seem to be synonymous. See Cooke (1994), 31–32.

51. See Habermas (1984d), 177.52. Habermas (1984c), 25. Habermas’s reference to “truth” should be read to

consider the other “truth-analogous validity claims” he identifies.53. See, for example, Habermas (1984d), 174–83; Habermas (1984c), 25; Haber-

mas (1998i), 365, 367; Habermas (1996), 322–323; Habermas (1993c), 50.54. See, for example, Habermas (1998i), 365; Habermas (1996), 322.55. Habermas (1984c), 25.56. Ibid.; Habermas (1996), 178.57. Habermas (1982), 235.58. See Husserl (1970). In an essay published after Theory of Communicative Ac-

tion, Habermas discusses the Husserlian origins of the term lifeworld. For Husserl, Habermas notes, the concept of lifeworld “forms a counterconcept to those ideal-izations that first constitute the object domain of the natural sciences” (Habermas (1988a), 239).

59. Husserl (1970), 127.60. Ibid., 130–131.61. Ibid., 135–189.62. Ibid., 173.63. Husserl’s analysis of the lifeworld occupies Part III of the Crisis of European

Sciences. This part remained unpublished until 1954; see Translator’s Introduction, in Husserl (1970), xvi–xxi, though some scholars, including Schutz, had access to it before publication.

64. On Weber’s early influence on Schutz, see Wagner (1970), 13–16.65. See ibid., 29; see generally ibid., 287–327.66. I say “came to call” because Schutz had published an important work that

sounded many of the same themes before Husserl’s use of the term lifeworld. See Schutz (1967).

67. Habermas relies in particular on a work Schutz left unpublished at his death in 1959, entitled Strukturen der Lebenswelt (Structures of the Lifeworld). Schutz’s student, Thomas Luckmann, has completed part of the work, using much of what Schutz had left behind but deleting some of it and adding some of his own material. See Schutz and Luckmann (1973). For reasons of convenience, I refer to “Schutz” rather than “Schutz and Luckmann” in text.

Page 271: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 260

68. See Habermas (1987b), 121–125.69. See Schutz and Luckmann (1973), 28–35.70. See Habermas (1987b), 119.71. Ibid., 119; see also ibid., 144, 204.72. Ibid., 121, 126–127.73. Ibid., 134.74. Ibid., 139; see also ibid., 138.75. See also ibid., 135:

Action, or mastery of situations, presents itself as a circular process in which the actor is at once both the initiator of his accountable actions and the product of the [cultural] tradition in which he stands, of the solidary groups to which he belongs, of socialization and learning processes to which he is exposed.

The criticism of Schutz is not entirely fair. At the very least, he includes in the “stock of knowledge” many of the skills, competences, and know-hows that Habermas places under the heading of “personality.”

76. See Habermas (1984c), 158.77. Habermas (1987b), 133; see also ibid., 134, 138, 145, 153, 255, 308, 356.78. Ibid., 138.79. See ibid., 366.80. See ibid., 134, 141, 146, 153, 174, 262, 318, 366.81. See ibid., 266.82. See ibid., 365.83. See ibid., 183, 276.84. See ibid., 136–137. Joas criticizes Habermas’s shift from the idea of lifeworld

as background to social action to the idea of society as lifeworld. See Joas (1991), 116.85. Ibid., 138.86. Ibid., 232; see also ibid., 138.87. See ibid., 140–141.88. See ibid., 86, 107, 137–138, 139, 142–143, 144 fig. 23, 232, 261, 266, 267, 288;

see also Habermas (1991d), 227, 234, 268, 281.89. See Habermas (1987b), 142 figure 21.90. Ibid., 137.91. See ibid., 142, 143 figure 22.92. Ibid., 330.93. Ibid., 304.94. See ibid., 283–284, 305, 322, 369, 372–373, 403.95. Habermas (1988c), 82–83. Habermas made similar observations in his 1973

work, Legitimation Crisis, though this time referring to “systems theory” (Parsons, Luhmann) rather than to functionalism. See Habermas (1975), 2–3. To the same effect are his remarks in Theory of Communicative Action (Habermas, 1987b, 292).

96. With respect to social integration, for example, liberals and republicans would differ as to necessary breadth and depth of a consensus about values. With respect to personality, egalitarians and elitists would differ as to the proper distri-bution of competences.

97. See Habermas (1987b), 292; Habermas (1975), 3.

Page 272: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 261

98. Habermas (1987b), 375–376, 391.99. See ibid., 356.100. As opposed to psychology, where the term rationalization has a very dif-

ferent sense.101. The essay appears as the “Author’s Introduction” in Weber (1930).102. Ibid., 13–27.103. Ibid., 158.104. Ibid., 167 figure 3.105. Ibid., 180.106. Ibid., 161.107. He refers here to “scientific jurisprudence.” The German word wissen-

schaftlich, translated as “scientific,” has a broader connotation than its English counterpart, meaning something like “systematic” and “professionalized.”

108. The classic instance is his closing to The Protestant Ethic:

The Puritan wanted to work in a calling; we are forced to do so. For when asceticism was carried out of monastic cells into everyday life, and began to dominate worldly morality, it did its part in building the tremendous cosmos of the modern economic order. This order is now bound to the technical and economic conditions of machine production which today determine the lives of all the individuals who are born into this mechanism, not only those di-rectly concerned with economic acquisition, with irresistible force. Perhaps it will so determine them until the last ton of fossilized coal is burnt. In [the Pu-ritan theologian] Baxter’s view the care for external goods should only lie on the shoulders of the “saint like a light cloak, which can be thrown aside at any moment.” But fate decreed that the cloak should become an iron cage. . . . Of the last stage of this cultural development, it might well be truly said: “Specialists without spirit, sensualists without heart; this nullity imagines that it has attained a level of civilization never before achieved.” But this brings us to the world of judgments of value and of faith, with which this purely historical discussion need not be burdened . . . . (Weber, 1930, 181–182)

109. See Habermas (1984c), 216–222.110. See ibid., 156–159.111. Habermas (1987b), 146.112. Ibid.113. Weber is said to have remarked of democracy: “In a democracy the people

choose a leader in whom they trust. Then the chosen leader says, ‘Now shut up and obey me.’ People and party are no longer free to interfere in his business . . . ” (Gerth and Mills (1958), 42).

114. Habermas (1987b), 146–147.115. See ibid., 146–147.116. Ibid., 77; see also ibid., 88, 146, 180, 288.117. See ibid., 160.

Page 273: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 262

118. Ibid., 232.119. See ibid., 138.120. See Habermas (1984a), 174.121. Habermas (1987), 151.122. Ibid., 148, 150; Habermas (1996), 21, 524 n. 18; Habermas (1987), 121.123. Habermas (1996), 25.124. See Habermas (1987b), 149–150.125. Habermas (1987b), 148; Habermas (1991d), 253; cf. McCarthy (1991), 137

(“We do not need the paraphernalia of social systems theory to identify unin-tended consequences”).

126. Habermas (1987b), 182–183, 262.127. Ibid., 180–181, 183, 261–263, 272, 276, 281.128. See, for example, ibid., 117, 150, 186–187.129. Ibid., 150.130. Ibid.131. See, for example, Habermas (1987b), 117–118, 150–151, 186–187.132. Ibid., 117.133. Ibid., 150, 154, 171, 173, 185, 242, 307, 327.134. Ibid., 309.135. Ibid., 357; see also ibid., 361, 366–367, 369.136. See Joas (1991), 105–106; McCarthy (1991), 137.137. See ibid., 185, 313, 334–338 (re Marx); 358 (re Hobbes); Habermas (1996),

39–40 (re Smith).138. For an account of Luhmann’s autopoietic theory in its application to law,

see Baxter (1998).139. See, for example, Joas (1991); McCarthy (1991). Johannes Aranson, writ-

ing just as Luhmann began developing his autopoietic version of social-systems theory, distinguishes between Luhmann’s and Parsons’s versions. See Aronson (1991), 194–195.

140. See, for example, Easton (1965), 25–26; Buckley (1967), 50.141. See Easton (1965), 29–32. The model becomes more complicated once one

recognizes that a system has more than one “feedback loop.” See ibid., 372–376.142. Subsystem is always a relative term, used to signal that the system under

discussion is part of a larger system. Whether one speaks of “system” or “subsys-tem” depends on the intended level of analysis.

143. See Habermas (1987b), 235, 242, 243 fig. 32, 244 fig. 33.144. See Parsons (1967), 348.145. For Parsons’s overview of this project, see Parsons (1977), 43–48, 59–60,

204–269.146. See Parsons (1967b), 348–351.147. Alexander (1983), 84.148. Parsons (1967b), 354.149. Alexander (1983), 82.150. See Parsons (1977b), 230.151. Ibid., 236.152. See Parsons (1977a), 46–48; Parsons (1977b), 244–245.

Page 274: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 263

153. Parsons (1977b), 262–269.154. See Parsons (1978), 361.155. See ibid., 393 fig. 4, 407 fig 5. 156. A two-volume Festschrift for Parsons provides good examples of the way

some of Parsons’s followers sought to deploy the AGIL schema at various levels of generality. See, for example, Fararo (1976), 182 (applying the four-function para-digm to name sixteen subsystems of the scientific system, four levels removed from Parsons’s original level of the social system); Lidz (1976), 231–236 (naming media for the “adaptive” subsystem of the general action system); Rocher (1976), 404 (us-ing the four-function paradigm to name sixteen kinds of aspiration).

157. Niklas Luhmann, the prominent German systems theorist, has observed: “At every level of system-building there is a subsystem that displays the whole schema once again. . . . But how far can this process be repeated? Is there a point past which it gives out? Does it become senseless after the second repetition, like the process of reflection? And, especially, is this the way to represent the structure of functional differentiation? Does this theoretical schema yield not structural complexity but only structural complications?” (Luhmann (1982), 58).

158. See Habermas (1987), 250–256. 159. The German word Steurung can be translated either as “steering” or “con-

trol.” In some of Habermas’s writings, the term Steurungsmedium has been ren-dered as either “steering medium” or “control medium.” See Thomas McCarthy, Translator’s Note, in Habermas (1975), 148 n. 11. I prefer “control medium,” but in deference to McCarthy’s choice in his translation of Theory of Communicative Action, and William Rehg’s choice in his translation of Between Facts and Norms, I use “steering medium.”

So far as I have been able to see, Parsons does not use either term—“steering medium” or “control medium.” Habermas may have developed the term Steu-rungsmedium through his encounter in the early 1970s with the systems theorist Niklas Luhmann. (This encounter led to a joint book, see Habermas & Luhmann (1971), and to much greater sympathy on Habermas’s part for systems theory. Luh-mann seems to have been unaffected by the encounter.) At that time, Luhmann, first trained in sociology by Parsons, was much under Parsons’s influence. He was developing Parsons’s notion of a “generalized interchange medium” into the concept of a “generalized communications medium.” Luhmann described such a medium as a way to “condition,” “regulate,” “steer,” or “control” the selections of a rational counterpart in interaction. Luhmann (1975), 7, 9. Luhmann refers, also, to media as a way to “induce” or “steer” one’s counterpart to accept an “offer.” Parsons, too, sees media as—from the point of view of actors—a means of exerting strategic influence over others.

One difficulty with this explanation is that both Parsons and Luhmann (until the early 1980s, after the publication of Theory of Communicative Action) also exam-ine the operation of these “media” from the perspective of social subsystems, not just actors. Still, one could speak of the economic system (and Habermas does) as “steering” or “controlling” itself through the medium of money.

160. See Parsons (1967a); Parsons (1967b); Parsons (1969).161. Parsons (1967a), 357; Parsons (1977b), 241.

Page 275: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 264

162. See Habermas (1987b), 264.163. Parsons (1967a), 358.164. Ibid., 363.165. That money operates through positive sanctions only is not obvious. Rob-

ert Hale describes the process of exchanging labor-power for wages, or money for goods, as a process of reciprocal coercion that involves threats to withhold the desired money or commodity. See Hale (1923), 472–479. The process can be described in terms of either offers to provide or to withhold and in terms of either positive or negative sanctions.

166. Habermas (1987b), 265–266.167. Ibid. The parallel is forced. Reasons—or at least particular reasons—do

not “back” the medium of language itself, just particular claims. And certainly one does not wait for a communicative “panic” to ask for reasons in communicative ac-tion. Drawing on the “reserve” of reasons is not such an extraordinary occurrence in everyday communicative action, and it is established practice where discourse is institutionalized.

168. See Habermas (1987b), 266.169. Ibid., 154, 309, 312, 344; see also ibid., 266.170. See ibid., 265.171. See ibid., 427 n56172. See ibid., 266.173. Ibid., 268.174. Here, as with Parsons’ account of money, one could describe the relevant

sanctions in the opposite way. Compliance with commands may bring pleasant consequences, particularly if the addressee is located in a bureaucratic organiza-tion that rewards dutiful order-followers. The main point here is that for Parsons, power-mediated interaction, as with money, is coordinated by potential sanctions rather than by agreement about validity claims.

175. One might object that power often seems to be enjoyed for its own sake, or for selfish purposes, rather than for its capacity to attain “collective goals.” Parsons’s point, which Habermas will amplify, is that in modern societies (at least) a stable political system requires that power generally be directed toward collective goals.

176. Habermas (1987b), 268–269.177. Ibid., 269–270.178. Ibid., 270–271.179. See ibid., 271–272.180. See ibid., 274–276.181. See ibid., 275.182. Ibid., 274, 276–277.183. Hans Joas criticizes Habermas for this claim (Joas (1991), 111).184. Habermas (1987b), 155.185. Ibid., 153.186. See ibid., 156–197.187. See ibid., 156–172. The four mechanisms Habermas identifies are: “seg-

mentation,” or the linking of similarly structured units, as in an association of equal families; “stratification,” or the ranking of similarly structured units, as in

Page 276: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Notes to Chapter 1 265

an association of families with different degrees of status; “state organization,” or the development of a functionally specified political organization largely indepen-dent of the kinship system; and “steering media,” through which first the capitalist economy and then the modern bureaucratic state, are differentiated.

188. Ibid., 172–179.189. Ibid., 173–179. The distinctions among “preconventional,” “conventional,”

and “postconventional” come from Lawrence Kohlberg’s work in moral psychol-ogy. Habermas defines the three levels as “the preconventional level, on which only the consequences of action are judged, the conventional level, on which the orientation to norms and the intentional violation of them are already judged, and finally the postconventional level, on which norms themselves are judged in the light of principles” (Ibid., 174).

190. See ibid., 165 (re money); ibid., 169–171, 167 fig. 25, 166 fig. 24 (re power).191. See ibid., 171.192. See ibid., 318–320.193. The structural components of the lifeworld do not have steering me-

dia. This difficulty appears in Habermas’s general model of system/lifeworld interchange.

194. Ibid., 154; see also ibid., 173.195. Ibid., 183.196. Ibid., 172.197. See ibid., 309, 357, 366.198. See ibid., 305, 307, 318. Thomas McCarthy has criticized the move from

bureaucratic contexts of action to a differentiated bureaucratic system of action as understood by social-systems theory. See McCarthy (1991), 124; ibid., 131.

199. Habermas (1987b), 154 (typographical error corrected).200. Ibid., 308–309.201. Ibid., 183.202. Others have made this point as well. See, for example, Joas (1991); Berger

(1991), 174–178. My first formulation of this argument was in Baxter (1987).203. See Habermas (1987b), 185, 309, 311, 332, 356, 367, 368, 370.204. See ibid., 320.205. Douglas Kellner similarly criticizes Habermas’s “romanticism of the life-

world, appealing to the ‘true humanity’ operative within interpersonal relations” (Kellner (2000), 273).

206. See Habermas (1987b), 310–311.207. The quotations in the following paragraphs up to the table are from ibid.,

319–322.208. Ibid., 322.209. See ibid., 335–336.210. Ibid., 322.211. See Habermas (1984c,) 399; Habermas (1987b,) 302. For Habermas’s inter-

pretation and critique of Lukács and the Frankfurt School, see Habermas (1984c), 339–99; Habermas 1987b, 332–334, 389–391. For a defense of Adorno against the charge that his “negative dialectical” critique is doomed by its “performative self-contradiction,” see Morris (1996).

Page 277: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

266 Notes to Chapters 1 and 2

212. See Habermas (1987b), 322–323, 330–331.213. Ibid., 385.214. See Habermas (1987b), 385; see also Habermas (1975), 61–68, 93.215. Habermas (1987b), 330; see also ibid., 327, 355.216. Ibid., 309. In an alternative and less clear formulation, Habermas writes

that we can speak of colonization when “the destruction of traditional forms of life can no longer be offset by more effectively fulfilling the functions of society as a whole” (Ibid., 322).

217. Ibid., 355.218. Ibid., 330–331.219. Ibid., 348–351. Habermas is not altogether clear about the employee role.

He notes that compensation and security against risk have improved but that work remains “heteronomously determined.”

220. Ibid., 356.221. Ibid., 357.222. For a contrary judgment, see Tweedy and Hunt (1994), 307.223. Habermas (1987b), 362–363.224. Ibid., 364.225. See ibid., 363–364, 368–373.226. Ibid., 365–366.227. Habermas (1996), 562 n48.228. McCarthy criticizes the thinness of Habermas’s account of the political

system in Theory of Communicative Action, as well as his treatment of it as the ad-ministrative (rather than political) system. See McCarthy (1991), 124–125.

229. Habermas had developed the beginnings of this notion in an essay pub-lished in 1976. See Habermas (1977), 3. But in Theory of Communicative Action, published just five years later, this “communications concept of power” gives way to the concept of power as steering medium.

230. See Habermas (1987b), 319.

2. habermas’s “reconstruction” of modern law

Portions of this chapter were adapted from “Habermas’s Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy,” Buffalo Law Review 50: 205–340 (2002).

1. Habermas (1996), 29.2. See Habermas (1996), 67–68; see also, for example, Weber (1978), 31, 213

(Vol. I).3. See, for example, Weber (1978), 31–33, 311–313 (Vol. 1).4. See Habermas (1996), 69–70.5. Ibid., 82 (emphasis omitted).6. See ibid., 106–107.7. The word “Faktizität” is not so rare as the English word “facticity.” The

latter, however, shows up at least in unabridged dictionaries, and is defined as “having the quality of being a fact.” The Oxford English Dictionary, 652 (Vol. 5) (2d ed. 1989).

Page 278: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

267 Notes to Chapter 2

8. See Habermas (1996), 8, 28–30, 32, 64, 198, 447–448 (coercive enforcement); ibid., 198 (certainty or predictability); ibid., 64 (law’s institutional dimension); ibid., 28, 95, 447–448 (positivity).

9. See ibid., 29; see also ibid., 38, 64, 95, 198, 447–448.10. I say “proper” because Habermas sometimes calls his whole project the

“discourse theory of law and democracy.” This part comprises Chapters 3 through 6 of Between Facts and Norms. (The first two chapters are introductory, designed to set out the basic distinction between facticity and validity.)

11. See Habermas (1996), 38, 82.12. See, for example, ibid., 64, 82, 95.13. Ibid., 42.14. In this respect, and ironically, Habermas’s recent work seems close in logic

to the theory of autopoietic systems developed by Niklas Luhmann—Habermas’s long-time partner in debate and still the object of Habermas’s polemic. Luhmann’s recurring strategy is to identify an “internal” and an “external” side of a distinction— as between “self-reference” and “external reference,” “closure” and “openness,” or “system” and “environment”—then to show that each side of the distinction pre-supposes the other. See, for example, Luhmann (1993), 74, 76, 83, 223–224, 308; Luhmann (1998), 23. As Luhmann notes, however, the distinction between facticity and validity is not one of mutual exclusion. See Luhmann (1998), 161. In this respect, the facticity/validity distinction differs from the distinctions on which Luhmann’s method thrives. Perhaps for this reason, Luhmann does not see a parallel between Habermas’s rhetorical strategy and his own.

I have discussed systematically Luhmann’s autopoietic theory of law in Baxter (1998).

15. I say “seem to divide” because Habermas does not make the claim explicitly.16. See Habermas (1996), 82, 129, 136.17. Ibid., 82–83.18. See ibid., 127.19. Ibid., 99.20. Ibid., 85–89.21. See ibid., 101–102.22. Ibid., 94 (emphasis omitted).23. See ibid., 105–106, 449.24. See ibid., 105.25. Ibid., 105–106.26. See ibid., 97–98.27. See ibid., 111.28. See ibid., 79, 110.29. See ibid., 155–156.30. Ibid., 108.31. Ibid., 105–106, 113, 118, 452, 453.32. See ibid., 114–115.33. See ibid., 153.34. See ibid., 115–116.35. See ibid., 105, 107.

Page 279: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

268 Notes to Chapter 2

36. Ibid., 118.37. See ibid., 104, 120.38. Ibid., 104.39. Ibid., 119–120.40. Ibid.41. Ibid., 120.42. See Günther (1998), 238. Ulrich Preuss suggests that on this point Haber-

mas needs a theory of civic obligation and virtue. See Preuss (1998), 334–335. In his reply, Habermas makes clear that he means only that there can be no legally en-forceable duty to exercise one’s communicative freedom (Habermas (1998h), 438). Habermas does not preclude a moral duty to exercise one’s political autonomy, although Preuss is right that Habermas does not argue for such a duty.

43. Habermas notes that his prior work has failed to distinguish adequately between the discourse principle in general and the version appropriate to moral discourse (Habermas (1996), 108).

44. Ibid., 107.45. Ibid. Habermas’s idea that agreement on a norm in an ideal rational dis-

course constitutes the norm’s validity has been challenged by (among others) epis-temic theorists. For a good account of these criticisms circa 1998, see Bohman (1998), 401–407.

46. Niklas Luhmann makes this observation and argues that Habermas relies on the ambiguity of the word could. See Luhmann (1998), 164–165. I take up this point with respect to the “democracy principle,” corollary of the discourse principle.

47. Habermas (1996), 107–108.48. Ibid., 108, 165–166, 283.49. He introduces the idea in a discussion of Kant’s distinction between legal

and moral norms. See ibid., 111–112. He invokes it a second time in the context of, again, distinguishing between legal and moral norms. See ibid., 118–119.

50. Ibid., 119, 122; see also Rehg (1998), 262 (referring to “what Habermas calls the ‘legal medium’ or ‘legal form’ ”).

51. In Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas did claim that in at least some of its operations, law functioned as a steering medium like money or power. See Habermas (1987b), 365–373. He repudiates this notion expressly in Between Facts and Norms. See Habermas (1996), 562 n48.

52. Habermas (1996), 56.53. Ibid., 119. He says, in an alternative formulation, that “the general right to

liberties” is “constitutive for the legal form as such” (ibid., 121).54. See ibid., 119.55. Ibid., 122. Here he seems to equate the legal medium with “the conditions

for the legal form of a horizontal association of free and equal persons.” Ibid.56. Ibid.57. Ibid., 123.58. Ibid., 107.59. I think this is the answer to the question Joshua Cohen raises: “I don’t see

how the discourse principle gives us equal liberties” (Cohen (1999), 395).

Page 280: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

269 Notes to Chapter 2

60. This formulation might be more Rawlsian than Habermasian—and more early-Rawlsian than late-Rawlsian. But alternative justifications are not obvious. Insofar as it validates moral norms, the discourse principle takes the form of a strict universalization principle. See Habermas (1996), 116–117. So one might think that equality of legal liberties follows straight from the discourse principle. But as noted in text above, the “reference system” for legal norms is narrower—a legal community, not humanity at large. Perhaps, though, the idea is that the discourse principle imports a more limited universalization requirement for legal norms, such that within a legal community the distribution of liberties must be equal. Still, the question would remain: Why the “greatest possible measure” of equal indi-vidual liberties? How does the discourse principle imply this requirement (sensible as it might be)?

61. See Habermas (1996), 123–124.62. Ibid., 126.63. Ibid., 118.64. Another way to reach this same conclusion would be to note that the con-

cept of the “legal medium” (or “legal form”) is too abstract to generate a list of particular rights. There are a variety of ways to distribute liberties without violat-ing the idea of modern law.

65. Ibid., 122.66. Ibid., 124–125.67. See ibid., 123–125.68. Ibid., 123.69. Ibid.70. See ibid., 127.71. See ibid., 118.72. See Alexy (1994), 232–233.73. Alexy points to the fact that Habermas, in describing actual constitutional

orders, sees basic rights as a constraint on majoritarian lawmaking. See ibid., 233.74. Habermas (1996), 26; see id at 23–24, 42. At least apparently inconsistently,

Habermas also describes the tension between facticity and validity as “ ‘given’ with the fact of the symbolic infrastructure of sociocultural forms of life” (ibid., 446).

75. See ibid., 126.76. Ibid., 111.77. Ibid., 110. I have amended the translation, rendering Gesetze as “laws” rather

than as “statutes.”78. Cf. Luhmann (1998), 164–165 (noting the ambiguity of the word could in

the discourse principle’s criterion that “all potentially affected persons could agree as participants in rational discourses”).

79. Habermas (1996), 166; see also ibid., 108, 140.80. Ibid., 282; see also ibid., 155.81. I say this with the proviso that the categories are, at this point in Haber-

mas’s analysis, just “unsaturated placeholders,” not fully specified legal rights.82. Habermas (1996), 123. For the connection to the welfare-state project, see

ibid., 77, 415.

Page 281: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

270 Notes to Chapter 2

83. Ibid., 123, 134.84. Ibid., 123.85. Rawls uses the expression “device of representation” to describe his use of

the original-position idea. See, for example, Rawls (2005), xxix, 24, 25. His alterna-tive description is that it is “a thought-experiment for the purpose of public- and self-clarification” (Rawls (2001), 17).

86. Rawls (2005), 24–25; Rawls (2001), 15. According to Rawls, it is “one of our considered convictions that the fact that we occupy a particular social position, say, is not a good reason for us to accept, or to expect others to accept, a concep-tion of justice that favors those in that position. . . . To model this and other simi-lar convictions, we do not let the parties know the social position of the persons they represent” (Rawls (2001), 18).

87. For example, Rawls stipulates that the parties to the contract do not know which comprehensive doctrines are affirmed by the citizens they represent because “reasonable pluralism” in such matters is a “permanent feature of the public cul-ture of democracy” (Rawls (2005), 36). He develops the content of public reason by reflection on “fundamental political ideas viewed as implicit in the public po-litical culture of a democratic society” (ibid., 223). Rawls’s list of basic liberties comes from “specif[ying] the common and guaranteed status of equal citizens in a well-ordered democratic society” (ibid., 335). And he adopts his general idea that the principles of justice would be those “agree[d] to by the representatives of free and equal citizens when fairly situated” because, Rawls says, that idea is rooted in “fundamental ideas of the public political culture as well as in citizens’ shared principles and conceptions of practical reason” (ibid., 97).

88. Strictly speaking, of course, Habermas generates abstract categories of rights rather than principles.

89. Rawls (2005), 5.90. Habermas (1996), 122 (emphasis omitted). 91. Rawls (1971), 302.92. Habermas (1996), 122.93. Rawls (2005), 5.94. See ibid., 166.95. See, for example, ibid., 235.96. See ibid., 231–240. For Habermas’s views on the issue, see section 3.2.2.97. See Rawls (2005), 228–229. According to Rawls, “constitutional essen-

tials and questions of basic justice” comprise (1) principles specifying “the general structure of government and the political process,” including the various legisla-tive executive and judicial powers, and “the scope of majority rule”; (2) “equal basic rights and liberties of citizenship,” for example, “the right to vote and to par-ticipate in politics, liberty of conscience, freedom of thought and of association, as well as the protections of the rule of law” (ibid., 227).

98. See ibid., 7, 166.99. See ibid., 230 (“a social minimum covering citizens’ basic needs count[s] as

[a] constitutional essential[] while the principle of fair opportunity and the differ-ence principle do not”).

100. See ibid., 293, 298, 334–340.

Page 282: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

271 Notes to Chapter 2

101. Habermas (1995b), 110.102. Ibid., 119.103. Rawls (2005), 339.104. Ibid., 14.105. Ibid., 192–193; see also ibid., 195–197.106. Rawls (1995), 136–137.107. Joshua Cohen argues that this sense in which the discourse principle is

nonneutral speaks against using it to support a theory of democracy:

Philosophical theories about the nature and competence of reason do not pro-vide the common ground for equal citizens that is desirable in public argu-ment in a democracy. An appeal to reason cannot help us “get behind” the plu-rality of competing moral, political, religious, metaphysical outlooks, because the nature and competence of reason is one matter on which such outlooks disagree. (Cohen (1999), 387)

108. Larmore (1999), 614. Habermas withdraws from this position in his more recent writing. See section 5.1.2, discussing Habermas’s 2005 book (translated in 2008) Between Naturalism and Religion.

109. Larmore argues that Habermas’s discourse principle is substantive and has specifically moral content. See Larmore (1999), 618–622.

110. Rawls (2005), 5.111. Rawls associates the liberties of the moderns with Locke and the liberties

of the ancients with Rousseau. See ibid., 4–5. As indicated in text, Habermas tends to refer to “liberal” and “republican” conceptions, and he sees Rousseau as one of the foremost proponents of the latter.

112. See Habermas (1995b), 110, 127–128.113. Ibid., 128.114. Rawls writes that we need not decide whether the liberties of the moderns

are more intrinsically valuable than those of the ancients; even if the political liber-ties are thought to be largely instrumental in value, they still may count as basic liberties. See Rawls (2005), 299.

115. See ibid., 292.116. See ibid., 292, 299.117. See ibid., 5, 327; see also ibid., 329–331.118. See Habermas (1995b), 128.119. See Rawls (2005), 290, 293, 298.120. See ibid., xix. After his debate with Habermas, Rawls makes the point

more clear in Rawls (2001), 26–29. My argument here is consistent with McMahon (2002), 112–117. McMahon demonstrates that the difference between Rawls’s al-legedly “monological” strategy and Habermas’s own “dialogical” strategy is not nearly so important as Habermas suggests.

121. See Habermas (1996), 104.122. See Habermas (1995b), 130–131.123. See Habermas (1996), 133, 196, 289; see also ibid., 137, 320, 336.124. Ibid., 150.

Page 283: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

272 Notes to Chapter 2

125. In this context, the term internal relation seems to mean “conceptual rela-tion.” See ibid., 449, 454.

126. Ibid., 134.127. Ibid., 134.128. Ibid., p 133.129. See ibid., 47–56, 74, 130–131, 330, 333–136, 341–353, 461, 481; see also

Habermas (1987a).130. Habermas (1996), 143; Baxter (1998), 2004–2009 (introducing Luhmann’s

general notion of binary coding and the legal system’s legal/illegal code in particular).131. Habermas (1996), 143.132. See Baxter (1998), 2040, 2067–2068 (criticizing Luhmann’s equivocation

between “government/opposition” and “governing/ governed”).133. Habermas (1996), 143.134. See ibid.; see also ibid., 169.135. See Luhmann (1988).136. See section 4.2.1.137. See Habermas (1996), 38, 55.138. See ibid., 145.139. See Habermas (1977). Then and now, Habermas credits Hannah Arendt

with the insight. See Habermas (1996), 146–149.140. Habermas (1996), 147.141. Habermas (1996), 147. The terms jurisgenesis and jurisgenerative are most

closely associated with the work of Robert Cover. See Cover (1983), 11, 25. Both Habermas and Cover emphasize the role of groups outside of official state institu-tions in producing law. Habermas, however, is interested in how discourse outside of formal state institutions influences the production of state law. Cover’s focus was more on the production of nonstate law, and there not so much through ar-gumentation as through shared forms of life and shared narratives. From his per-spective, formal state institutions, and especially courts, are “jurispathic” as well as jurisgenerative. Habermas’s idea of jurisgenesis is thus decidedly more “statist” than Cover’s.

142. Habermas (1996), 148.143. Ibid., 185.144. Ibid., 461.145. For Habermas’s conception of civil society as a network of voluntary as-

sociations, see ibid., 175, 358, 359, 367. For his requirement that civil society must be independent from the state and the economic system, see ibid., 269, 301, 367, 368–369.

146. Ibid., 301.147. See ibid., 288; see also ibid., 296, 298, 372.148. Habermas refers to these informal circuits of communication as “sub-

jectless” and “anonymous” (ibid., 136, 171). The likely reason he adopts this char-acterization is to avoid creating the impression, common in the “deliberative democracy” literature, that there is a single, unified, deliberating subject of de-mocracy. See Rubin (2001), 747–750; Bohman (1994), 914.

149. Habermas (1996), 170.

Page 284: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

273 Notes to Chapter 2

150. Ibid., 170–171.151. Ibid., 150.152. See ibid., 56, 343, 407, 469.153. Ibid., 150.154. Habermas (1987b), 185; see also ibid., 304, 309, 333, 349, 356, 366, 372.155. Ibid., 319–323.156. See Habermas (1996), 169, 176, 327.157. See Habermas (1993b), 2.158. Habermas (1996), 159; see also Habermas (1993b), 3.159. Habermas (1993b), 10.160. Ibid., 11.161. Ibid., 2.162. Habermas (1996), 160; Habermas (1993b), 3–4.163. Habermas (1993b), 4, 96.164. Ibid., 5–6.165. Habermas (1996), 160.166. See ibid., 108; see also ibid., 97, 161.167. Ibid., 160–161.168. See, for example, ibid., 101–102, 267–269, 276–279.169. See ibid., 267–269, 276–279.170. Thomas McCarthy points out that, despite recognizing ethical plurality,

Habermas still refers in the singular to a legal community’s “form of life, self-understanding, and collective identity” (McCarthy (1998), 130).

171. See Habermas (1996), 308–314.172. Ibid., 309. Michel Rosenfeld notes, however, that Habermas’s “postmeta-

physical” theory may have the effect of excluding, or at least devaluing, religious or otherwise “metaphysical” perspectives, as well as perspectives that reject egali-tarianism. See Rosenfeld (1998), 101. Habermas’s recent writings about religion, however, take a different position. See Chapter Five, section 5.1.2.

173. See McCarthy (1998), 115.174. Habermas (1996), 107.175. See ibid., 151, 285, 296.176. See ibid., 97; see also Habermas (1993b), 12.177. See Habermas (1996), 159–161; Habermas (1993b), 8.178. Habermas formulates his discourse principle in terms of the agreement of

“all possibly affected persons.” By this quoted expression he means “anyone whose interests are touched by the foreseeable consequences of a general practice regu-lated by the norms at issue” (Habermas (1996), 107).

179. See ibid., 61.180. Habermas (1993b), 13.181. See Günther (1993), 14.182. Habermas (1996), 165–166.183. Ibid.184. Ibid., 108.185. See ibid., 165.186. Ibid., 282.

Page 285: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

274 Notes to Chapter 2

187. See ibid., 283.188. See, for example, ibid., 339.189. Jon Elster’s well-known study of “arguing and bargaining” (see Elster

(1999–2000) relies on Habermas for its basic distinction. His discussion of Haber-mas, however, is brief. In my opinion, Elster reduces Habermas’s idea of com-municative action to the special case of discourse, and, as I explain in text, I think Habermas’s account places bargaining between communicative and strategic ac-tion. Still, Elster’s account is interesting because it explores the strategic use of what purports to be impartial argument. This would be concealed strategic ac-tion, in Habermas’s typology, and Elster’s historical account fills out Habermas’s hypothetical-example-based analysis.

190. Ibid., 230.191. Ibid., 166.192. Ibid., 190.193. Ibid., 192.194. See, for example, ibid., 232.195. See ibid., 153–155.196. Ibid., 155–156.197. See, for example, Habermas (1998d).198. Ibid., 170–171.199. See ibid., 178–179. The discussion in text makes clear that, despite Haber-

mas’s distinction between the communicative power of the citizenry and the administrative power of the state apparatus, state institutions—including legis-latures, agencies, and courts—are sites of various kinds of discourse, not just loci of administrative power. Communicative power, then, could be generated within state institutions and not just outside.

Cohen nicely formulates the different natures and functions of discourse in-side and outside state institutions:

Formal political processes—elections, legislatures, agencies, and courts— provide the second stage in an idealized problem-solving system. They provide institutionally regulated ways to assess ideas: to deliberate about proposals un-der fair conditions, evaluate alternative solutions, and make authoritative deci-sions after due consideration. So on the second, institutional track we have a disciplined testing through reason of proposals that emerge from open-ended public discussion. (Cohen (1999), 401).

200. Ibid., 110 (citation omitted).201. Cf. McCarthy (1998), 132–133 (noting likely disagreement even as to

“such core elements of procedural impartiality as equal consideration and equal treatment”).

202. McCarthy makes this point forcefully. See ibid., 139, 145.203. See Bohman (1994), 921–923; Rehg (1998), 265; McCarthy (1998), 152. As

discussed in section 2.3.1, Rawls’s political liberalism also makes use of a unanim-ity requirement. Both Habermas and Rawls pursue the idea that a political order could in some sense be consented to by all. But for Rawls, the requirement applies only in the original position, where artificial parties rather than the citizenry as a

Page 286: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

275 Notes to Chapter 2

whole deliberate. The informational constraints imposed by the veil of ignorance, together with the limited nature of the agreement, are what make universal agree-ment conceivable.

204. Habermas (1996), 182. See generally ibid., 181–186.205. Ibid., 171.206. Ibid., 183.207. See ibid., 302.208. See ibid., 130–131, 175, 184, 302, 317, 358, 371, 437, 461.209. As Rawls formulates the question: What are “the conditions of the pos-

sibility of a reasonable public basis of justification on fundamental political ques-tions?” (Rawls (2005), xix).

210. Rawls presents the basic problem of political liberalism as the problem of how “there may exist over time a stable and just society of free and equal citizens profoundly divided by reasonable though incompatible religious, philosophical, and moral doctrines” (Rawls (2005), xviii). His solution to the problem is the idea of the overlapping consensus (ibid.).

211. Habermas (1998h), 444.212. Habermas (1996), 64.213. See, for example, Rawls (2005), 214.214. Rawls suggests that “most” political questions are not matters of constitu-

tional essentials or basic justice. See Rawls (2005), 214.215. See, for example, Rawls (2005), 14.216. Habermas (1996), 356.217. See Habermas (1996), 372.218. See Habermas (1996), 189.219. See ibid., 190.220. Ibid., 172.221. Ibid.222. For a defense of Habermas’s discourse theory on this point, see Peterson

(2010). I take up the matter in section 3.1.223. See Habermas (1996), 172. He addresses briefly the “pragmatic” reasons

often given for separating lawmaking from law applying, having to do with judi-cial professionalization and specialization.

224. Ibid.225. Ibid., 192.226. See ibid., 169.227. Ibid., 173.228. See ibid., 190.229. Ibid., 191.230. Ibid., 211.231. Ibid., 191–192.232. See ibid., 186, 189–192.233. Ibid., 187.234. See, for example, Habermas (1984c), 396–400.235. Habermas (1998h), 444.236. Habermas (1996), 7.

Page 287: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

276 Notes to Chapter 3

3. discourse theory and the theory and practice of adjudication

Portions of this chapter were adapted from “Habermas’s Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy,” Buffalo Law Review 50: 205–340 (2002).

1. Habermas (1996), 195–197.2. See ibid., 195–196.3. James Bohman, a philosopher, finds it “odd that Habermas spends so much

time” discussing adjudication rather than legislation. See Bohman (1994), 910 n.20. His perspective reflects the disciplinary difference between philosophy and law.

4. See Habermas (1996), 197–199.5. Ibid., 199. On the meaning of “external justification,” see Alexy (1989), 230:

“Internal justification is concerned with the question of whether an opinion fol-lows logically from the premisses adduced as justifying it. The correctness of these premisses is the subject-matter of external justification.”

6. See Habermas (1996), 197.7. Ibid., 192.8. Under the heading of “legal realism,” Habermas considers American legal

realism, interest jurisprudence (Interessenjurisprudenz), and the “Free Law” school (Freirechtsschule). See ibid., 201, 538 nn10–11.

9. See ibid., 201.10. See ibid., 201–203.11. See ibid., 199–200.12. One problem, of course, is that the body of work referred to as “legal

realism”—or even “American legal realism”—is diverse in style, subject matter, and conclusions. Habermas would have done better to consider one or another “real-ist” rather than try to characterize “realism” generally in two paragraphs. But the idea that “realism” flatly revoked the certainty guarantee seems consistent only with one early work by Jerome Frank. See Frank (1970) [1930] 46–52 (interpret-ing the quest for legal certainty as [in part] a projection of infantile needs). But much “realist” work could be seen as recasting rather than “revoking” the idea of legal certainty. A more characteristic realist argument is not that we cannot predict the outcome of most legal disputes but, instead, that any predictive capac-ity we have depends less on analysis of black-letter legal rules than commonly has been thought. At least a significant body of “realist” work was directed toward in-creasing the predictability and certainty of legal rules—partly by verbal reformula-tion but also by improving the information available to decision makers (through procedural and other changes), by finding better decision makers than generalist judges and juries, and to some extent, by crafting different systems of rules that would more closely track reasonable procedures in the field being regulated. This list of “realist” reform strategies suggests also that the concern for “rightness” was not simply a matter of trusting judges to take on a policy-making role. A charac-teristic “realist” argument was that judges always had been performing that role but usually covertly, sometimes unconsciously, and often badly. And at least for some important “realist” thinkers, both procedural changes and incorporation of reasonable extralegal norms could improve the rightness of adjudicative decisions.

Page 288: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

277 Notes to Chapter 3

13. William Forbath argues that a better understanding of legal-realist think-ing would have improved Habermas’s account of the economic and administrative system. See Forbath (1998b), 279–283, 286.

14. See, for example, Dworkin (1986), 14–15.15. See Habermas (1996), 203 (regarding Dworkin).16. See Dworkin (1986), 30.17. Dworkin does not always describe this second dimension of interpretation

as “justification,” but sometimes he does. See ibid., 239, 255. He refers on other occasions to the dimension of “substance” or (in discussing legal interpretation) “justice.” More recently, in Justice as Robes, he has used the term justification to describe the process that comprises both dimensions, with at least “rough fit” re-quired for a “competent justification” (Dworkin, 2006, 15).

18. See Dworkin (1986), 239. 19. Habermas (1996), 211.20. See ibid., 198–199.21. See ibid., 212–213.22. See ibid., 213–214.23. Ibid., 216.24. See ibid., 216–217.25. Dworkin (1986), 268–271; Habermas (1996), 208–209. According to Ger-

man legal theorist Robert Alexy, Dworkin’s idea is that “valid rules apply in an all-or-nothing way” while “principles only contain reasons pointing in a certain direction but not necessarily requiring a particular decision.” This idea, he says, is “simplistic and needs to be more nuanced” (Alexy, 2002, 57). Rather than the vector metaphor of pointing, Alexy prefers the metaphor of “weight” and “balanc-ing.” The conflict of principles is to be determined by balancing and “establishing a conditional relation of precedence between the principles in the light of the circum-stances of the case.” See Alexy (2002), 47–57.

Alexy connects this balancing approach to the practice of the German consti-tutional court. As discussed in the following section, Habermas is critical of the court’s balancing approach. In this, he sides with Klaus Günther, who rejects the balancing metaphor and distinguishes between two kinds of discourse (justifica-tion and application) rather than just two kinds of norm (rule and principle). See Günther (1993), 210–219.

26. Habermas (1996), 217.27. Ibid., 217–218.28. As Peterson describes Günther’s theory of the application process: “Se-

lecting one norm by coherently ordering the conflicting applicable norms in an ‘exhaustively’ described situation does not permanently rank the norms; the un-selected applicable norm(s) remain prima facie valid and available to be applied in other situations” (Peterson (2010), 36).

29. Habermas’s main example from critical legal studies scholarship is Ken-nedy (1976)

30. See Günther (1993), 228–245 for his “logic of appropriateness argumenta-tion,” the form of argumentation employed in application discourses. Here, but

Page 289: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

278 Notes to Chapter 3

not in justification discourses, the standard is essentially one of coherence. See ibid., 244.

31. See Habermas (1996), 219.32. Alexy writes: “The idea of the discourse of application is at the same time

correct, empty, and easy to misunderstand. It is correct as far as it expresses the old hermeneutic demand for the consideration of all aspects. This demand is an el-ementary postulate of rationality. It is empty because it does not say which aspects are to be considered in what way” (Alexy (1998), 231).

33. See Alexy (1998), 226, 231.34. Habermas (1996), 220.35. See ibid., 197–198.36. Ibid., 220.37. Ibid., 201.38. See ibid., 433, 435.39. Günther suggests that “paradigms” might be helpful in selecting which fea-

tures of a situation should count as relevant in an application discourse (Günther (1993), 245).

40. Ibid., 194–195. For Niklas Luhmann’s treatment of this problem within the theory of autopoietic systems, see Luhmann (2004), 423–463.

41. Habermas (1996), 195.42. See, for example, ibid., 195, 221–222, 389–391, 409–410, 414–415, 437.

Sometimes Habermas refers only to the former two paradigms, but usually when viewing them from the perspective of his own. See ibid., 250–251, 401–402, 407, 418–419.

43. See Alexy (1998), 231.44. See Habermas (1996), 221.45. Ibid., 252 (quoting Sunstein (1990), 170–171). Sunstein’s proposal is as

follows:

Where there is ambiguity, courts should construe regulatory statutes so that (1) politically unaccountable actors are prohibited from deciding important is-sues; (2) collective action problems do not subvert statutory programs; (3) vari-ous regulatory statutes are, to the extent possible, coordinated into a coherent whole; (4) obsolete statutes are kept consistent with changing developments of law, policy, and fact; (5) procedural qualifications of substantive rights are kept narrow; (6) the complex systemic effects of regulation are taken into ac-count; and most generally, (7) irrationality and injustice, measured against the statute’s own purposes, are avoided.

46. See Habermas (1996), 252–253.47. See ibid., 221, 224–225.48. Mark Modak-Truran also criticizes Habermas’s suggestion that “para-

digms” can significantly ease the problem of legal indeterminacy. See Modak-Truran (2007), 110–116. I differ from Modak-Truran, however, in that I don’t see Habermas’s paradigms as themselves norms. Cf. ibid., 111.

49. Habermas (1996), 222–224. Andrew Arato defends this idea of a public sphere that would constrain courts, particularly in their exercise of constitutional

Page 290: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

279 Notes to Chapter 3

jurisdiction, but notes that Habermas has not gone far in addressing questions of institutional design. See Arato (1998), 32–34.

50. The real use of this “open society of interpreters” idea is to provide a check, called for by discourse theory’s prodemocracy tilt, in cases where courts engage in what might be considered lawmaking rather than law-application.

51. Habermas (1996), 235–237.52. Ibid., 238.53. One of the four cases Dworkin uses to illustrate his theory of constructive

interpretation is a common-law case (see Dworkin (1986), 23–29), and he devotes a chapter to “the common law” (see ibid., 276–312), alongside his chapters on “stat-utes” and “the constitution.”

54. See Kemp (1999). Victor Peterson argues that “accusations that Habermas disregards common law adjudication are easily refuted, because Between Facts and Norms repeatedly acknowledges the reality of the creative development of law by the judiciary” (Peterson (2010), 53). I have noted the same references as Peterson, but, as explained in text, I assess the overall picture differently.

55. See, for example, Weber (1978), 641–900 (Vol. 2).56. See Luhmann (2004), vii. In his commentary on Between Facts and Norms,

Luhmann notes that Habermas places “a very traditional emphasis on legislation, thereby underestimating judicial lawmaking” (Luhmann (1998), 166).

57. Cf. Habermas (1996), 172–174.58. Cf. ibid., 280, 440. For a suggestion that Habermas needs to think further

about questions of institutional design, see Arato (1998), 32–34. A basic problem is that the lay public probably is less interested in the constraints Habermas would place on judicial activity and more interested in politically desirable outcomes.

59. Cf. Habermas (1996), 120–121.60. Ibid., 198.61. See Peterson (2010), 76–87.62. Habermas (1996), 190.63. Ibid., 193.64. Ibid., 439.65. Ibid., 440.66. Christopher Zurn comes to a similar conclusion about Dworkin’s idea of

constructive interpretation, which, despite Dworkin’s application of the idea to statutory and constitutional cases, is essentially a common-law form of reason-ing. Habermas proposes to add to Dworkin’s analysis “a dialogic twist, as it were, by subjecting Hercules’s lonely considerations to the broader intersubjective scru-tiny of a juridical public sphere.” But as Zurn notes, “It remains an open question whether the multiplication of Hercules is sufficient to render the method of con-structive interpretation sufficiently democratic” (Zurn (2007), 247 n33). The same conclusion follows, I think, with respect to specifically and professedly common-law forms of reason.

67. See Habermas (1996), 212, 214.68. Peterson suggests that the answer is “no”:

Habermas’ discourse theory of law and democracy cannot simply reject common law as undemocratic, because it aims to succeed not only as a

Page 291: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

280 Notes to Chapter 3

philosophical theory of justice, but also at the level of legal theory. For Haber-mas, legal theory differs from philosophy of law in presupposing the basic prin-ciples and institutions of a particular legal order, which in the U.S. includes common law. (Peterson (2010), 75).

69. See Habermas (1996), 240–241, 243–244.70. See ibid., 174, 245, 249–250, 263, 269, 407.71. See ibid., 250.72. Ibid.73. Bernhard Schlink, a former German constitutional-court judge, law profes-

sor, and most recently best-selling author (The Reader), has argued that the German high constitutional court’s alleged “value-orientation” is a “myth” and “fiction.” See Schlink (1998), 371.

74. Ibid., 254–256.75. 533 U.S. 27 (2001).76. I select an opinion authored by Justice Scalia because he is a sharp critic of

the idea that constitutional courts may make law. His preferred “textualist” ap-proach would interpret the Constitution to discover its “original public meaning,” that is, the meaning it would have had to an ordinary interpreter at the time of the framing or ratification. See Scalia (1997).

77. 533 U.S., 31; see also ibid., 34, 37, 40.78. Ibid., 31–32, 35, 37.79. Another potentially applicable interpretive principle would focus on the

meaning of constitutional texts rather than the purpose of constitutional rights protection: The meaning of a constitutional provision, according to this principle, is its original public meaning, that is, the meaning it had at the time of ratification. For a sustained defense of this thesis, see Solum (2008).

80. See ibid., 34, 38–39, 40.81. Zurn (2007), 257.82. Habermas’s account of application discourses emphasizes strongly the sin-

gularity of decision. See Habermas (1996), 229.83. Alexy (1993), 167.84. Ibid., 439.85. Christopher Zurn correctly points out the sharp tension between Dwor-

kin’s idea of constructive interpretation and Habermas’s conception of democracy. See Zurn (2007), 247 n33. In a recent tribute to Dworkin, Habermas has raised the question of “what influence may, or even should, a judge’s moral convictions have on his rulings?” (Habermas (2009h), 38). But neither in that essay nor (to my knowledge) anywhere else has Habermas clearly and systematically addressed Dworkin’s idea of a “moral reading of the constitution.” See Dworkin (1996), 1–38. In both its recommendation of a “moral reading” of the Constitution and its (con-tinuing) near-exclusive focus on courts as constitutional interpreters, Dworkin’s work seems to me difficult to reconcile with Habermas’s critique of “value juris-prudence” and judicial paternalism.

86. Dworkin (1986), 225.87. Cf. Michelman (1998), 321–322 (noting that the distinction between appli-

cation and justification is difficult in constitutional practice).

Page 292: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

281 Notes to Chapter 3

88. See Habermas (1996), 212–213.89. Ibid., 172.90. Alexy (2002), 4, 93.91. Ibid., 44, 47–50.92. Ibid., 50. Dworkin, too, uses the language of weight: The weight of a right

is “its “power to withstand” competition with a another principle or policy. See Dworkin (1977), 92.

93. In Alexy’s terminology, “balancing” is “proportionality in the narrow sense.” It, together with the ideas of “necessity” (or, “use of the least intrusive means”) and “suitability,” comprise proportionality in the broader sense.

94. Ibid., 50–51, 52–53.95. Ibid. (quoting BVerfGE vol. 7, 198, 215).96. Alexy (2003), 133 (quoting BVerfGE vol. 81, 242, 254).97. Alexy (2003), 93.98. Alexy (2002), 86.99. Ibid., 93.100. Ibid., 88.101. Ibid., 87, 93.102. Ibid., 93.103. Ibid., 100–101.104. Ibid., 62.105. Basic Law, article 1(1)(1). 106. Alexy (2002), 63.107. Habermas (1996), 192; see also ibid., 283.108. Ibid., 262.109. Gunther Teubner argues that legal practice, including judicial practice,

is indifferent to the principle/value distinction in its “balancing” procedures. See Teubner (1998), 186.

110. Habermas (1996), 154 (emphasis added). No doubt Habermas is nervous about interpreting constitutional provisions as deals to be enforced. But, if that is his concern, a more plausible “reconstruction” of modern democracies’ “normative self-understanding” might be a canon that constitutional norms should be inter-preted in a public-regarding way, not as deals. That seems to me more plausible than the idea of a “firewall” between legal norms and values or collective goals.

111. Cf. Michelman, supra, 321 (“The practical-institutional logic of consti-tutionalism precludes anything like a strict working dissociation of justification from application”).

112. Habermas (1996), vi. The title to Section 6.2 of Between Facts and Norms is “Norms versus Values: Methodological Errors in the Self-Understanding of the Constitutional Court.”

113. Habermas (1996), 172, 192.114. Ibid., 99–100.115. Ibid., 268.116. See ibid., 174, 245, 249–251, 263.117. See ibid., 268–269, 269–270.118. Ibid., 272.

Page 293: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

282 Notes to Chapter 3

119. See ibid., 270, 298.120. Ibid., 272, 273–274.121. Ibid., 263–264.122. Alexy (2002), 352, 354. Alexy states that “all agree” that German constitu-

tional norms have this effect (ibid., 354).123. See Habermas (1996), 402–403.124. Alexy (2002), 355–356.125. Ibid., 362.126. Ibid., 358.127. Habermas (1996), 268, 270.128. Michelman (1988), 1531.129. Habermas (1996), 275 (citing Michelman (1988), 1531).130. Habermas (1996), 275–276.131. Ibid., 279.132. See ibid., 267–268, 279 (discussing classical republican notions of politics

without distinguishing Michelman’s neorepublican view).133. Ibid., 277.134. See ibid., 268–269, 278.135. See ibid., 279.136. See Michelman (1988), 1505–1506.137. Ibid., 1526.138. See ibid. (referring to “the challenge of reclaiming the idea of jurisgenera-

tive politics from its ancient context of hierarchical, organicist, solidaristic com-munities for the modern context of equality of respect, liberation from ascriptive social roles, and indissoluble plurality of perspective”).

139. Ibid., 277.140. Michelman (1988), 1508–1509.141. Ibid., 1515–1518.142. Michelman points out in a reply to Habermas that if one believed society

to be totally and consensually integrated, then a cross-section of the population, not full engagement of the citizenry, would suffice. And so the alleged connec-tion between the “deep consensus” assumption, on one hand, and republicanism’s demanding notion of participation, on the other, seems lacking. See Michelman (1998), 314–315.

143. Habermas (1996), 278.144. Michelman (1988), 1525.145. Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186, 196 (1986).146. Michelman (1988), 1495.147. Ibid., 1537.148. Ibid.149. The passage Habermas quotes is as follows: “The Court helps protect the

republican state—that is, the people politically engaged—from lapsing into a poli-tics of self-denial. It challenges ‘the people’s’ self-enclosing tendency to assume their own moral completion as they now are and thus to deny to themselves the plurality on which their capacity for transformative self-renewal depends” (ibid., 1532).

150. Ibid.

Page 294: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

283 Notes to Chapter 3

151. The work of John Hart Ely is important here, particularly the part of his “representation-reinforcing theory” directed toward “facilitating the representa-tion of minorities” (Ely (1980)). Ely’s connection to Supreme Court case law is the famous footnote four of United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 141, 152 n4 (“discrete and insular minorities”).

152. For Michelman’s substantive argument, see Michelman (1988), 1532–1536.153. Habermas (1996), 265.154. See Ely (1980), 105–180.155. Forbath (1998a), 995.156. Forbath notes, in the context of Habermas’s theory more generally, the

diametrically different political interpretations that Richard Posner and Frank Mi-chelman gave Between Facts and Norms in their book reviews (ibid., 998 n27).

157. Habermas (1996), 280.158. See ibid., 376–378.159. Ibid., 386.160. Ibid., 378–379.161. The Court recently has stated:

Premised on mistrust of governmental power, the First Amendment stands against attempts to disfavor certain subjects or viewpoints. Prohibited, too, are restrictions distinguishing among different speakers, allowing speech by some but not others. As instruments to censor, these categories are interre-lated: Speech restrictions based on the identity of the speaker are all too often simply a means to control content. (Citizens United v. FEC (January 21, 2010), slip opinion, 24 (citations omitted)).

162. Joseph Staats suggests that “Habermas’s more recent work fails to capture fully the way in which corporate power can corrupt the democratic process” (Staats (2004), 585). Specifically, Staats says, “we must study the impact on democracy of the modern corporation, especially as it is expressed through the modern mass me-dia” (ibid.). But Staats’s account of how “corporate power allied with the mass me-dia is able to use powers of agenda control definition” to “corrupt[] the democratic process” (see ibid., 590–593) seems to be an elaboration of the argument Habermas makes in Between Facts and Norms, not a correction of mistaken principle. In Chap-ter Five, I discuss Habermas’s revision of the model he uses in Between Facts and Norms and how his most recent work addresses the issue Staats identifies.

163. See Habermas (1996), 368–369.164. Ibid., 265.165. This is Ely’s suggestion for the case of groups whose access to the political

process, once effectively blocked, no longer is so—but who cannot reasonably be expected to exhaust their political capital on repealing outdated statutes. See Ely (1980), 169.

166. Habermas (1996), 265.167. The U.S. Supreme Court has recognized this point expressly and refused to

grant third parties relief: “Many features of our political system—e.g., single-member districts, ‘first past the post’ elections, and the high costs of campaigning—make it difficult for third parties to succeed in American politics. But the Constitution does

Page 295: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

284 Notes to Chapter 3

not require States to . . . move to proportional-representation elections or public financing of campaigns” (Timmons v. Twin Cities Area New Party, 520 U.S. 351, 362 (1997); citation omitted).

168. The German system mixes proportional representation with more American-style single-district representation.

169. 377 U.S. 533 (1964).170. See Rawls (2001), 149. Rawls acknowledges that these and related reforms

(equalizing access to public media, for example) may “infringe upon the freedoms of speech and press,” but

these liberties are no more absolute than the political liberties with their guar-anteed fair value. In adjusting these basic liberties one aim is to enable legisla-tors and political parties to be independent of large concentrations of private economic and social power in a private-property democracy, and of govern-ment control and bureaucratic power in a liberal socialist regime. This is to further the conditions of deliberative democracy and to set the stage for the exercise of public reason. (Ibid., 149–150)

In Political Liberalism, Rawls presents an extended critique of the Supreme Court’s campaign-finance cases, particularly Buckley v. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1 (1976) (per curiam) and First National Bank v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765 (1978). Buckley and Bel-lotti were the cases on which the Court recently relied most heavily in overruling two decisions that limited business corporations’ ability to spend general treasury money on campaign speech. See Citizens United v. FEC (January 21, 2010), slip opinion, 28–46.

171. Rawls (2005), 360.172. Dworkin (2006a), 129.173. Ibid., 151. For Dworkin’s immediate criticism of the Citizens United deci-

sion, see Dworkin (2010).174. Citizens United, slip opinion, 3, quoting 2 U.S.C. §434(f)(3)(A).175. For explanation of “soft money” and its relation to the “phony issue ads”

(or, “sham issue advocacy”) that were a staple of “electioneering communica-tions,” see the Court’s decision upholding the soft-money ban, McConnell v. FEC, 540 U.S. 93, 122–132 (2003). The Court emphasized substantial evidence before Congress that soft money bought access to elected officials and otherwise either “ha[d] a corrupting influence or g[a]ve rise to the appearance of corruption” (540 U.S., 145).

The classic example of the “phony issue ad”:

Announcer: Who is Bill Yellowtail? He preaches family values, but he took a swing at his wife. Yellowtail’s explanation? He only slapped her, but her nose was not broken. He talks law and order, but is himself a convicted criminal. And though he talks about protecting children, Yellowtail failed to make his own child support payments, then voted against child support enforcement. Call Bill Yellowtail and tell him we don’t approve of his wrongful behavior. Call (406) 443-3620.

Page 296: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

285 Notes to Chapter 3

The ad does not expressly call upon the listener to vote against Bill Yellowtail, but that unmistakably is the central (really, only) message. While the group that ran the ad was formally independent of the campaign of Yellowtail’s opponent, the expenditure on the ad is functionally equivalent to a contribution to that campaign.

176. A prominent example of those groups includes, from the 2004 election, the “Swift Boat Veterans for Truth” who targeted presidential candidate John Kerry’s war record. The majority of 527 money, however, has been on the side of Democratic/liberal causes. See the analysis by the Center for Responsive Politics, online at www.opensecrets.org/527s/.

177. See Transcript of Oral Argument in Citizens United v. FEC (September 9, 2009), 22. Justice Stevens’s dissent in Citizens United points to the follow-up question by Justice Kennedy, who went on to author the Citizens United opinion. Indeed, Stevens implies that the Court, not Congress, may be targeting the soft-money ban. Citizens United (Stevens, J., dissenting) (slip op., 21 n. 22).

178. See, e.g., Persily (2010). In a case many observers thought was headed for the Supreme Court, the U.S. District Court for the District of Columbia noted the “disparity,” due to the soft-money ban, that disfavors national political parties “as compared to outside groups.” While that court noted that, as a lower court, it was bound by Supreme Court precedent to uphold the ban, it expressly flagged the issue for Supreme Court review (Republican National Committee v. FEC, 698 F.Supp.2d 151, 160 note 5; DDC 2010). As it happened, however, the Supreme Court decided not to hear the case (and thus, at this time, the issue). Three Justices (Scalia, Kennedy, and Thomas) dissented from the denial of review. See 130 S. Ct. 3544 (2010) (June 29, 2010).

179. Citizens United, slip opinion, 55.180. See Lessig (2010).181. The term was coined to describe a salamander-shaped district drawn in

1812 by Massachusetts governor Elbridge Gerry to favor his party. While the prac-tice undoubtedly goes back earlier, the specifically partisan gerrymander depended on the coalescing of a party system in the early Republic.

182. Because all agree that the framers of the Constitution affirmatively sought to discourage the formation of political parties, it would be difficult to argue that the Constitution as originally ratified would give partisan gerrymanders special protection.

183. An additional technique is “tacking,” or “reaching out from the bulk of a district to grab a distant area with specific desired (usually partisan) demograph-ics” (Levitt (2008), 56). A third technique is “shacking,” through which district lines are “redrawn so an incumbent’s residence (her ‘shack’) is in a district that no longer contains her current constituents,” and ideally so as to pit the disfavored incumbent against another incumbent (Issacharoff and Karlan (2004), 552).

184. See Issaacharoff, Karlan, and Pildes (2009), 880. 185. See, for example, Issacharoff and Nagler (2007). The evidence these au-

thors discuss concerns Congress; the same forces, however, are at work in state legislatures.

186. See Davis v. Bandemer, 478 U.S. 109 (1986).

Page 297: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

286 Notes to Chapter 3

187. See Vieth v. Jubelirer, 541 U.S. 267 (2004). Justice Kennedy was the fifth vote for the possibility of granting relief in some future case, but he declined to commit himself to a constitutional standard (541 U.S., 306). Justices Stevens, Souter, and Breyer stated different versions of what they believed to be the proper judicial test.

188. See LULAC v. Perry, 548 U.S. 399 (2006).189. Some argue that the 2006 and 2008 elections have demonstrated that

partisan gerrymanders are inherently self-limiting—that is, that the democratic system itself contains the antidote for partisan gerrymanders without judicial in-tervention. For a good overview of the argument and evaluation of the 2006 and 2008 results, see Note (2009).

190. See Vieth, 541 U.S., 293.191. Vieth, 541 U.S., 275 (opinion of Scalia, J.) (citing Article I, section 4 of the

U.S. Constitution).192. See Fairness and Independence in Redistricting Act, 111th Cong., S. 1332

and H.R. 3025 (2009).193. See Levitt (2008), 20–22. For computer-generated redistricting, the idea

would be to let politically more neutral criteria—compactness, contiguity, re-spect for political and natural geographic boundaries, and the like—provide the parameters.

194. In other areas, the Supreme Court has tended to guard jealously its pre-rogative of prescribing what the Constitution means, notwithstanding the resis-tance of other actors. At times—such as in confronting state executive resistance to the Brown v. Board of Education decision—the Court has acted for laudable pur-poses, even if its self-conception is not defensible in principle. See Cooper v. Aaron, 358 U.S. 1 (1958) (the Supreme Court’s interpretation of the Constitution is “the su-preme law of the land”). In other contexts, the laudability of the Court’s purposes is less clear. This is so, for example, in the restrictive interpretation the Court recently has given to section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment, which authorizes Congress to “enforce” due-process and equal-protection guarantees “by appropri-ate legislation.” See United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598 (2000) (invalidating the civil remedy provision of the Violence against Women Act) and City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507 (1997) (invalidating the Religious Freedom Restoration Act as against state action).

195. See Brest (1975); Levinson et al. (5th edition, 2006) (first edition by Brest in 1975, and second by Brest and Levinson in 1983).

196. For comparative analysis, see Tushnet (2008). In that work, Tushnet ex-tends the U.S.–focused analysis of Tushnet (1999).

197. Tushnet (2008), 33.198. Ibid., 23.199. See ibid., 25–31, 52.200. Tushnet (2009), 504.201. See Boumediene v. Bush, 533 U.S. 723 (2008). In fairness to Specter: After

the Military Commissions Act passed, he cosponsored legislation to amend the offending provision.

Page 298: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

287 Notes to Chapters 3 and 4

202. As Tushnet observes, one must beware of taking judicial interpretations to set the standard for interpretive correctness. Whether judicial interpretive ca-pacity is greater is precisely the question at issue. See Tushnet (2009), 500.

203. Kramer (2004).204. Ibid., 81.205. See Whittington (2007).206. See Post and Siegel (2009, 2004).207. Zurn (2007), 30. For his full discussion, see ibid., 253–342.208. Habermas (1996), 263.209. Ibid., 123.210. See ibid., 154 (“It must be possible to interpret even ordinary legislation as

serving to realize and specify the system of rights elaborated in the constitution”).211. Ibid., 402–403.212. One version of such an argument is offered by Günter Frankenberg. See

Frankenberg (1996). Frankenberg objects to Habermas’s treatment of social rights as justified only so far as they are necessary for private or public autonomy. He proposes that social rights be justified independently, based on notions of social solidarity and empowerment. He is clear, however, that social rights are “a project that has to stand the test of public controversy” (ibid., 1385).

213. In American constitutional law, for example, Mark Tushnet has connected general reflections on weak-form judicial review with comparative analysis of constitutional protection for social and economic rights. See Tushnet (2008). In philosophy, one is beginning to see, for example, attempts to connect relatively ab-stract rights theory with an understanding of how newer forms of constitutional rights actually are being protected through judicial review and other institutions. See, for example, Bilchitz (2007).

214. See Schlink (1998), 377.

4. system, lifeworld, and habermas’s “communication theory of society”

Portions of this chapter were adapted from “System and Lifeworld in Haber-mas’s Theory of Law,” Cardozo Law Review 23: 473–615 (2002).

1. Habermas (1998h), 444.2. See Habermas (1996), 341.3. Ibid., 2–22, 23.4. See ibid., 26, 55, 353.5. See ibid., 324.6. Ibid., 80; see also ibid., 354. Habermas allows that strategic action, not just

communicative action, is possible “in the lifeworld” (ibid., 524 n18). But while the lifeworld provides a “background” for strategic action, it is “neutralized in its action-coordinating force” (ibid). By this cryptic phrase Habermas means that to strategic actors, norms are just “social facts,” not normatively obligatory.

7. Habermas’s continued use of the “components” idea is in tension with his claim that “the communicative concept of the lifeworld breaks with the idea of a

Page 299: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

288 Notes to Chapter 4

whole composed of parts” (ibid., 80). The discussion following this quotation, however, suggests that he means that the lifeworld’s “components” are not sepa-rate but interrelated, see ibid., or, as he puts it elsewhere, “intertwined” (ibid., 55). The idea of culture, society, and personality as “components” is in tension, also, with Habermas’s statement that “the lifeworld forms, as a whole, a network com-posed of communicative actions” (ibid., 354).

8. See ibid., 25–26.9. Ibid., 39. As before, the term Habermas uses to include both system and

social integration is societal integration—gesellschaftlich rather than sozial.10. See ibid., 55–56, 354.11. Ibid., 40.12. Ibid., 354.13. Ibid.; see also ibid., 40.14. Ibid., 56.15. Ibid., 81; see also ibid., 56 (describing law as a “transformer”).16. The account of this “institutionalization” is thin in Between Facts and

Norms. He refers to the “legal institutionalization of markets” (ibid., 75) but with-out further analysis.

17. Ibid., 80. Habermas adds that “legal symbolism,” as a body of knowledge, is “represented” in the cultural component, and that “competences acquired via legal socialization” are “represented” in the personality component (ibid., 81).

18. See ibid., 38–39, 386.19. See ibid., 55–56, 81, 302, 354.20. Ibid., 56.21. The model is set out in Habermas (1996), 354–359.22. See ibid., 353–354.23. See ibid., 354 (citing Peters (1993)).24. Peters (1994), 125. For the full set of criticisms, see ibid., 120–126.25. Andrew Edgar agrees. See Edgar (2005), 249.26. Habermas (1996), 321; see also ibid., 326, 327–328.27. The account of “colonization” focuses entirely on the relation between

administrative system and lifeworld. William Forbath has pointed out the defi-ciencies in Habermas’s analysis of the economic system, both in Theory of Commu-nicative Action and in Between Facts and Norms. See Forbath (1998a), 1001–1007; see also Forbath (1998b), 279–286.

28. Likely Peters borrowed this center/periphery schema from the German sys-tems theorist, Niklas Luhmann. For an account of how Luhmann uses the center/periphery schema to analyze the legal system, see Baxter (1998), 2014–2024.

29. Habermas (1996), 354–355.30. See Habermas (1987b), 367–373.31. For example, in one passage Habermas defines “the legal system in the nar-

row sense” as including “all interactions that are not only oriented to law, but are also geared to produce new law and reproduce law as law” (Habermas (1996), 195 [emphasis omitted]). He goes on to explain that courts, legislatures, “Govern-ment leaders,” and administrative agencies, as well as “parties, political parties, [and] electorates,” are part of the process that produces and reproduces law (ibid.,

Page 300: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

289 Notes to Chapter 4

195–196). That list corresponds to the list of players that Habermas’s model puts in the political system’s center.

32. The term autopoiesis means “self-making,” “self-creation,” or “self-production.” The central idea is that modern societies are differentiated into dif- ferent systems of communication—for example, science, art, politics, law, economy—and these systems are “self-referential” and “autonomous.” By “autono-mous,” however, Luhmann does not mean “independent of ‘external’ influences,” and by “self-referential” he does not mean that systems do not refer to other sys-tems. His claim, however, is that the conditions for their external reference are determined internally, through standards, criteria, and procedures produced in the referring system’s own communication.

The terms autonomous and self-referential have invited much criticism—and in my view, much confusion. One way of understanding what Luhmann means is to think of “autonomy” as a methodological rather than a substantive principle: To understand the operation of a differentiated system of communication, begin “internally,” with the system’s own practices, procedures, and standards.

33. See Luhmann (1988).34. See Habermas (1996), 143.35. See ibid., 55, 143. This conception would fit Habermas’s idea that the sys-

tem’s medium is “power,” and Habermas conceives power as a medium in terms of command. For his part, Luhmann equivocates, positing two different codes for the political system. See Baxter (1998), 2040, 2067–2068 (criticizing Luhmann’s equiv-ocation between “government/opposition” and “governing/governed” as the code).

36. One might think that Habermas’s discussion of how law and politics mutu-ally establish one another’s codes (see Habermas (1996), 143–144), together with his more general emphasis on the “internal connection” between law and political power (see ibid., 133–151), would establish that law and politics are not separate sys-tems. But Habermas’s discussion tracks Luhmann’s analysis of the functions that law and politics perform for one another, and Luhmann concludes that law and politics are separate but “structurally coupled” systems. See Baxter (1998), 2036–2045. Further, to describe law and politics as “internally linked” is simply to say that they are conceptually related, or that they mutually presuppose another. The term “link” implies a distinctness even as it implies relation. Compare Habermas (1996), 79 (“I would like to distinguish law and morality from the start”), with ibid., 118 (stating that law and morality are “internally coupled”).

37. In a passage separate from the “circulation of power” model, Habermas writes:

Because the specific features of a legal system first appear in state-sanctioned law, there is a certain plausibility to Weber’s theoretical strategy of conceiving law as part of the political system. Less plausible is Luhmann’s further step of taking modern law out of politics again and giving it independent status as its own subsystem alongside the administration, economy, family, and the like. (Ibid., 74)

38. See ibid., 168–193, 238–286.39. Ibid., 355.

Page 301: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

290 Notes to Chapter 4

40. Ibid.41. Habermas says that these organizations “fulfill certain coordination

functions in more or less opaque social sectors” (ibid.). “Opacity” sometimes is Habermas-code for “functional systems.” See ibid., 321. Further, unions and trade associations both represent economic interests and (could be said to) “fulfill coor-dination functions” in the economic sphere.

42. Habermas refers to “clientele bargaining” (ibid., 355).43. Ibid. “Charitable organizations” thus appear both in the inner and outer

periphery. Presumably this is not mere inadvertence on Habermas’s part; he must have a distinction in mind between different kinds of charities—one whose primary function is provision of welfare services, and the other whose primary function is advocacy. Or he may be recognizing that many charities perform both functions.

44. See ibid., 355–356.45. Ibid., 359–362.46. Ibid., 136; see also ibid., 299, 301.47. Ibid., 171; see also ibid., 136.48. Or one might think simply that they, or some of them, are ill chosen and

symptomatic of weaknesses in Habermas’s theory. William Forbath criticizes Habermas’s “electronics metaphors”—not just the “sensors” of the political pub-lic sphere but also the “transformer” metaphor of law. Forbath reads these meta-phors to be “anxious”—connected with a defensive politics aimed at preventing colonization of the lifeworld. See Forbath (1998a), 999; see also Forbath (1998b), 276–277. I agree with Forbath that Theory of Communicative Action has that defen-sive quality, and I agree also that the system/lifeworld distinction both reflects and confirms Habermas’s defensiveness. My view, however, is that Habermas’s revised model moves away from the rigidity of the system/lifeworld conception, even if elsewhere in Between Facts and Norms Habermas recites his earlier formulations of “system” and “lifeworld.”

49. Habermas (1996), 327. For other uses of the “sluice” metaphor, see ibid., 170, 300, 354, 356, 358.

50. See, for example, ibid., 135–136.51. Ibid., 362.52. Ibid. (emphasis added).53. In prior work, Habermas used the term civil society to mean “a sphere of

legally domesticated, incessant competition between strategically acting private persons.” Habermas (1987b), 178. In that sense, civil society referred essentially to the sphere of economic relations. Habermas now disavows that usage. See Haber-mas (1996), 366.

54. See ibid., 354.55. See Habermas (1987b), 320 nn8,39. For a table representing the system/

lifeworld relation as conceived in Theory of Communicative Action, see section 1.4.56. Habermas (1996), 175; see also ibid., 358, 366–367.57. See ibid., 354, 365.58. Ibid., 366.59. See, for example, ibid., 352.

Page 302: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

291 Notes to Chapter 4

60. Ibid., 367. Parent–child relations presumably do not count as fully egalitarian.61. See ibid., 299, 301, 366.62. See ibid., 302, 335, 352, 366–367, 382.63. See, for example, ibid., 367.64. Ibid., 354.65. Ibid., 367.66. Ibid., 372.67. Ibid., 317; see also ibid., 131, 302, 437.68. Ibid., 371.69. See ibid., 368–369.70. Ibid., 175.71. Habermas distinguishes between facilitative and restrictive effects of social

power. To participate at all, one must be in a position to assert one’s will and in-terests. But a grossly unequal distribution of social power threatens to restrict the communicative freedom of the comparatively disempowered. See ibid., 175.

72. See ibid.73. See, for example, ibid., 307.74. Ibid., 308.75. See ibid., 376–378.76. See ibid., 378.77. Ibid., 356. Habermas writes “parliamentary complex or the courts,” but at

the moment my interest is only in the legislative process.78. Ibid., 357.79. Ibid., 373 (emphasis omitted). Joshua Cohen perceptively criticizes Haber-

mas’s tendency here to privilege “outside” ideas and to disparage ideas formulated within formal political institutions:

The requirement of outside initiative strikes me as ill-conceived: Lots of politi-cal movements are initially provoked by developments internal to conventional institutions and actors—for example, by competition between and among elites who mobilize popular support with the expectation that that mobiliza-tion can be controlled—even though the subsequent evolution of those move-ments proceeds independently; when it comes to popular movements, genesis is not identity. (Cohen, 1999, 409)

80. See Habermas (1996), 367, 443.81. See ibid., 354–355.82. See ibid., 367.83. See ibid., 381.84. See ibid., 354.85. I leave aside here the question whether the public-spirited “suppliers” of the

“outer periphery” are among the voluntary associations Habermas takes to con-stitute civil society. The answer seems to be yes, unless Habermas is distinguish-ing between relatively informal associations (civil society) and the more formally organized organizations he calls “suppliers.”

86. Habermas (1996), 355–356.

Page 303: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

292 Notes to Chapter 4

87. See ibid., 352, 356, 357, 358, 442.88. See, for example, ibid., 298.89. Ibid., 330; see also ibid., 381, 382.90. One passage in Between Facts and Norms seems to confirm this interpreta-

tion. Describing the way in which impulses from the periphery may affect official decision making, Habermas writes: “An activated periphery must then introduce [latent problems] via parliamentary (or judicial) sluices into the political system in a way that disrupts the latter’s routines” (ibid., 358). Here the periphery seems to be conceived as lying outside the political system.

91. See ibid., 360.92. Ibid., 366–367.93. Ibid., 110.94. Ibid., 461.95. Ibid., 280.96. Ibid., 461.97. Ibid., 362, 363.98. See, for example, ibid., 371.99. Habermas is aware that his use of the term recalls his rejection of Parsons’s

proposed “influence” medium. See ibid., 363, 556 n50.100. See ibid., 171, 179.101. Ibid., 354.102. See ibid., 235–237.103. See ibid., 192.104. I take this phrase from William Forbath. See Forbath (1998a), 999; see

also Forbath (1998b), 276–277.105. See Habermas (1996), 354 (“The language of law brings ordinary commu-

nication from the public and private spheres and puts it into a form in which these messages can also be received by the special codes of autopoietic systems—and vice versa.”). But cf. ibid., 352 (calling it “impossible to conceive politics and law as autopoietically closed systems”).

106. In his selective incorporation of Luhmann’s autopoetic theory, however, Neil MacCormick places the idea of a binary code front and center. See MacCormick (2007), 99, 177, 184–185, 289. Still, MacCormick realizes that even if one takes the Recht/Unrecht code to be fundamental, one would have to consider, at least in “devel-oped systems,” the further “bifurcat[ion]” between civil and criminal wrongs” and, “in the context of two- or more tier institutional order, . . . the valid/invalid opposi-tion” to account for powers as well as rights and wrongs.” As indicated in the fol-lowing discussion, I accept the idea that the communications proper to a particular system are distinguished by a particular “theme” or “circulating symbol,” but I find the emphasis on a code’s binary quality too inflexible.

107. See ibid., 136–137.108. Habermas (1996), 80.109. Alexander (1983), 84.110. Habermas (1996), 80.111. Between Facts and Norms does not analyze the economic system.

Page 304: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

293 Notes to Chapter 4

112. Bernhard Peters, from whom Habermas borrowed the “circulation of power” model, maintains that with Between Facts and Norms Habermas moves away from a polar distinction between system and lifeworld. See Peters (1994).

113. Cf. ibid., 127.114. Habermas (1996), 354–355.115. Ibid., 354. See Habermas, Faktiztät und Geltung (1992) (German edition of

Between Facts and Norms), 430 for the German terms. Translator William Rehg ex-plains that Verwaltung refers to “the aspect or branch of the state as a bureaucrati-cally organized implementing power,” while Regierung “refer[s] to the leadership or party in office.”

116. Bowling leagues, for example, are civil-social organizations that do not ordinarily contribute to discussion in the political public sphere.

117. See Habermas (1996), 299, 308.118. See ibid., 48-49.119. This example comes from Gordon (1985).120. Luhmann (1997), 286.121. In this respect Luhmann’s thinking coincides with that of American legal

realists, most memorably Friedrich Kessler, who saw the institution of contract as delegated law-making power. See Kessler (1943), 629–630. But with the growing concentration of economic power, Kessler argued, the effect was a shift from a democratizing institution to an authoritarian institution (ibid., 640). Although Luhmann does not use the idea of contract as legal decision for such critical pur-poses, the possibility is there for theorists, such as legal pluralists, who follow him in seeing contract as decision.

122. See, for example, Habermas (1996), 196–197.123. Teubner (1992), 1459. Teubner is an autopoietic theorist, and, for reasons

stated in text, Luhmann would agree with this statement.124. Habermas (1996), 367.125. See Baxter (1998), 2067–2072. One problem with the idea of code as unity-

establishing system mechanism is that Luhmann himself posits two codes for the political system and equivocates on the nature of the economic system’s code. His argument would suggest that the political system really is two systems—because the code is what establishes the system’s unity—and his uncertainty about the eco-nomic system’s code makes it difficult to believe that there is a code for that system so basic as to organize all communication. See ibid., 2067–2068. A second prob-lem is that the emphasis on communication as allocation of code values flattens out the nature of communication. See ibid., 2068–2069.

126. See Luhmann (2004), 443.127. This “theme” actually corresponds to the two codes Luhmann posits for

the political system (see ibid., 367, 378), although I state it as a theme rather than an opposition between binary “code values.”

128. Certainly one could define the organizing theme or point differently. Or one could choose different conceptions for different purposes of analysis. My idea of this organizing theme or point is not so “fundamentalist” as Luhmann’s notion of the binary code, according to which all system communication is about the al-location of opposed code values.

Page 305: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

294 Notes to Chapter 4

129. See Habermas (1996), 49, 51.130. Ibid., 51.131. Ibid., 335.132. Ibid., 56.133. See ibid., 54, 335, 343, 346.134. Ibid., 51.135. Ibid., 54–56.136. See Baxter (1998), 2004–2005.137. See ibid., 2005–2006.138. See ibid., 2009–2010.139. Luhmann’s term for these standards, criteria, and procedures is program-

ming. See ibid., 2009–2013. I find the term programming unhelpful. See ibid., 2068–2069.

140. Luhmann (1992), 1432.141. Luhmann (2004), 377–378.142. Neil MacCormick has appropriated this Luhmannian insight for his own

theory of law as “institutional normative order.” See MacCormick (2007), 177–178.143. Luhmann (2004), 392.144. On the dominance of the “bundle of rights” formulation, see Penner

(1996), 712–715.145. See Baxter (1998), 2047–2057.146. See Kansas v. Hendricks, 521 U.S. 346, 359 (1997).147. Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc., 509 U.S. 579, 592–597.148. In prior work I have suggested a number of other possible “structural cou-

plings.” Many link the legal and economic systems. For example: the concept of negligence (particularly as elaborated economically), the idea of the corporation, “competition” in antitrust law, and the general idea of “liability.” Intellectual prop-erty law establishes links between law and both art and science. Administrative law couples the legal and political systems. The couplings are much more dense than Luhmann’s short list of examples suggests. See Baxter (1998), 2075–2078. Further, Luhmann understates the coupling of systems through events rather than structures. As he acknowledges, a communication may be simultaneously (for example) legal and economic—as when a losing defendant pays a judgment, or when a lawyer presents an argument in court for a fee. See id at 2038, 2078–2079. Finally, Luhmann’s emphasis on structural coupling leads him to understate the importance of other kinds of “irritation” among systems, as when, for example, a legal event (for example, a decision in important business litigation) registers in both the economic and political systems. See ibid., 2079–2080.

149. See Habermas (1987a). See also McCarthy (1992), 1625; Frankenberg (1989), 381.

150. This essay is from 1992, but to this day Teubner finds illuminating the idea that social systems are discourses. See, for example, Teubner (2009), 12 (referring to the systems in law’s environment as “different social discourses,” for example, “educational, scientific, medical, political, and economic discourse”).

151. Teubner (1992), 1447.

Page 306: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

295 Notes to Chapters 4 and 5

152. Teubner defends strongly the idea that systems have binary codes. See, for example, Teubner (1992), 1452. The binary code is for Teubner the basis for one of autopoietic theory’s “most important” contributions: “the foundation of law on paradoxes, antinomies, and tautologies” (ibid., 1444). For example, Luhmann has interpreted the idea of the constitution as a mutual solution, of sorts, to the foun-dational self-referential paradoxes of the political and legal systems. See Luhmann (2004), 410.

153. See MacCormick (2007), 99, 177–179, 181, 183–186, 229–230, 289, 301–302.154. See ibid., 302; see also ibid., 177–178.155. Ibid., 303.156. The founders of autopoietic theory, Humberto Maturana and Francisco

Varela, introduced autopoiesis as a biological concept. See their Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living (1980).

157. Another prominent thinker who significantly incorporates autopoietic concepts—while, again, relativizing their place—is the social theorist Bob Jessop. See Jessop (2002).

158. Habermas (1996), 381.159. Ibid., 367.160. See Baxter (1998), 2014–2016.161. See Luhmann (1992), 1433.

5. after between facts and norms1. Rawls (2005), xvi.2. Ibid., 13.3. See, for example, ibid., 205, 224–225, 311. As specific examples of nonreli-

gious comprehensive doctrines, Rawls mentions utilitarianism and the “reason-able liberalism[] of Kant.” See ibid., 13, 37, 135 n3, 169–171.

4. Ibid., 12.5. Ibid., xxx, 10, 12, 144.6. See, for example, ibid., 12.7. Ibid., 144.8. For Rawls’s account of an “overlapping consensus,” see especially ibid.,

133–172.9. Ibid., 162.10. Rawls defines these as (1) principles specifying “the general structure of gov-

ernment and the political process,” including the various legislative, executive, and judicial powers, together with “the scope of majority rule”; (2) “equal basic rights and liberties of citizenship,” such as “the right to vote and to participate in politics, liberty of conscience, freedom of thought and of association, as well as the protec-tions of the rule of law” (Ibid., 227). From these Rawls distinguishes other “po-litical questions,” which may be “most” political questions—for example, “much tax legislation and many laws regulating property,” environmental protection laws, provisions for “museums and the arts.” See also ibid., 244–245, noting problems,

Page 307: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

296 Notes to Chapter 5

arguably fundamental, that he has not addressed: duties to future generations, international-law questions, health care, protection of animals and nature.

11. Ibid., 214. In nonfundamental matters, the limits of public reason do not apply. See, for example, ibid., 245.

12. Ibid., 215.13. Ibid., 218, 241, 254.14. See ibid., 247.15. For Rawls’s idea of a well-ordered society, see ibid., 35–40. The central point

is that a well-ordered society is one in which all mutually accept the same prin-ciples of justice and in which citizens comply with society’s just basic institutions.

16. Ibid., 248.17. Ibid. In his example, the dispute is over whether government aid to schools

should be provided to religious schools as well as public schools.18. Ibid., 249.19. The essay is reprinted in ibid., 440–490.20. Ibid., 464.21. Ibid., 462.22. Rawls mentions three other forms of discourse in this connection. In the

first, “declaration,” each citizen in political discussion “shows how, from our own doctrines, we can and do endorse a reasonable public political conception of jus-tice” (ibid., 465). This form of discourse seems to me only to involve providing public reasons “in due course.” The second form of discourse Rawls calls “conjec-ture.” Here a speaker explains to her partner in discussion how a political concep-tion of justice might be consistent with what she takes, or “conjectures,” to be her partner’s comprehensive doctrine (ibid., 465). The third form of discourse Rawls calls “witnessing.” The examples Rawls provides concern Quaker expression of pacifism and Catholic expression of opposition to abortion (ibid., 466 n57).

23. See Audi (1997a), 9; Rawls (2005), 444–445. Audi also suggests a distinc-tion between acting within one’s moral rights and virtuous citizenship (Audi (1997a), 33). In addition to addressing the situation of individual citizens, Audi considers also the obligations of religious associations. See ibid., 38–47 (section entitled “Separation of Church and State as Addressed to the Church”). I leave that discussion to the side here.

24. Audi’s idea is not that there must be unanimity as to all substantive po-litical matters but instead that citizens must debate together with reasons whose type is acceptable to all. He makes clear that, in his view, religious reasons are not of this type. See Audi (1997a), 16. Paul Weithman makes a similar point. See Weithman (2002), 166–167.

25. See Audi (1997a), 16–17. Nicholas Wolterstorff questions the principle be-hind Rawls’s more religion-friendly conception. See Wolterstorff (1997b), 106. Paul Weithman suggests that the boundary between basic issues and other politi-cal issues is “hazy,” but he grants Rawls the distinction “for the sake of argument” (Weithman (2002), 187). For his part, Habermas questions the significance of the distinction: “Rawls confines the proviso to key issues affecting ‘constitutional es-sentials’; I consider this reservation unrealistic in the case of modern legal systems

Page 308: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

297 Notes to Chapter 5

in which basic rights directly affect concrete legislation and adjudication, so that virtually any controversial legal issue can be heightened into an issue of principle” (Habermas (2008g), 123 n18).

26. Unlike Rawls, Audi seems unconcerned to limit reliance on nonreligious comprehensive doctrines.

27. Audi (1997a), 25.28. Ibid., 26. Audi suggests a test for when a reason is secular: “We should con-

sider whether it would be taken to be secular by a reflective person who sincerely and comprehendingly claims to be non-religious and considers it carefully” (ibid., 48).

29. Ibid., 53. See also ibid., 35.30. Rawls (2005), 465.31. Audi (1997a), 25.32. Audi (1997b), 123, 140.33. Ibid., 124.34. Audi (1997a), 54.35. See Weithman (2002), 132.36. Ibid., 167.37. Ibid., 206.38. See Chapter Two in ibid., entitled “Religion’s Role in Promoting Democracy.”39. Weithman uses the term church to refer also to mosques and synagogues

but not to “secondary institutional bearers like religious orders and religious schools” (ibid., 37).

40. Ibid., 14; see also ibid., 76.41. Ibid., 49.42. Ibid., 42–43, 49–50, 76.43. Ibid., 45–47, 138–139.44. Ibid., 139–140.45. See ibid., 85–90.46. Ibid., 50–52, 56–58. He notes particularly Catholic advocacy during the

Reagan presidency.47. Ibid., 53.48. Ibid., 55–56, 81.49. Ibid., 58–59.50. Ibid., 56, 60–61.51. Ibid., 61; see also ibid., 52.52. Ibid., 5.53. Ibid., 81; see also ibid., 54, 81, 141.54. Ibid., 3.55. See ibid., 153–164.56. Wolterstorff (1997b), 67.57. Ibid., 111–112.58. Ibid., 116–118.59. Ibid., 74–75.60. Ibid., 77.61. Ibid., 79–80.62. Ibid., 106, 108.

Page 309: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

298 Notes to Chapter 5

63. Ibid., 99.64. Ibid., 108; see also ibid., 106.65. Ibid., 109.66. Ibid., 110–112; Wolterstorff (1997a), 158. Wolterstorff acknowledges that for

reasons of persuasion a religious person might be wise to offer secular reasons in political discussion. “But that,” he says, “is a requirement of strategy, not a re-quirement embodied in the ethic of the citizen in a liberal democracy” (Ibid., 164).

67. Wolterstorff (1997b), 105.68. Habermas (2008g), 147; see also ibid., 119.69. Ibid., 123, 124.70. Ibid., 119.71. Ibid., 125 and n24. 72. Ibid., 126; see also ibid., 127–128 (quoting Wolterstorff).73. Ibid., 140. In Between Facts and Norms, Habermas described postmetaphys-

ical thinking as thinking that “avoids taking sides in the context of competing forms of life and worldviews” (Habermas (1996), 60).

74. Habermas (2008g), 140.75. See, for example, Habermas (2008g), 111; Habermas (2009c), 59.76. Habermas (2009i), 74.77. See ibid., 71, 73.78. Ibid., 74.79. Habermas (2008g), 139.80. Ibid., 75–76.81. Habermas (2008g), 140; see also ibid., 142.82. Habermas (2008g), 114, 131.83. See ibid., 111, 143.84. See ibid., 124 (referring to the contribution of religious thinking to the

American civil rights movement and to the socialist movement); ibid., 131. In ad-dition to the four positions described in text, Habermas argues that religious dis-agreement “must be articulated in public discourses lest it foster mute hostility and breed violence” (Habermas (2008b), 240).

85. Habermas (2009i), 77.86. Habermas (2008g), 131.87. Habermas (2009i), 64. Writing in 2005, Lincoln Dahlberg defends

Habermas against the charge by “difference democrats” that Habermas’s idea of public-sphere deliberation does not accommodate “ ‘aesthetic-affective’ forms of discourse” (Dahlberg (2005), 129). The writings on religion I am considering here appeared in 2005 and later; they lend further support to Dahlberg’s argument.

88. Rawls (2005), 462.89. See Habermas (2008h), 262–263. Although Habermas does not refer ex-

plicitly to Rawls here, such a reference is unmistakable: his comparison invokes “the secularized citizen with light metaphysical baggage who can accept a morally ‘freestanding’ or autonomous justification of democracy and human rights.”

90. Wolterstorff (1997b), 105.91. Habermas (2008g), 136.92. Habermas (2008c), 283.

Page 310: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

299 Notes to Chapter 5

93. Ibid., 286.94. Here Habermas parts way with Wolterstorff and perhaps with Weithman.

See Habermas (2008g), 132–134. For Wolterstorff ’s views, see Wolterstorff (1997b), 116–118. Erroneously in my view, Wolterstorff thinks that reliance on personal re-ligious views is an issue only for legislators. Judges and executive branch officials, he reasons, are bound to apply the community’s law, not make it.

95. Habermas (2008g), 130. The distance Habermas has traveled from his thinking in his debate with Rawls is suggested by a reading of Bohman (2004). In that essay, James Bohman suggests that Habermas, even as he criticized Rawls’s position, then held “a standard liberal conception of the limits of toleration” (Ibid., 776 n8).

96. Habermas (2008g), 137.97. Habermas (2008e), 113.98. Habermas (2008h), 261–262. See also Habermas (2009i), 75: “Religious

citizens and communities must do more than merely conform to the constitu-tional order in a superficial way. They must appropriate the secular legitimation of constitutional principles under the premises of their own faith.” See further Habermas (2008c), 308; Habermas (2008g), 112.

99. Habermas (2009i), 75.100. For Rawls’s notion of a modus vivendi, see, for example, Rawls (2001), 192:

Here I use the phrase “modus vivendi” in the usual way, as may be illustrated by a treaty between two states whose national interests put them at odds. In negotiating a treaty, each state would be wise and prudent to make sure that the treaty is drawn up in such a way that it is public knowledge that it is not advantageous for either state to violate it. Both states, however, are ready to pursue their goals at the expense of the other, and should conditions change they may do so.

101. See Habermas (2008g), 130; Habermas (2009i), 76.102. See Habermas (2008h), 263; Habermas (2008c), 310.103. Habermas (2008c), 310.104. Habermas (2008h), 264.105. See ibid., 263; see also Habermas (2008g), 138–139.106. Habermas (2008c), 310.107. Ibid.; see also Habermas (2008g), 131–132.108. See Lafont (2009), 146.109. Ibid., 131.110. Habermas (2008g), 137.111. Lafont (2009), 147 n24.112. To say that religious citizens should be free to question the authority of

science, especially the authority of particular scientific claims, does not mean that a polity may not decide the issue against them—by, for example, deciding that evolution and not creationism should be taught in science classrooms.

113. Lafont (2009), 141 (emphasis deleted); ibid., 128.114. Habermas (2008g), 139.115. Lafont (2009), 141.

Page 311: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

300 Notes to Chapter 5

116. Ibid., 132.117. Ibid., 142.118. I assume that Lafont’s expression “reasons generally acceptable to demo-

cratic citizens” amounts to the same thing as Rawls’s “public reasons.” She de-scribes “generally acceptable” reasons as ones “based on basic democratic principles of freedom and equality” (ibid., 142).

119. Ibid. (emphasis added).120. Ibid., 138. Further, Lafont criticizes, as inconsistent with deliberative de-

mocracy, the idea that religious citizens have “a right to ‘mono-glot’ political ad-vocacy” (ibid.). This would indicate that, while citizens may initially frame their arguments in purely religious terms, they must switch over to a different “lan-guage” when presented with objections based on public reasons.

If this interpretation is right, then it addresses also a gap in Lafont’s analy-sis. Because her focus is on the obligation of citizens who debate in the informal public sphere, she does not (unlike Rawls and Habermas) clearly address the posi-tion of officials. At one point, it would seem that she allows public officials, too, the right to present purely religious arguments. She seems to criticize Habermas for excluding religious reasons “beyond the institutional threshold”—that is, at the stage of policy formation, she says, “when it matters most” (ibid., 135). While I remain uncertain of her position, I think the preceding is only a suggestion of inconsistency in Habermas: He worries about those ordinary citizens who cannot provide secular translations for their religious views in the informal public sphere, but he has no similar concern for the plight of public officials.

121. Ibid., 128–129.122. Weithman asks, rhetorically: “Why think that adequately informed, ratio-

nal adults cannot see the reason-giving force of religious reasons or would not take them as sufficient reasons for action?” (Weithman (2002), 167).

123. Ibid., 206.124. Kymlicka (1995), 34–35.125. Ibid., 46–47, 128–129.126. Ibid., 27–29.127. Ibid., 31.128. Ibid., 133–134, 146–147.129. See ibid., 132.130. See Thornburg v. Gingles, 478 U.S. 30, 50–51 (1986). 131. Section 2(b) of the Voting Rights Act of 1965, codified at 42 U.S.C.

§1973(b).132. Miller v. Johnson, 515 U.S. 900 (1995). Such a use of race, the Court held,

is unconstitutional unless necessary to accomplish a compelling governmental purpose—the so-called strict scrutiny standard. The original case in this line, cited by Kymlicka, was Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630 (1993).

133. Kymlicka (1995), 108.134. Ibid., 7.135. Ibid., 40–41.136. Ibid., 41, 161, 170.137. On the Amish, see ibid., 41, 161, 170. On the Hutterites, see ibid., 120, 161, 177.

Page 312: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

301 Notes to Chapter 5

138. Ibid., 10–12.139. Ibid., 96–99.140. For example, Barry entitles the first two sections “Losing Our Way” and

“Flight from Enlightenment.”141. Barry (2001), 12.142. Ibid., 233–234 (quoting Nathan Glazer, We Are All Multiculturalists Now).143. Ibid., 33, 35.144. Ibid., 44.145. Ibid., 47–48.146. Ibid., 49.147. Ibid.148. Ibid., 57. According to Barry, Muslim norms for women’s public dress

“vary enormously” (ibid).149. Ibid., 59.150. Ibid., 62. Barry thinks the number of pragmatically required exemptions

likely is small because, to support that approach, the rule must be important enough to justify generally following it but “not so important as to preclude al-lowing exceptions to it.” We must be dealing with, in other words, “cases in which uniformity is a value but not a great enough one to override the case for exemp-tions” (ibid.). I don’t see how Barry can be so confident that there aren’t many rules of this kind.

151. Yoder v. Wisconsin, 406 U.S. 205, 209 (1971).152. On free exercise, see Yoder, 406 U.S. at 230–231; on the parental right to

direct the upbringing of children, see ibid., 232.153. Ibid., 202–203.154. Ibid., 205, 211.155. Ibid., 242.156. Ibid., 215–216.157. The term politics of difference is Iris Young’s, and Barry reserves for her his

most biting criticism. See Barry (2001), 69–70, 95 (comparing her views to those of the Dodo in Alice and Wonderland), 267–273. On Barry’s contrast between the politics of multiculturalism and the politics of redistribution, see ibid., 8.

158. Ibid., 315.159. Ibid., 325–326.160. For a similar judgment, see Benhabib (2002), 112–114.161. Barry (2001), 7.162. Habermas (2009i), 204 n22 (citing Barry (2001)).163. See Chapter 2, section 2.2.164. Habermas (2009i), 71.165. See ibid., 204 n22.166. Habermas (1998j), 221.167. Habermas (2008c), 297.168. Habermas refers to “quotas for nonwhites” that might lead whites to “see

themselves as disadvantaged.” While American defenders of affirmative action of course distinguish systems they support from “quotas,” I can’t be sure that Haber-mas would make that distinction as well.

Page 313: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

302 Notes to Chapter 5

169. See Habermas (2008c), 297.170. See ibid., 297, 298, 302–303. In the same collection of essays, however,

Habermas writes: “Modern law is constructed out of individual or ‘subjective’ rights that guarantee individual persons carefully circumscribed spaces of free-dom. . . . ” (Habermas (2008a), 90).

171. At one point Habermas presents cultural rights on the model of ordi-nary individual rights (“subjective rights,” in German terminology) (Habermas (2008h), 269).

172. See Habermas (2008c), 295.173. See Habermas (2008h), 267.174. See Habermas (2008c), 293–294.175. See ibid., 294–295: “One misses the point of cultural rights by incorporat-

ing them into an extended model of the welfare state. Unlike social rights, cultural rights must be justified in terms of their role in facilitating the equal inclusion of all citizens.”

176. Ibid., 293.177. Ibid. But compare Habermas’s contrary account—in an essay that appears

in the same volume—cited above in note 171.178. Ibid., 296; see also ibid., 297.179. Ibid., 293. See also Habermas (2008h), 266 (describing the French head-

scarf case as a “secularist” violation of neutrality).180. Habermas (2008c), 293.181. Habermas (2008h), 266. This would seem to be a group or collective right.182. Ibid., 264.183. See ibid., 265, and the longer list in footnote 22 on the same page.184. Habermas (2008c), 297.185. Ibid., 298.186. Ibid.187. Kymlicka (1995), 7.188. Habermas (2008c), 299.189. Ibid., 298.190. Yoder, 408 U.S., 233.191. Habermas (2008c), 299.192. Ibid., 302.193. Ibid., 302–303.194. For the charge against Kymlicka, see Benhabib (2002), 67–68.195. Ibid., ix.196. Ibid., 2–3.197. Ibid., 8.198. Ibid., 106. Benhabib speaks of Habermas’s “dual-track” approach. See

ibid., xii, 20–21, 106.199. See ibid., 36, 127; see also Habermas (2009i), 70 (insisting on “the

difference-sensitive inclusion of foreign minority cultures” and “the inclusion of minorities in civil society”).

200. Habermas (2008h), 270. 201. Ibid.

Page 314: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

303 Notes to Chapter 5

202. Ibid., 265–266.203. Müller (2007), 26. See Habermas (1989).204. Müller (2007), 1–2.205. Ibid., 5, 40.206. Ibid., 32.207. Ibid., 42. Müller defines “supplements of particularity” as the “constel-

lation of subsidiary concepts which have allowed the universalist morality at the center of constitutional patriotism to be embedded within a (necessarily) particu-lar political culture” (ibid.).

208. See ibid., 21–24, 33–34, 36–37.209. Ibid., 12. 210. Ibid., 47.211. Ibid., 48; see also ibid., 67–68.212. Ibid., 67–68.213. Ibid., 55. In a similar formulation, the object of attachment is found in

“citizens conceiving each other as free and equal” and thereby “find[ing] fair terms of political cooperation that they can justify to each other.”

214. Ibid., 54.215. Michelman (2001), 254.216. Ibid.217. Müller (2007), 55–56.218. See Michelman (2001), 266.219. For Müller’s statement of the problem, see Müller (2007), 54: “It is per-

fectly reasonable for citizens to disagree even about some constitutional essentials (and not just their application, for instance). Such disagreement will be likely, not least since a general justification, on the one hand, and application, on the other, can almost always not be properly separated.”

220. See Cronin (2006), 358–359 (attributing the term to Michelman and not-ing that the problem is “potentially devastating” to Habermas’s project).

Michelman raises against Habermas a further difficulty: the foundational problem of a constitutional democracy. If ordinary outcomes are justified by pro-cedure, what justifies the basic procedures themselves? See Michelman (1996), 308–309. We cannot say that the basic procedures are justified by the idea of democracy because those procedures are what define the notion of democracy. The problem here is essentially a special case of the problem (some would say para-dox) at the foundation of any legal system. H. L. A. Hart’s “rule of recognition,” for example, is what grounds the validity of all other rules, primary or secondary. See Hart (1994), 100–108. But as the rule that defines the meaning of legal valid-ity, Hart observes, the rule of recognition cannot itself be legally valid (or invalid). Hart speaks of its “acceptance” rather than its validity. See ibid., 108–110.

Michelman does not, however, argue that Habermas’s idea of constitutional patriotism is designed to address this regress problem. For an argument that con-stitutional patriotism cannot serve that task, see Olson (2007).

221. Habermas (2003), 192.222. Michelman (2001), 269.223. See ibid., 270–271.

Page 315: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

304 Notes to Chapter 5

224. Müller (2007), 55–57.225. Habermas (2003b), 192.226. Ibid., 193. Cécile Laborde helpfully distinguishes between critical and

neutralist constitutional patriotism. The former “concentrate[s] on the radical po-tential of constitutional patriotism as a subversive force intent on ‘de-centring’ and destabilizing homogeneous, hegemonic national identities.” Neutralist constitu-tional patriots, by contrast, focus on “the reconciliation of social inclusion and political legitimacy” (Laborde (2002), 595–596).

227. Habermas (2003b), 192.228. See section 3.2.2 for Habermas’s earlier response to Michelman.229. Müller (2007), 59.230. Ibid., 59–60.231. Habermas (2008e), 106; see also Habermas (1995a), 264.232. See de Grieff (2002), 430–432.233. Accord McCormick (2007), 216.234. See Kreide (2009), 98–99: “Habermas has become interested in the key

question about how the comprehensive proposal he developed in his 1992 treatise Between Facts and Norms can be applied to political relations above the level of the nation-state.”

235. Each of the books Habermas has published since Between Facts and Norms is a collection of essays.

236. Habermas (2001c), 66; Habermas (2009a), 187.237. Habermas infers that the process of economic globalization therefore is

not beyond political control. See Habermas (2006c), 93. In my view, Habermas’s conclusion does not necessarily follow. That globalization resulted (in part) from political decisions does not mean that now, unleashed, it will be susceptible of ef-fective political control.

238. Habermas (2001c), 66.239. See ibid., 77; Habermas (2006d), 75, 77.240. Habermas (1998e), 174; see also Habermas (2001c), 78.241. Habermas (1998a), 157.242. Ibid., 157–158.243. Ibid., 66–68.244. Habermas (2009e), 91–93.245. See Habermas (2009a).246. Habermas (2001c), 70. Pablo de Grieff dubs this argument for transna-

tional and/or supranational institutions “the argument from the weakness of the nation-state.” See de Grieff (2002), 427–429.

247. Habermas (2006e), 42; Habermas (2009e), 88.248. Habermas (2006h), 21.249. Habermas (2006m), 6.250. Habermas (2008d), 326–327.251. Ibid., 330.252. Habermas (2009c), 112.253. Habermas (2008d), 333. Pablo de Grieff dubs this argument “the argument

from the democratic deficit of nationalism.” To the considerations mentioned in

Page 316: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

305 Notes to Chapter 5

text, he adds that “the twentieth century has manifested grotesquely the dangers of clinging to” the connection between nationalism and democracy (de Grieff (2002), 429–432).

254. Habermas (2006i), 109.255. For a still helpful overview of normative political issues facing the EU, see

Føllesdal (2005).256. See Habermas (2006e), 46; Habermas (2006j), 76; Habermas (2006d), 87;

see generally Habermas (2001d).257. Habermas (2001d), 11.258. Habermas (2001c), 76.259. Habermas (2001d), 19. Perhaps a more serious obstacle than the cultural

nonidentity difficulty concerns the different political and legal histories of core EU countries and the newer (mostly Eastern) additions. See Lupel (2005), 124. Habermas addresses this problem with his most recent criticisms of the “convoy” model of European integration. I discuss these criticisms later in this section.

260. See Habermas (1998g); Habermas (1998a), 160; Habermas (2006d), 87.261. Habermas (1998a), 159. In the republican tradition, Habermas says, “ ‘peo-

ple’ and ‘nation’ are interchangeable concepts for a citizenry that is co-original with the political community” (Habermas (1998g), 133).

262. See Habermas (2006c), 100.263. Habermas (2008d), 334.264. Habermas (2001c), 84.265. Habermas (2006c), 101.266. Habermas (1998a), 161.267. English-language essays advocating a European constitution include

Habermas (1998a) and Habermas (2006c).268. Both countries received “opt outs” from provisions that make the EU

Charter of Fundamental Rights binding and effective against contrary domestic law. See Protocol on the Application of the Charter of Fundamental Rights to Poland and to the United Kingdom.

269. There were court tests in Germany and the Czech Republic.270. For his proposal concerning the Constitution, see Habermas (2006c)

(published in German in 2001). The process that would produce genuine EU de-mocracy “would begin with a referendum on the constitution, which would touch off a large-scale debate throughout Europe.”

271. Habermas (2009e), 103.272. Habermas (2009b), 58.273. Habermas (2009e), 103. The American experience might lend support to

this supposition. The American Constitution became effective when nine of the thirteen colonies ratified, though binding only on those who ratified. See U.S. Constitution, Article VII. Of course eventually all thirteen colonies ratified, al-though the last two were induced by the proposal of a Bill of Rights.

274. Ibid., 80–81. By “national exclusion clauses,” Habermas presumably means the various opt-outs included for member states. Some cover criminal law, and others allow the United Kingdom and Poland to opt out of provisions that would make the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights control contrary domestic law.

Page 317: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

306 Notes to Chapter 5

275. See Article 9(c) of the Treaty of Lisbon; Habermas (2009e), 79.276. See Protocol on the Role of National Parliaments in the European Union.277. Habermas (2009e), 79.278. Habermas (2006j), 71; Habermas (2006c), 101; Habermas (1998b), 106;

Habermas (1998a), 160. In Habermas’s discussion of what would be required to establish a “European public sphere,” he begins to respond to the criticisms Nancy Fraser leveled against his earlier accounts in Structural Transformation of the Pub-lic Sphere (originally published in 1962) and Between Facts and Norms (originally published in 1992): that Habermas’s idea of the public sphere is “Westphalian” in presupposing an exclusively nation-state framework. See Fraser (2007), 9–14.

279. Habermas (2006i), 101; Habermas (1998a), 156.280. Habermas (2006l), 63; Habermas (2001c), 102–103.281. Habermas (2001c), 103.282. Habermas (2006m), 8; Habermas (2006d), 87; Habermas (2006c), 104;

Habermas (2001c), 103.283. Habermas (2006d), 88.284. See Habermas (2001c), 99.285. Habermas (2006j), 81.286. Habermas (2006d), 87.287. Habermas (2006c), 102.288. Habermas (2009g), 182.289. Ibid., 183.290. Habermas (1999), 58. Matthias Kumm maintains that institutional fea-

tures of the European Parliament contribute to the underdevelopment of a Euro-pean party system. It is “not the central agenda setter in Europe,” he says; it is “an editor, not the author, of European laws” (Kumm (2008)), 129).

291. The essay was originally published in 2006 (see Habermas (2006k)); a revised and expanded version is included in his collection Europe: The Faltering Project (see Habermas, (2009g)). That collection was published in German in No-vember 2007. Habermas describes the essay as one “particularly close to my heart” (Habermas (2009d), vii).

292. Habermas (2009g), 181.293. Without comment on the change of term, Habermas reads the present

schema, with “deliberative” in the place of “procedural,” back into Between Facts and Norms. See ibid., 143.

294. Ibid., 143.295. Habermas (2009f), 135.296. Habermas (2009g), 140.297. Ibid., 159.298. Ibid., 143, 156.299. Ibid., 146.300. Ibid., 159–160.301. Ibid., 165, 171.302. Ibid., 162.303. Ibid., 166.

Page 318: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

307 Notes to Chapter 5

304. See ibid., 166, Figure 9.2 (“Public Sphere: Inputs and Outputs”). Earlier in the essay, Habermas noted that the “representatives of the functional systems” occupy a strategic position as against the state. The state provides “subsidies and public infrastructure for various functional subsystems, such as industry and the labor market, health care, traffic, energy, research and development, education, etc.” And “representatives” of these subsystems are in a position to extract benefits by asserting “what they present as ‘functional imperatives.’ ” “Pressure groups,” he says, “can employ the threat of the ‘malfunction’ of a particular system, for instance redundancies, capital flight, or growth in inflation, a breakdown in traffic, energy shortages, a shortfall of skilled workers, a brain drain, and so on” (Ibid., 163).

305. Ibid., 164.306. Ibid., 154.307. Ibid., 156.308. This typology does not mention the ideas of communicative or adminis-

trative power, on which he relied so heavily in Between Facts and Norms, but I do not read him as renouncing those concepts.

309. Habermas (2009g), 167–168.310. Ibid., 168.311. Ibid., 168–169.312. Ibid., 169. Habermas plays with systems-theoretical concepts in referring

to “a self-regulating media system” and “its social environments.” But he does not further develop the systems-theoretical frame.

313. Ibid., 171–172. Habermas presents this requirement as a condition for “con-sidered public opinions.” (Recall that he develops a normative and not a merely descriptive notion of public opinion. See section 4.2.3.) I think it makes sense to understand the requirement as a normative limit on media power.

314. Ibid., 175.315. Ibid., 176–177.316. Ibid., 177.317. Ibid., 177.318. Ibid., 156–157.319. Ibid., 154.320. See Habermas (1998b) [1996], 121: “The publics produced by the internet

remain closed off from one another like global villages.” 321. Habermas (2009g), 157.322. Ibid., 157–158.323. For fuller treatments of Habermas or deliberative democracy and the In-

ternet, see Dahlberg (2007); Froomkin (2003); Gimmler (2001).324. See Neblo (2008).325. See Habermas (2009g), 150–151.326. See www.tomorrowseurope.eu/ (last visited January 10, 2010). 327. See Habermas (2009g), 150 (discussing the British Columbia’s Citizen’s

Assembly, in which 160 randomly selected citizens deliberated to propose a new voting system, albeit one that was defeated in a popular referendum), ibid., 151–152 (discussing the study by Wolfgang van den Daele, whose moderated discussion groups operated in ways that would support deliberative democratic theory).

Page 319: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

308 Notes to Chapter 5

328. See, most recently, Sunstein (2009).329. See, for example, Ackerman’s and Fishkin’s proposal for a “National De-

liberation Day” (Ackerman and Fishkin (2005)).330. Habermas (2009g), 167 (emphasis in the original).331. Writing in 2004, before Habermas’s recent discussion of the issue, Joseph

Staats argues that Habermas “fails to capture fully the way in which corporate power,” as “expressed through the mass media,” “can corrupt the democratic pro-cess” (Staats (2004), 585). My assessment of Habermas’s treatment of the issue is more positive than Staats’s, and I think the recent work is more resistant still to Staats’s criticism.

332. In this sense, despite Habermas’s attempt to consider what a “European public sphere” would entail, his analysis of the public sphere remains in large part (to borrow Nancy Fraser’s term) “Westphalian.” See Fraser (2007), 9–15.

333. Habermas (2006b), 141.334. Habermas (2006m), 7.335. Habermas (2006b), 140, 141, 176; Habermas (2006d), 87.336. Habermas (2006b), 141; see also Habermas (1999), 58: “A federal Euro-

pean state [if established] will . . . be of a different calibre than national federal states; it cannot simply copy their legitimation processes.”

337. Habermas (2008d), 333.338. This is the conclusion of Kumm (2008), 119.339. James Bohman draws just this conclusion: While the idea of democracy

implies self-determination, it “does not, however, require the more specific con-ception of self-determination that has guided much of democratic theory since the eighteenth century—self-legislation in a bounded political community—that is thoroughly imbricated with democracy’s current difficulties” (Bohman (2007), 3).

340. See McCormick (2007), 267. Matthias Kumm argues that this conclusion is much too quick. See Kumm (2008), 135–136.

341. Ibid., 268.342. Ibid., 271.343. See ibid., 23.344. See Cohen and Sabel (1997), 347.345. See McCormick (2007), 268.346. Habermas (1996), 191–192.347. See Joerges (1999), 311; Weiler (1999), 98; Weiler (1999b), 343; McCormick

(2007), 285–286.348. See McCormick (2007), 251; Joerges and Neyer (1997), 285.349. See, for example, Joerges (1999), 311; Joerges and Neyer (1997), 285.350. See Joerges (2002), 150–151; Joerges (1999), 321; see also Weiler (1999b), 344.351. See McCormick (2007), 274 (“Many comitology proponents exhibit some

serious myopia when it comes to asymmetries of power”). 352. See, for example, Habermas (2009c), 113 (referring, at the “transnational

level,” to “expert committees”).353. Repeatedly Habermas distinguishes between the constitutionalization

of international law and the establishment of a world state. See, for example,

Page 320: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

309 Notes to Chapter 5

Habermas (2008d), 316–317, 333–334; Habermas (2006b), 123, 132, 136; Habermas (2006g), 26; Habermas (2001a), 56; Habermas (2001c), 105.

354. Habermas (1998c). The accuracy of Habermas’s reading of Kant is not my present concern; I’m interested only in Habermas’s diagnosis of the present and prescriptions for the future. For a critique of “the standard view of Kant’s position on international relations”—a view the author attributes to Habermas as well as Rawls—see Kleingeld (2004).

355. Habermas (1998e), 165.356. Ibid., 168–169.357. Ibid., 169–171.358. Ibid., 174.359. Ibid., 176–177.360. Ibid., 180; see also Habermas (2006h), 20; Habermas (2006i), 107.361. Habermas (1998e), 179–180.362. Ibid. Habermas’s position seems to be that the United Nations should

have “command” of military forces for peacekeeping operations. See ibid., 187–188.363. Ibid., 181.364. See especially Habermas (2008d) and Habermas (2006b).365. Habermas (1998e), 187.366. Ibid., 187.367. Writing of Kant’s discussion of a possible world republic, Habermas seems

to share “Kant’s fear that the normalizing pressure exerted by the ‘soulless despo-tism’ of a global ‘state of nations’ would rob particular nations of their cultural specificity and identity” (Habermas, (2008d), 315; see also Habermas (2006b), 128).

368. Habermas (2008d), 323.369. Thomas Giegerich notes that Habermas’s “use of the term ‘constitution’

as such necessarily evokes state analogies and is obviously intended to do so” (Giegerich (2009), 42).

370. Habermas (2006b), 132.371. Habermas notes, with apparent approval, a report by the U.N. High Level

Panel that would extend the peacekeeping and security function to:

sources of danger beyond classical interstate conflicts to include not only civil war and internal conflicts, international terrorism, the possession of weapons of mass destruction, and transnational organized crime; with an eye to the developing countries, it expands this catalogue of sources of danger to cover the mass deprivation of the population through poverty and disease, social marginalization, and environmental degradation. (Habermas (2008d), 337).

372. See, for example, Habermas (2006b), 136. See also Habermas (2008d), 140.373. Habermas (2006b), 134. Tinnevelt and Mertens maintain that this argu-

ment does not establish that “no form of world state is needed.” They argue that a “minimal world state” would be required by a “theory of global democracy.” In particular, they argue that the supranational organization would have to pursue functions other than peacekeeping and backup protection of basic human rights (Tinnevelt and Mertens (2009), 73, 77). These additional functions Habermas would assign to the transnational bargaining system.

Page 321: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

310 Notes to Chapter 5

374. Habermas suggests that besides the United States, China, India, and Rus-sia might potentially be sufficiently powerful “global players” to be outside such regimes. See Habermas (2009c), 114.

375. Habermas (2008d), 333.376. A more comprehensive list of problems to be addressed at either the trans-

national or supranational level suggests governance “in the fields of energy, envi-ronment, finance, and trade policy; of labor relations; of organized crime; of arms trafficking; of combating epidemics, and so on” (Habermas (2009c), 109).

377. Habermas (2006d), 83.378. Habermas (2008d), 325.379. Ibid., 327. Regina Kreide rightly cautions that “a cosmopolitan, multi-

layered system cannot reproduce the civic solidarity or welfare-state policies of the European Union” (Kreide (2009), 101).

380. Habermas (2008d), 333.381. Ibid., 322–323; see also Habermas (2006b), 141.382. Habermas (2006b), 142.383. See section 2.4.3.384. Habermas (2008d), 347.385. Habermas (2006b), 141.386. Ibid., 143.387. Habermas (2009c), 119.388. Ibid., 120.389. Ibid., 122.390. Ibid., 123.391. Ibid., 111.392. Ibid., 125.393. Ibid., 126–128.

Page 322: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography

Ackerman, Bruce, and Fishkin, James S. (2005). Deliberation Day.Alexander, Jeffrey C. (1983). Theoretical Logic in Sociology, Volume IV.Alexy, Robert. (1989) [1978]. A Theory of Legal Argumentation: The Theory of Ra-

tional Discourse as a Theory of Legal Argumentation, trans. Ruth Adler and Neil MacCormick.

———. (1993). Justification and Application of Norms, Ratio Juris 6:157–170.———. (1994). Basic Rights and Democracy in Jürgen Habermas’s Procedural Para-

digm of the Law, Ratio Juris 7:227.———. (1998). Jürgen Habermas’s Theory of Legal Discourse. In Rosenfeld and

Arato (1998), 226–233.———. (2002) [1986]. A Theory of Constitutional Rights, trans. Julian Rivers.———. (2003). Constitutional Rights, Balancing, and Rationality, Ratio Juris 16:131.Arato, Andrew. (1998). Procedural Law and Civil Society: Interpreting the Radi-

cal Democratic Paradigm. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 26–36.Aronson, Johannes. (1991) [1986]. Modernity as Project and Field of Tension. In

Honneth and Joas (1991), 181–213.Audi, Robert. (1997a). Liberal Democracy and the Place of Religion in Politics. In

Audi and Wolterstorff (1997), 1–66.———. (1997b). Wolterstorff on Religion, Politics, and the Liberal State. In Audi

and Wolterstorff (1997), 121–144.Audi, Robert, and Wolterstorff, Nicholas. (1997). Religion in the Public Square: The

Place of Religious Convictions in Public Debate.Austin, J. L. (1962). How to Do Things with Words.Barry, Brian. (2001). Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique of

Multiculturalism.Baxter, Hugh. (1987). System and Lifeworld in Habermas’s Theory of Communica-

tive Action, Theory and Society 16:39–86.———. (1998). Autopoiesis and the Relative Autonomy of Law, Cardozo Law Review

19:1987–2090.

Page 323: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 312

———. (2002). Habermas’s Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy,” Buffalo Law Review 50: 205–340.

———. (2002). “System and Lifeworld in Habermas’s Theory of Law,” Cardozo Law Review 23: 473–615.

Benhabib, Seyla. (2002). The Claims of Culture: Equality and Diversity in the Global Era.

Berger, Johannes. (1991) [1986]. The Linguistification of the Sacred and the Delin-guistification of the Economy. In Joas and Honneth (1991), 164–180.

Bilchitz, David. (2007). Poverty and Fundamental Rights: The Justification and En-forcement of Socio-Economic Rights.

Bohman, James. (1994). Complexity, Pluralism, and the Constitutional State: On Habermas’s Faktizität und Geltung, Law & Society Review 28:897–930.

———. (1998). The Coming of Age of Deliberative Democracy, The Journal of Politi-cal Philosophy, 6:400–425.

———. (2004). Deliberative Toleration, Political Theory 31:757–779.———. (2007). Democracy across Borders: From Demos to Demoi.Brest, Paul. (1975). The Conscientious Legislator’s Guide to Constitutional Inter-

pretation, Stanford Law Review 27:585–602.Buckley, Walter. (1967). Sociology and Modern Systems Theory.Cohen, Joshua. (1999). Reflections on Habermas on Democracy, Ratio Juris

12:385–416.———. (2003). Sovereignty and Solidarity: EU and US. In Jonathan Zeitlin and

David M. Trubek, eds., Governing Work and Welfare in a New Economy: Euro-pean and American Experiments, 345–375.

Cohen, Joshua, and Sabel, Charles. (1997). Directly-Deliberative Polyarchy, Euro-pean Law Journal 3:313–342.

Cooke, Maeve. (1994). Language and Reason: A Study of Habermas’s Pragmatics.Cover, Robert M. (1983). Nomos and Narrative, Harvard Law Review 97:4–68.Cronin, Ciaran. (2006). On the Possibility of a Democratic Founding: Habermas

and Michelman in Dialogue, Ratio Juris 19:343–69.Culler, Jonathan. (1985). Communicative Competence and Normative Force, New

German Critique 35:133.Dahlberg, Lincoln. (2005). The Habermasian Public Sphere: Taking Difference

Seriously? Theory and Society, 34:111–136.———. (2007). Rethinking the Fragmentation of the Cyberpublic: From Consen-

sus to Contestation, New Media Society 9:827.de Grieff, Pablo. (2002). Habermas on Nationalism and Cosmopolitanism, Ratio

Juris 15:418–438.D’Entrèves, Maurizio Passerin, and Benhabib, Seyla. (1997). Habermas and the

Unfinished Project of Modernity: Critical Essays on the Philosophical Discourse of Modernity.

Dworkin, Ronald. (1977). Taking Rights Seriously.———. (1986). Law’s Empire.———. (1996). Freedom’s Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution.———. (2006a). Is Democracy Possible Here? Principles for a New Political Debate.———. (2006b). Justice in Robes.

Page 324: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 313

———. (2010). The “Devastating” Decision, New York Review of Books 57:3. Available online at www.nybooks.com/articles/23678.

Easton, David. (1965). A Systems Analysis of Political Life.Edgar, Andrew. (2005). The Philosophy of Habermas.Elster, Jon. (1999–2000). Arguing and Bargaining in Two Constituent Assem-

blies, University of Pennsylvania Constitutional Law Journal, 2:345–421.Ely, John Hart. (1980). Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review.Fararo, Thomas J. (1976). Science as a Cultural System. In Loubser (1976) (Vol. 1),

90–122.Føllesdal, Andreas. (2005). EU Legitimacy and Normative Political Theory. In

Michelle Cini and Angela K. Bourne, eds., Palgrave Advances in European Union Studies, 151–173.

Forbath, William E. (1998a). Habermas’s Constitution: A History, Guide, and Critique, Law and Social Inquiry 23:969–1016.

———. (1998b). Short Circuit: A Critique of Habermas’s Understanding of Law, Politics, and Economic Life. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 272–286.

Frank, Jerome. (1970). Law and the Modern Mind [1930].Frankenberg, Günter (1989). Down By Law: Irony, Seriousness, and Reason,

Northwestern University Law Review 83:360–397.———. (1996). Why Care? The Trouble with Social Rights, Cardozo Law Review

17:1365–1390.Fraser, Nancy (2007). Transnationalizing the Public Sphere: On the Legitimacy

and Efficacy of Public Opinion in a Post-Westphalian World, Theory, Culture, and Society 24:7–30.

Froomkin, A. Michael. (2003). [email protected]: Toward a Critical The-ory of Cyberspace, Harvard Law Review 116:751–873.

Gerth, H. H., and Mills, C. Wright. (1958) [1946]. Introduction, in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology.

Giegerich, Thomas. (2009). The Is and the Ought of International Constitution-alism: How Far Have We Come on Habermas’s Road to a “Well-Considered Constitutionalization of International Law?” German Law Journal 10:32–62.

Gimmler, Antje. (2001). Deliberative Democracy, the Public Sphere and the Inter-net, Philosophy and Social Criticism 27:21–39.

Gordon, Robert W. (1985). Autopoiesis—Questions of a Fascinated Skeptic (un-published paper proposed for the Conference on Autopoiesis in Law and Soci-ety, European Law Institute, Florence, Italy, December 12–15, 1985).

Günther, Klaus. (1993). The Sense of Appropriateness: Application Discourses in Moral-ity and Law. Trans. John Farrell [1988].

———. (1998). Communicative Freedom, Communicative Power, and Jurisgenesis. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 234–255.

Habermas, Jürgen. (1970). On Systematically Distorted Communication, Inquiry 13:205–218.

———. (1971). Knowledge and Human Interests. Trans. Jeremy J. Shapiro [1968].———. (1975). Legitimation Crisis. Trans. Thomas McCarthy [1973].———. (1977). Hannah Arendt’s Communications Concept of Power, Social Re-

search 40:3–24 [1976].

Page 325: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 314

———. (1979). What Is Universal Pragmatics? In Communication and the Evolution of Society. Trans. Thomas McCarthy, 1–68.

———. (1982). Reply to My Critics. In Habermas: Critical Debates. Eds. John B. Thompson and David Held [1980], 219–283.

———. (1984a). Erläuterungen zum Begriff des kommunikativen Handelns. In Vorstudien und Ergänzungen zur Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns [1982], 571–606.

———. (1984b). Remarks on the Concept of Communicative Action. In Seebaß and Tuomela (1985), 151–178.

———. (1984c). Theory of Communicative Action, Volume One: Reason and the Ratio-nalization of Society. Trans. Thomas McCarthy [1981].

———. (1984d), Wahrheitstheorien. In Vorstudien und Ergänzungen zur theorie des kommunikativen Handelns [1972], 127–183.

———. (1985). Reply to Skej, Inquiry 28:105–113.———. (1986a). Autonomy and Solidarity: Interviews with Jürgen Habermas. Ed. Peter

Dews.———. (1986b). Communicative Rationality and the Theories of Meaning and Ac-

tion. In Habermas (1998f), 183–214.———. (1987a). Excursus on Luhmann’s Appropriation of the Philosophy of the

Subject through Systems Theory. In The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, trans. Frederick Lawrence, 368–385.

———. (1987b). Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 2: Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason. Trans. Thomas McCarthy [1981].

———. (1988a). Actions, Speech Acts, Linguistically Mediated Interaction, and Lifeworld. In Habermas (1998f), 214–255.

———. (1988b). Law and Morality, in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 8:217–279. Ed. Sterling M. McMurrin; trans. Kenneth Baynes [1986].

———. (1988c). On the Logic of the Social Sciences. Shierry Weber Nicholsen and Jerry A. Stark, trans. [1970].

———. (1989). Jürgen Habermas, The New Conservatism: Cultural Criticism and the Historians’ Debate.

———. (1989a). The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Investigation into a Category of Bourgeois Society. Thomas Burger and Frederick Lawrence, trans. [1962].

———. (1990). Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Frederick G. Lawrence trans. [1985].

———. (1990a). Die Nacholende Revolution.———. (1991a). Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justifica-

tion. In Habermas (1991b), 43–115.———. (1991b). Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action [1982]. ———. (1991c). Reconstruction and Interpretation in the Social Sciences. In Haber-

mas (1991b), 21–42. ———. (1991d). A Reply. In Honneth and Joas, (1991) [1986], 214–264.———. (1992). Toward a Critique of Meaning. In Postmetaphysical Thinking: Philo-

sophical Essays. Trans. William Mark Hohengarten [1988], 57–87.

Page 326: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 315

———. (1993a). Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics. Trans. Ciaran P. Cronin (1993) [1991].

———. (1993b). On the Pragmatic, Ethical, and Moral Employments of Practical Reason. In Habermas (1993a) [1991], 1–18.

———. (1993c). Remarks on Discourse Ethics. In Habermas (1993a), 19–112.———. (1995a). Citizenship and National Identity: Some Reflections on the Future

of Europe. In Ronald Beiner ed., Theorizing Citizenship (1995), 225–281.———. (1995b). Reconciliation through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks on

John Rawls’s Political Liberalism, Journal of Philosophy 92:109–131.———. (1996). Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law

and Democracy. Trans. William H. Rehg [1992].———. (1997) A Berlin Republic: Writings on Germany. Peter Uwe Hohendahl,

trans. [1995].———. (1998a). Does Europe Need a Constitution? Response to Dieter Grimm. In

Habermas (1998c), 155–161.———. (1998b). The European Nation-State: On the Past and Future of Sover-

eignty and Citizenship. In Habermas (1998c), 105–127.——— (1998c) Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory. Eds. Ciaran Cronin

and Pablo DeGrieff [1996].———. (1998d). On the Internal Relation between Law and Democracy. In Haber-

mas (1998c), 253–264.———. (1998e). Kant’s Idea of Perpetual Peace: At Two Hundred Years Historical

Remove. In Habermas (1998c), 165–201.———. (1998f). On the Pragmatics of Communication. Ed. Maeve Cooke.———. (1998g). On the Relation between the Nation, the Rule of Law, and Democ-

racy. In Habermas (1998c), 129–153.———. (1998h). Reply to Symposium Participants. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998),

381–452.———. (1998i). Richard Rorty’s Pragmatic Turn. In Habermas (1998f), 343–382.———. (1998j). Struggles for Recognition in the Democratic Constitutional State.

In Habermas (1998c), 203–237.———. (1999). The European Nation-State and the Pressures of Globalization, New

Left Review, 235:46–59.———. (2001a). Learning from Catastrophe? A Look Back at the Short Twentieth

Century. In Habermas (2001b), 38–57.———. (2001b) [1998]. The Postnational Constellation: Political Essays.———. (2001c). The Postnational Constellation and the Future of Democracy. In

Habermas (2001b), 58–112.———. (2001d). What Is a People? The Frankfurt “Germanists” Assembly of 1846

and the Self-Understanding of the Humanities in the Vormärz. In Habermas (2001b), 1–25.

———. (2002). Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, God, and Modernity.———. (2003a) [2001]. The Future of Human Nature.———. (2003b). On Law and Disagreement. Some Comments on “Interpretative

Pluralism,” Ratio Juris 16:187–194.———. (2006a) [2004]. The Divided West.

Page 327: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 316

———. (2006b). Does the Constitutionalization of International Law Still Have a Chance? In Habermas (2006a), 115–193.

———. (2006c) [2001]. Does Europe Need a Constitution? In Habermas (2006n), 89–109.

———. (2006d) [2001]. Euroskepticism, Market Europe, or a Europe of (World) Citizens? In Habermas (2006n), 73–88.

———. (2006e) [2004]. February 15, or: What Binds Europeans. In Habermas (2006a), 39–48.

———. (2006f) [2001]. The Finger of Blame: The Germans and Their Memorial. In Habermas 2006(h), 38–50.

———. (2006g) [2001]. From Power Politics to Cosmopolitan Society. In Haber-mas (2006n), 19–30.

———. (2006h) [2004]. Fundamentalism and Terror. In Habermas (2006a), 3–25.———. (2006i) [2004]. An Interview on War and Peace. In Habermas (2006a),

85–112.———. (2006j) [2004]. Is the Development of a European Identity Necessary, and

Is It Possible? In Habermas (2006a), 67–82.———. (2006k). Political Communication in Media Society: Does Democracy Still

Enjoy an Epistemic Dimension? The Impact of Normative Theory on Empiri-cal Research, Communication Theory, 16:411–424.

———. (2006l) [2004]. The State of German-Polish Relations. In Habermas (2006a), 57–66.

———. (2006m) [2001]. There Are Alternatives! In Habermas (2006n), 3–15.———. (2006n) [2001]. Time of Transitions.———. (2008a) [2005]. Between Naturalism and Religion. Trans. Ciaran Cronin.———. (2008b). The Boundary between Faith and Knowledge: On the Reception

and Contemporary Importance of Kant’s Philosophy of Religion. In Habermas (2008a), 209–47.

———. (2008c). Equal Treatment of Cultures and the Limits of Postmodern Liber-alism. In Habermas (2008a), 271–311.

———. (2008d). A Political Constitution for the Pluralist World Society? In Haber-mas (2008a), 312–352.

———. (2008e). Prepolitical Foundations of the Constitutional State? In Habermas (2008a), 101–113.

———. (2008f) [2005]. Public Space and Political Public Sphere—The Biographical Roots of Two Motifs in my Thought. In Habermas (2008a), 11–23.

———. (2008g). Religion in the Public Sphere: Cognitive Presuppositions for the “Public Use of Reason” by Religious and Secular Citizens. In Habermas (2008a), 114–147.

———. (2008h). Religious Tolerance as Pacemaker for Cultural Rights. In Haber-mas (2008a), 251–270.

———. (2009a). Afterword: Lessons of the Financial Crisis. In Habermas (2009d), 184–196.

———. (2009b). An Avantgardistic Instinct for Relevances: The Role of the Intel-lectual and the European Cause. In Habermas (2009d), 49–58.

Page 328: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 317

———. (2009c). The Constitutionalization of International Law and the Legiti-mation Problems of a Constitution for World Society. In Habermas (2009d), 109–130.

———. (2009d) [2008]. Europe: The Faltering Project.———. (2009e). European Politics at an Impasse: A Plea for a Policy of Graduated

Integration. In Habermas (2009d), 78–105.———. (2009f). Media, Markets, and Consumers: The Quality Press as the Back-

bone of the Political Public Sphere. In Habermas (2009d), 131–137.———. (2009g). Political Community in Media Society: Does Democracy Still

Have an Epistemic Dimension? The Impact of Normative Theory on Empirical Research. In Habermas (2009d), 138–182.

———. (2009h) [2008]. Ronald Dworkin: A Maverick among Legal Scholars. In Habermas (2009d), 37–45.

———. (2009i). What Is Meant by a Post-Secular Society? A Discussion on Islam in Europe. In Habermas (2009d), 59–77.

Habermas, Jürgen, and Luhmann, Niklas. (1971). Theorie der Gesellschaft oder Sozi-altechnologie: Was leistet die Systemforschung?

Hale, Robert L. (1923). Coercion and Distribution in a Supposedly Non-Coercive State, Political Science Quarterly 38:470.

Hart, H. L. A. (1994) [1961]. The Concept of Law (2nd ed.).Holmes, O. W. Jr. (1897). The Path of the Law. Harvard Law Review 10:457–478.Honneth, Axel, & Joas, Hans. (1991). Communicative Action: Essays on Habermas’s

Theory of Communicative Action.Husserl, Edmund. (1970). The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phe-

nomenology. Ed. and trans. David Carr.Issacharoff, Samuel, and Nagler, Jonathan. (2007). Protected from Politics: Di-

minishing Margins of Electoral Competition in U.S. Congressional Elections, 68 Ohio State Law Journal 1121–1137.

Issaacharoff, Samuel, and Karlan, Pamela S. (2004). Where to Draw the Line? Ju-dicial Review of Political Gerrymanders. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 153:541–578.

Issaacharoff, Samuel, Karlan, Pamela S., and Pildes, Richard H. (2009). The Law of Democracy: The Legal Structure of the Political Process (3rd ed.).

Jessop, Bob. (2002). The Future of the Capitalist State.Joas, Hans. (1991) [1986]. The Unhappy Marriage of Hermeneutics and Function-

alism. In Honneth and Joas (1991), 97–118.Joerges, Christian. (1999). “Good Governance” through Comitology? In Chris-

tian Joerges and Ellen Vos, eds., EU Committees: Social Regulation, Law and Politics, 311–338.

———. (2002). “Deliberative Supranationalism”: Two Defenses, European Law Journal, 8:133–151.

Joerges, Christian, and Neyer, Jürgen. (1997). From Intergovernmental Bargain-ing to Deliberative Political Processes: The Constitutionalisation of Comitol-ogy, European Law Journal, 3:273–299.

Johnson, James. (1991). Habermas on Strategic and Communicative Action, Politi-cal Theory 19:181–201.

Page 329: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 318

Kellner, Douglas. (2000). Habermas, the Public Sphere, and Democracy: A Criti-cal Intervention. In Perspectives on Habermas. Ed. Lewis Hahn, 259–287.

Kemp, Catherine. (1999). Habermas among the Americans: Some Reflections on the Common Law, Denver University Law Review 76:961–975.

Kennedy, Duncan. (1976). Form and Substance in Private-Law Adjudication, Har-vard Law Review 89:1685–1788.

Kessler, Friedrich. (1943). Contracts of Adhesion—Some Thoughts about Free-dom of Contract, Columbia Law Review 43:629–642.

Kleingeld, Pauline. (2004). Approaching Perpetual Peace: Kant’s Defence of a League of States and His Ideal of a World Federation, European Journal of Phi-losophy, 12:304–325.

Kramer, Larry. (2004). The People Themselves: Popular Constitutionalism and Judi-cial Review.

Kreide, Regina. (2009). Preventing Military Humanitarian Intervention? John Rawls and Jürgen Habermas on a Just Global Order, German Law Journal 10:93–113.

Kumm, Matthias. (2008). Why Europeans Will Not Embrace Constitutional Pa-triotism, International Journal of Constitutional Law, 6:117–136.

Kymlicka, Will. (1995). Multicultural Citizenship.Laborde, Cécile. (2002). From Constitutional to Civic Patriotism, British Journal

of Political Science 32:591–612.Lafont, Cristina. (2009). Religion and the Public Sphere: What Are the Delib-

erative Obligations of Democratic Citizenship? Philosophy and Social Criticism 35:127–150.

Larmore, Charles. (1999). The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism, Journal of Phi-losophy 96:599–625.

Lessig, Lawrence. (2010). Citizens Unite: The Constitutional Amendment, pub-lished online at www.tnr.com/article/politics/citizens-unite (March 16, 2010).

Levinson, Sanford, Balkin, Jack M., Amar, Akhil Reed, Siegel, Reva B., and Brest, Paul. (2006). Processes of Constitutional Decisionmaking (5th edition).

Levitt, Justin. (2008). A Citizen’s Guide to Redistricting. Lidz, Victor Meyer. (1976). Appendix to Victor Meyer Lidz and Charles W. Lidz,

Piaget’s Psychology of Intelligence and the Theory of Action. In J. Loubser (1976) (Vol. 1), 195–239.

Loubser, J. (1976). Explorations in General Theory in Social Science.Luhmann, Niklas. (1975). Macht.———. (1982). Talcott Parsons: The Future of a Theory. In The Differentiation of

Society. Trans. Stephen Holmes and Charles Larmore, 47–68.———. (1988). The Unity of the Legal System. In Autopoietic Law. Ed. Gunther

Teubner, 12–35.———. (1992). Operational Closure and Structural Coupling: The Differentiation

of the Legal System, Cardozo Law Review 13:1419–1442.———. (1993). Das Recht der Gesellschaft.———. (1997). Legal Argumentation: An Analysis of Its Form, Modern Law Review

58:285–298.

Page 330: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 319

———. (1998). Quod Omnes Tangit: Remarks on Jürgen Habermas’s Legal Theory. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 157–172.

———. (2004) [1993]. Law as a Social System. Trans. Klaus A. Ziegert. (Translation of Luhmann, 1993.)

Lupel, Adam. (2005). Tasks of a Global Civil Society: Held, Habermas, and Dem-ocratic Legitimacy beyond the Nation-State, Globalizations 2:117–133.

MacCormick, Neal. (2007). Institutions of Law: An Essay in Legal Theory.McCarthy, Thomas. (1979). The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas.———. (1991). Complexity and Democracy: Or, the Seducements of Systems The-

ory. In Honneth and Joas (1991), 119–139.———. (1992). Interaction, Indeterminacy, Normativity: Comments on Gum-

brecht, Yablon, and Cornell, Cardozo Law Review 13:1625–1629.———. (1998). Legitimacy and Diversity: Dialectical Reflections on Analytical Dis-

tinctions. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 115–155.McCormick, John P. (2007). Weber, Habermas, and Transformations of the European

State: Constitutional, Social, and Supranational Democracy.Maturana, Humberto, and Varela, Francisco. (1980). Autopoiesis and Cognition: The

Realization of the Living.Matustik, Martin Beck. (2001). Jürgen Habermas: A Philosophical-Political Profile.McMahon, Christopher. (2002). Why There Is No Issue between Habermas and

Rawls, The Journal of Philosophy, 99:111–29.Michelman, Frank. (1988). Law’s Republic, Yale Law Journal 97:1493–1537.———. (1996). Review of Between Facts and Norms, Journal of Philosophy 93:307–315.———. (1998). Family Quarrel. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 309–322.———. (2001). Morality, Identity, and “Constitutional Patriotism,” Ratio Juris

14:253–271.Modak-Truran, Mark. (2007). Secularization, Legal Indeterminacy, and Haber-

mas’ Discourse Theory of Law, Florida State University Law Review 35:73–118.Morris, Martin. (1996). On the Logic of the Performative Contradiction: Haber-

mas and the Radical Critique of Reason, The Review of Politics, 58:735–760.Müller, Jan-Werner. (2007). Constitutional Patriotism.Neblo, Michael A. (2008). Change for the Better? Linking the Mechanisms of

Deliberative Opinion Change to Normative Theory. Retrieved on January 10, 2010, from: http://polisci.osu.edu/faculty/mneblo/papers/ChangeC4.pdf.

Note (anonymous student author). (2009). Political Gerrymandering, 2000–2008: “A Self-Limiting Enterprise?” Harvard Law Review 122:1467–1488.

Olson, Kevin. (2007). Paradoxes of Constitutional Democracy, American Journal of Political Science 51:330–343.

Parsons, Talcott. (1967a). On the Concept of Influence. In Sociological Theory and Modern Society, 355–382.

———. (1967b). On the Concept of Political Power. In Sociological Theory and Mod-ern Society, 297–354.

———. (1969). On the Concept of Value Commitments. In Politics and Social Struc-ture, 439–472.

———. (1977a). On Building Social Systems Theory: A Personal History. In Social Systems and the Evolution of Action Theory, 22–76.

Page 331: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 320

———. (1977b). Some Problems of General Theory in Sociology. In Social Systems and the Evolution of Action Theory, 229–269.

———. (1978). A Paradigm of the Human Condition. In Action Theory and the Hu-man Condition, 352–444.

Parsons, Talcott, and Smelser, Neil J. (1956). Economy and Society: A Study in the Integration of Economic and Social Theory.

Penner, J. E. (1996). The Bundle of Rights Picture of Property, UCLA Law Review 43:711–820.

Persily, Nathaniel. (2010). The Floodgates Were Already Open: What Will the Su-preme Court’s Campaign Finance Ruling Really Change? Available at www .slate.com/id/2242558/.

Peters, Bernhard. (1993). Die Integration moderner Gesellschaften.———. (1994). On Reconstructive Legal and Political Theory, Philosophy & Social

Criticism 20:101–134.Peterson, Victor. (2010). Creativity in Norm Application and Legal Adjudication:

Discourse Theory on the Democratic Legitimacy of Legal Norms Developed through Common Law Adjudication and Judicial Review. Available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1570065.

Post, Robert C., and Siegel, Reva B. (2004). Popular Constitutionalism, Depart-mentalism, and Judicial Supremacy, California Law Review 92:1027–1043.

———. (2009). Democratic Constitutionalism. In The Constitution in 2020, 25–34. Eds. Jack M. Balkin and Reva B. Siegel.

Power, Michael K. (1998). Habermas and the Counterfactual Imagination. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 207–225.

Preuss, Ulrich K. (1998). Communicative Power and the Concept of Law. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 323–335.

Rawls, John. (1971). A Theory of Justice.———. (1995). Reply to Habermas, Journal of Philosophy 92:132–180.———. (2001). Justice as Fairness: A Restatement.———. (2005). Political Liberalism (expanded edition).Rehg, William. (1998). Against Subordination: Morality, Discourse, and Deci-

sion in the Legal Theory of Jürgen Habermas. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 257–271.

Rocher, Guy. (1976) Toward a Psychosociological Theory of Aspirations. In J. Loubser (1976) (Vol. 1), 391–406.

Rosenfeld, Michel. (1998). Can Rights, Democracy, and Justice Be Reconciled through Discourse Theory? Reflections on Habermas’s Proceduralist Para-digm of Law. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 82–113.

Rosenfeld, Michel, and Andrew Arato, eds. (1998). Habermas on Law and Democ-racy: Critical Exchanges.

Rubin, Edward L. (2001). Getting Past Democracy, University of Pennsylvania Law Review 149:711–792.

Scalia, Antonin. (1997). Common-Law Courts in a Civil-Law System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws. In A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law, 3–48.

Page 332: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 321

Schlink, Bernhard. (1998). The Dynamics of Constitutional Adjudication. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 371–379.

Schutz, Alfred. (1967) [1932]. The Phenomenology of the Social World.Schutz, Alfred, and Luckmann, Thomas. (1973). The Structures of the Lifeworld.

Trans. Richard M. Zaner and H. Tristram Engelhardt Jr.Seebaß, Gottfried, and Raimo Tuomela, eds. (1985). Social Action. Solum, Lawrence B. (2008). Semantic Originalism. Available at papers.ssrn.com/

sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1120244.Staats, Joseph. (2004). Habermas and Democratic Theory: The Threat to Democ-

racy of Unchecked Corporate Power, Political Science Quarterly, 57:585–594.Sunstein, Cass R. (1990). After the Rights Revolution.———. (2009). Going to Extremes: How Like Minds Unite and Divide.Teubner, Gunther. (1992). The Two Faces of Janus: Rethinking Legal Pluralism,

Cardozo Law Review 13:1443–1462.———. (1998). De Collisione Discursuum: Communicative Rationalities in Law, Mo-

rality, and Politics. In Rosenfeld and Arato (1998), 173–189.———. (2009). Self-Subversive Justice: Contingency or Transcendence Formula-

tion in Law, Modern Law Review 72:1–23.Tinnevelt, Ronald, and Mertens, Thomas. (2009). The World State: A Forbidding

Nightmare of Tyranny? Habermas on the Institutional Implications of Moral Cosmopolitanism, German Law Journal 10:63–80. www.tomorrowseurope.eu (Created 2007).

Tugendhat, Ernst. (1991). Habermas on Communicative Action. In Seebaß and Tuomela (1985), 179–186.

Tushnet, Mark. (1999). Taking the Constitution away from the Courts.———. (2008). Weak Courts, Strong Rights: Judicial Review and Social Welfare Rights

in Comparative Constitutional Law.———. (2009). Is Congress Capable of Conscientious, Responsible Constitutional

Interpretation? Some Notes on Congressional Capacity to Interpret the Con-stitution, Boston University Law Review 89:499–510.

Tweedy, John, and Hunt, Alan. (1994). The Future of the Welfare State and Social Rights: Reflections on Habermas, Journal of Law and Society 21:288–316 (1994).

Vos, Ellen. (1999). EU Committees: the Evolution of Unforeseen Actors in Euro-pean Product Regulation. In EU Committees: Social Regulation, Law and Poli-tics. Eds. Christian Joerges and Ellen Vos, 19–47.

Wagner, Helmut R. (1970). Alfred Schutz: An Intellectual Biography.Weber, Max. (1930) [1902]. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Trans.

Talcott Parsons.———. (1978). Economy and Society. Eds. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich.Weiler, J. H. H. (1999a). The Constitution of Europe.———. (1999b). Epilogue: “Comitology” as Revolution—Infranationalism, Con-

stitutionalism, and Democracy. In EU Committees: Social Regulation, Law and Politics. Eds. Christian Joerges and Ellen Vos, 339–350.

Weithman, Paul (2002). Religion and the Obligations of Citizenship.Whittington, Keith. (2007). Political Foundations of Judicial Supremacy: The Presi-

dency, the Supreme Court, and Constitutional Leadership in U.S. History.

Page 333: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Bibliography 322

Wiggershaus, Rolf. (2004). Habermas.Wolterstorff, Paul. (1997a). Audi on Religion, Politics, and Liberal Democracy. In

Audi and Wolterstorff (1997), 145–166.———. (1997b). The Role of Religion in Decision and Discussion of Political Issues,

In Audi and Wolterstorff (1997), 67–120.Wood, Allen W. (1985). Habermas’ Defense of Rationalism, New German Critique

35:145–164.Zurn, Christopher. (2007). Deliberative Democracy and the Institutions of Judicial

Review.

Page 334: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index

action orientations: vs. action conse-quences, 33–34; consensual understand-ing, 9, 10, 11, 13, 14, 30, 31, 33, 34, 40, 43, 47, 48, 49; regarding legal norms, 61; success, 10–11, 14, 17, 31, 33–34, 40, 41, 43, 92, 93, 151

adjudication, 63, 95, 103–4, 276n3; appel-late review, 114; as application of legal norms, 107–16; certainty requirement, 107–10, 111–12, 113, 114, 276n12; in common-law jurisdictions, 7, 114, 116–19, 279nn53,54,66,68; consis- tency in, 107; defined, 102; discourses of application regarding, 7, 92, 102–4, 110–12, 113, 117, 119–20, 121–24, 127–28, 275n223, 277nn25,28, 280nn82,87; in German system, 114; and indeterminacy of application, 110–16, 278n48; judicial impartiality, 115; and legal hermeneutics, 108–9; and legal paradigms, 112–13; and legal positivism, 108–9; and legal realism, 108–9, 112; legitimacy requirement, 107–10, 111; and normative justifi-ability, 107–10; and open society of interpreters, 114, 117, 278n49, 279n50; procedural approach to, 112–16; rules vs. principles in, 110–12, 125, 277n25. See also constitutional adjudication

Adorno, Theodor, 2, 4, 54Alexander, Jeffrey, 174; on Parsons, 36–37Alexy, Robert: on balancing of principles,

125–26, 128, 277n25, 281n93; on ba-

sic rights and popular sovereignty, 73, 269n73; on discourse of application, 111, 124, 278n32; on discourse of justi-fication, 124, 276n5; on German consti-tutional norms, 282n122; on horizontal effect, 130–31; on rules vs. principles, 125–26, 277n25; A Theory of Constitu-tional Rights, 125

Amish, 211, 213–14Amnesty International, 244analytic philosophy, 3apartheid, 199Aranson, Johannes, 262n139Arato, Andrew, 279n58; on public sphere,

278n49art, 27, 29, 53, 57Audi, Robert: on principle of secular moti-

vation, 196, 198; on principle of secular rationale, 195–96, 198, 297n28; on reli-gion, 193, 195–97, 198, 199–200, 201, 207, 208, 296nn23,24, 297n26

Austin, J. L., 3, 258n28

bargaining and compromise: vs. com-municative and strategic action, 95–96, 274n189; in constitutional state, 69, 75, 89, 92–94, 96, 97, 99, 100, 104, 115, 168; and equal bargaining power, 93; exclusion of exploitation from, 92; legal bargaining/plea-bargaining, 115; rela-tionship to discourse principle, 92–93, 94, 96

Page 335: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 324

cognitive interests: emancipatory interest, 2; practical interest, 2; technical inter-est, 2

Cohen, Joshua, 268n59, 274n199; on dis-course principle, 271n107; on outside initiative, 291n79

collective rights, 208–9, 215–17, 218–22, 301n168

comitology, 241–42, 308n351common-law adjudication, 7, 116–19,

279nn53,54,66,68communicative action, 3, 4, 5, 10–20, 28,

44, 156, 169, 176, 274n189; and bar-gaining, 93–94, 274n189; and formal pragmatics, 11–12, 256n12; vs. instru-mental action, 10–11; and normatively authorized requests, 14–15; orientation toward consensual understanding in, 9, 10, 11, 13, 14, 30, 31, 33, 34, 40, 43, 47, 48, 49; performative attitude in, 17–18, 61; and personal identity, 217; purposive aspect of, 23, 31; and rational motiva-tion, 85; redemption of claims, 39–40; relationship to lifeworld, 4, 21, 22, 24, 46, 150, 151, 170, 176, 260n84, 288n7; relationship to speech acts, 11, 13; vs. strategic action, 10–18, 42, 49–50, 51, 60, 61, 93, 259n45, 274n189, 287n6; and validity of speech acts, 12–13, 18–19. See also communicative rational-ity; discourse

communicative rationality, 3, 18–20, 26–30, 40, 44, 168, 236

communism, 199constitutional adjudication, 7, 63, 116,

119–47, 280nn76,79; civic republican model of, 120, 129, 131–35; constitu-tion as ongoing project, 142, 144; discourses of justification vs. discourses of application in, 103–4, 107, 117, 119–20, 121–24, 127–28, 275n223, 277nn25,28, 280nn82,87, 281n112; external vs. internal justification in, 107, 276n5; judicial review of legisla-tion, 120, 133–35, 137–42, 143–46, 287n213; liberal model of, 120, 129–30, 137; procedural model of, 120, 129–47, 147, 224–25; value jurisprudence in, 119, 120–28, 147, 280n85

constitutionalization of international law, 192, 228, 242–49, 308n353

Barry, Brian: on bilingual education, 214; Culture and Equality, 211–15, 216, 301n140; on multiculturalism, 208, 211–15, 216, 219, 301nn148,150,157; politics of difference vs. politics of redis-tribution, 215, 301n157; on Yoder deci-sion, 213–14

basic rights and popular sovereignty, 7, 63–65, 73–74, 82, 269n73

Benedict XVI, 8Benhabib, Seyla, 221, 301nn160,198,

302n194Berger, Johannes, 265n205Berlusconi, Silvio, 238biotechnology, 8Bohman, James, 276n3, 299n95, 308n339Brest, Paul, 143British Columbia: Citizen’s Assembly,

307n327Buckley, Walter, 262n140Bush, George W., 8, 229

Canada, 143, 209, 225, 227capitalism, 27, 237; crises in, 3, 54; glo-

balization, 228–29, 230, 243, 246, 304n237; markets in, 4, 15, 34, 41, 47; Marx on, 3, 54; and system, 4, 9, 34, 47, 265n187

categories of basic rights. See system of rights/categories of basic rights

Catholic Church, 197–98, 204, 219, 296n22, 297n46

circulation of power model, 154–64, 188, 192, 233, 235–36, 241, 250; vs. system/life world model, 149, 152–53, 154, 155, 165–77, 179, 190–91, 293n112

citizenship rules, 71–72civil society, 149, 174–75, 221, 244,

247, 302n199; and basic rights, 162; defined, 85, 101, 290n53; as global, 244, 250, 251; as network of voluntary associations, 85, 101, 102, 131, 159, 161, 175, 189, 233, 272n145, 291n85; relationship to center of political system, 166–67, 170, 179, 181, 182, 189, 250; relationship to legitimate law, 168–69; relationship to outer periphery of politi-cal system, 291n85; relationship to po-litical public sphere, 102, 160–63, 164, 168–69, 179, 181, 188, 189, 233, 235, 250, 293n116

Page 336: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 325

democracy principle, 74–75, 89, 97–100, 268n46; democratic procedures, 20, 95–100, 224–25, 303n220; and juridi-fication, 55; and legitimation of power, 42; liberal model of, 120, 129–30, 137; and modern complexity, 58; precondi-tions for, 162–64, 233; principle of, 74–75, 89, 95–100, 95–98, 103, 168, 268n46; procedural model of, 120, 129–47, 147, 224–25, 235, 303n220, 306n293; reflexivity of democratic pro-cess, 29–30; relationship to legitimate law, 10, 16, 17, 64–66, 82–83, 85, 86–87, 88, 95–102, 103, 104–5, 118–19, 128, 131, 134, 144, 152–53, 154, 168–69, 182, 225–26, 250–51; and religion, 197–98, 199, 201–2, 204, 206–8; role of legislatures in, 83, 96–102, 104–5, 116–17, 125, 137, 142, 143–44, 146, 155, 164, 166, 170–71, 176, 178, 210, 274n199, 279n56, 287n210, 288n31, 291n77. See also po-litical public sphere; political system; popular sovereignty

Derrida, Jacques, 5discourse: as argumentation, 19, 259n50;

ideal conditions for, 19–20, 259n52; in-stitutionalization of, 20, 30; as rational, 30, 68–69, 76, 89, 92, 94, 156; systems as discourses/communicative networks, 187–88; typology of discourses, 89–92

discourse principle, 7, 171, 268n43, 268n45, 271nn107,108; and catego-ries of basic rights, 68–69, 70–75, 79, 81; definition of action norms, 68; and democracy principle, 74–75, 89, 97–100, 268n46; and equality, 70–71, 79, 268n59, 269n60; relationship to bargaining and compromise, 92–93, 94, 96; universal assent requirement, 68, 70, 72, 74–75, 79, 90–92, 96, 97–100, 168, 236–37, 268n46, 269nn60,78, 273n178, 274n201

Durkheim, Emile, 4, 29Dworkin, Ronald: on campaign contribu-

tions, 138; on common law, 279n53; on constructive interpretation, 7, 103, 104, 109–10, 113–14, 115, 116, 119, 124–25, 279nn53,66; on fit and justifi-cation, 109–10, 277n17; vs. Habermas, 7, 103, 104, 109–10, 113–14, 115, 119, 124–25, 279n66, 280n85; Hercules

constitutional norms: due process, 72, 121, 224, 286n194; equal protection, 72, 121, 224, 286n194

constitutional patriotism, 5, 222–27, 241, 246, 251, 303n220, 304n226

constitutional state (Rechtsstaat), 6, 7, 77, 82–105; and administrative power, 83, 85–89, 95–105, 116–17, 128, 129, 133, 136, 149, 152, 153, 154, 155, 159–60, 169, 171, 182, 274n199, 307n308; and communicative power, 83, 85–89, 95–102, 103, 104, 105, 116–17, 128, 129, 133, 149, 152, 155, 159–60, 164, 169, 171, 176, 182, 274n199, 307n308; development of, 55–56; executive power, 83, 104, 118; legislative process, 83, 96–102, 104–5, 116–17, 146, 164, 279n56, 287n210, 291n77; reconstruc-tive analysis of, 93, 97, 99, 103, 145–47, 190; relationship to categories of rights, 63, 73; relationship to collective identity, 230–31; relationship to lifeworld, 23, 57–58; role of bargaining and com-promise in, 69, 75, 89, 92–94, 96, 97, 99, 100, 104, 115, 168; separation of powers in, 7, 88, 95, 102, 103–5, 107, 118–19, 120, 121, 128, 129–30, 144, 157, 241–42; system of state offices, 23, 42, 57–58, 83, 152, 235–36

courts. See adjudication; German constitu-tional court; legal institutions; United States Supreme Court

Cover, Robert: on jurisgenesis, 272n141criminal law, principles of, 23critical legal studies, 111, 277n29criticizability: relationship to communica-

tive rationality, 18–19; of validity claims, 12–13, 15, 16–17, 18–19, 40, 43, 257n19

Cronin, Ciarin, 303n220cultural rights, 215–16, 217–22,

302nn171,175

Daele, Wolfgang van den, 307n327Dahlberg, Lincoln, 298n87decision theory, 16, 18De Grieff, Pablo, 227, 304nn246,253democracy: beyond the nation-state, 8,

227–42; civic republican model of, 120, 129, 131–35, 235; deliberative model of, 131, 133, 136, 138, 144–45, 159–60, 170–71, 207–8, 235, 236–41, 272n148, 300n120, 306n293, 307n327;

Page 337: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 326

France: affaire du foulard in, 213, 218, 222, 302n179; rejection of European consti-tution by, 231

Frank, Jerome, 276n12Frankenberg, Günter: on social rights,

287n212Frankfurter allgemeine Zeitung, Die, 5Frankfurt School, 2, 4, 54Fraser, Nancy, 306n278, 308n332functionalist systems theories, 35functional necessity, 25

game theory, 16, 18, 258n38German constitutional court, 130, 146,

277n25, 280n73, 282n122; Lüth deci-sion, 125–26; and value jurisprudence, 119–20, 121, 125–28

Germany: Basic Law, 125, 126; historians’ debate in, 222; mass-communication law in, 136; Nazi regime, 1, 5, 222, 223; nineteenth-century civil-law theory in, 63, 64, 65, 66, 70, 102; political cam-paigns in, 138–39; proportional repre-sentation in, 284n168; vs. United States, 118, 130, 147

Giegerich, Thomas, 309n369globalization, 228–29, 230, 243, 246,

304n237global public sphere, 243–44, 249, 250, 251Gordon, Robert W., 293n119Greenpeace, 244Gulf War, first, 243Günther, Klaus: on discourses of justifica-

tion vs. discourses of application, 91–92, 110–11, 124, 277nn25,28,30, 278n39; vs. Habermas, 91–92, 110–11, 112, 124; on legal paradigms, 278n39

Habermas, Jürgen: A Berlin Republic, 8; Between Facts and Norms, 6–8, 9, 10, 62, 63, 78, 82, 84, 88, 112, 116, 124, 128, 129, 136, 146, 148–49, 150–53, 154–55, 161, 163, 165, 166, 167, 168–69, 170–71, 172, 174–76, 177, 180, 191, 192, 215–16, 226, 227, 233, 234, 235, 241, 255n16, 258n44, 267n10, 268n51, 279nn54,56, 281n112, 283nn156,162, 288n16, 290n48, 292nn90,111, 293n112, 298n73, 304n234, 306nn278,293, 307n308; Between Naturalism and Religion, 8, 200–201, 271n108; early life, 1–2; Econ-

Dworkin, Ronald (continued)device, 110, 113–14, 115; Justice as Robes, 277n17; Law’s Empire, 109, 110, 116; on rules vs. principles, 110–12, 277n25; on weight of rights, 281n92

Easton, David, 262nn140,141Edgar, Andrew, 288n25Elster, Jon: on arguing and bargaining,

274n189Ely, John Hart: vs. Habermas, 135, 136;

on representation reinforcement, 135, 136, 283nn151,165

enforcement of law and validity of legal norms, 62, 72, 83, 86, 95, 272n125

equality: in bargaining power, 93; and collective rights, 218, 220, 221; and discourse principle, 70–71, 79, 268n59, 269n60; equal protection, 72, 121, 224, 286n194; Kant on right to equal liber-ties, 65, 66, 71, 120; Kymlicka on, 210; Rawls on equal basic rights and liber-ties, 76, 77, 80–81, 138, 140, 270n97, 284n170, 295n10

ethical discourses, 96, 97, 102; at collective level, 89–90; ethical-political discourse, 90, 95, 121, 127–28; at individual level, 89–90

European Union (EU), 8, 192, 227–42, 246, 308n336, 310n379; and comitol-ogy, 241–42, 308n351; Council of the EU, 245; European Commission, 241; European identity vs. national identity, 230, 233, 305n259; European Parlia-ment, 232–33, 241, 306n290; political public sphere absent in, 233–35, 249, 306n278, 308n332; Treaty Establish-ing a Constitution for Europe, 231, 232, 305n270; Treaty of Lisbon, 228, 231–33, 305nn268,269,274

facticity vs. validity, 6, 17, 62–64, 73–74, 82, 107–10, 116, 267nn10,14, 269n74

family, the, 47, 52, 56, 291n60Fararo, Thomas J., 263n156fascism, 199Fishkin, James: deliberative polling experi-

ments of, 239–40Forbath, William, 277n13, 283n156,

288n27, 290n48, 292n104formal organizations, 48–49, 50–51, 170Foucault, Michel, 5

Page 338: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 327

188, 190, 233, 235, 292n90; in strategic action, 13–14

Institute for Social Research, 2institutional translation proviso, 201,

203–4, 206instrumental action, 18; orientation toward

success in, 11–12International Court of Justice, 244International Criminal Court (ICC), 244International Monetary Fund, 246Internet, 140, 163, 238–39, 307n320interpretive pluralism, radical, 225–26Ireland and Treaty of Lisbon, 231Islam, 204, 217, 222, 301n148; and head-

scarves, 213, 218, 222, 302n179Israel, 218Issacharoff, Samuel, 285n183

Jessop, Bob, 295n157Joas, Hans, 256n8, 260n84, 262n139,

264nn183,202Johnson, James, 258n38juridification, 55–56juries, 114

Kant, Immanuel: on cosmopolitan law, 242–43; vs. Habermas, 65–66, 71, 80, 242–45, 309n367; on legal vs. moral norms, 268n49; on perpetual peace, 8, 192, 228, 242–45, 309nn354,367; on reason, 243; on right to equal liberties, 65, 66, 71, 120; social contract theory of, 64; on universalizability, 66

Karlan, Pamela S., 285n183Kellner, Douglas, 265n205Kelsen, Hans: the Grundnorm, 108Kennedy, Duncan, 277n29Kerry, John, 285n176Kessler, Friedrich, 293n121King, Martin Luther, Jr., 195, 198Kleingeld, Pauline, 309n354Kohlberg, Lawrence, 265n189Kramer, Larry: on popular constitutional-

ism, 144Kreide, Regina, 304n234, 310n379Kumm, Matthias, 306n290, 308n340Kymlicka, Will: on collective rights,

208–9; on equality, 210; on group-differentiated rights, 208–11, 215, 216; on internal restrictions, 210–11, 219; Multicultural Citizenship, 208–11, 215; on multiculturalism, 208–12, 216, 218,

omy and Society, 38–39; at Frankfurt, 2, 5; The Inclusion of the Other, 8; at Johann Wolfgang Goether-University, 2; “Kant’s Idea of Perpetual Peace”, 242–45; Knowledge and Human Interests, 2; Le-gitimation Crisis, 2–3, 4, 5, 260n95; at Max-Planck Institute, 5; Die Moderne—ein unvollendetes Projekt, 255n14; Die nachholende Revolution, 8; Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, 5; polar distinc-tions employed by, 10, 34, 49–50, 51, 58, 293n112; “Political Communication in Media Society”, 234–41, 306n291, 307n304; political views, 2, 5, 8; The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere, 2, 251, 255n8, 306n278; Tanner Lectures/“Law and Morality”, 5; Theory of Communicative Action, 4–5, 6, 7, 9, 10, 14, 25, 50–51, 54, 57–58, 84, 85, 86, 87–88, 148, 151–53, 154–55, 161, 165, 167, 168, 169–70, 174–76, 177, 222, 257n28, 266nn228,229, 268n51, 290nn48,55

Hale, Robert, 264n165Hart’s rule of recognition, 108, 303n220Hasidic Jews, 211hermeneutic idealism, fictions of: auton-

omy of actors, 32; independence of culture, 32; transparency of communi-cation, 32

Hobbes, Thomas, 35Holmes, O. W., Jr.: the bad man’s view of

the law, 17Horkheimer, Max, 2, 4, 54human rights, 129, 225, 244–45. See also

rights; system of rights/categories of basic rights

Hunt, Alan, 266n222Husserl, Edmund: Crisis of European Sci-

ences, 259n63; on lifeworld, 20–21, 150, 176, 259nn58,63,66

identity, group/collective, 129, 132, 230–31, 233

identity, personal, 129, 172, 217individual rights, 209, 216, 219–20,

302n170influence: of mass media, 135–36, 160,

163, 164, 236, 237–40, 283n162, 307n313, 308n331; Parsons on, 36, 38, 43–44, 168, 263n159, 292n99; of public opinion, 160, 164, 167, 169, 170,

Page 339: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 328

153, 155, 156–57, 176, 178, 180, 186, 274n199, 278n49, 279n50, 288n31; property, 23, 40, 64, 77, 80, 153, 174, 180, 185, 294n144. See also adjudica-tion; German constitutional court; United States Supreme Court

legal norms: application of, 7, 92, 102–4, 107–16, 110–12, 113, 117, 119–20, 121–24, 127–28, 275n223, 277nn25,28, 280nn82,87, 281n112; enforcement and validity of, 62, 72, 83, 86, 95, 145, 272n125; indeterminacy of application, 110–16, 278n48; justi-fication of, 92, 102, 103, 107, 109–11, 113, 117, 119–20, 121–24, 127–28, 275n223, 276n5, 277nn17,25, 280n87; and legal medium/legal form, 69–70, 268nn50,53,55; vs. moral norms, 66–67, 89, 92, 94, 95–96, 99, 127–28, 268n49, 269n60, 281n110, 289n36; procedural rules as, 97–98; relation-ship to principle of democracy, 74–75, 95–98, 103, 168

legal paradigms: liberal/bourgeois formal-law paradigm, 112–13, 278n48; proce-duralist paradigm, 112–13, 278n48; social-welfare paradigm, 112–13, 278n48

legal pluralism, 187–88, 293n121legal positivism, 64, 108–9legal procedures: and adjudication, 112–16,

278n48; and constitutional adjudica-tion, 120, 129–47, 147, 224–25; and discourse principle, 113–16; and due process, 72; and equal treatment, 72; as legal norms, 97–98; and positivization of law, 20, 66

legal realism, 108–9, 112, 276nn8,12, 277n13, 293n121

legitimate law: and categories of basic rights, 63, 64–66, 67–68, 73, 73–74, 81–82, 120, 145; legal validity, 62–63, 64–68, 153, 181–82, 303n220; and popular sovereignty, 64–66, 67–68, 73–74; and procedural principles, 96, 225–26; relationship to compliance, 60–61; relationship to democracy, 10, 16, 17, 64–66, 82–83, 85, 86–87, 88, 95–102, 103, 104–5, 118–19, 128, 131, 134, 144, 152–53, 154, 168–69, 182, 225–26, 250–51; tension between legiti-macy and enforcement, 62

Kymlicka, Will: on multiculturalism (continued)219, 221; on polyethnic rights, 209, 210, 211, 212, 216, 218, 221; on self-government rights, 209, 211, 216, 218; on special representation rights, 209–10, 216; on voluntary immigrants vs. na-tional minorities, 211, 215

Laborde, Cécile, 304n226LaFont, Cristina, 205–7, 300nn118,120language: consensus formation in, 44; vs.

money, 39–40, 264n167Larmore, Charles, 79, 271n109law: family law, 56, 156; as hinge between

system and lifeworld, 149, 152, 153, 183; and juridification, 55–56; jurisgen-erative power of citizens, 85, 88, 100, 117, 129, 131, 134, 152–53, 154, 169, 250, 272n141, 282n138; legal com-munity, 66–67, 76, 81, 89, 90, 94, 95, 146, 269n60, 273n170; legal discourse, 89, 94, 95, 113–16; legal personhood, 29, 69–70, 71, 79–80; legal sanctions, 60–61, 67, 83, 86, 107, 153, 244; as medium, 57, 149, 156, 268n51; private law, 42, 51, 56, 57, 64, 130–31, 146, 174; public law, 42, 51, 56, 57, 174; rela-tionship to dissensus, 18; relationship to lifeworld, 23, 34, 56–58, 152, 153, 174; relationship to morality, 64, 66–67, 79; relationship to political power, 83–85, 184–85; relationship to system, 23, 34, 40, 51, 56–57, 69–70, 149, 152–53, 156, 157, 170, 174, 183, 268n51, 288n16; rule of, 80, 88; school law, 56; and social evolution, 46, 265n189; social-welfare law, 56; as transformer between system and lifeworld, 149, 152–53, 183, 290n48. See also adjudica-tion; constitutional adjudication; legal institutions; legal norms; legal proce-dures; legitimate law

legal form/legal medium, 83, 149, 269n64; and legal norms, 69–70, 268nn50,53,55; and legal personhood, 69–70, 79–80

legal hermeneutics, 108–9legal institutions, 49, 50–51, 56, 149, 152;

contracts, 23, 40, 64, 153, 174, 180, 293n121; courts, 72, 77, 83, 84, 88,

Page 340: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 329

29–30, 31, 45–46, 54–56, 150, 152, 154, 168, 172–73; vs. system, 3, 4, 5, 45–51, 52, 149–50, 175–77, 290n48. See also civil society; political public sphere; private sphere; system/lifeworld interchange

Locke, John, 271n111Luckman, Thomas, 259n67Luhmann, Niklas: autopoietic sys-

tems theory of, 35, 83–85, 116, 150, 156–57, 171–72, 180–90, 250, 262n139, 267n14, 278n40, 289n32, 292nn105,106, 293nn123,125, 295n152; on binary codes, 83–85, 156, 157, 171–72, 180, 181, 183, 188, 289n36, 292n106, 293nn125,127,128; on center and periphery, 180–81, 186–87, 288n28; on circulating sym-bols, 181–82; on communication across system boundaries, 183–86; vs. Habermas, 2, 7, 35, 83–85, 116, 150, 156–57, 171–72, 180–90, 260n95, 263n159, 267n14, 269n78, 289nn36,37, 292n105; on Habermas and legislation, 279n56; on idea of the constitution, 295n152; on irritation, 184, 187, 189–90; on legal system, 180, 184–85, 186–87, 289nn36,37, 293n121, 295n152; on operative closure vs. cogni-tive openness, 183–84; on program-ming, 294n139; on structural coupling, 184–86, 187–88, 190, 294n148; on subsystems, 84, 263n157; on system closure, 84

Lukács, Georg, 4, 54

MacCormick, Neil: on binary codes, 292n106; Institutions of Law, 188; on law as institutional normative order, 294n142

Marx, Karl, 2, 4, 12, 35; on capitalism, 3, 54; on crises in capitalism, 3, 54; on labor theory of value, 3; on real abstrac-tions, 54

mass communications media, 307n312, 308n331; influence in political public sphere, 135–36, 160, 163, 164, 236, 237–40, 283n162, 307n313, 308n331; Internet, 140, 163, 238–39, 307n320

Maturana, Humberto: Autopoiesis and Cog-nition, 295n156

legitimation crisis, 3Lessig, Lawrence, 140Levinson, Sanford, 143Levitt, Justin, 285n183liberalism, 260n96, 271n111; model

of constitutional adjudication, 120, 129–30, 137; and multiculturalism, 210–11, 212; of Rawls, 80, 101–2, 199–200, 208, 274n203, 275n210

Lidz, Victor Meyer, 263n156lifeworld: colonization of, 10, 55–57, 154,

156, 157, 168, 173, 177, 266n216, 288n27, 290n48; consensus between actors in, 21–22; context of relevance in, 21; crises of reproductive processes, 24–26; cultural reproduction, 24, 25–26, 29, 150, 151, 173, 175; culture component, 22, 24, 25–27, 28–29, 31, 32–33, 48–49, 50, 56, 57, 150, 151, 162, 170, 172–75, 176, 217, 260n75, 287n7, 288n17; as domain of action, 50; and fictions of hermeneutic ideal-ism, 32; Husserl on, 20–21, 150, 176, 259nn58,63,66; material reproduction of, 23, 30–32, 45–46, 51; norms and values in, 4, 29–30, 33, 34; personal-ity component, 22, 23, 24, 25, 26–27, 30, 31, 32–33, 48–49, 50, 52, 149, 150, 151, 162, 170, 172–75, 176, 217, 260n75, 287n7, 288n17; phenomeno-logical conception of, 9, 20–21, 150, 172, 176, 259n58; rationalization of, 25, 26–30, 33, 45, 47, 56, 58, 60, 61, 66, 68, 150–51, 168, 173; reflexivity in symbolic reproduction, 29–30; relation-ship to communicative action, 4, 21, 22, 24, 46, 150, 151, 170, 176, 260n84, 288n7; relationship to law, 23, 34, 56–58, 152, 153, 174; relationship to the state, 23, 57–58; Schutz on, 20–22, 31, 150, 172, 176, 259nn66,67, 260n75; and social complexity, 32, 33, 58; social integration, 24, 25, 26, 29–30, 34, 150, 151, 152, 173, 175, 222, 230, 260n96, 288n9; socialization, 24, 25, 26, 30, 52, 150, 151, 175, 260n75, 260n96; soci-ety component, 22–23, 24, 25, 26–27, 29–30, 32–33, 34, 40, 47, 48–49, 50, 52, 57–58, 149, 150, 151, 152, 153, 162, 165, 167, 170, 172–75, 176, 217, 287n7; symbolic reproduction of, 10, 23–26,

Page 341: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 330

265n189; universalization principle, 66–67, 89, 91–92, 94, 99, 127

moral norms: application of, 91–92, 94, 110–11; justification of, 91–92, 110–11; vs. legal norms, 66–67, 89, 92, 94, 95–96, 99, 127–28, 268n49, 269n60, 281n110, 289n36; normative rightness (Richtigkeit), 12, 14–15, 16–17, 19, 27, 42, 96, 256n12, 258n29

motivation crisis, 3Müller, Jan-Werner: Constitutional Patrio-

tism, 222–25; on constitutional patrio-tism, 222–25, 226–27, 303n207; on disagreement about constitutional essen-tials, 303n219; on object of attachment, 223–24, 303n213

multiculturalism: Barry on, 208, 211–15, 216, 219, 301nn148,150,157; Habermas on, 8, 192, 209, 212, 215–22, 227, 230, 241; Kymlicka on, 208–12, 216, 218, 219, 221

Murdoch, Rupert, 238

Neblo, Michael, 239Netherlands: rejection of European consti-

tution by, 231New Zealand, 143nongovernmental organizations (NGOs).

See civil society

Parsons, Talcott: AGIL schema of, 35–38, 263n156; on collective goals, 42; culture/ society/personality schema of, 22, 26–27, 172; on general action system, 37, 38, 263n156; vs. Habermas, 4, 9, 22, 26–27, 31, 35, 38, 39–45, 47, 53, 59, 69, 84, 167–68, 172, 260n95, 263n159, 264nn174,175, 292n99; on influence, 36, 38, 43–44, 168, 263n159, 292n99; interchange paradigm of, 35–38, 53, 167–68; on money, 36, 38, 39, 40–41, 47, 264n174; on power, 36, 38, 41, 42, 47, 264nn174,175; social systems theory of, 35–38, 262n139, 263n156; on value-commitment, 36, 38, 43–44

penal procedure, 23personhood, legal, 29, 69–70, 71, 79–80Peters, Berhard, 154, 288n28, 293n112Peterson, Victor, 118, 277n28,

279nn54,68phenomenology, 9, 20–21, 150, 172, 176,

259n58

McCarthy, Thomas, 91, 262nn125,139, 263n159, 265n198, 266n228, 273n170, 274nn201,202

McMahon, Christopher, 271n120Mead, George Herbert, 4, 29media, steering, 38–45, 178–79, 265n187;

money, 33, 36, 38–43, 44, 45, 47, 50–51, 52, 53, 56, 57, 69, 87–88, 151, 152, 153, 161, 167–68, 169, 170, 174, 183, 263n159, 264nn165,167,174; power, 33, 36, 41–43, 44, 45, 47, 50–51, 52, 53, 54, 56, 57, 58, 69, 84, 86–89, 149, 151, 152, 153, 155, 156, 166, 167–68, 169, 170, 174, 183, 264nn174,173, 266n229, 289n35; and real abstractions, 54; relationship to law, 56–57, 69–70, 149, 152, 156, 157, 174, 183, 268n51, 288n16; role in system in-tegration, 33–34, 47, 48, 151, 155–56, 169–70, 288n9; role in system/lifeworld interchange, 47, 48, 59, 60, 87, 152, 153, 155–56, 161, 165, 167–68, 169, 175, 181; steering crises, 54

Mennonites, 211Mertens, Thomas, 309n373Michelman, Frank, 283n156; on attach-

ment to idea of the constitution, 224–25; on constitutional patriotism, 224–27; vs. Habermas, 7, 90, 113, 131–35, 224–25, 226–27, 280n87, 281n111, 282nn142,149, 303n220; Law’s Republic, 133; on neorepublican theory of constitu-tional adjudication, 7, 131–35, 282n149

Modak-Truran, Mark, 278n48modernity: communicative practice in,

257n12; development of bureaucratic state, 9, 27, 56; dissensus in, 16, 18, 33, 47, 60, 90, 151, 259n48; institution-alization of discursive practices in, 20; multicultural societies in, 90; process of differentiation in, 45–46; uncoupling of system and lifeworld in, 25, 40, 45–51, 151; as unfinished project, 5, 255n14

money: vs. language, 39–40, 264n167; as steering medium, 33, 36, 38–43, 44, 45, 47, 50–51, 52, 53, 56, 57, 69, 87–88, 151, 152, 153, 161, 167–68, 169, 170, 174, 183, 263n159, 264nn165,167,174

morality: moral agents, 29; moral dis-course, 89, 91–92, 93, 94, 95, 102, 104, 127–28, 268n43; relationship to law, 64, 66–67, 79; and social evolution, 46,

Page 342: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 331

postmetaphysical thinking, 201, 202, 273n172, 298n73

postmodernity, 5postnational constellation, 192, 227–29,

240–41power: administrative power, 83, 85–89,

95–105, 116–17, 128, 129, 133, 136, 149, 152, 153, 154, 155, 159–60, 169, 171, 182, 274n199, 307n308; as com-mand, 14–15, 16–17, 42, 58, 59, 84, 85, 86, 88, 153, 156, 166, 170–71, 264n174, 289n35; communicative power, 83, 85–89, 95–102, 103, 104, 105, 116–17, 128, 129, 133, 149, 152, 155, 159–60, 164, 169, 171, 176, 182, 237, 266n229, 274n199, 307n308; legitimation of, 42, 43, 58, 236–37; of media, 237–40; as social and eco-nomic, 130, 137, 140, 147, 162–63, 164, 237, 283n162, 284n170, 291n71; as steering medium, 33, 36, 41–43, 44, 45, 47, 50–51, 52, 53, 54, 56, 57, 58, 69, 84, 86–89, 149, 151, 152, 153, 155, 156, 166, 167–68, 169, 170, 174, 183, 264nn174,173, 266n229, 289n35

pragmatic discourses, 89, 95, 96, 102, 104–5, 121, 127–28

pragmatics, formal, 11–12, 14preconventional/conventional/

postconventional levels, 46, 265n189Preuss, Ulrich, 268n42principles: balancing of, 125–26; vs.

rules, 110–12, 125–27; vs. values, 121, 125–26, 128

private autonomy: and categories of basic rights, 69–73, 129, 131; and legal per-sonhood, 69–70; and liberal model of democracy, 129, 235; vs. public auton-omy, 7, 63–66, 67–68, 72–73, 76–77, 80, 81, 129–30, 132, 235

private sphere: as civil society, 149; con-sumer role, 52, 53, 54, 55, 161; em-ployee role, 52, 53, 55, 161, 266n219; interchange with economic system, 51–52, 53, 59, 168; real abstractions, 54; relationship to political public sphere, 159, 160–62

procedural model of constitutional adjudi-cation, 120, 129–47, 147, 224–25

proportional representation, 137–38, 209, 283n167, 284n168

philosophy of law, 280n68pluralistic societies, 108, 125, 132Poland and Treaty of Lisbon, 231,

305nn268,274political parties, 155, 164, 166, 178, 236,

288n31political public sphere, 101, 149, 174–75,

290n48, 298n87; as absent in EU, 233–35, 249, 306n278, 308n332; vs. artistic/literary sphere, 53; and basic rights, 162; citizen role, 52, 53, 54, 55; client role, 52, 53, 55–56; and democ-racy, 162–63; formation of public opin-ion, 160, 164, 169, 307n313; influence of mass media in, 135–36, 160, 163, 164, 236, 237–40, 283n162, 307n313, 308n331; interchange with administra-tive system, 51–52, 53, 58, 59, 165, 168; as productive of legitimate law, 85, 129, 131, 152–53, 154; and real abstractions, 54; relationship to center of political system, 159–60, 166–67, 169, 170, 179, 181, 182, 188–89, 190, 233, 235–36, 250; relationship to civil society, 102, 160–63, 164, 168–69, 179, 181, 188, 189, 233, 235–36, 250, 293n116; role of mass loyalty in, 52, 53, 54, 58, 88, 136, 154, 168; role of taxes in, 52, 53, 88, 168. See also religion

political system: boundaries of, 156, 165–67, 170, 176–77, 179–80, 181–82, 189, 289n36, 292n90; center of, 155–57, 159–60, 163–64, 165–67, 169, 170–71, 176, 177–79, 181, 182, 188–89, 190, 233, 235–36, 250, 288n31, 292n90, 293n115; customers vs. suppliers in, 158–59, 166, 179, 236; influence of public opinion on, 160, 164, 167, 169, 170, 188, 190, 233, 235, 292n90; inner periphery of, 155, 157–58, 166, 177, 290n43; outer periph-ery of, 155, 157, 158–59, 166, 179–80, 236, 290n43, 291n85

popular sovereignty: and basic rights, 7, 63–65, 73, 82, 269n73; informal dis-cussion vs. governmental decisions in, 100–101; relationship to communicative power, 86, 100–101, 102; relationship to legitimate law, 64–66, 67–68, 73–74; and republicanism, 129

Posner, Richard, 283n156Post, Robert, 144

Page 343: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 332

Habermas, 6–7, 8, 76–82, 101–2, 192, 200–208, 271nn111,120, 274n203, 296n25, 298n89, 299n95, 309n354; “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited”, 195; on judicial stage, 78, 81; on legisla-tive stage, 78, 81; liberalism of, 80, 101–2, 199–200, 208, 274n203, 275n210; on liberties of moderns, vs. liberties of ancients, 76, 80–82, 271nn111,114; on matters of basic justice, 102, 194, 195, 207, 275n214, 295n10; on modus vivendi, 204, 299n100; on original position, 6–7, 76, 78, 80, 81–82, 270nn85–87, 274n203; on political conception as module, 204; Political Liberalism, 78, 193, 284n170; on principle of fair opportunity, 270n99; on principles of justice, 6–7, 76, 78, 80, 81, 270n87; on public funding of campaigns, 138; on public reason, 102, 193–95, 196, 198, 199, 200–201, 202–5, 206–7, 208, 270n87, 284n170, 296nn11,22,25, 300n118; on reason-able pluralism, 193, 194, 204, 207, 270n87; on religion, 8, 191, 193–95, 196, 198, 199–201, 202–5, 206–7, 208, 296nn22,25, 300n120; on social-welfare rights, 77; Theory of Justice, 76; on veil of ignorance, 76, 270nn86,87, 275n203; on well-ordered society, 194, 296n15

reconstructive analysis, 11, 16, 76, 79–80, 82, 101, 105, 119, 132, 148, 154, 163–64, 250, 256nn10,12, 271n108, 281n110; of constitutional state, 93, 97, 99, 103, 145–47, 190; as nonutopian, 61–62, 97, 148

reference systems: humanity, 66, 67, 89, 94, 95, 127, 269n60; legal community, 66–67, 76, 81, 89, 90, 94, 95, 146, 269n60, 273n170

Rehg, William, 263n159, 268n50, 293n115reification, 4religion: Audi on, 193, 195–97, 198,

199–200, 201, 207, 208, 296nn23,24; and democracy, 197–98, 199, 201–2, 204, 206–8; free exercise of, 200, 201, 203; Habermas on, 8, 191, 200–206, 207–8, 271n108, 273n172, 296n25, 298nn84,87, 299nn94,95,98, 300n120; Rawls on, 8, 191, 193–95, 196, 198, 199–201, 202–5, 206–7, 208,

Protestantism, 204psychoanalysis, 2public autonomy, 76, 129, 132; and first

category of basic rights, 70–71; and fourth category of basic rights, 72–73; vs. private autonomy, 7, 63–66, 67–68, 72–73, 76–77, 80, 81, 129–30, 132, 235; and republican model of democ-racy, 129, 131, 235; and second category of basic rights, 71–72; and third cat-egory of basic rights, 71–72

public opinion: formation of, 160, 164, 169, 237, 307n313; influence on politi-cal system, 160, 164, 167, 169, 170, 188, 190, 233, 235, 292n90

public reason: exclusive view of, 194; inclusive view of, 194–95; Rawls on, 102, 193–95, 196, 198, 199, 200–201, 202–5, 206–7, 208, 270n87, 284n170, 296nn11,22,25, 300n118

public sphere See global public sphere; po-litical public sphere

Quakers, 296n22

rationality: communicative rationality, 3, 18–20, 26–30, 40, 44, 168, 236; rational choice theory, 16, 18; rational discourse, 30, 68–69, 76, 89, 92, 94, 156; rationality crisis, 3; rationalization of lifeworld, 25, 26–30, 33, 45, 47, 56, 58, 60, 61, 66, 68, 150–51, 168, 173; rules of rational choice, 10, 15–16; types of rational action, 10, 256n1; Weber on rationalization, 4, 20, 26–28, 173, 261n108. See also communicative action; instrumental action; strategic action

Rawls, John: on basic needs, 77, 270n99; on comprehensive doctrines, 193, 194–95, 196, 199, 200, 202, 204, 270n87, 295n3, 296n22, 297n26, 298n89; on concept of person as norma-tive, 78–80; on consensus regarding justice, 193; on constitutional essentials, 77, 102, 193–94, 195, 207, 270n99, 275n214, 296n25; on constitutional stage, 78, 81; on declaration, 196; on democracy, 76, 78–79; on difference principle, 77, 270n99; on equal basic rights and liberties, 76, 77, 80–81, 138, 140, 270n97, 284n170, 295n10; vs.

Page 344: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 333

social and ecological rights, 75, 77, 81, 120, 146–47, 287nn212,213

social and economic power, 130, 137, 140, 147, 162–63, 164, 237, 283n162, 284n170, 291n71

social complexity, 32, 33, 58, 62social crises: colonization of lifeworld, 10,

55–57, 154, 156, 157, 168, 173, 177, 266n216, 288n27, 290n48; in symbolic reproduction, 4–5, 24–26, 54–57

social crisis theory, 3, 4–5, 168social evolution, 4, 9, 46social pathologies, 24–26, 54–57, 168social stratification, 92Solum, Lawrence B., 280n79Specter, Arlen, 143, 286n201speech acts: Austin on, 3, 258n28; con-

stative utterances, 12; expressive ut-terances, 12; normatively authorized requests, 14–15, 16–17, 42–43; regula-tive utterances, 12, 13; relationship to communicative action, 11, 13; simple imperatives, 14–15, 16–17, 19, 42–43. See also validity of speech acts

Staats, Joseph: on corporate power, 283n162, 308n331

steering media. See media, steeringstrategic action: and avowability of par-

ties’ intention, 13–14; and bargaining, 93–94, 274n189; vs. communicative ac-tion, 10–18, 42, 49–50, 51, 60, 61, 93, 259n45, 274n189, 287n6; as concealed, 13–14, 33, 257nn27,28, 274n189; and formal pragmatics, 11–12, 14–15, 258n29; lifeworld as background for, 287n6; objectivating attitude in, 17–18, 48, 61; as open, 13, 14–18, 93, 258n38; orientation toward success in, 10–11, 31; and rational choice, 15–16; relationship to material reproduction of lifeworld, 31–32, 33; relationship to norms, 31; role of causal influence in, 13–14; role of competition in, 15–16; and simple imperatives, 14–15, 16, 19; and speech acts, 11; spheres of, 15, 68

Sunstein, Cass, 131; on canons of interpre-tation, 113, 278n45; on deliberation, 240

system: administrative system, 4, 5, 9, 10, 25, 33–34, 35, 38, 45, 46, 48, 49, 50, 51, 54, 55–56, 57, 58, 59, 68, 86–89,

296nn22,25, 300n120; Weithman on, 193, 196–99, 201, 207–8, 296n24, 297n39, 299n94, 300n122; Wolterstorff on, 193, 198–200, 201, 202–3, 208, 296n25, 298n66, 299n94

republicanism, civic, 7, 80, 90, 130–35, 260n96, 282nn132,149, 305n261; model of constitutional adjudication, 120, 129, 131–35; and Rousseau, 271n111

rights: actionability of, 71; collective rights, 208–9, 215–17, 218–22, 301n168; human rights, 129, 225, 244–45; immigration/emigration rights, 72; individual rights, 209, 216, 219–20, 302n170; negative rights vs. positive rights, 120; right of assembly, 162, 190; right of association, 80, 162, 190; right of free press, 162, 190; right of free speech, 162, 163, 190; right to equal liberties, 65, 66, 70–71; right to privacy, 68, 268n42; social and ecologi-cal rights, 75, 77, 81, 120, 130, 146–47, 287nn212,213. See also system of rights/categories of basic rights

Rocher, Guy, 263n156Rosenfeld, Michael, 273n172Rousseau, Jean-Jacques: vs. Habermas,

64–66, 80, 90; on popular sovereignty, 64–66; and republicanism, 271n111; social contract theory of, 64

Scalia, Antonin, 122, 142, 280n76Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von:

on nature, 2Schlink, Bernhard, 280n73Schutz, Alfred: vs. Habermas, 20–21, 31,

172; on lifeworld, 20–22, 31, 150, 172, 176, 259nn66,67, 260n75; on stock of knowledge, 22; Strukturen der Leb-enswelt, 259n67

science, 27, 29, 57, 204, 205–6, 259n58, 299n112; scientific discourse, 99; scien-tific research, 20; Supreme Court deci-sions regarding, 185–86, 294n147

Searle, John, 3secular citizens: requirements on, 205, 207Siegel, Reva, 144Sikhs, 212–13, 217, 218Smelser, Neil, 38Smith, Adam, 35

Page 345: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 334

ing tension between private and public autonomy, 63–64, 73–74; and private autonomy, 69–73, 129, 131, 145–46; and public autonomy, 69–73, 129, 131, 145–46; second category of rights, 71–72, 76–77, 81; third category of rights, 71–72, 76–77, 81; as unsaturated, 71, 78, 120, 145, 269n81

Teubner, Gunther, 293n123; on binary codes, 295n152; on legal practice, 281n109; “Rethinking Legal Pluralism”, 187–88, 294n150

Tinnevelt, Ronald, 309n373transnational negotiation systems, 242,

246–47, 248–49, 250, 308n352, 309n373, 310n376

Tushnet, Mark, 286n196, 287n202; on social and economic rights, 287n213; on strong-form vs. weak-form judicial review, 143–44

Tweedy, John, 266n222

unconscious deception, 257n27United Kingdom, 143; and Treaty of Lis-

bon, 231, 305nn268,274United Nations: Charter, 244, 248; Gen-

eral Assembly, 245, 248; Human Rights Commission, 244; peacekeeping opera-tions, 244, 245, 248, 309nn362,371; reorganization of, 244, 245, 246, 247–48, 248, 249; Security Council, 244

United States: abolitionist movement, 194–95, 199; affirmative action in, 216, 301n168; African Americans, 197, 215; Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act (BCRA)/McCain-Feingold, 139–40, 284n175, 285n178; campaign fi- nance in, 137–40, 284nn170,175, 285nn176–78; civil rights movement, 194–95, 198, 298n84; common-law ad-judication in, 102–4, 119; constitutional law in, 7, 75, 121–24, 132, 133–35, 136, 137–42, 143, 144, 145, 185–86, 209–10, 213–14, 219–20, 225, 227, 280n76, 286n194, 287n213; vs. Ger-many, 118, 130, 147; and ICC, 244; Iraq invasion, 8, 237; mass media in, 237–38; national minorities in, 211;

system: administrative system (continued)149, 151, 152, 153, 154, 155, 156, 157, 161, 165–66, 167–68, 170, 175, 183, 266n228, 288n27; as colonizing life-world, 10, 55–57, 154, 156, 157, 168, 173, 177, 266n216, 288n27, 290n48; and consequences of self-interested ac-tion, 4, 9, 32, 33–34, 40, 51; develop-ment of, 9, 33–34, 56; differentiation of systems, 45, 47, 49, 151, 264n187; economic system, 4, 5, 9, 10, 25, 33–34, 35, 38, 45, 46, 48, 49, 50, 51–52, 54, 56, 57, 59, 68, 87, 151, 153, 154, 155, 158, 161, 167–68, 170, 175, 183, 263n159, 288n27, 290n41, 292n111; vs. lifeworld, 3, 4, 5, 45–51, 52, 149–50, 175–77, 290n48; as norm free, 34, 48, 49, 50, 175–76; relationship to capital-ism, 4, 9, 34, 47, 265n187; relationship to law, 23, 34, 40, 51, 56–57, 69–70, 149, 152–53, 156, 157, 170, 174, 183, 268n51, 288n16; role of formal organi-zations in, 48–49, 50–51, 56; as uncou-pled from lifeworld, 25, 35, 40, 45–51, 151. See also media, steering; system/lifeworld interchange

system/lifeworld interchange, 9, 10, 26, 43, 148; vs. circulation of power model, 154, 155, 165–77, 179; role of private sphere in, 51–52, 149, 154; role of public sphere in, 51–52, 149, 152–53, 154; role of steering media in, 47, 48, 59, 60, 87, 152, 153, 155–56, 161, 165, 167–68, 169, 175, 181, 265n193; systems- theoretical model of, 47, 50, 51–59, 87–88; uncoupling of system and life-world, 25, 35, 40, 45–51, 151. See also media, steering

system of rights/categories of basic rights, 6–7, 63–75, 98, 129, 147, 270n88; and constitutional state, 63, 73; and discourse principle, 68–69, 70–75, 79, 81–82; fifth category of rights, 75, 77, 81, 120, 146–47; first category of rights, 70–71, 76–77, 81, 120; fourth category of rights, 72–73, 77, 81, 120; and le-gitimate law, 63, 64–66, 67–68, 73, 73–74, 81–82, 120, 145; as mediating tension between basic rights and popular sovereignty, 63–64, 73–74; as mediat-

Page 346: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Index 335

validity of speech acts: normative rightness (Richtigkeit), 12, 14–15, 16–17, 19, 27, 42, 96, 256n12, 258n29; propositional truth, 12, 27, 256nn11,12, 258n29; sin-cerity (Wahrhaftigkeit), 12, 27, 256n12, 258n29; validity claims as criticizable, 12–13, 15, 16–17, 18–19, 40, 43, 257n19

Varela, Francisco: Autopoiesis and Cognition, 295n156

Vietnam War, 243

wage labor, 47, 59; commodification of, 54Weber, Max: on democracy, 29, 261n113;

vs. Habermas, 4, 5, 10, 20, 26–28, 29, 61, 116, 256n1, 289n37; on occidental rationalism, 256n1; on political legiti-macy, 5; postulate of social-scientific value-freedom, 27–28; on Protestant ethic of labor, 26, 27, 261n108; on ratio-nalization, 4, 20, 26–28, 173, 261n108; on social vs. ideal validity, 61; on social vs. nonsocial action, 10; on sociology of law, 5, 61; theory of action, 28

Weithman, Paul J.: on Catholic Church, 197–98, 297n46; on Rawls, 296n25; on realized citizenship, 197; on religion, 193, 196–99, 201, 207, 207–8, 296n24, 297n39, 299n94, 300n122

welfare-state services, 55–56, 67; basic rights regarding, 75, 77

Whittington, Keith, 144Wolterstorff, Robert: on religion, 193,

198–200, 201, 202–3, 208, 296n25, 298n66, 299n94

World Bank, 246world government/world state, 192, 228,

242, 245–46, 248, 251, 308n353, 309n367

World Trade Organization, 246

Young, Iris, 301n157

Zeit, Die, 5Zurn, Christopher: on constitutional re-

view, 144–45; on constructive interpre-tation, 279nn66,85; on justification and application, 123

Native Americans, 209, 211; PACs in, 139; redistricting in, 7, 138, 140–42, 285nn181–83, 286nn187,189,193; re-ligion in, 197–98, 199, 201; two-party framework in, 101; Voting Rights Act, 137, 209. See also United States Consti-tution; United States Supreme Court

United States Constitution: Bill of Rights, 305n273; First Amendment, 136, 139, 283n161; Fourteenth Amendment, 286n194; Fourth Amendment, 122–24; ratification of, 305n273; and redistrict-ing, 285n182

United States Supreme Court: Boumediene v. Bush, 286n201; Bowers v. Hardwick, 133–35; Brown v. Board of Education, 286n194; Buckley v. Valeo, 284n170; Citizens United v. FEC, 138–40, 283n161, 285n177; City of Boerne v. Flores, 286n194; Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, Inc., 294n147; Davis v. Bandemer, 285n186; decisions regarding corporate speech/campaign finance, 7, 138–40, 284nn170,175, 285nn177,178; decisions regarding insanity, 185, 294n146; decisions regarding legal vs. scientific inquiry, 185–86, 294n147; decisions regarding race-conscious dis-tricting, 209–10, 300n132; decisions regarding redistricting, 7, 141–42, 209–10, 300n132; decisions regarding third parties, 283n167; First National Bank v. Bellotti, 284n170; Justice Scalia, 122, 142, 280n76; Kansas v. Hendricks, 294n146; Kyllo v. United States, 122–24; LULAC v. Perry, 286n188; McConnell v. FEC, 284n175; Miller v. Johnson, 300n132; Reynolds v. Sims, 138; Shaw v. Reno, 300n132; subordinate rules fash-ioned by, 121–24; Thornburg v. Gingles, 300n130; Timmons v. Twin Cities Area New Party, 283n167; United States v. Carolene Products Co., 283n151; United States v. Morrison, 286n194; Vieth v. Jubelirer, 286n187; Yoder v. Wisconsin, 213–14, 219–20, 301nn151,152

validity vs. facticity, 6, 17, 62–64, 73–74, 82, 107–10, 116, 267nn10,14, 269n74

Page 347: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)
Page 348: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)

Jurists: Profiles in Legal Theory

general editor

William Twining

Thomas Garden Barnes, edited and with an introduction by Allen D. Boyer, Shaping the Common Law: From Glanvill to Hale, 1188–1688

William E. Conklin, Hegel’s Laws: The Legitimacy of a Modern Legal Order

Neil MacCormick, H. L. A. Hart, Second EditionWouter de Been, Legal Realism Regained:

Saving Realism from Critical Acclaim

John Dinwiddy, edited by William Twining, Bentham: Selected Writings of John Dinwiddy

Allen D. Boyer, Sir Edward Coke and the Elizabethan Age

Colin Imber, Ebu’s-su’ud: The Islamic Legal Tradition

Edited by Robert W. Gordon, The Legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr.

Page 349: (Jurists_ Profiles in Legal Theory ) Hugh Baxter-Habermas_ the Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy -Stanford Law Books (2011)