hy561/data/other/tata.pdf · contents introduction 9 preliminaries 13 1 recognizable tree languages...

222
Tree Automata Techniques and Applications Hubert Comon Max Dauchet Rmi Gilleron Florent Jacquemard Denis Lugiez Sophie Tison Marc Tommasi

Upload: others

Post on 12-May-2020

4 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

TreeAutomataTechniques andApplications

Hubert Comon Max Dauchet Rmi Gilleron

Florent Jacquemard Denis Lugiez Sophie Tison

Marc Tommasi

Page 2: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata
Page 3: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Contents

Introduction 9

Preliminaries 13

1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 171.1 Finite Tree Automata . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 181.2 The Pumping Lemma for Recognizable Tree Languages . . . . . 261.3 Closure Properties of Recognizable Tree Languages . . . . . . . . 271.4 Tree Homomorphisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 291.5 Minimizing Tree Automata . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 331.6 Top Down Tree Automata . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 361.7 Decision Problems and their Complexity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 371.8 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 411.9 Bibliographic Notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45

2 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions 492.1 Tree Grammar . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49

2.1.1 Definitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 492.1.2 Regularity and Recognizabilty . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52

2.2 Regular Expressions. Kleene’s Theorem for Tree Languages . . . 522.2.1 Substitution and Iteration . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 532.2.2 Regular Expressions and Regular Tree Languages . . . . . 56

2.3 Regular Equations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 592.4 Context-free Word Languages and Regular Tree Languages . . . 612.5 Beyond Regular Tree Languages: Context-free Tree Languages . 64

2.5.1 Context-free Tree Languages . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 652.5.2 IO and OI Tree Grammars . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65

2.6 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 672.7 Bibliographic notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 69

3 Logic, Automata and Relations 713.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 713.2 Automata on Tuples of Finite Trees . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 73

3.2.1 Three Notions of Recognizability . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 733.2.2 Examples of The Three Notions of Recognizability . . . . 753.2.3 Comparisons Between the Three Classes . . . . . . . . . . 773.2.4 Closure Properties for Rec× and Rec; Cylindrification and

Projection . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 78

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 4: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4 CONTENTS

3.2.5 Closure of GTT by Composition and Iteration . . . . . . 803.3 The Logic WSkS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 86

3.3.1 Syntax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 863.3.2 Semantics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 863.3.3 Examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 863.3.4 Restricting the Syntax . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 883.3.5 Definable Sets are Recognizable Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . 893.3.6 Recognizable Sets are Definable . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 923.3.7 Complexity Issues . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 943.3.8 Extensions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 94

3.4 Examples of Applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 953.4.1 Terms and Sorts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 953.4.2 The Encompassment Theory for Linear Terms . . . . . . 963.4.3 The First-order Theory of a Reduction Relation: the Case

Where no Variables are Shared . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 983.4.4 Reduction Strategies . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 993.4.5 Application to Rigid E-unification . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1013.4.6 Application to Higher-order Matching . . . . . . . . . . . 102

3.5 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1043.6 Bibliographic Notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108

3.6.1 GTT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1083.6.2 Automata and Logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1083.6.3 Surveys . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1083.6.4 Applications of tree automata to constraint solving . . . . 1083.6.5 Application of tree automata to semantic unification . . . 1093.6.6 Application of tree automata to decision problems in term

rewriting . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1093.6.7 Other applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 110

4 Automata with Constraints 1114.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1114.2 Automata with Equality and Disequality Constraints . . . . . . . 112

4.2.1 The Most General Class . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1124.2.2 Reducing Non-determinism and Closure Properties . . . . 1154.2.3 Undecidability of Emptiness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 118

4.3 Automata with Constraints Between Brothers . . . . . . . . . . . 1194.3.1 Closure Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1194.3.2 Emptiness Decision . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1214.3.3 Applications . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125

4.4 Reduction Automata . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1254.4.1 Definition and Closure Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1264.4.2 Emptiness Decision . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1274.4.3 Finiteness Decision . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1294.4.4 Term Rewriting Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1294.4.5 Application to the Reducibility Theory . . . . . . . . . . 130

4.5 Other Decidable Subclasses . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1304.6 Tree Automata with Arithmetic Constraints . . . . . . . . . . . . 131

4.6.1 Flat Trees . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1314.6.2 Automata with Arithmetic Constraints . . . . . . . . . . 1324.6.3 Reducing Non-determinism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 134

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 5: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

CONTENTS 5

4.6.4 Closure Properties of Semilinear Flat Languages . . . . . 1364.6.5 Emptiness Decision . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 137

4.7 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1404.8 Bibliographic notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 143

5 Tree Set Automata 1455.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1455.2 Definitions and Examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 150

5.2.1 Generalized Tree Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1505.2.2 Tree Set Automata . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1505.2.3 Hierarchy of GTSA-recognizable Languages . . . . . . . . 1535.2.4 Regular Generalized Tree Sets, Regular Runs . . . . . . . 154

5.3 Closure and Decision Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1575.3.1 Closure properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1575.3.2 Emptiness Property . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1605.3.3 Other Decision Results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 162

5.4 Applications to Set Constraints . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1635.4.1 Definitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1635.4.2 Set Constraints and Automata . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1635.4.3 Decidability Results for Set Constraints . . . . . . . . . . 164

5.5 Bibliographical Notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 166

6 Tree Transducers 1696.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1696.2 The Word Case . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 170

6.2.1 Introduction to Rational Transducers . . . . . . . . . . . 1706.2.2 The Homomorphic Approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 174

6.3 Introduction to Tree Transducers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1756.4 Properties of Tree Transducers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 179

6.4.1 Bottom-up Tree Transducers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1796.4.2 Top-down Tree Transducers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1826.4.3 Structural Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1846.4.4 Complexity Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 185

6.5 Homomorphisms and Tree Transducers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1856.6 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1876.7 Bibliographic notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 189

7 Alternating Tree Automata 1917.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1917.2 Definitions and Examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191

7.2.1 Alternating Word Automata . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1917.2.2 Alternating Tree Automata . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1937.2.3 Tree Automata versus Alternating Word Automata . . . . 194

7.3 Closure Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1967.4 From Alternating to Deterministic Automata . . . . . . . . . . . 1977.5 Decision Problems and Complexity Issues . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1977.6 Horn Logic, Set Constraints and Alternating Automata . . . . . 198

7.6.1 The Clausal Formalism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1987.6.2 The Set Constraints Formalism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1997.6.3 Two Way Alternating Tree Automata . . . . . . . . . . . 200

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 6: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6 CONTENTS

7.6.4 Two Way Automata and Definite Set Constraints . . . . . 2027.6.5 Two Way Automata and Pushdown Automata . . . . . . 203

7.7 An (other) example of application . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2037.8 Exercises . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2047.9 Bibliographic Notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 205

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 7: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

CONTENTS 7

Acknowledgments

Many people gave substantial suggestions to improve the contents of thisbook. These are, in alphabetic order, Witold Charatonik, Zoltan Flp, WernerKuich, Markus Lohrey, Jun Matsuda, Aart Middeldorp, Hitoshi Ohsaki, SanjivaPrasad, Masahiko Sakai, Helmut Seidl, Stephan Tobies, Ralf Treinen, ThomasUribe, Sandor Vgvlgyi, Kumar Neeraj Verma, Toshiyuki Yamada.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 8: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

8 CONTENTS

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 9: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Introduction

During the past few years, several of us have been asked many times aboutreferences on finite tree automata. On one hand, this is the witness of the live-ness of this field. On the other hand, it was difficult to answer. Besides severalexcellent survey chapters on more specific topics, there is only one monographdevoted to tree automata by Gcseg and Steinby. Unfortunately, it is now impos-sible to find a copy of it and a lot of work has been done on tree automata sincethe publication of this book. Actually using tree automata has proved to be apowerful approach to simplify and extend previously known results, and also tofind new results. For instance recent works use tree automata for applicationin abstract interpretation using set constraints, rewriting, automated theoremproving and program verification, databases and XML schema languages.

Tree automata have been designed a long time ago in the context of circuitverification. Many famous researchers contributed to this school which washeaded by A. Church in the late 50’s and the early 60’s: B. Trakhtenbrot,J.R. Bchi, M.O. Rabin, Doner, Thatcher, etc. Many new ideas came out ofthis program. For instance the connections between automata and logic. Treeautomata also appeared first in this framework, following the work of Doner,Thatcher and Wright. In the 70’s many new results were established concerningtree automata, which lose a bit their connections with the applications and werestudied for their own. In particular, a problem was the very high complexityof decision procedures for the monadic second order logic. Applications of treeautomata to program verification revived in the 80’s, after the relative failureof automated deduction in this field. It is possible to verify temporal logicformulas (which are particular Monadic Second Order Formulas) on simpler(small) programs. Automata, and in particular tree automata, also appearedas an approximation of programs on which fully automated tools can be used.New results were obtained connecting properties of programs or type systemsor rewrite systems with automata.

Our goal is to fill in the existing gap and to provide a textbook which presentsthe basics of tree automata and several variants of tree automata which havebeen devised for applications in the aforementioned domains. We shall discussonly finite tree automata, and the reader interested in infinite trees should con-sult any recent survey on automata on infinite objects and their applications(See the bibliography). The second main restriction that we have is to focus onthe operational aspects of tree automata. This book should appeal the readerwho wants to have a simple presentation of the basics of tree automata, andto see how some variations on the idea of tree automata have provided a nicetool for solving difficult problems. Therefore, specialists of the domain probablyknow almost all the material embedded. However, we think that this book can

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 10: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

10 Introduction

be helpful for many researchers who need some knowledge on tree automata.This is typically the case of PhD a student who may find new ideas and guessconnections with his (her) own work.

Again, we recall that there is no presentation nor discussion of tree automatafor infinite trees. This domain is also in full development mainly due to appli-cations in program verification and several surveys on this topic do exist. Wehave tried to present a tool and the algorithms devised for this tool. Therefore,most of the proofs that we give are constructive and we have tried to give asmany complexity results as possible. We don’t claim to present an exhaustivedescription of all possible finite tree automata already presented in the literatureand we did some choices in the existing menagerie of tree automata. Althoughsome works are not described thoroughly (but they are usually described in ex-ercises), we think that the content of this book gives a good flavor of what canbe done with the simple ideas supporting tree automata.

This book is an open work and we want it to be as interactive as possible.Readers and specialists are invited to provide suggestions and improvements.Submissions of contributions to new chapters and improvements of existing onesare welcome.

Among some of our choices, let us mention that we have not defined anyprecise language for describing algorithms which are given in some pseudo algo-rithmic language. Also, there is no citation in the text, but each chapter endswith a section devoted to bibliographical notes where credits are made to therelevant authors. Exercises are also presented at the end of each chapter.

Tree Automata and Their Applications is composed of six main chapters(numbered 1– 6). The first one presents tree automata and defines recognizabletree languages. The reader will find the classical algorithms and the classicalclosure properties of the class of recognizable tree languages. Complexity re-sults are given when they are available. The second chapter gives alternativepresentation of recognizable tree languages which may be more relevant in somesituations. This includes regular tree grammars, regular tree expressions andregular equations. The description of properties relating regular tree languagesand context-free word languages form the last part of this chapter. In Chap-ter 3, we show the deep connections between logic and automata. In particular,we prove in full details the correspondence between finite tree automata andthe weak monadic second order logic with k successors. We also sketch severalapplications in various domains.

Chapter 4 presents a basic variation of automata, more precisely automatawith equality constraints. An equality constraint restricts the application ofrules to trees where some subtrees are equal (with respect to some equalityrelation). Therefore we can discriminate more easily between trees that wewant to accept and trees that we must reject. Several kinds of constraints aredescribed, both originating from the problem of non-linearity in trees (the samevariable may occur at different positions).

In Chapter 5 we consider automata which recognize sets of sets of terms.Such automata appeared in the context of set constraints which themselves areused in program analysis. The idea is to consider, for each variable or eachpredicate symbol occurring in a program, the set of its possible values. Theprogram gives constraints that these sets must satisfy. Solving the constraintsgives an upper approximation of the values that a given variable can take. Suchan approximation can be used to detect errors at compile time: it acts exactly as

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 11: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Introduction 11

a typing system which would be inferred from the program. Tree set automata(as we call them) recognize the sets of solutions of such constraints (hence setsof sets of trees). In this chapter we study the properties of tree set automataand their relationship with program analysis.

Originally, automata were invented as an intermediate between function de-scription and their implementation by a circuit. The main related problem inthe sixties was the synthesis problem: which arithmetic recursive functions canbe achieved by a circuit ? So far, we only considered tree automata which ac-cepts sets of trees or sets of tuples of trees (Chapter 3 or sets of sets of trees(Chapter 5). However, tree automata can also be used as a computationaldevice. This is the subject of Chapter 6 where we study tree transducers.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 12: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

12 Introduction

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 13: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Preliminaries

Terms

We denote by N the set of positive integers. We denote the set of finite stringsover N by N∗. The empty string is denoted by ε.

A ranked alphabet is a couple (F ,Arity) where F is a finite set and Arity isa mapping from F into N . The arity of a symbol f ∈ F is Arity(f). The set ofsymbols of arity p is denoted by Fp. Elements of arity 0, 1, . . . p are respectivelycalled constants, unary, . . . , p-ary symbols. We assume that F contains at leastone constant. In the examples, we use parenthesis and commas for a shortdeclaration of symbols with arity. For instance, f(, ) is a short declaration for abinary symbol f .

Let X be a set of constants called variables. We assume that the sets Xand F0 are disjoint. The set T (F ,X ) of terms over the ranked alphabet F andthe set of variables X is the smallest set defined by:

- F0 ⊆ T (F ,X ) and- X ⊆ T (F ,X ) and- if p ≥ 1, f ∈ Fp and t1, . . . , tp ∈ T (F ,X ), then f(t1, . . . , tp) ∈ T (F ,X ).If X = ∅ then T (F ,X ) is also written T (F). Terms in T (F) are called

ground terms. A term t in T (F ,X ) is linear if each variable occurs at mostonce in t.

Example 1. Let F = cons(, ), nil, a and X = x, y. Here cons is abinary symbol, nil and a are constants. The term cons(x, y) is linear; theterm cons(x, cons(x, nil)) is non linear; the term cons(a, cons(a, nil)) is a groundterm. Terms can be represented in a graphical way. For instance, the termcons(a, cons(a, nil)) is represented by:

a

a nil

cons

cons

Terms and Trees

A finite ordered tree t over a set of labels E is a mapping from a prefix-closedset Pos(t) ⊆ N∗ into E. Thus, a term t ∈ T (F ,X ) may be viewed as a finite

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 14: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

14 Preliminaries

ordered ranked tree, the leaves of which are labeled with variables or constantsymbols and the internal nodes are labeled with symbols of positive arity, without-degree equal to the arity of the label, i.e. a term t ∈ T (F ,X ) can also bedefined as a partial function t : N∗ → F ∪X with domain Pos(t) satisfying thefollowing properties:

(i) Pos(t) is nonempty and prefix-closed.

(ii) ∀p ∈ Pos(t), if t(p) ∈ Fn, n ≥ 1, then j | pj ∈ Pos(t) = 1, . . . , n.

(iii) ∀p ∈ Pos(t), if t(p) ∈ X ∪ F0, then j | pj ∈ Pos(t) = ∅.

We confuse terms and trees, that is we only consider finite ordered ranked treessatisfying (i), (ii) and (iii). The reader should note that finite ordered trees withbounded rank k – i.e. there is a bound k on the out-degrees of internal nodes –can be encoded in finite ordered ranked trees: a label e ∈ E is associated withk symbols (e, 1) of arity 1, . . . , (e, k) of arity k.

Each element in Pos(t) is called a position. A frontier position is aposition p such that ∀j ∈ N , pj 6∈ Pos(t). The set of frontier positions isdenoted by FPos(t). Each position p in t such that t(p) ∈ X is called a variable

position. The set of variable positions of p is denoted by VPos(t). We denoteby Head(t) the root symbol of t which is defined by Head(t) = t(ε).

SubTerms

A subterm t|p of a term t ∈ T (F ,X ) at position p is defined by the following:

- Pos(t|p) = j | pj ∈ Pos(t),- ∀q ∈ Pos(t|p), t|p(q) = t(pq).

We denote by t[u]p the term obtained by replacing in t the subterm t|p byu.

We denote by ¥ the subterm ordering , i.e. we write t ¥ t′ if t′ is a subtermof t. We denote t ¤ t′ if t ¥ t′ and t 6= t′.

A set of terms F is said to be closed if it is closed under the subtermordering, i.e. ∀t ∈ F (t ¥ t′ ⇒ t′ ∈ F ).

Functions on Terms

The size of a term t, denoted by ‖t‖ and the height of t, denoted by Height(t)are inductively defined by:

- Height(t) = 0, ‖t‖ = 0 if t ∈ X ,- Height(t) = 1, ‖t‖ = 1 if t ∈ F0,- Height(t) = 1+max(Height(ti) | i ∈ 1, . . . , n), ‖t‖ = 1+

∑i∈1,...,n ‖ti‖

if Head(t) ∈ Fn.

Example 2. Let F = f(, , ), g(, ), h(), a, b and X = x, y. Consider theterms

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 15: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Preliminaries 15

t =

a b

g a

b

h

f

; t′ =

x1 x2

g a

x2 x1

g

f

The root symbol of t is f ; the set of frontier positions of t is 11, 12, 2, 31; theset of variable positions of t′ is 11, 12, 31, 32; t|3 = h(b); t[a]3 = f(g(a, b), a, a);Height(t) = 3; Height(t′) = 2; ‖t‖ = 7; ‖t′‖ = 4.

Substitutions

A substitution (respectively a ground substitution) σ is a mapping from Xinto T (F ,X ) (respectively into T (F)) where there are only finitely many vari-ables not mapped to themselves. The domain of a substitution σ is the subsetof variables x ∈ X such that σ(x) 6= x. The substitution x1←t1, . . . , xn←tnis the identity on X \ x1, . . . , xn and maps xi ∈ X on ti ∈ T (F ,X ), for everyindex 1 ≤ i ≤ n. Substitutions can be extended to T (F ,X ) in such a way that:

∀f ∈ Fn,∀t1, . . . , tn ∈ T (F ,X ) σ(f(t1, . . . , tn)) = f(σ(t1), . . . , σ(tn)).

We confuse a substitution and its extension to T (F ,X ). Substitutions willoften be used in postfix notation: tσ is the result of applying σ to the term t.

Example 3. Let F = f(, , ), g(, ), a, b and X = x1, x2. Let us considerthe term t = f(x1, x1, x2). Let us consider the ground substitution σ = x1←a, x2←g(b, b) and the substitution σ′ = x1←x2, x2←b. Then

tσ = tx1←a, x2←g(b, b) =a a

b b

g

f

; tσ′ = tx1←x2, x2←b =x2 x2 b

f

Contexts

Let Xn be a set of n variables. A linear term C ∈ T (F ,Xn) is called a context

and the expression C[t1, . . . , tn] for t1, . . . , tn ∈ T (F) denotes the term in T (F)obtained from C by replacing variable xi by ti for each 1 ≤ i ≤ n, that isC[t1, . . . , tn] = Cx1← t1, . . . , xn← tn. We denote by Cn(F) the set of contextsover (x1, . . . , xn).

We denote by C(F) the set of contexts containing a single variable. A contextis trivial if it is reduced to a variable. Given a context C ∈ C(F), we denoteby C0 the trivial context, C1 is equal to C and, for n > 1, Cn = Cn−1[C] is acontext in C(F).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 16: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata
Page 17: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Chapter 1

Recognizable TreeLanguages and Finite TreeAutomata

In this chapter, we present basic results on finite tree automata in the style ofthe undergraduate textbook on finite automata by Hopcroft and Ullman [HU79].Finite tree automata deal with finite ordered ranked trees or finite ordered treeswith bounded rank. We discuss unordered and/or unranked finite trees in thebibliographic notes (Section 1.9). We assume that the reader is familiar withfinite automata. Words over finite alphabet can be viewed as unary terms. Forinstance a word abb over A = a, b can be viewed as a unary term t = a(b(b(])))over the ranked alphabet F = a(), b(), ] where ] is a new constant symbol.The theory of tree automata arises as a straightforward extension of the theoryof word automata when words are viewed as unary terms.

In Section 1.1, we define bottom-up finite tree automata where “bottom-up”has the following sense: assuming a graphical representation of trees or groundterms with the root symbol at the top, an automaton starts its computation atthe leaves and moves upward. Recognizable tree languages are the languagesrecognized by some finite tree automata. We consider the deterministic caseand the nondeterministic case and prove the equivalence. In Section 1.2, weprove a pumping lemma for recognizable tree languages. This lemma is usefulfor proving that some tree languages are not recognizable. In Section 1.3, weprove the basic closure properties for set operations. In Section 1.4, we definetree homomorphisms and study the closure properties under these tree trans-formations. In this Section the first difference between the word case and thetree case appears. Indeed, if recognizable word languages are closed under ho-momorphisms, recognizable tree languages are closed only under a subclass oftree homomorphisms: linear homomorphisms, where duplication of trees is for-bidden. We will see all along this textbook that non linearity is one of the maindifficulty for the tree case. In Section 1.5, we prove a Myhill-Nerode Theoremfor tree languages and the existence of a unique minimal automaton. In Sec-tion 1.6, we define top-down tree automata. A second difference appears withthe word case because it is proved that deterministic top-down tree automataare strictly less powerful than nondeterministic ones. The last section of the

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 18: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

18 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

present chapter gives a list of complexity results.

1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Nondeterministic Finite Tree Automata

A finite Tree Automaton (NFTA) over F is a tuple A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) whereQ is a set of (unary) states, Qf ⊆ Q is a set of final states, and ∆ is a set oftransition rules of the following type:

f(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)) → q(f(x1, . . . , xn)),

where n ≥ 0, f ∈ Fn, q, q1, . . . , qn ∈ Q, x1, . . . , xn ∈ X .

Tree automata over F run on ground terms over F . An automaton starts atthe leaves and moves upward, associating along a run a state with each subterminductively. Let us note that there is no initial state in a NFTA, but, whenn = 0, i.e. when the symbol is a constant symbol a, a transition rule is ofthe form a → q(a). Therefore, the transition rules for the constant symbolscan be considered as the “initial rules”. If the direct subterms u1, . . . , un oft = f(u1, . . . , un) are labeled with states q1, . . . , qn, then the term t will belabeled by some state q with f(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)) → q(f(x1, . . . , xn)) ∈ ∆. Wenow formally define the move relation defined by an NFTA.

Let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) be an NFTA over F . The move relation →A isdefined by: let t, t′ ∈ T (F ∪ Q),

t→A

t′ ⇔

∃C ∈ C(F ∪ Q),∃u1, . . . , un ∈ T (F),

∃f(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)) → q(f(x1, . . . , xn)) ∈ ∆,

t = C[f(q1(u1), . . . , qn(un))],

t′ = C[q(f(u1, . . . , un))].

∗−→A

is the reflexive and transitive closure of →A.

Example 4. Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Consider the automaton A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆)defined by: Q = qa, qg, qf, Qf = qf, and ∆ is the following set of transitionrules:

a → qa(a) g(qa(x)) → qg(g(x))g(qg(x)) → qg(g(x)) f(qg(x), qg(y)) → qf (f(x, y))

We give two examples of reductions with the move relation →A

a a

f

→A

a

qa a

f

→A

a

qa

a

qa

f

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 19: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.1 Finite Tree Automata 19

a

g

a

g

f∗−→A

a

qa

g

a

qa

g

f∗−→A

a

g

qg

a

g

qg

f

→A

a

g

a

g

f

qf

A ground term t in T (F) is accepted by a finite tree automaton A =(Q,F , Qf ,∆) if

t∗−→A

q(t)

for some state q in Qf . The reader should note that our definition correspondsto the notion of nondeterministic finite tree automaton because our finite treeautomaton model allows zero, one or more transition rules with the same left-hand side. Therefore there are possibly more than one reduction starting withthe same ground term. And, a ground term t is accepted if there is one reduction(among all possible reductions) starting from this ground term and leading to aconfiguration of the form q(t) where q is a final state. The tree language L(A)recognized by A is the set of all ground terms accepted by A. A set L of groundterms is recognizable if L = L(A) for some NFTA A. The reader should alsonote that when we talk about the set recognized by a finite tree automaton Awe are referring to the specific set L(A), not just any set of ground terms all ofwhich happen to be accepted by A. Two NFTA are said to be equivalent ifthey recognize the same tree languages.

Example 5. Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Consider the automaton A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆)defined by: Q = q, qg, qf, Qf = qf, and ∆ =

a → q(a) g(q(x)) → q(g(x))g(q(x)) → qg(g(x)) g(qg(x)) → qf (g(x))

f(q(x), q(y)) → q(f(x, y)) .

We now consider a ground term t and exhibit three different reductions ofterm t w.r.t. move relation →A.

t = g(g(f(g(a), a)))∗−→A

g(g(f(qg(g(a)), q(a))))

t = g(g(f(g(a), a)))∗−→A

g(g(q(f(g(a), a))))∗−→A

q(t)

t = g(g(f(g(a), a)))∗−→A

g(g(q(f(g(a), a))))∗−→A

qf (t)

The term t is accepted by A because of the third reduction. It is easy toprove that L(A) = g(g(t)) | t ∈ T (F) is the set of ground instances of g(g(x)).

The set of transition rules of a NFTA A can also be defined as a groundrewrite system, i.e. a set of ground transition rules of the form: f(q1, . . . , qn) →q. A move relation →A can be defined like previously. The only difference is

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 20: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

20 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

that, now, we “forget” the ground subterms. And, a term t is accepted by aNFTA A if

t∗−→A

q

for some final state q in Qf . Unless it is stated otherwise, we will now referto the definition with a set of ground transition rules. Considering a reductionstarting from a ground term t and leading to a state q with the move relation,it is useful to remember the “history” of the reduction, i.e. to remember inwhich states are reduced the ground subterms of t. For this, we will adopt thefollowing definitions. Let t be a ground term and A be a NFTA, a run r of Aon t is a mapping r : Pos(t) → Q compatible with ∆, i.e. for every positionp in Pos(t), if t(p) = f ∈ Fn, r(p) = q, r(pi) = qi for each i ∈ 1, . . . , n, thenf(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆. A run r of A on t is successful if r(ε) is a final state.And a ground term t is accepted by a NFTA A if there is a successful run r ofA on t.

Example 6. Let F = or(, ), and(, ), not(), 0, 1. Consider the automatonA = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) defined by: Q = q0, q1, Qf = q1, and ∆ =

0 → q0 1 → q1

not(q0) → q1 not(q1) → q0

and(q0, q0) → q0 and(q0, q1) → q0

and(q1, q0) → q0 and(q1, q1) → q1

or(q0, q0) → q0 or(q0, q1) → q1

or(q1, q0) → q1 or(q1, q1) → q1 .

A ground term over F can be viewed as a boolean formula without variable and arun on such a ground term can be viewed as the evaluation of the correspondingboolean formula. For instance, we give a reduction for a ground term t and thecorresponding run given as a tree

0 1

or

not

1

0

not

or

and∗−→A

q0 ; the run r:

q0 q1

q1

q0

q1

q0

q1

q1

q0

The tree language recognized by A is the set of true boolean expressions overF .

NFTA with ε-rules

Like in the word case, it is convenient to allow ε-moves in the reduction ofa ground term by an automaton, i.e. the current state is changed but no newsymbol of the term is processed. This is done by introducing a new type of rulesin the set of transition rules of an automaton. A NFTA with ε-rules is likea NFTA except that now the set of transition rules contains ground transition

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 21: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.1 Finite Tree Automata 21

rules of the form f(q1, . . . , qn) → q, and ε-rules of the form q → q′. The abilityto make ε-moves does not allow the NFTA to accept non recognizable sets. ButNFTA with ε-rules are useful in some constructions and simplify some proofs.

Example 7. Let F = cons(, ), s(), 0, nil. Consider the automaton A =(Q,F , Qf ,∆) defined by: Q = qNat, qList, qList∗, Qf = qList, and ∆ =

0 → qNat s(qNat) → qNat

nil → qList cons(qNat, qList) → qList∗

qList∗ → qList.

The recognized tree language is the set of Lisp-like lists of integers. If the finalstate set Qf is set to qList∗, then the recognized tree language is the set ofnon empty Lisp-like lists of integers. The ε-rule qList∗ → qList says that a nonempty list is a list. The reader should recognize the definition of an order-sortedalgebra with the sorts Nat, List, and List∗ (which stands for the non empty lists),and the inclusion List∗ ⊆ List (see Section 3.4.1).

Theorem 1 (The equivalence of NFTA’s with and without ε-rules). IfL is recognized by a NFTA with ε-rules, then L is recognized by a NFTA withoutε-rules.

Proof. Let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) be a NFTA with ε-rules. Consider the subset ∆ε

consisting of those ε-rules in ∆. We denote by ε-closure(q) the set of all statesq′ in Q such that there is a reduction of q into q′ using rules in ∆ε. We considerthat q ∈ ε-closure(q). This computation is a transitive closure computation andcan be done in O(|Q|3). Now let us define the NFTA A′ = (Q,F , Qf ,∆′) where∆′ is defined by:

∆′ = f(q1, . . . , qn) → q′ | f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆, q′ ∈ ε-closure(q)

Then it may be proved that t∗−→A

q iff t∗

−−→A′

q.

Unless it is stated otherwise, we will now consider NFTA without ε-rules.

Deterministic Finite Tree Automata

Our definition of tree automata corresponds to the notion of nondeterministicfinite tree automata. We will now define deterministic tree automata (DFTA)which are a special case of NFTA. It will turn out that, like in the word case, anylanguage recognized by a NFTA can also be recognized by a DFTA. However,the NFTA are useful in proving theorems in tree language theory.

A tree automaton A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) is deterministic (DFTA) if there areno two rules with the same left-hand side (and no ε-rule). Given a DFTA, thereis at most one run for every ground term, i.e. for every ground term t, there isat most one state q such that t

∗−→A

q. The reader should note that it is possible

to define a tree automaton in which there are two rules with the same left-handside such that there is at most one run for every ground term (see Example 8).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 22: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

22 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

It is also useful to consider tree automata such that there is at least onerun for every ground term. This leads to the following definition. A NFTA Ais complete if there is at least one rule f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆ for all n ≥ 0,f ∈ Fn, and q1, . . . , qn ∈ Q. Let us note that for a complete DFTA there isexactly one run for every ground term.

Lastly, for practical reasons, it is usual to consider automata in which un-necessary states are eliminated. A state q is accessible if there exists a groundterm t such that t

∗−→A

q. A NFTA A is said to be reduced if all its states are

accessible.

Example 8.The automaton defined in Example 5 is reduced, not complete, and it is not

deterministic because there are two rules of left-hand side g(q(x)). Let us alsonote (see Example 5) that at least two runs (one is successful) can be definedon the term g(g(f(g(a), a))).

The automaton defined in Example 6 is a complete and reduced DFTA.Let F = g(), a. Consider the automaton A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) defined by:

Q = q0, q1, q, Qf = q0, and ∆ is the following set of transition rules:

a → q0 g(q0) → q1

g(q1) → q0 g(q) → q0

g(q) → q1.

This automaton is not deterministic because there are two rules of left-handside g(q), it is not reduced because state q is not accessible. Nevertheless, oneshould note that there is at most one run for every ground term t.

Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Consider the automaton A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) definedin Example 4 by: Q = qa, qg, qf, Qf = qf, and ∆ is the following set oftransition rules:

a → qa g(qa) → qg

g(qg) → qg f(qg, qg) → qf .

This automaton is deterministic and reduced. It is not complete because, forinstance, there is no transition rule of left-hand side f(qa, qa). It is easy to definea deterministic and complete automaton A′ recognizing the same language byadding a “dead state”. The automaton A′ = (Q′,F , Qf ,∆′) is defined by:Q′ = Q ∪ π, ∆′ = ∆∪

g(qf ) → π g(π) → πf(qa, qa) → π f(qa, qg) → π

. . . f(π, π) → π .

It is easy to generalize the construction given in Example 8 of a completeNFTA equivalent to a given NFTA: add a “dead state” π and all transitionrules with right-hand side π such that the automaton is complete. The readershould note that this construction could be expensive because it may requireO(|F| × |Q|Arity(F)) new rules where Arity(F) is the maximal arity of symbolsin F . Therefore we have the following:

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 23: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.1 Finite Tree Automata 23

Theorem 2. Let L be a recognizable set of ground terms. Then there exists acomplete finite tree automaton that accepts L.

We now give a polynomial algorithm which outputs a reduced NFTA equiv-alent to a given NFTA as input. The main loop of this algorithm computes theset of accessible states.

Reduction Algorithm REDinput: NFTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆)begin

Set Marked to ∅ /* Marked is the set of accessible states */repeat

Set Marked to Marked ∪ qwhere

f ∈ Fn, q1, . . . , qn ∈ Marked , f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆until no state can be added to MarkedSet Qr to MarkedSet Qrf

to Qf ∩ MarkedSet ∆r to f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆ | q, q1, . . . , qn ∈ Markedoutput: NFTA Ar = (Qr,F , Qrf

,∆r)end

Obviously all states in the set Marked are accessible, and an easy inductionshows that all accessible states are in the set Marked . And, the NFTA Ar

accepts the tree language L(A). Consequently we have:

Theorem 3. Let L be a recognizable set of ground terms. Then there exists areduced finite tree automaton that accepts L.

Now, we consider the reduction of nondeterminism. Since every DFTA isa NFTA, it is clear that the class of recognizable languages includes the classof languages accepted by DFTA’s. However it turns out that these classes areequal. We prove that, for every NFTA, we can construct an equivalent DFTA.The proof is similar to the proof of equivalence between DFA’s and NFA’s inthe word case. The proof is based on the “subset construction”. Consequently,the number of states of the equivalent DFTA can be exponential in the numberof states of the given NFTA (see Example 10). But, in practice, it often turnsout that many states are not accessible. Therefore, we will present in the proofof the following theorem a construction of a DFTA where only the accessiblestates are considered, i.e. the given algorithm outputs an equivalent and reducedDFTA from a given NFTA as input.

Theorem 4 (The equivalence of DFTA’s and NFTA’s). Let L be a rec-ognizable set of ground terms. Then there exists a DFTA that accepts L.

Proof. First, we give a theoretical construction of a DFTA equivalent to aNFTA. Let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) be a NFTA. Define a DFTA Ad = (Qd,F , Qdf

,∆d),as follows. The states of Qd are all the subsets of the state set Q of A. Thatis, Qd = 2Q. We denote by s a state of Qd, i.e. s = q1, . . . , qn for some states

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 24: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

24 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

q1, . . . , qn ∈ Q. We define

f(s1, . . . , sn) → s ∈ ∆d

iff

s = q ∈ Q | ∃q1 ∈ s1, . . . ,∃qn ∈ sn, f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆.

And Qdfis the set of all states in Qd containing a final state of A.

We now give an algorithmic construction where only the accessible statesare considered.

Determinization Algorithm DETinput: NFTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆)begin

/* A state s of the equivalent DFTA is in 2Q */Set Qd to ∅; set ∆d to ∅repeat

Set Qd to Qd ∪ s; Set ∆d to ∆d ∪ f(s1, . . . , sn) → swhere

f ∈ Fn, s1, . . . , sn ∈ Qd,s = q ∈ Q | ∃q1 ∈ s1, . . . , qn ∈ sn, f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆

until no rule can be added to ∆d

Set Qdfto s ∈ Qd | s ∩ Qf 6= ∅

output: DFTA Ad = (Qd,F , Qdf,∆d)

end

It is immediate from the definition of the determinization algorithm thatAd is a deterministic and reduced tree automaton. In order to prove thatL(A) = L(Ad), we now prove that:

(t∗

−−→Ad

s) iff (s = q ∈ Q | t∗−→A

q).

The proof is an easy induction on the structure of terms.

• base case: let us consider t = a ∈ F0. Then, there is only one rule a → sin ∆d where s = q ∈ Q | a → q ∈ ∆.

• induction step: let us consider a term t = f(t1, . . . , tn).

– First, let us suppose that t∗

−−→Ad

f(s1, . . . , sn)→Ads. By induction

hypothesis, for each i ∈ 1, . . . , n, si = q ∈ Q | ti∗−→A

q. states si

are in Qd, thus a rule f(s1, . . . , sn) → s ∈ ∆d is added in the set ∆d

by the determinization algorithm and s = q ∈ Q | ∃q1 ∈ s1, . . . , qn ∈

sn, f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆. Thus, s = q ∈ Q | t∗−→A

q.

– Second, let us consider s = q ∈ Q | t = f(t1, . . . , tn)∗−→A

q. Let

us consider the state sets si defined by si = q ∈ Q | ti∗−→A

q.

By induction hypothesis, for each i ∈ 1, . . . , n, ti∗

−−→Ad

si. Thus

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 25: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.1 Finite Tree Automata 25

s = q ∈ Q | ∃q1 ∈ s1, . . . , qn ∈ sn, f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆. Therule f(s1, . . . , sn) ∈ ∆d by definition of the state set ∆d in the deter-

minization algorithm and t∗

−−→Ad

s.

Example 9. Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Consider the automaton A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆)defined in Example 5 by: Q = q, qg, qf, Qf = qf, and ∆ =

a → q g(q) → qg(q) → qg g(qg) → qf

f(q, q) → q .

Given A as input, the determinization algorithm outputs the DFTA Ad =(Qd,F , Qdf

,∆d) defined by: Qd = q, q, qg, q, qg, qf, Qdf= q, qg, qf,

and ∆d =

a → qg(q) → q, qg

g(q, qg) → q, qg, qfg(q, qg, qf) → q, qg, qf

∪ f(s1, s2) → q | s1, s2 ∈ Qd .

We now give an example where an exponential blow-up occurs in the deter-minization process. This example is the same used in the word case.

Example 10. Let F = f(), g(), a and let n be an integer. And let us considerthe tree language

L = t ∈ T (F) | the symbol at position 1n is f.

Let us consider the NFTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) defined by: Q = q, q1, . . . , qn+1,Qf = qn+1, and ∆ =

a → q f(q) → qg(q) → q f(q) → q1

g(q1) → q2 f(q1) → q2

. . .g(qn) → qn+1 f(qn) → qn+1 .

The NFTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) accepts the tree language L, and it has n + 2states. Using the subset construction, the equivalent DFTA Ad has 2n+1 states.Any equivalent automaton has to memorize the n + 1 last symbols of the inputtree. Therefore, it can be proved that any DFTA accepting L has at least 2n+1

states. It could also be proved that The automaton Ad is minimal in the numberof states (minimal tree automata are defined in Section 1.5).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 26: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

26 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

If a finite tree automaton is deterministic, we can replace the transitionrelation ∆ by a transition function δ. Therefore, it is sometimes convenient toconsider a DFTA A = (Q,F , Qf , δ) where

δ :⋃

n

Fn × Qn → Q .

The computation of such an automaton on a term t as input tree can be viewedas an evaluation of t on finite domain Q. Indeed, define the labeling functionδ : T (F) → Q inductively by

δ(f(t1, . . . , tn)) = δ(f, δ(t1), . . . , δ(tn)) .

We shall for convenience confuse δ and δ.We now make clear the connections between our definitions and the language

theoretical definitions of tree automata and of recognizable tree languages. In-deed, the reader should note that a complete DFTA is just a finite F-algebraA consisting of a finite carrier |A| = Q and a distinguished n-ary functionfA : Qn → Q for each n-ary symbol f ∈ F together with a specified subset Qf

of Q. A ground term t is accepted by A if δ(t) = q ∈ Qf where δ is the uniqueF-algebra homomorphism δ : T (F) → A.

Example 11. Let F = f(, ), a and consider the F-algebra A with |A| =Q = Z2 = 0, 1, fA = + where the sum is formed modulo 2, aA = 1, and letQf = 0. A and Qf defines a DFTA. The recognized tree language is the setof ground terms over F with an even number of leaves.

Since DFTA and NFTA accept the same sets of tree languages, we shall notdistinguish between them unless it becomes necessary, but shall simply refer toboth as tree automata (FTA).

1.2 The Pumping Lemma for Recognizable TreeLanguages

We now give an example of a tree language which is not recognizable.

Example 12. Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Let us consider the tree languageL = f(gi(a), gi(a)) | i > 0. Let us suppose that L is recognizable by anautomaton A having k states. Now, consider the term t = f(gk(a), gk(a)). tbelongs to L, therefore there is a successful run of A on t. As k is the cardinalityof the state set, there are two distinct positions along the first branch of the termlabeled with the same state. Therefore, one could cut the first branch betweenthese two positions leading to a term t′ = f(gj(a), gk(a)) with j < k such thata successful run of A can be defined on t′. This leads to a contradiction withL(A) = L.

This (sketch of) proof can be generalized by proving a pumping lemma

for recognizable tree languages. This lemma is extremely useful in proving that

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 27: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.3 Closure Properties of Recognizable Tree Languages 27

certain sets of ground terms are not recognizable. It is also useful for solvingdecision problems like emptiness and finiteness of a recognizable tree language(see Section 1.7).

Pumping Lemma. Let L be a recognizable set of ground terms. Then, thereexists a constant k > 0 satisfying: for every ground term t in L such thatHeight(t) > k, there exist a context C ∈ C(F), a non trivial context C ′ ∈ C(F),and a ground term u such that t = C[C ′[u]] and, for all n ≥ 0 C[C ′n [u]] ∈ L.

Proof. Let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) be a FTA such that L = L(A) and let k = |Q|be the cardinality of the state set Q. Let us consider a ground term t in Lsuch that Height(t) > k and consider a successful run r of A on t. Now let usconsider a path in t of length strictly greater than k. As k is defined to be thecardinality of the state set Q, there are two positions p1 < p2 along this pathsuch that r(p1) = r(p2) = q for some state q. Let u be the ground subterm of tat position p2. Let u′ be the ground subterm of t at position p1, there exists anon trivial context C ′ such that u′ = C ′[u]. Now define the context C such thatt = C[C ′[u]]. Consider a term C[C ′n [u]] for some integer n > 1, a successful runcan be defined on this term. Indeed suppose that r corresponds to the reductiont

∗−→A

qf where qf is a final state of A, then we have:

C[C ′n [u]]∗−→A

C[C ′n [q]]∗−→A

C[C ′n−1

[q]] . . .∗−→A

C[q]∗−→A

qf .

The same holds when n = 0.

Example 13. Let F = f(, ), a. Let us consider the tree language L = t ∈T (F) | |Pos(t)| is a prime number. We can prove that L is not recognizable.For all k > 0, consider a term t in L whose height is greater than k. For allcontexts C, non trivial contexts C ′, and terms u such that t = C[C ′[u]], thereexists n such that C[C ′n [u]] 6∈ L.

¿From the Pumping Lemma, we derive conditions for emptiness and finite-ness given by the following corollary:

Corollary 1. Let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) be a FTA. Then L(A) is non empty if andonly if there exists a term t in L(A) with Height(t) ≤ |Q|. Then L(A) is infiniteif and only if there exists a term t in L(A) with |Q| < Height(t) ≤ 2 × |Q|.

1.3 Closure Properties of Recognizable Tree Lan-guages

A closure property of a class of (tree) languages is the fact that the classis closed under a particular operation. We are interested in effective closureproperties where, given representations for languages in the class, there is analgorithm to construct a representation for the language that results by applyingthe operation to these languages. Let us note that the equivalence betweenNFTA and DFTA is effective, thus we may choose the representation that suits

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 28: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

28 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

us best. Nevertheless, the determinization algorithm may output a DFTA whosenumber of states is exponential in the number of states of the given NFTA.For the different closure properties, we give effective constructions and we givethe properties of the resulting FTA depending on the properties of the givenFTA as input. In this section, we consider the Boolean set operations: union,intersection, and complementation. Other operations will be studied in the nextsections. Complexity results are given in Section 1.7.

Theorem 5. The class of recognizable tree languages is closed under union,under complementation, and under intersection.

Union

Let L1 and L2 be two recognizable tree languages. Thus there are tree au-tomata A1 = (Q1,F , Qf1,∆1) and A2 = (Q2,F , Qf2,∆2) with L1 = L(A1)and L2 = L(A2). Since we may rename states of a tree automaton, withoutloss of generality, we may suppose that Q1 ∩ Q2 = ∅. Now, let us considerthe FTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) defined by: Q = Q1 ∪ Q2, Qf = Qf1 ∪ Qf2, and∆ = ∆1∪∆2. The equality between L(A) and L(A1)∪L(A2) is straightforward.Let us note that A is nondeterministic and not complete, even if A1 and A2 aredeterministic and complete.

We now give another construction which preserves determinism. The intu-itive idea is to process in parallel a term by the two automata. For this weconsider a product automaton. Let us suppose that A1 and A2 are complete.And, let us consider the FTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) defined by: Q = Q1 × Q2,Qf = Qf1 × Q2 ∪ Q1 × Qf2, and ∆ = ∆1 × ∆2 where

∆1 × ∆2 = f((q1, q′1), . . . , (qn, q′n)) → (q, q′) |

f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆1 f(q′1, . . . , q′n) → q′ ∈ ∆2

The proof of the equality between L(A) and L(A1)∪L(A2) is left to the reader,but the reader should note that the hypothesis that the two given tree automataare complete is crucial in the proof. Indeed, suppose for instance that a groundterm t is accepted by A1 but not by A2. Moreover suppose that A2 is notcomplete and that there is no run of A2 on t, then the product automatondoes not accept t because there is no run of the product automaton on t. Thereader should also note that the construction preserves determinism, i.e. ifthe two given automata are deterministic, then the product automaton is alsodeterministic.

Complementation

Let L be a recognizable tree language. Let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) be a completeDFTA such that L(A) = L. Now, complement the final state set to recognizethe complement of L. That is, let Ac = (Q,F , Qc

f ,∆) with Qcf = Q \ Qf , the

DFTA Ac recognizes the complement of set L in T (F).If the input automaton A is a NFTA, then first apply the determinization

algorithm, and second complement the final state set. This could lead to anexponential blow-up.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 29: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.4 Tree Homomorphisms 29

Intersection

Closure under intersection follows from closure under union and complementa-tion because

L1 ∩ L2 = L1 ∪ L2.

where we denote by L the complement of set L in T (F). But if the recogniz-able tree languages are defined by NFTA, we have to use the complementa-tion construction, therefore the determinization process is used leading to anexponential blow-up. Consequently, we now give a direct construction whichdoes not use the determinization algorithm. Let A1 = (Q1,F , Qf1,∆1) andA2 = (Q2,F , Qf2,∆2) be FTA such that L(A1) = L1 and L(A2) = L2. And,consider the FTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) defined by: Q = Q1×Q2, Qf = Qf1×Qf2,and ∆ = ∆1 ×∆2. A recognizes L1 ∩L2. Moreover the reader should note thatA is deterministic if A1 and A2 are deterministic.

1.4 Tree Homomorphisms

We now consider tree transformations and study the closure properties underthese tree transformations. In this section we are interested with tree transfor-mations preserving the structure of trees. Thus, we restrict ourselves to treehomomorphisms. Tree homomorphisms are a generalization of homomorphismsfor words (considered as unary terms) to the case of arbitrary ranked alpha-bets. In the word case, it is known that the class of regular sets is closed underhomomorphisms and inverse homomorphisms. The situation is different in thetree case because if recognizable tree languages are closed under inverse ho-momorphisms, they are closed only under a subclass of homomorphisms, i.e.linear homomorphisms (duplication of terms is forbidden). First, we define treehomomorphisms.

Let F and F ′ be two sets of function symbols, possibly not disjoint. Foreach n > 0 such that F contains a symbol of arity n, we define a set of variablesXn = x1, . . . , xn disjoint from F and F ′.

Let hF be a mapping which, with f ∈ F of arity n, associates a termtf ∈ T (F ′,Xn). The tree homomorphism h : T (F) → T (F ′) determined byhF is defined as follows:

• h(a) = ta ∈ T (F ′) for each a ∈ F of arity 0,

• h(f(t1, . . . , tn)) = tfx1 ← h(t1), . . . , xn ← h(tn)

where tfx1 ← h(t1), . . . , xn ← h(tn) is the result of applying the substi-tution x1 ← h(t1), . . . , xn ← h(tn) to the term tf .

Example 14. Let F = g(, , ), a, b and F ′ = f(, ), a, b. Let us consider thetree homomorphism h determined by hF defined by: hF (g) = f(x1, f(x2, x3)),hF (a) = a and hF (b) = b. For instance, we have:

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 30: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

30 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

If t =a

b b b

g a

g

, then h(t) =a

b

b b

f

f a

f

f

The homomorphism h defines a transformation from ternary trees into binarytrees.

Let us now consider F = and(, ), or(, ), not(), 0, 1 and F ′ = or(, ), not(), 0, 1.Let us consider the tree homomorphism h determined by hF defined by: hF (and) =not(or(not(x1), not(x2)), and hF is the identity otherwise. This homomorphismtransforms a boolean formula in an equivalent boolean formula which does notcontain the function symbol and.

A tree homomorphism is linear if for each f ∈ F of arity n, hF (f) = tf isa linear term in T (F ′,Xn). The following example shows that tree homomor-phisms do not always preserve recognizability.

Example 15. Let F = f(), g(), a and F ′ = f ′(, ), g(), a. Let us considerthe tree homomorphism h determined by hF defined by: hF (f) = f ′(x1, x1),hF (g) = g(x1), and hF (a) = a. h is not linear. Let L = f(gi(a)) | i ≥ 0,then L is a recognizable tree language. h(L) = f ′(gi(a), gi(a)) | i ≥ 0 is notrecognizable (see Example 12).

Theorem 6 (Linear homomorphisms preserve recognizability). Let hbe a linear tree homomorphism and L be a recognizable tree language, then h(L)is a recognizable tree language.

Proof. Let L be a recognizable tree language. Let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) be areduced DFTA such that L(A) = L. Let h be a linear tree homomorphism fromT (F) into T (F ′) determined by a mapping hF .

First, let us define a NFTA A′ = (Q′,F ′, Q′f ,∆′). Let us consider a rule r =

f(q1, . . . , qn) → q in ∆ and consider the linear term tf = hF (f) ∈ T (F ′,Xn) andthe set of positions Pos(tf ). We define a set of states Qr = qr

p | p ∈ Pos(tf ),and we define a set of rules ∆r as follows: for all positions p in Pos(tf )

• if tf (p) = g ∈ F ′k, then g(qr

p1, . . . , qrpk) → qr

p ∈ ∆r,

• if tf (p) = xi, then qi → qrp ∈ ∆r,

• qrε → q ∈ ∆r.

The preceding construction is made for each rule in ∆. We suppose that all thestate sets Qr are disjoint and that they are disjoint from Q. Now define A′ by:

• Q′ = Q ∪⋃

r∈∆ Qr,

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 31: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.4 Tree Homomorphisms 31

• Q′f = Qf ,

• ∆′ =⋃

r∈∆ ∆r.

Second, we have to prove that h(L) = L(A′).

h(L) ⊆ L(A′). We prove that if t∗−→A

q then h(t)∗

−−→A′

q by induction on the

length of the reduction of ground term t ∈ T (F) by automaton A.

• Base case. Suppose that t→A q. Then t = a ∈ F0 and a → q ∈ ∆.Then there is a reduction h(a) = ta

∗−−→A′

q using the rules in the set

∆a→q.

• Induction step.

Suppose that t = f(u1, . . . , un), then h(t) = tfx1←h(u1), . . . , xn←

h(un). Moreover suppose that t∗−→A

f(q1, . . . , qn)→A q. By induc-

tion hypothesis, we have h(ui)∗

−−→A′

qi, for each i in 1, . . . , n. Then

there is a reduction tfx1← q1, . . . , xn← qn∗

−−→A′

q using the rules in

the set ∆f(q1,...,qn)→q.

h(L) ⊇ L(A′). We prove that if t′∗

−−→A′

q ∈ Q then t′ = h(t) with t∗−→A

q for

some t ∈ T (F). The proof is by induction on the number of states in Q

occurring along the reduction t′∗

−−→A′

q ∈ Q.

• Base case. Suppose that t′∗

−−→A′

q ∈ Q and no state in Q apart from q

occurs in the reduction. Then, because the state sets Qr are disjoint,only rules of some ∆r can be used in the reduction. Thus, t′ is ground,t′ = hF (f) for some symbol f ∈ F , and r = f(q1, . . . , qn) → q.Because the automaton is reduced, there is some ground term t withHead(t) = f such that t′ = h(t) and t

∗−→A

q.

• Induction step. Suppose that

t′∗

−−→A′

vx′1←q1, . . . , x

′m←qm

∗−−→A′

q

where v is a linear term in T (F ′, x′1, . . . , x

′m), t′ = vx′

1← u′1, . . . , x

′m←

u′m, u′

i∗

−−→A′

qi ∈ Q, and no state in Q apart from q occurs in the

reduction of vx′1 ← q1, . . . , x

′m ← qm in q. The reader should

note that different variables can be substituted by the same state.Then, because the state sets Qr are disjoint, only rules of some∆r can be used in the reduction of vx′

1← q1, . . . , x′m← qm in q.

Thus, there exists some linear term tf such that vx′1←q1, . . . , x

′m←

qm = tfx1 ← q1, . . . , xn ← qn for some symbol f ∈ Fn andr = f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆. By induction hypothesis, there are

terms u1, . . . , um in L such that u′i = h(ui) and ui

∗−→A

qi for each

i in 1, . . . ,m. Now consider the term t = f(v1, . . . , vn), where

vi = ui if xi occurs in tf and vi is some term such that vi∗−→A

qi

otherwise (terms vi always exist because A is reduced). We have

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 32: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

32 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

h(t) = tfx1←h(v1), . . . , xn←h(vn), h(t) = vx′1←h(u1), . . . , x

′m←

h(um), h(t) = t′. Moreover, by definition of the vi and by induc-

tion hypothesis, we have t∗−→A

q. Note that if qi occurs more than

once, you can substitute qi by any term satisfying the conditions.The proof does not work for the non linear case because you have tocheck that different occurrences of some state qi corresponding to thesame variable xj ∈ Var(tf ) can only be substituted by equal terms.

Only linear tree homomorphisms preserve recognizability. An example of anon linear homomorphism which transforms recognizable tree languages eitherin recognizable tree languages or in non recognizable tree languages is given inExercise 6. For linear and non linear homomorphisms, we have:

Theorem 7 (Inverse homomorphisms preserve recognizability). Let hbe a tree homomorphism and L be a recognizable tree language, then h−1(L) isa recognizable tree language.

Proof. Let h be a tree homomorphism from T (F) into T (F ′) determined by amapping hF . Let A′ = (Q′,F ′, Q′

f ,∆′) be a complete DFTA such that L(A′) =L. We define a DFTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) by Q = Q′ ∪ s where s 6∈ Q′,Qf = Q′

f and ∆ is defined by the following:

• for a ∈ F0, if ta∗

−−→A′

q then a → q ∈ ∆;

• for f ∈ Fn where n > 0, if tfx1← p1, . . . , xn← pn∗

−−→A′

q then f(q1, . . . , qn) →

q ∈ ∆ where qi = pi if xi occurs in tf and qi = s otherwise;

• for a ∈ F0, a → s ∈ ∆;

• for f ∈ Fn where n > 0, f(s, . . . , s) → s ∈ ∆.

The rule set ∆ is computable. The proof of the equivalence t∗−→A

q if and only

if h(t)∗

−−→A′

q is left to the reader.

It can be proved that the class of recognizable tree languages is the smallestnon trivial class of tree languages closed by linear tree homomorphisms andinverse tree homomorphisms. Tree homomorphisms do not in general preserverecognizability, therefore let us consider the following problem: given as in-stance a recognizable tree language L and a tree homomorphism h, is the seth(L) recognizable ? To our knowledge it is not known whether this problem isdecidable. The reader should note that if this problem is decidable, the prob-lem whether the set of normal forms of a rewrite system is recognizable is easilyshown decidable (see Exercises 6 and 12).

As a conclusion we consider different special types of tree homomorphisms.These homomorphisms will be used in the next sections in order to simplifysome proofs and will be useful in Chapter 6. Let h be a tree homomorphismdetermined by hF . The tree homomorphism h is said to be:

• ε-free if for each symbol f ∈ F , tf is not reduced to a variable.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 33: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.5 Minimizing Tree Automata 33

• symbol to symbol if for each symbol f ∈ F , Height(tf ) = 1. The readershould note that with our definitions a symbol to symbol tree homomor-phism is ε-free. A linear symbol to symbol tree homomorphism changesthe label of the input symbol, possibly erases some subtrees and possiblymodifies order of subtrees.

• complete if for each symbol f ∈ Fn, Var(tf ) = Xn.

• a delabeling if h is a complete, linear, symbol to symbol tree homomor-phism. Such a delabeling only changes the label of the input symbol andpossibly order of subtrees.

• alphabetic if for each symbol f ∈ Fn, tf = g(x1, . . . , xn), where g ∈ F ′n.

As a corollary of Theorem 6, alphabetic tree homomorphisms, delabelings andlinear, symbol to symbol tree homomorphisms preserve recognizability. It canbe proved that for these classes of tree homomorphisms, given h and a FTA Asuch that L(A) = L as instance, a FTA for the recognizable tree language h(L)can be constructed in linear time. The same holds for h−1(L).

Example 16. Let F = f(, ), g(), a and F ′ = f ′(, ), g′(), a′. Let us considersome tree homomorphisms h determined by different hF .

• hF (f) = x1, hF (g) = f ′(x1, x1), and hF (a) = a′. h is not linear, notε-free, and not complete.

• hF (f) = g′(x1), hF (g) = f ′(x1, x1), and hF (a) = a′. h is a non linearsymbol to symbol tree homomorphism. h is not complete.

• hF (f) = f ′(x2, x1), hF (g) = g′(x1), and hF (a) = a′. h is a delabeling.

• hF (f) = f ′(x1, x2), hF (g) = g′(x1), and hF (a) = a′. h is an alphabetictree homomorphism.

1.5 Minimizing Tree Automata

In this section, we prove that, like in the word case, there exists a unique minimalautomaton in the number of states for a given recognizable tree language.

A Myhill-Nerode Theorem for Tree Languages

The Myhill-Nerode Theorem is a classical result in the theory of finite au-tomata. This theorem gives a characterization of the recognizable sets and ithas numerous applications. A consequence of this theorem, among other con-sequences, is that there is essentially a unique minimum state DFA for everyrecognizable language over finite alphabet. The Myhill-Nerode Theorem gener-alizes in a straightforward way to automata on finite trees.

An equivalence relation ≡ on T (F) is a congruence on T (F) if for everyf ∈ Fn

ui ≡ vi 1 ≤ i ≤ n ⇒ f(u1, . . . , un) ≡ f(v1, . . . , vn) .

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 34: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

34 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

It is of finite index if there are only finitely many ≡-classes. Equivalently acongruence is an equivalence relation closed under context, i.e. for all contextsC ∈ C(F), if u ≡ v, then C[u] ≡ C[v]. For a given tree language L, let us definethe congruence ≡L on T (F) by: u ≡L v if for all contexts C ∈ C(F),

C[u] ∈ L iff C[v] ∈ L.

We are now ready to give the Theorem:

Myhill-Nerode Theorem. The following three statements are equivalent:

(i) L is a recognizable tree language

(ii) L is the union of some equivalence classes of a congruence of finite index

(iii) the relation ≡L is a congruence of finite index.

Proof.

• (i) ⇒ (ii) Assume that L is recognized by some complete DFTA A =(Q,F , Qf , δ). We consider δ as a transition function. Let us considerthe relation ≡A defined on T (F) by: u ≡A v if δ(u) = δ(v). Clearly≡A is a congruence relation and it is of finite index, since the number ofequivalence classes is at most the number of states in Q. Furthermore, Lis the union of those equivalence classes that include a term u such thatδ(u) is a final state.

• (ii) ⇒ (iii) Let us denote by ∼ the congruence of finite index. And let usassume that u ∼ v. By an easy induction on the structure of terms, it canbe proved that C[u] ∼ C[v] for all contexts C ∈ C(F). Now, L is the unionof some equivalence classes of ∼, thus we have C[u] ∈ L iff C[v] ∈ L. Thusu ≡L v, and the equivalence class of u in ∼ is contained in the equivalenceclass of u in ≡L. Consequently, the index of ≡L is lower or equal than theindex of ∼ which is finite.

• (iii) ⇒ (i) Let Qmin be the finite set of equivalence classes of ≡L. Andlet us denote by [u] the equivalence class of a term u. Let the transitionfunction δmin be defined by:

δmin(f, [u1], . . . , [un]) = [f(u1, . . . , un)].

The definition of δmin is consistent because ≡L is a congruence. Andlet Qminf

= [u] | u ∈ L. The DFTA Amin = (Qmin,F , Qminf, δmin)

recognizes the tree language L.

As a corollary of the Myhill-Nerode Theorem, we can deduce an other al-gebraic characterization of recognizable tree languages. This characterizationis a reformulation of the definition of recognizability. A set of ground termsL is recognizable if and only if there exist a finite F-algebra A, a F-algebrahomomorphism φ : T (F) → A and a subset A′ of the carrier |A| of A suchthat L = φ−1(A′).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 35: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.5 Minimizing Tree Automata 35

Minimization of Tree Automata

First, we prove the existence and uniqueness of the minimum DFTA for a rec-ognizable tree language. It is a consequence of the Myhill-Nerode Theorembecause of the following result:

Corollary 2. The minimum DFTA recognizing a recognizable tree language Lis unique up to a renaming of the states and is given by Amin in the proof ofMyhill-Nerode Theorem.

Proof. Assume that L is recognized by some DFTA A = (Q,F , Qf , δ). Therelation ≡A is a refinement of ≡L (see the proof of Myhill-Nerode Theorem).Therefore the number of states of A is greater than or equal to the number ofstates of Amin. If equality holds, A is reduced, i.e. all states are accessible,because otherwise a state could be removed leading to a contradiction. Let qbe a state in Q and let u be such that δ(u) = q. The state q can be identifiedwith the state δmin(u). This identification is consistent and defines a one to onecorrespondence between Q and Qmin.

Second, we give a minimization algorithm for finding the minimum stateDFTA equivalent to a given reduced DFTA. We confuse an equivalence relationand the sequence of its equivalence classes.

Minimization Algorithm MINinput: complete and reduced DFTA A = (Q,F , Qf , δ)begin

Set P to Qf , Q − Qf /* P is the initial equivalence relation*/repeat

P ′ = P/* Refine equivalence P in P ′ */qP ′q′ if

qPq′ and∀f ∈ Fn∀q1, . . . , qi−1, qi+1, . . . , qn ∈ Qδ(f(q1, . . . , qi−1, q, qi+1, . . . , qn))Pδ(f(q1, . . . , qi−1, q

′, qi+1, . . . , qn))until P ′ = PSet Qmin to the set of equivalence classes of P/* we denote by [q] the equivalence class of state q w.r.t. P */Set δmin to (f, [q1], . . . , [qn]) → [f(q1, . . . , qn)]Set Qminf

to [q] | q ∈ Qfoutput: DFTA Amin = (Qmin,F , Qminf

, δmin)end

The DFTA constructed by the algorithm MIN is the minimum state DFTAfor its tree language. Indeed, let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) the DFTA to which is ap-plied the algorithm and let L = L(A). Let Amin be the output of the algorithm.It is easy to show that the definition of Amin is consistent and that L = L(Amin).Now, by contradiction, we can prove that Amin has no more states than thenumber of equivalence classes of ≡L.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 36: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

36 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

1.6 Top Down Tree Automata

Tree automata that we have defined in the previous sections are also known asbottom-up tree automata because these automata start their computation atthe leaves of trees. In this section we define top-down tree automata. Such anautomaton starts its computation at the root in an initial state and then simul-taneously works down the paths of the tree level by level. The tree automatonaccepts a tree if a run built up in this fashion can be defined. It appears thattop-down tree automata and bottom-up tree automata have the same expres-sive power. An important difference between bottom-up tree automata andtop-down automata appears in the question of determinism since deterministictop-down tree automata are strictly less powerful than nondeterministic onesand therefore are strictly less powerful than bottom-up tree automata. In-tuitively, it is due to the following: tree properties specified by deterministictop-down tree automata can depend only on path properties. We now makeprecise these remarks and first, let us formally define top-down tree automata.

A nondeterministic top-down finite Tree Automaton (top-down NFTA)over F is a tuple A = (Q,F , I,∆) where Q is a set of states (states are unarysymbols), I ⊆ Q is a set of initial states, and ∆ is a set of rewrite rules of thefollowing type :

q(f(x1, . . . , xn)) → f(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)),

where n ≥ 0, f ∈ Fn, q, q1, . . . , qn ∈ Q, x1, . . . , xn ∈ X .When n = 0, i.e. when the symbol is a constant symbol a, a transition rule

of top-down NFTA is of the form q(a) → a. A top-down automaton starts at theroot and moves downward, associating along a run a state with each subterminductively. We do not formally define the move relation →A defined by a top-down NFTA because the definition is easily deduced from the correspondingdefinition for bottom-up NFTA. The tree language L(A) recognized by A is theset of all ground terms t for which there is an initial state q in I such that

q(t)∗−→A

t.

The expressive power of bottom-up and top-down tree automata is the same.Indeed, we have the following Theorem:

Theorem 8 (The equivalence of top-down and bottom-up NFTA’s).The class of languages accepted by top-down NFTA’s is exactly the class ofrecognizable tree languages.

Proof. The proof is left to the reader. Hint. Reverse the arrows and exchangethe sets of initial and final states.

Top-down and bottom-up tree automata have the same expressive powerbecause they define the same classes of tree languages. Nevertheless they donot have the same behavior from an algorithmic point of view because nonde-terminism can not be reduced in the class of top-down tree automata.

Proposition 1 (Top-down NFTA’s and top-down DFTA’s). A top-downfinite Tree Automaton (Q,F , I,∆) is deterministic (top-down DFTA) if thereis one initial state and no two rules with the same left-hand side. Top-downDFTA’s are strictly less powerful than top-down NFTA’s, i.e. there exists arecognizable tree language which is not accepted by a top-down DFTA.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 37: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.7 Decision Problems and their Complexity 37

Proof. Let F = f(, ), a, b. And let us consider the recognizable tree languageT = f(a, b), f(b, a). Now let us suppose there exists a top-down DFTA thataccepts T , the automaton should accept the term f(a, a) leading to a contra-diction. Obviously the tree language T = f(a, b), f(b, a) is recognizable by afinite union of top-down DFTA but there is a recognizable tree language whichis not accepted by a finite union of top-down DFTA (see Exercise 2).

1.7 Decision Problems and their Complexity

In this section, we study some decision problems and their complexity. The sizeof an automaton will be the size of its representation. More formally:

Definition 1. Let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) be an NFTA over F . The size of a rulef(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)) → q(f(x1, . . . , xn)) is arity(f) + 2. The size of A noted‖A‖, is defined by:

‖A‖ = |Q| +∑

f(q1(x1),...,qn(xn))→q(f(x1,...,xn))∈∆

(arity(f) + 2).

We will work in the frame of RAM machines, with uniform measure.

Membership

Instance A ground term.

Answer “yes” if and only if the term is recognized by a given automaton.

Let us first remark that, in our model, for a given deterministic automaton,a run on a tree can be computed in O(‖t‖). The complexity of the problem is:

Theorem 9. Membership problem is ALOGTIME-complete.

Uniform Membership

Instance A tree automaton and a ground term.

Answer “yes” if and only if the term is recognized by a given automaton.

Theorem 10. Uniform membership problem can be decided in linear time forDFTA, in polynomial time for NFTA.

Proof. In the deterministic case, from a term t and the automaton ‖A‖, we cancompute a run in O(‖t‖+‖A‖). In the nondeterministic case, the idea is similarto the word case: the algorithm determinizes along the computation, i.e. foreach node of the term, we compute the set of reached states. The complexityof this algorithm will be in O(‖t‖ × ‖A‖).

The uniform membership problem has been proved LOGSPACE-completefor deterministic top-down tree automata, LOGCFL-complete for NFTA underlog-space reductions. For DFTA, it has been proven LOGDCFL, but the precisecomplexity remains open.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 38: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

38 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

Emptiness

Instance A tree automaton

Answer “yes” if and only if the recognized language is empty.

Theorem 11. It can be decided in linear time whether the language acceptedby a finite tree automaton is empty.

Proof. The minimal height of accepted terms can be bounded by the number ofstates using Corollary 1; so, as membership is decidable, emptiness is decidable.Of course, this approach does not provide a practicable algorithm. To get anefficient algorithm, it suffices to notice that a NFTA accepts at least one treeif and only if there is an accessible final state. In other words, the languagerecognized by a reduced automaton is empty if and only if the set of finalstates is non empty. Reducing an automaton can be done in O(|Q| × ‖A‖)by the reduction algorithm given in Section 1.1. Actually, this algorithm canbe improved by choosing an adequate data structure in order to get a linearalgorithm (see Exercise 17). This linear least fixpoint computation holds inseveral frameworks. For example, it can be viewed as the satisfiability test ofa set of propositional Horn formulae. The reduction is easy and linear: eachstate q can be associated with a propositional variable Xq and each rule r :f(q1, . . . , qn) → q can be associated with a propositional Horn formula Fr =Xq∨¬Xq1

∨· · ·∨¬Xqn. It is straightforward that satisfiability of Fr∪¬Xq/q ∈

Qf is equivalent to emptiness of the language recognized by (Q,F , Qf ,∆). So,as satisfiability of a set of propositional Horn formulae can be decided in lineartime, we get a linear algorithm for testing emptiness for NFTA.

The emptiness problem is P-complete with respect to logspace reductions,even when restricted to deterministic tree automata. The proof can easily bedone since the problem is very close to the solvable path systems problem whichis known to be P-complete (see Exercise 18).

Intersection non-emptiness

Instance A finite sequence of tree automata.

Answer “yes” if and only if there is at least one term recognized by eachautomaton of the sequence.

Theorem 12. The intersection problem for tree automata is EXPTIME-complete.

Proof. By constructing the product automata for the n automata, and thentesting non-emptiness, we get an algorithm in O(‖A1‖×· · ·×‖An‖). The proofof EXPTIME-hardness is based on simulation of an alternating linear space-bounded Turing machine. Roughly speaking, with such a machine and an inputof length n can be associated polynomially n tree automata whose intersectioncorresponds to the set of accepting computations on the input. It is worthnoting that the result holds for deterministic top down tree automata as well asfor deterministic bottom-up ones.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 39: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.7 Decision Problems and their Complexity 39

Finiteness

Instance A tree automaton

Answer “yes” if and only if the recognized language is finite.

Theorem 13. Finiteness can be decided in polynomial time.

Proof. Let us consider a NFTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆). Deciding finiteness of A isdirect by Corollary 1: it suffices to find an accepted term t s.t. |Q| < ‖t‖ ≤2∗ |Q|. A more efficient way to test finiteness is to check the existence of a loop:the language is infinite if and only if there is a loop on some useful state, i.e.there exist an accessible state q and contexts C and C ′ such that C[q]

∗−→A

q and

C ′[q]∗−→A

q′ for some final state q′. Computing accessible and coaccessible states

can be done in O(|Q| × ‖A‖) or in O(‖A‖) by using an ad hoc representationof the automaton. For a given q, deciding if there is a loop on q can be done inO(A). So, finiteness can be decided in O(|Q| × ‖A‖).

Emptiness of the Complement

Instance A tree automaton.

Answer “yes” if and only if every term is accepted by the automaton

Deciding whether a deterministic tree automaton recognizes the set of allterms is polynomial for a fixed alphabet: we just have to check whether theautomaton is complete (which can be done in O(|F| × |Q|Arity(F))) and then itremains only to check that all accessible states are final. For nondeterministicautomata, the following result proves in some sense that determinization withits exponential cost is unavoidable:

Theorem 14. The problem whether a tree automaton accepts the set of allterms is EXPTIME-complete for nondeterministic tree automata.

Proof. The proof of this theorem is once more based on simulation of linear spacebounded alternating Turing machine: indeed, the complement of the acceptingcomputations on an input w can be coded polynomially in a recognizable treelanguage.

Equivalence

Instance Two tree automata

Answer “yes” if and only if the automata recognize the same language.

Theorem 15. Equivalence is decidable for tree automata.

Proof. Clearly, as the class of recognizable sets is effectively closed under com-plementation and intersection, and as emptiness is decidable, equivalence isdecidable. For two deterministic complete automata A1 and A2, we get bythese means an algorithm in O(‖A1‖ × ‖A2‖). (An other way is to comparethe minimal automata). For nondeterministic ones, this approach leads to anexponential algorithm.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 40: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

40 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

As we have proved that deciding whether an automaton recognizes the setof all ground terms is EXPTIME-hard, we get immediately:

Corollary 3. The inclusion problem and the equivalence problem for NFTA’sare EXPTIME-complete.

Singleton Set Property

Instance A tree automaton

Answer “yes” if and only if the recognized language is a singleton set.

Theorem 16. The singleton set property is decidable in polynomial time.

Proof. There are several ways to get a polynomial algorithm for this property.A first one would be to first check non-emptiness of L(A) and then ”extract”from A a DFA B whose size is smaller than ‖A‖ and which accepts a single termrecognized by A. Then it remains to check emptiness of L(A)∩L(B). This canbe done in polynomial time, even is B is non complete.

An other algorithm is: for each state of a bottom-up tree automaton A,compute, up to 2, the number C(q) of terms leading to state q. This can be donein a straightforward way when A is deterministic; when A is non deterministic,this can be also done in polynomial time:

Singleton Set Test Algorithminput: NFTA A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆)begin

Set C(q) to 0, for every q in Q/* C(q) ∈ 0, 1, 2 is the number, up to 2, of terms leading to state q *//* if C(q) = 1 then T (q) is a representation of the accepted tree */repeat

for each rule f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆ doCase ∧jC(qj) >= 1 and C(qi) = 2 for some i: Set C(q) to 2Case ∧jC(qj) = 1 and C(q) = 0: Set C(q) to 1, T (q) to f(q1, ...qn)Case ∧jC(qj) = 1, C(q) = 1 and Diff(T (q), f(q1, . . . , qn)):

Set C(q) to 2Others nullwhere Diff(f(q1, ..., qn), g(q′1, ..., q

′n)) defined by:

/* Diff can be computed polynomially by using memoization. */if (f 6= g) then return trueelseif Diff(T (qi), T (q′i) for some qi then return Trueelse return False

until C can not be changedoutput:/*L(A) is empty */if ∧q∈Qf

C(q) = 0 then return False/* two terms in L(A) accepted in the same state or two different states */elseif ∃q ∈ Qf C(q) = 2 then return Falseelseif ∃q, q′ ∈ Qf C(q) = C(q′) = 1 and Diff(T (q), T (q′)) then return False/* in all other cases L(A) is a singleton set*/

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 41: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.8 Exercises 41

else return True.end

Other complexity results for “classical” problems can be found in the exer-cises. E.g., let us cite the following problem whose proof is sketched in Exer-cise 11

Ground Instance Intersection Problem

Instance A term t, a tree automaton A.

Answer “yes” if and only if there is at least a ground instance of t which isaccepted by A.

Theorem 17. The Ground Instance Intersection Problem for tree automatais P when t is linear, NP-complete when t is non linear and A deterministic,EXPTIME-complete when t is non linear and A non deterministic.

1.8 Exercises

Starred exercises are discussed in the bibliographic notes.

Exercise 1. Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Define a top-down NFTA, a NFTA and a DFTA

for the set G(t) of ground instances of term t = f(f(a, x), g(y)) which is defined by

G(t) = f(f(a, u), g(v)) | u, v ∈ T (F). Is it possible to define a top-down DFTA for

this language?

Exercise 2. Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Define a top-down NFTA, a NFTA and a DFTA

for the set M(t) of terms which have a ground instance of term t = f(a, g(x)) as a

subterm, that is M(t) = C[f(a, g(u))] | C ∈ C(F), ∈ T (F). Is it possible to define

a top-down DFTA for this language?

Exercise 3. Let F = g(), a. Is the set of ground terms whose height is even

recognizable? Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Is the set of ground terms whose height is even

recognizable?

Exercise 4. Let F = f(, ), a. Prove that the set L = f(t, t) | t ∈ T (F) is

not recognizable. Let F be any ranked alphabet which contains at least one constant

symbol a and one binary symbol f(, ). Prove that the set L = f(t, t) | t ∈ T (F) is

not recognizable.

Exercise 5. Prove the equivalence between top-down NFTA and NFTA.

Exercise 6. Let F = f(, ), g(), a and F ′ = f ′(, ), g(), a. Let us consider thetree homomorphism h determined by hF defined by: hF (f) = f ′(x1, x2), hF (g) =f ′(x1, x1), and hF (a) = a. Is h(T (F)) recognizable? Let L1 = gi(a) | i ≥ 0, thenL1 is a recognizable tree language, is h(L1) recognizable? Let L2 be the recognizable

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 42: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

42 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

tree language defined by L2 = L(A) where A = (Q,F , Qf , ∆) is defined by: Q =qa, qg, qf, Qf = qf, and ∆ is the following set of transition rules:

a → qa g(qa) → qg

f(qa, qa) → qf f(qg, qg) → qf

f(qa, qg) → qf f(qg, qa) → qf

f(qa, qf ) → qf f(qf , qa) → qf

f(qg, qf ) → qf f(qf , qg) → qf

f(qf , qf ) → qf .

Is h(L2) recognizable?

Exercise 7. Let F1 = or(, ), and(, ), not(), 0, 1, x. A ground term over F can be

viewed as a boolean formula over variable x. Define a DFTA which recognizes the set

of satisfiable boolean formulae over x. Let Fn = or(, ), and(, ), not(), 0, 1, x1, . . . , xn.

A ground term over F can be viewed as a boolean formula over variables x1, . . . , xn.

Define a DFTA which recognizes the set of satisfiable boolean formulae over x1, . . . , xn.

Exercise 8. Let t be a linear term in T (F ,X ). Prove that the set G(t) of ground

instances of term t is recognizable. Let R be a finite set of linear terms in T (F ,X ).

Prove that the set G(R) of ground instances of set R is recognizable.

Exercise 9. * Let R be a finite set of linear terms in T (F ,X ). We define the setRed(R) of reducible terms for R to be the set of ground terms which have a groundinstance of some term in R as a subterm.

1. Prove that the set Red(R) is recognizable.

2. Prove that the number of states of a DFA recognizing Red(R) can be at least2n−1 where n is the size (number of nodes) of R. Hint: Consider the set reducedto the pattern h(f(x1, f(x2, f(x3), . . . , (f(xp−1, f(a, xp) · · · ).

3. Let us now suppose that R is a finite set of ground terms. Prove that we canconstruct a DFA recognizing Red(R) whose number of states is at most n + 2where n is the number of different subterms of R.

Exercise 10. * Let R be a finite set of linear terms in T (F ,X ). A term t is inductively

reducible for R if all the ground instances of term t are reducible for R. Prove that

inductive reducibility of a linear term t for a set of linear terms R is decidable.

Exercise 11. *We consider the following decision problem:

Instance t a term in T (F ,X ) and A a NFTA

Answer “yes” if and only if Yes, iff at least one ground instance of t is accepted by|A.

1. Let us first suppose that t is linear; prove that the property is P .

Hint: a NFTA for the set of ground instances of t can ce computed polynomially(see Exercise 8

2. Let us now suppose that t is non linear but that A is deterministic.

(a) Prove that the property is NP. Hint: we just have to guess a substitutionof the variables of t by states.

(b) Prove that the property is NP-hard.

Hint: just consider a term t which represents a boolean formula and A aDFTA which accepts valid formulas.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 43: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.8 Exercises 43

3. Let us now suppose that t is non linear and that A is non deterministic.

Prove that the property is EXPTIME−complete.

Hint: use the EXPTIME-hardness of intersection non-emptiness.

Exercise 12. * We consider the following two problems. First, given as instance a

recognizable tree language L and a tree homomorphism h, is the set h(L) recognizable?

Second, given as instance a set R of terms in T (F ,X ), is the set Red(R) recogniz-

able? Prove that if the first problem is decidable, the second problem is easily shown

decidable.

Exercise 13. Let F = f(, ), a, b.

1. Let us consider the set of ground terms L1 defined by the following two condi-tions:

• f(a, b) ∈ L1,

• t ∈ L1 ⇒ f(a, f(t, b)) ∈ L1.

Prove that the set L1 is recognizable.

2. Prove that the set L2 = t ∈ T (F) | |t|a = |t|b is not recognizable where |t|a(respectively |t|b) denotes the number of a (respectively the number of b) in t.

3. Let L be a recognizable tree language over F . Let us suppose that f is acommutative symbol. Let C(L) be the congruence closure of set L for the setof equations C = f(x, y) = f(y, x). Prove that C(L) is recognizable.

4. Let L be a recognizable tree language over F . Let us suppose that f is a com-mutative and associative symbol. Let AC(L) be the congruence closure of set Lfor the set of equations AC = f(x, y) = f(y, x); f(x, f(y, z)) = f(f(x, y), z).Prove that in general AC(L) is not recognizable.

5. Let L be a recognizable tree language over F . Let us suppose that f is anassociative symbol. Let A(L) be the congruence closure of set L for the set ofequations A = f(x, f(y, z)) = f(f(x, y), z). Prove that in general A(L) is notrecognizable.

Exercise 14. * Consider the complement problem:

• Instance A term t ∈ T (F ,X ) and terms t1, . . . , tn,

• Question There is a ground instance of t which is not an instance of any ti.

Prove that the complement problem is decidable whenever term t and all terms ti are

linear. Extend the proof to handle the case where t is a term (not necessarily linear).

Exercise 15. * Let F be a ranked alphabet and suppose that F contains some symbolswhich are commutative and associative. The set of ground AC-instances of a term t isthe AC-congruence closure of set G(t). Prove that the set of ground AC-instances of alinear term is recognizable. The reader should note that the set of ground AC-instancesof a set of linear terms is not recognizable (see Exercice 13).

Prove that the AC-complement problem is decidable where the AC-complementproblem is defined by:

• Instance A linear term t ∈ T (F ,X ) and linear terms t1, . . . , tn,

• Question There is a ground AC-instance of t which is not an AC-instance ofany ti.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 44: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

44 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

Exercise 16. * Let F be a ranked alphabet and X be a countable set of variables.Let S be a rewrite system on T (F ,X ) (the reader is referred to [DJ90]) and L be aset of ground terms. We denote by S∗(L) the set of reductions of terms in L by S andby S(L) the set of ground S-normal forms of set L. Formally,

S∗(L) = t ∈ T (F) | ∃u ∈ L u∗→ t,

S(L) = t ∈ T (F) | t ∈ IRR(S) and ∃u ∈ L u∗→ t = IRR(S) ∩ S∗(L)

where IRR(S) denotes the set of ground irreducible terms for S. We consider the twofollowing decision problems:

(1rst order reachability)

• Instance A rewrite system S, two ground terms u and v,

• Question v ∈ S∗(u).

(2nd order reachability)

• Instance A rewrite system S, two recognizable tree languages L and L′,

• Question S∗(L) ⊆ L′.

1. Let us suppose that rewrite system S satisfies:

(PreservRec) If L is recognizable, then S∗(L) is recognizable.

What can be said about the two reachability decision problems? Give a suffi-cient condition on rewrite system S satisfying (PreservRec) such that S satisfies(NormalFormRec) where (NormalFormRec) is defined by:

(NormalFormRec) If L is recognizable, then S(L) is recognizable.

2. Let F = f(, ), g(), h(), a. Let L = f(t1, t2) | t1, t2 ∈ T (g(), h(), a, and Sis the following set of rewrite rules:

f(g(x), h(y)) → f(x, y) f(h(x), g(y)) → f(x, y)g(h(x)) → x h(g(x)) → xf(a, x) → x f(x, a) → x

Are the sets L, S∗(L), and S(L) recognizable?

3. Let F = f(, ), g(), h(), a. Let L = g(hn(a)) | n ≥ 0, and S is the followingset of rewrite rules:

g(x) → f(x, x)

Are the sets L, S∗(L), and S(L) recognizable?

4. Let us suppose now that rewrite system S is linear and monadic, i.e. all rewriterules are of one of the following three types:

(1) l → a , a ∈ F0

(2) l → x , x ∈ Var(l)(3) l → f(x1, . . . , xp) , x1, . . . , xp ∈ Var(l), f ∈ Fp

where l is a linear term (no variable occurs more than once in t) whose heightis greater than 1. Prove that a linear and monadic rewrite system satisfies(PreservRec). Prove that (PreservRec) is false if the right-hand side of rules oftype (3) may be non linear.

Exercise 17. Design a linear-time algorithm for testing emptiness of the languagerecognized by a tree automaton:

Instance A tree automaton

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 45: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.9 Bibliographic Notes 45

Answer “yes” if and only if the language recognized is empty.

Hint: Choose a suitable data structure for the automaton. For example, a state

could be associated with the list of the “adresses” of the rules whose left-hand side

contain it (eventually, a rule can be repeated); each rule could be just represented by

a counter initialized at the arity of the corresponding symbol and by the state of the

right-hand side. Activating a state will decrement the counters of the corresponding

rules. When the counter of a rule becomes null, the rule can be applied: the right-hand

side state can be activated.

Exercise 18.The Solvable Path Problem is the following:

Instance a finite set X and three sets R ⊂ X × X × X, Xs ⊂ X and Xt ⊂ X.

Answer “yes” if and only if Xt ∩ A is non empty, where A is the least subset of Xsuch that Xs ⊂ A and if y, z ∈ A and (x, y, z) ∈ R, then x ∈ A.

Prove that this P − complete problem is log-space reducible to the emptinessproblem for tree automata.

Exercise 19. A flat automaton is a tree automaton which has the following property:there is an ordering ≥ on the states and a particular state q> such that the transitionrules have one of the following forms:

1. f(q>, . . . , q>) → q>

2. f(q1, . . . , qn) → q with q > qi for every i

3. f(q>, . . . , q>, q, q>, . . . , q>) → q

Moreover, we assume that all terms are accepted in the state q>. (The automaton iscalled flat because there are no “nested loop”).

Prove that the intersection of two flat automata is a finite union of automata whosesize is linear in the sum of the original automata. (This contrasts with the constructionof Theorem 5 in which the intersection automaton’s size is the product of the sizes ofits components).

Deduce from the above result that the intersection non-emptiness problem for flat

automata is in NP (compare with Theorem 12).

1.9 Bibliographic Notes

Tree automata were introduced by Doner [Don65, Don70] and Thatcher andWright [TW65, TW68]. Their goal was to prove the decidability of the weaksecond order theory of multiple successors. The original definitions are basedon the algebraic approach and involve heavy use of universal algebra and/orcategory theory.

Many of the basic results presented in this chapter are the straightforwardgeneralization of the corresponding results for finite automata. It is difficult toattribute a particular result to any one paper. Thus, we only give a list of someimportant contributions consisting of the above mentioned papers of Doner,Thatcher and Wright and also Eilenberg and Wright [EW67], Thatcher [Tha70],Brainerd [Bra68, Bra69], Arbib and Give’on [AG68]. All the results of thischapter and a more complete and detailed list of references can be found in thetextbook of Gcseg and Steinby [GS84] and also in their recent survey [GS96].For an overview of the notion of recognizability in general algebraic structuressee Courcelle [Cou89] and the fundamental paper of Mezei and Wright [MW67].

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 46: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

46 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata

In Nivat and Podelski [NP89] and [Pod92], the theory of recognizable tree lan-guages is reduced to the theory of recognizable sets in an infinitely generatedfree monoid.

The results of Sections 1.1, 1.2, and 1.3 were noted in many of the papersmentioned above, but, in this textbook, we present these results in the style ofthe undergraduate textbook on finite automata by Hopcroft and Ullman [HU79].Tree homomorphisms were defined as a special case of tree transducers, seeThatcher [Tha73]. The reader is referred to the bibliographic notes in Chapter 6of the present textbook for detailed references. The reader should note that ourproof of preservation of recognizability by tree homomorphisms and inverse treehomomorphisms is a direct construction using FTA. A more classical proof canbe found in [GS84] and uses regular tree grammars (see Chapter 2).

Minimal tree recognizers and Nerode’s congruence appear in Brainerd [Bra68,Bra69], Arbib and Give’on [AG68], and Eilenberg and Wright [EW67]. Theproof we presented here is by Kozen [Koz92] (see also Flp and Vagvlgyi [FV89]).Top-down tree automata were first defined by Rabin [Rab69]. The reader isreferred to [GS84] and [GS96] for more references and for the study of somesubclasses of recognizable tree languages such as the tree languages recognizedby deterministic top-down tree automata. An alternative definition of determin-istic top-down tree automata was defined in [NP97] leading to “homogeneous”tree languages, also a minimization algorithm was given.

Some results of Sections 1.7 are “folklore” results. Complexity results forthe membership problem and the uniform membership problem could be foundin [Loh01]. Other interesting complexity results for tree automata can be foundin Seidl [Sei89], [Sei90]. The EXPTIME-hardness of the problem of intersec-tion non-emptiness is often used; this problem is close to problems of typeinference and an idea of the proof can be found in [FSVY91]. A proof for de-terministic top-down automata can be found in [Sei94b]. A detailed proof inthe deterministic bottom-up case as well as some other complexity results arein [Vea97a], [Vea97b].

We have only considered finite ordered ranked trees. Unranked trees areused for XML Document Type Definitions and more generally for XML schemalanguages [MLM01]. The theory of unranked trees dates back to Thatcher. Allthe fundamental results for finite tree automata can be extended to the case ofunranked trees and the methods are similar [BKMW01]. An other extension isto consider unordered trees. A general discussion about unordered and unrankedtrees can be found in the bibliographical notes of Section 4.

Numerous exercises of the present chapter illustrate applications of tree au-tomata theory to automated deduction and to the theory of rewriting systems.These applications are studied in more details in Section 3.4. Results about treeautomata and rewrite systems are collected in Gilleron and Tison [GT95]. LetS be a term rewrite system (see for example Dershowitz and Jouannaud [DJ90]for a survey on rewrite systems), if S is left-linear the set IRR(S) of irreducibleground terms w.r.t. S is a recognizable tree language. This result first appearsin Gallier and Book [GB85] and is the subject of Exercise 9. However not everyrecognizable tree language is the set of irreducible terms w.r.t. a rewrite systemS (see Flp and Vagvlgyi [FV88]). It was proved that the problem whether,given a rewrite system S as instance, the set of irreducible terms is recognizableis decidable (Kucherov [Kuc91]). The problem of preservation of regularity bytree homomorphisms is not known decidable. Exercise 12 shows connections

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 47: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

1.9 Bibliographic Notes 47

between preservation of regularity for tree homomorphisms and recognizabilityof sets of irreducible terms for rewrite systems.

The notion of inductive reducibility (or ground reducibility) was introducedin automated deduction. A term t is S-inductively (or S-ground) reducible forS if all the ground instances of term t are reducible for S. Inductive reducibilityis decidable for linear term t and left-linear rewrite system S. This is Exer-cise 10, see also Section 3.4.2. Inductive reducibility is decidable for finite S(see Plaisted [Pla85]). Complement problems are also introduced in automateddeduction. They are the subject of Exercises 14 and 15. The complement prob-lem for linear terms was proved decidable by Lassez and Marriott [LM87] andthe AC-complement problem by Lugiez and Moysset [LM94].

The reachability problem is defined in Exercise 16. It is well known that thisproblem is undecidable in general. It is decidable for rewrite systems preservingrecognizability, i.e. such that for every recognizable tree language L, the setof reductions of terms in L by S is recognizable. This is true for linear andmonadic rewrite systems (right-hand sides have depth less than 1). This resultwas obtained by K. Salomaa [Sal88] and is the matter of Exercise 16. This istrue also for linear and semi-monadic (variables in the right-hand sides havedepth at most 1) rewrite systems, Coquid et al. [CDGV94]. Other interestingresults can be found in [Jac96] and [NT99].

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 48: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata
Page 49: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Chapter 2

Regular Grammars andRegular Expressions

2.1 Tree Grammar

In the previous chapter, we have studied tree languages from the acceptor pointof view, using tree automata and defining recognizable languages. In this chap-ter we study languages from the generation point of view, using regular treegrammars and defining regular tree languages. We shall see that the two no-tions are equivalent and that many properties and concepts on regular wordlanguages smoothly generalize to regular tree languages, and that algebraiccharacterization of regular languages do exist for tree languages. Actually, thisis not surprising since tree languages can be seen as word languages on an infi-nite alphabet of contexts. We shall show also that the set of derivation trees ofa context-free language is a regular tree language.

2.1.1 Definitions

When we write programs, we often have to know how to produce the elements ofthe data structures that we use. For instance, a definition of the lists of integersin a functional language like ML is similar to the following definition:

Nat = 0 | s(Nat)List = nil | cons(Nat, List)

This definition is nothing but a tree grammar in disguise, more precisely theset of lists of integers is the tree language generated by the grammar with axiomList, non-terminal symbols List,Nat, terminal symbols 0, s, nil, cons and rules

Nat → 0Nat → s(Nat)List → nilList → cons(Nat, List)

Tree grammars are similar to word grammars except that basic objects aretrees, therefore terminals and non-terminals may have an arity greater than 0.More precisely, a tree grammar G = (S,N,F , R) is composed of an axiom

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 50: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

50 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

S, a set N of non-terminal symbols with S ∈ N , a set F of terminal

symbols, a set R of production rules of the form α → β where α, β are treesof T (F∪N∪X ) where X is a set of dummy variables and α contains at least onenon-terminal. Moreover we require that F ∩N = ∅, that each element of N ∪Fhas a fixed arity and that the arity of the axiom S is 0. In this chapter, weshall concentrate on regular tree grammars where a regular tree grammarG = (S,N,F , R) is a tree grammar such that all non-terminal symbols havearity 0 and production rules have the form A → β, with A a non-terminal of Nand β a tree of T (F ∪ N).

Example 17. The grammar G with axiom List, non-terminals List,Natterminals 0, nil, s(), cons(, ), rules

List → nilList → cons(Nat, List)Nat → 0Nat → s(Nat)

is a regular tree grammar.

A tree grammar is used to build terms from the axiom, using the corre-sponding derivation relation. Basically the idea is to replace a non-terminalA by the right-hand side α of a rule A → α. More precisely, given a regulartree grammar G = (S,N,F , R), the derivation relation →G associated to G isa relation on pairs of terms of T (F ∪ N) such that s →G t if and only if thereare a rule A → α ∈ R and a context C such that s = C[A] and t = C[α].The language generated by G, denoted by L(G), is the set of terms of T (F)which can be reached by successive derivations starting from the axiom, i.e.

L(G) = s ∈ TF | S+

→G s with+→ the transitive closure of →G. We write →

instead of →G when the grammar G is clear from the context. A regular tree

language is a language generated by a regular tree grammar.

Example 18. Let G be the grammar of the previous example, then a derivationof cons(s(0), nil) from List is

List →G cons(Nat, List) →G cons(s(Nat), List) →G cons(s(Nat), nil)→G cons(s(0), nil)

and the language generated by G is the set of lists of non-negative integers.

From the example, we can see that trees are generated top-down by replacinga leaf by some other term. When A is a non-terminal of a regular tree grammarG, we denote by LG(A) the language generated by the grammar G′ identical toG but with A as axiom. When there is no ambiguity on the grammar referred to,we drop the subscript G. We say that two grammars G and G′ are equivalent

when they generate the same language. Grammars can contain useless rules ornon-terminals and we want to get rid of these while preserving the generatedlanguage. A non-terminal is reachable if there is a derivation from the axiom

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 51: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.1 Tree Grammar 51

containing this non-terminal. A non-terminal A is productive if LG(A) is non-empty. A regular tree grammar is reduced if and only if all its non-terminalsare reachable and productive. We have the following result:

Proposition 2. A regular tree grammar is equivalent to a reduced regular treegrammar.

Proof. Given a grammar G = (S,N,F , R), we can compute the set of reach-able non-terminals and the set of productive non-terminals using the sequences(Reach)n and (Prod)n which are defined in the following way.

Prod0 = ∅Prodn = Prodn−1

∪A ∈ N | ∃(A → α) ∈ R s.t. each non-terminal of α is in Prodn−1

Reach0 = SReachn = Reachn−1

∪A ∈ N | ∃(A′ → α) ∈ R s.t. A′ ∈ Reachn−1 and A occurs in α

For each sequence, there is an index such that all elements of the sequencewith greater index are identical and this element is the set of productive (resp.reachable) non-terminals of G. Each regular tree grammar is equivalent to areduced tree grammar which is computed by the following cleaning algorithm.

Computation of an equivalent reduced grammarinput: a regular tree grammar G = (S,N,F , R).

1. Compute the set of productive non-terminals NProd =⋃

n≥0 Prodn for Gand let G′ = (S,NProd,F , R′) where R′ is the subset of R involving rulescontaining only productive non-terminals.

2. Compute the set of reachable non-terminals NReach =⋃

n≥0 Reachn forG′ (not G) and let G′′ = (S,NReach,F , R′′) where R′′ is the subset of R′

involving rules containing only reachable non-terminals.

output: G′′

The equivalence of G,G′ and G′′ is left to the reader. Moreover each non-terminal A of G′′ must appear in a derivation S

∗→G′′ C[A]

∗→G′′ C[s] which

proves that G′′ is reduced. The reader should notice that exchanging the twosteps of the computation may result in a grammar which is not reduced (seeExercise 22).

Actually, we shall use even simpler grammars, i.e. normalized regular treegrammar, where the production rules have the form A → f(A1, . . . , An) orA → a where f, a are symbols of F and A,A1, . . . , An are non-terminals. Thefollowing result shows that this is not a restriction.

Proposition 3. A regular tree grammar is equivalent to a normalized regulartree grammar.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 52: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

52 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

Proof. Replace a rule A → f(s1, . . . , sn) by A → f(A1, . . . , An) with Ai = si ifsi ∈ N otherwise Ai is a new non-terminal. In the last case add the rule Ai → si.Iterate this process until one gets a (necessarily equivalent) grammar with rulesof the form A → f(A1, . . . , An) or A → a or A1 → A2. The last rules are

replaced by the rules A1 → α for all α 6∈ N such that A1+→Ai and Ai → α ∈ R

(these A′is are easily computed using a transitive closure algorithm).

From now on, we assume that all grammars are normalized, unless this isstated otherwise explicitly.

2.1.2 Regularity and Recognizabilty

Given some normalized regular tree grammar G = (S,N,F , RG), we show howto build a top-down tree automaton which recognizes L(G). We define A =(Q,F , I,∆) by

• Q = qA | A ∈ N

• I = qS

• qA(f(x1, . . . , xn)) → f(qA1(x1), . . . , qAn

(xn)) ∈ ∆ if and only if A →f(A1, . . . , An) ∈ RG.

A standard proof by induction on derivation length yields L(G) = L(A). There-fore we have proved that the languages generated by regular tree grammar arerecognizable languages.

The next question to ask is whether recognizable tree languages can begenerated by regular tree grammars. If L is a regular tree language, thereexists a top-down tree automata A = (Q,F , I,∆) such that L = L(A). Wedefine G = (S,N,F , RG) with S a new symbol, N = Aq | q ∈ Q, RG =Aq → f(Aq1

, . . . , Aqn) | q(f(x1, . . . , xn)) → f(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)) ∈ R∪S →

AI | AI ∈ I. A standard proof by induction on derivation length yields L(G) =L(A).

Combining these two properties, we get the equivalence between recogniz-ability and regularity.

Theorem 18. A tree language is recognizable if and only if it is a regular treelanguage.

2.2 Regular Expressions. Kleene’s Theorem forTree Languages

Going back to our example of lists of non-negative integers, we can write thesets defined by the non-terminals Nat and List as follows.

Nat = 0, s(0), s(s(0)), . . .List = nil, cons( , nil), cons( , cons( , nil), . . .

where stands for any element of Nat. There is some regularity in each setwhich reminds of the regularity obtained with regular word expressions con-structed with the union, concatenation and iteration operators. Therefore we

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 53: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.2 Regular Expressions. Kleene’s Theorem for Tree Languages 53

can try to use the same idea to denote the sets Nat and List. However, since weare dealing with trees and not words, we must put some information to indicatewhere concatenation and iteration must take place. This is done by using anew symbol which behaves as a constant. Moreover, since we have two indepen-dent iterations, the first one for Nat and the second one for List, we shall usetwo different new symbols 21 and 22 and a natural extension of regular wordexpression leads us to denote the sets Nat and List as follows.

Nat = s(21)∗,21 .21

0List = nil + cons( (s(21)

∗,21 .210) ,22)

∗,22 .22nil

Actually the first term nil in the second equality is redundant and a shorter(but slightly less natural) expression yields the same language.

We are going to show that this is a general phenomenon and that we candefine a notion of regular expressions for trees and that Kleene’s theorem forwords can be generalized to trees. Like in the example, we must introduce aparticular set of constants K which are used to indicate the positions whereconcatenation and iteration take place in trees. This explains why the syntaxof regular tree expressions is more cumbersome than the syntax of word regularexpressions. These new constants are usually denoted by 21,22, . . .. Therefore,in this section, we consider trees constructed on F∪K where K is a distinguishedfinite set of symbols of arity 0 disjoint from F .

2.2.1 Substitution and Iteration

First, we have to generalize the notion of substitution to languages, replacingsome 2i by a tree of some language Li. The main difference with term sub-stitution is that different occurrences of the same constant 2i can be replacedby different terms of Li. Given a tree t of T (F ∪ K), 21, . . . ,2n symbols of Kand L1, . . . , Ln languages of T (F ∪K), the tree substitution (substitution forshort) of 21, . . . ,2n by L1, . . . , Ln in t, denoted by t21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln, isthe tree language defined by the following identities.

• 2i21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln = Li for i = 1, . . . , n,

• a21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln = a for all a ∈ F ∪ K such that arity of a is 0and a 6= 21, . . . , a 6= 2n,

• f(s1, . . . , sn)21← L1, . . . ,2n← Ln = f(t1, . . . , tn) | ti ∈ si 21←L1

. . .2n←Ln

Example 19. Let F = 0, nil, s(), cons(, ) and K = 21,22, let

t = cons(21, cons(21,22))

and let

L1 = 0, s(0)

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 54: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

54 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

thent21←L = cons(0, cons(0,22)),

cons(0, cons(s(0),22)),cons(s(0), cons(0,22)),cons(s(0), cons(s(0),22))

Symbols of K are mainly used to distinguish places where the substitutionmust take place, and they are usually not relevant. For instance, if t is a treeon the alphabet F ∪ 2 and L be a language of trees on the alphabet F , thenthe trees of t2 ← L don’t contain the symbol 2.

The substitution operation generalizes to languages in a straightforward way.When L,L1, . . . , Ln are languages of T (F ∪ K) and 21, . . . ,2n are elements ofK, we define L21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln to be the set

⋃t∈L t21←L1, . . . ,2n←

Ln.Now, we can define the concatenation operation for tree languages. Given L

and M two languages of TF∪K, and 2 be a element of K, the concatenation

of M to L through 2, denoted by L .2 M , is the set of trees obtained bysubstituting the occurrence of 2 in trees of L by trees of M , i.e. L .2 M =⋃

t∈Lt2←M.To define the closure of a language, we must define the sequence of successive

iterations. Given L a language of T (F∪K) and 2 an element of K, the sequenceLn,2 is defined by the equalities.

• L0, 2 = 2

• Ln+1, 2 = Ln, 2 ∪ L .2 Ln, 2

The closure L∗,2 of L is the union of all Ln, 2 for non-negative n, i.e., L∗,2 =∪n≥0L

n,2. From the definition, one gets that 2 ⊆ L∗,2 for any L.

Example 20. Let F = 0, nil, s(), cons(, ), let L = 0, cons(0,2) andM = nil, cons(s(0),2), then

L .2 M = 0, cons(0, nil), cons(0, cons(s(0),2))L∗,2 = 2∪

0, cons(0,2)∪0, cons(0,2), cons(0, cons(0,2)) ∪ . . .

We prove now that the substitution and concatenation operations yield reg-ular languages when they are applied to regular languages.

Proposition 4. Let L be a regular tree language on F ∪ K, let L1, . . . , Ln beregular tree languages on F ∪K, let 21, . . . ,2n ∈ K, then L21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln is a regular tree language.

Proof. Since L is regular, there exists some normalized regular tree grammarG = (S,N,F ∪ K, R) such that L = L(G), and for each i = 1, . . . , n thereexists a normalized grammar Gi = (Si, Ni,F ∪ K, Ri) such that Li = L(Gi).We can assume that the sets of non-terminals are pairwise disjoint. The ideaof the proof is to construct a grammar G′ which starts by generating trees like

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 55: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.2 Regular Expressions. Kleene’s Theorem for Tree Languages 55

G but replaces the generation of a symbol 2i by the generation of a tree ofLi via a branching towards the axiom of Gi. More precisely, we show thatL21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln = L(G′) where G′ = (S,N ′,F ∪ K, R′) such that

• N ′ = N ∪ N1 ∪ . . . ∪ Nn,

• R′ contains the rules of Ri and the rules of R but the rules A → 2i whichare replaced by the rules A → Si, where Si is the axiom of Li.

2i 2i

A → 2i A → 2i

Si+→ s Si

+→ s′

Figure 2.1: Replacement of rules A → 2i

A straightforward induction on the height of trees proves that G′ generateseach tree of L21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln.

The converse is to prove that L(G′) ⊆ L21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln. This isachieved by proving the following property by induction on the derivation length.

A+→ s′ where s′ ∈ T (F ∪ K) using the rules of G′

if and only if

there is some s such that A+→ s using the rules of G and

s′ ∈ s21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln.

• base case: A → s in one step. Therefore this derivation is a derivation ofthe grammar G and no 2i occurs in s, yielding s ∈ L21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln

• induction step: we assume that the property is true for any terminal andderivation of length less than n. Let A be such that A → s′ in n steps.

This derivation can be decomposed as A → s1+→ s′. We distinguish several

cases depending on the rule used in the derivation A → s1.

– the rule is A → f(A1, . . . , Am), therefore s′ = f(t1, . . . , tm) and ti ∈L(Ai)21← L1, . . . ,2n← Ln, therefore s′ ∈ L(A)21← L1, . . . ,2n←Ln,

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 56: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

56 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

– the rule is A → Si, therefore A → 2i ∈ R and s′ ∈ Li and s′ ∈L(A)21←L1, . . . ,2n←Ln.

– the rule A → a with a ∈ F , a of arity 0, a 6= 21, . . . , a 6= 2n are notconsidered since no further derivation can be done.

The following proposition states that regular languages are stable also underclosure.

Proposition 5. Let L be a regular tree language of T (F ∪K), let 2 ∈ K, thenL∗,2 is a regular tree language of T (F ∪ K).

Proof. There exists a normalized regular grammar G = (S,N,F ∪ K, R) suchthat L = L(G) and we obtain from G a grammar G′ = (S′, N ∪S′,F ∪K, R′)for L∗,2 by replacing rules leading to 2 such as A → 2 by rules A → S′ leadingto the (new) axiom. Moreover we add the rule S′ → 2 to generate 2 = L0,2

and the rule S′ → S to generate Li,2 for i > 0. By construction G′ generatesthe elements of L∗,2.

Conversely a proof by induction on the length on the derivation proves thatL(G′) ⊆ L∗,2.

2.2.2 Regular Expressions and Regular Tree Languages

Now, we can define regular tree expression in the flavor of regular word expres-sion using the +, .2,∗,2 operators.

Definition 2. The set Regexp(F ,K) of regular tree expressions on F andK is the smallest set such that:

• the empty set ∅ is in Regexp(F ,K)

• if a ∈ F0 ∪ K is a constant, then a ∈ Regexp(F ,K),

• if f ∈ Fn has arity n > 0 and E1, . . . , En are regular expressions ofRegexp(F ,K) then f(E1, . . . , En) is a regular expression of Regexp(F ,K),

• if E1, E2 are regular expressions of Regexp(F ,K) then (E1 + E2) is aregular expression of Regexp(F ,K),

• if E1, E2 are regular expressions of Regexp(F ,K) and 2 is an element ofK then E1 .2 E2 is a regular expression of Regexp(F ,K),

• if E is a regular expression of Regexp(F ,K) and 2 is an element of Kthen E∗,2 is a regular expression of Regexp(F ,K).

Each regular expression E represents a set of terms of T (F ∪ K) which wedenote [[E]] and which is formally defined by the following equalities.

• [[∅]] = ∅,

• [[a]] = a for a ∈ F0 ∪ K,

• [[f(E1, . . . , En)]] = f(s1, . . . , sn) | s1 ∈ [[E1]], . . . , sn ∈ [[En]],

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 57: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.2 Regular Expressions. Kleene’s Theorem for Tree Languages 57

• [[E1 + E2]] = [[E1]] ∪ [[E2]],

• [[E1.2 E2]] = [[E1]]2←[[E2]],

• [[E∗,2]] = [[E]]∗,2

Example 21. Let F = 0, nil, s(), cons(, ) and 2 ∈ K then

(cons(0,2)∗,2).2nil

is a regular expression of Regexp(F ,K) which denotes the set of lists of zeros:

nil, cons(0, nil), cons(0, cons(0, nil)), . . .

In the remaining of this section, we compare the relative expressive powerof regular expressions and regular languages. It is easy to prove that for eachregular expression E, the set [[E]] is a regular tree language. The proof is doneby structural induction on E. The first three cases are obvious and the two lastcases are consequences of Propositions 5 and 4. The converse, i.e. a regular treelanguage can be denoted by a regular expression, is more involved and the proofis similar to the proof of Kleene’s theorem for word language. Let us state theresult first.

Proposition 6. Let A = (Q,F , QF ,∆) be a bottom-up tree automaton, thenthere exists a regular expression E of Regexp(F , Q) such that L(A) = [[E]].

The occurrence of symbols of Q in the regular expression denoting L(A)doesn’t cause any trouble since a regular expression of Regexp(F , Q) can denotea language of TF .

Proof. The proof is similar to the proof for word languages and word automata.For each 1 ≤ i, j,≤ |Q|,K ⊆ Q, we define the set T (i, j,K) as the set of treest of T (F ∪ K) such that there is a run r of A on t satisfying the followingproperties:

• r(ε) = qi,

• r(p) ∈ q1, . . . , qj for all p 6= ε labelled by a function symbol.

Roughly speaking, a term is in T (i, j,K) if we can reach qi at the root byusing only states in q1, . . . , qj when we assume that the leaves are states of K.By definition, L(A) the language accepted by A is the union of the T (i, |Q|, ∅)’sfor i such that qi is a final state: these terms are the terms of T (F) suchthat there is a successful run using any possible state of Q. Now, we proveby induction on j that T (i, j,K) can be denoted by a regular expression ofRegexp(F , Q).

• Base case j = 0. The set T (i, 0,K) is the set of trees t where the root islabelled by qi, the leaves are in F ∪ K and no internal node is labelledby some q. Therefore there exist a1, . . . , an, a ∈ F ∪ K such that t =f(a1, . . . , an) or t = a, hence T (i, 0,K) is finite and can be denoted by aregular expression of Regexp(F ∪ Q).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 58: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

58 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

• Induction case. Let us assume that for any i′,K ′ ⊆ Q and 0 ≤ j′ < j, theset T (i′, j′,K ′) can be denoted by a regular expression. We can write thefollowing equality:

T (i, j, K) = T (i, j − 1, K)∪T (i, j − 1, K ∪ qj) .qj T (j, j − 1, K ∪ qj)

∗,qj .qj T (j, j − 1, K)

The inclusion of T (i, j,K) in the right-hand side of the equality can beeasily seen from Figure 2.2.2.

qj

qj

qj

T(j,

j−

1,K

∪qj

)∗,q

j.q

jT

(j,j−

1,K

)

qi

qj

qj

T (j, j − 1, K)

T(j,

j−

1,K

∪qj

)∗,q

j.q

jT

(j,j−

1,K

)

T (j, j − 1, K)

qj

Figure 2.2: Decomposition of a term of T (i, j,K)

The converse inclusion is also not difficult. By definition:T (i, j − 1, K) ⊆ T (i, j, K)

and an easy proof by induction on the number of occurrences of qj yields:T (i, j − 1, K ∪ qj) .qj T (j, j − 1, K ∪ qj)

∗,qj .qj T (j, j − 1, K) ⊆ T (i, j, K)

By induction hypothesis, each set of the right-hand side of the equalitydefining T (i, j,K) can be denoted by a regular expression of Regex(F∪Q).This yields the desired result because the union of these sets is representedby the sum of the corresponding expressions.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 59: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.3 Regular Equations 59

Since we have already seen that regular expressions denote recognizable treelanguages and that recognizable languages are regular, we can state Kleene’stheorem for tree languages.

Theorem 19. A tree language is recognizable if and only if it can be denotedby a regular tree expression.

2.3 Regular Equations

Looking at our example of the set of lists of non-negative integers, we canrealize that these lists can be defined by equations instead of grammar rules.For instance, denoting set union by +, we could replace the grammar given inSection 2.1.1 by the following equations.

Nat = 0 + s(Nat)List = nil + cons(Nat, List)

where the variables are List and Nat. To get the usual lists of non-negativenumbers, we must restrict ourselves to the least fixed-point solution of this setof equations. Systems of language equations do not always have solution nordoes a least solution always exists. Therefore we shall study regular equation

systems defined as follows.

Definition 3. Let X1, . . . ,Xn be variables denoting sets of trees, for 1 ≤ j ≤ p,1 ≤ i ≤ mj,let sj

i ’s be terms over F ∪ X1, . . . ,Xn, then a regular equationsystem S is a set of equations of the form:

X1 = s11 + . . . + s1

m1

. . .Xp = sp

1 + . . . + spmp

A solution of S is any n-tuple (L1, . . . , Ln) of languages of T (F) such that

L1 = s11X1←L1, . . . , Xn←Ln ∪ . . . ∪ s1

m1X1←L1, . . . , Xn←Ln

. . .Lp = sp

1X1←L1, . . . , Xn←Ln ∪ . . . ∪ spmp

X1←L1, . . . , Xn←Ln

Since equations with the same left-hand side can be merged into one equa-tion, and since we can add equations Xk = Xk without changing the set ofsolutions of a system, we assume in the following that p = n.

The ordering ⊆ is defined on T (F)n by

(L1, . . . , Ln) ⊆ (L′1, . . . , L

′n) iffLi ⊆ L′

i for all i = 1, . . . , n

By definition (∅, . . . , ∅) is the smallest element of ⊆ and each increasingsequence has an upper bound. To a system of equations, we associate the fixed-point operator T S : T (F)n → T (F)n defined by:

T S(L1, . . . , Ln) = (L′1, . . . , L

′n)

whereL′

1 = L1 ∪ s11X1←L1, . . . , Xn←Ln ∪ . . . ∪ s1

m1X1←L1, . . . , Xn←Ln

. . .L′

n = Ln ∪ sn1 X1←L1, . . . , Xn←Ln ∪ . . . ∪ sn

mnX1←L1, . . . , Xn←Ln

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 60: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

60 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

Example 22. Let S be

Nat = 0 + s(Nat)List = nil + cons(Nat, List)

thenT S(∅, ∅) = (0, nil)T S2(∅, ∅) = (0, s(0), nil, cons(0, nil))

Using a classical approach we use the fixed-point operator to compute theleast fixed-point solution of a system of equations.

Proposition 7. The fixed-point operator T S is continuous and its least fixed-point T Sω(∅, . . . , ∅) is the least solution of S.

Proof. We show that T S is continuous in order to use Knaster-Tarski’s theoremon continuous operators. By construction, T S is monotonous, and the lastpoint is to prove that if S1 ⊆ S2 ⊆ . . . is an increasing sequence of n-tuples oflanguages, the equality T S(

⋃i≥1 Si) =

⋃i≥1 T S(Si)) holds. By definition, each

Si can be written as (Si1, . . . , S

in).

• We have that⋃

i=1,... T S(Si) ⊆ T S(⋃

i=1,...(Si) holds since the sequenceS1 ⊆ S2 ⊆ . . . is increasing and the operator T S is monotonous.

• Conversely we must prove T S(⋃

i=1,... Si) ⊆⋃

i=1,... T S(Si)).

Let v = (v1, . . . , vn) ∈ T S(⋃

i=1,... Si). Then for each k = 1, . . . , n

either vk ∈⋃

i=1,... Si hence vk ∈ Slk for some lk, or there is some

u = (u1, . . . , un) ∈⋃

i≥1 Si such that vk = skjkX1 ← u1, . . . ,Xn ← un.

Since the sequence (Si, i≥1) is increasing we have that u ∈ Slk for some lk.Therefore vk ∈ T S(SL) ⊆ T S(

⋃i=1,... Si) for L = maxlk | k = 1, . . . , n.

We have introduced systems of regular equations to get an algebraic charac-terization of regular tree languages stated in the following theorem.

Theorem 20. The least fixed-point solution of a system of regular equationsis a tuple of regular tree languages. Conversely each regular tree language is acomponent of the least solution of a system of regular equations.

Proof. Let S be a system of regular equations, and let Gi = (Xi, X1, . . . ,Xn,F , R)where R = ∪k=1,...,nXk → s1

k, . . . ,Xk → sjk

k if the kth equation of S is

Xk = s1k + . . . + sjk

k . We show that L(Gi) is the ith component of (L1, . . . , Ln)the least fixed-point solution of S.

• We prove that T Sp(∅, . . . , ∅) ⊆ (L(G1), . . . , L(Gn)) by induction on p.

Let us assume that this property holds for all p′ ≤ p. Let u = (u1, . . . , un)be an element of TSp+1(∅, . . . , ∅) = T S(T Sp(∅, . . . , ∅)). For each i in

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 61: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.4 Context-free Word Languages and Regular Tree Languages 61

1, . . . , n, either ui ∈ T Sp(∅, . . . , ∅) and ui ∈ L(Gi) by induction hypoth-esis, or there exist vi = (vi

1, . . . , vin) ∈ TSp(∅, . . . , ∅) and sj

i such that

ui = sjiX1 → vi

1, . . . ,Xn → vin. By induction hypothesis vi

j ∈ L(Gj) forj = 1, . . . , n therefore ui ∈ L(Gi).

• We prove now that (L(X1), . . . , L(Xn)) ⊆ T Sω(∅, . . . , ∅) by induction onderivation length.

Let us assume that for each i = 1, . . . , n, for each p′ ≤ p, if Xi →p′

ui thenui ∈ T Sp′

(∅, . . . , ∅). Let Xi →p+1 ui, then Xi → sji (X1, . . . ,Xn) →p vi

with ui = sji (v1, . . . , vn) and Xj →p′

vj for some p′ ≤ p. By induction

hypothesis vj ∈ T Sp′

(∅, . . . , ∅) which yields that ui ∈ T Sp+1(∅, . . . , ∅).

Conversely, given a regular grammar G = (S, A1, . . . , An,F , R), with R =A1 → s1

1, . . . , A1 → s1p1

, . . . , An → sn1 , . . . , An → sn

pn, a similar proof yields

that the least solution of the system

A1 = s11 + . . . + s1

p1

. . .An = sn

1 + . . . + snpn

is (L(A1), . . . , L(An)).

Example 23. The grammar with axiom List, non-terminals List,Nat termi-nals 0, s(), nil, cons(, ) and rules

List → nilList → cons(Nat, List)Nat → 0Nat → s(Nat)

generates the second component of the least solution of the system given inExample 22.

2.4 Context-free Word Languages and RegularTree Languages

Context-free word languages and regular tree languages are strongly related.This is not surprising since derivation trees of context-free languages and deriva-tions of tree grammars look alike. For instance let us consider the context-freelanguage of arithmetic expressions on +,∗ and a variable x. A context-free wordgrammar generating this set is E → x | E + E | E ∗ E where E is the axiom.The generation of a word from the axiom can be described by a derivation treewhich has the axiom at the root and where the generated word can be readby picking up the leaves of the tree from the left to the right (computing whatwe call the yield of the tree). The rules for constructing derivation trees showsome regularity, which suggests that this set of trees is regular. The aim of thissection is to show that this is true indeed. However, there are some traps which

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 62: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

62 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

must be avoided when linking tree and word languages. First, we describe howto relate word and trees. The symbols of F are used to build trees but alsowords (by taking a symbol of F as a letter). The Yield operator computes aword from a tree by concatenating the leaves of the tree from the left to theright. More precisely, it is defined as follows.

Yield(a) = a if aıF0,

Yield(f(s1, . . . , sn)) = Yield(s1) . . .Yield(sn) if f ∈ Fn, si ∈ T (F).

Example 24. Let F = x,+, ∗, E(, , ) and let

s =x ∗

x + x

E

E

then Yield(s) = x ∗ x + x which is a word on x, ∗,+. Note that ∗ and + arenot the usual binary operator but syntactical symbols of arity 0. If

t =

x ∗ x

E + x

E

then Yield(t) = x ∗ x + x.

We recall that a context-free word grammar G is a tuple (S,N, T,R)where S is the axiom, N the set of non-terminals letters, T the set of terminalletters, R the set of production rules of the form A → α with A ∈ N,α ∈(T ∪N)∗. The usual definition of derivation trees of context free word languagesallow nodes labelled by a non-terminal A to have a variable number of sons,which is equal to the length of the right-hand side α of the rule A → α used tobuild the derivation tree at this node.

Since tree languages are defined for signatures where each symbol has a fixedarity, we introduce a new symbol (A,m) for each A ∈ N such that there is a ruleA → α with α of length m. Let G be the set composed of these new symbolsand of the symbols of T . The set of derivation trees issued from a ∈ G, denotedby D(G, a) is the smallest set such that:

• D(G, a) = a if a ∈ T ,

• (a, 0)(ε) ∈ D(G, a) if a → ε ∈ R where ε is the empty word,

• (a, p)(t1, . . . , tp) ∈ D(G, (a, p)) if t1 ∈ D(G, a1), . . . , tp ∈ D(G, ap) and(a → a1 . . . ap) ∈ R where ai ∈ G.

The set of derivation trees of G is D(G) = ∪(S,i)∈GD(G, (S, i)).

Example 25. Let T = x,+, ∗ and let G be the context free word grammarwith axiom S, non terminal Op, and rules

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 63: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.4 Context-free Word Languages and Regular Tree Languages 63

S → S Op SS → xOp → +Op → ∗

Let the word u = x ∗ x + x, a derivation tree for u with G is dG(u), and thesame derivation tree with our notations is DG(u) ∈ D(G,S)

dG(u) =

x

S

Op

x

S

+

Op

x

S

S

S

; DG(u) =

x

(S, 1)

(Op, 1)

x

(S, 1)

+

(Op, 1)

x

(S, 1)

(S, 3)

(S, 3)

By definition, the language generated by a context-free word grammar G isthe set of words computed by applying the Yield operator to derivation trees ofG. The next theorem states how context-free word languages and regular treelanguages are related.

Theorem 21. The following statements hold.

1. Let G be a context-free word grammar, then the set of derivation trees ofL(G) is a regular tree language.

2. Let L be a regular tree language then Yield(L) is a context-free word lan-guage.

3. There exists a regular tree language which is not the set of derivation treesof a context-free language.

Proof. We give the proofs of the three statements.

1. Let G = (S,N, T,R) be a context-free word language. We consider thetree grammar G′ = (S,N,F , R′)) such that

• the axiom and the set of non-terminal symbols of G and G′ are thesame,

• F = T ∪ ε ∪ (A,n) | A ∈ N, ∃A → α ∈ R with α of length n,

• if A → ε then A → (A, 0)(ε) ∈ R′

• if (A → a1 . . . ap) ∈ R then (A → (A, p)(a1, . . . , ap)) ∈ R′

Then L(G) = Yield(s) | s ∈ L(G′). The proof is a standard induction onderivation length. It is interesting to remark that there may and usuallydoes exist several tree languages (not necessarily regular) such that thecorresponding word language obtained via the Yield operator is a givencontext-free word language.

2. Let G be a normalized tree grammar (S,X,N,R). We build the wordcontext-free grammar G′ = (S,X,N,R′) such that a rule X → X1 . . . Xn

(resp. X → a) is in R′ if and only if the rule X → f(X1, . . . ,Xn) (resp.X → a) is in R for some f . It is straightforward to prove by induction onthe length of derivation that L(G′) = Yield(L(G)).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 64: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

64 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

3. Let G be the regular tree grammar with axiom X, non-terminals X,Y,Z,terminals a, b, g and rules

X → f(Y,Z)Y → g(a)Z → g(b)

The language L(G) consists of the single tree (arity have been indicatedexplicitly to make the link with derivation trees):

a

(g, 1)

b

(g, 1)

(f, 2)

Assume that L(G) is the set of derivation trees of some context-free wordgrammar. To generate the first node of the tree, one must have a ruleF → G G where F is the axiom and rules G → a, G → b (to get the innernodes). Therefore the following tree:

a

(g, 1)

a

(g, 1)

(f, 2)

should be in L(G) which is not the case.

2.5 Beyond Regular Tree Languages: Context-free Tree Languages

For word language, the story doesn’t end with regular languages but there is astrict hierarchy.

regular ⊂ context-free ⊂ recursively enumerable

Recursively enumerable tree languages are languages generated by tree gram-mar as defined in the beginning of the chapter, and this class is far too generalfor having good properties. Actually, any Turing machine can be simulated bya one rule rewrite system which shows how powerful tree grammars are (anygrammar rule can be seen as a rewrite rule by considering both terminals andnon-terminals as syntactical symbols). Therefore, most of the research has beendone on context-free tree languages which we describe now.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 65: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.5 Beyond Regular Tree Languages: Context-free Tree Languages 65

2.5.1 Context-free Tree Languages

A context-free tree grammar is a tree grammar G = (S,N,F , R) where therules have the form X(x1, . . . , xn) → t with t a tree of T (F ∪N ∪x1, . . . , xn),x1, . . . , xn ∈ X where X is a set of reserved variables with X ∩ (F ∪ N) = ∅,X a non-terminal of arity n. The definition of the derivation relation is slightlymore complicated than for regular tree grammar: a term t derives a term t′

if no variable of X occurs in t or t′, there is a rule l → r of the grammar, asubstitution σ such that the domain of σ is included in X and a context Csuch that t = C[lσ] and t′ = C[rσ]. The context-free tree language L(G)is the set of trees which can be derived from the axiom of the context-free treegrammar G.

Example 26. The grammar of axiom Prog, set of non-terminals Prog,Nat, Fact(),set of terminals 0, s, if(, ), eq(, ), not(), times(, ), dec() and rules

Prog → Fact(Nat)Nat → 0Nat → s(Nat)Fact(x) → if(eq(x, 0), s(0))Fact(x) → if(not(eq(x, 0)), times(x, Fact(dec(x))))

where X = x is a context-free tree grammar. The reader can easily see thatthe last rule is the classical definition of the factorial function.

The derivation relation associated to a context-free tree grammar G is a gen-eralization of the derivation relation for regular tree grammar. The derivationrelation → is a relation on pairs of terms of T (F∪N) such that s → t iff there isa rule X(x1, . . . , xn) → α ∈ R, a context C such that s = C[X(t1, . . . , tn)] andt = C[αx1← t1, . . . , xn← tn]. For instance, the previous grammar can yieldthe sequence of derivations

Prog → Fact(Nat) → Fact(0) → if(eq(0, 0), s(0))

The language generated by G, denoted by L(G) is the set of terms of T (F)which can be reached by successive derivations starting from the axiom. Suchlanguages are called context-free tree languages. Context-free tree languages areclosed under union, concatenation and closure. Like in the word case, one candefine pushdown tree automata which recognize exactly the set of context-freetree languages. We discuss only IO and OI grammars and we refer the readerto the bibliographic notes for more informations.

2.5.2 IO and OI Tree Grammars

Context-free tree grammars have been extensively studied in connection withthe theory of recursive program scheme. A non-terminal F can be seen asa function name and production rules F (x1, . . . , xn) → t define the function.Recursive definitions are allowed since t may contain occurrences of F . Since weknow that such recursive definitions may not give the same results depending

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 66: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

66 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

on the evaluation strategy, IO and OI tree grammars have been introduced toaccount for such differences.

A context-free grammar is IO (for innermost-outermost) if we restrict legalderivations to derivations where the innermost terminals are derived first. Thiscontrol corresponds to call by value evaluation. A context-free grammar is OI

(for outermost-innermost) if we restrict legal derivations to derivations wherethe outermost terminals are derived first. This corresponds to call by nameevaluation. Therefore, given one context-free grammar G, we can define IO-Gand OI-G and the next example shows that the languages generated by thesegrammars may be different.

Example 27. Let G be the context-free grammar with axiom Exp, non-terminals Exp,Nat,Dup, terminals double, s, 0) and rulesExp → Dup(Nat)Nat → s(Nat)Nat → 0Dup(x) → double(x, x)

Then outermost-innermost derivations have the form

Exp → Dup(Nat) → double(Nat,Nat)∗→ double(sn(0), sm(0))

while innermost-outermost derivations have the form

Exp → Dup(Nat)∗→Dup(sn(0)) → double(sn(0), sn(0))

Therefore L(OI-G) = double(sn(0), sm(0)) | n,m ∈ N andL(IO-G) = double(sn(0), sn(0)) | n ∈ N.

A tree language L is IO if there is some context-free grammar G such thatL = L(IO-G). The next theorem shows the relation between L(IO-G), L(OI-G)and L(G).

Theorem 22. The following inclusion holds: L(IO-G) ⊆ L(OI-G) = L(G)

Example 27 shows that the inclusion can be strict. IO-languages are closedunder intersection with regular languages and union, but the closure underconcatenation requires another definition of concatenation: all occurrences of aconstant generated by a non right-linear rule are replaced by the same term, asshown by the next example.

Example 28. Let G be the context-free grammar with axiom Exp, non-terminals Exp,Nat, Fct, terminals 2, f( , , ) and rulesExp → Fct(Nat,Nat)Nat → 2

Fct(x, y) → f(x, x, y)and let L = IO-G and M = 0, 1, then L.2M contains f(0, 0, 0),f(0, 0, 1),f(1, 1, 0), f(1, 1, 1) but not f(1, 0, 1) nor f(0, 1, 1).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 67: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.6 Exercises 67

There is a lot of work on the extension of results on context-free word gram-mars and languages to context-free tree grammars and languages. Unfortu-nately, many constructions and theorem can’t be lifted to the tree case. Usuallythe failure is due to non-linearity which expresses that the same subtrees mustoccur at different positions in the tree. A similar phenomenon occurred when westated results on recognizable languages and tree homomorphisms: the inverseimage of a recognizable tree language by a tree homorphism is recognizable, butthe assumption that the homomorphism is linear is needed to show that thedirect image is recognizable.

2.6 Exercises

Exercise 20. Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Consider the automaton A = (Q,F , Qf , ∆)defined by: Q = q, qg, qf, Qf = qf, and ∆ =

a → q(a) g(q(x)) → q(g(x))g(q(x)) → qg(g(x)) g(qg(x)) → qf (g(x))

f(q(x), q(y)) → q(f(x, y)) .

Define a regular tree grammar generating L(A).

Exercise 21.

1. Prove the equivalence of a regular tree grammar and of the reduced regular treegrammar computed by algorithm of proposition 2.

2. Let F = f(, ), g(), a. Let G be the regular tree grammar with axiom X,non-terminal A, and rules

X → f(g(A), A)A → g(g(A))

Define a top-down NFTA, a NFTA and a DFTA for L(G). Is it possible todefine a top-down DFTA for this language?

Exercise 22. Let F = f(, ), a. Let G be the regular tree grammar with axiom X,non-terminals A, B, C and rules

X → CX → aX → AA → f(A, B)B → a

Compute the reduced regular tree grammar equivalent to G applying the algorithm

defined in the proof of Proposition 2. Now, consider the same algorithm, but first

apply step 2 and then step 1. Is the output of this algorithm reduced ? equivalent to

G ?

Exercise 23.

1. Prove Theorem 6 using regular tree grammars.

2. Prove Theorem 7 using regular tree grammars.

Exercise 24. (Local languages) Let F be a signature, let t be a term of T (F), thenwe define fork(t) as follows:

• fork(a) = ∅, for each constant symbol a;

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 68: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

68 Regular Grammars and Regular Expressions

• fork(f(t1, . . . , tn)) = f(Head(t1), . . . ,Head(tn)) ∪Si=n

i=1 fork(ti)

A tree language L is local if and only if there exist a set F ′ ⊆ F and a set

G ⊆ fork(T (F)) such that t ∈ L iff root(t) ∈ F ′ and fork(t) ⊆ G. Prove that every

local tree language is a regular tree language. Prove that a language is local iff it is

the set of derivation trees of a context-free word language.

Exercise 25. The pumping lemma for context-free word languages states:

for each context-free language L, there is some constant k ≥ 1 such thateach z ∈ L of length greater than or equal to k can be written z = uvwxysuch that vx is not the empty word, vwx has length less than or equal tok, and for each n ≥ 0, the word uvnwxny is in L.

Prove this result using the pumping lemma for tree languages and the results of this

chapter.

Exercise 26. Another possible definition for the iteration of a language is:

• L0, 2 = 2

• Ln+1, 2 = Ln, 2 ∪ Ln, 2 .2 L

(Unfortunately that definition was given in the previous version of TATA)

1. Show that this definition may generate non-regular tree languages. Hint: onebinary symbol f( , ) and 2 are enough.

2. Are the two definitions equivalent (i.e. generate the same languages) if Σ consistsof unary symbols and constants only?

Exercise 27. Let F be a ranked alphabet, let t be a term of T (F), then we definethe word language Branch(t) as follows:

• Branch(a) = a, for each constant symbol a;

• Branch(f(t1, . . . , tn)) =Si=n

i=1 fu | u ∈ Branch(ti)

Let L be a regular tree language, prove that Branch(L) =S

t∈LBranch(t) is a regular

word language. What about the converse?

Exercise 28.

1. Let F be a ranked alphabet such that F0 = a, b. Find a regular tree languageL such that Yield(L) = anbn | n ≥ 0. Find a non regular tree language Lsuch that Yield(L) = anbn | n ≥ 0.

2. Same questions with Yield(L) = u ∈ F∗0 | |u|a = |u|b where |u|a (respectively

|u|b) denotes the number of a (respectively the number of b) in u.

3. Let F be a ranked alphabet such that F0 = a, b, c, let A1 = anbncp | n, p ≥0, and let A2 = anbpcp | n, p ≥ 0. Find regular tree languages such thatYield(L1) = A1 and Yield(L2) = A2. Does there exist a regular tree languagesuch that Yield(L) = A1 ∩ A2.

Exercise 29.

1. Let G be the context free word grammar with axiom X, terminals a, b, andrules

X → XXX → aXbX → ε

where ε stands for the empty word. What is the word language L(G)? Give aderivation tree for u = aabbab.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 69: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

2.7 Bibliographic notes 69

2. Let G′ be the context free word grammar in Greibach normal form with axiomX, non terminals X ′, Y ′, Z′ terminals a, b, and rules l

X ′ → aX ′Y ′

X ′ → aY ′

X ′ → aX ′Z′

X ′ → aZ′

Y ′ → bX ′

Z′ → b

prove that L(G′) = L(G). Give a derivation tree for u = aabbab.

3. Find a context free word grammar G′′ such that L(G′′) = A1 ∪ A2 (A1 and A2

are defined in Exercise 28). Give two derivation trees for u = abc.

Exercise 30. Let F be a ranked alphabet.

1. Let L and L′ be two regular tree languages. Compare the sets Yield(L ∩ L′)and Yield(L) ∩ Yield(L′).

2. Let A be a subset of F0. Prove that T (F , A) = T (F ∩ A) is a regular treelanguage. Let L be a regular tree language over F , compare the sets Yield(L ∩T (F , A)) and Yield(L) ∩ Yield(T (F , A)).

3. Let R be a regular word language over F0. Let T (F , R) = t ∈ T (F) |Yield(t) ∈ R. Prove that T (F , R) is a regular tree language. Let L be a regu-lar tree language over F , compare the sets Yield(L ∩ T (F , R)) and Yield(L) ∩Yield(T (F , R)). As a consequence of the results obtained in the present exer-cise, what could be said about the intersection of a context free word languageand of a regular tree language?

2.7 Bibliographic notes

This chapter only scratches the topic of tree grammars and related topics. Auseful reference on algebraic aspects of regular tree language is [GS84] whichcontains a lot of classical results on these features. There is a huge litterature ontree grammars and related topics, which is also relevant for the chapter on treetransducers, see the references given in this chapter. Systems of equations canbe generalized to formal tree series with similar results [BR82, Boz99, Boz01,Kui99, Kui01]. The notion of pushdown tree automaton has been introduced byGuessarian [Gue83] and generalized to formal tree series by Kuich [Kui01] Thereader may consult [Eng82, ES78] for IO and OI grammars. The connectionbetween recursive program scheme and formalisms for regular tree languages isalso well-known, see [Cou86] for instance. We should mention that some openproblems like equivalence of deterministic tree grammars are now solved usingthe result of Senizergues on the equivalence of deterministic pushdown wordautomata [Sen97].

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 70: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata
Page 71: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Chapter 3

Logic, Automata andRelations

3.1 Introduction

As early as in the 50s, automata, and in particular tree automata, played animportant role in the development of verification . Several well-known logicians,such as A. Church, J.R. Buchi, Elgott, MacNaughton, M. Rabin and otherscontributed to what is called “the trinity” by Trakhtenbrot: Logic, Automataand Verification (of Boolean circuits).

The idea is simple: given a formula φ with free variables x1, ..., xn and a do-main of interpretation D, φ defines the subset of Dn containing all assignmentsof the free variables x1, . . . , xn that satisfy φ. Hence formulas in this case arejust a way of defining subsets of Dn (also called n-ary relations on D). In casen = 1 (and, as we will see, also for n > 1), finite automata provide anotherway of defining subsets of Dn. In 1960, Bchi realized that these two ways ofdefining relations over the free monoid 0, . . . , n∗ coincide when the logic isthe sequential calculus, also called weak second-order monadic logic with onesuccessor, WS1S. This result was extended to tree automata: Doner, Thatcherand Wright showed that the definability in the weak second-order monadic logicwith k successors, WSkS coincide with the recognizability by a finite tree au-tomaton. These results imply in particular the decidability of WSkS, followingthe decision results on tree automata (see chapter 1).

These ideas are the basis of several decision techniques for various logicssome of which will be listed in Section 3.4. In order to illustrate this correspon-dence, consider Presburger’s arithmetic: the atomic formulas are equalities andinequalities s = t or s ≥ t where s, t are sums of variables and constants. For in-stance x+y+y = z+z+z+1+1, also written x+2y = 3z+2, is an atomic formula.In other words, atomic formulas are linear Diophantine (in)equations. Thenatomic formulas can be combined using any logical connectives among ∧,∨,¬and quantifications ∀,∃. For instance ∀x.(∀y.¬(x = 2y)) ⇒ (∃y.x = 2y+1)) is a(true) formula of Presburger’s arithmetic. Formulas are interpreted in the natu-ral numbers (non-negative integers), each symbol having its expected meaning.A solution of a formula φ(x) whose only free variable is x, is an assignment ofx to a natural number n such that φ(n) holds true in the interpretation. For

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 72: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

72 Logic, Automata and Relations

000

101

110

011

0

10

010

001

111

Figure 3.1: The automaton with accepts the solutions of x = y + z

instance, if φ(x) is the formula ∃y.x = 2y, its solutions are the even numbers.

Writing integers in base 2, they can be viewed as elements of the free monoid0, 1∗, i.e. words of 0s and 1s. The representation of a natural number is notunique as 01 = 1, for instance. Tuples of natural numbers are displayed bystacking their representations in base 2 and aligning on the right, then complet-ing with some 0s on the left in order to get a rectangle of bits. For instance the

pair (13,6) is represented as10

11

01

10 (or

00

10

11

01

10 as well). Hence, we can see the

solutions of a formula as a subset of (0, 1n)∗ where n is the number of freevariables of the formula.

It is not difficult to see that the set of solutions of any atomic formula isrecognized by a finite word automaton working on the alphabet 0, 1n. Forinstance, the solutions of x = y + z are recognized by the automaton of Figure3.1.

Then, and that is probably one of the key ideas, each logical connectivecorresponds to a basic operation on automata (here word automata): ∨ is aunion, ∧ and intersection, ¬ a complement, ∃x a projection (an operation whichwill be defined in Section 3.2.4). It follows that the set of solutions of anyPresburger formula is recognized by a finite automaton.

In particular, a closed formula (without free variable), holds true in theinterpretation if the initial state of the automaton is also final. It holds falseotherwise. Therefore, this gives both a decision technique for Presburger formu-las by computing automata and an effective representation of the set of solutionsfor open formulas.

The example of Presburger’s arithmetic we just sketched is not isolated.That is one of the purposes of this chapter to show how to relate finite treeautomata and formulas.

In general, the problem with these techniques is to design an appropriatenotion of automaton, which is able to recognize the solutions of atomic formulasand which has the desired closure and decision properties. We have to cite herethe famous Rabin automata which work on infinite trees and which have indeedthe closure and decidability properties, allowing to decide the full second-ordermonadic logic with k successors (a result due to M. Rabin, 1969). It is howeverout of the scope of this book to survey automata techniques in logic and com-puter science. We restrict our attention to finite automata on finite trees andrefer to the excellent surveys [Rab77, Tho90] for more details on other applica-tions of automata to logic.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 73: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.2 Automata on Tuples of Finite Trees 73

We start this chapter by reviewing some possible definitions of automataon pairs (or, more generally, tuples) of finite trees in Section 3.2. We define inthis way several notions of recognizability for relations, which are not necessaryunary, extending the frame of chapter 1. This extension is necessary since,automata recognizing the solutions of formulas actually recognize n-tuples ofsolutions, if there are n free variables in the formula.

The most natural way of defining a notion of recognizability on tuples is toconsider products of recognizable sets. Though this happens to be sometimessufficient, this notion is often too weak. For instance the example of Figure 3.1could not be defined as a product of recognizable sets. Rather, we stacked thewords and recognized these codings. Such a construction can be generalized totrees (we have to overlap instead of stacking) and gives rise to a second notionof recognizability. We will also introduce a third class called “Ground TreeTransducers” which is weaker than the second class above but enjoys strongerclosure properties, for instance by iteration. Its usefulness will become evidentin Section 3.4.

Next, in Section 3.3, we introduce the weak second-order monadic logic withk successor and show Thatcher and Wright’s theorem which relates this logicwith finite tree automata. This is a modest insight into the relations betweenlogic and automata.

Finally in Section 3.4 we survey a number of applications, mostly issuedfrom Term Rewriting or Constraint Solving. We do not detail this part (wegive references instead). The goal is to show how the simple techniques devel-oped before can be applied to various questions, with a special emphasis ondecision problems. We consider the theories of sort constraints in Section 3.4.1,the theory of linear encompassment in Section 3.4.2, the theory of ground termrewriting in Section 3.4.3 and reduction strategies in orthogonal term rewrit-ing in Section 3.4.4. Other examples are given as exercises in Section 3.5 orconsidered in chapters 4 and 5.

3.2 Automata on Tuples of Finite Trees

3.2.1 Three Notions of Recognizability

Let Rec× be the subset of n-ary relations on T (F) which are finite unions ofproducts S1 × . . .×Sn where S1, . . . , Sn are recognizable subsets of T (F). Thisnotion of recognizability of pairs is the simplest one can imagine. Automata forsuch relations consist of pairs of tree automata which work independently. Thisnotion is however quite weak, as e.g. the diagonal

∆ = (t, t) | t ∈ T (F)

does not belong to Rec×. Actually a relation R ∈ Rec× does not really relateits components !

The second notion of recognizability is used in the correspondence withWSkS and is strictly stronger than the above one. Roughly, it consists in over-lapping the components of a n-tuple, yielding a term on a product alphabet.Then define Rec as the set of sets of pairs of terms whose overlapping coding isrecognized by a tree automaton on the product alphabet.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 74: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

74 Logic, Automata and Relations

f , f → ff

g f gf

a a aa

g a ga

a ⊥ aa a ⊥

Figure 3.2: The overlap of two terms

Let us first define more precisely the notion of “coding”. (This is illustratedby an example on Figure 3.2). We let F ′ = (F∪⊥)n, where ⊥ is a new symbol.This is the idea of “stacking” the symbols, as in the introductory example ofPresburger’s arithmetic. Let k be the maximal arity of a function symbol in F .Assuming ⊥ has arity 0, the arities of function symbols in F ′ are defined bya(f1 . . . fn) = max(a(f1), . . . , a(fn)).

The coding of two terms t1, t2 ∈ T (F) is defined by induction:

[f(t1, . . . , tn), g(u1, . . . , um)]def= fg([t1, u1], . . . [tm, um], [tm+1,⊥], . . . , [tn,⊥])

if n ≥ m and

[f(t1, . . . , tn), g(u1, . . . , um)]def= fg([t1, u1], . . . [tn, un], [⊥, un+1], . . . , [⊥, um])

if m ≥ n.More generally, the coding of n terms f1(t

11, . . . , t

k11 ), . . . , fn(tn1 , . . . , tkn

n ) isdefined as

f1 . . . fn([t11, . . . , t1n], . . . , [tm1 , . . . , tmn ])

where m is the maximal arity of f1, . . . , fn ∈ F and tji is, by convention, ⊥ whenj > ki.

Definition 4. Rec is the set of relations R ⊆ T (F)n such that

[t1, . . . , tn] | (t1, . . . , tn) ∈ R

is recognized by a finite tree automaton on the alphabet F ′ = (F ∪ ⊥)n.

For example, consider the diagonal ∆, it is in Rec since its coding is recog-nized by the bottom-up tree automaton whose only state is q (also a final state)and transitions are the rules ff(q, . . . , q) → q for all symbols f ∈ F .

One drawback of this second notion of recognizability is that it is not closedunder iteration. More precisely, there is a binary relation R which belongs toRec and whose transitive closure is not in Rec (see Section 3.5). For this reason,a third class of recognizable sets of pairs of trees was introduced: the GroundTree Transducers (GTT for short) .

Definition 5. A GTT is a pair of bottom-up tree automata (A1,A2) workingon the same alphabet. Their sets of states may however share some symbols (thesynchronization states).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 75: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.2 Automata on Tuples of Finite Trees 75

t =

t’=

t1 tn t’1 t’n

q1 qn

C

Figure 3.3: GTT acceptance

A pair (t, t′) is recognized by a GTT (A1,A2) if there is a context C ∈ Cn(F)such that t = C[t1, . . . , tn], t′ = C[t′1, . . . , t

′n] and there are states q1, . . . , qn of

both automata such that, for all i, ti∗

−−→A1

qi and t′i∗

−−→A2

qi. We write L(A1,A2)

the language accepted by the GTT (A1,A2), i.e. the set of pairs of terms whichare recognized.

The recognizability by a GTT is depicted on Figure 3.3. For instance, ∆ isaccepted by a GTT. Another typical example is the binary relation “one stepparallel rewriting” for term rewriting system whose left members are linear andwhose right hand sides are ground (see Section 3.4.3).

3.2.2 Examples of The Three Notions of Recognizability

The first example illustrates Rec×. It will be developed in a more generalframework in Section 3.4.2.

Example 29. Consider the alphabet F = f, g, a where f is binary, g is unaryand a is a constant. Let P be the predicate which is true on t if there are termst1, t2 such that f(g(t1), t2) is a subterm of t. Then the solutions of P (x)∧P (y)define a relation in Rec×, using twice the following automaton :

Q = qf , qg, q>Qf = qfT = a → q> f(q>, q>) → q>

g(q>) → q> f(qf , q>) → qf

g(qf ) → qf f(qg, q>) → qf

g(q>) → qg f(q>, qf ) → qf

For instance the pair (g(f(g(a), g(a))), f(g(g(a)), a)) is accepted by the pairof automata.

The second example illustrates Rec. Again, it is a first account of the devel-opments of Section 3.4.4

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 76: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

76 Logic, Automata and Relations

Example 30. Let F = f, g, a,Ω where f is binary, g is unary, a and Ω areconstants. Let R be the set of terms (t, u) such that u can be obtained from tby replacing each occurrence of Ω by some term in T (F) (each occurrence of Ωneeds not to be replaced with the same term). Using the notations of Chapter2

R(t, u) ⇐⇒ u ∈ t.ΩT (F)

R is recognized by the following automaton (on codings of pairs):

Q = q, q′Qf = q′T = ⊥ a → q ⊥ f(q, q) → q

⊥ g(q) → q Ωf(q, q) → q′

⊥ Ω → q ff(q′, q′) → q′

aa → q′ gg(q′) → q′

ΩΩ → q′ Ωg(q) → q′

Ωa → q′

For instance, the pair (f(g(Ω), g(Ω)), f(g(g(a)), g(Ω))) is accepted by theautomaton: the overlap of the two terms yields

[tu] = ff(gg(Ωg(⊥ a)), gg(ΩΩ))

And the reduction:

[tu]∗−→ ff(gg(Ωg(q)), gg(q′))∗−→ ff(gg(q′), q′)

→ ff(q′, q′)→ q′

The last example illustrates the recognition by a GTT. It comes from thetheory of rewriting; further developments and explanations on this theory aregiven in Section 3.4.3.

Example 31. Let F = ×,+, 0, 1. Let R be the rewrite system 0 × x → 0.

The many-steps reduction relation defined by R:∗−→R

is recognized by the

GTT(A1,A2) defined as follows (+ and × are used in infix notation to meettheir usual reading):

T1 = 0 → q> q> + q> → q>1 → q> q> × q> → q>0 → q0 q0 × q> → q0

T2 = 0 → q0

Then, for instance, the pair (1 + ((0 × 1) × 1), 1 + 0) is accepted by the GTTsince

1 + ((0 × 1) × 1)∗

−−→A1

1 + (q0 × q>) × q> −−→A1

1 + (q0 × q>) −−→A1

1 + q0

one hand and 1 + 0 −−→A2

1 + q0 on the other hand.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 77: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.2 Automata on Tuples of Finite Trees 77

Rec

GTTRec×

••

Rc

∆T (F)2a, f(a)2

Figure 3.4: The relations between the three classes

3.2.3 Comparisons Between the Three Classes

We study here the inclusion relations between the three classes: Rec×,Rec, GTT .

Proposition 8. Rec× ⊂ Rec and the inclusion is strict.

Proof. To show that any relation in Rec× is also in Rec, we have to constructfrom two automata A1 = (Q1,F , Qf

1 , R1),A2 = (F , Q2, Qf2 , R2) an automaton

which recognizes the overlaps of the terms in the languages. We define such anautomaton A = (Q, (F ∪ ⊥)2, Qf , R) by: Q = (Q1 ∪ q⊥) × (Q2 ∪ q⊥),

Qf = Qf1 × Qf

2 and R is the set of rules:

• f ⊥ ((q1, q⊥), . . . , (qn, q⊥)) −→ (q, q⊥) if f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ R1

• ⊥ f((q⊥, q1), . . . , (q⊥, qn)) −→ (q⊥, q) if f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ R2

• fg((q1, q′1), . . . , (qm, q′m), (qm+1, q⊥), . . . , (qn, q⊥)) → (q, q′) if f(q1, . . . , qn) →

q ∈ R1 and g(q′1, . . . , q′m) → q′ ∈ R2 and n ≥ m

• fg((q1, q′1), . . . , (qn, q′n), (q⊥, qn+1), . . . , (q⊥, qm)) → (q, q′) if f(q1, . . . , qn) →

q ∈ R1 and g(q′1, . . . , q′m) → q′ ∈ R2 and m ≥ n

The proof that A indeed accepts L(A1) × L(A2) is left to the reader.Now, the inclusion is strict since e.g. ∆ ∈ Rec \ Rec×.

Proposition 9. GTT ⊂ Rec and the inclusion is strict.

Proof. Let (A1,A2) be a GTT accepting R. We have to construct an automatonA which accepts the codings of pairs in R.

Let A0 = (Q0,F , Qf0 , T0) be the automaton constructed in the proof of

Proposition 8. [t, u]∗

−−→A0

(q1, q2) if and only if t∗

−−→A1

q1 and u∗

−−→A2

q2. Now we

let A = (Q0 ∪ qf,F , Qf = qf, T ). T consists of T0 plus the following rules:

(q, q) → qf ff(qf , . . . , qf ) → qf

For every symbol f ∈ F and every state q ∈ Q0.If (t, u) is accepted by the GTT, then

t∗

−−→A1

C[q1, . . . , qn]p1,...,pn

∗←−−A2

u.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 78: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

78 Logic, Automata and Relations

Then

[t, u]∗

−−→A0

[C,C][(q1, q1), . . . , (qn, qn)]p1,...,pn

∗−→A

[C,C][qf , . . . , qf ]p1,...,pn

∗−→A

qf

Conversely, if [t, u] is accepted by A then [t, u]∗−→A

qf . By definition of A, there

should be a sequence:

[t, u]∗−→A

C[(q1, q1), . . . , (qn, qn)]p1,...,pn

∗−→A

C[qf , . . . , qf ]p1,...,pn

∗−→A

qf

Indeed, we let pi be the positions at which one of the ε-transitions steps (q, q) →qf is applied. (n ≥ 0). Now, C[qf , . . . , qf ]p1,...,pm

qf if and only if C can bewritten [C1, C1] (the proof is left to the reader).

Concerning the strictness of the inclusion, it will be a consequence of Propo-sitions 8 and 10.

Proposition 10. GTT 6⊆ Rec× and Rec× 6⊆ GTT.

Proof. ∆ is accepted by a GTT (with no state and no transition) but it doesnot belong to Rec×. On the other hand, if F = f, a, then a, f(a)2 is inRec× (it is the product of two finite languages) but it is not accepted by anyGTT since any GTT accepts at least ∆.

Finally, there is an example of a relation Rc which is in Rec and not in theunion Rec× ∪GTT; consider for instance the alphabet a(), b(), 0 and the onestep reduction relation associated with the rewrite system a(x) → x. In otherwords,

(u, v) ∈ Rc ⇐⇒ ∃C ∈ C(F),∃t ∈ T (F), u = C[a(t)] ∧ v = C[t]

It is left as an exercise to prove that Rc ∈ Rec \ (Rec× ∪ GTT).

3.2.4 Closure Properties for Rec× and Rec; Cylindrificationand Projection

Let us start with the classical closure properties.

Proposition 11. Rec× and Rec are closed under Boolean operations.

The proof of this proposition is straightforward and left as an exercise.These relations are also closed under cylindrification and projection. Let us

first define these operations which are specific to automata on tuples:

Definition 6. If R ⊆ T (F)n (n ≥ 1) and 1 ≤ i ≤ n then the ith projection ofR is the relation Ri ⊆ T (F)n−1 defined by

Ri(t1, . . . , tn−1) ⇔ ∃t ∈ T (F) R(t1, . . . , ti−1, t, ti, . . . , tn−1)

When n = 1, T (F)n−1 is by convention a singleton set > (so as to keepthe property that T (F)n+1 = T (F) × T (F)n). > is assumed to be a neutralelement w.r.t. Cartesian product. In such a situation, a relation R ⊆ T (F)0 iseither ∅ or > (it is a propositional variable).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 79: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.2 Automata on Tuples of Finite Trees 79

Definition 7. If R ⊆ T (F)n (n ≥ 0) and 1 ≤ i ≤ n + 1, then the ith cylindri-fication of R is the relation Ri ⊆ T (F)n+1 defined by

Ri(t1, . . . , ti−1, t, ti, . . . , tn) ⇔ R(t1, . . . , ti−1, ti, . . . , tn)

Proposition 12. Rec× and Rec are effectively closed under projection andcylindrification. Actually, ith projection can be computed in linear time and theith cylindrification of A can be computed in linear time (assuming that the sizeof the alphabet is constant).

Proof. For Rec×, this property is easy: projection on the ith component simplyamounts to remove the ith automaton. Cylindrification on the ith componentsimply amounts to insert as a ith automaton, an automaton accepting all terms.

Assume that R ∈ Rec. The ith projection of R is simply its image by thefollowing linear tree homomorphism:

hi([f1, . . . , fn](t1, . . . , tk))def= [f1 . . . fi−1fi+1 . . . fn](hi(t1), . . . , hi(tm))

in which m is the arity of [f1 . . . fi−1fi+1 . . . fn] (which is smaller or equal tok). Hence, by Theorem 6, the ith projection of R is recognizable (and we canextract from the proof a linear construction of the automaton).

Similarly, the ith cylindrification is obtained as an inverse homomorphicimage, hence is recognizable thanks to Theorem 7.

Note that using the above construction, the projection of a deterministicautomaton may be non-deterministic (see exercises)

Example 32. Let F = f, g, a where f is binary, g is unary and a is aconstant. Consider the following automaton A on F ′ = (F ∪ ⊥)2: The set ofstates is q1, q2, q3, q4, q5 and the set of final states is q3

1

a ⊥ → q1 f ⊥ (q1, q1) → q1

g ⊥ (q1) → q1 fg(q2, q1) → q3

ga(q1) → q2 f ⊥ (q4, q1) → q4

g ⊥ (q1) → q4 fa(q4, q1) → q2

gg(q3) → q3 ff(q3, q3) → q3

aa → q5 ff(q3, q5) → q3

gg(q5) → q5 ff(q5, q3) → q3

ff(q5, q5) → q5

The first projection of this automaton gives:

a → q2 g(q3) → q3

a → q5 g(q5) → q5

g(q2) → q3 f(q3, q3) → q3

f(q3, q5) → q3 f(q5, q5) → q5

f(q5, q3) → q3

1This automaton accepts the set of pairs of terms (u, v) such that u can be rewritten inone or more steps to v by the rewrite system f(g(x), y) → g(a).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 80: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

80 Logic, Automata and Relations

Which accepts the terms containing g(a) as a subterm2.

3.2.5 Closure of GTT by Composition and Iteration

Theorem 23. If R ⊆ T (F)2 is recognized by a GTT, then its transitive closureR∗ is also recognized by a GTT.

The detailed proof is technical, so let us show it on a picture and explain itinformally.

We consider two terms (t, v) and (v, u) which are both accepted by the GTTand we wish that (t, u) is also accepted. For simplicity, consider only one state q

such that t∗

−−→A1

C[q]∗

←−−A2

v and v∗

−−→A1

C ′[q1, . . . , qn]∗

←−−A2

u. There are actually

two cases: C can be “bigger” than C ′ or “smaller”. Assume it is smaller. Thenq is reached at a position inside C ′: C ′ = C[C ′′]p. The situation is depictedon Figure 3.5. Along the reduction of v to q by A2, we enter a configurationC ′′[q′1, . . . , q

′n]. The idea now is to add to A2 ε-transitions from qi to q′i. In this

way, as can easily be seen on Figure 3.5, we get a reduction from u to C[q],hence the pair (t, u) is accepted.

Proof. Let A1 and A2 be the pair of automata defining the GTT which acceptsR. We compute by induction the automata An

1 ,An2 . A0

i = Ai and An+1i is

obtained by adding new transitions to Ani : Let Qi be the set of states of Ai

(and also the set of states of Ani ).

• If LAn2(q)∩LAn

1(q′) 6= ∅, q ∈ Q1 ∩Q2 and q 6

∗−−→An

1

q′, then An+11 is obtained

from An1 by adding the ε-transition q → q′ and An+1

2 = An2 .

• If LAn1(q)∩LAn

2(q′) 6= ∅, q ∈ Q1 ∩Q2 and q 6

∗−−→An

2

q′, then An+12 is obtained

from An2 by adding the ε-transition q → q′ and An+1

1 = An1 .

If there are several ways of obtaining An+1i from An

i using these rules, we don’tcare which of these ways is used.

First, these completion rules are decidable by the decision properties ofchapter 1. Their application also terminates as at each application strictlydecreases k1(n) + k2(n) where ki(n) is the number of pairs of states (q, q′) ∈(Q1 ∪Q2)× (Q1 ∪Q2) such that there is no ε-transition in An

i from q to q′. Welet A∗

i be a fixed point of this computation. We show that (A∗1,A

∗2) defines a

GTT accepting R∗.

• Each pair of terms accepted by the GTT (A∗1,A

∗2) is in R∗: we show by

induction on n that each pair of terms accepted by the GTT (An1 ,An

2 )is in R∗. For n = 0, this follows from the hypothesis. Let us nowassume that An+1

1 is obtained by adding q → q′ to the transitions ofAn

1 (The other case is symmetric). Let (t, u) be accepted by the GTT(An+1

1 ,An+12 ). By definition, there is a context C and positions p1, . . . , pk

2i.e. the terms that are obtained by applying at least one rewriting step using f(g(x), y) →g(a)

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 81: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.2 Automata on Tuples of Finite Trees 81

q’nq’1

q1 qnA1A2

A2

A1

A2

q

C =

t =

C’ =

v =

u =

Figure 3.5: The proof of Theorem 23

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 82: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

82 Logic, Automata and Relations

such that t = C[t1, . . . , tk]p1,...,pk, u = C[u1, . . . , uk]p1,...,pk

and there are

states q1, . . . , qk ∈ Q1∩Q2 such that, for all i, ti∗

−−−→An+1

1

qi and ui∗

−−→An

2

qi.

We prove the result by induction on the number m of times q → q′ isapplied in the reductions ti

∗−−−→An+1

1

qi. If m = 0. Then this is the first

induction hypothesis: (t, u) is accepted by (An1 ,An

2 ), hence (t, u) ∈ R∗.Now, assume that, for some i,

ti∗

−−−→An+1

1

t′i[q]p∗

−−−→q→q′

t′i[q′]p

∗−−→An

1

qi

By definition, there is a term v such that v∗

−−→An

2

q and v∗

−−→An

1

q′. Hence

ti[v]p∗

−−−→An+1

1

qi

And the number of reduction steps using q → q′ is strictly smaller herethan in the reduction from ti to qi. Hence, by induction hypothesis,(t[v]pip, u) ∈ R∗. On the other hand, (t, t[v]pip) is accepted by the GTT

(An+11 ,An

2 ) since t|pip∗

−−−→An+1

1

q and v∗

−−→An

2

q. Moreover, by construction,

the first sequence of reductions uses strictly less than m times the transi-tion q → q′. Then, by induction hypothesis, (t, t[v]pip) ∈ R∗. Now from(t, t[v]pip) ∈ R∗ and (t[v]pip, u) ∈ R∗, we conclude (t, u) ∈ R∗.

• If (t, u) ∈ R∗, then (t, u) is accepted by the GTT (A∗1,A

∗2). Let us prove

the following intermediate result:

Lemma 1.

If

t∗

−−→A∗

1

q

v∗

−−→A∗

2

q

v∗

−−→A∗

1

C[q1, . . . , qk]p1,...,pk

u∗

−−→A∗

2

C[q1, . . . , qk]p1,...,pk

then u∗

−−→A∗

2

q

and hence (t, u) is accepted by the GTT.

Let v∗

−−→A∗

2

C[q′1, . . . , q′k]p1,...,pk

∗−−→A∗

2

q. For each i, v|pi∈ LA∗

2(q′i)∩LA∗

1(qi)

and qi ∈ Q1 ∩ Q2. Hence, by construction, qi −−→A∗

2

q′i. It follows that

u∗

−−→A∗

2

C[q1, . . . qk]p1,...,pk

∗−−→A∗

2

C[q′1, . . . , q′k]p1,...,pk

∗−−→A∗

2

q

Which proves our lemma.

Symmetrically, if t∗

−−→A∗

1

C[q1, . . . , qk]p1,...,pk, v

∗−−→A∗

2

C[q1, . . . , qk]p1,...,pk,

v∗

−−→A∗

1

q and u∗

−−→A∗

2

q, then t∗

−−→A∗

1

q

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 83: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.2 Automata on Tuples of Finite Trees 83

Now, let (t, u) ∈ Rn: we prove that (t, u) is accepted by the GTT (A∗1,A

∗2)

by induction on n. If n = 1, then the result follows from the inclu-sion of L(A1,A2) in L(A∗

1,A∗2). Now, let v be such that (t, v) ∈ R and

(v, u) ∈ Rn−1. By induction hypothesis, both (t, v) and (v, u) are ac-cepted by the GTT (A∗

1,A∗2): there are context C and C ′ and positions

p1, . . . , pk, p′1, . . . , p′m such that

t = C[t1, . . . , tk]p1,...,pk, v = C[v1, . . . , vk]p1,...,pk

v = C ′[v′1, . . . , v

′m]p′

1,...,p′m

, u = C ′[u1, . . . , um]

and states q1, . . . , qk, q′1, . . . , q′m ∈ Q1 ∩Q2 such that for all i, j, ti

∗−−→A∗

1

qi,

vi∗

−−→A∗

2

qi, v′j

∗−−→A∗

1

q′j , uj∗

−−→A∗

2

q′j . Let C ′′ be the largest context more

general than C and C ′; the positions of C ′′ are the positions of bothC[q1, . . . , qn]p1,...,pn

and C ′[q′1, . . . , q′m]p′

1,...,p′m

. C ′′, p′′1 , . . . , p′′l are suchthat:

– For each 1 ≤ i ≤ l, there is a j such that either pj = p′′i or p′j = p′′i

– For all 1 ≤ i ≤ n there is a j such that pi ≥ p′′j

– For all 1 ≤ i ≤ m there is a j such that p′i ≥ p′′j

– the positions p′′j are pairwise incomparable w.r.t. the prefix ordering.

Let us fix a j ∈ [1..l]. Assume that p′′j = pi (the other case is symmetric).We can apply our lemma to tj = t|p′′

j(in place of t), vj = v|p′′

j(in place

of v) and u|p′′j

(in place of u), showing that u|p′′j

∗−−→A∗

2

qi. If we let now

q′′j = qi when p′′j = pi and q′′j = q′i when p′′j = p′i, we get

t∗

−−→A∗

1

C ′′[q′′1 , . . . , q′′l ]p′′1 ,...,p′′

l

∗←−−A∗

2

u

which completes the proof.

Proposition 13. If R and R′ are in GTT then their composition R R′ is alsoin GTT.

Proof. Let (A1,A2) and (A′1,A

′2) be the two pairs of automata which recognize

R and R′ respectively. We assume without loss of generality that the set ofstates are disjoint:

(Q1 ∪ Q2) ∩ (Q′1 ∪ Q′

2) = ∅

We define the automaton A∗1 as follows: the set of states is Q1 ∪Q′

1 and thetransitions are the union of:

• the transitions of A1

• the transitions of A′1

• the ε-transitions q −→ q′ if q ∈ Q1 ∩Q2, q′ ∈ Q′1 and LA2

(q)∩LA′1(q′) 6= ∅

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 84: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

84 Logic, Automata and Relations

CC’’ C’

q1qk

qn q’1

q’lq’m

u w v

Figure 3.6: The proof of Proposition 13

Symmetrically, the automaton A∗2 is defined by: its states are Q2 ∪ Q′

2 and thetransitions are:

• the transitions of A2

• the transitions of A′2

• the ε-transitions q′ −→ q if q′ ∈ Q′1 ∩Q′

2, q ∈ Q2 and LA′1(q′)∩LA2

(q) 6= ∅

We prove below that (A∗1,A

∗2) is a GTT recognizing R R′. See also the figure

3.6.

• Assume first that (u, v) ∈ R R′. Then there is a term w such that(u,w) ∈ R and (w, v) ∈ R′:

u = C[u1, . . . , uk]p1,...,pk, w = C[w1, . . . , wk]p1,...,pk

w = C ′[w′1, . . . , w

′m]p′

1,...,p′m

, v = C ′[v1, . . . , vm]p′1,...,p′

m

and, for every i ∈ 1, . . . , k, ui∗

−−→A1

qi, wi∗

−−→A2

qi, for every i ∈ 1, ...,m,

w′i

∗−−→A′

1

q′i, vi∗

−−→A′

2

q′i. Let p′′1 , . . . , p′′l be the minimal elements (w.r.t. the

prefix ordering) of the set p1, . . . , pk ∪ p′1, . . . , p′m. Each p′′i is either

some pj or some p′j . Assume first p′′i = pj . Then pj is a position in C ′ and

C ′[q′1, . . . , q′m]p′

1,...,p′m|pj

= Cj [q′mj

, . . . , q′mj+kj]p′

mj,...,p′

mj+kj

Now, wj∗

−−→A2

qj and

wj = Cj [w′mj

, . . . , w′mj+kj

]p′mj

,...,p′mj+kj

with w′mj+i

∗−−→A′

1

q′mj+i for every i ∈ 1, . . . , kj. For i ∈ 1, . . . , kj, let

qj,i be such that:

w′mj+i = wj |p′

mj+i

∗−−→A2

qj,i

Cj [qj,1, . . . , qj,kj]p′

mj,...,p′

mj+kj

∗−−→A2

qj

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 85: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.2 Automata on Tuples of Finite Trees 85

For every i, w′mj+i ∈ LA2

(qj,i) ∩ LA′1(q′mj+i) and q′mj+i ∈ Q′

1 ∩ Q′2.

Then, by definition, there is a transition q′mj+i −−→A∗

2

qj,i. Therefore,

Cj [q′mj

, . . . , q′mj+kj]

∗−−→A∗

2

qj and then v|pj

∗−−→A∗

2

qj .

Now, if p′′i = p′j , we get, in a similar way, u|p′j

∗−−→A∗

1

q′j . Altogether:

u∗

−−→A∗

1

C ′′[q′′1 , . . . , q′′l ]p′′1 ,...,p′′

l

∗←−−A∗

2

v

where q′′i = qj if p′′i = pj and q′′j = q′j if p′′i = p′j .

• Conversely, assume that (u, v) is accepted by (A∗1,A

∗2). Then

u∗

−−→A∗

1

C[q′′1 , . . . , q′′l ]p′′1 ,...,p′′

l

∗←−−A∗

2

v

and, for every i, either q′′i ∈ Q1 ∩Q2 or q′′i ∈ Q′1 ∩Q′

2 (by the disjointnesshypothesis). Assume for instance that q′′i ∈ Q′

1 ∩ Q′2 and consider the

computation of A∗1: u|p′′

i

∗−−→A∗

1

q′′i . By definition, u|p′′i

= Ci[u1, . . . , uki]

withuj

∗−−→A1

qj −−→A∗

1

q′j

for every j = 1, . . . , ki and Ci[q′1, . . . , q

′ki

]∗

−−→A′

1

q′′i . By construction, qj ∈

Q1∩Q2 and LA2(qj)∩LA′

1(q′j) 6= ∅. Let wi,j be a term in this intersection

and wi = Ci[wi,1, . . . , wi,ki]. Then

wi∗

−−→A2

Ci[q1, . . . , qki]

u|p′′i

∗−−→A1

Ci[q1, . . . , qki]

wi∗

−−→A′

1

q′′i

v|p′′i

∗−−→A′

2

q′′i

The last property comes from the fact that v|p′′i

∗−−→A∗

2

q′′i and, since q′′i ∈

Q′2, there can be only transition steps from A′

2 in this reduction.

Symmetrically, if q′′i ∈ Q1 ∩ Q2, then we define wi and the contexts Ci

such that

wi∗

−−→A2

q′′i

u|p′′i

∗−−→A1

q′′i

wi∗

−−→A′

1

Ci[q′1, . . . , q

′ki

]

v|p′′i

∗−−→A′

2

Ci[q′1, . . . , q

′ki

]

Finally, letting w = C[w1, . . . , wl], we have (u,w) ∈ R and (w, v) ∈ R′.

GTTs do not have many other good closure properties (see the exercises).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 86: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

86 Logic, Automata and Relations

3.3 The Logic WSkS

3.3.1 Syntax

Terms of WSkS are formed out of the constant ε, first-order variable symbols(typically written with lower-case letters x, y, z, x′, x1, ...) and unary symbols1, . . . , n written in postfix notation. For instance x1123, ε2111 are terms. Thelatter will be often written omitting ε (e.g. 2111 instead of ε2111).

Atomic formulas are either equalities s = t between terms, inequalities s ≤ tor s ≥ t between terms, or membership constraints t ∈ X where t is a term andX is a second-order variable symbol. Second-order variables will be typicallydenoted using upper-case letters.

Formulas are built from the atomic formulas using the logical connectives∧,∨,¬,⇒,⇐,⇔ and the quantifiers ∃x,∀x(quantification on individuals)∃X,∀X(quantification on sets); we may quantify both first-order and second-order vari-ables.

As usual, we do not need all this artillery: we may stick to a subset of logicalconnectives (and even a subset of atomic formulas as will be discussed in Section3.3.4). For instance φ ⇔ ψ is an abbreviation for (φ ⇒ ψ) ∧ (ψ ⇒ φ), φ ⇒ ψis another way of writing ψ ⇐ φ, φ ⇒ ψ is an abbreviation for (¬φ) ∨ ψ, ∀x.φstands for ¬∃x.¬φ etc ... We will use the extended syntax for convenience, butwe will restrict ourselves to the atomic formulas s = t, s ≤ t, t ∈ X and thelogical connectives ∨,¬,∃x,∃X in the proofs.

The set of free variables of a formula φ is defined as usual.

3.3.2 Semantics

We consider the particular interpretation where terms are strings belongingto 1, . . . , k∗, = is the equality of strings, and ≤ is interpreted as the prefixordering. Second order variables are interpreted as finite subsets of 1, . . . , k∗,so ∈ is then the membership predicate.

Let t1, . . . , tn ∈ 1, . . . , k∗ and S1, . . . , Sn be finite subsets of 1, . . . , k∗.Given a formula

φ(x1, . . . , xn,X1, . . . ,Xm)

with free variables x1, . . . , xn,X1, . . . ,Xm, the assignment x1 7→ t1, . . . xn 7→tn,X1 7→ S1, . . . Xm 7→ Sm satisfies φ, which is written σ |= φ (or alsot1, . . . , tn, S1, . . . , Sm |= φ) if replacing the variables with their correspondingvalue, the formula holds in the above model.

Remark: the logic SkS is defined as above, except that set variables may beinterpreted as infinite sets.

3.3.3 Examples

We list below a number of formulas defining predicates on sets and singletons.After these examples, we may use the below-defined abbreviations as if therewere primitives of the logic.

X is a subset of Y :

X ⊆ Ydef= ∀x.(x ∈ X ⇒ x ∈ Y )

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 87: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.3 The Logic WSkS 87

Finite union:

X =

n⋃

i=1

Xidef=

n∧

i=1

Xi ⊆ X ∧ ∀x.(x ∈ X ⇒n∨

i=1

x ∈ Xi)

Intersection:X ∩ Y = Z

def= ∀x.x ∈ Z ⇔ (x ∈ X ∧ x ∈ Y )

Partition:

Partition(X,X1, . . . ,Xn)def= X =

n⋃

i=1

Xi ∧n−1∧

i=1

n∧

j=i+1

Xi ∩ Xj = ∅

X is closed under prefix:

PrefixClosed(X)def= ∀z.∀y.(z ∈ X ∧ y ≤ z) ⇒ y ∈ X

Set equality:

Y = Xdef= Y ⊆ X ∧ X ⊆ Y

Emptiness:

X = ∅def= ∀Y.(Y ⊆ X ⇒ Y = X)

X is a Singleton:

Sing(X)def= X 6= ∅ ∧ ∀Y (Y ⊆ X ⇒ (Y = X ∨ Y = ∅)

The prefix ordering:

x ≤ ydef= ∀X.(y ∈ X ∧ (∀z.(

k∨

i=1

zi ∈ X) ⇒ z ∈ X)) ⇒ x ∈ X

“every set containing y and closed by predecessor contains x”

This shows that ≤ can be removed from the syntax of WSkS formulaswithout decreasing the expressive power of the logic.

Coding of trees: assume that k is the maximal arity of a function symbolin F . If t ∈ T (F) C(t) is the tuples of sets (S, Sf1

, . . . , Sfn) if F =

f1, . . . , fn, S =⋃n

i=1 Sfiand Sfi

is the set of positions in t which arelabeled with fi.

For instance C(f(g(a), f(a, b))) is the tuple S = ε, 1, 11, 2, 21, 22, Sf =ε, 2, Sg = 1, Sa = 11, 21, Sb = 22.

(S, Sf1, . . . , Sfn

) is the coding of some t ∈ T (F) is defined by:

Term(X,X1, . . . ,Xn)def= X 6= ∅

∧ Partition(X,X1, . . . ,Xn) ∧PrefixClosed(X)

∧∧k

i=1

∧a(fj)=i (

∧il=1 ∀x.(x ∈ Xfj

⇒ xl ∈ X)

∧∧k

l=i+1 ∀y.(y ∈ Xfj⇒ yl /∈ X))

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 88: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

88 Logic, Automata and Relations

3.3.4 Restricting the Syntax

If we consider that a first-order variable is a singleton set, it is possible totransform any formula into an equivalent one which does not contain any first-order variable.

More precisely, we consider now that formulas are built upon the atomicformulas:

X ⊆ Y,Sing(X),X = Y i,X = ε

using the logical connectives and second-order quantification only. Let uscall this new syntax the restricted syntax.

These formulas are interpreted as expected. In particular Sing(X) holds truewhen X is a singleton set and X = Y i holds true when X and Y are singletonsets s and t respectively and s = ti. Let us write |=2 the satisfaction relationfor this new logic.

Proposition 14. There is a translation T from WSkS formulas to the restrictedsyntax such that

s1, . . . , sn, S1, . . . , Sm |= φ(x1, . . . , xn,X1, . . . ,Xm)

if and only if

s1, . . . , sn, S1, . . . , Sm |=2 T (φ)(Xx1, . . . ,Xxn

,X1, . . . ,Xm)

Conversely, there is a translation T ′ from the restricted syntax to WSkS suchthat

S1, . . . , Sm |= T ′(φ)(X1, . . . ,Xm)

if and only if

S1, . . . , Sm |=2 φ(X1, . . . ,Xm))

Proof. First, according to the previous section, we can restrict our attention toformulas built upon the only atomic formulas t ∈ X and s = t. Then, eachatomic formula is flattened according to the rules:

ti ∈ X → ∃y.y = ti ∧ y ∈ Xxi = yj → ∃z.z = xi ∧ z = yj

ti = s → ∃z.z = t ∧ zi = s

The last rule assumes that t is not a variableNext, we associate a second-order variable Xy to each first-order variable y

and transform the flat atomic formulas:

T (y ∈ X)def= Xy ⊆ X

T (y = xi)def= Xy = Xxi

T (x = ε)def= Xx = ε

T (x = y)def= Xx = Xy

The translation of other flat atomic formulas can be derived from these ones, inparticular when exchanging the arguments of =.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 89: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.3 The Logic WSkS 89

Now, T (φ ∨ ψ)def= T (φ) ∨ T (ψ), T (¬(φ))

def= ¬T (φ), T (∃X.φ)

def= ∃X.T (φ),

T (∃y.φ)def= ∃Xy.Sing(Xy)∧T (φ). Finally, we add Sing(Xx) for each free variable

x.For the converse, the translation T ′ has been given in the previous section,

except for the atomic formulas X = Y i (which becomes Sing(X) ∧ Sing(Y ) ∧∃x∃y.x ∈ X ∧ y ∈ Y ∧ x = yi) and X = ε (which becomes Sing(X) ∧ ∀x.x ∈X ⇒ x = ε).

3.3.5 Definable Sets are Recognizable Sets

Definition 8. A set L of tuples of finite sets of words is definable in WSkS ifthere is a formula φ of WSkS with free variables X1, . . . ,Xn such that

(S1, . . . , Sn) ∈ L if and only if S1, . . . , Sn |= φ.

Each tuple of finite sets of words S1, . . . , Sn ⊆ 1, . . . , k∗ is identified to afinite tree (S1, . . . , Sn)∼ over the alphabet 0, 1,⊥n where any string containinga 0 or a 1 is k-ary and ⊥n is a constant symbol, in the following way3:

Pos((S1, . . . , Sn)∼)def= ε ∪ pi | ∃p′ ∈

n⋃

i=1

Si, p ≤ p′, i ∈ 1, . . . , k

is the set of prefixes of words in some Si. The symbol at position p:

(S1, . . . , Sn)∼(p) = α1 . . . αn

is defined as follows:

• αi = 1 if and only if p ∈ Si

• αi = 0 if and only if p /∈ Si and ∃p′ ∈ Si and ∃p′′.p · p′′ = p′

• αi =⊥ otherwise.

Example 33. Consider for instance S1 = ε, 11, S2 = ∅, S3 = 11, 22 threesubsets of 1, 2∗. Then the coding (S1, S2, S3)

∼ is depicted on Figure 3.7.

Lemma 2. If a set L of tuples of finite subsets of 1, . . . , k∗ is definable in

WSkS, then Ldef= (S1, . . . , Sn)∼ | (S1, . . . , Sn) ∈ L is in Rec.

Proof. By Proposition 14, if L is definable in WSkS, it is also definable with therestricted syntax. We are going now to prove the lemma by induction on thestructure of the formula φ which defines L. We assume that all variables in φare bound at most once in the formula and we also assume a fixed total ordering≤ on the variables. If ψ is a subformula of φ with free variables Y1 < . . . < Yn,we construct an automaton Aψ working on the alphabet 0, 1,⊥n such that(S1, . . . , Sn) |=2 ψ if and only if (S1, . . . , Sn)∼ ∈ L(Aψ)

3This is very similar to the coding of Section 3.2.1

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 90: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

90 Logic, Automata and Relations

0 0

11 1

1 0

0

Figure 3.7: An example of a tree coding a triple of finite sets of strings

0

q’q

1

qq

q’

q q’

0

qq’

q’

Figure 3.8: The automaton for Sing(X)

The base case consists in constructing an automaton for each atomic formula.(We assume here that k = 2 for simplicity, but this works of course for arbitraryk).

The automaton ASing(X) is depicted on Figure 3.8. The only final state is

q′.

The automaton AX⊆Y (with X < Y ) is depicted on Figure 3.9. The onlystate (which is also final) is q.

The automaton AX=Y 1 is depicted on Figure 3.10. The only final state isq′′. An automaton for X = Y 2 is obtained in a similar way.

The automaton for X = ε is depicted on Figure 3.11 (the final state is q′).

Now, for the induction step, we have several cases to investigate:

• If φ is a disjunction φ1 ∨ φ2, where ~Xi are the set of free variables ofφi respectively. Then we first cylindrify the automata for φ1 and φ2

respectively in such a way that they recognize the solutions of φ1 andφ2, with free variables ~X1 ∪ ~X2. (See Proposition 12).More precisely, let~X1 ∪ ~X2 = Y1, . . . , Yn with Y1 < . . . < Yn. Then we successively applythe ith cylindrification to the automaton of φ1 (resp. φ2) for the variablesYi which are not free in φ1 (resp. φ2). Then the automaton Aφ is obtainedas the union of these automata. (Rec is closed under union by Proposition11).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 91: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.3 The Logic WSkS 91

q

1

q q

q

00

q q

q q

qq

11

0

q q

q

q q

q01

Figure 3.9: The automaton for X ⊆ Y

q

00

q’’

q’’1

q

q

01

q q

q’

q’

q’’

00 q’’

q q’’

Figure 3.10: The automaton for X = Y 1

q

q

1 q’

q

Figure 3.11: The automaton for X = ε

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 92: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

92 Logic, Automata and Relations

• If φ is a formula ¬φ1 then Aφ is the automaton accepting the complementof Aφ1

. (See Theorem 5)

• If φ is a formula ∃X.φ1. Assume that X correspond to the ith component.Then Aφ is the ith projection of Aφ1

(see Proposition 12).

Example 34. Consider the following formula, with free variables X,Y :

∀x, y.(x ∈ X ∧ y ∈ Y ) ⇒ ¬(x ≥ y)

We want to compute an automaton which accepts the assignments to X,Ysatisfying the formula. First, write the formula as

¬∃X1, Y1.X1 ⊆ X ∧ Y1 ⊆ Y ∧ G(X1, Y1)

where G(X1, Y1) expresses that X1 is a singleton x, Y1 is a singleton y andx ≥ y. We can use the definition of ≥ as a WS2S formula, or compute directlythe automaton, yielding

⊥⊥ → q 11(q, q) → q2

1 ⊥ (q, q) → q1 0 ⊥ (q, q1) → q1

0 ⊥ (q1, q) → q1 01(q1, q) → q2

01(q, q2) → q2 00(q2, q) → q2

00(q, q2) → q2

where q2 is the only final state. Now, using cylindrification, intersection, pro-jection and negation we get the following automaton (intermediate steps yieldlarge automata which would require a full page to be displayed):

⊥⊥ → q0 ⊥ 1(q0, q0) → q1 1 ⊥ (q0, q0) → q2

⊥ 0(q0, q1) → q1 ⊥ 0(q1, q0) → q1 ⊥ 0(q1, q1) → q1

0 ⊥ (q0, q2) → q2 0 ⊥ (q2, q0) → q2 0 ⊥ (q2, q2) → q2

⊥ 1(q0, q1) → q1 ⊥ 1(q1, q0) → q1 ⊥ 1(q1, q1) → q1

1 ⊥ (q0, q2) → q2 1 ⊥ (q2, q0) → q2 1 ⊥ (q2, q2) → q2

10(q1, q0) → q3 10(q0, q1) → q3 10(q1, q1) → q3

10(q1, q2) → q3 10(q2, q1) → q3 10(qi, q3) → q3

10(q3, qi) → q3 00(qi, q3) → q3 00(q3, qi) → q3

where i ranges over 0, 1, 2, 3 and q3 is the only final state.

3.3.6 Recognizable Sets are Definable

We have seen in section 3.3.3 how to represent a term using a tuple of setvariables. Now, we use this formula Term on the coding of tuples of terms; if(t1, . . . , tn) ∈ T (F)n, we write [t1, . . . , tn] the (|F| + 1)n + 1-tuple of finite setswhich represents it: one set for the positions of [t1, . . . , tn] and one set for eachelement of the alphabet (F ∪⊥)n . As it has been seen in section 3.3.3, thereis a WSkS formula Term([t1, . . . , tn]) which expresses the image of the coding.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 93: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.3 The Logic WSkS 93

Lemma 3. Every relation in Rec is definable. More precisely, if R ∈ Rec thereis a formula φ such that, for every terms t1, . . . , tn, if (S1, . . . , Sm) = [t1, . . . , tn],then

(S1, . . . , Sm) |=2 φ if and only if (t1, . . . , tn) ∈ R

Proof. Let A be the automaton which accepts the set of terms [t1, . . . , tn] for(t1, . . . , tn) ∈ R. The terminal alphabet of A is F ′ = (F∪⊥)n, the set of statesQ, the final states Qf and the set of transition rules T . Let F ′ = f1, . . . , fmand Q = q1, . . . , ql. The following formula φA (with m + 1 free variables)defines the set [t1, . . . , tn] | (t1, . . . , tn) ∈ R.

∃Yq1, . . . ,∃Yql

.Term(X,Xf1

, . . . ,Xfm)

∧ Partition(X,Yq1, . . . , Yql

)∧

∨q∈Qf

ε ∈ Yq

∧ ∀x.∧

f∈F ′

q∈Q

((x ∈ Xf ∧ x ∈ Yq) ⇒ (∨

f(q1,...,qs)→q∈T

s∧

i=1

xi ∈ Yqi))

This formula basically expresses that there is a successful run of the automatonon [t1, . . . , tn]: the variables Yqi

correspond to sets of positions which are labeledwith qi by the run. They should be a partition of the set of positions. The roothas to be labeled with a final state (the run is successful). Finally, the last lineexpresses local properties that have to be satisfied by the run: if the sons xi ofa position x are labeled with q1, ..., qn respectively and x is labeled with symbolf and state q, then there should be a transition f(q1, . . . , qn) → q in the set oftransitions.

We have to prove two inclusions. First assume that (S, S1, . . . , Sm) |=2

φ. Then (S, S1, . . . , Sm) |= Term(X,Xf1, . . . ,Xfm

), hence there is a term u ∈T (F)′ whose set of position is S and such that for all i, Si is the set of positionslabeled with fi. Now, there is a partition Eq1

, . . . , Eqlof S which satisfies

S, S1, . . . , Sm, Eq1, . . . , Eql

|=

∀x.∧

f∈F ′

q∈Q

((x ∈ Xf ∧ x ∈ Yq) ⇒ (∨

f(q1,...,qs)→q∈T

s∧

i=1

xi ∈ Yqi))

This implies that the labeling Eq1, . . . , Eql

is compatible with the transitionrules: it defines a run of the automaton. Finally, the condition that the root εbelongs to Eqf

for some final state qf implies that the run is successful, hencethat u is accepted by the automaton.

Conversely, if u is accepted by the automaton, then there is a successful runof A on u and we can label its positions with states in such a way that thislabeling is compatible with the transition rules in A.

Putting together Lemmas 2 and 3, we can state the following slogan (whichis not very precise; the precise statements are given by the lemmas):

Theorem 24. L is definable if and only if L is in Rec.

And, as a consequence:

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 94: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

94 Logic, Automata and Relations

Theorem 25 ([TW68]). WSkS is decidable.

Proof. Given a formula φ of WSkS, by Lemma 2, we can compute a finite treeautomaton which has the same solutions as φ. Now, assume that φ has no freevariable. Then the alphabet of the automaton is empty (or, more precisely, itcontains the only constant > according to what we explained in Section 3.2.4).Finally, the formula is valid iff the constant > is in the language, i.e. iff thereis a rule > −→ qf for some qf ∈ Qf .

3.3.7 Complexity Issues

We have seen in chapter 1 that, for finite tree automata, emptiness can be de-cided in linear time (and is PTIME-complete) and that inclusion is EXPTIME-complete. Considering WSkS formulas with a fixed number of quantifiers al-ternations N , the decision method sketched in the previous section will workin time which is a tower of exponentials, the height of the tower being O(N).This is so because each time we encounter a sequence ∀X,∃Y , the existentialquantification corresponds to a projection, which may yield a non-deterministicautomaton, even if the input automaton was deterministic. Then the eliminationof ∀X requires a determinization (because we have to compute a complementautomaton) which requires in general exponential time and exponential space.

Actually, it is not really possible to do much better since, even when k = 1,deciding a formula of WSkS requires non-elementary time, as shown in [SM73].

3.3.8 Extensions

There are several extensions of the logic, which we already mentioned: thoughquantification is restricted to finite sets, we may consider infinite sets as models(this is what is often called weak second-order monadic logic with k successorsand also written WSkS), or consider quantifications on arbitrary sets (this isthe full SkS).

These logics require more sophisticated automata which recognize sets ofinfinite terms. The proof of Theorem 25 carries over these extensions, with theprovision that the devices enjoy the required closure and decidability properties.But this becomes much more intricate in the case of infinite terms. Indeed, forinfinite terms, it is not possible to design bottom-up tree automata. We have touse a top-down device. But then, as mentioned in chapter 1, we cannot expectto reduce the non-determinism. Now, the closure by complement becomes prob-lematic because the usual way of computing the complement uses reduction ofnon-determinism as a first step.

It is out of the scope of this book to define and study automata on infiniteobjects (see [Tho90] instead). Let us simply mention that the closure under com-plement for Rabin automata which work on infinite trees (this result is knownas Rabin’s Theorem) is one of the most difficult results in the field

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 95: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.4 Examples of Applications 95

3.4 Examples of Applications

3.4.1 Terms and Sorts

The most basic example is what is known in the algebraic specification commu-nity as order-sorted signatures . These signatures are exactly what we calledbottom-up tree automata. There are only differences in the syntax. For in-stance, the following signature:

SORTS:Nat, int

SUBSORTS : Nat ≤ int

FUNCTION DECLARATIONS:0 : → Nat

+ : Nat × Nat → Nat

s : Nat → Nat

p : Nat → int

+ : int × int → int

abs : int → Nat

fact : Nat → Nat

. . .

is an automaton whose states are Nat, int with an ε-transition from Nat to int

and each function declaration corresponds to a transition of the automaton. Forexample +(Nat,Nat) → Nat. The set of well-formed terms (as in the algebraicspecification terminology) is the set of terms recognized by the automaton inany state.

More general typing systems also correspond to more general automata (aswill be seen e.g. in the next chapter).

This correspondence is not surprising; types and sorts are introduced in orderto prevent run-time errors by some “abstract interpretation” of the inputs. Treeautomata and tree grammars also provide such a symbolic evaluation mecha-nism. For other applications of tree automata in this direction, see e.g. chapter5.

From what we have seen in this chapter, we can go beyond simply recogniz-ing the set of well-formed terms. Consider the following sort constraints (thealphabet F of function symbols is given):

The set of sort expressions SE is the least set such that

• SE contains a finite set of sort symbols S, including the two particularsymbols >S and ⊥S .

• If s1, s2 ∈ SE , then s1 ∨ s2, s1 ∧ s2, ¬s1 are in SE

• If s1, . . . , sn are in SE and f is a function symbol of arity n, then f(s1, . . . , sn) ∈SE .

The atomic formulas are expressions t ∈ s where t ∈ T (F ,X ) and s ∈ SE .The formulas are arbitrary first-order formulas built on these atomic formulas.

These formulas are interpreted as follows: we are giving an order-sorted sig-nature (or a tree automaton) whose set of sorts is S. We define the interpretation[[·]]Sof sort expressions as follows:

• if s ∈ S, [[s]]S is the set of terms in T (F) that are accepted in state s.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 96: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

96 Logic, Automata and Relations

t

u

Figure 3.12: u encompasses t

• [[>S ]]S = T (F) and [[⊥S ]]S = ∅

• [[s1 ∨ s2]]S = [[s1]]S ∪ [[s2]]S , [[s1 ∧ s2]]S = [[s1]]S ∩ [[s2]]S , [[¬s]]S = T (F) \ [[s]]S

• [[f(s1, . . . , sn)]]S = f(t1, . . . , tn) | t1 ∈ [[s1]]S , . . . tn ∈ [[sn]]S

An assignment σ, mapping variables to terms in T (F), satisfies t ∈ s (wealso say that σ is a solution of t ∈ s) if tσ ∈ [[s]]S . Solutions of arbitrary formulasare defined as expected. Then

Theorem 26. Sort constraints are decidable.

The decision technique is based on automata computations, following theclosure properties of Rec× and a decomposition lemma for constraints of theform f(t1, . . . , tn) ∈ s.

More results and applications of sort constraints are discussed in the biblio-graphic notes.

3.4.2 The Encompassment Theory for Linear Terms

Definition 9. If t ∈ T (F ,X ) and u ∈ T (F), u encompasses t if there is a substi-tution σ such that tσ is a subterm of u. (See Figure 3.12.) This binary relationis denoted t ·£u or, seen as a unary relation on ground terms parametrized byt: ·£t(u).

Encompassment plays an important role in rewriting: a term t is reducibleby a term rewriting system R if and only if t encompasses at least one left handside of a rule.

The relationship with tree automata is given by the proposition:

Proposition 15. If t is linear, then the set of terms that encompass t is recog-nized by an NFTA of size O(|t|).

Proof. To each non-variable subterm v of t we associate a state qv. In additionwe have a state q>. The only final state is qt. The transition rules are:

• f(q>, . . . , q>) → q> for all function symbols.

• f(qt1 , . . . , qtn) → qf(t1,...,tn) if f(t1, . . . , tn) is a subterm of t and qti

isactually q> is ti is a variable.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 97: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.4 Examples of Applications 97

• f(q> . . . , q>, qt, q>, . . . , q>) → qt for all function symbols f whose arity isat least 1.

The proof that this automaton indeed recognizes the set of terms that encompasst is left to the reader.

Note that the automaton may be non deterministic. With a slight modifica-tion, if u is a linear term, we can construct in linear time an automaton whichaccepts the set of instances of u (this is also left as an exercise in chapter 1,exercise 8).

Corollary 4. If R is a term rewriting system whose all left members are linear,then the set of reducible terms in T (F), as well as the set NF of irreducibleterms in T (F) are recognized by a finite tree automaton.

Proof. This is a consequence of Theorem 5.

The theory of reducibility associated with a set of term S ⊆ T (F ,X ) is theset of first-order formulas built on the unary predicate symbols Et, t ∈ S andinterpreted as the set of terms encompassing t.

Theorem 27. The reducibility theory associated with a set of linear terms isdecidable.

Proof. By proposition 15, the set of solutions of an atomic formula is recog-nizable, hence definable in WSkS by Lemma 3. Hence, any first-order formulabuilt on these atomic predicate symbols can be translated into a (second-order)formula of WSkS which has the same models (up to the coding of terms intotuples of sets). Then, by Theorem 25, the reducibility theory associated with aset of linear terms is decidable.

Note however that we do not use here the full power of WSkS. Actually,the solutions of a Boolean combination of atomic formulas are in Rec×. So, wecannot apply the complexity results for WSkS here. (In fact, the complexity ofthe reducibility theory is unknown so far).

Let us simply show an example of an interesting property of rewrite systemswhich can be expressed in this theory.

Definition 10. Given a term rewriting system R, a term t is ground reducibleif, for every ground substitution σ, tσ is reducible by R.

Note that a term might be irreducible and still ground reducible. For in-stance consider the alphabet F = 0, s and the rewrite system R = s(s(0)) →0. Then the term s(s(x)) is irreducible by R, but all its ground instances arereducible.

It turns out that ground reducibility of t is expressible in the encompassmenttheory by the formula:

∀x.( ·£t(x) ⇒n∨

i=1

·£li(x))

Where l1, . . . , ln are the left hand sides of the rewrite system. By Theorem27, if t, l1, . . . , ln are linear, then ground reducibility is decidable. Actually, ithas been shown that this problem is EXPTIME-complete, but is beyond thescope of this book to give the proof.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 98: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

98 Logic, Automata and Relations

3.4.3 The First-order Theory of a Reduction Relation: theCase Where no Variables are Shared

We consider again an application of tree automata to decision problem in logicand term rewriting.

Consider the following logical theory. Let L be the set of all first-orderformulas using no function symbols and a single binary predicate symbol →.

Given a rewrite system R, interpreting → as −→R

, yields the theory of one

step rewriting; interpreting → as∗−→R

yields the theory of rewriting.

Both theories are undecidable for arbitrary R. They become however decid-able if we restrict our attention to term rewriting systems in which each variableoccurs at most once. Basically, the reason is given by the following:

Proposition 16. If R is a linear rewrite system such that left and right mem-bers of the rules do not share variables, then

∗−→R

is recognized by a GTT.

Proof. As in the proof of Proposition 15, we can construct in linear time a(non-deterministic) automaton which accepts the set of instances of a linearterm. For each rule li → ri we can construct a pair (Ai,A′

i) of automata whichrespectively recognize the set of instances of li and the set of instances of ri.Assume that the sets of states of the Ais are pairwise disjoint and that eachAi has a single final state qi

f . We may assume a similar property for the A′is:

they do not share states and for each i, the only common state between Ai andA′

i is qif (the final state for both of them). Then A (resp. A′) is the union of

the Ais: the states are the union of all sets of states of the Ais (resp. A′is),

transitions and final states are also unions of the transitions and final states ofeach individual automaton.

We claim that (A,A′) defines a GTT whose closure by iteration (A∗,A′∗)

(which is again a GTT according to Theorem 23) accepting∗−→R

. For, assume

first that up

−−−−→li→ri

v. Then u|p is an instance liσ of li, hence is accepted in state

qif . v|p is an instance riθ of ri, hence accepted in state qi

f . Now, v = u[riθ]p,

hence (u, v) is accepted by the GTT (A,A′). It follows that if u∗−→R

v, (u, v) is

accepted by (A∗,A′∗).

Conversely, assume that (u, v) is accepted by (A,A′), then

u∗−→A

C[q1, . . . , qn]p1,...,pn

∗←−−A′

v

Moreover, each qi is some state qjf , which, by definition, implies that u|pi

is aninstance of lj and v|pi

is an instance of rj . Now, since lj and rj do not share

variables, for each i, u|pi−→R

v|pi. Which implies that u

∗−→R

v. Now, if (u, v) is

accepted by (A∗,A′∗), u can be rewritten in v by the transitive closure of

∗−→R

,

which is∗−→R

itself.

Theorem 28. If R is a linear term rewriting system such that left and rightmembers of the rules do not share variables, then the first-order theory of rewrit-ing is decidable.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 99: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.4 Examples of Applications 99

Proof. By Proposition 16,∗−→R

is recognized by a GTT. From Proposition

9,∗−→R

is in Rec. By Lemma 3, there is a WSkS formula whose solutions are

exactly the pairs (s, t) such that s∗−→R

t. Finally, by Theorem 25, the first-order

theory of∗−→R

is decidable.

3.4.4 Reduction Strategies

So far, we gave examples of first-order theories (or constraint systems) whichcan be decided using tree automata techniques. Other examples will be givenin the next two chapters. We give here another example of application in adifferent spirit: we are going to show how to decide the existence (and com-pute) “optimal reduction strategies” in term rewriting systems. Informally, areduction sequence is optimal when every redex which is contracted along thissequence has to be contracted in any reduction sequence yielding a normal form.For example, if we consider the rewrite system x ∨> → >;>∨ x → >, thereis no optimal sequential reduction strategy in the above sense since, given anexpression e1 ∨ e2, where e1 and e2 are unevaluated, the strategy should spec-ify which of e1 or e2 has to be evaluated first. However, if we start with e1,then maybe e2 will reduce to > and the evaluation step on e1 was unnecessary.Symmetrically, evaluating e2 first may lead to unnecessary computations. Aninteresting question is to give sufficient criteria for a rewrite system to admitoptimal strategies and, in case there is such a strategy, give it explicitly.

The formalization of these notions was given by Huet and Levy in [HL91]who introduce the notion of sequentiality. We give briefly a summary of (partof) their definitions.

F is a fixed alphabet of function symbols and FΩ = F ∪Ω is the alphabetF enriched with a new constant Ω (whose intended meaning is “unevaluatedterm”).

We define on T (FΩ) the relation “less evaluated than” as:

u v v if and only if either u = Ω or else u = f(u1, . . . , un), v =f(v1, . . . , vn) and for all i, ui v vi

Definition 11. A predicate P on T (FΩ) is monotonic if u ∈ P and u v vimplies v ∈ P .

For example, a monotonic predicate of interest for rewriting is the predicateNR: t ∈ NR if and only if there is a term u ∈ T (F) such that u is irreducible

by R and t∗−→R

u.

Definition 12. Let P be a monotonic predicate on T (FΩ). If R is a termrewriting system and t ∈ T (FΩ), a position p of Ω in t is an index for P if forall terms u ∈ T (FΩ) such that t v u and u ∈ P , then u|p 6= Ω

In other words: it is necessary to evaluate t at position p in order to havethe predicate P satisfied.

Example 35. Let R = f(g(x), y) → g(f(x, y)); f(a, x) → a; b → g(b).Then 1 is an index of f(Ω,Ω) for NR: any reduction yielding a normal form

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 100: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

100 Logic, Automata and Relations

without Ω will have to evaluate the term at position 1. More formally, everyterm f(t1, t2) which can be reduced to a term in T (F) in normal form satisfies

t1 6= Ω. On the contrary, 2 is not an index of f(Ω,Ω) since f(a,Ω)∗−→R

a.

Definition 13. A monotonic predicate P is sequential if every term t such that:

• t /∈ P

• there is u ∈ T (F), t v u and u ∈ P

has an index for P .

If NR is sequential, the reduction strategy consisting of reducing an indexis optimal for non-overlapping and left linear rewrite systems.

Now, the relationship with tree automata is given by the following result:

Theorem 29. If P is definable in WSkS, then the sequentiality of P is express-ible as a WSkS formula.

The proof of this result is quite easy: it suffices to translate directly thedefinitions.

For instance, if R is a rewrite system whose left and right members donot share variables, then NR is recognizable (by Propositions 16 and 9), hencedefinable in WSkS by Lemma 3 and the sequentiality of NR is decidable byTheorem 29.

In general, the sequentiality of NR is undecidable. However, one can noticethat, if R and R′ are two rewrite systems such that −→

R⊆ −−→

R′, then a

position p which is an index for R′ is also an index for R. (And thus, R issequential whenever R′ is sequential).

For instance, we may approximate the term rewriting system, replacing allright hand sides by a new variable which does not occur in the correspondingleft member. Let R? be this approximation and N? be the predicate NR?. (Thisis the approximation considered by Huet and Levy).

Another, refined, approximation consists in renaming all variables of theright hand sides of the rules in such a way that all right hand sides becomelinear and do not share variables with their left hand sides. Let R′ be such anapproximation of R. The predicate NR′ is written NV .

Proposition 17. If R is left linear, then the predicates N? and NV are defin-able in WSkS and their sequentiality is decidable.

Proof. The approximations R? and R′ satisfy the hypotheses of Proposition 16and hence

∗−−→R?

and∗

−−→R′

are recognized by GTTs. On the other hand, the

set of terms in normal form for a left linear rewrite system is recognized by afinite tree automaton (see Corollary 4). By Proposition 9 and Lemma 3, allthese predicates are definable in WSkS. Then N? and NV are also definable inWSkS. For instance for NV :

NV (t)def= ∃u.t

∗−−→R′

u ∧ u ∈ NF

Then, by Theorem 29, the sequentiality of N? and NV are definable inWSkS and by Theorem 25 they are decidable.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 101: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.4 Examples of Applications 101

3.4.5 Application to Rigid E-unification

Given a finite (universally quantified) set of equations E, the classical problemof E-unification is, given an equation s = t, find substitutions σ such thatE |= sσ = tσ. The associated decision problem is to decide whether such asubstitution exists. This problem is in general unsolvable: there are decisionprocedures for restricted classes of axioms E.

The simultaneous rigid E-unification problem is slightly different: we arestill giving E and a finite set of equations si = ti and the question is to find asubstitution σ such that

|= (∧

e∈E

eσ) ⇒ (

n∧

i=1

siσ = tiσ)

The associated decision problem is to decide the existence of such a substitution.The relevance of such questions to automated deduction is very briefly de-

scribed in the bibliographic notes. We want here to show how tree automatahelp in this decision problem.

Simultaneous rigid E-unification is undecidable in general. However, for theone variable case, we have:

Theorem 30. The simultaneous rigid E-unification problem with one variableis EXPTIME-complete.

The EXPTIME membership is a direct consequence of the following lemma,together with closure and decision properties for recognizable tree languages.The EXPTIME-hardness is obtained by reduction the intersection non-emptinessproblem, see Theorem 12).

Lemma 4. The solutions of a rigid E-unification problem with one variable arerecognizable by a finite tree automaton.

Proof. (sketch) Assume that we have a single equation s = t. Let x be theonly variable occurring in E, s = t and E be the set E in which x is consideredas a constant. Let R be a canonical ground rewrite system (see e.g. [DJ90])associated with E (and for which x is minimal). We define v as x if s and thave the same normal form w.r.t. R and as the normal form of xσ w.r.t. Rotherwise.

Assume Eσ |= sσ = tσ. If v 6≡ x, we have E ∪ x = v |= x = xσ. HenceE ∪x = v |= s = t in any case. Conversely, assume that E ∪x = v |= s = t.Then E ∪ x = xσ |= s = t, hence Eσ |= sσ = tσ.

Now, assume v 6≡ x. Then either there is a subterm u of an equation in Esuch that E |= u = v or else R1 = R ∪ v → x is canonical. In this case, fromE ∪v = x |= s = t, we deduce that either E |= s = t (and v ≡ x) or there is asubterm u of s, t such that E |= v = u. we can conclude that, in all cases, thereis a subterm u of E ∪ s = t such that E |= u = v.

To summarize, σ is such that Eσ |= sσ = tσ iff there is a subterm u ofE ∪ s = t such that E |= u = xσ and E ∪ u = x |= s = t.

If we let T be the set of subterms u of E ∪ s = t such that E ∪ u = x |=s = t, then T is finite (and computable in polynomial time). The set of solutions

is then∗

−−−→R−1

(T ), which is a recognizable set of trees, thanks to Proposition

16.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 102: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

102 Logic, Automata and Relations

Further comments and references are given in the bibliographic notes.

3.4.6 Application to Higher-order Matching

We give here a last application (but the list is not closed!), in the typed lambda-calculus.

To be self-contained, let us first recall some basic definitions in typed lambdacalculus.

The set of types of the simply typed lambda calculus is the least set contain-ing the constant o (basic type) and such that τ → τ ′ is a type whenever τ andτ ′ are types.

Using the so-called Curryfication, any type τ → (τ ′ → τ ′′) is written τ, τ ′ →τ ′′. In this way all non-basic types are of the form τ1, . . . , τn → o with intuitivemeaning that this is the type of functions taking n arguments of respective typesτ1, . . . , τn and whose result is a basic type o.

The order of a type τ is defined by:

• O(o) = 1

• O(τ1, . . . , τn → o) = 1 + maxO(τ1), . . . , O(τn)

Given, for each type τ a set of variables Xτ of type τ and a set Cτ of constantsof type τ , the set of terms (of the simply typed lambda calculus) is the leastset Λ such that:

• x ∈ Xτ is a term of type τ

• c ∈ Cτ is a term of type τ

• If x1 ∈ Xτ1, . . . , xn ∈ Xτn

and t is a term of type τ , then λx1, . . . xn : t isa term of type τ1, . . . , τn → τ

• If t is a term of type τ1, . . . , τn → τ and t1, . . . , tn are terms of respectivetypes τ1, . . . , τn, then t(t1, . . . , tn) is a term of type τ .

The order of a term t is the order of its type τ(t).The set of free variables Var(t) of a term t is defined by:

• Var(x) = x if x is a variable

• Var(c) = ∅ if c is a constant

• Var(λx1, . . . , xn : t) = Var(t) \ x1, . . . , xn

• Var(t(u1, . . . , un)) = Var(t) ∪ Var(u1) ∪ . . . ∪ Var(un)

Terms are always assumed to be in η-long form, i.e. they are assumed tobe in normal form with respect to the rule:

(η) t → λx1, . . . , xn.t(x1, . . . , xn) if τ(t) = τ1, . . . τn → τand xi ∈ Xτi

\ Var(t) for all i

We define the α-equivalence =α on Λ as the least congruence relation suchthat: λx1, . . . , xn : t =α λx′

1 . . . , x′n : t′ when

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 103: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.4 Examples of Applications 103

• t′ is the term obtained from t by substituting for every index i, every freeoccurrence of xi with x′

i.

• There is no subterm of t in which, for some index i, both xi and x′i occur

free.

In the following, we consider only lambda terms modulo α-equivalence. Thenwe may assume that, in any term, any variable is bounded at most once andfree variables do not have bounded occurrences.

The β-reduction is defined on Λ as the least binary relation −→β

such that

• λx1, . . . , xn : t(t1, . . . , tn) −→β

tx1←t1, . . . , xn←tn

• for every context C, C[t] −→β

C[u] whenever t −→β

u

It is well-known that βη-reduction is terminating and confluent on Λ and,for every term t ∈ Λ, we let t ↓ be the unique normal form of t.

A matching problem is an equation s = t where s, t ∈ Λ and Var(t) = ∅.A solution of a matching problem is a substitution σ of the free variables of tsuch that sσ ↓= t ↓.

Whether or not the matching problem is decidable is an open question at thetime we write this book. However, it can be decided when every free variableoccurring in s is of order less or equal to 4. We sketch here how tree automatamay help in this matter. We will consider only two special cases here, leaving thegeneral case as well as details of the proofs as exercises (see also bibliographicnotes).

First consider a problem

(1) x(s1, . . . , sn) = t

where x is a third order variable and s1, . . . , sn, t are terms without free variables.

The first result states that the set of solutions is recognizable by a 2-automaton. 2-automata are a slight extension of finite tree automata: weassume here that the alphabet contains a special symbol 2. Then a term u isaccepted by a 2-automaton A if and only if there is a term v which is accepted(in the usual sense) by A and such that u is obtained from v by replacing eachoccurrence of the symbol 2 with a term (of appropriate type). Note that twodistinct occurrences of 2 need not to be replaced with the same term.

We consider the automaton As1,...,sn,t defined by: F consists of all symbolsoccurring in t plus the variable symbols x1, . . . , xn whose types are respectivelythe types of s1, . . . , sn and the constant 2.

The set of states Q consists of all subterms of t, which we write qu (insteadof u) and a state q2. In addition, we have the final state qf .

The transition rules ∆ consist in

• The rules

f(qt1 , . . . , qtn) → qf(t1,...,tn)

each time qf(t1,...,tn) ∈ Q

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 104: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

104 Logic, Automata and Relations

• For i = 1, . . . , n, the rules

xi(qt1 , . . . , qtn) → qu

where u is a subterm of t such that si(t1, . . . , tn) ↓= u and tj = 2 wheneversi(t1, . . . , tj−1,2, tj+1, . . . , tn) ↓= u.

• the rule λx1, . . . , λxn.qt → qf

Theorem 31. The set of solutions of (1) (up to α-conversion) is accepted bythe 2-automaton As1,...,sn,t.

More about this result, its proof and its extension to fourth order will begiven in the exercises (see also bibliographic notes). Let us simply give anexample.

Example 36. Let us consider the interpolation equation

x(λy1λy2.y1, λy3.f(y3, y3)) = f(a, a)

where y1, y2 are assumed to be of base type o. Then F = a, f, x1, x2,2o.Q = qa, qf(a,a), q2o

, qf and the rules of the automaton are:

a → qa f(qa, qa) → qf(a,a)

2o → q2ox1(qa, q2o

) → qa

x1(qf(a,a), q2o) → qf(a,a) x2(qa) → qf(a,a)

λx1λx2.qf(a,a) → qf

For instance the term λx1λx2.x1(x2(x1(x1(a,2o),2o)),2o) is accepted bythe automaton :

λx1λx2.x1(x2(x1(x1(a,2o),2o)),2o)∗−→A

λx1λx2.x1(x2(x1(x1(qa, q2o), q2o

)), q2o)

−→A

λx1λx2.x1(x2(x1(qa, q2o)), q2o

)

−→A

λx1λx2.x1(x2(qa), q2o)

−→A

λx1λx2.x1(qf(a,a), q2o)

−→A

λx1λx2.qf(a,a)

−→A

qf

And indeed, for every terms t1, t2, t3, λx1λx2.x1(x2(x1(x1(a, t1), t2)), t3) is asolution of the interpolation problem.

3.5 Exercises

Exercise 31. Let F be the alphabet consisting of finitely many unary functionsymbols a1, . . . , an and a constant 0.

1. Show that the set S of pairs (of words) (an1 (a1(a2(a

p2(0)))), an

1 (ap2(0))) | n, p ∈

N is in Rec. Show that S∗ is not in Rec, hence that Rec is not closed undertransitive closure.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 105: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.5 Exercises 105

2. More generally, show that, for any finite rewrite system R (on the alphabet F!), the reduction relation −→

Ris in Rec.

3. Is there any hope to design a class of tree languages which contains Rec, which isclosed by all Boolean operations and by transitive closure and for which empti-ness is decidable ? Why ?

Exercise 32. Show that the set of pairs (t, f(t, t′)) | t, t′ ∈ T (F) is not in Rec.

Exercise 33. Show that if a binary relation is recognized by a GTT, then its inverse

is also recognized by a GTT.

Exercise 34. Give an example of two relations that are recognized by GTTs andwhose union is not recognized by any GTT.

Similarly, show that the class of relations recognized by a GTT is not closed bycomplement. Is the class closed by intersection ?

Exercise 35. Give an example of a n-ary relation such that its ith projection followed

by its ith cylindrification does not give back the original relation. On the contrary,

show that ith cylindrification followed by ith projection gives back the original relation.

Exercise 36. About Rec and bounded delay relations. We assume that F onlycontains unary function symbols and a constant, i.e. we consider words rather thantrees and we write u = a1 . . . an instead of u = a1(. . . (an(0)) . . .). Similarly, u · vcorresponds to the usual concatenation of words.

A binary relation R on T (F) is called a bounded delay relation if and only if

∃k/∀(u, v) ∈ R, |u| − |v| ≤ k

R preserves the length if and only if

∀(u, v) ∈ R, |u| = |v|

If A, B are two binary relations, we write A · B (or simply AB) the relation

A · Bdef= (u, v)/∃(u1, v1) ∈ A, (u2, v2) ∈ Bu = u1.u2, v = v1.v2

Similarly, we write (in this exercise !)

A∗ = (u, v)/∃(u1, v1) ∈ A, . . . , (un, vn) ∈ A, u = u1 . . . un, v = v1 . . . vn

1. Given A, B ∈ Rec, is A · B necessary in Rec ? is A∗ necessary in Rec ? Why ?

2. Show that if A ∈ Rec preserves the length, then A∗ ∈ Rec.

3. Show that if A, B ∈ Rec and A is of bounded delay, then A · B ∈ Rec.

4. The family of rational relations is the smallest set of subsets of T (F)2 which con-tains the finite subsets of T (F)2 and which is closed under union, concatenation(·) and ∗.

Show that, if A is a bounded delay rational relation, then A ∈ Rec. Is theconverse true ?

Exercise 37. Let R0 be the rewrite system x×0 → 0; 0×x → 0 and F = 0, 1, s,×

1. Construct explicitly the GTT accepting∗

−−→R0

.

2. Let R1 = R0 ∪ x × 1 → x. Show that∗

−−→R1

is is not recognized by a GTT.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 106: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

106 Logic, Automata and Relations

3. Let R2 = R1 ∪ 1 × x → x × 1. Using a construction similar to the transitive

closure of GTTs, show that the set t ∈ T (F) | ∃u ∈ T (F), t∗

−−→R2

u, u ∈ NF

where NF is the set of terms in normal form for R2 is recognized by a finitetree automaton.

Exercise 38. (*) More generally, prove that given any rewrite system li → ri | 1 ≤i ≤ n such that

1. for all i, li and ri are linear

2. for all i, if x ∈ Var(li) ∩ Var(ri), then x occurs at depth at most one in li.

the set t ∈ T (F) | ∃u ∈ NF, t∗−→R

u is recognized by finite tree automaton.

What are the consequences of this result ?

(See [Jac96] for details about this results and its applications. Also compare with

Exercise 16, question 4.)

Exercise 39. Show that the set of pairs (f(t, t′), t) | t, t′ ∈ T (F) is not definable

in WSkS. (See also Exercise 32)

Exercise 40. Show that the set of pairs of words (w, w′) | l(w) = l(w′), where l(x)

is the length of x, is not definable in WSkS.

Exercise 41. Let F = a1, . . . , an, 0 where each ai is unary and 0 is a constant.Consider the following constraint system: terms are built on F , the binary symbols∩,∪, the unary symbol ¬ and set variables. Formulas are conjunctions of inclusionconstraints t ⊆ t′. The formulas are interpreted by assigning to variables finite subsetsof T (F), with the expected meaning for other symbols.

Show that the set of solutions of such constraints is in Rec2. What can we conclude?

(*) What happens if we remove the condition on the ai’s to be unary?

Exercise 42. Complete the proof of Proposition 13.

Exercise 43. Show that the subterm relation is not definable in WSkS.Given a term t Write a WSkS formula φt such that a term u |= φt if and only if t

is a subterm of u.

Exercise 44. Define in SkS “X is finite”. (Hint: express that every totally orderedsubset of X has an upper bound and use Konig’s lemma)

Exercise 45. A tuple (t1, . . . , tn) ∈ T (F)n can be represented in several ways asa finite sequence of finite sets. The first one is the encoding given in Section 3.3.6,overlapping the terms and considering one set for each tuple of symbols. A second oneconsists in having a tuple of sets for each component: one for each function symbol.

Compare the number of free variables which result from both codings when defining

an n-ary relation on terms in WSkS. Compare also the definitions of the diagonal ∆

using both encodings. How is it possible to translate an encoding into the other one

?

Exercise 46. (*) Let R be a finite rewrite system whose all left and right membersare ground.

1. Let Termination(x) be the predicate on T (F) which holds true on t when thereis no infinite sequence of reductions starting from t. Show that adding thispredicate as an atomic formula in the first-order theory of rewriting, this theoryremains decidable for ground rewrite systems.

2. Generalize these results to the case where the left members of R are linear andthe right members are ground.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 107: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.5 Exercises 107

Exercise 47. The complexity of automata recognizing the set of irreducible groundterms.

1. For each n ∈ N, give a linear rewrite system Rn whose size is O(n) and suchthat the minimal automaton accepting the set of irreducible ground terms hasa size O(2n).

2. Assume that for any two strict subterms s, t of left hand side(s) of R, if s and tare unifiable, then s is an instance of t or t is an instance of s. Show that thereis a NFTA A whose size is linear in R and which accepts the set of irreducibleground terms.

Exercise 48. Prove Theorem 29.

Exercise 49. The Propositional Linear-time Temporal Logic. The logic PTLis defined as follows:

Syntax P is a finite set of propositional variables. Each symbol of P is a formula (anatomic formula). If φ and ψ are formulas, then the following are formulas:

φ ∧ ψ, φ ∨ ψ, φ → ψ, ¬φ, φUψ, Nφ, Lφ

Semantics Let P ∗ be the set of words over the alphabet P . A word w ∈ P ∗ isidentified with the sequence of letters w(0)w(1) . . . w(|w| − 1). w(i..j) is theword w(i) . . . w(j). The satisfaction relation is defined by:

• if p ∈ P , w |= p if and only if w(0) = p

• The interpretation of logical connectives is the usual one

• w |= Nφ if and only if |w| ≥ 2 and w(1..|w| − 1) |= φ

• w |= Lφ if and only if |w| = 1

• w |= φUψ if and only if there is an index i ∈ [0..|w|] such that for allj ∈ [0..i], w(j..|w| − 1) |= φ and w(i..|w| − 1) |= ψ.

Let us recall that the language defined by a formula φ is the set of words w suchthat w |= φ.

1. What it is the language defined by N(p1Up2) (with p1, p2 ∈ P ) ?

2. Give PTL formulas defining respectively P ∗p1P∗, p∗

1, (p1p2)∗.

3. Give a first-order WS1S formula (i.e. without second-order quantification andcontaining only one free second-order variable) which defines the same languageas N(p1Up2)

4. For any PTL formula, give a first-order WS1S formula which defines the samelanguage.

5. Conversely, show that any language defined by a first-order WS1S formula isdefinable by a PTL formula.

Exercise 50. About 3rd-order interpolation problems

1. Prove Theorem 31.

2. Show that the size of the automaton As1,...,sn,t is O(n × |t|)

3. Deduce from Exercise 19 that the existence of a solution to a system of interpo-lation equations of the form x(s1, . . . , sn) = t (where x is a third order variablein each equation) is in NP.

Exercise 51. About general third order matching.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 108: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

108 Logic, Automata and Relations

1. How is it possible to modify the construction of As1,...,sn,t so as to forbid somesymbols of t to occur in the solutions ?

2. Consider a third order matching problem u = t where t is in normal form anddoes not contain any free variable. Let x1, . . . , xn be the free variables of u andxi(s1, . . . , sm) be the subterm of u at position p. Show that, for every solutionσ, either u[2]pσ ↓=α t or else that xiσ(s1σ, . . . , smσ) ↓ is in the set Sp definedas follows: v ∈ Sp if and only if there is a subterm t′ of t and there are positionsp1, . . . , pk of t′ and variables z1, . . . , zk which are bound above p in u such thatv = t′[z1, . . . , zk]p1,...,pk

.

3. By guessing the results of xiσ(s1σ, . . . , smσ) and using the previous exercise,show that general third order matching is in NP.

3.6 Bibliographic Notes

The following bibliographic notes only concern the applications of the usualfinite tree automata on finite trees (as defined at this stage of the book). Weare pretty sure that there are many missing references and we are pleased toreceive more pointers to the litterature.

3.6.1 GTT

GTT were introduced in [DTHL87] where they were used for the decidability ofconfluence of ground rewrite systems.

3.6.2 Automata and Logic

The development of automata in relation with logic and verification (in thesixties) is reported in [Tra95]. This research program was explained by A.Church himself in 1962 [Chu62].

Milestones of the decidability of monadic second-order logic are the papers[Buc60] [Rab69]. Theorem 25 is proved in [TW68].

3.6.3 Surveys

There are numerous surveys on automata and logic. Let us mention some ofthem: M.O. Rabin [Rab77] surveys the decidable theories; W. Thomas [Tho90,Tho97] provides an excellent survey of relationships between automata and logic.

3.6.4 Applications of tree automata to constraint solving

Concerning applications of tree automata, the reader is also referred to [Dau94]which reviews a number of applications of Tree automata to rewriting and con-straints.

The relation between sorts and tree automata is pointed out in [Com89]. Thedecidability of arbitrary first-order sort constraints (and actually the first ordertheory of finite trees with equality and sort constraints) is proved in [CD94].

More general sort constraints involving some second-order terms are studiedin [Com98b] with applications to a sort constrained equational logic [Com98a].

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 109: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

3.6 Bibliographic Notes 109

Sort constraints are also applied to specifications and automated inductiveproofs in [BJ97] where tree automata are used to represent some normal formssets. They are used in logic programming and automated reasoning [FSVY91,GMW97], in order to get more efficient procedures for fragments which fallinto the scope of tree automata techniques. They are also used in automateddeduction in order to increase the expressivity of (counter-)model constructions[Pel97].

Concerning encompassment, M. Dauchet et al gave a more general result(dropping the linearity requirement) in [DCC95]. We will come back to thisresult in the next chapter.

3.6.5 Application of tree automata to semantic unification

Rigid unification was originally considered by J. Gallier et al. [GRS87] whoshowed that this is a key notion in extending the matings method to a logicwith equality. Several authors worked on this problem and it is out of the scopeof this book to give a list of references. Let us simply mention that the resultof Section 3.4.5 can be found in [Vea97b]. Further results on application of treeautomata to rigid unification can be found in [DGN+98], [GJV98].

Tree automata are also used in solving classical semantic unification prob-lems. See e.g. [LM93] [KFK97] [Uri92]. For instance, in [KFK97], the idea isto capture some loops in the narrowing procedure using tree automata.

3.6.6 Application of tree automata to decision problemsin term rewriting

Some of the applications of tree automata to term rewriting follow from theresults on encompassment theory. Early works in this area are also mentionedin the bibliographic notes of Chapter 1. The reader is also referred to the survey[GT95].

The first-order theory of the binary (many-steps) reduction relation w.r.t.a ground rewrite system has been shown decidable by. M. Dauchet and S.Tison [DT90]. Extensions of the theory, including some function symbols, orother predicate symbols like the parallel rewriting or the termination predicate(Terminate(t) holds if there is no infinite reduction sequence starting from t),or fair termination etc... remain decidable [DT90]. **Mauvaise citation !? Seealso the exercises.

Both the theory of one step and the theory of many steps rewriting areundecidable for arbitrary R [Tre96].

Reduction strategies for term rewriting have been first studied by Huet andLevy in 1978 [HL91]. They show here the decidability of strong sequential-ity for orthogonal rewrite systems. This is based on an approximation of therewrite system which, roughly, only considers the left sides of the rules. Bet-ter approximation, yielding refined criteria were further proposed in [Oya93],[Com95], [Jac96]. The orthogonality requirement has also been replaced withthe weaker condition of left linearity. The first relation between tree automata,WSkS and reduction strategies is pointed out in [Com95]. Further studies ofcall-by-need strategies, which are still based on tree automata, but do not usea detour through monadic second-order logic can be found in [DM97]. For allthese works, a key property is the preservation of regularity by (many-steps)

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 110: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

110 Logic, Automata and Relations

rewriting, which was shown for ground systems in [Bra69], for linear systemswhich do not share variables in [DT90], for shallow systems in [Com95], for rightlinear monadic rewrite systems [Sal88], for linear semi-monadic rewrite systems[CG90], also called (with slight differences) growing systems in [Jac96]. Grow-ing systems are the currently most general class for which the preservation ofrecognizability is known.

As already pointed out, the decidability of the encompassment theory impliesthe decidability of ground reducibility. There are several papers written alongthese lines which will be explained in the next chapter.

Finally, approximations of the reachable terms are computed in [Gen97]using tree automata techniques, which implies the decision of some safety prop-erties.

3.6.7 Other applications

The relationship between finite tree automata and higher-order matching isstudied in [CJ97b].

Finite tree automata are also used in logic programming [FSVY91], typereconstruction [Tiu92] and automated deduction [GMW97].

For further applications of tree automata in the direction of program verifi-cation, see e.g. chapter 5 of this book or e.g. [Jon87].

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 111: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Chapter 4

Automata with Constraints

4.1 Introduction

A typical example of a language which is not recognized by a finite tree au-tomaton is the set of terms f(t, t) | t ∈ T (F). The reason is that the twosons of the root are recognized independently and only a fixed finite amount ofinformation can be carried up to the root position, whereas t may be arbitrar-ily large. Therefore, as seen in the application section of the previous chapter,this imposes some linearity conditions, typically when automata techniques areapplied to rewrite systems or to sort constraints. The shift from linear to nonlinear situations can also be seen as a generalization from tree automata to DAG(directed acyclic graphs) automata. This is the purpose of the present chapter:how is it possible to extend the definitions of tree automata in order to carryover the applications of the previous chapter to (some) non-linear situations ?

Such an extension has been studied in the early 80’s by M. Dauchet and J.Mongy. They define a class of automata which (when working in a top-downfashion) allow duplications. Considering bottom-up automata, this amounts tocheck equalities between subtrees. This yields the RATEG class . This classis not closed under complement. If we consider its closure, we get the classof automata with equality and disequality constraints. This class is studied inSection 4.2.

Unfortunately, the emptiness problem is undecidable for the class RATEG(and hence for automata with equality and disequality constraints).Several decidable subclasses have been studied in the literature. The mostremarkable ones are

• The class of automata with constraints between brothers which, roughly,allows equality (or disequality) tests only between positions with the sameancestors. For instance, the set of terms f(t, t) is recognized by suchan automaton. This class is interesting because all properties of treeautomata carry over this extension and hence most of the applications oftree automata can be extended, replacing linearity conditions with suchrestrictions on non-linearities.

We study this class in Section 4.3.

• The class of reduction automata which, roughly, allows arbitrary disequal-

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 112: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

112 Automata with Constraints

ity constraints but only a fixed finite amount of equality constraints oneach run of the automaton. For instance the set of terms f(t, t) also be-longs to this class. Though closure properties have to be handled withcare (with the definition sketched above, the class is not closed by com-plement), reduction automata are interesting because for example the setof irreducible terms (w.r.t. an arbitrary, possibly non-linear rewrite sys-tem) is recognized by an reduction automaton. Then the decidability ofground reducibility is a direct consequence of emptiness decidability forreduction automata. There is also a logical counterpart: the reducibilitytheory which is presented in the linear case in the previous chapter andwhich can be shown decidable in the general case using a similar technique.

Reduction automata are studied in Section 4.4.

We also consider in this chapter automata with arithmetic constraints. Theynaturally appear when some function symbols are assumed to be associative andcommutative (AC). In such a situation, the sons of an AC symbol can be per-muted and the relevant information is then the number of occurrences of thesame subtree in the multisets of sons. These integer variables (number of occur-rences) are subject to arithmetic constraints which must belong to a decidablefragment of arithmetic in order to keep closure and decidability properties.

4.2 Automata with Equality and Disequality Con-straints

4.2.1 The Most General Class

An equality constraint (resp. a disequality constraint) is a predicate onT (F) written π = π′ (resp. π 6= π′) where π, π′ ∈ 1, . . . , k∗. Such a predicateis satisfied on a term t, which we write t |= π = π′, if π, π′ ∈ Pos(t) and t|π = t|π′

(resp. π 6= π′ is satisfied on t if π = π′ is not satisfied on t).The satisfaction relation |= is extended as usual to any Boolean combination

of equality and disequality constraints. The empty conjunction and disjunctionare respectively written ⊥ (false) and > (true).

An automaton with equality and disequality constraints is a tuple(Q,F , Qf ,∆) where F is a finite ranked alphabet, Q is a finite set of states, Qf

is a subset of Q of finite states and ∆ is a set of transition rules of of the form

f(q1, . . . , qn)c−→ q

where f ∈ F , q1, . . . , qn, q ∈ Q, and c is a Boolean combination of equality(and disequality) constraints. The state q is called target state in the abovetransition rule.

We write for short AWEDC the class of automata with equality and dise-quality constraints.

Let A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) ∈ AWEDC. The move relation →A is defined by asfor NFTA modulo the satisfaction of equality and disequality constraints: lett, t′ ∈ F (F ∪ Q,X), then t→A t′ if and only

there is a context C ∈ C(F ∪ Q) and some terms u1, . . . , un ∈ T (F)

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 113: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.2 Automata with Equality and Disequality Constraints 113

there exists f(q1, . . . , qn)c−→ q ∈ ∆

t = C[f(q1(u1), . . . , qn(un)] and t′ = C[q(f(u1, . . . , un))]

C[f(u1, . . . , un)] |= c

∗→A is the reflexive and transitive closure of →A. As in Chapter 1, we usuallywrite t

∗→A q instead of t

∗→A q(t).

An automaton A ∈ AWEDC accepts (or recognizes) a ground term

t ∈ T (F) if t∗

→A q for some state q ∈ Qf . More generally, we also say that

A accepts t in state q iff t∗

→A q (acceptance by A is the particular case ofacceptance by A in a final state).

A run) is a mapping ρ from Pos(t) into ∆ such that:

• ρ(Λ) ∈ Qf

• if t(p) = f and the target state of ρ(p) is q, then there is a transition rule

f(q1, . . . , qn)c−→ q in ∆ such that for all 1 ≤ i ≤ n, the target state of

ρ(pi) is qi and t|p |= c.

Note that we do not have here exactly the same definition of a run as inChapter 1: instead of the state, we keep also the rule which yielded this state.This will be useful in the design of an emptiness decision algorithm for non-deterministic automata with equality and disequality constraints.

The language accepted (or recognized) by an automaton A ∈ AWEDCis the set L(A) of terms t ∈ T (F) that are accepted by A.

Example 37. Balanced complete binary trees over the alphabet f (binary)and a (constant) are recognized by the AWEDC (q, f, a, q,∆) where ∆consists of the following rules:

r1 : a → q

r2 : f(q, q)1=2−−→ q

For example, t = f(f(a, a), f(a, a)) is accepted. The mapping which associatesr1 to every position p of t such that t(p) = a and which associates r2 to everyposition p of t such that t(p) = f is indeed a successful run: for every positionp of t such that t(p) = f , t|p·1 = tp·2, hence t|p |= 1 = 2.

Example 38. Consider the following AWEDC: (Q,F , Qf ,∆) with F =0, s, f where 0 is a constant, s is unary and f has arity 4, Q = qn, q0, qf,Qf = qf, and ∆ consists of the following rules:

0 → q0 s(q0) → qn

s(qn) → qn f(q0, q0, qn, qn)3=4−−→ qf

f(q0, q0, q0, q0) → qf f(q0, qn, q0, qn)2=4−−→ qf

f(qf , qn, qn, qn)14=4∧21=12∧131=3−−−−−−−−−−−−−→ qf

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 114: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

114 Automata with Constraints

s

s

s

f

f

f s

s

s

s

s

s

s

s

s

ss

sss

s0 0

0

0

0

0 0

0

0

0

Figure 4.1: A computation of the sum of two natural numbers

This automaton computes the sum of two natural numbers written in baseone in the following sense: if t is accepted by A then1 t = f(t1, s

n(0), sm(0), sn+m(0))for some t1 and n,m ≥ 0. Conversely, for each n,m ≥ 0, there is a termf(t1, s

n(0), sm(0), sn+m(0)) which is accepted by the automaton.For instance the term depicted on Figure 4.1 is accepted by the automaton.

Similarly, it is possible to design an automaton of the class AWEDC which“computes the multiplication” (see exercises)

In order to evaluate the complexity of operations on automata of the classAWEDC, we need to precise a representation of the automata and estimate thespace which is necessary for this representation.

The size of is a Boolean combination of equality and disequality constraintsis defined by induction:

• ‖π = π′‖def= ‖π 6= π′‖

def= |π| + |π′| (|π| is the length of π)

• ‖c ∧ c′‖def= ‖c ∨ c′‖

def= ‖c‖ + ‖c′‖ + 1

• ‖¬c‖def= ‖c‖

Now, deciding whether t |= c depends on the representation of t. If t isrepresented as a directed acyclic graph (a DAG) with maximal sharing, then thiscan be decided in O(‖c‖) on a RAM. Otherwise, it requires to compute first thisrepresentation of t, and hence can be computed in time at most O(‖t‖ log ‖t‖+‖c‖).

1sn(0) denotes s(. . . s| z

n

(0)

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 115: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.2 Automata with Equality and Disequality Constraints 115

¿From now on, we assume, for complexity analysis, that the terms are rep-resented with maximal sharing in such a way that checking an equality or adisequality constraint on t can be completed in a time which is independent of‖t‖.

The size of an automaton A ∈ AWEDC is

‖A‖def= |Q| +

f(q1,...,qn)c−→ q∈∆

n + 2 + ‖c‖

An automaton A in AWEDC is deterministic if for every t ∈ T (F), there

is at most one state q such that t∗−→A

q. It is complete if for every t ∈ T (F)

there is at least one state q such that t∗−→A

q.

When every constraint is a tautology, then our definition of automata re-duces to the definition of Chapter 1. However, in such a case, the notions ofdeterminacy do not fully coincide, as noticed in Chapter 1, page 21.

Proposition 18. Given t ∈ T (F) and A ∈AWEDC, deciding whether t is ac-cepted by A can be completed in polynomial time (linear time for a deterministicautomaton).

Proof. Because of the DAG representation of t, the satisfaction of a constraintπ = π′ on t can be completed in time O(|π| + |π′|). Thus, if A is determinis-tic, the membership test can be performed in time O(‖t‖ + ‖A‖ + MC ) whereMC = max(‖c‖

∣∣ c is a constraint of a rule of A). If A is nondeterministic, thecomplexity of the algorithm will be O(‖t‖ × ‖A‖ × MC ).

4.2.2 Reducing Non-determinism and Closure Properties

Proposition 19. For every automaton A ∈ AWEDC, there is a complete au-tomaton A′ which accepts the same language as A. The size ‖A′‖ is polynomialin ‖A‖ and the computation of A′ can be performed in polynomial time (for afixed alphabet). If A is deterministic, then A′ is deterministic.

Proof. The proof is the same as for Theorem 2: we add a trash state andevery transition is possible to the trash state. However, this does not keep thedeterminism of the automaton. We need the following more careful computationin order to preserve the determinism.

We also add a single trash state q⊥. The additional transitions are computedas follows: for each function symbol f ∈ F and each tuple of states (including the

trash state) q1, . . . , qn, if there is no transition f(q1, . . . , qn)c−→ q ∈ ∆, then we

simply add the rule f(q1, . . . , qn) → q⊥ to ∆. Otherwise, let f(q1, . . . , qn)ci−→ si

(i = 1, ..m) be all rules in ∆ whose left member is f(q1, . . . , qn). We add the

rule f(q1, . . . , qn)c′−→ q⊥ to ∆, where c′

def= ¬

m∨

i=1

ci.

Proposition 20. For every automaton A ∈ AWEDC, there is a deterministicautomaton A′ which accepts the same language as A. A′ can be computed inexponential time and its size is exponential in the size of A. Moreover, if A iscomplete, then A′ is complete.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 116: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

116 Automata with Constraints

Proof. The construction is the same as in Theorem 4: states of A′ are sets ofstates of A. Final states of A′ are those which contain at least one final stateof A. The construction time complexity as well as the size A′ are also of thesame magnitude as in Theorem 4. The only difference is the computation of theconstraint: if S1, . . . , Sn, S are sets of states, in the deterministic automaton,the rule f(S1, . . . , Sn)

c−→ S is labeled by a constraint c defined by:

c =( ∧

q∈S

f(q1,...,qn)cr−→ q∈∆

qi∈Sii≤n

cr

)∧

( ∧

q/∈S

f(q1,...,qn)cr−→ q∈∆

qi∈Sii≤n

¬cr

)

Let us prove that t is accepted by A in states q1, . . . , qk (and no other states) ifand only if there t is accepted by A′ in the state q1, . . . , qk:

⇒ Assume that tn−→A

qi (i.e. t∗−→A

qi in n steps), for i = 1, . . . , k. We prove,

by induction on n, that

tn

−−→A′

q1, . . . , qk.

If n = 1, then t is a constant and t → S is a rule of A′ where S =q | a −→

Aq.

Assume now that n > 1. Let, for each i = 1, . . . , k,

t = f(t1, . . . , tp)m−→A

f(qi1, . . . , q

ip) −→

Aqi

and f(qi1, . . . , q

ip)

ci−→ qi be a rule of A such that t |= ci. By induction

hypothesis, each term tj is accepted by A′ in the states of a set Sj ⊇

q1j , . . . , qk

j . Moreover, by definition of S = q1, . . . , qk, if t∗−→A

q′ then

q′ ∈ S. Therefore, for every transition rule of A f(q′1, . . . , q′p)

c′−→ q′ such

that q′ /∈ S and qj ∈ Sj for every j ≤ p, we have t 6|= c′. Then t satisfiesthe above defined constraint c.

⇐ Assume that tn

−−→A′

S. We prove by induction on n that, for every q ∈ S,

tn−→A

q.

If n = 1, then S is the set of states q such that t −→A

q, hence the property.

Assume now that

t = f(t1, . . . , tp)n

−−→A′

f(S1, . . . , Sp) −−→A′

S.

Let f(S1, . . . , Sp)c−→ S be the last rule used in this reduction. Then

t |= c and, by definition of c, for every state q ∈ S, there is a rule

f(q1, . . . , qn)cr−→ q ∈ ∆ such that qi ∈ Si for every i ≤ n and t |= cr. By

induction hypothesis, for each i, timi−−→A′

Si implies timi−−→A

qi (mi < n)

and hence tn−→A

f(q1, . . . , qp) −→A

q.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 117: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.2 Automata with Equality and Disequality Constraints 117

Thus, by construction of the final states set, a ground term t is accepted by A′

iff t is accepted by A.Now, we have to prove that A′ is deterministic indeed. Assume that t

∗−→A

′S

and t∗

−−→A′

S′. Assume moreover that S 6= S′ and that t is the smallest term (in

size) with the property of being recognized in two different states. Then there ex-

ists S1, . . . , Sn such that t∗

−−→A′

f(S1, . . . , Sn) and such that f(S1, . . . , Sn)c−→ S

and f(S1, . . . , Sn)c′−→ S′ are transition rules of A′, wit t |= c and t |= c′.

By symmetry, we may assume that there is a state q ∈ S such that q /∈ S′.Then, by definition, there are some states qi ∈ Si, for every i ≤ n, and a rulef(q1, . . . , qn)

cr−→ q of A where cr occurs positively in c, and is therefore satisfied

by t, t |= cr. By construction of the constraint of A′, cr must occur negatively inthe second part of (the conjunction) c′. Therefore, t |= c′ contradicts t |= cr.

Example 39. Consider the following automaton on the alphabet F = a, fwhere a is a constant and f is a binary symbol: Q = q, q⊥, Qf = q and ∆contains the following rules:

a → q f(q, q)1=2−−→ q f(q, q) → q⊥

f(q⊥, q) → q⊥ f(q, q⊥) → q⊥ f(q⊥, q⊥) → q⊥

This is the (non-deterministic) complete version of the automaton of Exam-ple 37.

Then the deterministic automaton computed as in the previous propositionis given by:

a → q f(q, q)1=2∧⊥−−−−−→ q

f(q, q)1=2−−→ q, q⊥ f(q, q)

16=2−−→ q⊥

f(q, q⊥) → q⊥ f(q⊥, q) → q⊥

f(q⊥, q⊥) → q⊥ f(q, q⊥, q)1=2∧⊥−−−−−→ q

f(q, q⊥, q)1=2−−→ q, q⊥ f(q, q⊥, q⊥) −→ q⊥

f(q, q⊥, q, q⊥)1=2−−→ q, q⊥ f(q, q⊥, q)

16=2−−→ q⊥

f(q, q, q⊥)1=2−−→ q, q⊥ f(q, q, q⊥)

16=2−−→ q⊥

f(q, q⊥, q)16=2−−→ q⊥ f(q, q, q⊥)

1=2∧⊥−−−−−→ q

f(q, q⊥, q, q⊥)1=2∧⊥−−−−−→ q f(q⊥, q, q⊥) −→ q⊥

For instance, the constraint 1=2∧⊥ is obtained by the conjunction of the label

of f(q, q)1=2−−→ q and the negation of the constraint labelling f(q, q) −→ q⊥,

(which is >).Some of the constraints, such as 1=2∧⊥ are unsatisfiable, hence the corre-

sponding rules can be removed. If we finally rename the two accepting statesq and q, q⊥ into a single state qf (this is possible since by replacing oneof these states by the other in any left hand side of a transition rule, we get

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 118: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

118 Automata with Constraints

another transition rule), then we get a simplified version of the deterministicautomaton:

a → qf f(qf , qf )1=2−−→ qf

f(qf , qf )16=2−−→ q⊥ f(q⊥, qf ) → q⊥

f(qf , q⊥) → q⊥ f(q⊥, q⊥) → q⊥

Proposition 21. The class AWEDC is effectively closed by all Boolean op-erations. Union requires linear time, intersection requires quadratic time andcomplement requires exponential time. The respective sizes of the AWEDC ob-tained by these construction are of the same magnitude as the time complexity.

Proof. The proof of this proposition can be obtained from the proof of The-orem 5 (Chapter 1, pages 28–29) with straightforward modifications. Theonly difference lies in the product automaton for the intersection: we have toconsider conjunctions of constraints. More precisely, if we have two AWEDCA1 = (Q1,F , Qf1,∆1) and A1 = (Q2,F , Qf2,∆2), we construct an AWEDC

A = (Q1 × Q2,F , Qf1 × Qf2,∆) such that if f(q1, . . . , qn)c−→ q ∈ ∆1 and

f(q′1, . . . , q′n)

c′−→ q′ ∈ ∆2, then f((q1, q

′1), . . . , (qn, q′n))

c∧c′−−−→ (q, q′) ∈ ∆. The

AWEDC A recognizes L(A1) ∩ L(A2).

4.2.3 Undecidability of Emptiness

Theorem 32. The emptiness problem for AWEDC is undecidable.

Proof. We reduce the Post Correspondence Problem (PCP). If w1, . . . , wn andw′

1, . . . , w′n are the word sequences of the PCP problem over the alphabet a, b,

we let F contain h (ternary), a, b (unary) and 0 (constant). Lets recall that theanswer for the above instance of the PCP is a sequence i1, . . . , ip (which maycontain some repetitions) such that wi1 . . . wip

= w′i1

. . . w′ip

.

If w ∈ a, b∗, w = a1 . . . ak and t ∈ T (F), we write w(t) the term a1(. . . (ak(t)) . . .) ∈T (F).

Now, we construct A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) ∈ AWEDC as follows:

• Q contains a state qv for each prefix v of one of the words wi, w′i (including

qwiand qw′

ias well as 3 extra states: q0, q and qf . We assume that a and

b are both prefix of at least one of the words wi, w′i. Qf = qf.

• ∆ contains the following rules:

a(q0) → qa b(q0) → qb

a(qv) → qa·v if qv, qa·v ∈ Qb(qv) → qb·v if qv, qb·v ∈ Q

a(qwi) → qa b(qwi

) → qb

a(qw′i) → qa b(qw′

i) → qb

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 119: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.3 Automata with Constraints Between Brothers 119

∆ also contains the rules:

0 → q0

h(q0, q0, q0) → q

h(qwi, q, qw′

i)

1·1|wi|=2·1∧3·1|w′i|=2·3

−−−−−−−−−−−−−−−→ q

h(qwi, q, qw′

i)

1·1|wi|=2·1∧3·1|w′i|∧1=3

−−−−−−−−−−−−−−−−→ qf

The rule with left member h(q0, q0, q0) recognizes the beginning of a Postsequence. The rules with left members h(qwi

, q.qw′i) ensure that we are really in

presence of a successor in the PCP sequences: the constraint expresses that thesubterm at position 1 is obtained by concatenating some wi with the term atposition 2 · 1 and that the subterm at position 3 is obtained by concatenatingw′

i (with the same index i) with the subterm at position 2 · 3. Finally, enteringthe final state is subject to the additional constraint 1 = 3. This last constraintexpresses that we went thru two identical words with the wi sequences and thew′

i sequences respectively. (See Figure 4.2).

The details that this automaton indeed accepts the solutions of the PCP areleft to the reader.

Then the language accepted by A is empty if and only if the PCP has asolution. Since PCP is undecidable, emptiness of A is also undecidable.

4.3 Automata with Constraints Between Broth-ers

The undecidability result of the previous section led to look for subclasses whichhave the desired closure properties, contain (properly) the classical tree au-tomata and still keep the decidability of emptiness. This is the purpose of theclass AWCBB:

An automaton A ∈ AWEDC is an automaton with constraints be-

tween brothers if every equality (resp disequality) constraint has the formi = j (resp. i 6= j) where i, j ∈ N+.

AWCBB is the set automata with constraints between brothers.

Example 40. The set of terms f(t, t) | t ∈ T (F) is accepted by an automatonof the class AWCBB, because the automaton of Example 37 is in AWCBBindeed.

4.3.1 Closure Properties

Proposition 22. AWCBB is a stable subclass of AWEDC w.r.t. Boolean op-erations (union, intersection, complementation).

Proof. It is sufficient to check that the constructions of Proposition 21 preservethe property of being a member of AWCBB.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 120: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

120 Automata with Constraints

h

hw w

···

h

h

wi w′i

v v′

v v′···

h

0 00

Figure 4.2: An automaton in AWEDC accepting the solutions of PCP

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 121: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.3 Automata with Constraints Between Brothers 121

Recall that the time complexity of each such construction is the same inAWEDC and in the unconstrained case: union and intersection are polynomial,complementation requires determinization and is exponential.

4.3.2 Emptiness Decision

To decide emptiness we would like to design for instance a “cleaning algorithm”as in Theorem 11. As in this result, the correctness and completeness of themarking technique relies on a pumping lemma. Is there an analog of Lemma 1in the case of automata of the class AWCBB ?

There are additional difficulties. For instance consider the following example.

Example 41. A contains only one state and the rules

a → q f(q, q)16=2−−→ q

b → q

Now consider the term f(f(a, b), b) which is accepted by the automaton. f(a, b)and b yield the same state q. Hence, for a classical finite tree automaton, wemay replace f(a, b) with b and still get a term which is accepted by A. This isnot the case here since, replacing f(a, b) with b we get the term f(b, b) whichis not accepted. The reason of this phenomenon is easy to understand: someconstraint which was satisfied before the pumping is no longer valid after thepumping.

Hence the problem is to preserve the satisfaction of constraints along termreplacements. First, concerning equality constraints, we may see the terms asDAGs in which each pair of subterms which is checked for equality is consideredas a single subterm referenced in two different ways. Then replacing one ofits occurrences automatically replaces the other occurrences and preserves theequality constraints. This is what is formalized below.

Preserving the equality constraints. Let t be a term accepted by theautomaton A in AWCBB. Let ρ be a run of the automaton on t. With ev-ery position p of t, we associate the conjunction cons(p) of atomic (equal-ity or disequality) constraints that are checked by ρ(p) and satisfied by t.

More precisely: let ρ(p) = f(q1, . . . , qn)c′−→ q; cons(p)

def= decomp(c′, p) where

decomp(c′, p) is recursively defined by: decomp(>, p)def= >, decomp(c1∧c2, p)

def=

decomp(c1, p)∧decomp(c2, p) and decomp(c1∨ c2, p) = decomp(c1, p) if t|p |= c1,decomp(c1 ∨ c2, p) = decomp(c2, p) otherwise. We can show by a simple induc-tion that t|p |= cons(p).

Now, we define the equivalence relation =t on the set of positions of t as theleast equivalence relation such that:

• if i = j ∈ cons(p), then p · i =t p · j

• if p =t p′ and p · π ∈ Pos(t), then p · π =t p′ · π

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 122: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

122 Automata with Constraints

Note that in the last case, we have p′ · π ∈ Pos(t). Of course, if p =t p′, thent|p = t|p′ (but the converse is not necessarily true). Note also (and this is aproperty of the class AWCBB) that p =t p′ implies that the lengths of p and p′

are the same, hence, if p 6= p′, they are incomparable w.r.t. the prefix ordering.We can also derive from this remark that each equivalence class is finite (wemay assume that each equality constraint of the form i = i has been replacedby >).

Example 42. Consider the automaton whose transition rules are:

r1 : f(q, q) → q r2 : a → q

r3 : f(q, q)1=2−−→ qf r4 : b → q

r5 : f(q, qf ) → qf r6 : f(qf , q) → qf

r7 : f(q, qf ) → q r8 : f(qf , q) → q

Let t = f(b, f(f(f(a, a), f(a, b)), f(f(a, a), f(a, b)))). A possible run of A on t isr5(r4, r3(r1(r1(r2, r2), r1(r2, r5)), r8(r3(r2, r2), r1(r2, r5)))) Equivalence classesof positions are:

Λ, 1, 2, 21, 22, 211, 221, 212, 222,2111, 2211, 2112, 2212, 2121, 2221, 2122, 2222

Let us recall the principle of pumping, for finite bottom-up tree automata(see Chapter 1). When a ground term C[C ′[t]] (C and C ′ are two contexts)is such that t and C ′[t] are accepted in the same state by an NFTA A, thenevery term C[C ′n[t]] (n ≥ 0) is accepted by A in the same state as C[C ′[t]]. Inother words, any C[C ′n[t]] ∈ L(A) may be reduced by pumping it up to theterm C[t] ∈ L(A). We consider here a position p (corresponding to the termC ′[t]) and its equivalence class [[p]] modulo =t. The simultaneous replacementon [[p]] with t in u, written u[t][[p]], is defined as the term obtained by successivelyreplacing the subterm at position p′ with t for each position p′ ∈ [[p]]. Since anytwo positions in [[p]] are incomparable, the replacement order is irrelevant. Now,a pumping is a pair (C[C ′[t]]p, C[C ′n[t]][[p]]) where C ′[t] and t are accepted inthe same state.

Preserving the disequality constraints. We have seen on Example 41that, if t is accepted by the automaton, replacing one of its subterms, say u,with a term v accepted in the same state as u, does not necessary yield anaccepted term. However, the idea is now that, if we have sufficiently manysuch candidates v, at least one of the replacements will keep the satisfaction ofdisequality constraints.

This is the what shows the following lemma which states that minimal ac-cepted terms cannot contain too many subterms accepted in the same state.

Lemma 5. Given any total simplification ordering, a minimal term acceptedby a deterministic automaton in AWCBB contains at most |Q| × N distinctsubterms where N is the maximal arity of a function symbol and |Q| is thenumber of states of the automaton.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 123: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.3 Automata with Constraints Between Brothers 123

⇓ Replacement

pN+1

=

= · · · 6= · · · = · · · 6= · · ·

pN+1

=

= · · · 6= · · · = · · · 6= · · ·

Figure 4.3: Constructing a smaller term accepted by the automaton

Proof. If ρ is a run, let τρ be the mapping from positions to states such thatτρ(p) is the target state of ρ(p).

If t is accepted by the automaton (let ρ be a successful run on t) and containsat least 1 + |Q| × N distinct subterms, then there are at least N + 1 positionsp1, . . . , pN+1 such that τρ(p1) = . . . = τρ(pN+1) and t|p1

, . . . , t|pN+1are dis-

tinct. Assume for instance that t|pN+1is the largest term (in the given total

simplification ordering) among t|p1, . . . , t|pN+1

. We claim that one of the terms

videf= t[t|pi

][[pN+1]] (i ≤ N) is accepted by the automaton.For each i ≤ N , we may define unambiguously a tree ρi by: ρi = ρ[ρ|pi

][[pN+1]].First, note that, by determinacy, for each position p ∈ [[pN+1]], τρ(p) =

τρ(pN+1) = τρ(pi). To show that there is a ρi which is a run, it remains to finda ρi the constraints of which are satisfied. Equality constraints of any ρi aresatisfied, from the construction of the equivalence classes (details are left to thereader).

Concerning disequality constraints, we choose i in such a way that all sub-terms at brother positions of pN+1 are distinct from t|pi

(this choice is possiblesince N is the maximal arity of a function symbol and there are N distinctcandidates). We get a replacement as depicted on Figure 4.3.

Let pN+1 = π · k where k ∈ N (π is the position immediately above pN+1).Every disequality in cons(π) is satisfied by choice of i. Moreover, if p′ ∈ [[pN+1]]and p′ = π′ ·k′ with k′ ∈ N, then every disequality in mathitcons(π′) is satisfiedsince vi|π = vi|π′ .

Hence we constructed a term which is smaller than t and which is acceptedby the automaton. This yields the lemma.

Theorem 33. Emptiness can be decided in polynomial time for deterministicautomata in AWCBB.

Proof. The basic idea is that, if we have enough distinct terms in states q1, . . . , qn,then the transition f(q1, . . . , qn)

c−→ q is possible. Use a marking algorithm (as

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 124: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

124 Automata with Constraints

in Theorem 3) and keep for each state the terms that are known to be acceptedin this state. It is sufficient to keep at most N terms in each state (N is themaximal arity of a function symbol) according to Lemma 5 and the determinacyhypothesis (terms in different states are distinct). More precisely, we use thefollowing algorithm:

input: AWCBB A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆)begin

– Marked is a mapping which associates each state with a set ofterms accepted in that state.

Set Marked to the function which maps each state to the ∅repeat

Set Marked(q) to Marked(q) ∪ twhere

f ∈ Fn, t1 ∈ Marked(q1), . . . , tn ∈ Marked(qn),

f(q1, . . . , qn)c−→ q ∈ ∆,

t = f(t1, . . . , tn) and t |= c,|Marked(q)| ≤ N − 1,

until no term can be added to any Marked(q)output: true if, for every state qf ∈ Qf , Marked(qf ) = ∅.

end

Complexity. For non-deterministic automata, an exponential time algorithmis derived from Proposition 20 and Theorem 33. Actually, in the non-deterministiccase, the problem is EXPTIME-complete.

We may indeed reduce the following problem which is known to be EXPTIME-complete to non-emptiness decision for nondeterministic AWCBB.

Instance n tree automata A1,. . . ,An over F .

Answer “yes” iff the intersection the respective languages recognized by A1,. . . ,An

is not empty.

We may assume without loss of generality that the states sets of A1,. . . ,An

(called respectively Q1,. . . ,Qn) are pairwise disjoint, and that every Ai has a

single final state called qfi . We also assume that n = 2k for some integer k. If

this is not the case, let k be the smallest integer i such that n < 2i and letn′ = 2k. We consider a second instance of the above problem: A′

1,. . . ,A′n′

where

A′i = Ai for each i ≤ n.

A′i = (q,F , q, f(q, . . . , q) → q|f ∈ F) for each n < i ≤ n′.

Note that the tree automaton in the second case is universal, i.e. it acceptsevery term of T (F). Hence, the answer is “yes” for A′

1,. . . ,A′n′ iff it is “yes”

for A1,. . . ,An.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 125: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.4 Reduction Automata 125

Now, we add a single new binary symbol g to F , getting F ′, and considerthe following AWCBB A:

A = (

n⋃

i=1

Qi ] q1, . . . , qn−1,F′, q1,∆)

where q1,. . . ,q2n−1 are new states, and the transition of ∆ are:

every transition rule of A1,. . . ,An is a transition rule of A,

for each i < n2 , g(q2i, q2i+1)

1=2−−→ qi is a transition rule of A,

for each i, n2 ≤ i < n − 1, g(qf

2i, qf2i+1)

1=2−−→ qi is a transition rule of A.

Note that A is non-deterministic, even if every Ai is deterministic.We can show by induction on k (n = 2k) that the answer to the above

problem is “yes” iff the language recognized by A is not empty. Moreover, thesize of A si linear in the size of the initial problem and A is constructed in a timewhich is linear in his size. This proves the EXPTIME-hardness of emptinessdecision for AWCBB.

4.3.3 Applications

The main difference between AWCBB and NFTA is the non-closure of AWCBBunder projection and cylindrification. Actually, the shift from automata on treesto automata on tuples of trees cannot be extended to the class AWCBB.

As long as we are interested in automata recognizing sets of trees, all resultson NFTA (and all applications) can be extended to the class AWCBB (withan bigger complexity). For instance, Theorem 26 (sort constraints) can beextended to interpretations of sorts as languages accepted by AWCBB. Propo-sition 15 (encompassment) can be easily generalized to the case of non-linearterms in which non-linearities only occur between brother positions, providedthat we replace NFTA with AWCBB. Theorem 27 can also be generalized tothe reducibility theory with predicates ·£t where t is non-linear terms, providedthat non-linearities in t only occur between brother positions.

However, we can no longer invoke an embedding into WSkS. The importantpoint is that this theory only requires the weak notion of recognizability ontuples (Rec×). Hence we do not need automata on tuples, but only tuplesof automata. As an example of application, we get a decision algorithm forground reducibility of a term t w.r.t. left hand sides l1, . . . , ln, provided thatall non-linearities in t, l1, . . . , ln occur at brother positions: simply compute theautomata Ai accepting the terms that encompass li and check that L(A) ⊆L(A1) ∪ . . . ∪ L(An).

Finally, the application on reduction strategies does not carry over the caseof non-linear terms because there really need automata on tuples.

4.4 Reduction Automata

As we have seen above, the first-order theory of finitely many unary encom-passment predicates ·£t1 , . . . , ·£tn

(reducibility theory) is decidable when non-linearities in the terms ti are restricted to brother positions. What happens

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 126: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

126 Automata with Constraints

when we drop the restrictions and consider arbitrary terms t1, . . . , tn, t ? Itturns out that the theory remains decidable, as we will see. Intuitively, we makeimpossible counter examples like the one in the proof of Theorem 32 (statingundecidability of the emptiness problem for AWEDC) with an additional con-dition that using the automaton which accepts the set of terms encompassing t,we may only check for a bounded number of equalities along each branch. Thatis the idea of the next definitions of reduction automata.

4.4.1 Definition and Closure Properties

A reduction automaton A is a member of AWEDC such that there is anordering on the states of A such that,

for each rule f(q1, . . . , qn)π1=π2∧c−−−−−−→ q, q is strictly smaller than each

qi.

In case of an automaton with ε-transitions q → q′ we also require q′ to benot larger than q.

Example 43. Consider the set of terms on the alphabet F = a, g encom-passing g(g(x, y), x). It is accepted by the following reduction automaton, thefinal state of which is qf and qf is minimal in the ordering on states.

a → q> g(q>, q>) → qg(x,y)

g(q>, qg(x,y)) → qg(x,y)

g(qg(x,y), q>)11=2−−−→ qf g(qg(x,y), q>)

116=2−−−→ qg(x,y)

g(qg(x,y), qg(x,y))11=2−−−→ qf g(qg(x,y), qg(x,y))

116=2−−−→ qg(x,y)

g(q, qf ) → qf g(qf , q) → qf

where q ∈ q>, qg(x,y), qf

This construction can be generalized, along the lines of the proof of Propo-sition 15 (page 96):

Proposition 23. The set of terms encompassing a term t is accepted by adeterministic and complete reduction automaton. The size of this automaton ispolynomial in ‖t‖ as well as the time complexity for its construction.

As usual, we are now interested in closure properties:

Proposition 24. The class of reduction automata is closed under union andintersection. It is not closed under complementation.

Proof. The constructions for union and intersection are the same as in the proofof Proposition 21, and therefore, the respective time complexity and sizes arethe same. The proof that the class of reduction automata is closed under theseconstructions is left as an exercise. Consider the set L of ground terms on thealphabet a, f defined by a ∈ L and for every t ∈ L which is not a, t has asubterm of the form f(s, s′) where s 6= s′. The set L is accepted by a (non-deterministic, non-complete) reduction automaton, but its complement is theset of balanced binary trees and it cannot be accepted by a reduction automaton(see Exercise 56).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 127: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.4 Reduction Automata 127

The weak point is of course the non-closure under complement. Conse-quently, this is not possible to reduce the non-determinism.

However, we have a weak version of stability:

Proposition 25. • With each reduction automaton, we can associate acomplete reduction automaton which accepts the same language. More-over, this construction preserves the determinism.

• The class of complete deterministic reduction automata is closed undercomplement.

4.4.2 Emptiness Decision

Theorem 34. Emptiness is decidable for the class of reduction automata.

The proof of this result is quite complicated and gives quite high upperbounds on the complexity (a tower of several exponentials). Hence, we are notgoing to reproduce it here. Let us only sketch how it works, in the case ofdeterministic reduction automata.

As in Section 4.3.2, we have both to preserve equality and disequality con-straints.

Concerning equality constraints, we also define an equivalence relation be-tween positions (of equal subtrees). We cannot claim any longer that two equiv-alent positions do have the same length. However, some of the properties of theequivalence classes are preserved: first, they are all finite and their cardinalcan be bounded by a number which only depends on the automaton, becauseof the condition with the ordering on states (this is actually not true for theclass AWCBB). Then, we can compute a bound b2 (which only depends on theautomaton) such that the difference of the lengths of two equivalent positionsis smaller than b2. Nevertheless, as in Section 4.3.2, equalities are not a realproblem, as soon as the automaton is deterministic. Indeed, pumping can thenbe defined on equivalence classes of positions. If the automaton is not determin-istic, the problem is more difficult since we cannot guarantee that we reach thesame state at two equivalent positions, hence we have to restrict our attentionto some particular runs of the automaton.

Handling disequalities requires more care; the number of distinct subterms ofa minimal accepted term cannot be bounded as for AWCBB by |Q|×N , where Nis the maximal arity of a function symbol. The problem is the possible “overlap”of disequalities checked by the automaton. As in Example 41, a pumping mayyield a term which is no longer accepted, since a disequality checked somewherein the term is no longer satisfied. In such a case, we say that the pumping createsan equality. Then, we distinguish two kinds of equalities created by a pumping:the close equalities and the remote equalities. Roughly, an equality createdby a pumping (t[v(u)]p, t[u]p) is a pair of positions (π ·π1, π ·π2) of t[v(u)]p whichwas checked for disequality by the run ρ at position π on t[v(u)]p and such thatt[u]p|π·π1

= t[u]p|π·π2(π is the longest common prefix to both members of the

pair). This equality (π · π1, π · π2) is a close equality if π ≤ p < π · π1 orπ ≤ p < π · π2. Otherwise (p ≥ π · π1 or p ≥ π · π2), it is a remote equality. Thedifferent situations are depicted on Figures 4.4 and 4.5.

One possible proof sketch is

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 128: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

128 Automata with Constraints

π π2π π1

π

p

π π2π π1

π

p

Figure 4.4: A close equality is created

π π2

π π1

π

pπ π2

π π1

π

p

Figure 4.5: A remote equality is created

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 129: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.4 Reduction Automata 129

• First show that it is sufficient to consider equalities that are created atpositions around which the states are incomparable w.r.t. >

• Next, show that, for a deep enough path, there is at least one pumpingwhich does not yield a close equality (this makes use of a combinatorialargument; the bound is an exponential in the maximal size of a constraint).

• For remote equalities, pumping is not sufficient. However, if some pump-ing creates a remote equality anyway, this means that there are “big”equalterms in t. Then we switch to another branch of the tree, combining pump-ing in both subtrees to find one (again using a combinatorial argument)such that no equality is created.

Of course, this is a very sketchy proof. The reader is referred to the bibliog-raphy for more information about the proof.

4.4.3 Finiteness Decision

The following result is quite difficult to establish. We only mention them forsake of completeness.

Theorem 35. Finiteness of the language is decidable for the class of reductionautomata.

4.4.4 Term Rewriting Systems

There is a strong relationship between reduction automata and term rewriting.We mention them readers interested in that topic.

Proposition 26. Given a term rewriting system R, the set of ground R-normalforms is recognizable by a reduction automaton, the size of which is exponentialin the size of R. The time complexity of the construction is exponential.

Proof. The set of R-reducible ground terms can be defined as the union of setsof ground terms encompassing the left members of rules of R. Thus, by Propo-sitions 23 and 24 the set of R-reducible ground terms is accepted by a deter-ministic and complete reduction automaton. For the union, we use the productconstruction, preserving determinism (see the proof of Theorem 5, Chapter 1)with the price of an exponential blowup. The set of ground R-normal formsis the complement of the set of ground R-reducible terms, and it is thereforeaccepted by a reduction automaton, according to Proposition 25.

Thus, we have the following consequence of Theorems 35 and 34.

Corollary 5. Emptiness and finiteness of the language of ground R-normalforms is decidable for every term rewriting system R.

Let us cite another important result concerning recognizability of sets normalforms.

Theorem 36. The membership of the language of ground normal forms to theclass of recognizable tree languages is decidable.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 130: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

130 Automata with Constraints

4.4.5 Application to the Reducibility Theory

Consider the reducibility theory of Section 3.4.2: there are unary predicate sym-bols ·£t which are interpreted as the set of terms which encompass t. However,we accept now non linear terms t as indices.

Propositions 23, and 24, and 25 yield the following result:

Theorem 37. The reducibility theory associated with any sets of terms is de-cidable.

And, as in the previous chapter, we have, as an immediate corollary:

Corollary 6. Ground reducibility is decidable.

4.5 Other Decidable Subclasses

Complexity issues and restricted classes. There are two classes of au-tomata with equality and disequality constraints for which tighter complexityresults are known:

• For the class of automata containing only disequality constraints, empti-ness can be decided in deterministic exponential time. For any termrewriting system R, the set of ground R-normal forms is still recogniz-able by an automaton of this subclass of reduction automata.

• For the class of deterministic reduction automata for which the constraints“cannot overlap”, emptiness can be decided in polynomial time.

Combination of AWCBB and reduction automata. If you relax thecondition on equality constraints in the transition rules of reduction automata soas to allow constraints between brothers, you obtain the biggest known subclassof AWEDC with a decidable emptiness problem.

Formally, these automata, called generalized reduction automata, aremembers of AWEDC such that there is an ordering on the states set such that,

for each rule f(q1, . . . , qn)π1=π2∧c−−−−−−→ q, q is a lower bound of q1, . . . , qn

and moreover, if |π1| > 1 or |π2| > 1, then q is strictly smaller thaneach qi.

The closure and decidability results for reduction automata may be trans-posed to generalized reduction automata, with though a longer proof for theemptiness decision. Generalized reduction automata can thus be used for thedecision of reducibility theory extended by some restricted sort declarations. Inthis extension, additionally to encompassment predicates ·£t, we allow a familyof unary sort predicates . ∈ S, where S is a sort symbol. But, sort declarationsare limited to atoms of the form t ∈ S where where non linear variables in tonly occur at brother positions. This fragment is decidable by an analog ofTheorem 37 for generalized reduction automata.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 131: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.6 Tree Automata with Arithmetic Constraints 131

4.6 Tree Automata with Arithmetic Constraints

Tree automata deal with finite trees which have a width bounded by the maxi-mal arity of the signature but there is no limitation on the depth of the trees.A natural idea is to relax the restriction on the width of terms by allowingfunction of variadic arity. This has been considered by several authors for ap-plications to graph theory, typing in object-oriented languages, temporal logicand automated deduction. In these applications, variadic functions are set ormultiset constructors in some sense, therefore they enjoy additional propertieslike associativity and/or commutativity and several types of tree automata havebeen designed for handling these properties. We describe here a class of treeautomata which recognize terms build with usual function symbols and multisetconstructors. Therefore, we deal not only with terms, but with so-called flatterms. Equality on these terms is no longer the syntactical identity, but it isextended by the equality of multisets under permutation of their elements. Torecognize sets of flat terms with automata, we shall use constrained rules wherethe constraints are Presburger’s arithmetic formulas which set conditions on themultiplicities of terms in multisets. These automata enjoy similar properties toNFTA and are used to test completeness of function definitions and inductivereducibility when associative-commutative functions are involved, provided thatsome syntactical restrictions hold.

4.6.1 Flat Trees

The set of function symbols G is composed of F , the set of function symbolsand of M, the set of function symbols for building multisets. For simplicity weshall assume that there is only one symbol of the latter form, denoted by t andwritten as an infix operator. The set of variables is denoted by X . Flat terms

are terms generated by the non-terminal T of the following grammar.

N ::= 1 | 2 | 3 . . .T ::= S |U (flat terms)S ::= x | f(T1, . . . , Tn) (flat terms of sort F)U ::= N1.S1 t . . . t Np.Sp (flat terms of sort t)

where x ∈ X , n ≥ 0 is the arity of f , p ≥ 1 and∑i=p

i=1 Ni ≥ 2. Moreover theinequality Si 6=P Sj holds for i 6= j, 1 ≤ i, j < n, where =P is defined as thesmallest congruence such that:

• x =P x,

• f(s1, . . . , sn) =P f(t1, . . . , tn) if f ∈ F and si =P ti for i = 1, . . . , n,

• n1.s1 t . . . t np.sp =P m1.t1 t . . . t mq.tq if p = q and there is somepermutation σ on 1, . . . , p such that si =P tσ(i) and ni = mσ(i) fori = 1, . . . , p.

Example 44. 3.a and 3.a t 2.f(x, b) are flat terms, but 2.a t 1.a t f(x, b) isnot since 2.a and 1.a must be grouped together to make 3.a.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 132: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

132 Automata with Constraints

The usual notions on terms can be generalized easily for flat terms. Werecall only what is needed in the following. A flat term is ground if it containsno variables. The root of a flat term is defined by

• for the flat terms of sort F , root(x) = x, root(f(t1, . . . , tn)) = f ,

• for the flat terms of sort t, root(s1 t . . . t sn) = t.

Our notion of subterm is slightly different from the usual one. We say thats is a subterm of t if and only if

• either s and t are identical,

• or t = f(s1, . . . , sn) and s is a subterm of some si,

• or t = n1.t1 t . . . t np.tp and s is a subterm of some ti.

For simplicity, we extend t to an operation between flat terms s, t denoting(any) flat term obtained by regrouping elements of sort F in s and t whichare equivalent modulo =P , leaving the other elements unchanged. For instances = 2.a t 1.f(a, a) and t = 3.b t 2.f(a, a) yields s t t = 2.a t 3.b t 3.f(a, a).

4.6.2 Automata with Arithmetic Constraints

There is some regularity in flat terms that is likely to be captured by some classof automata-like recognizers. For instance, the set of flat terms such that allinteger coefficients occurring in the terms are even, seems to be easily recogniz-able, since the predicate even(n) can be easily decided. The class of automatathat we describe now has been designed for accepting such sets of ground flatterms. A flat tree automaton with arithmetic constraints (NFTAC) overG is a tuple (QF , Qt,G, Qf ,∆) where

• QF ∪ Qt is a finite set of states, such that

– QF is the set of states of sort F ,

– Qt is the set of states of sort t,

– QF ∩ Qt = ∅,

• Qf ⊆ QF t Qt is the set of final states,

• ∆ is a set of rules of the form:

– f(q1, . . . , qn) → q, for n ≥ 0, f ∈ Fn, q1, . . . , qn ∈ QF ∪ Qt, andq ∈ QF ,

– N.qc(N)−→ q′, where q ∈ QF , q′ ∈ Qt, and c is a Presburger’s arith-

metic2 formula with the unique free variable N ,

– q1 t q2 → q3 where q1, q2, q3 ∈ Qt.

Moreover we require that

2Presburger’s arithmetic is first order arithmetic with addition and constants 0 and 1. Thisfragment of arithmetic is known to be decidable.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 133: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.6 Tree Automata with Arithmetic Constraints 133

– q1 t q2 → q3 is a rule of ∆ implies that q2 t q1 → q3 is also a rule of∆,

– q1 t (q2 t q3) → q4 is a rule of ∆ implies that (q1 t q2) t q3 → q4 isalso a rule of ∆ where q2tq3 (resp. q1tq2) denotes any state q′ suchthat there is a rule q2 t q3 → q′ (resp. q1 t q2 → q′).

These two conditions on ∆ will ensure that two flat terms equivalent modulo=P reach the same states.

Example 45. Let F = a, f and let A = (QF , Qt,G, Qf ,∆) where

QF = q, Qt = qt,

Qf = qu,

∆ =

a −→ q N.q

∃n:N=2n−→ qt

f( , ) −→ q qt t qt −→ qt

where stands for q or qt.

Let A = (QF , Qt,G, Qf ,∆) be a flat tree automaton. The move relation→A is defined by: let t, t′ ∈ T (F ∪ Q,X), then t→A t′ if and only if there is acontext C ∈ C(G ∪ Q) such that t = C[s] and t′ =P C[s′] where

• either there is some f(q1, . . . , qn) → q′ ∈ ∆ and s = f(q1, . . . , qn), s′ = q′,

• or there is some N.qc(N)−→ q′ ∈ ∆ and s = n.q with |= c(n), s′ = q′,

• or there is some q1 t q2 → q3 ∈ ∆ and s = q1 t q2, s′ = q3.

∗→A is the reflexive and transitive closure of →A.

Example 46. Using the automaton of the previous example, one has

2.a t 6.f(a, a) t 2.f(a, 2.a)∗

→A 2.q t 6.f(q, q) t 2.f(q, 2.q)∗

→A 2.q t 6.q t 2.f(q, qt)∗

→A 2.q t 6.q t 2.q∗

→A qt t qt t qt∗

→A qt t qt∗

→A qt

We define now semilinear flat languages. Let A = (QF , Qt,G, Qf ,∆) bea flat tree automaton. A ground flat term t is accepted by A, if there is someq ∈ Qf such that t

∗→A q. The flat tree language L(A) accepted by A is the

set of all ground flat terms accepted by A. A set of flat terms is semilinear ifthere L = L(A) for some NFTAC A. Two flat tree automata are equivalent ifthey recognize the same language.

Example 47. The language of terms accepted by the automaton of Example 45is the set of ground flat terms with root t such that for each subterm n1.s1 t. . . t np.sp we have that ni is an even number.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 134: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

134 Automata with Constraints

Flat tree automata are designed to take into account the =P relation, whichis stated by the next proposition.

Proposition 27. Let s, t, be two flat terms such that s =P t, let A be a flattree automaton, then s

∗→A q implies t

∗→A q.

Proof. The proof is by structural induction on s.

Proposition 28. Given a flat term t and a flat tree automaton A, it is decidablewhether t is accepted by A.

Proof. The decision algorithm for membership for flat tree automata is nearlythe same as the one for tree automata presented in Chapter 1, using an oraclefor the decision of Presburger’s arithmetic formulas.

Our definition of flat tree automata corresponds to nondeterministic flat treeautomata. We now define deterministic flat tree automata (DFTAC).

Let A = (QF , Qt,G, Qf ,∆) be a NFTAC over G.

• The automaton A is deterministic if for each ground flat term t, thereis at most one state q such that t

∗→A q.

• The automaton A is complete if for each ground flat term t, there a statesuch that t

∗→A q.

• A state q is accessible if there is one ground flat term t such that t∗

→A q.The automaton is reduced if all states are accessible.

4.6.3 Reducing Non-determinism

As for usual tree automata, there is an algorithm for computing an equivalentDFTAC from any NFTAC which proves that a language recognized by a NFTACis also recognized by a DFTAC. The algorithm is similar to the determiniza-tion algorithm of the class AWEDC: the ambiguity arising from overlappingconstraints is lifted by considering mutually exclusive constraints which coverthe original constraints, and using sets of states allows to get rid of the non-determinism of rules having the same left-hand side. Here, we simply have todistinguish between states of QF and states of Qt.

Determinization algorithm

input A = (QF , Qt,G, Qf ,∆) a NFTAC.

begin

A state [q] of the equivalent DFTAC is in 2QF ∪ 2Qt .

Set QdF = ∅, Qd

t = ∅, ∆d = ∅.

repeat

for each f of arity n, [q]1, . . . , [q]n ∈ QdF ∪ Qd

t do

let [q] = q | ∃f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆ with qi ∈ [q]i for i = 1, . . . , n

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 135: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.6 Tree Automata with Arithmetic Constraints 135

in Set QdF to Qd

F ∪ [q]Set ∆d to ∆d ∪ f([q]1, . . . , [q]n) → [q]

endfor

for each [q] ∈ QF do

for each [q′] ⊆ q′′ | ∃N.qc(N)−→ q′′ ∈ ∆ with q ∈ [q] do

let C be( ∧

q∈[q]

N.qci(N)−→ q′∈∆

q′∈[q′]

ci(N))∧

( ∧

q∈[q]

N.qci(N)−→ q′∈∆

q′ 6∈[q′]

¬ci(N))

in Set Qdt to Qd

F ∪ [q′]

Set ∆d to ∆d ∪ N.[q]C(N)−→ [q′]

endfor

endfor

for each [q]1, [q]2 ∈ Qdt do

let [q] = q | ∃q1 ∈ [q]1, q2 ∈ [q]2, q1 t q2 → q ∈ ∆

in Set Qdt to Qd

F ∪ [q]Set ∆d to ∆d ∪ [q]1 t [q]2 → [q]

endfor

until no rule can be added to ∆d

Set Qdf = [q] ∈ Qd

F ∪ Qdt | [q] ∩ Qf 6= ∅,

end

output: Ad = (QdF , Qd

t,F , Qdf ,∆d)

Proposition 29. The previous algorithm terminates and computes a determin-istic flat tree automaton equivalent to the initial one.

Proof. The termination is obvious. The proof of the correctness relies on thefollowing lemma:

Lemma 6. t∗

→Ad[q] if and only if t

∗→A q for all q ∈ [q].

The proof is by structural induction on t and follows the same pattern asthe proof for the class AWEDC.

Therefore we have proved the following theorem stating the equivalence be-tween DFTAC and NFTAC.

Theorem 38. Let L be a semilinear set of flat terms, then there exists a DFTACthat accepts L.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 136: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

136 Automata with Constraints

4.6.4 Closure Properties of Semilinear Flat Languages

Given an automaton A = (Q,G, Qf ,∆), it is easy to construct an equivalentcomplete automaton. If A is not complete then

• add two new trash states qt of sort F and qtt of sort t,

• for each f ∈ F , q1, . . . , qn ∈ Q∪qt, qtt , such that there is no rule having

f(q1, . . . , qn) as left-hand side, then add f(q1, . . . , qn) → qt,

• for each q of sort F , let c1(N), . . . , cm(N) be the conditions of the rules

N.qci(N)−→ q′,

– if the formula ∃N (c1(N) ∨ . . . ∨ cm(N)) is not equivalent to true,

then add the rule N.q¬(c1(N)∨...∨cm(N))(N)

−→ qtt ,

– if there are some q, q′ of sort t such that there is no rule qt q′ → q”,then add the rules q t q′ → qtt and q′ t q → qtt .

– if there is some rule (q1 t q2) t q3 → qtt (resp. q1 t (q2 t q3) → qtt ,add the rule q1 t (q2 t q3) → qtt (resp. (q1 t q2) t q3 → qtt ) if it ismissing.

This last step ensures that we build a flat tree automaton, and it is straight-forward to see that this automaton is equivalent to the initial one (same proofas for DFTA). This is stated by the following proposition.

Theorem 39. For each flat tree automaton A, there exists a complete equivalentautomaton B.

Example 48. The automaton of Example 45 is not complete. It can be

completed by adding the states qt, qtt , and the rules N.qt

N≥0−→ qtt

N.q∃n N=2n+1

−→ qttf( , ) −→ qt

where ( , ) stands for a pair of q, qt, qt, qtt such that if a rule the left hand side

of which is f( , ) is not already in ∆.

Theorem 40. The class of semilinear flat languages is closed under union.

Proof. Let L (resp. M) be a semilinear flat language recognized by A =(QF , Qt,G, Qf ,∆) (resp. B = (Q′

F , Q′t,G, Q′

f ,∆′)), then L ∪ M is recognizedby C = (QF ∪ Q′

F , Qt ∪ Q′t,G, Qf ∪ Q′

f ,∆ ∪ ∆′).

Theorem 41. The class of semilinear flat languages is closed under comple-mentation.

Proof. Let A be an automaton recognizing L. Compute a complete automatonB equivalent to A. Compute a deterministic automaton C equivalent to B usingthe determinization algorithm. The automaton C is still complete, and we get anautomaton recognizing the complement of L by exchanging final and non-finalstates in C.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 137: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.6 Tree Automata with Arithmetic Constraints 137

From the closure under union and complement, we get the closure underintersection (a direct construction of an automaton recognizing the intersectionalso exists).

Theorem 42. The class of semilinear flat languages is closed under intersec-tion.

4.6.5 Emptiness Decision

The last important property to state is that the emptiness of the languagerecognized by a flat tree automaton is decidable. The decision procedure relieson an algorithm similar to the decision procedure for tree automata combinedto a decision procedure for Presburger’s arithmetic. However a straightforwardmodification of the algorithm in Chapter 1 doesn’t work. Assume that theautomaton contains the rule qt1 t qt1 → qt2 and assume that there is some

flat term t such that 1.t∗

→A qt1 . These two hypothesis don’t imply that 1.t t

1.t∗

→A qt2 since 1.tt1.t is not a flat term, contrary to 2.t. Therefore the decisionprocedure involves some combinatorics in order to ensure that we always dealwith correct flat terms.

From now on, let A = (QF , Qt,G, Qf ,∆) be some given deterministic flattree automaton and let M be the number of states of sort t. First, we need tocontrol the possible infinite number of solutions of Presburger’s conditions.

Proposition 30. There is some computable B such that for each conditionc(N) of the rules of A, either each integer n validating c is smaller than B orthere are at least M + 1 integers smaller than B validating c.

Proof. First, for each constraint c(N) of a rule of ∆, we check if c(N) has afinite number of solutions by deciding if ∃P : c(N) ⇒ N < P is true. If c(N)has a finite number of solutions, it is easy to find a bound B1(c(N)) on thesesolutions by testing ∃n : n > k ∧ c(n) for k = 1, 2, . . . until it is false. If c(N)

has an infinite number of solutions, one computes the Mth solution obtained

by checking |= c(k) for k = 1, 2, . . .. We call this Mth solution B2(c(N)). Thebound B is the maximum of all the B1(c(N))’s and B2(c(N))’s.

Now we control the maximal width of terms needed to reach a state.

Proposition 31. For all t∗

→A q, there is some s∗

→A q such that for each sub-term of s of the form n1.v1 t . . . t np.vp, we have p ≤ M and ni ≤ B.

Proof. The bound on the coefficients ni is a direct consequence of the previousproposition. The proof on p is by structural induction on t. The only non-trivialcase is for t = m1.t1 t . . . t mk.tk. Let us assume that t is the term with thesmallest value of k among the terms t′ | t′

∗→A q.

First we show that k ≤ M . Let qti be the states such that ni.ti →A qti .

We have thus t∗

→A qt1 t . . . t qtk∗

→A q. By definition of DFTAC, the reduction

qt1 t . . . t qtk∗

→A q has the form:

qt1 t . . . t qtk∗→A

qt[12] t qt3 t . . . t qtk∗→A

. . .∗→A

qt[1...k] = q

for some states qt[12],. . . , qt[1...k] of Qt.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 138: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

138 Automata with Constraints

Assume that k > M . The pigeonhole principle yields that q[1,...,j1] = q[1,...,j2]

for some 1 ≤ j1 < j2 ≤ k. Therefore the term

t = m1.t1 t . . . t mj1 .tj1 t mj2+1.tj2+1 t . . . t mk.tk

also reaches the state q which contradicts our hypothesis that k is minimal.Now, it remains only to use the induction hypothesis to replace each ti by

some si reaching the same state and satisfying the required conditions.

A term s such that for all subterm n1.v1 t . . . np.vp of s, we have p ≤ M andni ≤ B will be called small. We define some extension →n

A of the move relationby:

• t→1A q if and only if t→A q,

• t→nA q if and only if t

∗→A q and

– either t = f(t1, . . . , tk) and for i = 1, . . . , k we have ti →n−1A qi(ti),

– or t = n1.t1 t . . . t np.tp and for i = 1, . . . , p, we have ti →n−1A qi(ti).

Let Lnq = t→p

A q | p ≤ n and t is small with the convention that L0q = ∅

and Lq =⋃∞

n=1 Lnq . By Proposition 31, t→A q if and only if there is some

s ∈ Lq such that s→A q. The emptiness decision algorithm will compute afinite approximation Rn

q of these Lnq such that Rn

q 6= ∅ if and only if Lnq 6= ∅.

Some technical definition is needed first. Let L be a set of flat term, thenwe define ‖ L ‖P as the number of distinct equivalence classes of terms for the=P relation such that one representant of the class occurs in L. The reader willcheck easily that the equivalence class of a flat term for the =P relation is finite.

The decision algorithm is the following one.

begin

for each state q do set R0q to ∅.

i=1.repeat

for each state q do set Riq to Ri−1

q

if ‖ Riq ‖P≤ M then

repeat

add to Riq all flat terms t = f(t1, . . . , tn)

such that tj ∈ Ri−1qj

, j ≤ n and f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆

add to Riq all flat terms t = n1.t1 t . . . t np.tp

such that p ≤ M ,nj ≤ B, tj ∈ Ri−1qj

and n1.q1 t . . . t np.qp∗

→A q.

until no new term can be added or ‖ Riq ‖P > M

endifi=i+1

until ∃q ∈ Qf such that Riq 6= ∅ or ∀q,Ri

q = Ri−1q

if ∃q ∈ QF s.t. Riq 6= ∅

then return not emptyelse return empty endif

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 139: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.6 Tree Automata with Arithmetic Constraints 139

end

Proposition 32. The algorithm terminates after n iterations for some n andRn

q = ∅ if and only if Lq = ∅

Proof. At every iteration, either one Riq increases or else all the Ri

q’s are leftuntouched in the repeat . . .until loop. Therefore the termination conditionwill be satisfied after a finite number of iterations, since equivalence classes for=P are finite.

By construction we have Rmq ⊆ Lm

q , but we need the following additionalproperty.

Lemma 7. For all m,Rmq = Lm

q or Rmq ⊆ Lm

q and ‖ Rmq ‖P > M

The proof is by induction on m.

Base case m = 0. Obvious from the definitions.

Induction step. We assume that the property is true for m and we prove thatit holds for m + 1.Either Lm

q = ∅ therefore Rmq = ∅ and we are done, or Lm

q 6= ∅, which we assumefrom now on.

• q ∈ QF .

– Either there is some rule f(q1, . . . , qn) → q such that Rmqi

6= ∅ forall i = 1, . . . , n and such that for some q′ among q1, . . . , qn, we have‖ Rm

q′ ‖P > M . Then we can construct at least M + 1 terms t =

f(t1, . . . , t′, . . . , tn) where t′ ∈ Rm

q′ , such that t ∈ Rm+1q by giving

M +1 non equivalent values to t′ (corresponding values for t are alsonon equivalent). This yields that ‖ Rm+1

q ‖P > M .

– Or there is no rule as above, therefore Rm+1q = Lm+1

q .

• q ∈ Qt.

For each small term t = n1.t1 t . . . t np.tp such that t ∈ Lm+1q , there

are some terms s1, . . . , sn in Rmqi

such that ti∗

→A qi implies that si∗

→A qi.What we must prove is that ‖ Rm

qi‖P > M for some i ≤ p implies ‖

Rm+1q ‖P > M . Since A is deterministic, we have that s

∗→A q and t

∗→A q′

with q 6= q′ implies that s 6=P t. Let S be the set of states occurring inthe sequence q1, . . . , qp. We prove by induction on the cardinal of S thatif there is some qi such that ‖ Rm

qi‖P > M , we can build at least M + 1

terms in Rm+1q otherwise we build at least one term of Rm+1

q .

Base case S = q′, and therefore all the qi are equal to q′. Either‖ Rm

q′ ‖P≤ M and we are done or ‖ Rmq′ ‖P > M and we know that there

are s1, . . . , sM+1, . . . pairwise non equivalent terms reaching q′. Therefore,there are at least

(M+1M

)≥ M + 1 different non equivalent possible terms

ni1 .si1 t . . . t nip.sip

. Moreover each of these terms S satisfies s→m+1A q,

which proves the result.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 140: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

140 Automata with Constraints

Induction step. Let S = S′ ∪ q′ where the property is true for S′. Wecan assume that ‖ Rm

q′ ‖P≤ M (otherwise all ‖ Rmqi

‖P are less than orequal to M ).

Let i1, . . . , ik be the positions of q′ in q1, . . . , qp, let j1, . . . , jl be the posi-tions of the states different from q′ in q1, . . . , qp. By induction hypothesis,there are some flat terms sj such that nj1 .sj1 t . . . t njl

.sjlis a valid flat

term. Since A is deterministic and q′ is different from all element of S′,we know that si 6=P sj for any i ∈ i1, . . . , ik, j ∈ j1, . . . , jk. There-fore, we use the same reasoning as in the previous case to build at leastCk

M+1 ≥ M + 1 pairwise non equivalent flat terms s = n1.s1 t . . . t np.sp

such that s→m+1A q.

The termination of the algorithm implies that for each m ≥ n, Rmq = Lm

q orRm

q ⊆ Lmq and ‖ Rm

q ‖P > M . Therefore Lq = ∅ if and only if Rnq = ∅.

The following theorem summarizes the previous results.

Theorem 43. Let A be a DFTAC, then it is decidable whether the languageaccepted by A is empty or not.

The reader should see that the property that A deterministic is crucial inproving the emptiness decision property. Therefore proving the emptiness of thelanguage recognized by a NFTAC implies to compute an equivalent DFTACfirst.

Another point is that the previous algorithm can be easily modified to com-pute the set of accessible states of A.

4.7 Exercises

Exercise 52.

1. Show that the automaton A+ of Example 38 accepts only terms of the formf(t1, s

n(0), sm(0), sn+m(0))

2. Conversely, show that, for every pair of natural numbers (n, m), there exists aterm t1 such that f(t1, s

n(0), sm(0), sn+m(0)) is accepted by A+.

3. Construct an automaton A× of the class AWEDC which has the same propertiesas above, replacing + with ×

4. Give a proof that emptiness is undecidable for the class AWEDC, reducingHilbert’s tenth problem.

Exercise 53. Give an automaton of the class AWCBB which accepts the set of terms

t (over the alphabet a(0), b(0), f(2)) having a subterm of the form f(u, u). (i.e the

set of terms that are reducible by a rule f(x, x) → v).

Exercise 54. Show that the class AWCBB is not closed under linear tree homomor-

phisms. Is it closed under inverse image of such morphisms ?

Exercise 55. Give an example of two automata in AWCBB such that the set of pairs

of terms recognized respectively by the automata is not itself a member of AWCBB.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 141: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.7 Exercises 141

Exercise 56. (Proposition 24) Show that the class of (languages recognized by)

reduction automata is closed under intersection and union. Show that the set of bal-

anced term on alphabet a, f is not recognizable by a reduction automaton, showing

that the class of languages recognized by) reduction automata is not closed under

complement.

Exercise 57. Show that the class of languages recognized by reduction automata is

preserved under linear tree homomorphisms. Show however that this is no longer true

for arbitrary tree homomorphisms.

Exercise 58. Let A be a reduction automaton. We define a ternary relation qw−→ q′

contained in Q × N∗ × Q as follows:

• for i ∈ N, qi−→ q′ if and only if there is a rule f(q1, . . . , qn)

c−→A

q′ with qi = q

• qi·w−−→ q′ if and only if there is a state q′′ such that q

i−→ q′′ and q′′

w−→ q′.

Moreover, we say that a state q ∈ Q is a constrained state if there is a rule f(q1, . . . , qn)c−→A

q

in A such that c is not a valid constraint.We say that the the constraints of A cannot overlap if, for each rule f(q1, . . . , qn)

c−→ q

and for each equality (resp. disequality) π = π′ of c, there is no strict prefix p of π

and no constrained state q′ such that q′p−→ q.

1. Consider the rewrite system on the alphabet f(2), g(1), a(0) whose left mem-bers are f(x, g(x)), g(g(x)), f(a, a). Compute a reduction automaton, whoseconstraints do not overlap and which accepts the set of irreducible ground terms.

2. Show that emptiness can be decided in polynomial time for reduction automatawhose constraints do not overlap. (Hint: it is similar to the proof of Theorem33.)

3. Show that any language recognized by a reduction automaton whose constraintsdo not overlap is an homomorphic image of a language in the class AWCBB.Give an example showing that the converse is false.

Exercise 59. Prove the Proposition ?? along the lines of Proposition 15.

Exercise 60. The purpose of this exercise is to give a construction of an automatonwith disequality constraints (no equality constraints) whose emptiness is equivalent tothe ground reducibility of a given term t with respect to a given term rewriting systemR.

1. Give a direct construction of an automaton with disequality constraints ANF(R)

which accepts the set of irreducible ground terms

2. Show that the class of languages recognized by automata with disequality con-straints is closed under intersection. Hence the set of irreducible ground in-stances of a linear term is recognized by an automaton with disequality con-straints.

3. Let ANF(R) = (QNF,F , QfNF, ∆NF). We compute ANF,t

def= (QNF,t,F , Qf

NF,t, ∆NF,t)as follows:

• QNF,tdef= tσ|p | p ∈ Pos(t)×QNF where σ ranges over substitutions from

NLV (t) (the set of variables occurring at least twice in t) into QfNF.

• For all f(q1, . . . , qn)c−→ q ∈ ∆NF, and all u1, . . . , un ∈ tσ|p | p ∈ Pos(t),

∆NF,t contains the following rules:

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 142: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

142 Automata with Constraints

– f([qu1 , q1], . . . , [qun , qn])c∧c′

−−−→ [qf(u1,...,un), q] if f(u1, . . . , un) = tσ0

and c′ is constructed as sketched below.

– f([qu1 , q1], . . . , [qun , qn])c−→ [qf(u1,...,un), q] if [qf(u1,...,un), q] ∈ QNF,t

and we are not in the first case.

– f([qu1 , q1], . . . , [qun , qn])c−→ [qq, q] in all other cases

c′ is constructed as follows. From f(u1, . . . , un) we can retrieve the rules appliedat position p in t. Assume that the rule at p checks π1 6= π2. This amounts tocheck pπ1 6= pπ2 at the root position of t. Let D be all disequalities pπ1 6= pπ2

obtained in this way. The non linearity of t implies some equalities: let E bethe set of equalities p1 = p2, for all positions p1, p2 such that t|p1 = t|p2 is avariable. Now, c′ is the set of disequalities π 6= π′ which are not in D and thatcan be inferred from D, E using the rules

pp1 6= p2, p = p′ ` p′p1 6= p2

p 6= p′, pp1 = p2 ` p′p1 6= p2

For instance, let t = f(x, f(x, y)) and assume that the automaton ANF con-

tains a rule f(q, q)1 6=2−−→ q. Then the automaton ANF,t will contain the rule

f([qq, q], [qf(q,q), q])1 6=2∧1 6=22−−−−−−−→ q.

The final states are [qu, qf ] where qf ∈ QfNF and u is an instance of t.

Prove that ANF,t accepts at least one term if and only if t is not ground reducibleby R.

Exercise 61. Prove Theorem 37 along the lines of the proof of Theorem 27.

Exercise 62. Show that the algorithm for deciding emptiness of deterministic com-

plete flat tree automaton works for non-deterministic flat tree automata such that for

each state q the number of non-equivalent terms reaching q is 0 or greater than or

equal to 2.

Exercise 63. (Feature tree automata)Let F be a finite set of feature symbols (or attributes) denoted by f, g, . . . and S bea set of constructor symbols (or sorts) denoted by A, B, . . .. In this exercise and thenext one, a tree is a rooted directed acyclic graph, a multitree is a tree such that thenodes are labeled over S and the edges over F . A multitree is either (A, ∅) or (A, E)where E is a finite multiset of pairs (f, t) with f a feature and t a multitree. A featuretree is a multitree such that the edges outgoing from the same node are labeled bydifferent features. The + operation takes a multitree t = (A, E), a feature f and amultitree t′ to build the multitree (A, E ∪ (f, t′)) denoted by t + ft′.

1. Show that t + f1t1 + f2t2 = t + f2t2 + f1t1 (OI axiom: order independenceaxiom) and that the algebra of multitrees is isomorphic to the quotient of thefree term algebra over + ∪ F ∪ S by OI.

2. A deterministic M-automaton is a triple (A, h, Qf ) where A is an finite + ∪F ∪S-algebra, h : M → A is a homomorphism, Qf (the final states) is a subsetof the set of the values of sort M. A tree is accepted if and only if h(t) ∈ Qf .

(a) Show that a M-automaton can be identified with a bottom-up tree au-tomaton such that all trees equivalent under OI reach the same states.

(b) A feature tree automaton is a M-automaton such that for each sort s (Mor F), for each q the set of the c’s of arity 0 interpreted as q in A is finiteor co-finite. Give a feature tree to recognize the set of natural numberswhere n is encoded as (0, suc, (0, . . . , (0, ∅))) with n edges labeled bysuc.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 143: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

4.8 Bibliographic notes 143

(c) Show that the class of languages accepted by feature tree automata isclosed under boolean operations and that the emptiness of a languageaccepted by a feature automaton is decidable.

(d) A non-deterministic feature tree automaton is a tuple (Q, P, h, Qf ) suchthat Q is the set of states of sort M, P the set of states of sort F , h iscomposed of three functions h1 : S → 2Q, h2 : F → 2P and the transitionfunction + : Q×P ×Q → 2Q. Moreover q + p1q1 + p2q2 = q + p2q2 + p1q1

for each q, q1, q2, p1, p2, s ∈ S | p ∈ h1(s) and f ∈ F | p ∈ h2(f) arefinite or co-finite for each p. Show that any non-deterministic feature treeautomaton is equivalent to a deterministic feature tree automaton.

Exercise 64. (Characterization of recognizable flat feature languages)A flat feature tree is a feature tree of depth 1 where depth is defined by depth((A, ∅)) =0 and depth((A, E)) = 1+maxdepth(t) | (f, t) ∈ E. Counting constraints are definedby: C(x) ::= card(ϕ ∈ F | ∃y.(xϕy) ∧ Ty) = n mod m

| Sx| C(x) ∨ C(x)| C(x) ∧ C(x)

where n, m are integers, S and T finite or co-finite subsets of S, F a finite or co-finitesubset of F and n mod 0 is defined as n. The semantics of the first type of constraintis: C(x) holds if the number of edges of x going from the root to a node labeled by asymbol of T is equal to n mod m. The semantics of Sx is: Sx holds if the root of x islabeled by a symbol of S.

1. Show that the constraints are closed under negation. Show that the followingconstraints can be expressed in the constraint language (F is a finite subset ofF , f ∈ F , A ∈ S): there is one edge labeled f from the root, a given finitesubset of F . There is no edge labeled f from the root, the root is labeled by A.

2. A set L of flat multitrees is counting definable if and only if there some countingconstraint C such that L = x | C(x) holds. Show that a set of flat feature treesis counting definable if and only if it is recognizable by a feature tree automaton.hint: identify flat trees with multisets over (F ∪root)×S and + with multisetunion.

4.8 Bibliographic notes

RATEG appeared in Mongy’s thesis [Mon81]. Unfortunately, as shown in[Mon81] the emptiness problem is undecidable for the class RATEG (and hencefor AWEDC). The undecidability can be even shown for a more restricted classof automata with equality tests between cousins (see [Tom92]).The remarkable subclass AWCBB is defined in [BT92]. This paper presents theresults cited in Section 4.3, especially Theorem 33.Concerning complexity, the result used in Section 4.3.2 (EXPTIME-completenessof the emptiness of the intersection of n recognizable tree languages) may befound in [FSVY91, Sei94b].[DCC95] is concerned with reduction automata and their use as a tool for thedecision of the encompassment theory in the general case.The first decidability proof for ground reducibility is due to [Pla85]. In [CJ97a],ground reducibility decision is shown EXPTIME-complete. In this work, anEXPTIME algorithm for emptiness decision for AWEDC with only disequalityconstrained The result mentioned in Section 4.5.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 144: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

144 Automata with Constraints

The class of generalized reduction automata is introduced in [CCC+94]. In thispaper, a efficient cleaning algorithm is given for emptiness decision.

There have been many work dealing with automata where the width ofterms is not bounded. In [Cou89], Courcelle devises an algebraic notion of rec-ognizability and studies the case of equational theories. Then he gives severalequational theories corresponding to several notions of trees like ordered or un-ordered, ranked or unranked trees and provides the tree automata to acceptthese objects. Actually the axioms used for defining these notions are commu-tativity (for unordered) or associativity (for unranked) and what is needed is tobuild tree automata such that all element of the same equivalence class reachthe same state. Trees can be also defined as finite, acyclic rooted ordered graphsof bounded degree. Courcelle [Cou92] has devised a notion of recognizable set ofgraphs and suggests to devise graph automata for accepting recognizable graphsof bounded tree width. He gives such automata for trees defined as unbounded,unordered, undirected, unrooted trees (therefore these are not what we call treein this book). Actually, he shows that recognizable sets of graphs are (homomor-phic image of) sets of equivalence class of terms, where the equivalence relationis the congruence induced by a set of equational axioms including associativity-commutativity axiom and identity element. He gives several equivalent notionsfor recognizability from which he gets the definitions of automata for acceptingrecognizable languages. Hedge automata [PQ68, Mur00, BKMW01] are au-tomata that deal with unranked but ordered terms, and use constraint whichare membership to some regular word expressions on an alphabet which is theset of states of the automaton. These automata are closed under the booleanoperations and emptiness can be decided. Such automata are used for XMLapplications. Generalization of tree automata with Presburger’s constraints canbe found in [LD02].

Feature tree are a generalization of first-order trees introduced for modelingrecord structures. A feature tree is a finite tree whose nodes are labelled byconstructor symbols and edges are labelled by feature symbols Niehren andPodelski [NP93] have studied the algebraic structures of feature trees and havedevised feature tree automata for recognizing sets of feature trees. They haveshown that this class of feature trees enjoys the same properties as regular treelanguage and they give a characterization of these sets by requiring that thenumbern of occurrences of a feature f satisfies a Presburger formula ψf (N).See Exercise 63 for more details. Equational tree automata, introduced byH.Ohsaki, allow equational axioms to take place during a run. For instance usingAC axioms allows to recognize languages which are closed under associativity-commutativity which is not the case of ordinary regular languages. See [Ohs01]for details.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 145: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Chapter 5

Tree Set Automata

This chapter introduces a class of automata for sets of terms called General-ized Tree Set Automata. Languages associated with such automata are sets ofsets of terms. The class of languages recognized by Generalized Tree Set Au-tomata fulfills properties that suffices to build automata-based procedures forsolving problems involving sets of terms, for instance, for solving systems of setconstraints.

5.1 Introduction

“The notion of type expresses the fact that one just cannot apply any operatorto any value. Inferring and checking a program’s type is then a proof of partialcorrection” quoting Marie-Claude Gaudel. “The main problem in this field is tobe flexible while remaining rigorous, that is to allow polymorphism (a value canhave more than one type) in order to avoid repetitions and write very generalprograms while preserving decidability of their correction with respect to types.”

On that score, the set constraints formalism is a compromise between powerof expression and decidability. This has been the object of active research for afew years.

Set constraints are relations between sets of terms. For instance, let us definethe natural numbers with 0 and the successor relation denoted by s. Thus, theconstraint

Nat = 0 ∪ s(Nat) (5.1)

corresponds to this definition. Let us consider the following system:

Nat = 0 ∪ s(Nat)List = cons(Nat, List) ∪ nil

List+ ⊆ List

car(List+) ⊆ s(Nat)

(5.2)

The first constraint defines natural numbers. The second constraint codes theset of LISP-like lists of natural numbers. The empty list is nil and other listsare obtained using the constructor symbol cons. The last two constraints rep-resent the set of lists with a non zero first element. Symbol car has the usualinterpretation: the head of a list. Here car(List+) can be interpreted as the set

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 146: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

146 Tree Set Automata

of all terms at first position in List+, that is all terms t such that there exists uwith cons(t, u) ∈ List+. In the set constraint framework such an operator car isoften written cons

−11 .

Set constraints are the essence of Set Based Analysis. The basic idea is toreason about program variables as sets of possible values. Set Based Analy-sis involves first writing set constraints expressing relationships between sets ofprogram values, and then solving the system of set constraints. A single approxi-mation is: all dependencies between the values of program variables are ignored.Techniques developed for Set Based Analysis have been successfully applied inprogram analysis and type inference and the technique can be combined withothers [HJ92].

Set constraints have also been used to define a constraint logic programminglanguage over sets of ground terms that generalizes ordinary logic programmingover an Herbrand domain [Koz98].

In a more general way, a system of set constraints is a conjunction of positiveconstraints of the form exp ⊆ exp′1 and negative constraints of the form exp 6⊆exp′. Right hand side and left hand side of these inequalities are set expressions,which are built with

• function symbols: in our example 0, s, cons, nil are function symbols.

• operators: union ∪, intersection ∩, complement ∼

• projection symbols: for instance, in the last equation of system (5.2) car

denotes the first component of cons. In the set constraints syntax, this iswritten cons

−1(1).

• set variables like Nat or List.

An interpretation assigns to each set variable a set of terms only built withfunction symbols. A solution is an interpretation which satisfies the system.For example, 0, s(0), s(s(0)), . . . is a solution of Equation (5.1).

In the set constraint formalism, set inclusion and set union express in anatural way parametric polymorphism: List ⊆ nil ∪ cons(X, List).

In logic or functional programming, one often use dynamic procedures todeal with type. In other words, a run-time procedure checks whether or not anexpression is well-typed. This permits maximum programming flexibility at thepotential cost of efficiency and security. Static analysis partially avoids thesedrawbacks with the help of type inference and type checking procedures. Theinformation extracted at compile time is also used for optimization.

Basically, program sources are analyzed at compile time and an ad hoc for-malism is used to represent the result of the analysis. For types considered assets of values, the set constraints formalism is well suited to represent them andto express their relations. Numerous inference and type checking algorithms inlogic, functional and imperative programming are based on a resolution proce-dure for set constraints.

1exp = exp′ for exp ⊆ exp′ ∧ exp′ ⊆ exp.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 147: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.1 Introduction 147

Most of the earliest algorithms consider systems of set constraints with weakpower of expression. More often than not, these set constraints always have aleast solution — w.r.t. inclusion — which corresponds to a (tuple of) regularset of terms. In this case, types are usual sorts. A sort signature defines atree automaton (see Section 3.4.1 for the correspondence between automataand sorts). For instance, regular equations iontroduced in Section 2.3 such asubclass of set constraints. Therefore, these methods are closely related finitetree automata and use classical algorithms on these recognizers, like the onespresented in Chapter 1.

In order to obtain a more precise information with set constraints in staticanalysis, one way is to enrich the set constraints vocabulary. In one hand, witha large vocabulary an analysis can be accurate and relevant, but on the otherhand, solutions are difficult to obtain.

Nonetheless, an essential property must be preserved: the decidability ofsatisfiability. There must exists a procedure which determines whether or not asystem of set constraints has solutions. In other words, extracted informationmust be sufficient to say whether the objects of an analyzed program have a type.It is crucial, therefore, to know which classes of set constraints are decidable,and identifying the complexity of set constraints is of paramount importance.

A second important characteristic to preserve is to represent solutions in aconvenient way. We want to obtain a kind of solved form from which one candecide whether a system has solutions and one can “compute” them.

In this chapter, we present an automata-based algorithm for solving systemsof positive and negative set constraints where no projection symbols occurs. Wedefine a new class of automata recognizing sets of (codes of) n-tuples of treelanguages. Given a system of set constraints, there exists an automaton of thisclass which recognizes the set of solutions of the system. Therefore propertiesof our class of automata directly translate to set constraints.

In order to introduce our automata, we discuss the case of unary symbols,i.e. the case of strings over finite alphabet. For instance, let us consider thefollowing constraints over the alphabet composed of two unary symbols a andb and a constant 0:

Xaa ∪ Xbb ⊆ X (5.3)

Y ⊆ X

This system of set constraints can be encoded in a formula of the monadicsecond order theory of 2 successors named a and b:

∀u (u ∈ X ⇒ (uaa ∈ X ∧ ubb ∈ X))∧

∀u u ∈ Y ⇒ u ∈ X

We have depicted in Fig 5.1 (a beginning of) an infinite tree which is amodel of the formula. Each node corresponds to a string over a and b. Theroot is associated with the empty string; going down to the left concatenates aa; going down to the right concatenates a b. Each node of the tree is labelledwith a couple of points. The two components correspond to sets X and Y . A

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 148: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

148 Tree Set Automata

black point in the first component means that the current node belongs to X.Conversely, a white point in the first component means that the current nodedoes not belong to X. Here we have X = ε, aa, bb, . . . and Y = ε, bb, . . . .

Figure 5.1: An infinite tree for the representation of a couple of word languages(X,Y ). Each node is associated with a word. A black dot stands for belongsto. X = ε, aa, bb, . . . and Y = ε, bb, . . . .

A tree language that encodes solutions of Eq. 5.3 is Rabin-recognizable bya tree automaton which must avoid the three forbidden patterns depicted inFigure 5.2.

•?

??

?

•?

??

?

Figure 5.2: The set of three forbidden patterns. ’?’ stands for black or whitedot. The tree depicted in Fig. 5.1 exclude these three patterns.

Given a ranked alphabet of unary symbols and one constant and a systemof set constraints over X1, . . . ,Xn, one can encode a solution with a 0, 1n-valued infinite tree and the set of solutions is recognized by an infinite treeautomaton. Therefore, decidability of satisfiability of systems of set constraintscan easily be derived from Rabin’s Tree Theorem [Rab69] because infinite treeautomata can be considered as an acceptor model for n-tuples of word languagesover finite alphabet2.

We extend this method to set constraints with symbols of arbitrary arity.Therefore, we define an acceptor model for mappings from T (F), where F is aranked alphabet, into a set E = 0, 1n of labels. Our automata can be viewedas an extension of infinite tree automata, but we will use weaker acceptancecondition. The acceptance condition is: the range of a successful run is in aspecified set of accepting set of states. We will prove that we can design an

2The entire class of Rabin’s tree languages is not captured by solutions of set of wordsconstraints. Set of words constraints define a class of languages which is strictly smaller thanBuchi recognizable tree languages.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 149: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.1 Introduction 149

automaton which recognizes the set of solutions of a system of both positiveand negative set constraints. For instance, let us consider the following system:

Y 6⊆ ⊥ (5.4)

X ⊆ f(Y,∼ X) ∪ a (5.5)

where ⊥ stands for the empty set and ∼ stands for the complement symbol.The underlying structure is different than in the previous example since it is

now the whole set of terms on the alphabet composed of a binary symbol f anda constant a. Having a representation of this structure in mind is not trivial.One can imagine a directed graph whose vertices are terms and such that thereexists an edge between each couple of terms in the direct subterm relation (seefigure 5.3).

f(f(a,a),a) f(a,f(a,a))

f(a,a)

f

f f

a

f

f(f(f(a,a),a),a) ... ... ...

Figure 5.3: The (beginning of the) underlying structure for a two letter alphabetf(, ), a.

An automaton have to associate a state with each node following a finite setof rules. In the case of the example above, states are also couples of • or .

Each vertex is of infinite out-degree, nonetheless one can define as in theword case forbidden patterns for incoming vertices which such an automatonhave to avoid in order to satisfy Eq. (5.5) (see Fig. 5.4, Pattern ? stands for or •). The acceptance condition is illustrated using Eq. (5.4). Indeed, todescribe a solution of the system of set constraints, the pattern ?• must occursomewhere in a successful “run” of the automaton.

?

f

???

?

??

f

?

Figure 5.4: Forbidden patterns for (5.5).

Consequently, decidability of systems of set constraints is a consequence ofdecidability of emptiness in our class of automata. Emptiness decidability is

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 150: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

150 Tree Set Automata

easy for automata without acceptance conditions (it corresponds to the case ofpositive set constraints only). The proof is more difficult and technical in thegeneral case and is not presented here. Moreover, and this is the main advantageof an automaton-based method, properties of recognizable sets directly translateto sets of solutions of systems of set constraints. Therefore, we are able to provenice properties. For instance, we can prove that a non empty set of solutionsalways contain a regular solution. Moreover we can prove the decidability ofexistence of finite solutions.

5.2 Definitions and Examples

Infinite tree automata are an acceptor model for infinite trees, i.e. for mappingsfrom A∗ into E where A is a finite alphabet and E is a finite set of labels. Wedefine and study F-generalized tree set automata which are an acceptor modelfor mappings from T (F) into E where F is a finite ranked alphabet and E is afinite set of labels.

5.2.1 Generalized Tree Sets

Let F be a ranked alphabet and E be a finite set. An E-valued F-generalized

tree set g is a mapping from T (F) into E. We denote by GE the set of E-valuedF-generalized tree sets.

For the sake of brevity, we do not mention the signature F which strictlyspeaking is in order in generalized tree sets. We also use the abbreviation GTSfor generalized tree sets.

Throughout the chapter, if c ∈ 0, 1n, then ci denotes the ith componentof the tuple c. If we consider the set E = 0, 1n for some n, a generalized treeset g in G0,1n can be considered as a n-tuple (L1, . . . , Ln) of tree languagesover the ranked alphabet F where Li = t ∈ T (F) | g(t)i = 1.

We will need in the chapter the following operations on generalized tree sets.Let g (resp. g′) be a generalized tree set in GE (resp. GE′). The generalizedtree set g ↑ g′ ∈ GE×E′ is defined by g ↑ g′(t) = (g(t), g′(t)), for each term tin T (F). Conversely let g be a generalized tree set in GE×E′ and consider theprojection π from E × E′ into the E-component then π(g) is the generalizedtree set in GE defined by π(g)(t) = π(g(t)). Let G ⊆ GE×E′ and G′ ⊆ GE , thenπ(G) = π(g) | g ∈ G and π−1(G′) = g ∈ GE×E′ | π(g) ∈ G′.

5.2.2 Tree Set Automata

A generalized tree set automaton A = (Q,∆,Ω) (GTSA) over a finite setE consist of a finite state set Q, a transition relation ∆ ⊆

⋃p Qp ×Fp ×E ×Q

and a set Ω ⊆ 2Q of accepting sets of states.A run of A (or A-run) on a generalized tree set g ∈ GE is a mapping

r : T (F) → Q with :

(r(t1), . . . , r(tp), f, g(f(t1, . . . , tp)), r(f(t1, . . . , tp))) ∈ ∆

for t1, . . . , tp ∈ T (F) and f ∈ Fp. The run r is successful if the range of r isin Ω i.e. r(T (F)) ∈ Ω.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 151: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.2 Definitions and Examples 151

A generalized tree set g ∈ GE is accepted by the automaton A if some runr of A on g is successful. We denote by L(A) the set of E-valued generalizedtree sets accepted by a generalized tree set automaton A over E. A set G ⊆ GE

is recognizable if G = L(A) for some generalized tree set automaton A.

In the following, a rule (q1, . . . , qp, f, l, q) is also denoted by f(q1, . . . , qp) l→ q.

Consider a term t = f(t1, . . . , tp) and a rule f(q1, . . . , qp) l→ q, this rule can

be applied in a run r on a generalized tree set g for the term t if r(t1) =q1,. . . ,r(tp) = qp, t is labeled by l, i.e. g(t) = l. If the rule is applied, thenr(t) = q.

A generalized tree set automaton A = (Q,∆,Ω) over E is

• deterministic if for each tuple (q1, . . . , qp, f, l) ∈ Qp ×Fp ×E there is atmost one state q ∈ Q such that (q1, . . . , qp, f, l, q) ∈ ∆.

• strongly deterministic if for each tuple (q1, . . . , qp, f) ∈ Qp ×Fp thereis at most one pair (l, q) ∈ E × Q such that (q1, . . . , qp, f, l, q) ∈ ∆.

• complete if for each tuple (q1, . . . , qp, f, l) ∈ Qp ×Fp ×E there is at leastone state q ∈ Q such that (q1, . . . , qp, f, l, q) ∈ ∆.

• simple if Ω is “subset-closed”, that is ω ∈ Ω ⇒ (∀ω′ ⊆ ω ω′ ∈ Ω).

Successfulness for simple automata just implies some states are not assumedalong a run. For instance, if the accepting set of a GTSA A is Ω = 2Q then A issimple and any run is successful. But, if Ω = Q, then A is not simple and eachstate must be assumed at least once in a successful run. The definition of simpleautomata will be clearer with the relationships with set constraints and theemptiness property (see Section 5.4). Briefly, positive set constraints are relatedto simple GTSA for which the proof of emptiness decision is straightforward.Another and equivalent definition for simple GTSA relies on the acceptancecondition : a run r is successful if and only if r(T (F)) ⊆ ω ∈ Ω.

There is in general an infinite number of runs — and hence an infinitenumber of GTS recognized — even in the case of deterministic generalized treeset automata (see example 49.2). Nonetheless, given a GTS g, there is at mostone run on g for a deterministic generalized tree set automata. But, in the caseof strongly deterministic generalized tree set automata, there is at most one run(see example 49.1) and therefore there is at most one GTS recognized.

Example 49.Ex. 49.1 Let E = 0, 1, F = cons(, ), s(), nil, 0. Let A = (Q,∆,Ω) be

defined by Q = Nat, List,Term, Ω = 2Q, and ∆ is the following set ofrules:

0 0→Nat ; s(Nat) 0

→Nat ; nil 1→ List ;

cons(Nat, List) 1→ List ;

cons(q, q′) 0→Term ∀(q, q′) 6= (Nat, List) ;

s(q) 0→Term ∀q 6= Nat .

A is strongly deterministic, simple, and not complete. L(A) is a singletonset. Indeed, there is a unique run r on a unique generalized tree set g ∈G0,1n . The run r maps every natural number on state Nat, every list on

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 152: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

152 Tree Set Automata

state List and the other terms on state Term. Therefore g maps a naturalnumber on 0, a list on 1 and the other terms on 0. Hence, we say that L(A)is the regular tree language L of Lisp-like lists of natural numbers.

Ex. 49.2 Let E = 0, 1, F = cons(, ), s(), nil, 0, and let A′ = (Q′,∆′,Ω′)be defined by Q′ = Q, Ω′ = Ω, and

∆′ = ∆ ∪ cons(Nat, List) 0→ List, nil 0

→ List.

A′ is deterministic (but not strongly), simple, and not complete, and L(A′)is the set of all subsets of the regular tree language L of Lisp-like lists ofnatural numbers. Indeed, successful runs can now be defined on generalizedtree sets g such that a term in L is labeled by 0 or 1.

Ex. 49.3 Let E = 0, 12, F = cons(, ), s(), nil, 0, and let A = (Q,∆,Ω)be defined by Q = Nat,Nat

′, List,Term, Ω = 2Q, and ∆ is the followingset of rules:

0 (0,0)→ Nat ; 0 (1,0)

→ Nat′ ; s(Nat) (0,0)

→ Nat

s(Nat) (1,0)→ Nat

′ ; s(Nat′) (0,0)

→ Nat ; s(Nat′) (1,0)

→ Nat′

nil(0,1)→ List ; cons(Nat

′, List) (0,1)→ List ;

s(q) (0,0)→ Term ∀q 6= Nat

cons(q, q′) (0,0)→ Term ∀(q, q′) 6= (Nat

′, List)

A is deterministic, simple, and not complete, and L(A) is the set of 2-tuplesof tree languages (N ′, L′) where N ′ is a subset of the regular tree languageof natural numbers and L′ is the set of Lisp-like lists of natural numbersover N ′.

Let us remark that the set N ′ may be non-regular. For instance, one candefine a run on a characteristic generalized tree set gp of Lisp-like lists ofprime numbers. The generalized tree set gp is such that gp(t) = (1, 0) whent is a (code of a) prime number.

In the previous examples, we only consider simple generalized tree set au-tomata. Moreover all runs are successful runs. The following examples arenon-simple generalized tree set automata in order to make clear the interest ofacceptance conditions. For this, compare the sets of generalized tree sets ob-tained in examples 49.3 and 50 and note that with acceptance conditions, wecan express that a set is non empty.

Example 50. Example 49.3 continuedLet E = 0, 12, F = cons(, ), nil, s(), 0, and let A′ = (Q′,∆′,Ω′) be

defined by Q′ = Q, ∆′ = ∆, and Ω′ = ω ∈ 2Q | Nat′ ∈ ω. A′ is deterministic,

not simple, and not complete, and L(A′) is the set of 2-tuples of tree languages(N ′, L′) where N ′ is a subset of the regular tree language of natural numbersand L′ is the set of Lisp-like lists of natural numbers over N ′, and N ′ 6= ∅.Indeed, for a successful r on g, there must be a term t such that r(t) = Nat

therefore, there must be a term t labelled by (1, 0), henceforth N ′ 6= ∅.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 153: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.2 Definitions and Examples 153

5.2.3 Hierarchy of GTSA-recognizable Languages

Let us define:

• RGTS, the class of languages recognizable by GTSA,

• RDGTS, the class of languages recognizable by deterministic GTSA,

• RSGTS, the class of languages recognizable by Simple GTSA.

The three classes defined above are proved to be different. They are alsoclosely related to classes of languages defined from the set constraint theorypoint of view.

RGTS

RDGTS

RSGTS

Figure 5.5: Classes of GTSA-recognizable languages

Classes of GTSA-recognizable languages have also different closure prop-erties. We will prove in Section 5.3.1 that RSGTS and the entire class RGTS

are closed under union, intersection, projection and cylindrification; RDGTS isclosed under complementation and intersection.

We propose three examples that illustrate the differences between the threeclasses. First, RDGTS is not a subset of RSGTS.

Example 51. Let E = 0, 1, F = f, a where a is a constant and f is unary.Let us consider the deterministic but non-simple GTSA A1 = (q0, q1,∆1,Ω1)where ∆1 is:

a 0→ q0, a 1

→ q1,

f(q0) 0→ q0, f(q1) 0

→ q0,

f(q0) 1→ q1, f(q1) 1

→ q0.

and Ω1 = q0, q1, q1. Let us prove that

L(A1) = L | L 6= ∅

is not in RSGTS.Assume that there exists a simple GTSA As with n states such that L(A1) =

L(As). Hence, As recognizes also each one of the singleton sets f i(a) for i > 0.Let us consider some i greater than n + 1, we can deduce that a run r on theGTS g associated with f i(a) maps two terms fk(a) and f l(a), k < l < i to

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 154: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

154 Tree Set Automata

the same state. We have g(t) = 0 for every term t£f l(a) and r “loops” betweenfk(a) and f l(a). Therefore, one can build another run r0 on a GTS g0 suchthat g0(t) = 0 for each t ∈ T (F). Since As is simple, and since the range of r0

is a subset of the range of r, g0 is recognized, hence the empty set is recognizedwhich contradicts the hypothesis.

Basically, using simple GTSA it is not possible to enforce a state to beassumed somewhere by every run. Consequently, it is not possible to expressglobal properties of generalized tree languages such as non-emptiness.

Second, RSGTS is not a subset of RDGTS.

Example 52. Let us consider the non-deterministic but simple GTSA A2 =(qf , qh,∆2,Ω2) where ∆2 is:

a 0→ qf | qh, a 1

→ qf | qh,

f(qf ) 1→ qf | qh, h(qh) 1

→ qf | qh,

f(qh) 0→ qf | qh, h(qf ) 0

→ qf | qh,

and Ω2 = 2qf ,qh. It is easy to prove that L(A2) = L | ∀t f(t) ∈ L ⇔ h(t) 6∈L. The proof that no deterministic GTSA recognizes L(A2) is left to the reader.

We terminate with an example of a non-deterministic and non-simple gen-eralized tree set automaton. This example will be used in the proof of Proposi-tion 36.

Example 53. Let A = (Q,∆,Ω) be defined by Q = q, q′, Ω = Q, and ∆ isthe following set of rules:

a 1→ q ; a 1

→ q′ ; a 0→ q′ ; f(q) 1

→ q ;f(q′) 0

→ q′ ; f(q′) 1→ q′ ; f(q′) 1

→ q ;

The proof that A is not deterministic, not simple, and not complete, andL(A) = L ⊆ T (F) | ∃t ∈ T (F) ((t ∈ L) ∧ (∀t′ ∈ T (F) (t £ t′) ⇒ (t′ ∈ L))) isleft as an exercise to the reader.

5.2.4 Regular Generalized Tree Sets, Regular Runs

As we mentioned it in Example 49.3, the set recognized by a GTSA may containGTS corresponding to non-regular languages. But regularity is of major interestfor practical reasons because it implies a GTS or a language to be finitely defined.

A generalized tree set g ∈ GE is regular if there exist a finite set R, amapping α : T (F) → R, and a mapping β : R → E satisfying the following twoproperties.

1. g = αβ (i.e. g = β α),

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 155: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.2 Definitions and Examples 155

2. α is closed under contexts, i.e. for all context c and terms t1, t2, we have

(α(t1) = α(t2)) ⇒ (α(c[t1]) = α(c[t2]))

In the case E = 0, 1n, regular generalized tree sets correspond to n-tuplesof regular tree languages.

Although the definition of regularity could lead to the definition of regularrun — because a run can be considered as a generalized tree set in GQ, we usestronger conditions for a run to be regular. Indeed, if we define regular runsas regular generalized tree sets in GQ, regularity of generalized tree sets andregularity of runs do not correspond in general. For instance, one could defineregular runs on non-regular generalized tree sets in the case of non-strongly de-terministic generalized tree set automata, and one could define non-regular runson regular generalized tree sets in the case of non-deterministic generalized treeset automata. Therefore, we only consider regular runs on regular generalizedtree sets:

A run r on a generalized tree set g is regular if r ↑ g ∈ GE×Q

is regular. Consequently, r and g are regular generalized tree sets.

Proposition 33. Let A be a generalized tree set automaton, if g is a regulargeneralized tree set in L(A) then there exists a regular A-run on g.

Proof. Consider a generalized tree set automaton A = (Q,∆,Ω) over E and aregular generalized tree set g in L(A) and let r be a successful run on g. LetL be a finite tree language closed under the subterm relation and such thatF0 ⊆ L and r(L) = r(T (F)). The generalized tree set g is regular, thereforethere exist a finite set R, a mapping α : T (F) → R closed under context and amapping β : R → E such that g = αβ. We now define a regular run r′ on g.

Let L? = L∪? where ? is a new constant symbol and let φ be the mappingfrom T (F) into Q×R×L? defined by φ(t) = (r(t), α(t), u) where u = t if t ∈ Land u = ? otherwise. Hence R′ = φ(T (F)) is a finite set because R′ ⊆ Q×R×L?.For each ρ in R′, let us fix tρ ∈ T (F) such that φ(tρ) = ρ.

The run r′ is now (regularly) defined via two mappings α′ and β′. Let β′ bethe projection from Q × R × L? into Q and let α′ : T (F) → R′ be inductivelydefined by :

∀a ∈ F0 α′(a) = φ(a);

and

∀f ∈ Fp∀t1, . . . , tp ∈ T (F)

α′(f(t1, . . . , tp)) = φ(f(tα′(t1), . . . , tα′(tp))).

Let r′ = α′β′. First we can easily prove by induction that ∀t ∈ L α′(t) = φ(t)and deduce that ∀t ∈ L r′(t) = r(t). Thus r′ and r coincide on L. It remainsto prove that (1) the mapping α′ is closed under context, (2) r′ is a run on gand (3) r′ is a successful run.

(1) From the definition of α′ we can easily derive that the mapping α′ is closedunder context.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 156: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

156 Tree Set Automata

(2) We prove that the mapping r′ = α′β′ is a run on g, that is if t = f(t1, . . . , tp)then (r′(t1), . . . , r

′(tp), f, g(t), r′(t)) ∈ ∆.

Let us consider a term t = f(t1, . . . , tp). From the definitions of α′, β′, andr′, we get r′(t) = r(t′) with t′ = f(tα′(t1), . . . , tα′(tp)). The mapping r is a runon g, hence (r(tα′(t1)), . . . , r(tα′(tp)), f, g(t′), r(t′)) ∈ ∆, and thus it suffices toprove that g(t) = g(t′) and, for all i, r′(ti) = r(tα′(ti)).

Let i ∈ 1, . . . , p, r′(ti) = β′(α′(ti)) by definition of r′. By definition of tα′(ti),α′(ti) = φ(tα′(ti)), therefore r′(ti) = β′(φ(tα′(ti))). Now, using the definitionsof φ and β′, we get r′(ti) = r(tα′(ti)).

In order to prove that g(t) = g(t′), we prove that α(t) = α(t′). Let π bethe projection from R′ into R. We have α(t′) = π(φ(t′)) by definition ofφ and π. We have α(t′) = π(α′(t)) using definitions of t′ and α′. Nowα(t′) = π(φ(tα′(t))) because φ(tα′(t)) = α′(t) by definition of tα′(t). And thenα(t′) = α(tα′(t)) by definition of π and φ. Therefore it remains to prove thatα(tα′(t)) = α(t). The proof is by induction on the structure of terms.

If t ∈ F0 then tα′(t) = t, so the property holds (note that this property holdsfor all t ∈ L). Let us suppose that t = f(t1, . . . , tp) and α(tα′(ti)) = α(ti) ∀i ∈1, . . . , p. First, using induction hypothesis and closure under context of α,we get

α(f(t1, . . . , tp)) = α(f(tα′(t1), . . . , tα′(tp)))

Therefore,

α(f(t1, . . . , tp)) = α(f(tα′(t1), . . . , tα′(tp)))

= π(φ(f(tα′(t1), . . . , tα′(tp)))) ( def. of φ and π)

= π(α′(f(t1, . . . , tp))) ( def. of α′)

= π(φ(tα′(f(t1,...,tp)))) ( def. of tα′(f(t1,...,tp)))

= α(tα′(f(t1,...,tp))) ( def. of φ and π).

(3) We have r′(T (F)) = r′(L) = r(L) = r(T (F)) using the definition of r′, thedefinition of L, and the equality r′(L) = r(L). The run r is a successful run.Consequently r′ is a successful run.

Proposition 34. A non-empty recognizable set of generalized tree sets containsa regular generalized tree set.

Proof. Let us consider a generalized tree set automaton A and a successful runr on a generalized tree set g. There exists a tree language closed under thesubterm relation F such that r(F ) = r(T (F)). We define a regular run rr on aregular generalized tree set gg in the following way.

The run rr coincides with r on F : ∀t ∈ F , rr(t) = r(t) and gg(t) = g(t). Theruns rr and gg are inductively defined on T (F)\F : given q1, . . . , qp in r(T (F)),let us fix a rule f(q1, . . . , qp) l

→ q such that q ∈ r(T (F)). The rule exists sincer is a run. Therefore, ∀t = f(t1, . . . , tp) 6∈ F such that rr(ti) = qi for all i ≤ p,we define rr(t) = q and gg(t) = l, following the fixed rule f(q1, . . . , qp) l

→ q.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 157: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.3 Closure and Decision Properties 157

From the preceding, we can also deduce that a finite and recognizable set ofgeneralized tree sets only contains regular generalized tree sets.

5.3 Closure and Decision Properties

5.3.1 Closure properties

This section is dedicated to the study of classical closure properties on GTSA-recognizable languages. For all positive results — union, intersection, projec-tion, cylindrification — the proofs are constructive. We show that the class ofrecognizable sets of generalized tree sets is not closed under complementationand that non-determinism cannot be reduced for generalized tree set automata.

Set operations on sets of GTS have to be distinguished from set operationson sets of terms. In particular, in the case where E = 0, 1n, if G1 and G2 aresets of GTS in GE , then G1 ∪G2 contains all GTS in G1 and G2. This is clearlydifferent from the set of all (L1

1 ∪ L21, . . . , L

1n ∪ L2

n) where (L11, . . . , L

1n) belongs

to G1 and (L21, . . . , L

2n) belongs to G2.

Proposition 35. The class RGTS is closed under intersection and union, i.e.if G1, G2 ⊆ GE are recognizable, then G1 ∪ G2 and G1 ∩ G2 are recognizable.

This proof is an easy modification of the classical proof of closure propertiesfor tree automata, see Chapter 1.

Proof. Let A1 = (Q1,∆1,Ω1) and A2 = (Q2,∆2,Ω2) be two generalized treeset automata over E. Without loss of generality we assume that Q1 ∩ Q2 = ∅.

Let A = (Q,∆,Ω) with Q = Q1 ∪Q2, ∆ = ∆1 ∪∆2, and Ω = Ω1 ∪Ω2. It isimmediate that L(A) = L(A1) ∪ L(A2).

We denote by π1 and π2 the projections from Q1 × Q2 into respectively Q1

and Q2. Let A′ = (Q′,∆′,Ω′) with Q′ = Q1 × Q2, ∆′ is defined by

(f(q1, . . . , qp) l→ q ∈ ∆′) ⇔ (∀i ∈ 1, 2 f(πi(q1), . . . , πi(qp)) l

→πi(q) ∈ ∆i) ,

where q1, . . . , qp, q ∈ Q′, f ∈ Fp, l ∈ E, and Ω′ is defined by

Ω′ = ω ∈ 2Q′

| πi(ω) ∈ Ωi , i ∈ 1, 2.

One can easily verify that L(A′) = L(A1) ∩ L(A2) .

Let us remark that the previous constructions also prove that the class RSGTS

is closed under union and intersection.The class languages recognizable by deterministic generalized tree set au-

tomata is closed under complementation. But, this property is false in thegeneral case of GTSA-recognizable languages.

Proposition 36. (a) Let A be a generalized tree set automaton, there existsa complete generalized tree set automaton Ac such that L(A) = L(Ac).

(b) If Acd is a deterministic and complete generalized tree set automaton, thereexists a generalized tree set automaton A′ such that L(A′) = GE −L(Acd).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 158: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

158 Tree Set Automata

(c) The class of GTSA-recognizable languages is not closed under complemen-tation.

(d) Non-determinism can not be reduced for generalized tree set automata.

Proof. (a) Let A = (Q,∆,Ω) be a generalized tree set automaton over E and letq′ be a new state, i.e. q′ 6∈ Q. Let Ac = (Qc,∆c,Ωc) be defined by Qc = Q∪q′,Ωc = Ω, and

∆c = ∆ ∪ (q1, . . . , qp, f, l, q′) | (q1, . . . , qp, f, l) × Q ∩ ∆ = ∅;

q1, . . . , qp ∈ Qc, f ∈ Fp, l ∈ E.

Ac is complete and L(A) = L(Ac). Note that Ac is simple if A is simple.

(b) Acd = (Q,∆,Ω) be a deterministic and complete generalized tree setautomaton over E. The automaton A′ = (Q′,∆′,Ω′) with Q′ = Q, ∆′ = ∆,and Ω′ = 2Q − Ω recognizes the set GE − L(Acd).

(c) E = 0, 1, F = c, a where a is a constant and c is of arity 1. LetG = g ∈ G0,1n | ∃t ∈ T (F) ((g(t) = 1)∧ (∀t′ ∈ T (F) (t£ t′) ⇒ (g(t′) = 1))).Clearly, G is recognizable by a non deterministic GTSA (see Example 53). LetG = G0,1n − G, we have G = g ∈ G0,1n | ∀t ∈ T (F) ∃t′ ∈ T (F) (t £ t′) ∧

(g(t′) = 0) and G is not recognizable. Let us suppose that G is recognizedby an automaton A = (Q,∆,Ω) with Card(Q) = k − 2 and let us consider thegeneralized tree set g defined by: g(ci(a)) = 0 if i = k × z for some integer z,and g(ci(a)) = 1 otherwise. The generalized tree set g is in G and we considera successful run r on g. We have r(T (F)) = ω ∈ Ω therefore there exists someinteger n such that r(g(ci(a)) | i ≤ n) = ω. Moreover we can suppose that nis a multiple of k. As Card(Q) = k − 2 there are two terms u and v in the setci(a) | n+1 ≤ i ≤ n+k−1 such that r(u) = r(v). Note that by hypothesis, forall i such that n+1 ≤ i ≤ n+k+1, g(ci(a)) = 1. Consequently, a successful rung′ could be defined from g on the generalized tree set g′ defined by g′(t) = g(t)if t = ci(a) when i ≤ n, and g′(t) = 1 otherwise. This leads to a contradictionbecause g′ 6∈ G.

(d) This result is a consequence of (b) and (c).

We will now prove the closure under projection and cylindrification. We willfirst prove a stronger lemma.

Lemma 8. Let G ⊆ GE1be a GTSA-recognizable language and let R ⊆ E1×E2.

The set R(G) = g′ ∈ GE2| ∃g ∈ G ∀t ∈ T (F) (g(t), g′(t)) ∈ R is recognizable.

Proof. Let A = (Q,∆,Ω) such that L(A) = G. Let A′ = (Q′,∆′,Ω′) where

Q′ = Q, ∆′ = f(q1, . . . , qp) l′→ q | ∃l ∈ E1 f(q1, . . . , qp) l

→ q ∈ ∆ and (l, l′) ∈ Rand Ω′ = Ω. We prove that R(G) = L(A′).

⊇ Let g′ ∈ L(A′) and let r′ be a successful run on g′. We construct a generalizedtree set g such that for all t ∈ T (F), (g(t), g′(t)) ∈ R and such that r′ isalso a successful A-run on g.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 159: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.3 Closure and Decision Properties 159

Let a be a constant. According to the definition of ∆′, a g′(a)→ r′(a) ∈ ∆′

implies that there exists la such that (la, g′(a)) ∈ R and a la→ r′(a) ∈ ∆.So let g(a) = la.

Let t = f(t1, . . . , tp) with ∀i r′(ti) = qi. There exists a rule f(q1, . . . , qp)g′(t)→ r′(t)

in ∆′ because r′ is a run on g′ and again, from the definition of ∆′, thereexists lt ∈ E1 such that f(q1, . . . , qp) lt→ r′(t) in ∆ with (lt(t), g

′(t)) ∈ R.So, we define g(t) = lt. Clearly, g is a generalized tree set and r′ is asuccessful run on g and for all t ∈ T (F), (g(t), g′(t)) ∈ R by construction.

⊆ Let g′ ∈ R(G) and let g ∈ G such that ∀t ∈ T (F) (g(t), g′(t)) ∈ R. One caneasily prove that any successful A-run on g is also a successful A′-run ong′.

Let us recall that if g is a generalized tree set in GE1×···×En, the ith projection

of g (on the Ei-component, 1 ≤ i ≤ n) is the GTS πi(g) defined by: let π fromE1 × · · · ×En into Ei, such that π(l1, . . . , ln) = li and let πi(g)(t) = π(g(t)) forevery term t. Conversely, the ith cylindrification of a GTS g denoted by π−1

i (g)is the set of GTS g′ such that πi(g

′) = g. Projection and cylindrification areusually extended to sets of GTS.

Corollary 7. (a) The class of GTSA-recognizable languages is closed underprojection and cylindrification.

(b) Let G ⊆ GE and G′ ⊆ GE′ be two GTSA-recognizable languages. The setG ↑ G′ = g ↑ g′ | g ∈ G, g′ ∈ G′ is a GTSA-recognizable language inGE×E′ .

Proof. (a) The case of projection is an immediate consequence of Lemma 8using E1 = E × E′, E2 = E, and R = π where π is the projection fromE × E′ into E. The case of cylindrification is proved in a similar way.

(b) Consequence of (a) and of Proposition 35 because G ↑ G′ = π−11 (G) ∩

π−12 (G′) where π−1

1 (respectively π−12 ) is the inverse projection from E to

E × E′ (respectively from E′ to E × E′).Let us remark that the construction preserves simplicity, so RSGTS is closed

under projection and cylindrification.

We now consider the case E = 0, 1n and we give two propositions withoutproof. Proposition 37 can easily be deduced from Corollary 7. The proof ofProposition 38 is an extension of the constructions made in Examples 49.1 and49.2.

Proposition 37. Let A and A′ be two generalized tree set automata over0, 1n.

(a) (L1 ∪ L′1, . . . , Ln ∪ L′

n) | (L1, . . . , Ln) ∈ L(A) and (L′1, . . . , L

′n) ∈ L(A′)

is recognizable.

(b) (L1 ∩ L′1, . . . , Ln ∩ L′

n) | (L1, . . . , Ln) ∈ L(A) and (L′1, . . . , L

′n) ∈ L(A′)

is recognizable.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 160: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

160 Tree Set Automata

(c) (L1, . . . , Ln) | (L1, . . . , Ln) ∈ L(A) is recognizable, where Li = T (F) −Li, ∀i.

Proposition 38. Let E = 0, 1n and let (F1, . . . , Fn) be a n-tuple of regulartree languages. There exist deterministic simple generalized tree set automataA , A′, and A′′ such that

• L(A) = (F1, . . . , Fn);

• L(A′) = (L1, . . . , Ln) | L1 ⊆ F1, . . . , Ln ⊆ Fn;

• L(A′′) = (L1, . . . , Ln) | F1 ⊆ L1, . . . , Fn ⊆ Ln.

5.3.2 Emptiness Property

Theorem 44. The emptiness property is decidable in the class of generalizedtree set automata. Given a generalized tree set automaton A, it is decidablewhether L(A) = ∅.

Labels of the generalized tree sets are meaningless for the emptiness deci-sion thus we consider “label-free” generalized tree set automata. Briefly, thetransition relation of a “label-free” generalized tree set automata is a relation∆ ⊆ ∪p Qp ×Fp × Q.

The emptiness decision algorithm for simple generalized tree set automatais straightforward. Indeed, Let ω be a subset of Q and let COND(ω) be thefollowing condition:

∀p ∀f ∈ Fp ∀q1, . . . , qp ∈ ω ∃q ∈ ω (q1, . . . , qp, f, q) ∈ ∆

We easily prove that there exists a set ω satisfying COND(ω) if and only ifthere exists an A-run. Therefore, the emptiness problem for simple generalizedtree set automata is decidable because 2Q is finite and COND(ω) is decidable.Decidability of the emptiness problem for simple generalized tree set automatais NP-complete (see Prop. 39).

The proof is more intricate in the general case, and it is not given in thisbook. Without the property of simple GTSA, we have to deal with a reachabilityproblem of a set of states since we have to check that there exists ω ∈ Ω and arun r such that r assumes exactly all the states in ω.

We conclude this section with a complexity result of the emptiness problemin the class of generalized tree set automata.

Let us remark that a finite initial fragment of a “label-free” generalized treeset corresponds to a finite set of terms that is closed under the subterm relation.The size or the number of nodes in such an initial fragment is the number ofdifferent terms in the subterm-closed set of terms (the cardinality of the set ofterms). The size of a GTSA is given by:

‖A‖ = |Q| +∑

f(q1,...,qp) l→ q∈∆

(arity(f) + 3) +∑

ω∈Ω

|ω|.

Let us consider a GTSA A with n states. The proof shows that one mustconsider at most all initial fragments of runs —hence corresponding to finite

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 161: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.3 Closure and Decision Properties 161

tree languages closed under the subterm relation— of size smaller than B(A),a polynomial in n, in order to decide emptiness for A. Let us remark that thepolynomial bound B(A) can be computed. The emptiness proofs relies on thefollowing lemma:

Lemma 9. There exists a polynomial function f of degree 4 such that:

Let A = (Q,∆,Ω) be a GTSA. There exists a successful run rs suchthat rs(T (F)) = ω ∈ Ω if and only if there exists a run rm and aclosed tree language F such that:

• rm(T (F)) = rm(F ) = ω;

• Card(F ) ≤ f(n) where n is the number of states in ω.

Proposition 39. The emptiness problem in the class of (simple) generalizedtree set automata is NP-complete.

Proof. Let A = (Q,∆,Ω) be a generalized tree set automaton over E. Letn = Card(Q).

We first give a non-deterministic and polynomial algorithm for decidingemptiness: (1) take a tree language F closed under the subterm relation suchthat the number of different terms in it is smaller than B(A); (2) take a runr on F ; (3) compute r(F ); (4) check whether r(F ) = ω is a member of Ω; (5)check whether ω satisfies COND(ω).

From Theorem 44, this algorithm is correct and complete. Moreover, thisalgorithm is polynomial in n since (1) the size of F is polynomial in n: step(2) consists in labeling the nodes of F with states following the rules of theautomaton – so there is a polynomial number of states, step (3) consists incollecting the states; step (4) is polynomial and non-deterministic and finally,step (5) is polynomial.

We reduce the satisfiability problem of boolean expressions into the empti-ness problem for generalized tree set automata. We first build a generalizedtree set automaton A such that L(A) is the set of (codes of) satisfiable booleanexpressions over n variables x1, . . . , xn.

Let F = F0∪F1∪F2 where F0 = x1, . . . , xn, F1 = ¬, and F2 = ∧,∨.A boolean expression is a term of T (F). Let Bool = 0, 1 be the set of booleanvalues. Let A = (Q,∆,Ω), be a generalized tree set automaton such thatQ = q0, q1, Ω = 2Q and ∆ is the following set of rules:

xji→ qi where j ∈ 1, . . . , n and i ∈ Bool

¬(qi) ¬i→ q¬i where i ∈ Bool

∨(qi1 , qi2)i1∨i2→ qi1∨i2 where i1, i2 ∈ Bool

∧(qi1 , qi2)i1∧i2→ qi1∧i2 where i1, i2 ∈ Bool

One can easily prove that L(A) = Lv | v is a valuation of x1, . . . , xnwhere Lv = t | t is a boolean expression which is true under v. Lv correspondsto a run rv on a GTS gv and gv labels each xj either by 0 or 1. Hence, gv canbe considered as a valuation v of x1, . . . , xn. This valuation is extended in gv toevery node, that is to say that every term (representing a boolean expression)

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 162: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

162 Tree Set Automata

is labeled either by 0 or 1 accordingly to the usual interpretation of ¬, ∧, ∨. Agiven boolean expression is hence labeled by 1 if and only if it is true under thevaluation v.

Now, we can derive an algorithm for the satisfiability of any boolean expres-sion e: build Ae a generalized tree set automaton such that L(A) is the set ofall tree languages containing e: L | e ∈ L; build Ae ∩A and decide emptiness.

We get then the reduction because Ae ∩ A is empty if and only if e is notsatisfiable.

Now, it remains to prove that the reduction is polynomial. The size of Ais 2 ∗ n + 10. The size of Ae is the length of e plus a constant. So we get theresult.

5.3.3 Other Decision Results

Proposition 40. The inclusion problem and the equivalence problem for deter-ministic generalized tree set automata are decidable.

Proof. These results are a consequence of the closure properties under inter-section and complementation (Propositions 35, 36), and the decidability of theemptiness property (Theorem 44).

Proposition 41. Let A be a generalized tree set automaton. It is decidablewhether or not L(A) is a singleton set.

Proof. Let A be a generalized tree set automaton. First it is decidable whetherL(A) is empty or not (Theorem 44). Second if L(A) is non empty then a regulargeneralized tree set g in L(A) can be constructed (see the proof of Theorem44). Construct the strongly deterministic generalized tree set automaton A′

such that L(A′) is a singleton set reduced to the generalized tree set g. Finally,

build A∩A′to decide the equivalence of A and A′. Note that we can build A

′,

since A′ is deterministic (see Proposition 36).

Proposition 42. Let L = (L1, . . . , Ln) be a tuple of regular tree language andlet A be a generalized tree set automaton over 0, 1n. It is decidable whetherL ∈ L(A).

Proof. This result just follows from closure under intersection and emptinessdecidability.

First construct a (strongly deterministic) generalized tree set automaton AL

such that L(A) is reduced to the singleton set L. Second, construct A ∩ AL

and decide whether L(A ∩AL) is empty or not.

Proposition 43. Given a generalized tree set automaton over E = 0, 1, n

and I ⊆ 1, . . . , n. The following two problems are decidable:

1. It is decidable whether or not there exists (L1, . . . , Ln) in L(A) such thatall the Li are finite for i ∈ I.

2. Let x1 . . . , xn be natural numbers. It is decidable whether or not thereexists (L1, . . . , Ln) in L(A) such that Card(Li) = xi for each i ∈ I.

The proof is technical and not given in this book. It relies on Lemma 9 ofthe emptiness decision proof.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 163: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.4 Applications to Set Constraints 163

5.4 Applications to Set Constraints

In this section, we consider the satisfiability problem for systems of set con-straints. We show a decision algorithm using generalized tree set automata.

5.4.1 Definitions

Let F be a finite and non-empty set of function symbols. Let X be a set ofvariables. We consider special symbols >, ⊥, ∼, ∪, ∩ of respective arities 0, 0,1, 2, 2. A set expression is a term in TF ′(X ) where F ′ = F ∪ >,⊥,∼,∪,∩.

A set constraint is either a positive set constraint of the form e ⊆ e′ or anegative set constraint of the form e 6⊆ e′ (or ¬(e ⊆ e′)) where e and e′ are set

expressions, and a system of set constraints is defined by∧k

i=1 SCi where theSCi are set constraints.

An interpretation I is a mapping from X into 2T (F). It can immediately beextended to set expressions in the following way:

I(>) = T (F);

I(⊥) = ∅;

I(f(e1, . . . , ep)) = f(I(e1), . . . , I(ep));

I(∼ e) = T (F) \ I(e);

I(e ∪ e′) = I(e) ∪ I(e′);

I(e ∩ e′) = I(e) ∩ I(e′).

We deduce an interpretation of set constraints in Bool = 0, 1, the Booleanvalues. For a system of set constraints SC, all the interpretations I such thatI(SC) = 1 are called solutions of SC. In the remainder, we will considersystems of set constraints of n variables X1, . . . ,Xn. We will make no distinctionbetween a solution I of a system of set constraints and a n-tuple of tree languages(I(X1), . . . , I(Xn)). We denote by SOL(SC) the set of all solutions of a systemof set constraints SC.

5.4.2 Set Constraints and Automata

Proposition 44. Let SC be a system of set constraints (respectively of positiveset constraints) of n variables X1, . . . ,Xn. There exists a deterministic (respec-tively deterministic and simple) generalized tree set automaton A over 0, 1n

such that L(A) is the set of characteristic generalized tree sets of the n-tuples(L1, . . . , Ln) of solutions of SC.

Proof. First we reduce the problem to a single set constraint. Let SC = C1 ∧. . . ∧ Ck be a system of set constraints. A solution of SC satisfies all theconstraints Ci. Let us suppose that, for every i, there exists a deterministicgeneralized tree set automaton Ai such that SOL(Ci) = L(A). As all variables inX1, . . . ,Xn do not necessarily occur in Ci, using Corollary 7, we can constructa deterministic generalized tree set automaton An

i over 0, 1n satisfying: L(Ani )

is the set of (L1, . . . , Ln) which corresponds to solutions of Ci when restrictedto the variables of Ci. Using closure under intersection (Proposition 35), we can

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 164: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

164 Tree Set Automata

construct a deterministic generalized tree set automaton A over 0, 1n suchthat SOL(SC) = L(A).

Therefore we prove the result for a set constraint SC of n variables X1, . . . ,Xn.Let E(exp) be the set of set variables and of set expression exp with a root sym-bol in F which occur in the set expression exp:

E(exp) =exp′ ∈ TF ′(X ) | exp′ £ exp and such that

either Head(exp′) ∈ F or exp′ ∈ X.

If SC ≡ exp1 ⊆ exp2 or SC ≡ exp1 6⊆ exp2 then E(SC) = E(exp1)∪E(exp2).

Let us consider a set constraint SC and let ϕ be a mapping ϕ from E(SC)into Bool. Such a mapping is easily extended first to any set expression occurringin SC and second to the set constraint SC. The symbols ∪, ∩, ∼, ⊆ and 6⊆ arerespectively interpreted as ∨, ∧, ¬, ⇒ and ¬ ⇒.

We now define the generalized tree set automaton A = (Q,∆,Ω) over E =0, 1n.

• The set of states is Q is the set ϕ | ϕ : E(SC) → Bool.

• The transition relation is defined as follows: f(ϕ1, . . . , ϕp) l→ϕ ∈ ∆ where

ϕ1, . . . , ϕp ∈ Q, f ∈ Fp, l = (l1, . . . , ln) ∈ 0, 1n, and ϕ ∈ Q satisfies:

∀i ∈ 1, . . . , n ϕ(Xi) = li (5.6)

∀e ∈ E(SC) \ X (ϕ(e) = 1) ⇔

(e = f(e1, . . . , ep)∀i 1 ≤ i ≤ p ϕi(ei) = 1

)(5.7)

• The set of accepting sets of states Ω is defined depending on the case of apositive or a negative set constraint.

– If SC is positive, Ω = ω ∈ 2Q | ∀ϕ ∈ ω ϕ(SC) = 1;

– If SC is negative, Ω = ω ∈ 2Q | ∃ϕ ∈ ω ϕ(SC) = 1.

In the case of a positive set constraint, we can choose the state set Q = ϕ |ϕ(SC) = 1 and Ω = 2Q. Consequently, A is deterministic and simple.

The correctness of this construction is easy to prove and is left to the reader.

5.4.3 Decidability Results for Set Constraints

We now summarize results on set constraints. These results are immediateconsequences of the results of Section 5.4.2. We use Proposition 44 to encodesets of solutions of systems of set constraints with generalized tree set automataand then, each point is deduced from Theorem 44, or Propositions 38, 43, 40,41.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 165: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.4 Applications to Set Constraints 165

Properties on sets of solutions

Satisfiability The satisfiability problem for systems of set constraints is decid-able.

Regular solution There exists a regular solution, that is a tuple of regulartree languages, in any non-empty set of solutions.

Inclusion, Equivalence Given two systems of set constraints SC and SC ′, itis decidable whether or not SOL(SC) ⊆ SOL(SC ′).

Unicity Given a system SC of set constraints, it is decidable whether or notthere is a unique solution in SOL(SC).

Properties on solutions

fixed cardinalities, singletons Given a system SC of set constraints over(X1, . . . ,Xn), I ⊆ 1, . . . , n, and x1 . . . , xn natural numbers;

• it is decidable whether or not there is a solution (L1, . . . , Ln) ∈SOL(SC) such that Card(Li) = xi for each i ∈ I.

• it is decidable whether or not all the Li are finite for i ∈ I.

In both cases, proofs are constructive and exhibits a solution.

Membership Given SC a system of set constraints over (X1, . . . ,Xn) and an-tuple (L1, . . . , Ln) of regular tree languages, it is decidable whether ornot (L1, . . . , Ln) ∈ SOL(SC).

Proposition 45. Let SC be a system of positive set constraints, it is decidablewhether or not there is a least solution in SOL(SC).

Proof. Let SC be a system of positive set constraints. Let A be the deter-ministic, simple generalized tree set automaton over 0, 1n such that L(A) =SOL(SC) (see Proposition 44). We define a partial ordering ¹ on G0,1n by :

∀l, l′ ∈ 0, 1n l ¹ l′ ⇔ (∀i l(i) ≤ l′(i))∀g, g′ ∈ G0,1n g ¹ g′ ⇔ (∀t ∈ T (F) g(t) ¹ g′(t))

The problem we want to deal with is to decide whether or not there exists aleast generalized tree set w.r.t. ¹ in L(A). To this aim, we first build a minimalsolution if it exists, and second, we verify that this solution is unique.

Let ω be a subset of states such that COND(ω) (see the sketch of proofpage 160). Let Aω = (ω,∆ω, 2ω) be the generalized tree set automaton Arestricted to state set ω.

Now let ∆ωmin defined by: for each (q1, . . . , qp, f) ∈ ωp × Fp, choose in

the set ∆ω one rule (q1, . . . , qp, f, l, q) such that l is minimal w.r.t. ¹. LetAω

min = (ω,∆ωmin, 2ω). Consequently,

1. There exists only one run rω on a unique generalized tree set gω inAω

min because for all q1, . . . , qp ∈ ω and f ∈ Fp there is only one rule(q1, . . . , qp, f, l, q) in ∆ω

min;

2. the run rω on gω is regular;

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 166: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

166 Tree Set Automata

3. the generalized tree set gω is minimal w.r.t. ¹ in L(Aω).

Points 1 and 2 are straightforward. The third point follows from the factthat A is deterministic. Indeed, let us suppose that there exists a run r′ on ageneralized tree set g′ such that g′ ≺ gω. Therefore, ∀t g′(t) ¹ gω(t), and thereexists (w.l.o.g.) a minimal term u = f(u1, . . . , up) w.r.t. the subterm orderingsuch that g′(u) ≺ gω(u). Since A is deterministic and ∀v ¢ u gω(v) = g′(v), wehave rω(ui) = r′(ui). Hence, the rule (rω(u1), . . . , rω(up), f, gω(u), rω(u)) is notsuch that gω(u) is minimal in ∆ω, which contradicts the hypothesis.

Consider the generalized tree sets gω for all subsets of states ω satisfyingCOND(ω). If there is no such gω, then there is no least generalized tree set gin L(A). Otherwise, each generalized tree set defines a n-tuple of regular treelanguages and inclusion is decidable for regular tree languages. Hence we canidentify a minimal generalized tree set g among all gω. This GTS g defines an-tuple (F1, . . . , Fn) of regular tree languages. Let us remark this constructiondoes not ensure that (F1, . . . , Fn) is minimal in L(A).

There is a deterministic, simple generalized tree set automaton A′ such thatL(A′) is the set of characteristic generalized tree sets of all (L1, . . . , Ln) satis-fying F1 ⊆ L1, . . . , Fn ⊆ Ln (see Proposition 38). Let A′′ be the deterministicgeneralized tree set automaton such that L(A′′) = L(A) ∩ L(A′) (see Proposi-tion 35). There exists a least generalized tree set w.r.t. ¹ in L(A) if and only ifthe generalized tree set automata A and A′′ are equivalent. Since equivalenceof generalized tree set automata is decidable (see Proposition 40) we get theresult.

5.5 Bibliographical Notes

We now survey decidability results for satisfiability of set constraints and somecomplexity issues.

Decision procedures for solving set constraints arise with [Rey69], and Mishra[Mis84]. The aim of these works was to obtain new tools for type inference andtype checking [AM91, Hei92, HJ90b, JM79, Mis84, Rey69].

First consider systems of set constraints of the form:

X1 = exp1, . . . ,Xn = expn (5.8)

where the Xi are distinct variables and the expi are disjunctions of set expres-sions of the form f(Xi1 , . . . ,Xip

) with f ∈ Fp. These systems of set constraintsare essentially tree automata, therefore they have a unique solution and eachXi is interpreted as a regular tree language.

Suppose now that the expi are set expressions without complement symbols.Such systems are always satisfiable and have a least solution which is regular.For example, the system

Nat = s(Nat) ∪ 0X = X ∩ Nat

List = cons(X, List) ∪ nil

has a least solution

Nat = si(0) | i ≥ 0 ,X = ∅ , List = nil.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 167: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

5.5 Bibliographical Notes 167

[HJ90a] investigate the class of definite set constraints which are of the formexp ⊆ exp′, where no complement symbol occurs and exp′ contains no set opera-tion. Definite set constraints have a least solution whenever they have a solution.The algorithm presented in [HJ90a] provides a specific set of transformationrules and, when there exists a solution, the result is a regular presentation ofthe least solution, in other words a system of the form (5.8).

Solving definite set constraints is EXPTIME-complete [CP97]. Many devel-opments or improvements of Heinzte and Jaffar’s method have been proposedand some are based on tree automata [DTT97].

The class of positive set constraints is the class of systems of set constraintsof the form exp ⊆ exp′, where no projection symbol occur. In this case, when asolution exists, set constraints do not necessarily have a least solution. Severalalgorithms for solving systems in this class were proposed, [AW92] generalizethe method of [HJ90a], [GTT93, GTT99] give an automata-based algorithm,and [BGW93] use the decision procedure for the first order theory of monadicpredicates. Results on the computational complexity of solving systems of setconstraints are presented in a paper of [AKVW93]. The systems form a naturalcomplexity hierarchy depending on the number of elements of F of each arity.The problem of existence of a solution of a system of positive set constraints isNEXPTIME-complete.

The class of positive and negative set constraints is the class of systems of setconstraints of the form exp ⊆ exp′ or exp 6⊆ exp′, where no projection symboloccur. In this case, when a solution exists, set constraints do not necessarilyhave, neither a minimal solution, nor a maximal solution. Let F = a, b().Consider the system (b(X) ⊆ X) ∧ (X 6⊆ ⊥), this system has no minimalsolution. Consider the system (X ⊆ b(X) ∪ a) ∧ (> 6⊆ X), this system hasno maximal solution. The satisfiability problem in this class turned out tobe much more difficult than the positive case. [AKW95] give a proof basedon a reachability problem involving Diophantine inequalities. NEXPTIME-completeness was proved by [Ste94]. [CP94a] gives a proof based on the ideasof [BGW93].

The class of positive set constraints with projections is the class of systems ofset constraints of the form exp ⊆ exp′ with projection symbols. Set constraintsof the form f−1

i (X) ⊆ Y can easily be solved, but the case of set constraints ofthe form X ⊆ f−1

i (Y ) is more intricate. The problem was proved decidable by[CP94b].

The expressive power of these classes of set constraints have been studied andhave been proved to be different [Sey94]. In [CK96, Koz93], an axiomatization isproposed which enlightens the reader on relationships between many approacheson set constraints.

Furthermore, set constraints have been studied in a logical and topologicalpoint of view [Koz95, MGKW96]. This last paper combine set constraints withTarskian set constraints, a more general framework for which many complexityresults are proved or recalled. Tarskian set constraints involve variables, relationand function symbols interpreted relative to a first order structure.

Topological characterizations of classes of GTSA recognizable sets, have alsobeen studied in [Tom94, Sey94]. Every set in RSGTS is a compact set and every

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 168: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

168 Tree Set Automata

set in RGTS is the intersection between a compact set and an open set. Theseremarks give also characterizations for the different classes of set constraints.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 169: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Chapter 6

Tree Transducers

6.1 Introduction

Finite state transformations of words, also called a-transducers or rational trans-ducers in the literature, model many kinds of processes, such as coffee machinesor lexical translators. But these transformations are not powerful enough tomodel syntax directed transformations, and compiler theory is an importantmotivation to the study of finite state transformations of trees. Indeed, trans-lation of natural or computing languages is directed by syntactical trees, and atranslator from LATEXinto HTML is a tree transducer. Unfortunately, from atheoretical point of view, tree transducers do not inherit nice properties of wordtransducers, and the classification is very intricate. So, in the present chapterwe focus on some aspects. In Sections 6.2 and 6.3, toy examples introduce inan intuitive way different kinds of transducers. In Section 6.2, we summarizemain results in the word case. Indeed, this book is mainly concerned with trees,but the word case is useful to understand the tree case and its difficulties. Thebimorphism characterization is the ideal illustration of the link between the“machine” point of view and the “homomorphic” one. In Section 6.3, we moti-vate and illustrate bottom-up and top-down tree transducers, using compilationas leitmotiv. We precisely define and present the main classes of tree transduc-ers and their properties in Section 6.4, where we observe that general classesare not closed under composition, mainly because of alternation of copying andnondeterministic processing. Nevertheless most useful classes, as those used inSection 6.3, have closure properties. In Section 6.5 we present the homomorphicpoint of view.

Most of the proofs are tedious and are omitted. This chapter is a very incom-plete introduction to tree transducers. Tree transducers are extensively studiedfor themselves and for various applications. But as they are somewhat compli-cated objects, we focus here on the definitions and main general properties. Itis usefull for every theoretical computer scientist to know main notions abouttree transducers, because they are the main model of syntax directed manipu-lations, and that the heart of sofware manipulations and interfaces are syntaxdirected. Tree transducers are an essential frame to develop practical modularsyntax directed algorithms, thought an effort of algorithmic engineering remainsto do. Tree transducers theory can be fertilized by other area or can be usefull

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 170: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

170 Tree Transducers

for other areas (example: Ground tree transducers for decidability of the firstorder theory of ground rewriting). We will be happy if after reading this chap-ter, the reader wants for further lectures, as monograph of Z. Flp and H. Vgler(december 1998 [FV98]).

6.2 The Word Case

6.2.1 Introduction to Rational Transducers

We assume that the reader roughly knows popular notions of language theory:homomorphisms on words, finite automata, rational expressions, regular gram-mars. See for example the recent survey of A. Mateescu and A. Salomaa [MS96].A rational transducer is a finite word automaton W with output. In a wordautomaton, a transition rule f(q) → q′(f) means “if W is in some state q, if itreads the input symbol f , then it enters state q′ and moves its head one symbolto the right”. For defining a rational transducer, it suffices to add an output,and a transition rule f(q) → q′(m) means “if the transducer is in some stateq, if it reads the input symbol f , then it enters state q′, writes the word m onthe output tape, and moves its head one symbol to the right”. Remark thatwith these notations, we identify a finite automaton with a rational transducerwhich writes what it reads. Note that m is not necessarily a symbol but canbe a word, including the empty word. Furthermore, we assume that it is notnecessary to read an input symbol, i.e. we accept transition rules of the formε(q) → q′(m) (ε denotes the empty word).

Graph presentations of finite automata are popular and convenient. So it isfor rational transducers. The rule f(q) → q′(m) will be drawn

f/mq q′

Example 54. (Language L1) Let F = 〈, 〉, ; , 0, 1, A, ..., Z. In the following,we will consider the language L1 defined on F by the regular grammar (theaxiom is program):program → 〈 instructinstruct → LOAD register | STORE register | MULT register

→ | ADD registerregister → 1tailregistertailregister → 0tailregister | 1tailregister | ; instruct | 〉

( a → b|c is an abbreviation for the set of rules a → b, a → c)L1 is recognized by deterministic automaton A1 of Figure 6.1. Semantic of

L1 is well known: LOAD i loads the content of register i in the accumulator;STORE i stores the content of the accumulator in register i; ADD i adds in theaccumulator the content of the accumulator and the content of register i; MULTi multiplies in the accumulator the content of the accumulator and the contentof register i.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 171: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.2 The Word Case 171

D

TS

end

Begin

Instruct

O AL

Tailregister

Register

A

M

O R E

TLU

D D1

0,1

;

Figure 6.1: A recognizer of L1

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 172: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

172 Tree Transducers

A rational transducer is a tuple R = (Q,F ,F ′, Qi, Qf ,∆) where Q is a setof states, F and F ′ are finite nonempty sets of input letters and output letters,Qi, Qf ⊆ Q are sets of initial and final states and ∆ is a set of transductionrules of the following type:

f(q) → q′(m),

where f ∈ F ∪ ε , m ∈ F ′∗ , q, q′ ∈ Q.R is ε-free if there is no rule f(q) → q′(m) with f = ε in ∆.The move relation →R is defined by: let t, t′ ∈ F∗, u ∈ F ′∗ , q, q′ ∈ Q,

f ∈ F , m ∈ F ′∗ ,

(tqft′, u)→R

(tfq′t, um) ⇔ f(q) → q′(m) ∈ ∆,

and →∗R is the reflexive and transitive closure of →R. A (partial) transduction

of R on tt′t′′ is a sequence of move steps of the form (tqt′t′′, u)→∗R(tt′q′t′′, uu′).

A transduction of R from t ∈ F∗ into u ∈ F ′∗ is a transduction of the form(qt, ε)→∗

R(tq′, u) with q ∈ Qi and q′ ∈ Qf .The relation TR induced by R can now be formally defined by:

TR = (t, u) | (qt, ε)∗→R

(tq′, u) with t ∈ F∗, u ∈ F ′∗ , q ∈ Qi, q′ ∈ Qf.

A relation in F∗ ×F ′∗ is a rational transduction if and only if it is inducedby some rational transducer. We also need the following definitions: let t ∈ F∗,TR(t) = u | (t, u) ∈ TR. The translated of a language L is obviously thelanguage defined by TR(L) = u | ∃t ∈ L, u ∈ TR(t).

Example 55.Ex. 55.1 Let us name French-L1 the translation of L1 in French (LOAD is

translated into CHARGER and STORE into STOCKER). Transducer of Figure 6.2realizes this translation. This example illustrates the use of rational trans-ducers as lexical transducers.

Ex. 55.2 Let us consider the rational transducer Diff defined by Q = qi, qs, ql, qd,F = F ′ = a, b, Qi = qi, Qf = qs, ql, qd, and ∆ is the set of rules:

type i a(qi) → qi(a), b(qi) → qi(b)

type s ε(qi) → qs(a), ε(qi) → qs(b), ε(qs) → qs(a), ε(qs) → qs(b)

type l a(qi) → ql(ε), b(qi) → ql(ε), a(ql) → ql(ε), b(ql) → ql(ε)

type d a(qi) → qd(b), b(qi) → qd(a), a(qd) → qd(ε), b(qd) → qd(ε),ε(qd) → qd(a), ε(qd) → qd(b).

It is easy to prove that TDiff = (m,m′) | m 6= m′,m,m′ ∈ a, b∗.

We give without proofs some properties of rational transducers. For moredetails, see [Sal73] or [MS96] and Exercises 65, 66, 68 for 1, 4 and 5. Thehomomorphic approach presented in the next section can be used as an elegantway to prove 2 and 3 (Exercise 70).

Proposition 46 (Main properties of rational transducers).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 173: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.2 The Word Case 173

〉/〉

end

Begin

Instruct

O/ε

Tailregister

Register

A/ε

R/ε

L/ε

D/ε0/0

;/;

1/1

D/CHARGERA/ε

S/ε T/ε 0/ε

1/1

D/ε

T/MULTM/ε U/ε

L/ε

〈/〈

E/STOCKER

Figure 6.2: A rational transducer from L1 into French-L1.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 174: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

174 Tree Transducers

1. The class of rational transductions is closed under union but not closedunder intersection.

2. The class of rational transductions is closed under composition.

3. Regular languages and context-free languages are closed under rationaltransduction.

4. Equivalence of rational transductions is undecidable.

5. Equivalence of deterministic rational transductions is decidable.

6.2.2 The Homomorphic Approach

A bimorphism is defined as a triple B = (Φ, L,Ψ) where L is a recognizablelanguage and Φ and Ψ are homomorphisms. The relation induced by B (alsodenoted by B) is defined by B = (Φ(t),Ψ(t)) | t ∈ L. Bimorphism (Φ, L,Ψ)is ε-free if Φ is ε-free (an homomorphism is ε-free if the image of a letter isnever reduced to ε). Two bimorphisms are equivalent if they induce the samerelation.

We can state the following theorem, generally known as Nivat Theorem [Niv68](see Exercises 69 and 70 for a sketch of proof).

Theorem 45 (Bimorphism theorem). Given a rational transducer, an equiv-alent bimorphism can be constructed. Conversely, any bimorphism defines arational transduction. Construction preserve ε-freeness.

Example 56.

Ex. 56.1 The relation (a(ba)n, an) | n ∈ N ∪ ((ab)n, b3n) | n ∈ N isprocessed by transducer R and bimorphism B of Figure 6.3

b/ε

a/a

a/ε

a/ε

a/ε

b/bbbb/bbb

Φ(A) = a

Φ(B) = ba

Φ(C) = ab

Ψ(A) = ε

Ψ(B) = a

Ψ(C) = bbb

C

B

C

A

ΨΦ

Figure 6.3: Transducer R and an equivalent bimorphism B = (Φ(t),Ψ(t)) | t ∈AB∗ + CC∗.

Ex. 56.2 Automaton L of Figure 6.4 and morphisms Φ and Ψ bellow definea bimorphism equivalent to transducer of Figure 6.2

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 175: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.3 Introduction to Tree Transducers 175

Φ(β) = 〈 Φ(λ) = LOAD Φ(σ) = STORE Φ(µ) = MULT

Φ(α) = ADD Φ(ρ) =; Φ(ω) = 1 Φ(ζ) = 0Φ(θ) =〉Ψ(β) = 〈 Ψ(λ) = CHARGER Ψ(σ) = STOCKER Ψ(µ) = MULT

Ψ(α) = ADD Ψ(ρ) =; Ψ(ω) = 1 Ψ(ζ) = 0Ψ(θ) =〉

θend

Register

Instruct

Tailregister

Begin λ, σ, µ, α

β

ρ

ω

ζ, ω

Figure 6.4: The control automaton L.

Nivat characterization of rational transducers makes intuitive sense. Au-tomaton L can be seen as a control of the actions, morphism Ψ can be seen asoutput function and Φ−1 as an input function. Φ−1 analyses the input — it isa kind of part of lexical analyzer — and it generates symbolic names; regulargrammatical structure on theses symbolic names is controlled by L. Exam-ples 56.1 and 56.2 are an obvious illustration. L is the common structure toEnglish and French versions, Φ generates the English version and Ψ generatesthe French one. This idea is the major idea of compilation, but compilation ofcomputing languages or translation of natural languages are directed by syntax,that is to say by syntactical trees. This is the motivation of the rest of the chap-ter. But unfortunately, from a formal point of view, we will lose most of thebest results of the word case. Power of non-linear tree transducers will explainin part this complication, but even in the linear case, there is a new phenom-ena in trees, the understanding of which can be introduced by the “problem ofhomomorphism inversion” that we describe in Exercise 71.

6.3 Introduction to Tree Transducers

Tree transducers and their generalizations model many syntax directed trans-formations (see exercises). We use here a toy example of compiler to illustratehow usual tree transducers can be considered as modules of compilers.

We consider a simple class of arithmetic expressions (with usual syntax) assource language. We assume that this language is analyzed by a LL1 parser. Weconsider two target languages: L1 defined in Example 54 and an other languageL2. A transducer A translates syntactical trees in abstract trees (Figure 6.5).A second tree transducer R illustrates how tree transducers can be seen as

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 176: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

176 Tree Transducers

part of compilers which compute attributes over abstract trees. It decoratesabstract trees with numbers of registers (Figure 6.7). Thus R translates abstracttrees into attributed abstract trees. After that, tree transducers T1 and T2

generate target programs in L1 and L2, respectively, starting from attributedabstract trees (Figures 6.7 and 6.8). This is an example of nonlinear transducer.Target programs are yields of generated trees. So composition of transducersmodel succession of compilation passes, and when a class of transducers is closedby composition (see section 6.4), we get universal constructions to reduce thenumber of compiler passes and to meta-optimize compilers.

We now define the source language. Let us consider the terminal alphabet(, ),+,×, a, b, . . . , z. First, the context-free word grammar G1 is defined byrules (E is the axiom):

E → M | M + EM → F | F × MF → I | (E)I → a | b | · · · | z

Another context-free word grammar G2 is defined by (E is the axiom):

E → ME′

E′ → +E | εM → FM ′

M ′ → ×M | εF → I | (E)I → a | b | · · · | z

Let E be the axiom of G1 and G2. The semantic of these two grammarsis obvious. It is easy to prove that they are equivalent, i.e. they define thesame source language. On the one hand, G1 is more natural, on the otherhand G2 could be preferred for syntactical analysis reason, because G2 is LL1

and G1 is not LL. We consider syntactical trees as derivation trees for thetree grammar G2. Let us consider word u = (a + b) × c. u of the sourcelanguage. We define the abstract tree associated with u as the tree ×(+(a, b), c)defined over F = +(, ),×(, ), a, b, c. Abstract trees are ground terms overF . Evaluate expressions or compute attributes over abstract trees than oversyntactical trees. The following transformation associates with a syntacticaltree t its corresponding abstract tree A(t).

I(x) → x F (x) → xM(x,M ′(ε)) → x E(x,E′(ε)) → x

M(x,M ′(×, y)) → ×(x, y) E(x,E′(+, y)) → +(x, y)F ((, x, )) → x

We have not precisely defined the use of the arrow →, but it is intuitive.Likewise we introduce examples before definitions of different kinds of tree trans-ducers (section 6.4 supplies a formal frame).

To illustrate nondeterminism, let us introduce two new transducers A and A′.Some brackets are optional in the source language, hence A′ is nondeterministic.Note that A works from frontier to root and A′ works fromm root to frontier.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 177: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.3 Introduction to Tree Transducers 177

A : an Example of Bottom-up Tree Transducer

The following linear deterministic bottom-up tree transducer A carries outtransformation of derivation trees for G2 into the corresponding abstract trees.Empty word ε is identified as a constant symbol in syntactical trees. States ofA are q, qε, qI , qF , qM ′ε, qE′ε, qE , q×, qM ′×, q+, qE′+, q(, and q). Final state isqE . The set of transduction rules is:

a → q(a) b → q(b)c → q(c) ε → qε(ε)) → q)()) ( → q((()

+ → q+(+) × → q×(×)I(q(x)) → qI(x) F (qI(x)) → qF (x)

M ′(qε(x)) → qM ′ε(x) E′(qε(x)) → qE′ε(x)M(qF (x), qM ′ε(y)) → qM (x) E(qM (x), qE′ε(y)) → qE(x)M ′(q×(x), qM (y)) → qM ′×(y) M(qF (x), qM ′×(y)) → qM (×(x, y))E′(q+(x), qE(y)) → qE′+(y) E(qM (x), qE′+(y)) → qE(+(x, y))

F (q((x), qE(y), q)(z)) → qF (y)

The notion of (successful) run is an intuitive generalization of the notionof run for finite tree automata. The reader should note that FTAs can beconsidered as a special case of bottom-up tree transducers whose output is equalto the input. We give in Figure 6.5 an example of run of A which translatesderivation tree t which yields (a + b) × c for context-free grammar G2 into thecorresponding abstract tree ×(+(a, b), c).

t→∗A

(

q(

a

qM

b

qE′+

E

)

q)

F

ε

qM ′×

M

c

qE′ε

E

→∗A

a b

+

qF

ε

qM ′×

M

c

qE′ε

E

→∗A

a b

+ c

×

qE

Figure 6.5: Example of run of A

A′ : an Example of Top-down Tree Transducer

The inverse transformation A−1, which computes the set of derivation trees ofG2 associated with an abstract tree, is computed by a nondeterministic top-down tree transducer A′. The states of A′ are qE , qF , qM . The initial state isqE . The set of transduction rules is:

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 178: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

178 Tree Transducers

qE(x) → E(qM (x), E′(ε)) qE(+(x, y)) → E(qM (x), E′(+, qE(y)))qM (x) → M(qF (x),M ′(ε)) qM (×(x, y)) → M(qF (x),M ′(×, qM (y)))qF (x) → F ((, qE(x), )) qF (a) → F (I(a))qF (b) → F (I(b)) qF (c) → F (I(c))

Transducer A′ is nondeterministic because there are ε-rules like qE(x) →E(qM (x), E′(ε)). We give in Figure 6.6 an example of run of A′ which transformsabstract tree +(a,×(b, c)) into a syntactical tree t′ of the word a + b × c.

a

b c

×

+

qE

→A′

a

qM

+

b c

×

qE

E′

E

→∗A′

a

I

F

ε

M ′

M

+

b c

×

qE

E′

E

→∗A′ t′

Figure 6.6: Example of run of A′

Compilation

The compiler now transforms abstract trees into programs for some target lan-guages. We consider two target languages. The first one is L1 of Example 54.To simplify, we omit “;”, because they are not necessary — we introduced semi-colons in Section 6.2 to avoid ε-rules, but this is a technical detail, because word(and tree) automata with ε-rules are equivalent to usual ones. The second targetlanguage is an other very simple language L2, namely sequences of two instruc-tions +(i, j, k) (put the sum of contents of registers i and j in the register k) and×(i, j, k). In a first pass, we attribute to each node of the abstract tree the min-imal number of registers necessary to compute the corresponding subexpressionin the target language. The second pass generates target programs.

First pass: computation of register numbers by a deterministic linear bottom-up transducer R.

States of a tree automaton can be considered as values of (finitely val-ued) attributes, but formalism of tree automata does not allow decoratingnodes of trees with the corresponding values. On the other hand, this dec-oration is easy with a transducer. Computation of finitely valued inherited(respectively synthesized) attributes is modeled by top-down (respectivelybottom-up) tree transducers. Here, we use a bottom-up tree transducerR. States of R are q0, . . . , qn. All states are final states. The set of rules

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 179: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.4 Properties of Tree Transducers 179

is:

a → q0(a) b → q0(b)c → q0(c)

+(qi(x), qi(y)) → qi+1(+i+1(x, y)) ×(qi(x), qi(y)) → qi+1(

+i 1 × (x, y))

if i > j+(qi(x), qj(y)) → qi(

+i (x, y) ×(qi(x), qj(y)) → qi(

×i (x, y))

if i < j, we permute the order of subtrees+(qi(x), qj(y)) → qj(

+j (y, x)) ×(qi(x), qj(y)) → qj(

×j (y, x))

A run t→∗R qi(u) means that i registers are necessary to evaluate t. Root

of t is then relabelled in u by symbol +i or ×

i .

Second pass: generation of target programs in L1 or L2, by top-down de-terministic transducers T1 and T2. T1 contains only one state q. Setof rules of T1 is:

q( +i (x, y)) → ¦(q(x), STOREi, q(y), ADDi, STOREi)

q(×i (x, y)) → ¦(q(x), STOREi, q(y), MULTi, STOREi)

q(a) → ¦(LOAD, a)q(b) → ¦(LOAD, b)q(c) → ¦(LOAD, c)

where ¦(, , , , ) and ¦(, ) are new symbols.

State set of T2 is q, q′ where q′ is the initial state. Set of rules of T2 is:

q( +i (x, y)) → #(q(x), q(y),+, (, q′(x), q′(y), i, )) q′( +

i (x, y)) → iq(×

i (x, y)) → #(q(x), q(y),×, (, q′(x), q′(y), i, )) q′(×i (x, y)) → i

q(a) → ε q′(a) → aq(b) → ε q′(b) → bq(c) → ε q′(c) → c

where # is a new symbol of arity 8.

The reader should note that target programs are words formed with leavesof trees, i.e. yields of trees. Examples of transductions computed by T1

and T2 are given in Figures 6.7 and 6.8. The reader should also note thatT1 is an homomorphism. Indeed, an homomorphism can be considered asa particular case of deterministic transducer, namely a transducer withonly one state (we can consider it as bottom-up as well as top-down). Thereader should also note that T2 is deterministic but not linear.

6.4 Properties of Tree Transducers

6.4.1 Bottom-up Tree Transducers

We now give formal definitions. In this section, we consider academic examples,without intuitive semantic, to illustrate phenomena and properties. Tree trans-ducers are both generalization of word transducers and tree automata. We first

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 180: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

180 Tree Transducers

a

b c

+ d

×

+

→∗R

a

b c

+1 d

×1

+1

q1

= q1(u).

q(u)→∗T1

L b

¦ S1

L c

¦ A1 S1

¦ S1

L d

¦ M1 S1

¦ S1

L a

¦ A1 S1

¦

where L stands for LOAD, S stands for STORE, A stands for ADD, M stands for MULT.The corresponding program is the yield of this tree:LOADb STORE1 LOADc ADD1 STORE1 STORE1 LOADd MULT1 STORE1 STORE1 LOADaADD1 STORE1

Figure 6.7: Decoration with synthesized attributes of an abstract tree, andtranslation into a target program of L1.

q(u)→∗T2

ε ε + ( b c 1 )

] ε × ( 1 d 1 )

] ε + ( 1 a 1 )

]

The corresponding program is the yield of this tree: +(bc1) × (1d1) + (1a1)

Figure 6.8: Translation of an abstract tree into a target program of L2

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 181: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.4 Properties of Tree Transducers 181

consider bottom-up tree transducers. A transition rule of a NFTA is of the typef(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)) → q(f(x1, . . . , xn)). Here we extend the definition (as wedid in the word case), accepting to change symbol f into any term.

A bottom-up Tree Transducer (NUTT) is a tuple U = (Q,F ,F ′, Qf ,∆)where Q is a set of (unary) states, F and F ′ are finite nonempty sets of inputsymbols and output symbols, Qf ⊆ Q is a set of final states and ∆ is a set oftransduction rules of the following two types:

f(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)) → q(u) ,

where f ∈ Fn, u ∈ T (F ′,Xn), q, q1, . . . , qn ∈ Q , or

q(x1) → q′(u) (ε-rule),

where u ∈ T (F ′,X1), q, q′ ∈ Q.As for NFTA, there is no initial state, because when a symbol is a leave a

(i.e. a constant symbol), transduction rules are of the form a → q(u), whereu is a ground term. These rules can be considered as “initial rules”. Lett, t′ ∈ T (F ∪ F ′ ∪ Q). The move relation →U is defined by:

t→U

t′ ⇔

∃f(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)) → q(u) ∈ ∆∃C ∈ C(F ∪ F ′ ∪ Q)∃u1, . . . , un ∈ T (F ′)t = C[f(q1(u1), . . . , qn(un))]t′ = C[q(ux1←u1, . . . , xn←un)]

This definition includes the case of ε-rule as a particular case. The reflexiveand transitive closure of →U is →∗

U . A transduction of U from a ground termt ∈ T (F) to a ground term t′ ∈ T (F ′) is a sequence of move steps of the formt→∗

U q(t′), such that q is a final state. The relation induced by U is the relation(also denoted by U) defined by:

U = (t, t′) | t∗→U

q(t′), t ∈ T (F), t′ ∈ T (F ′), q ∈ Qf.

The domain of U is the set t ∈ T (F) | (t, t′) ∈ U. The image by U of aset of ground terms L is the set U(L) = t′ ∈ T (F ′) | ∃t ∈ L, (t, t′) ∈ U.

A transducer is ε-free if it contains no ε-rule. It is linear if all tran-sition rules are linear (no variable occurs twice in the right-hand side). Itis non-erasing if, for every rule, at least one symbol of F ′ occurs in theright-hand side. It is said to be complete (or non-deleting) if, for every rulef(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)) → q(u) , for every xi(1 ≤ i ≤ n), xi occurs at least oncein u. It is deterministic (DUTT) if it is ε-free and there is no two rules withthe same left-hand side.

Example 57.Ex. 57.1 Tree transducer A defined in Section 6.3 is a linear DUTT. Tree

transducer R in Section 6.3 is a linear and complete DUTT.

Ex. 57.2 States of U1 are q, q′; F = f(), a; F ′ = g(, ), f(), f ′(), a; q′ isthe final state; the set of transduction rules is:

a → q(a)f(q(x)) → q(f(x)) | q(f ′(x)) | q′(g(x, x))

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 182: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

182 Tree Transducers

U1 is a complete, non linear NUTT. We now give the transductions ofthe ground term f(f(f(a))). For the sake of simplicity, fffa stands forf(f(f(a))). We have:

U1(fffa) = g(ffa, ffa), g(ff ′a, ff ′a), g(f ′fa, f ′fa), g(f ′f ′a, f ′f ′a).

U1 illustrates an ability of NUTT, that we describe following Gcseg andSteinby.

B1- “Nprocess and copy” A NUTT can first process an input sub-tree nondeterministically and then make copies of the resultingoutput tree.

Ex. 57.3 States of U2 are q, q′; F = F ′ = f(), f ′(), a; q is the final state;the set of transduction rules is defined by:

a → q(a)f(q(x)) → q′(a)

f ′(q′(x)) → q(a)

U2 is a non complete DUTT. The tree transformation induced by U2 is

(t, a) |

t is accepted by the DFTA of final state q and rulesa → q(a), f(q(x)) → q′(f(x)), f ′(q′(x)) → q(f ′(x))

.

B2- “check and delete” A NUTT can first check regular con-straints on input subterms and delete these subterms afterwards.

Bottom-up tree transducers translate the input trees from leaves to root, sobottom-up tree transducers are also called frontier-to-root transducers. Top-down tree transducers work in opposite direction.

6.4.2 Top-down Tree Transducers

A top-down Tree Transducer (NDTT) is a tuple D = (Q,F ,F ′, Qi,∆) whereQ is a set of (unary) states, F and F ′ are finite nonempty sets of input sym-bols and output symbols, Qi ⊆ Q is a set of initial states and ∆ is a set oftransduction rules of the following two types:

q(f(x1, . . . , xn)) → u[q1(xi1), . . . , qp(xip)] ,

where f ∈ Fn, u ∈ Cp(F ′), q, q1, . . . , qp ∈ Q, , xi1 , . . . , xip∈ Xn, or

q(x) → u[q1(x), . . . , qp(x)] (ε-rule),

where u ∈ Cp(F ′), q, q1, . . . , qp ∈ Q, x ∈ X .As for top-down NFTA, there is no final state, because when a symbol is a

leave a (i.e. a constant symbol), transduction rules are of the form q(a) → u,where u is a ground term. These rules can be considered as “final rules”. Lett, t′ ∈ T (F ∪ F ′ ∪ Q). The move relation →D is defined by:

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 183: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.4 Properties of Tree Transducers 183

t→D

t′ ⇔

∃q(f(x1, . . . , xn)) → u[q1(xi1), . . . , qp(xip)] ∈ ∆

∃C ∈ C(F ∪ F ′ ∪ Q)∃u1, . . . , un ∈ T (F)t = C[q(f(u1, . . . , un))]t′ = C[u[q1(v1), . . . , qp(vp)])] where vj = uk if xij

= xk

This definition includes the case of ε-rule as a particular case. →∗D is the

reflexive and transitive closure of →D. A transduction of D from a ground termt ∈ T (F) to a ground term t′ ∈ T (F ′) is a sequence of move steps of the formq(t)→∗

D t′, where q is an initial state. The transformation induced by D is therelation (also denoted by D) defined by:

D = (t, t′) | q(t)∗→D

t′, t ∈ T (F), t′ ∈ T (F ′), q ∈ Qi.

The domain of D is the set t ∈ T (F) | (t, t′) ∈ D. The image of a setof ground terms L by D is the set D(L) = t′ ∈ T (F ′) | ∃t ∈ L, (t, t′) ∈ D.ε-free, linear, non-erasing, complete (or non-deleting), deterministic top-downtree transducers are defined as in the bottom-up case.

Example 58.

Ex. 58.1 Tree transducers A′, T1, T2 defined in Section 6.3 are examples ofNDTT.

Ex. 58.2 Let us now define a non-deterministic and non linear NDTT D1.States of D1 are q, q′. The set of input symbols is F = f(), a. The set ofoutput symbols is F ′ = g(, ), f(), f ′(), a. The initial state is q. The setof transduction rules is:

q(f(x)) → g(q′(x), q′(x)) (copying rule)

q′(f(x)) → f(q′(x)) | f ′(q′(x)) (non deterministic relabeling)

q′(a) → a

D1 transduces f(f(f(a))) (or briefly fffa) into the set of 16 trees:

g(ffa, ffa), g(ffa, ff ′a), g(ffa, f ′fa), . . . , g(f ′f ′a, f ′fa), g(f ′f ′a, f ′f ′a).

D1 illustrates a new property.

D- “copy and Nprocess” A NDTT can first make copies of aninput subtree and then process different copies independently andnondeterministically .

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 184: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

184 Tree Transducers

6.4.3 Structural Properties

In this section, we use tree transducers U1, U2 and D1 of the previous section inorder to point out differences between top-down and bottom-up tree transducers.

Theorem 46 (Comparison Theorem).

1. There is no top-down tree transducer equivalent to U1 or to U2.

2. There is no bottom-up tree transducer equivalent to D1.

3. Any linear top-down tree transducer is equivalent to a linear bottom-up treetransducer. In the linear complete case, classes of bottom-up and top-downtree transducers are equal.

It is not hard to verify that neither NUTT nor NDTT are closed undercomposition. Therefore, comparison of D-property “copy and Nprocess” andU -property “Nprocess and copy” suggests an important question:

does alternation of copying and non-determinism induces an infinitehierarchy of transformations?

The answer is affirmative [Eng78, Eng82], but it was a relatively long-standingopen problem. The fact that top-down transducers copy before non-deterministicprocesses, and bottom-up transducers copy after non-deterministic processes(see Exercise 75) suggests too that we get by composition two intricate infinitehierarchies of transformation. The following theorem summarizes results.

Theorem 47 (Hierarchy theorem). By composition of NUTT, we get aninfinite hierarchy of transformations. Any composition of n NUTT can be pro-cessed by composition of n+1 NDTT, and conversely (i.e. any composition of nNDTT can be processed by composition of n + 1 NUTT).

Transducer A′ of Section 6.3 shows that it can be useful to consider ε-rules,but usual definitions of tree transducers in literature exclude this case of nondeterminism. This does not matter, because it is easy to check that all importantresults of closure or non-closure hold simultaneously for general classes and ε-free classes. Deleting is also a minor phenomenon. Indeed, it gives rise to the“check and delete” property, which is specific to bottom-up transducers, butit does not matter for hierarchy theorem, which remains true if we considercomplete transducers.

Section 6.3 suggests that for practical use, non-determinism and non-linearityare rare. Therefore, it is important to note than if we assume linearity or deter-minism, hierarchy of Theorem 48 collapses. Following results supply algorithmsto compose or simplify transducers.

Theorem 48 (Composition Theorem).

1. The class of linear bottom-up transductions is closed under composition.

2. The class of deterministic bottom-up transductions is closed under com-position.

3. The class of linear top-down transductions is included in the class of lin-ear bottom-up transductions. These classes are equivalent in the completecase.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 185: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.5 Homomorphisms and Tree Transducers 185

4. Any composition of deterministic top-down transductions is equivalent toa deterministic complete top-down transduction composed with a linearhomomorphism.

The reader should note that bottom-up determinism and top-down deter-minism are incomparable (see Exercise 72).

Recognizable tree languages play a crucial role because derivation trees ofcontext-free word grammars are recognizable. Fortunately, we get:

Theorem 49 (Recognizability Theorem). The domain of a tree transduceris a recognizable tree language. The image of a recognizable tree language by alinear tree transducer is recognizable.

6.4.4 Complexity Properties

We present now some decidability and complexity results. As for structuralproperties, the situation is more complicated than in the word case, especiallyfor top-down tree transducers. Most of problems are untractable in the worstcase, but empirically “not so much complex” in real cases, though there is a lakeof “algorithmic engineering” to get performant algorithms. As in the word case,emptiness is decidable, and equivalence in undecidable in the general case but isdecidable in the k-valued case (a transducer is k-valued if there is no tree whichis transduced in more than k different terms; so a deterministic transducer is aparticular case of 1-valued transducer).

Theorem 50 (Recidability and complexity). Emptiness of tree transduc-tions is decidable. Equivalence of k-valued tree transducers is decidable.

Emptiness for bottom-up transducers is essentially the same as emptinessfor tree automata and therefore PTIME complete. Emptiness for top-downautomata, however, is essentially the same as emptiness for alternating topdowntree automata, giving DEXPTIME completeness for emptiness. The complexityPTIME for testing single-valuedness in the bottom-up case is contained in Seidl[Sei92]. Ramsey theory gives combinatorial properties onto which equivalencetests for k-valued tree transducers [Sei94a].

Theorem 51 (Equivalence Theorem). Equivalence of deterministic treetransducers is decidable.

6.5 Homomorphisms and Tree Transducers

Exercise 74 illustrates how decomposition of transducers using homomorphismscan help to get composition results, but we are far from the nice bimorphismtheorem of the word case, and in the tree case, there is no illuminating the-orem, but many complicated partial statements. Seminal paper of Engelfriet[Eng75] contains a lot of decomposition and composition theorems. Here, weonly present the most significant results.

A delabeling is a linear, complete, and symbol-to-symbol tree homomor-phism (see Section 1.4). This very special kind of homomorphism changes onlythe label of the input letter and possibly order of subtrees. Definition of tree

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 186: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

186 Tree Transducers

bimorphisms is not necessary, it is the same as in the word case. We get the fol-lowing characterization theorem. We say that a bimorphism is linear, (respec-tively complete, etc) if the two morphisms are linear, (respectively complete,etc).

Theorem 52. The class of bottom-up tree transductions is equivalent to theclass of bimorphisms (Φ, L,Ψ) where Φ is a delabeling.

Relation defined by (Φ, L,Ψ) is computed by a transduction which is linear(respectively complete, ε-free) if Ψ is linear (respectively complete, ε-free).

Remark that Nivat Theorem illuminates the symmetry of word transduc-tions: the inverse relation of a rational transduction is a rational transduction.In the tree case, non-linearity obviously breaks this symmetry, because a treetransducer can copy an input tree and process several copies, but it can nevercheck equality of subtrees of an input tree. If we want to consider symmetricrelations, we have two main situations. In the non-linear case, it is easy to provethat composition of two bimorphisms simulates a Turing machine. In the linearand the linear complete cases, we get the following results.

Theorem 53 (Tree Bimorphisms). .

1. The class LCFB of linear complete ε-free tree bimorphisms satisfies LCFB ⊂LCFB

2 = LCFB3.

2. The class LB of linear tree bimorphisms satisfies LB ⊂ LB2 ⊂ LB

3 ⊂LB

4 = LB5.

Proof of LCFB2 = LCFB

3 requires many refinements and we omit it.

To prove LCFB ⊂ LCFB2 we use twice the same homomorphism Φ(a) =

a,Φ(f(x)) = f(x),Φ(g(x, y)) = g(x, y)),Φ(h(x, y, z)) = g(x, g(y, z)).

For any subterms (t1, . . . , t2p+2) , let

t = h(t1, t2, h(t3, t4, h(t2i+1, t2i+2, . . . , h(t2p−1, t2p, g(t2p+1, t2p+2) . . . )))

and

t′ = g(t1, h(t2, t3, h(t4, . . . , h(t2i, t2i+1, h(t2i+2, t2i+3, . . . , h(t2p, t2p+1, t2p+2) . . . ))).

We get t′ ∈ (Φ Φ−1)(t). Assume that Φ Φ−1 can be processed by someΨ−1 Ψ′. Consider for simplicity subterms ti of kind fni(a). Roughly, if lengthsof ti are different enough, Ψ and Ψ′ must be supposed linear complete. Supposethat for some u we have Ψ(u) = t and Ψ′(u) = t′, then for any context u′

of u, Ψ(u′) is a context of t with an odd number of variables, and Ψ′(u′) isa context of t′ with an even number of variables. That is impossible becausehomomorphisms are linear complete.

Point 2 is a refinement of point 1 (see Exercise 79).

This example shows a stronger fact: the relation cannot be processed byany bimorphism, even non-linear, nor by any bottom-up transducer A directcharacterization of these transformations is given in [AD82] by a special class oftop-down tree transducers, which are not linear but are “globally” linear, andwhich are used to prove LCFB

2 = LCFB3.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 187: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.6 Exercises 187

6.6 Exercises

Exercises 65 to 71 are devoted to the word case, which is out of scoop of thisbook. For this reason, we give precise hints for them.

Exercise 65. The class of rational transductions is closed under rational operations.

Hint: for closure under union, connect a new initial state to initial state with (ε, ε)-

rules (parallel composition). For concatenation, connect by the same way final states

of the first transducer to initial states of the second (serial composition). For iteration,

connect final states to initial states (loop operation).

Exercise 66. The class of rational transductions is not closed under intersection. Hint:

consider rational transductions (anbp, an) | n, p ∈ N and (anbp, ap) | n, p ∈ N.

Exercise 67. Equivalence of rational transductions is undecidable. Hint: Associate

the transduction TP = (f(u), g(u)) | u ∈ Σ+ with each instance P = (f, g) of the Post

correspondance Problem such that TP defines (Φ(m), Ψ(m)) | m ∈ Σ∗. Consider

Diff of example 55.2. Diff 6= Diff ∪ TP if and only if P satisfies Post property.

Exercise 68. Equivalence of deterministic rational transductions is decidable. Hint:

design a pumping lemma to reduce the problem to a bounded one by suppression of

loops (if difference of lengths between two transduced subwords is not bounded, two

transducers cannot be equivalent).

Exercise 69. Build a rational transducer equivalent to a bimorphism. Hint: let f(q) →

q′(f) a transition rule of L. If Φ(f) = ε, introduce transduction rule ε(q) → q′(Ψ(f)).

If Φ(f) = a0 . . . an, introduce new states q1, . . . , qn and transduction rules a0(q) →

q1(ε), . . . ai(qi) → qi+1(ε), . . . an(qn) → q′(Ψ(f)).

Exercise 70. Build a bimorphism equivalent to a rational transducer. Hint: consider

the set ∆ of transition rules as a new alphabet. We may speak of the first state q and

the second state q′ in a letter “f(q) → q′(m)”. The control language L is the set of

words over this alphabet, such that (i) the first state of the first letter is initial (ii) the

second state of the last letter is final (iii) in every two consecutive letters of a word,

the first state of the second equals the second state of the first. We define Φ and Ψ by

Φ(f(q)− > q′(m)) = f and Ψ(f(q)− > q′(m)) = m.

Exercise 71. Homomorphism inversion and applications. An homomorphism Φ isnon-increasing if for every symbol a, Φ(a) is the empty word or a symbol.

1. For any morphism Φ, find a bimorphism (Φ′, L, Ψ) equivalent to Φ−1, with Φ′

non-increasing, and such that furthermore Φ′ is ε-free if Φ is ε-free. Hint: Φ−1

is equivalent to a transducer R (Exercise 69), and the output homomorphism Φ′

associated to R as in Exercise 70 is non-increasing. Furthermore, if Φ is ε-free,R and Φ′ are ε-free.

2. Let Φ and Ψ two homomorphism. If Φ is non-increasing, build a transducerequivalent to Ψ Φ−1 (recall that this notation means that we apply Ψ beforeΦ−1). Hint and remark: as Φ is non-increasing, Φ−1 satisfies the inverse homo-morphism property Φ−1(MM ′) = Φ−1(M)Φ−1(M ′) (for any pair of words orlanguages M and M ′). This property can be used to do constructions “symbolby symbol”. Here, it suffices that the transducer associates Φ−1(Ψ(a)) with a,for every symbol a of the domain of Ψ.

3. Application: prove that classes of regular and context-free languages are closedunder bimorphisms (we admit that intersection of a regular language with aregular or context-free language, is respectively regular or context-free).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 188: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

188 Tree Transducers

4. Other application: prove that bimorphisms are closed under composition. Hint: remark that for any application f and set E, (x, f(x)) | f(x) ∈ E =(x, f(x)) | x ∈ f−1(E).

Exercise 72. We identify words with trees over symbols of arity 1 or 0. Let relations

U = (fna, fna) | n ∈ N ∪ (fnb, gnb) | n ∈ N and D = (ffna, ffna) | n ∈

N ∪ (gfna, gfnb) | n ∈ N. Prove that U is a deterministic linear complete bottom-

up transduction but not a deterministic top-down transduction. Prove that D is a

deterministic linear complete top-down transduction but not a deterministic bottom-

up transduction.

Exercise 73. Prove point 3 of Comparison Theorem. Hint. Use rule-by-rule tech-

niques as in Exercise 74.

Exercise 74. Prove Composition Theorem. Hints: Prove 1 and 2 using composition

“rule-by-rule”, illustrated as following. States of A B are products of states of A

and states of B. Let f(q(x))→A q′(g(x, g(x, a))) and g(q1(x), g(q2(y), a)→B q4(u).

Subterms substituted to x and y in the composition must be equal, and determinism

implies q1 = q2. Then we build new rule f((q, q1)(x))→AB(q′, q4)(u). To prove 3

for example, associate q(g(x, y)) → u(q′(x), q′′(y)) with g(q′(x), q′′(y)) → q(u), and

conversely. For 4, Using ad hoc kinds of “rule-by-rule” constructions, prove DDTT ⊂

DCDTTLHOM and LHOMDCDTT ⊂ DCDTTLHOM (L means linear, C complete,

D deterministic - and suffix DTT means top-down tree transducer as usually).

Exercise 75. Prove NDTT = HOM NLDTT and NUTT = HOM NLBTT. Hint: to

prove NDTT ⊂ HOM NLDTT use a homomorphism H to produce in advance as may

copies of subtrees of the input tree as the NDTT may need, ant then simulate it by a

linear NDTT.

Exercise 76. Use constructions of composition theorem to reduce the number of

passes in process of Section 6.3.

Exercise 77. Prove recognizability theorem. Hint: as in exercise 74, “naive” con-

structions work.

Exercise 78. Prove Theorem 52. Hint: “naive” constructions work.

Exercise 79. Prove point 2 of Theorem 53. Hint: E denote the class of homomor-

phisms which are linear and symbol-to-symbol. L, LC, LCF denotes linear, linear

complete, linear complete ε-free homomorphisms, respectively. Prove LCS = L E =

E L and E−1 L ⊂ L E−1. Deduce from these properties and from point 1 of

Theorem 53 that LB4 = E LCFB2 E−1. To prove that LB3 6= LB4, consider

Ψ1 Ψ−12 Φ Φ−1 Ψ2 Ψ−1

1 , where Φ is the homomorphism used in point 1 of

Theorem 53; Ψ1 identity on a, f(x), g(x, y), h(x, y, z), Ψ1(e(x)) = x; Ψ2 identity on

a, f(x), g(x, y) and Ψ2(c(x, y, z) = b(b(x, y), z).

Exercise 80. Sketch of proof of LCFB2 = LCFB3 (difficult). Distance D(x, y, u) oftwo nodes x and y in a tree u is the sum of the lengths of two branches which join xand y to their younger common ancestor in u. D(x, u) denotes the distance of x tothe root of u.

Let H the class of deterministic top-down transducers T defined as follows: q0, . . . , qn

are states of the transducer, q0 is the initial state. For every context, consider the re-sult ui of the run starting from qi(u). ∃k, ∀ context u such that for every variable xof u, D(x, u) > k:

• u0 contains at least an occurrence of each variable of u,

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 189: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

6.7 Bibliographic notes 189

• for any i, ui contains at least a non variable symbol,

• if two occurrences x′ and x′′ of a same variable x occur in ui, D(x′, x”, ui) < k.

Remark that LCF is included in H and that there is no right hand side of rule withtwo occurrences of the same variable associated with the same state. Prove that

1. LCF−1 ⊆ Delabeling−1 H

2. H Delabeling−1 ⊆ Delabeling−1 H

3. H ⊆ LCFB2

4. Conclude. Compare with Exercise 71

Exercise 81. Prove that the image of a recognizable tree language by a linear tree

transducer is recognizable.

6.7 Bibliographic notes

First of all, let us precise that several surveys have been devoted (at least inpart) to tree transducers for 25 years. J.W. Thatcher [Tha73], one of the mainpioneer, did the first one in 1973, and F. Gcseg and M. Steinby the last onein 1996 [GS96]. Transducers are formally studied too in the book of F. Gcsegand M. Steinby [GS84] and in the survey of J.-C. Raoult [Rao92]. Survey of M.Dauchet and S. Tison [DT92] develops links with homomorphisms.

In section 6.2, some examples are inspired by the old survey of Thatcher,because seminal motivation remain, namely modelization of compilers or, moregenerally, of syntax directed transformations as interfacing softwares, whichare always up to date. Among main precursors, we can distinguish Thatcher[Tha73], W.S. Brainerd [Bra69], A. Aho, J.D. Ullman [AU71], M. A. Arbib, E.G. Manes [AM78]. First approaches where very linked to practice of compilation,and in some way, present tree transducers are evolutions of generalized syntaxdirected translations (B.S. Backer [Bak78] for example), which translate treesinto strings. But crucial role of tree structure have increased later.

Many generalizations have been introduced, for example generalized finitestate transformations which generalize both the top-down and the bottom-uptree transducers (J. Engelfriet [Eng77]); modular tree transducers (H. Vogler[EV91]); synchronized tree automata (K. Salomaa [Sal94]); alternating tree au-tomata (G.Slutzki [Slu85]); deterministic top-down tree transducers with iter-ated look-ahead (G. Slutzki, S. Vgvlgyi [SV95]). Ground tree transducers GTTare studied in Chapter 3 of this book. The first and the most natural generaliza-tion was introduction of top-down tree transducers with look-ahead. We haveseen that “check and delete” property is specific to bottom-up tree transducers,and that missing of this property in the non-complete top-down case induces nonclosure under composition, even in the linear case (see Composition Theorem).Top-down transducers with regular look-ahead are able to recognize before theapplication of a rule at a node of an input tree whether the subtree at a son ofthis node belongs to a given recognizable tree language. This definition remainssimple and gives to top-down transducers a property equivalent to “check anddelete”.

Contribution of Engelfriet to the theory of tree transducers is important,especially for composition, decomposition and hierarchy main results ([Eng75,Eng78, Eng82]).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 190: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

190 Tree Transducers

We did not many discuss complexity and decidability in this chapter, becausethe situation is classical. Since many problems are undecidable in the wordcase, they are obviously undecidable in the tree case. Equivalence decidabilityholds as in the word case for deterministic or finite-valued tree transducers (Z.Zachar [Zac79], Z. Esik [Esi83], H. Seidl [Sei92, Sei94a]).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 191: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Chapter 7

Alternating Tree Automata

7.1 Introduction

Complementation of non-deterministic tree (or word) automata requires a deter-minization step. This is due to an asymmetry in the definition. Two transitionrules with the same left hand side can be seen as a single rule with a disjunctiveright side. A run of the automaton on a given tree has to choose some memberof the disjunction. Basically, determinization gathers the disjuncts in a singlestate.

Alternating automata restore some symmetry, allowing both disjunctionsand conjunctions in the right hand sides. Then complementation is much easier:it is sufficient to exchange the conjunctions and the disjunction signs, as well asfinal and non-final states. In particular, nothing similar to determinization isneeded.

This nice formalism is more concise. The counterpart is that decision prob-lems are more complex, as we will see in Section 7.5.

There are other nice features: for instance, if we see a tree automaton asa finite set of monadic Horn clauses, then moving from non-deterministic toalternating tree automata consists in removing a very simple assumption on theclauses. This is explained in Section 7.6. In the same vein, removing anothersimple assumption yields two-way alternating tree automata, a more powerfuldevice (yet not more expressive), as described in Section 7.6.3.

Finally, we also show in Section 7.2.3 that, as far as emptiness is concerned,tree automata correspond to alternating word automata on a single-letter al-phabet, which shows the relationship between computations (runs) of a wordalternating automaton and computations of a tree automaton.

7.2 Definitions and Examples

7.2.1 Alternating Word Automata

Let us start first with alternating word automata.If Q is a finite set of states, B+(Q) is the set of positive propositional formulas

over the set of propositional variables Q. For instance, q1∧ (q2∨q3)∧ (q2∨q4) ∈B+(q1, q2, q3, q4).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 192: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

192 Alternating Tree Automata

Alternating word automata are defined as deterministic word automata, ex-cept that the transition function is a mapping from Q×A to B+(Q) instead ofbeing a mapping from Q×A to Q. We assume a subset Q0 of Q of initial statesand a subset Qf of Q of final states.

Example 59. Assume that the alphabet is 0, 1 and the set of states isq0, q1, q2, q3, q4, q

′1, q

′2, Q0 = q0, Qf = q0, q1, q2, q3, q4 and the transitions

are:q00 → (q0 ∧ q1) ∨ q′1 q01 → q0

q10 → q2 q11 → trueq20 → q3 q21 → q3

q30 → q4 q31 → q4

q40 → true q41 → trueq′10 → q′1 q′11 → q′2q′20 → q′2 q′21 → q′1

A run of an alternating word automaton A on a word w is a finite tree ρlabeled with Q × N such that:

• The root of ρ is labeled by some pair (q, 0).

• If ρ(p) = (q, i) and i is strictly smaller than the length of w, w(i + 1) = a,δ(q, a) = φ, then there is a set S = q1, . . . , qn of states such that S |= φ,positions p1, . . . , pn are the successor positions of p in ρ and ρ(pj) =(qj , i + 1) for every j = 1, ...n.

The notion of satisfaction used here is the usual one in propositional calculus:the set S is the set of propositions assigned to true, while the propositions notbelonging to S are assumed to be assigned to false. Therefore, we have thefollowing:

• there is no run on w such that w(i + 1) = a for some i, ρ(p) = (q, i) andδ(q, i) = false

• if δ(q, w(i + 1)) = true and ρ(p) = (q, i), then p can be a leaf node, inwhich case it is called a success node.

• All leaf nodes are either success nodes as above or labeled with some (q, n)such that n is the length of w.

A run of an alternating automaton is successful on w if and only if

• all leaf nodes are either success nodes or labeled with some (q, n), wheren is the length of w, such that q ∈ Qf .

• the root node ρ(ε) = (q0, 0) with q0 ∈ Q0.

Example 60. Let us come back to Example 59. We show on Figure 7.1 tworuns on the word 00101, one of which is successful.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 193: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

7.2 Definitions and Examples 193

0

0

1

1

0

q0, 2 q1, 2

q’2q′2, 5

q0, 3

q0, 5

q0, 1

q2, 2

q3, 3

q4, 4

q1, 1q0, 1

q0, 2 q1, 2 q2, 2

q3, 3

q4, 4q0, 4 q1, 4

q1, 1

q0, 3

q′1, 4

q0, 0 q0, 0

Figure 7.1: Two runs on the word 00101 of the automaton defined in Exam-ple 59. The right one is successful.

Note that non-deterministic automata are the particular case of alternatingautomata in which only disjunctions (no conjunctions) occur in the transitionrelation. In such a case, if there is a succesful run on w, then there is also asuccessful run, which is a string.

Note also that, in the definition of a run, we can always choose the set S tobe a minimal satisfaction set: if there is a successful run of the automaton, thenthere is a successful one in which we always choose a minimal set S of states.

7.2.2 Alternating Tree Automata

Now, let us switch to alternating tree automata: the definitions are simpleadaptations of the previous ones.

Definition 14. An alternating tree automaton over F is a tuple A = (Q,F , I,∆)where Q is a set of states, I ⊆ Q is a set of initial states and ∆ is a mappingfrom Q×F to B+(Q×N) such that ∆(q, f) ∈ B+(Q×1, . . . ,Arity(f)) whereArity(f) is the arity of f .

Note that this definition corresponds to a top-down automaton, which ismore convenient in the alternating case.

Definition 15. Given a term t ∈ T (F) and an alternating tree automaton Aon F , a run of A on t is a tree ρ on Q × N

∗ such that ρ(ε) = (q, ε) for somestate q and

if ρ(π) = (q, p), t(p) = f and δ(q, f) = φ, then there is a subset S =(q1, i1), . . . , (qn, in) of Q × 1, . . . ,Arity(f) such that S |= φ, thesuccessor positions of π in ρ are π1, . . . , πn and ρ(π ·j) = (qj , p·ij)for every j = 1..n.

A run ρ is successful if ρ(ε) = (q, ε) for some initial state q ∈ I.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 194: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

194 Alternating Tree Automata

Note that (completely specified) non-deterministic top-down tree automataare the particular case of alternating tree automata. For a set of non-deterministicrules q(f(x1, . . . , xn)) → f(q1(x1), . . . , qn(xn)), Delta(q, f) is defined by:

∆(q, f) =∨

(q1,...,qn)∈S

Arity(f)∧

i=1

(qi, i)

Example 61. Consider the automaton on the alphabet f(, ), a, b whosetransition relation is defined by:

∆ f a bq2 [((q1, 1) ∧ (q2, 2)) ∨ ((q1, 2) ∧ (q2, 1))] ∧ (q4, 1) true falseq1 ((q2, 1) ∧ (q2, 2)) ∨ ((q1, 2) ∧ (q1, 1)) false trueq4 ((q3, 1) ∧ (q3, 2)) ∨ ((q4, 1) ∧ (q4, 2)) true trueq3 ((q3, 1) ∧ (q2, 2)) ∨ ((q4, 1) ∧ (q1, 2)) ∧ (q5, 1)) false trueq5 false true false

Assume I = q2. A run of the automaton on the term t = f(f(b, f(a, b)), b).is depicted on Figure 7.2.

In the case of a non-deterministic top-down tree automaton, the differentnotions of a run coincide as, in such a case, the run obtained from Definition 15on a tree t is a tree whose set of positions is the set of positions of t, possiblychanging the ordering of sons.

Words over an alphabet A can be seen as trees over the set of unary functionsymbols A and an additional constant #. For convenience, we read the wordsfrom right to left. For instance, aaba is translate into the tree a(b(a(a(#)))).Then an alternating word automaton A can be seen as an alternating treeautomaton whose initial states are the final states of A, the transitions are thesame and there is additional rules δ(q0,#) = true for the initial state q0 of Aand δ(q,#) = false for other states.

7.2.3 Tree Automata versus Alternating Word Automata

It is interesting to remark that, guessing the input tree, it is possible to reducethe emptiness problem for (non-deterministic, bottom-up) tree automata tothe emptiness problem for an alternating word automaton on a single letteralphabet: assume that A = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) is a non-deterministic tree automaton,then construct the alternating word automaton on a one letter alphabet a asfollows: the states are Q × F , the initial states are Qf × F and the transitionrules:

δ((q, f), a) =∨

f(q1,...,qn)→q∈∆

n∧

i=1

fj∈F

((qi, fj), i)

Conversely, it is also possible to reduce the emptiness problem for an alter-nating word automaton over a one letter alphabet a to the emptiness prob-lem of non-deterministic tree automata, introducing a new function symbol foreach conjunction; assume the formulas in disjunctive normal form (this can

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 195: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

7.2 Definitions and Examples 195

f

f b

b f

a b

q2,ε

q2,1 q4,1 q1,2

q1,11 q2,12 q4,11 q3,11 q3,12

q4,121 q2,121 q1,122 q5,121 q4,121 q1,122

Figure 7.2: A run of an alternating tree automaton

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 196: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

196 Alternating Tree Automata

be assumed w.l.o.g, see Exercise 82), then replace each transition δ(q, a) =∨ni=1

∧ki

j=1(qi,j , i) with fi(qi,1, . . . , qi,ki) → q.

7.3 Closure Properties

One nice feature of alternating automata is that it is very easy to perform theBoolean operations (for short, we confuse here the automaton and the languagerecognized by the automaton). First, we show that we can consider automatawith only one initial state, without loss of generality.

Lemma 10. Given an alternating tree automaton A, we can compute in lineartime an automaton A′ with only one initial state and which accepts the samelanguage as A.

Proof. Add one state q0 to A, which will become the only initial state, and thetransitions:

δ(q0, f) =∨

q∈I

δ(q, f)

Proposition 47. Union, intersection and complement of alternating tree au-tomata can be performed in linear time.

Proof. We consider w.l.o.g. automata with only one initial state. Given A1 andA2, with a disjoint set of states, we compute an automaton A whose states arethose of A1 and A2 and one additional state q0. Transitions are those of A1

and A2 plus the additional transitions for the union:

δ(q0, f) = δ1(q01 , f) ∨ δ2(q

02 , f)

where q01 , q0

2 are the initial states of A1 and A2 respectively. For the intersection,we add instead the transitions:

δ(q0, f) = δ1(q01 , f) ∧ δ2(q

02 , f)

Concerning the complement, we simply exchange ∧ and ∨ (resp. true and

false) in the transitions. The resulting automaton A will be called the dualautomaton in what follows.

The proof that these constructions are correct for union and intersection areleft to the reader. Let us only consider here the complement.

We prove, by induction on the size of t that, for every state q, t is acceptedeither by A or A in state q and not by both automata.

If t is a constant a, then δ(q, a) is either true or false. If δ(q, a) = true,

then δ(q, a) = false and t is accepted by A and not by A. The other case issymmetric.

Assume now that t = f(t1, . . . , tn) and δ(q, f) = φ. Let S be the set ofpairs (qj , ij) such that tij

is accepted from state qj by A. t is accepted by A, iff

S |= φ. Let S be the complement of S in Q × [1..n]. By induction hypothesis,

(qj , i) ∈ S iff ti is accepted in state qj by A.

We show that S |= φ iff S 6|= φ. (φ is the dual formula, obtained by ex-changing ∧ and ∨ on one hand and true and false on the other hand in φ). We

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 197: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

7.4 From Alternating to Deterministic Automata 197

show this by induction on the size of φ: if φ is true (resp. false), then S |= φ

and S 6|= φ (resp. S = ∅) and the result is proved. Now, let, φ be, e.g., φ1 ∧ φ2.S 6|= φ iff either S 6|= φ1 or S 6|= φ2, which, by induction hypothesis, is equivalent

to S |= φ1 or S |= φ2. By construction, this is equivalent to S |= φ. The caseφ = φ1 ∨ φ2 is similar.

Now t is accepted in state q by A iff S |= φ iff S 6|= φ iff t not accepted in

state q by A.

7.4 From Alternating to Deterministic Automata

The expressive power of alternating automata is exactly the same as finite(bottom-up) tree automata.

Theorem 54. If A is an alternating tree automaton, then there is a finitedeterministic bottom-up tree automaton A′ which accepts the same language.A′ can be computed from A in deterministic exponential time.

Proof. Assume A = (Q,F , I,∆), then A′ = (2Q,F , Qf , δ) where Qf = S ∈2Q | S ∩ I 6= ∅ and δ is defined as follows:

f(S1, . . . , Sn) → q ∈ Q | S1 × 1 ∪ . . . ∪ Sn × n |= ∆(q, f)

A term t is accepted by A′ in state S iff t is accepted by A in all states q ∈ S.This is proved by induction on the size of t: if t is a constant, then t is accepted inall states q such that ∆(q, t) = true. Now, if t = f(t1, . . . , tn) we let S1, . . . , Sn

are the set of states in which t1, . . . , tn are respectively accepted by A. t isaccepted by A in a state q iff there is S0 ⊆ Q×1, . . . , n such that S0 |= ∆(q, f)and, for every pair (qi, j) ∈ S0, tj is accepted in qi. In other words, t is acceptedby A in state q iff there is an S0 ⊆ S1×1∪. . .∪Sn×n such that S0 |= ∆(q, f),which is in turn equivalent to S1 ×1∪ . . .∪Sn ×n |= ∆(q, f). We concludeby an application of the induction hypothesis.

Unfortunately the exponential blow-up is unavoidable, as a consequence ofProposition 47 and Theorems 14 and 11.

7.5 Decision Problems and Complexity Issues

Theorem 55. The emptiness problem and the universality problem for alter-nating tree automata are DEXPTIME-complete.

Proof. The DEXPTIME membership is a consequence of Theorems 11 and 54.

The DEXPTIME-hardness is a consequence of Proposition 47 and Theo-rem 14.

The membership problem (given t and A, is t accepted by A ?) can bedecided in polynomial time. This is left as an exercise.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 198: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

198 Alternating Tree Automata

7.6 Horn Logic, Set Constraints and Alternat-ing Automata

7.6.1 The Clausal Formalism

Viewing every state q as a unary predicate symbol Pq, tree automata can betranslated into Horn clauses in such a way that the language recognized in stateq is exactly the interpretation of Pq in the least Herbrand model of the set ofclauses.

There are several advantages of this point of view:

• Since the logical setting is declarative, we don’t have to distinguish be-tween top-down and bottom-up automata. In particular, we have a defi-nition of bottom-up alternating automata for free.

• Alternation can be expressed in a simple way, as well as push and popoperations, as described in the next section.

• There is no need to define a run (which would correspond to a proof inthe logical setting)

• Several decision properties can be translated into decidability problems forsuch clauses. Typically, since all clauses belong to the monadic fragment,there are decision procedures e.g. relying on ordered resolution strategies.

There are also weaknesses: complexity issues are harder to study in thissetting. Many constructive proofs, and complexity results have been obtainedwith tree automata techniques.

Tree automata can be translated into Horn clauses. With a tree automatonA = (Q,F , Qf ,∆) is associated the following set of Horn clauses:

Pq(f(x1, . . . , xn)) ← Pq1(x1), . . . , Pqn

(xn)

if f(q1, . . . , qn) → q ∈ ∆. The language accepted by the automaton is the unionof interpretations of Pq, for q ∈ Qf , in the least Herbrand model of clauses.

Also, alternating tree automata can be translated into Horn clauses. Alter-nation can be expressed by variable sharing in the body of the clause. Con-sider an alternating tree automaton (Q,F , I,∆). Assume that the transi-tions are in disjunctive normal form (see Exercise 82). With a transition

∆(q, f) =∨m

i=1

∧ki

j=1(qj , ij) is associated the clauses

Pq(f(x1, . . . , xn)) ←ki∧

j=1

Pqj(xij

)

We can also add ε-transitions, by allowing clauses

P (x) ← Q(x)

In such a setting, automata with equality constraints between brothers,which are studied in Section 4.3, are simply an extension of the above classof Horn clauses, in which we allow repeated variables in the head of the clause.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 199: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

7.6 Horn Logic, Set Constraints and Alternating Automata 199

Allowing variable repetition in an arbitrary way, we get alternating automatawith contraints between brothers, a class of automata for which emptiness isdecidable in deterministic exponential time. (It is expressible in Lwenheim’sclass with equality, also called sometimes the monadic class).

Still, for tight complexity bounds, for closure properties (typically by com-plementation) of automata with equality tests between brothers, we refer toSection 4.3. Note that it is not easy to derive the complexity results obtainedwith tree automata techniques in a logical framework.

7.6.2 The Set Constraints Formalism

We introduced and studied general set constraints in Chapter 5. Set constraintsand, more precisely, definite set constraints provide with an alternative descrip-tion of tree automata.

Definite set constraints are conjunctions of inclusions

e ⊆ t

where e is a set expression built using function application, intersection andvariables and t is a term set expression, constructed using function applicationand variables only.

Given an assignment σ of variables to subsets of T (F), we can interpret theset expressions as follows:

[[f(e1, . . . , en)]]σdef= f(t1, . . . , tn) | ti ∈ [[ei]]σ

[[e1 ∩ e2]]σdef= [[e1]]σ ∩ [[e2]]σ

[[X]]σdef= Xσ

Then σ is a solution of a set constraint if inclusions hold for the correspondinginterpretation of expressions.

When we restrict the left members of inclusions to variables, we get an-other formalism for alternating tree automata: such set constraints have alwaysa least solution, which is accepted by an alternating tree automaton. Moreprecisely, we can use the following translation from the alternating automatonA = (Q,F , I,∆): assume again that the transitions are in disjunctive normalform (see Exercise 82) and construct, the inclusion constraints

f(X1,f,q,d, . . . ,Xn,f,q,d) ⊆ Xq

(q′,j)∈d

Xq′ ⊆ Xj,f,q,d

for every (q, f) ∈ Q × F and d a disjunct of ∆(q, f). (An intersection over anempty set has to be understood as the set of all trees).

Then, the language recognized by the alternating tree automaton is theunion, for q ∈ I, of Xqσ where σ is the least solution of the constraint.

Actually, we are constructing the constraint in exactly the same way as weconstructed the clauses in the previous section. When there is no alternation, weget an alternative definition of non-deterministic automata, which correspondsto the algebraic characterization of Chapter 2.

Conversely, if all right members of the definite set constraint are variables,it is not difficult to construct an alternating tree automaton which accepts theleast solution of the constraint (see Exercise 85).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 200: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

200 Alternating Tree Automata

7.6.3 Two Way Alternating Tree Automata

Definite set constraints look more expressive than alternating tree automata,because inclusions

X ⊆ f(Y,Z)

cannot be directly translated into automata rules.We define here two-way tree automata which will easily correspond to definite

set constraints on one hand and allow to simulate, e.g., the behavior of standardpushdown word automata.

It is convenient here to use the clausal formalism in order to define suchautomata. A clause

P (u) ← P1(x1), . . . , Pn(xn)

where u is a linear, non-variable term and x1, . . . , xn are (not necessarily dis-tinct) variables occurring in u, is called a push clause. A clause

P (x) ← Q(t)

where x is a variable and t is a linear term, is called a pop clause. A clause

P (x) ← P1(x), . . . , Pn(x)

is called an alternating clause (or an intersection clause).

Definition 16. An alternating two-way tree automaton is a tuple (Q,Qf ,F , C)where Q is a finite set of unary function symbols, Qf is a subset of Q and C is afinite set of clauses each of which is a push clause, a pop clause or an alternatingclause.

Such an automaton accepts a tree t if t belongs to the interpretation of someP ∈ Qf in the least Herbrand model of the clauses.

Example 62. Consider the following alternating two-way automaton on thealphabet F = a, f(, ):

1. P1(f(f(x1, x2), x3)) ← P2(x1), P2(x2), P2(x3)2. P2(a)3. P1(f(a, x)) ← P2(x)4. P3(f(x, y)) ← P1(x), P2(y)5. P4(x) ← P3(x), P1(x)6. P2(x) ← P4(f(x, y))7. P1(y) ← P4(f(x, y))

The clauses 1,2,3,4 are push clauses. Clause 5 is an alternating clause andclauses 6,7 are pop clauses.

If we compute the least Herbrand model, we successively get for the five firststeps:

step 1 2 3 4 5

P1 f(a, a), f(f(a, a), a) a

P2 a f(a, a)

P3 f(f(a, a), a), f(f(f(a, a), a), a)

P4 f(f(a, a), a)

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 201: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

7.6 Horn Logic, Set Constraints and Alternating Automata 201

These automata are often convenient in expressing some problems (see theexercises and bibliographic notes). However they do not increase the expressivepower of (alternating) tree automata:

Theorem 56. For every alternating two-way tree automaton, it is possible tocompute in deterministic exponential time a tree automaton which accepts thesame language.

We do not prove the result here (see the bibliographic notes instead). Asimple way to compute the equivalent tree automaton is as follows: first flat-ten the clauses, introducing new predicate symbols. Then saturate the set ofclauses, using ordered resolution (w.r.t. subterm ordering) and keeping onlynon-subsumed clauses. The saturation process terminates in exponential time.The desired automaton is obtained by simply keeping only the push clauses ofthis resulting set of clauses.

Example 63. Let us come back to Example 62 and show how we get an equiv-alent finite tree automaton.

First flatten the clauses: Clause 1 becomes

1. P1(f(x, y)) ← P5(x), P2(y)8. P5(f(x, y)) ← P2(x), P2(y)

Now we start applying resolution;

From 4 + 5: 9. P4(f(x, y)) ← P1(x), P2(y), P1(f(x, y))Form 9 + 6: 10. P2(x) ← P1(x), P2(y)From 10 + 2: 11. P2(x) ← P1(x)

Clause 11 subsumes 10, which is deleted.

From 9 + 7: 12. P1(y) ← P1(x), P2(y)From 12 +1: 13. P1(y) ← P2(y), P5(x), P2(z)From 13 + 8: 14. P1(y) ← P2(y), P2(x1), P2(x2), P2(z)

Clause 14. can be simplified and, by superposition with 2. we get

From 14 + 2: 15. P1(y) ← P2(y)

At this stage, from 11. and 15. we have P1(x) ↔ P2(x), hence, for simplicity,we will only consider P1, replacing every occurrence of P2 with P1.

From 1 +5: 16. P4(f(x, y)) ← P3(f(x, y)), P5(x), P1(y)From 1 + 9: 17. P4(f(x, y)) ← P1(x), P1(y), P5(x)From 2 +5: 18. P4(a) ← P3(a)From 3 +5: 19. P4(f(a, x)) ← P3(f(a, x)), P1(x)From 3+ 9: 20. P4(f(a, x)) ← P1(x), P1(a)From 2 + 20: 21. P4(f(a, x)) ← P1(x)

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 202: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

202 Alternating Tree Automata

Clause 21. subsumes both 20 and 19. These two clauses are deleted.

From 5 + 6: 22. P1(x) ← P3(f(x, y)), P1(f(x, y))From 5 +7: 23. P1(y) ← P3(f(x, y)), P1(f(x, y))From 16 + 6: 24. P1(x) ← P3(f(x, y)), P5(x), P1(y)From 23 +1: 25. P1(y) ← P3(f(x, y)), P5(x), P1(y)

Now every new inference yields a redundant clause and the saturation termi-nates, yielding the automaton:

1. P1(f(x, y)) ← P5(x), P2(y)2. P1(a)3. P1(f(a, x)) ← P1(x)4. P3(f(x, y)) ← P1(x), P1(y)8. P5(f(x, y)) ← P1(x), P1(y)11. P1(x) ← P1(y)15. P2(x) ← P1(x)21. P4(f(a, x)) ← P1(x)

Of course, this automaton can be simplified: P1 and P2 accept all terms inT (F).

It follows from Theorems 56, 55 and 11 that the emptiness problem (resp.universality problems) are DEXPTIME-complete for two-way alternating au-tomata.

7.6.4 Two Way Automata and Definite Set Constraints

There is a simple reduction of two-way automata to definite set constraints:A push clause P (f(x1, . . . , xn)) ← P1(xi1), . . . , Pn(xin

) corresponds to aninclusion constraint

f(e1, . . . , en) ⊆ XP

where each ej is the intersection, for ik = j of the variables XPk. A (conditional)

pop clause P (xi) ← Q(f(x1, . . . , xn)), P1(x1), . . . Pk(xk) corresponds to

f(e1, . . . , en) ∩ XQ ⊆ f(>, . . . ,XP ,>, . . .)

where, again, each ej is the intersection, for ik = j of the variables XPkand > is a

variable containing all term expressions. Intersection clauses P (x) ← Q(x), R(x)correspond to constraints

XQ ∩ XR ⊆ XP

Conversely, we can translate the definite set constraints into two-way au-tomata, with additional restrictions on some states. We cannot do better sincea definite set constraint could be unsatisfiable.

Introducing auxiliary variables, we only have to consider constraints:

1. f(X1, . . . ,Xn) ⊆ X,

2. X1 ∩ . . . ∩ Xn ⊆ X,

3. X ⊆ f(X1, . . . ,Xn).

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 203: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

7.7 An (other) example of application 203

The first constraints are translated to push clauses, the second kind of con-straints is translated to intersection clauses. Consider the last constraints. Itcan be translated into the pop clauses:

PXi(xi) ← PX(f(x1, . . . , xn))

with the provision that all terms in PX are headed with f .Then the procedure which solves definite set constraints is essentially the

same as the one we sketched for the proof of Theorem 56, except that we haveto add unit negative clauses which may yield failure rules

Example 64. Consider the definite set constraint

f(X,Y ) ∩ X ⊆ f(Y,X), f(a, Y ) ⊆ X, a ⊆ Y, f(f(Y, Y ), Y ) ⊆ X

Starting from this constraint, we get the clauses of Example 62, with the addi-tional restriction

26. ¬P4(a)

since every term accepted in P4 has to be headed with f .If we saturate this constraint as in Example 63, we get the same clauses, of

course, but also negative clauses resulting from the new negative clause:

From 26 + 18 27. ¬P3(a)

And that is all: the constraint is satisfiable, with a minimal solution describedby the automaton resulting from the computation of Example 63.

7.6.5 Two Way Automata and Pushdown Automata

Two-way automata, though related to pushdown automata, are quite differ-ent. In fact, for every pushdown automaton, it is easy to construct a two-wayautomaton which accepts the possible contents of the stack (see Exercise 86).However, two-way tree (resp. word) automata have the same expressive poweras standard tree (resp. word) automata: they only accept regular languages,while pushdown automata accept context-free languages, which strictly containregular languages.

Note still that, as a corollary of Theorem 56, the language of possible stackcontents in a pushdown automaton is regular.

7.7 An (other) example of application

Two-way automata naturally arise in the analysis of cryptographic protocols.In this context, terms are constructed using the function symbols (binaryencryption symbols), < , > (pairing) and constants (and other symbols whichare irrelevant here). The so-called Dolev-Yao model consists in the deductionrules of Figure 7.3, which express the capabilities of an intruder. For simplicity,we only consider here symmetric encryption keys, but there are similar rules forpublic key cryptosystems. The rules basically state that an intruder can encrypt

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 204: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

204 Alternating Tree Automata

Pairingu v

< u, v >Encryption

u v

uv

Unpairing L< u, v >

uUnpairing R

< u, v >

v

Decryptionuv v

u

Figure 7.3: The Dolev-Yao intruder capabilities

a known message with a known key, can decrypt a known message encryptedwith k, provided he knows k and can form and decompose pairs.

It is easy to construct a two-way automaton which, given a regular set ofterms R, accepts the set of terms that can be derived by an intruder using therules of Figure 7.3 (see Exercise 87).

7.8 Exercises

Exercise 82. Show that, for every alternating tree automaton, it is possible to com-pute in polynomial time an alternating tree automaton which accepts the same lan-guage and whose transitions are in disjunctive normal form, i.e. each transition hasthe form

δ(q, f) =

m_

i=1

ki

j=1

(qj , lj)

Exercise 83. Show that the membership problem for alternating tree automata can

be decided in polynomial time.

Exercise 84. An alternating automaton is weak if there is an ordering on the set ofstates such that, for every state q and every function symbol f , every state q′ occurringin δ(q, f) satisfies q′ ≤ q.

Prove that the emptiness of weak alternating tree automata is in PTIME.

Exercise 85. Given a definite set constraint whose all right hand sides are variables,

show how to construct (in polynomial time) k alternating tree automata which accept

respectively X1σ, . . . , Xkσ where σ is the least solution of the constraint.

Exercise 86. A pushdown automaton on words is a tuple (Q, Qf , A, Γ, δ) where Q isa finite set of states, Qf ⊆ Q, A is a finite alphabet of input symbols, Γ is a finitealphabet of stack symbols and δ is a transition relation defined by rules: qa

w−→ q′

and qaw−1

−−−→ q′ where q, q′ ∈ Q, a ∈ A and w, w′ ∈ Γ∗.

A configuration is a pair of a state and a word γ ∈ Γ∗. The automaton may movewhen reading a, from (q, γ) to (q′, γ′) if either there is a transition qa

w−→ q′ and

γ′ = w · γ or there is a transition qaw−1

−−−→ q′ and γ = w · γ′.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 205: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

7.9 Bibliographic Notes 205

1. Show how to compute (in polynomial time) a two-way automaton which acceptsw in state q iff the configuration (q, w) is reachable.

2. This can be slightly generalized considering alternating pushdown automata:

now assume that the transitions are of the form: qaw−→ φ and qa

w−1

−−−→ φ

where φ ∈ B+(Q). Give a definition of a run and of an accepted word, which isconsistent with both the definition of a pushdown automaton and the definitionof an alternating automaton.

3. Generalize the result of the first question to alternating pushdown automata.

4. Generalize previous questions to tree automata.

Exercise 87. Given a finite tree automaton A over the alphabet a, , < , >,construct a two-way tree automaton which accepts the set of terms t which can bededuced by the rule of Figure 7.3 and the rule

tIf t is accepted by A

7.9 Bibliographic Notes

Alternation has been considered for a long time as a computation model, e.g. forTuring machines. The seminal work in this area is [CKS81], in which the rela-tionship between complexity classes defined using (non)-deterministic machinesand alternating machines is studied.

Concerning tree automata, alternation has been mainly considered in thecase of infinite trees. This is especially useful to keep small representationsof automata associated with temporal logic formulas, yielding optimal model-checking algorithms [KVW00].

Two-way automata and their relationship with clauses have been first consid-ered in [FSVY91] for the analysis of logic programs. They also occur naturallyin the context of definite set constraints, as we have seen (the completion mecha-nisms are presented in, e.g., [HJ90a, CP97]), and in the analysis of cryptographicprotocols [Gou00].

There several other definitions of two-way tree automata. We can distinguishbetween two-way automata which have the same expressive power as regularlanguages and what we refer here to pushdown automata, whose expressivepower is beyond regularity.

Decision procedures based on ordered resolution strategies could be foundin [Jr.76].

Alternating automata with contraints between brothers define a class oflanguages expressible in Lwenheim’s class with equality, also called sometimesthe monadic class. See for instance [BGG97].

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 206: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata
Page 207: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Bibliography

[AD82] A. Arnold and M. Dauchet. Morphismes et bimorphismes d’arbres.Theorical Computer Science, 20:33–93, 1982.

[AG68] M. A. Arbib and Y. Give’on. Algebra automata I: Parallel program-ming as a prolegomena to the categorical approach. Informationand Control, 12(4):331–345, April 1968.

[AKVW93] A. Aiken, D. Kozen, M. Vardi, and E. Wimmers. The complex-ity of set constraints. In E. Borger, Y. Gurevich, and K. Meinke,editors, Proceedings of Computer Science Logic, volume 832 of Lec-ture Notes in Computer Science, pages 1–17, 1993. Techn. Report93-1352, Cornell University.

[AKW95] A. Aiken, D. Kozen, and E.L. Wimmers. Decidability of systemsof set constraints with negative constraints. Information and Com-putation, 122(1):30–44, October 1995.

[AM78] M.A. Arbib and E.G. Manes. Tree transformations and semanticsof loop-free programs. Acta Cybernetica, 4:11–17, 1978.

[AM91] A. Aiken and B. R. Murphy. Implementing regular tree expressions.In Proceedings of the ACM conf. on Functional Programming Lan-guages and Computer Architecture, pages 427–447, 1991.

[AU71] A. V. Aho and J. D. Ullmann. Translations on a context-free gram-mar. Information and Control, 19:439–475, 1971.

[AW92] A. Aiken and E.L. Wimmers. Solving Systems of Set Constraints.In Proceedings, Seventh Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Com-puter Science [IEE92], pages 329–340.

[Bak78] B.S. Baker. Generalized syntax directed translation, tree transduc-ers, and linear space. Journal of Comput. and Syst. Sci., 7:876–891,1978.

[BGG97] E. Borger, E. Gradel, and Y. Gurevich. The Classical DecisionProblem. Perspectives of Mathematical Logic. Springer Verlag,1997.

[BGW93] L. Bachmair, H. Ganzinger, and U. Waldmann. Set constraints arethe monadic class. In Proceedings, Eighth Annual IEEE Sympo-sium on Logic in Computer Science, pages 75–83. IEEE ComputerSociety Press, 19–23 June 1993.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 208: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

208 BIBLIOGRAPHY

[BJ97] A. Bouhoula and J.-P. Jouannaud. Automata-driven automatedinduction. In Proceedings, 12th Annual IEEE Symposium on Logicin Computer Science [IEE97].

[BKMW01] A. Brggemann-Klein, M.Murata, and D. Wood. Regular tree andregular hedge languages over unranked alphabets. Technical ReportHKTUST-TCSC-2001-05, HKUST Theoretical Computer ScienceCenter Research, 2001.

[Boz99] S. Bozapalidis. Equational elements in additive algebras. Theoryof Computing Systems, 32(1):1–33, 1999.

[Boz01] S. Bozapalidis. Context-free series on trees. ICOMP, 169(2):186–229, 2001.

[BR82] Jean Berstel and Christophe Reutenauer. Recognizable formalpower series on trees. TCS, 18:115–148, 1982.

[Bra68] W. S. Brainerd. The minimalization of tree automata. Informationand Control, 13(5):484–491, November 1968.

[Bra69] W. S. Brainerd. Tree generating regular systems. Information andControl, 14(2):217–231, February 1969.

[BT92] B. Bogaert and S. Tison. Equality and disequality constraints ondirect subterms in tree automata. In A. Finkel and M. Jantzen, ed-itors, 9th Annual Symposium on Theoretical Aspects of ComputerScience, volume 577 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pages161–171, 1992.

[Buc60] J. R. Buchi. On a decision method in a restricted second orderarithmetic. In Stanford Univ. Press., editor, Proc. Internat. Congr.on Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, pages 1–11, 1960.

[CCC+94] A.-C. Caron, H. Comon, J.-L. Coquide, M. Dauchet, and F. Jacque-mard. Pumping, cleaning and symbolic constraints solving. In Pro-ceedings, International Colloquium Automata Languages and Pro-gramming, volume 820 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pages436–449, 1994.

[CD94] H. Comon and C. Delor. Equational formulae with membershipconstraints. Information and Computation, 112(2):167–216, Au-gust 1994.

[CDGV94] J.-L. Coquide, M. Dauchet, R. Gilleron, and S. Vagvolgyi. Bottom-up tree pushdown automata : Classification and connection withrewrite systems. Theorical Computer Science, 127:69–98, 1994.

[CG90] J.-L. Coquide and R. Gilleron. Proofs and reachability problemfor ground rewrite systems. In Proc. IMYCS’90, Smolenice Castle,Czechoslovakia, November 1990.

[Chu62] A. Church. Logic, arithmetic, automata. In Proc. InternationalMathematical Congress, 1962.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 209: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

BIBLIOGRAPHY 209

[CJ97a] H. Comon and F. Jacquemard. Ground reducibility is EXPTIME-complete. In Proceedings, 12th Annual IEEE Symposium on Logicin Computer Science [IEE97], pages 26–34.

[CJ97b] H. Comon and Y. Jurski. Higher-order matching and tree au-tomata. In M. Nielsen and W. Thomas, editors, Proc. Conf. onComputer Science Logic, volume 1414 of LNCS, pages 157–176,Aarhus, August 1997. Springer-Verlag.

[CK96] A. Cheng and D. Kozen. A complete Gentzen-style axiomatizationfor set constraints. In Proceedings, International Colloquium Au-tomata Languages and Programming, volume 1099 of Lecture Notesin Computer Science, pages 134–145, 1996.

[CKS81] A.K. Chandra, D.C. Kozen, and L.J. Stockmeyer. Alternation.Journal of the ACM, 28:114–133, 1981.

[Com89] H. Comon. Inductive proofs by specification transformations. InProceedings, Third International Conference on Rewriting Tech-niques and Applications, volume 355 of Lecture Notes in ComputerScience, pages 76–91, 1989.

[Com95] H. Comon. Sequentiality, second-order monadic logic and tree au-tomata. In Proceedings, Tenth Annual IEEE Symposium on Logicin Computer Science. IEEE Computer Society Press, 26–29 June1995.

[Com98a] H. Comon. Completion of rewrite systems with membership con-straints. Part I: deduction rules. Journal of Symbolic Computation,25:397–419, 1998. This is a first part of a paper whose abstract ap-peared in Proc. ICALP 92, Vienna.

[Com98b] H. Comon. Completion of rewrite systems with membership con-straints. Part II: Constraint solving. Journal of Symbolic Compu-tation, 25:421–453, 1998. This is the second part of a paper whoseabstract appeared in Proc. ICALP 92, Vienna.

[Cou86] B. Courcelle. Equivalences and transformations of regular systems–applications to recursive program schemes and grammars. Theori-cal Computer Science, 42, 1986.

[Cou89] B. Courcelle. On Recognizable Sets and Tree Automata, chapterResolution of Equations in Algebraic Structures. Academic Press,m. Nivat and Ait-Kaci edition, 1989.

[Cou92] B. Courcelle. Recognizable sets of unrooted trees. In M. Nivatand A. Podelski, editors, Tree Automata and Languages. ElsevierScience, 1992.

[CP94a] W. Charatonik and L. Pacholski. Negative set constraints withequality. In Proceedings, Ninth Annual IEEE Symposium on Logicin Computer Science, pages 128–136. IEEE Computer SocietyPress, 4–7 July 1994.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 210: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

210 BIBLIOGRAPHY

[CP94b] W. Charatonik and L. Pacholski. Set constraints with projectionsare in NEXPTIME. In Proceedings of the 35th Symp. Foundationsof Computer Science, pages 642–653, 1994.

[CP97] W. Charatonik and A. Podelski. Set Constraints with Intersec-tion. In Proceedings, 12th Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic inComputer Science [IEE97].

[Dau94] M. Dauchet. Rewriting and tree automata. In H. Comon and J.-P.Jouannaud, editors, Proc. Spring School on Theoretical ComputerScience: Rewriting, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Odeillo,France, 1994. Springer Verlag.

[DCC95] M. Dauchet, A.-C. Caron, and J.-L. Coquide. Reduction propertiesand automata with constraints. Journal of Symbolic Computation,20:215–233, 1995.

[DGN+98] A. Degtyarev, Y. Gurevich, P. Narendran, M. Veanes, andA. Voronkov. The decidability of simultaneous rigid e-unificationwith one variable. In T. Nipkow, editor, 9th International Con-ference on Rewriting Techniques and Applications, volume 1379 ofLecture Notes in Computer Science, 1998.

[DJ90] N. Dershowitz and J.-P. Jouannaud. Handbook of Theoretical Com-puter Science, volume B, chapter Rewrite Systems, pages 243–320.Elsevier, 1990.

[DM97] I. Durand and A. Middeldorp. Decidable call by need computationsin term rewriting. In W. McCune, editor, Proc. 14th Conference onAutomated Deduction, volume 1249 of Lecture Notes in ArtificialIntelligence, pages 4–18. Springer Verlag, 1997.

[Don65] J. E. Doner. Decidability of the weak second-order theory of twosuccessors. Notices Amer. Math. Soc., 12:365–468, March 1965.

[Don70] J. E. Doner. Tree acceptors and some of their applications. Journalof Comput. and Syst. Sci., 4:406–451, 1970.

[DT90] M. Dauchet and S. Tison. The theory of ground rewrite systemsis decidable. In Proceedings, Fifth Annual IEEE Symposium onLogic in Computer Science, pages 242–248. IEEE Computer Soci-ety Press, 4–7 June 1990.

[DT92] M. Dauchet and S. Tison. Structural complexity of classes of treelanguages. In M. Nivat and A. Podelski, editors, Tree Automataand Languages, pages 327–353. Elsevier Science, 1992.

[DTHL87] M. Dauchet, S. Tison, T. Heuillard, and P. Lescanne. Decidabilityof the confluence of ground term rewriting systems. In Proceed-ings, Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, pages 353–359.The Computer Society of the IEEE, 22–25 June 1987.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 211: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

BIBLIOGRAPHY 211

[DTT97] P. Devienne, J.-M. Talbot, and S. Tison. Solving classes of setconstraints with tree automata. In G. Smolka, editor, Proceedingsof the 3th International Conference on Principles and Practice ofConstraint Programming, volume 1330 of Lecture Notes in Com-puter Science, pages 62–76, oct 1997.

[Eng75] J. Engelfriet. Bottom-up and top-down tree transformations. acomparision. Mathematical System Theory, 9:198–231, 1975.

[Eng77] J. Engelfriet. Top-down tree transducers with regular look-ahead.Mathematical System Theory, 10:198–231, 1977.

[Eng78] J. Engelfriet. A hierarchy of tree transducers. In Proceedings of thethird Les Arbres en Algebre et en Programmation, pages 103–106,Lille, 1978.

[Eng82] J. Engelfriet. Three hierarchies of transducers. Mathematical Sys-tem Theory, 15:95–125, 1982.

[ES78] J. Engelfriet and E.M. Schmidt. IO and OI II. Journal of Comput.and Syst. Sci., 16:67–99, 1978.

[Esi83] Z. Esik. Decidability results concerning tree transducers. ActaCybernetica, 5:303–314, 1983.

[EV91] J. Engelfriet and H. Vogler. Modular tree transducers. TheoricalComputer Science, 78:267–303, 1991.

[EW67] S. Eilenberg and J. B. Wright. Automata in general algebras. In-formation and Control, 11(4):452–470, 1967.

[FSVY91] T. Fruhwirth, E. Shapiro, M. Vardi, and E. Yardeni. Logic pro-grams as types for logic programs. In Proc. 6th IEEE Symp. Logicin Computer Science, Amsterdam, pages 300–309, 1991.

[FV88] Z. Fulop and S. Vagvolgyi. A characterization of irreducible setsmodulo left-linear term rewiting systems by tree automata. Untype rr ??, Research Group on Theory of Automata, HungarianAcademy of Sciences, H-6720 Szeged, Somogyi u. 7. Hungary, 1988.

[FV89] Z. Fulop and S. Vagvolgyi. Congruential tree languages are thesame as recognizable tree languages–A proof for a theorem of D.kozen. Bulletin of the European Association of Theoretical Com-puter Science, 39, 1989.

[FV98] Z. Fulop and H. Vogler. Formal Models Based on Tree Transduc-ers. Monographs in Theoretical Computer Science. Springer Verlag,1998.

[GB85] J. H. Gallier and R. V. Book. Reductions in tree replacementsystems. Theorical Computer Science, 37(2):123–150, 1985.

[Gen97] T. Genet. Decidable approximations of sets of descendants andsets of normal forms - extended version. Technical Report RR-3325, Inria, Institut National de Recherche en Informatique et enAutomatique, 1997.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 212: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

212 BIBLIOGRAPHY

[GJV98] H. Ganzinger, F. Jacquemard, and M. Veanes. Rigid reachability.In Proc. ASIAN’98, volume 1538 of Lecture Notes in ComputerScience, pages 4–??, Berlin, 1998. Springer-Verlag.

[GMW97] H. Ganzinger, C. Meyer, and C. Weidenbach. Soft typing for or-dered resolution. In W. McCune, editor, Proc. 14th Conference onAutomated Deduction, volume 1249 of Lecture Notes in ArtificialIntelligence. Springer Verlag, 1997.

[Gou00] Jean Goubault-Larrecq. A method for automatic cryptographicprotocol verification. In Proc. 15 IPDPS 2000 Workshops, Can-cun, Mexico, May 2000, volume 1800 of Lecture Notes in ComputerScience, pages 977–984. Springer Verlag, 2000.

[GRS87] J. Gallier, S. Raatz, and W. Snyder. Theorem proving using rigidE-unification: Equational matings. In Proc. 2nd IEEE Symp. Logicin Computer Science, Ithaca, NY, June 1987.

[GS84] F. Gecseg and M. Steinby. Tree Automata. Akademiai Kiado, 1984.

[GS96] F. Gecseg and M. Steinby. Tree languages. In G. Rozenberg andA. Salomaa, editors, Handbook of Formal Languages, volume 3,pages 1–68. Springer Verlag, 1996.

[GT95] R. Gilleron and S. Tison. Regular tree languages and rewrite sys-tems. Fundamenta Informaticae, 24:157–176, 1995.

[GTT93] R. Gilleron, S. Tison, and M. Tommasi. Solving systems of setconstraints with negated subset relationships. In Proceedings ofthe 34th Symp. on Foundations of Computer Science, pages 372–380, 1993. Full version in the LIFL Tech. Rep. IT-247.

[GTT99] R. Gilleron, S. Tison, and M. Tommasi. Set constraints and au-tomata. Information and Control, 149:1 – 41, 1999.

[Gue83] I. Guessarian. Pushdowm tree automata. Mathematical SystemTheory, 16:237–264, 1983.

[Hei92] N. Heintze. Set Based Program Analysis. PhD thesis, CarnegieMellon University, 1992.

[HJ90a] N. Heintze and J. Jaffar. A Decision Procedure for a Class of SetConstraints. In Proceedings, Fifth Annual IEEE Symposium onLogic in Computer Science, pages 42–51. IEEE Computer SocietyPress, 4–7 June 1990.

[HJ90b] N. Heintze and J. Jaffar. A finite presentation theorem for approx-imating logic programs. In Proceedings of the 17th ACM Symp. onPrinciples of Programming Languages, pages 197–209, 1990. Fullversion in the IBM tech. rep. RC 16089 (#71415).

[HJ92] N. Heintze and J. Jaffar. An engine for logic program analysis. InProceedings, Seventh Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Com-puter Science [IEE92], pages 318–328.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 213: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

BIBLIOGRAPHY 213

[HL91] G. Huet and J.-J. Levy. Computations in orthogonal rewritingsystems I. In J.-L. Lassez and G. Plotkin, editors, ComputationalLogic: Essays in Honor of Alan Robinson, pages 395–414. MITPress, 1991. This paper was written in 1979.

[HU79] J. E. Hopcroft and J. D. Ullman. Introduction to Automata Theory,Languages, and Computation. Addison Wesley, 1979.

[IEE92] IEEE Computer Society Press. Proceedings, Seventh Annual IEEESymposium on Logic in Computer Science, 22–25 June 1992.

[IEE97] IEEE Computer Society Press. Proceedings, 12th Annual IEEESymposium on Logic in Computer Science, 1997.

[Jac96] F. Jacquemard. Decidable approximations of term rewriting sys-tems. In H. Ganzinger, editor, Proceedings. Seventh InternationalConference on Rewriting Techniques and Applications, volume 1103of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 1996.

[JM79] N. D. Jones and S. S. Muchnick. Flow Analysis and Optimizationof LISP-like Structures. In Proceedings of the 6th ACM Symposiumon Principles of Programming Languages, pages 244–246, 1979.

[Jon87] N. Jones. Abstract interpretation of declarative languages, chapterFlow analysis of lazy higher-order functional programs, pages 103–122. Ellis Horwood Ltd, 1987.

[Jr.76] William H. Joyner Jr. Resolution strategies as decision procedures.Journal of the ACM, 23(3):398–417, 1976.

[KFK97] Y. Kaji, T. Fujiwara, and T. Kasami. Solving a unification problemunder constrained substitutions using tree automata. Journal ofSymbolic Computation, 23(1):79–118, January 1997.

[Koz92] D. Kozen. On the Myhill-Nerode theorem for trees. Bulletin ofthe European Association of Theoretical Computer Science, 47:170–173, June 1992.

[Koz93] D. Kozen. Logical aspects of set constraints. In E. Borger, Y. Gure-vich, and K. Meinke, editors, Proceedings of Computer ScienceLogic, volume 832 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pages175–188, 1993.

[Koz95] D. Kozen. Rational spaces and set constraints. In Proceedings ofthe 6th International Joint Conference on Theory and Practice ofSoftware Development, volume 915 of Lecture Notes in ComputerScience, pages 42–61, 1995.

[Koz98] D. Kozen. Set constraints and logic programming. Informationand Computation, 142(1):2–25, 1998.

[Kuc91] G. A. Kucherov. On relationship between term rewriting systemsand regular tree languages. In R. Book, editor, Proceedings. FourthInternational Conference on Rewriting Techniques and Applica-tions, volume 488 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pages299–311, April 1991.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 214: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

214 BIBLIOGRAPHY

[Kui99] W. Kuich. Full abstract families of tree series i. In JuhaniKarhumaki, Hermann A. Maurer, and Gheorghe Paun andy Grze-gorz Rozenberg, editors, Jewels are Forever, pages 145–156. SV,1999.

[Kui01] W. Kuich. Pushdown tree automata, algebraic tree systems, andalgebraic tree series. Information and Computation, 165(1):69–99,2001.

[KVW00] O. Kupferman, M. Vardi, and P. Wolper. An automata-theoreticapproach to branching time model-checking. Journal of the ACM,47(2):312–360, 2000.

[LD02] Denis Lugiez and Silvano DalZilio. Multitrees automata, pres-burger’s constraints and tree logics. Technical Report 8, Labo-ratoire d’Informatique Fondamentale de Marseille, 2002.

[LM87] J.-L. Lassez and K. Marriott. Explicit representation of termsdefined by counter examples. Journal of Automated Reasoning,3(3):301–318, September 1987.

[LM93] D. Lugiez and J.-L. Moysset. Complement problems and tree au-tomata in AC-like theories. In P. Enjalbert, A. Finkel, and K. W.Wagner, editors, 10th Annual Symposium on Theoretical Aspectsof Computer Science, volume 665 of Lecture Notes in ComputerScience, pages 515–524, Wurzburg, 25–27 February 1993.

[LM94] Denis Lugiez and Jean-Luc Moysset. Tree automata help one tosolve equational formulae in ac-theories. Journal of Symbolic Com-putation, 18(4):297–318, 1994.

[Loh01] M. Lohrey. On the parallel complexity of tree automata. In Proceed-ings of the 12th Conference on Rewriting and Applications, pages201–216, 2001.

[MGKW96] D. McAllester, R. Givan, D. Kozen, and C. Witty. Tarskian set con-straints. In Proceedings, 11th Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic inComputer Science, pages 138–141. IEEE Computer Society Press,27–30 July 1996.

[Mis84] P. Mishra. Towards a Theory of Types in PROLOG. In Proceedingsof the 1st IEEE Symposium on Logic Programming, pages 456–461,Atlantic City, 1984.

[MLM01] M. Murata, D. Lee, and M. Mani. Taxonomy of xml schema lan-guages using formal language theory. In In Extreme Markup Lan-guages, 2001.

[Mon81] J. Mongy. Transformation de noyaux reconnaissables d’arbres.Forets RATEG. PhD thesis, Laboratoire d’Informatique Fonda-mentale de Lille, Universite des Sciences et Technologies de Lille,Villeneuve d’Ascq, France, 1981.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 215: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

BIBLIOGRAPHY 215

[MS96] A. Mateescu and A. Salomaa. Aspects of classical language theory.In G. Rozenberg and A. Salomaa, editors, Handbook of FormalLanguages, volume 1, pages 175–246. Springer Verlag, 1996.

[Mur00] M. Murata. “Hedge Automata: a Formal Model for XMLSchemata”. Web page, 2000.

[MW67] J. Mezei and J. B. Wright. Algebraic automata and context-freesets. Information and Control, 11:3–29, 1967.

[Niv68] M. Nivat. Transductions des langages de Chomsky. These d’etat,Paris, 1968.

[NP89] M. Nivat and A. Podelski. Resolution of Equations in AlgebraicStructures, volume 1, chapter Tree monoids and recognizable setsof finite trees, pages 351–367. Academic Press, New York, 1989.

[NP93] J. Niehren and A. Podelski. Feature automata and recognizablesets of feature trees. In Proceedings TAPSOFT’93, volume 668 ofLecture Notes in Computer Science, pages 356–375, 1993.

[NP97] M. Nivat and A. Podelski. Minimal ascending and descending treeautomata. SIAM Journal on Computing, 26(1):39–58, February1997.

[NT99] T. Nagaya and Y. Toyama. Decidability for left-linear growingterm rewriting systems. In M. Rusinowitch F. Narendran, editor,10th International Conference on Rewriting Techniques and Appli-cations, volume 1631 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pages256–270, Trento, Italy, 1999. Springer Verlag.

[Ohs01] Hitoshi Ohsaki. Beyond the regularity: Equational tree automatafor associative and commutative theories. In Proceedings of CSL2001, volume 2142 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science. SpringerVerlag, 2001.

[Oya93] M. Oyamaguchi. NV-sequentiality: a decidable condition for call-by-need computations in term rewriting systems. SIAM Journalon Computing, 22(1):114–135, 1993.

[Pel97] N. Peltier. Tree automata and automated model building. Funda-menta Informaticae, 30(1):59–81, 1997.

[Pla85] D. A. Plaisted. Semantic confluence tests and completion method.Information and Control, 65:182–215, 1985.

[Pod92] A. Podelski. A monoid approach to tree automata. In Nivat andPodelski, editors, Tree Automata and Languages, Studies in Com-puter Science and Artificial Intelligence 10. North-Holland, 1992.

[PQ68] C. Pair and A. Quere. Dfinition et tude des bilangages rguliers.Information and Control, 13(6):565–593, 1968.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 216: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

216 BIBLIOGRAPHY

[Rab69] M. O. Rabin. Decidability of Second-Order Theories and Automataon Infinite Trees. Transactions of the American Mathematical So-ciety, 141:1–35, 1969.

[Rab77] M. O. Rabin. Handbook of Mathematical Logic, chapter Decidabletheories, pages 595–627. North Holland, 1977.

[Rao92] J.-C. Raoult. A survey of tree transductions. In M. Nivat andA. Podelski, editors, Tree Automata and Languages, pages 311–325. Elsevier Science, 1992.

[Rey69] J. C. Reynolds. Automatic Computation of Data Set Definition.Information Processing, 68:456–461, 1969.

[Sal73] A. Salomaa. Formal Languages. Academic Press, New York, 1973.

[Sal88] K. Salomaa. Deterministic tree pushdown automata and monadictree rewriting systems. Journal of Comput. and Syst. Sci., 37:367–394, 1988.

[Sal94] K. Salomaa. Synchronized tree automata. Theorical ComputerScience, 127:25–51, 1994.

[Sei89] H. Seidl. Deciding equivalence of finite tree automata. In AnnualSymposium on Theoretical Aspects of Computer Science, 1989.

[Sei90] H. Seidl. Deciding equivalence of finite tree automata. SIAM Jour-nal on Computing, 19, 1990.

[Sei92] H. Seidl. Single-valuedness of tree transducers is decidable in poly-nomial time. Theorical Computer Science, 106:135–181, 1992.

[Sei94a] H. Seidl. Equivalence of finite-valued tree transducers is decidable.Mathematical System Theory, 27:285–346, 1994.

[Sei94b] H. Seidl. Haskell overloading is DEXPTIME-complete. InformationProcessing Letters, 52(2):57–60, 1994.

[Sen97] G. Senizergues. The equivalence problem for deterministic push-down automata is decidable. In P. Degano, R. Gorrieri, andA. Marchetti-Spaccamela, editors, Automata, Languages and Pro-gramming, 24th International Colloquium, volume 1256 of Lec-ture Notes in Computer Science, pages 671–681, Bologna, Italy,7–11 July 1997. Springer-Verlag.

[Sey94] F. Seynhaeve. Contraintes ensemblistes. Master’s thesis, LIFL,1994.

[Slu85] G. Slutzki. Alternating tree automata. Theorical Computer Sci-ence, 41:305–318, 1985.

[SM73] L. J. Stockmeyer and A. R. Meyer. Word problems requiring ex-ponential time. In Proc. 5th ACM Symp. on Theory of Computing,pages 1–9, 1973.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 217: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

BIBLIOGRAPHY 217

[Ste94] K. Stefansson. Systems of set constraints with negative constraintsare nexptime-complete. In Proceedings, Ninth Annual IEEE Sym-posium on Logic in Computer Science, pages 137–141. IEEE Com-puter Society Press, 4–7 July 1994.

[SV95] G. Slutzki and S. Vagvolgyi. Deterministic top-down tree transduc-ers with iterated look-ahead. Theorical Computer Science, 143:285–308, 1995.

[Tha70] J. W. Thatcher. Generalized sequential machines. Journal of Com-put. and Syst. Sci., 4:339–367, 1970.

[Tha73] J. W. Thatcher. Tree automata: an informal survey. In A.V.Aho, editor, Currents in the theory of computing, pages 143–178.Prentice Hall, 1973.

[Tho90] W. Thomas. Handbook of Theoretical Computer Science, volume B,chapter Automata on Infinite Objects, pages 134–191. Elsevier,1990.

[Tho97] W. Thomas. Languages, automata and logic. In G. Rozenberg andA. Salomaa, editors, Handbook of Formal Languages, volume 3,pages 389–456. Springer Verlag, 1997.

[Tiu92] J. Tiuryn. Subtype inequalities. In Proceedings, Seventh AnnualIEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science [IEE92], pages308–317.

[Tom92] M. Tommasi. Automates d’arbres avec tests d’egalite entre cousinsgermains. Memoire de DEA, Univ. Lille I, 1992.

[Tom94] M. Tommasi. Automates et contraintes ensemblistes. PhD thesis,LIFL, 1994.

[Tra95] B. Trakhtenbrot. Origins and metamorphoses of the trinity: Logic,nets, automata. In Proceedings, Tenth Annual IEEE Symposium onLogic in Computer Science. IEEE Computer Society Press, 26–29June 1995.

[Tre96] R. Treinen. The first-order theory of one-step rewriting is undecid-able. In H. Ganzinger, editor, Proceedings. Seventh InternationalConference on Rewriting Techniques and Applications, volume 1103of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pages 276–286, 1996.

[TW65] J. W. Thatcher and J. B. Wright. Generalized finite automata.Notices Amer. Math. Soc., 820, 1965. Abstract No 65T-649.

[TW68] J. W. Thatcher and J. B. Wright. Generalized finite automatawith an application to a decision problem of second-order logic.Mathematical System Theory, 2:57–82, 1968.

[Uri92] T. E. Uribe. Sorted Unification Using Set Constraints. In D. Ka-pur, editor, Proceedings of the 11th International Conference onAutomated Deduction, New York, 1992.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 218: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

218 BIBLIOGRAPHY

[Vea97a] M. Veanes. On computational complexity of basic decision prob-lems of finite tree automata. Technical report, Uppsala ComputingScience Department, 1997.

[Vea97b] M. Veanes. On simultaneous rigid E-unification. PhD thesis, Com-puting Science Department, Uppsala University, Uppsala, Sweden,1997.

[Zac79] Z. Zachar. The solvability of the equivalence problem for determin-istic frontier-to-root tree transducers. Acta Cybernetica, 4:167–177,1979.

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 219: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

Index

α-equivalence, 98β-reduction, 99ε-free, 28ε-rules, 17η-long form, 98|=, 82, 108Rec, 70Rec×, 69AWCBB, 115

axiom, 45equivalent, 46non-terminal, 46regular tree grammars, 46terminal, 46

acceptanceby an automaton, 109

accepted, 129accepts, 109accessible, 18, 130alphabetic, 29alternating

tree automaton, 187word automaton, 187

alternating automatonweak, 200

arity, 9automaton

2-automaton, 99generalized reduction automa-

ton, 126pushdown, 200reduction automaton, 122with constraints between broth-

ers, 115with equality and disequality con-

straints, 108automaton with constraints between

brothers, 115

automaton with equality and dise-quality constraints, 108

bimorphismword, 170

c, 61close equalities, 123closed, 10closure, 50closure properties

for Rec×,Rec, 74for GTTs, 76

closure property, 23complementation, 24intersection, 24union, 24

complete, 29, 111, 130complete specification

of an automaton with constraints,111

concatenation, 50congruence, 29

finite index, 30constraint

disequality constraint, 108equality constraint, 108

context, 11context-free tree grammar, 61context-free tree language, 61context-free word grammar, 58cryptographic protocols, 199cylindrification, 75

definableset, 85

definite set constraints, 195delabeling, 29derivation relation, 46derivation trees, 58determinacy

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 220: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

220 INDEX

of an automaton with constraints,111

deterministic, 111, 130determinization, 19, 111DFTA, see tree automatondisequality constraint, 108domain, 11DUTT, see tree transducer

E-unification, 97encompassment, 92equality constraint, 108equivalent, 15, 129

finite states, 108first order logic

monadic fragment, 194Flat terms, 127flat tree automaton with arithmetic

constraints, 128free variables, 98frontier position, 10FTA, see tree automaton

generalized reduction automata, 126generalized tree set, 146

accepted, 147regular, 150

generalized tree set automaton, 146,see GTSA

ground, 128ground reducibility, 93, 121, 126ground rewriting

theory of, 95ground substitution, 11ground terms, 9Ground Tree Transducer, 70GTS, see generalized tree setGTSA

complete, 147deterministic, 147run, 146simple, 147strongly deterministic, 147sucessful run, 146

GTT, 70

height, 10

index, 95IO, 62

Lwenheim class, 195, 201language

accepted by an automaton withconstraints, 109

recognizable, 15recognized, 15

language accepted, 109language generated, 46linear, 9, 26local, 64

matching problem, 99monadic class, 195monotonic

predicate, 95move relation

for NFTA, 14for rational transducers, 168

Myhill-Nerode Theorem, 29

NDTT, see tree transducerNFTA, see tree automatonnormalized, 47NUTT, see tree transducer

OI, 62order, 98order-sorted signatures, 91overlapping constraints, 137

pop clause, 196position, 10Presburger’s arithmetic, 67production rules, 46productive, 47program analysis, 142projection, 74pumping, 118pumping lemma, 22

for automata with constraintsbetween brothers, 118

push clause, 196pushdown automaton, 199

Rabinautomaton, 68, 90theorem, 90

ranked alphabet, 9RATEG, 107reachable, 46recognition

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 221: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

INDEX 221

by an automaton, 109recognized, 109recognizes, 109reduced, 47, 130reducibility

theory, 93reducibility theory, 121, 126reduction automaton, 122regular equation systems, 55regular tree expressions, 52regular tree language, 46relation

rational relation, 101of bounded delay, 101

remote equalities, 123replacement

simultaneous replacement, 118root, 128root symbol, 10rules

ε-rules, 17run, 16, 109

of an alternating tree automa-ton, 189

of an alternating word automa-ton, 188

of an automaton, 109successful, 16

semilinear, 129semilinear flat languages, 129sequential calculus, 67sequentiality, 96set constraints

definite, 195set constraints, 141size, 10, 110, 111

of a constraint, 110of an automaton with constraints,

111SkS, 82solution, 99sort

constraint, 91expression, 91symbol, 91

stateaccessible, 18dead, 18

substitution, 11

subterm, 10subterm ordering, 10success node, 188symbol to symbol, 29synchronization states, 70

target state, 108temporal logic

propositional linear time tem-poral logic, 103

termaccepted, 15in the simply typed lambda cal-

culus, 98well-formed, 91

terms, 9, 98theory

of reducibility, 93transducer

ε-free, 168rational, 168

transition rules, 108tree, 9tree automaton

product, 24tree homomorphism

ε-free, 28tree automaton

alternating, 189tree automaton

generalized, see GTSAreduced, 19

tree automaton, 14flat tree automaton, 41alternating, 187complete, 18deterministic, 17dual, 192reduced, 18reduction automaton, 107top down, 32two-way, 196weak alternating, 200with ε-rules, 16with constraints between broth-

ers, 107tree grammar, 45tree homomorphism, 25

alphabetic, 29complete, 29

TATA — October 28, 2004 —

Page 222: hy561/Data/Other/tata.pdf · Contents Introduction 9 Preliminaries 13 1 Recognizable Tree Languages and Finite Tree Automata 17 1.1 Finite Tree Automata

222 INDEX

delabeling, 29linear, 26symbol to symbol, 29

tree substitution, 49tree transducer

ε-free, 177bottom-up, 177complete, 177deterministic, 177linear, 177non-erasing, 177top-down, 178

two-way tree automaton, 196type

in the simply typed lambda cal-culus, 98

type inference, 142

variable position, 10variables, 9

Weak Second-order monadic logic withK successors, 90

WS1S, 67WSkS, 67, 82, 90

Yield, 58

TATA — October 28, 2004 —