how the mind works (the universe within- a new science explores the human mind)

Upload: xxdf

Post on 08-Mar-2016

3 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

x

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 1 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    This copy is for your personal, noncommercial use only. You can order presentation-ready copies fordistribution to your colleagues, clients or customers, please click here or use the "Reprints" tool that appearsnext to any article. Visit www.nytreprints.com for samples and additional information. Order a reprint of thisarticle now.

    January 24, 1982

    HOW THE MIND WORKS

    COPYRIGHT c 1982 BY MORTON HUNT This article is adapted from ''The Universe Within: A New

    Science Explores the Human Mind,'' to be published next month by Simon and Schuster. By Morton

    Hunt No scientific endeavor of recent years has been more dramatic or commanded greater public

    attention than our exploration of outer space. In these same years, with no drama whatever and

    almost no public notice, a small band of researchers, now numbering perhaps a thousand, has been

    exploring inner space - the universe within our minds, where, in words and images, we make a

    working model of what lies outside.

    These researchers are practitioners of a new discipline called cognitive science, an amalgam of

    psychology, psycholinguistics, computer science, psychobiology, anthropology and philosophy. They

    are investigating how we construct that inner universe and then how, by tinkering with it, we know

    what to expect of the world outside - in short, how we think. Their endeavors were characterized by

    a participant at a cognitive-science seminar organized several years ago by the Alfred P. Sloan

    Foundation in New York City (a major backer of the new discipline) as ''the start of an intellectual

    adventure somewhat comparable to the position in which physics stood toward the end of the

    Renaissance.''

    Cognitive science is still far from being a coherent and integrated body of knowledge. Often, indeed,

    the members of this new discipline are quarrelsome and at odds with one another - a trait that

    Thomas S. Kuhn, the philosopher of science and author o f ''The Structure of Scientific Revolutions,''

    has said is typical at this early stage of development.

    For what is happening is nothing less than revolutionary. From the 1920's until about a decade ago,

    the human mind was out of fashion, scientifically speaking, and ignored by most American

    psychologists on the ground that theories about what happens within it are both unverifiable and

    unnecessary. Such was the view of behaviorism, the theory that dominated academic and research

    psychology for half a century. (Freudian psychology, though inward-looking, reigned supreme only

    within the psychotherapies and, in any case, dealt more with emotional processes than with

    thinking.) Behaviorists held that the scientific approach to human behavior was to observe the

    relationships between the external stimuli and the observable responses; if, knowing the former, one

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 2 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    could predict the latter, there was no need to speculate about what took place, unseen, within the

    mind. Indeed, they viewed such speculations as benighted; B.F. Skinner, the dean of contemporary

    behaviorists, has said that efforts to explain human behavior in terms of what goes on in the mind

    are akin to primitive animism - the belief that spirits dwell in material objects.

    This disesteem of the human mind has had numerous parallels elsewhere in American life - in the

    behavior therapies that treat patients by methods not unlike those of animal trainers; in the doctrine

    of certain animal-behavior specialists that we are only naked apes, ruled more by primitive neural

    structures than by the thinking forebrain, and in those many movements that celebrate feeling and

    mystical experience while denigrating the intellect and reasoning.

    Cognitive scientists, in contrast, hold that the human mind is highly complex and thoroughly

    admirable, that one cannot understand human behavior without knowing what goes on in it and,

    most important, that it can be scientifically investigated. They share a heady sense of excitement at

    devising new techniques for finding out how the mind works, and they are beginning to derive a

    series of richly explanatory theories about it.

    Already, in fact, their ideas and findings have reverberated throughout American life. In the

    universities, cognitive theory is rapidly displacing behaviorism as the guiding viewpoint of

    psychology. More than a hundred institutions of higher learning now offer courses in how to think

    better, based on recent research in problem solving and creativity. Behavior therapies remain

    popular, but most behavior therapists are supplementing their treatment techniques with a goodly

    dose of ''cognitive therapy'' -the exploration of the misperceptions and distortions of thought that

    cause inappropriate responses to what other people say and do. Articles on various aspects of

    cognitive science appear frequently in professional journals and popular science magazines, either

    arousing or responding to (or both) a new interest on the part of the reading public in how the

    human mind functions.

    Cognitive science has had this much impact because it shows that, while the mind's processes cannot

    be directly observed, they can be explo red by m eans of circumstantial evidence. Even as physicists

    cannot see el ectrons, muons or other subatomic particles but infer their propert ies from the tracks

    they leave in a cloud chamber, so cognitive sci entists deduce the nature of the mind's machinery

    from what happens to information fed into it. Here are some recent experiments t hat, like cloud

    chambers, reveal the tracks of thought: In a classr oom at the University of Washington, the

    psychologist Elizabeth F. Loftus recently showed a group of student volunteers a brief videota pe of

    eight demonstrators bursting into and disrupting aclass. Afterw ard, she asked half of her subjects,

    ''Was the leader ofthe four demo nstrators a male?'' Speaking to the other subjects, she replaced ''fo

    ur'' with ''12.'' A week later, she asked all of them how many demo nstrators they had seen: The

    answers of the ''four'' group average d 6.4, but those of the ''12'' group averaged nearly nine. Dr. Lof

    tus concluded that, in these kinds of situations, we do not retain bo th our original memories of

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 3 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    events and subsequent information o r misinformation about them, but that the original memories

    are amalgamated with and revised by later influences. Even under hypnosi s (as she found in

    another experiment), the original experience ex ists nowhere in memory; we possess only the end

    product. In a labora tory at the University of Pennsylvania, a 3-year-old girl watched as the child

    psychologist Merry Bullock demonstrated a Snoopy jack-i n-the-box, a broad, flat wooden chest. Dr.

    Bullock put asteel ball in a hole toward one side of the top. It rolled down a slanting runw ay, visible

    to the child through a plastic front panel, and then disa ppeared; a second later, a Snoopy doll

    popped up from the top of th e box in the direction the ball had been headed, as if triggered by it.

    After the little girl had watched this performance several times , Dr. Bullock pulled the box apart (it

    was made in sections); no w the ball rolled down in the first section and disappeared, but the

    Snoopy doll in the central section, secretly activated by a button, continued to jump up, though the

    ball could not possibly have got to it. The little girl burst out laughing and wriggled arou nd in her

    chair. Dr. Bullock asked her what had happened. ''I don't know!'' she said, hunching up her skinny

    little shoulders. At 3, she was too young to talk in terms of cause and effect or to understand such

    words, but her surprise at s e eing a bizarre and seemingly uncaused event was evidence to Dr. B

    ullock thatthe human mind is built so as to connect events causally l ong before it can deal verbally

    with that sophisticated concept. In a psychology laboratory at the University of Texas at Austin, a

    student volunteer sat before a small video screen on which pairs of words appeared; his task was to

    decide as quickly as possi ble whethereach pair belonged to the same semantic category. On came

    these two: LION HORSE and he pushed a button indicating he thought they were ''Same.'' Then, on

    came these two: LION APPLE and he indicated: ''Different.'' In each case, it had taken him about

    three-quarters of a second to respond. Now the experimenters, Philip B. Gough and Michael J.

    Cosky, flashed on the screen a single word (PEAR) and added another word (APPLE) less than a

    second later. ''Same,'' answered the student - about a fifth of a second more quickly than before. The

    difference, though minute, struck Gough and Cosky as extremely significant. They were trying to

    deduce the steps by which we understand words we read and had hypothesized that before a word

    can be understood it must be carried from the retina to a part of the brain where it is briefly retained

    while we look up its meaning in our memory bank of words. If one word of a pair is shown to us

    first, we should be able to look it up before the second one comes along; thus, the time needed to

    decide ''Same'' or ''Different'' when the second word appears should be a trifle shorter than if both

    appear at once. And that is exactly what they found. In such a mote of fact, a large principle can be

    discerned: We ''process'' incoming information step by step, and what those steps are can be inferred

    from the different amounts of time it takes us to do slightly different tasks. In scores of laboratories,

    cognitive scientists use ''protocol analysis'' to deduce how the mind goes about the business of

    solving a problem. The subject is presented with, say, an end game at chess or a problem in

    cryptarithmetic (a mathematical puzzle in which digits have been replaced by letters; the task is to

    break the code). Or it may be a real-life problem: Several researchers have been confronting

    physicists, physicians, lawyers and engineers with the kinds of situations they deal with in their

    professional capacities. The subject is asked to say out loud everything he or she is thinking while

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 4 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    solving the problem. Then the protocol (the transcript of these utterances) is analyzed, step by step,

    to show how the subject generated various hypotheses, made tentative forays in this or that

    direction, backed away from unpromising avenues or blind alleys of thought and so on. The subject,

    to be sure, voices only conscious thoughts - a small part of what is going on - but from these traces

    the analyst conjectures what was going on in the subject's unconscious - for instance, whether he or

    she was proceeding chiefly by trial and error or on the basis of stored information and how he or she

    was ch oosing which of several alternatives to try first. The subject's total set of operating procedures

    ca n then be written out in the form of a computer program and actually run on a machine. If the

    machine deals with the problem much as the h uman being did, the researcher's overall analysis is

    confirmed. At the Cent er for Human Information Processing of the University ofCalifornia at San

    Diego, David E. Rumelhart has lately been telling rather dull l ittle stories to both children and

    adults. One such story begins: ''Mary heard the ice-cream truck coming down the street. She

    remembered her birthday money and ran into the house.'' At that point, Rumelhart stops and asks

    his listeners what is happening; most of them recognize that Mary is a little girl, wants ice cream

    when she hears the truck and goes into the house to get money for it. Isn't that obvious? Yes, but

    where in the two sentences is any of these things actually said?

    Rumelhart is looking into the way we understand one another's communications; we do so, he and

    others are discovering, not just by hearing what people actually say but by making a set of

    inferences, drawing upon our own extensive knowledge of the world, to supply what is missing. The

    speaker or writer can count on us to come up with the right stuff, because knowledge in the memory

    network is ''packaged'' in stereotypical routines or clusters of well-known cause-and-effect

    relationships. (Think of all that is mutually understood in the exchange, ''Yeah?'' ''Yeah.'' ''Oh, yeah?''

    ''Yeah!'')

    Long before the first stirrings of the cognitive-science revolution, many psychologists had been

    troubled by the inability of behaviorism to explain a number of aspects of human behavior. Memory

    was a case in point. Behaviorism dealt with it as if it were all of a piece: The organism remembers

    best what has been most often repeated, best rewarded and so on. There was a nice clarity and

    precision to this explanation; it was even turned into algebraic equations. But while the equations fit

    most laboratory observations of rats and other animals, they did not fit everyday human experience,

    which offers abundant evidence of two distinctly different forms of information storage - short-term

    memory and long-term memory. We look up a telephone number for the 20th time, repe at it to

    ourselves half a dozen times until we dial - and promptly fo rget it again. Yet much of what we have

    experienced only once remains long or permanently in memory: the price we paid for a book, a joke

    we found particularly funny, a special look on someone's face. Repe tition and reward are not a good

    enough explanation of learning; in ternal cognitive factors- such as meaning - play a part.

    Language was another area that cried out for explanations involving complex mental mechanisms

    rather than simple rote learning. Children do imitate the speech they hear, but they do a lot more

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 5 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    than that. As the linguist Noam Chomsky pointed out in 1959 in a withering critique of behaviorist

    theories of language acquisition, children produce all sorts of sentences they have never heard

    before. They create new sentences out of words they know, guided by some internal sense of syntax.

    So do adults; every day each of us utters sentences he has never heard or read. Clearly, a lot does go

    on inside and needs to be taken into account.

    By the late 1950's, many such observations had caused pressure to build up among psychologists for

    a new effort to explore the human mind. At the same time, a number of coincidental developments

    in related fields of study were yielding insights into various aspects of mental functioning and

    furnishing a wealth of bits of evidence about such thought processes as visualization, concept

    formation, logical reasoning, language comprehension and problem solving. But each process

    seemed to have its own rules; what was lacking was some unifying principle.

    About two decades ago, such a principle began to emerge from information theory and computer

    science. What a computer does from first to last is process information: It transforms punched-in

    letters into digital bits, routes these to where they can be recognized or stored, retrieves them as

    needed, puts them to work according to the program and the operator's commands, and eventually

    changes them back into a readable display on a screen or on paper.

    A few psychologists - among them, most notably Herbert A. Simon of Carnegie-Mellon University -

    saw by analogy that the mind, too, was engaged in information processing; that was the overall

    function of the separate mechanisms working within it.

    If, for instance, you read the question ''What is the largest number that will go into 100 an odd

    number of times (and more than once) with no remainder?'' you turn the perceived shapes of the

    letters and words into neuronal impulses; then you compare them to stored shapes, sounds and

    meanings in memory to identify them and decode the sense of the sentence; then you reason about

    how to find such a number, try the numbers suggested by the method you chose and find one that

    works; and finally you check your work. Each of these steps is part of an information-processing

    program. (The answer, of course, is 20.)

    Cognitive science is thus concerned with a system of processes for manipulating information; it is

    this concept that has come, in recentyears, to uni fy and guide the new field.

    (Brain research, though associated with cognitive science, deals with very different matters - the

    electrical impulses or chemical signals, for instance, produced by individual neurons. Thought

    processes are the highly organized product of millions or billions of these microevents; cognitive

    science is concerned with the principles governing these higher-level structures, much as the study of

    waves is concerned with wave mechanics and not the motions of water molecules.)

    The practitioners of this new discipline sometimes betray an attitude that seems unusual for

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 6 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    scientists: They are often awed by what they are studying. They rarely say so out loud, perhaps

    fearing to sound insufficiently objective, but one can read that message between the lines of their

    congested technical prose.

    Occasionally, though, some cognitive scientist will actually come out with it. Prof. Rochel Gelman,

    who specializes in childhood development at the University of Pennsylvania, said recently, ''The

    human mind, as I see it in my work, is a wonderful, a magnificent structure created by evolution.

    Nothing resembles it or comes close to it.'' Elliot Soloway, an artificial-intelligence researcher at

    Yale, painstakingly worked out a computer program a while ago that could figure out some of the

    simpler rules of baseball by watching a game being played. (It ''watched'' by ingesting a series of

    numbers and symbols representing the physical movements of the players.) Soloway's aim was to

    test his ideas about how human beings make sense of their experiences. ''The more I worked on it,''

    he says, ''the more I was amazed that people can understand anything. It's really very hard to make

    sense of the world - and yet we do. Even little kids do. It just blows me away!''

    When cognitive scientists reckon the information capacity of the human memory, they come up with

    numbers such as 1011 (100 billion) bits of information, a fact they are likely to offer, at least in

    writing, in the calmest of tones. (The average adult's memory thus holds at least 500 times as much

    information as the entire Encyclopaedia Britannica.) But when they speak informally, they may let

    their feelings slip. On e specialist in me mory research said to me, ''You couldn't fit into the biggest

    compu ter now available all ofwhat a 4-year-old knows about his mother's ki tchen - the properties

    of the furniture in it, what things will spil l and when, what actions will yield what results and so on,

    an d on.'' He shook his head wonderingly.

    But what is even more notable than the capacity of our memory is our ability to find what we need in

    it. To retrieve a fact from a card file or a computer, you have to know how to locate it; if you don't

    know how it has been classified and filed, it may as well not exist. The human memory, in contrast,

    is organized not just alphabetically, numerically and topically but in innumerable ways; items in it,

    research shows, are arranged in interlacing networks, with the result that practically any word, image

    or other memory can be reached from any one of many starting points by a vast number of routes.

    We are aware of that when we try to think of a forgotten word - we may cue ourselves with the first

    letter, or its general sound, or its meaning, or a mental image of the last time we heard it used or

    some other connection. Usually, though, we need not make a conscious effort; words are available to

    us as fast as we wish to utter them. Artificial-intelligence researchers are envious of this human

    ability. As Hans Berliner at Carnegie-Mellon University put it, ''Human beings can store large

    amounts of knowledge - and get at it. Computers have a lot of trouble doing that.'' He paused, and

    then added, ''In fact, the problem of having a computer find its way around in its memory'' - as a

    human being does - ''is pretty close to hopeless.''

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 7 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    Research in problem solving similarly offers many opportunities to be impressed by the machinery

    inside the head. Prof. Paul E. Johnson of the University of Minnesota is one of the researchers who

    have been investigating how experts in highly technical professions solve their problems. They do so,

    he finds, not by an orderly and stepwise method, as in solving a puzzle or playing a game, but by a

    far more complicated, hard-to-fathom, yet efficient, method.

    For instance, a cardiologist, presented with a fragmentary case history as a problem in diagnosis, is

    likely to break in with a correct answer after hearing just a few scraps of data. At that point,

    according to Johnson, ''We say to him, 'How did you know? With only three pieces of data, how

    could you possibly know?' And it turns out he doesn't really know, but he has a good hypothesis,

    based on experience and knowledge special to this domain, that consists of shortcuts and tricks. But

    the expert can't tell you how he does what he does. As he was growing proficient, he had to think

    about what he was doing, then he went through a phase where he was practicing these hookups, and

    finally he got to the stage of automaticity, where all that stuff is filed away out of sight. So he says,

    'You can't reduce diagnosis to rules. It's an art - I just do it.' ''What he c an't tell us - but what we're

    finding out - is that he'sdoing top-dow n and bottom-up thinking at the same time. He's seeing

    things in a g eneral way but also in a highly specific way, using his tremendous ne twork of

    experiential associations and relying on his intuitive jud gments.'' Then, beaming, Johnson exclaims,

    ''In our solving of pr oblems, we're not logical machines, we're psychological machines!''

    All of these issues are what cognitive scientists often refer to as ''interesting questions.'' They use

    that term in a special sense to mean issues that are not just attention-getting but important, not yet

    fully understood and, above all, difficult to deal with.

    Every science has its own similarly interesting questions, but cognitive science is willing to take on -

    indeed, by its nature cannot escape -ideas that have intrigued and puzzled thoughtful people through

    the ages.

    One of them is the ancient nature-nurture issue. One doctrine, dating back at least to Plato, holds

    that our minds come equipped with innate ideas or, at any rate, inherited tendencies to think and

    behave in very specific ways. The opposite doctrine, held by the behaviorists and their philosophical

    predecessors the empiricists, maintains that the mind is a blank slate at birth and comes to think

    only in ways that have been written upon it by experience and training.

    Cognitive science has been turning up a good deal of evidence that both sides are partly right and

    largely wrong. Recent research suggests that our minds come equipped with highly efficient neural

    arrangements built into us by evolution; these predispose us to make certain kinds of sense of our

    experiences and to use them in that distinctively human activity we call thinking. It is the product of

    an interaction between nature and nurture; each is essential, neither is wholly controlling.

    This is abundantly evident in the studies of language acquisition by children. It is experience that

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 8 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    causes children to learn the language they hear - yet they would learn none were it not for the built-

    in machinery that prepares them to reproduce what they hear and that enables them to make order

    out of the verbal chaos around them.

    Babies begin to babble at 3 or 4 months of age, and their babb ling increases until they start to form

    understand able words, at which point it decreases. Parents naturally take th e babbling to be an

    attempt to imitate adult speech, but they are wrong: Studies of deaf children show that they, too,

    babble. Evident ly, it is a spontaneous,hereditary activity that begins when the neur al centers

    directing it have reached a certain stage of maturation. I t is a necessary preliminary to speech, and

    in normal children it changes and increasingly comes to include the sounds of t he spoken language.

    In deaf children, however, it dwindles away from lack of feedback. Here,then, is evidence that both

    nature and nurtur e are involved in human mental development - not X percent from one a nd Y

    percent from the other, but the two interacting to produce the result.

    Another way in which our minds are predisposed to organize the welter of incoming experience is by

    recognizing patterns in the events around us. Even the tiny child is captivated by the meter and

    rhyme of verse and will respond to strong musical rhythm by dancing. We build on that inherent

    capability. A third grader, without being told what to look for or why, will notice the ways the

    numbers are changing in this simple problem and solve it without trouble: What number comes

    next? 2 3 5 6 8 9 - An adult, with much more experience, can handle far more complicated

    problems, such as this one: What are the next letters? A B R S Z B C T U Y -* (FOLLOWING LINE

    IS A FOOTNOTE:) *The answer is C D V W X. Our native sensitivity to patterns accounts for a great

    many human discoveries -everything from primitives' recognition of the cycle of the seasons to

    present-day astronomers' perception of the way the galaxies are dispersed throughout the universe.

    We human beings, moreover, are concept-making creatures: Unlike any other animal, we have a

    natural ability to group objects or events together into categories, give them abstract labels and so

    think about the world in a highly efficient way. The interesting aspect of this question is how we

    acquire the concepts by which we do our higher-level thinking. No doubt we acquire most of them

    from other people: The parent explains to the child that ''animal'' means cat, dog, mouse and the

    like; the professor explains to the student the meaning of significant correlation or, perhaps,

    romantic love. But a number of recent studies indicate that the human mind is capable of forming

    categories on its own, without outside help. Researchers showed 1-year-olds slides picturing pieces

    of furniture, two at a time. After a long series of such slides, they switched to one showing an item of

    furniture and a face; almost always, the child would look at the face rather than the piece of

    furniture. But if they showed a series of pairs of faces first, then a slide of a face and a piece o f

    furniture, the child would prefer the latter. Apparently ev en a 1-year-old child is able to categorize

    the objects he or she see s and takes more interest in something from a new category than from an

    old one.

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 9 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    Recently, at the Human Performance Center of the University of Michigan, the cognitive

    psychologists Lisbeth Fried and Keith Holyoak made up a number of slides of abstract geometrical

    patterns. They had started with two somewhat similar basic designs and, on a computer, generated a

    number of variations that differed from the original in varying degrees. Then they told a group of

    volunteers that they would be seeing designs by two minimalist artists and were to try to distinguish

    the work of one from the other - that is, sort them into two groups.

    As the designs were projected one by one, the volunteers made a choice by pushing one of two

    buttons. The researchers told some of them whether each choice was right or wrong as they made it;

    not surprisingly, these people quickly got better at the job. The researchers told the others nothing -

    yet this group, with no corrective feedback, got better at the job virtually as fast. Drs. Fried and

    Holyoak concluded that our minds file away incoming experiences in such a way that similarities

    overlap and we shortly perceive what is typical in a group of related things. We automatically create

    and refine.

    Once again, therefore, it appears that, as one cognitive scientist put it, ''We're hard-wired to make

    certain kinds of sense out of the world.'' (''Hard-wired'' is a computer-science term that refers to

    built-in traits, resulting from fixed circuitry rather than programming.) Unlike the lower animals, we

    human beings have very few specific behavior patterns built into us; we are not constrained by our

    hard-wiring to eat only certain foods, build only one kind of shelter or make love in a single fashion.

    But we are constrained by our mental hard-wiring to make certain kinds of order out of our

    experiences. Constraints, however, are not always limitations; they can also be capabilities - and

    those that are built into the human brain are our greatest asset, for they force us to construct the

    human intellect.

    Another classic question that cognitive science i s looking into is the matter of whether the human

    mind arrives at knowledge by means oflogical reasoning or in some other fashion. E ver since

    Aristotle's time, many philosophers have thought that ded uctive reasoning was theroad to truth. In

    our own time, the immensely influential psychologist Jean Piaget maintained that logi c was the

    natural mode of human reasoning and that every child inevi tably developed logical reasoning by the

    early teens. Not every paren t would agree.

    Cognitive scientists have more cogent reasons for thinking that logic is not the normal mode of

    human thought. For one thing, in logic every statement is true or false, but in real life many

    statements are neither. If someone says, ''John's wife is sick,'' and in fact John is unmarried, the

    statement is simply irrelevant, a condition the mind recognizes but logic does not. Again, with logic

    we can derive innumerable valid but useless inferences from any true statement - and nothing

    within the system of logic guides us to avoid such inferences. (For example, if it's true that ''Roses

    are red,'' then it's equally true that ''It isn't true that it isn't true that either roses are red or they

    aren't red.'')

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 10 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    More to the point, the evidence shows that our ''natural reasoning,'' as cognitive scientists call it,

    proceeds by quite other means. In everyday life we reason most of the time by noting similarities

    between things, making good guesses and reaching conclusions on the basis of likelihood or

    probability rather than logical certainty.

    The psychologist Allan Collins, senior scientist at the Cambridge, Mass., consulting firm of Bolt

    Beranek & Newman Inc., has spent years studying natural (or, as he calls it, ''plausible'') reasoning.

    He has tried a number of little problems on various subjects and asked them to talk out loud while

    thinking the problems through. From their answers, Collins has identified hundreds of common

    kinds of plausible inferences - the fundamental forms of everyday reasoning - one of which actually

    consists of reasoning not from knowledge but from the lack of it. ''Is the Nile longer than the

    Mekong River?'' he asked, and one young man said he thought it was, because in junior high school

    he read a book on rivers, and he remembered reading about the Nile and the Amazon but not about

    the Mekong. He was saying, in effect, that because he didn't know whether or not it was long, it

    probably wasn't.

    Most of our plausible reasoning relies on the intuitive recognition of similarities or analogies

    between two things. ''We reason analogically,'' says Robert J. Sternberg of Yale, ''whenever we make

    a decision about something new in our experience by drawing a parallel to something old.'' In most

    cases, the reasoning is invalid by strictly logical rules - but intuitively we know better. And most of

    the time we are right; were it not so, we would long since have become extinct. A very old example of

    such reasoning is Virgil's story of how Dido founded Carth age: She was granted as much land as she

    could enclose with an ox hi de - which she cleverly cut into long thin strips and laid out as a circle,

    the largest area that can be enclosed by a lineof given leng th. But how did she know that was the

    optimum shape? Intuitively, no doubt, based on analogy with such similar experiencesas tying as m

    any sticks as possible into a bundle with a piece of string.

    A more recent example: A couple of years ago at M.I.T., I was talking to the physicist Andrea di

    Sessa, who had been studying how high-school and college students think about physics problems.

    He diagramed on his blackboard a pulley with a rope running over it and down each side; at one end

    of the rope he drew a monkey and at the other end, a box representing a weight. The two weighed

    the same, he said. Ignoring friction, what would happen to the weight if the monkey climbed the

    rope?

    Grasping at a straw of thought, I said, ''Well, the energy he expends has to go someplace, so I guess

    the weight rises as high as he climbs.''

    ''That's right, it does,'' said di Sessa. I felt pleased. ''And many students get the right answer,'' he

    went on, ''but can't explain how they got it - or, like you, get it right for the wrong reasons.'' I felt

    less pleased. (The problem concerns the laws of motion: Since the forces acting on the two objects,

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 11 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    both initially at rest, are always equal, their motions must be. Viewing the problem as one of the

    conservation of energy, as I did, may lead to the right answer but ought not to.)

    Creativity - in the arts or any other area - is yet another classic issue that is gaining scientific

    respectability, thanks to cognitive science. Until recently, the investigation of creativity was carried

    on by a variety of dabblers from the arts and assorted sciences, plus a handful of nonbehaviorist

    psychologists. Some of them devised tests that identified who was creative - but not why they were

    or how they managed to do what they did. Others collected accounts of creative experiences that

    entertained but hardly explained. A famous example: The 19th-century German chemist Friedrich

    Kekule had been laboring long, and in vain, to figure out the structure of the benzene molecule.

    Exhausted, he sank into a reverie, staring into the fire, when a vision came to him of a snake biting

    its own tail and he realized that the core of the benzene molecule was a ring of carbon atoms. But

    how or why this vision came to him he could not say.

    Much of the older writing about creativity seems to regard it as describable but ineffable - an almost

    magical or spiritual act. Cognitive scientists, in contrast, regard it not as something unlike the rest of

    cognition but as a special kind of problem solving - the kind that yields answers to new problems, or

    new answers to old ones. (The question of to what degree creativity takes place in the right brain

    rather than in the left brain is not of much interest to cognitive scientists. The real question, they

    feel, is how the brain, whatever half is involved, comes up with new ideas.)

    One current approach to exploring creativity uses protocol analysis: John R. Hayes and Linda

    Flower, at Carnegie-Mellon University, have been asking subjects to voice all their thoughts while

    writing an essay. From the analysis of the trains of thought thus captured, Drs. Hayes and Flower

    have been able to portray the steps involved in writing in the form of a flow chart containing a score

    of little boxes (each box represents a mental function) connected by arrows. It seems to indicate that

    creative work, at least at the conscious level, involves a far more orderly set of procedures than many

    artistic people like to think.

    New ideas, however, pop into this system from the unconscious, an area the chart leaves unmapped

    thus far. How or when the unconscious is at its most creative is still largely conjectural, but other

    studies suggest that one important condition is that the goal of the problem be ''ill defined'' - that is,

    general, not specific. If a ship designer, for example, defines his goal as the more economical use of

    fuel in cargo vessels, he will fidget with and improve the boilers, the propellers and the hull shape.

    But if he defines it as moving the boat through the water more cheaply, he may be freed to think of

    going back to wind power, using mechanical sails, as the Japanese and others are beginning to do.

    But loosely defining the goal will not help unless, at the same time, the mind is packed with

    pertinent information. Current problem-solving research, Hayes told me, stresses the relationship

    between knowledge and creativity. ''Take that famous figure,'' he said, ''worked up by Herb Simon,

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 12 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    that the chess master has learned and stored in memory 50,000 patterns of positions on the board.

    What that says to me is that to generate creative answers to problems, you need many years of

    experience and hard work and a lot of information. We have studied composers' lives, and I claim

    that the magic number is 10 - that is, 10 years between the time a composer starts intensive study

    and the time the first notable compositions appear. It was true of Mozart, Mendelssohn, Schubert

    and others - I have a sample of 76 - but, of course, that amount of time and effort is only a necessary

    condition, no t a sufficient one. There are innumerable poor slobs wh o can spend the same amount

    of time and effort and stillnot produce a creative work of any magnitude.''

    Finally, several researchers have noticed that the human mind seems most capable of creativity when

    motivated, not by the hope of reward, but by the intrinsic joy of finding new answers to a problem.

    In one typical study, a group of students were told that they would earn a reward for thinking up the

    largest number of plot titles and stories; a second group, not promised any payoff, proved to be

    more imaginative and original than the first. Highly creative people, of course, hope for financial

    and social success, but one student of creativity, Dr. Teresa M. Amabile of Brandeis University,

    suggests that they may be able to shut out the thought of reward while working. In any case, the

    findings imply that most of us are at our most creative when playing with ideas for the sheer

    pleasure of it rather than out of need or greed. It is one of the paradoxes and splendors of the human

    intellect.

    Perhaps the most intractable of the old problems of the mind has been the question of the

    homunculus. Who or what is that? Let me quote Sir Francis Crick, co-discoverer of the double helix,

    who now is doing research in neurobiology. Writing in Scientific American, he tells of trying to

    explain to an intelligent woman why it was puzzling that we perceive anything at all: ''She could not

    see why there was a problem. Finally in despair I asked her how she herself thought she saw the

    world. She replied that she probably had somewhere in her head something like a little television set.

    'So who,' I asked, 'is looking at it?' She now saw the problem immediately.''

    This is, in fact, not one problem but two. The first is philosophy's ancient puzzle about mind and

    body. The homunculus, literally ''little man,'' is a symbol for something other than brain inside the

    brain - something incorporeal, a bodiless watcher and operator of the mechanism. There are, of

    course, serious difficulties in the ancient dualist position that mind or spirit exists apart from body

    or material things. Most cognitive scientists are untroubled by these difficulties because they simply

    do not believe in incorporeal substance. And for good reason: In science, a theory is not considered

    worthy of belief unless it can be put to tests that would prove it false if it were, indeed, false. The

    theory that the earth is round, for instance, is falsifiable, but the tests that might falsify it do not do

    so; that makes it credible. The assertion that unicorns exist is not f alsifiable -what test could

    disprove that claim? - so is unworthy of belief. The same i s true of the notion that mind is a

    separate form of existence, ap art from body.

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 13 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    But if mind is not an incorporeal something, what is it? The general answer of cognitive scientists,

    drawn from modern philosophy, computer theory and information theory, is that the thought

    processes that make up the mind are organizations of millions and billions of neural events; these

    organizations are higher-order events or entities known as epiphenomena. A flame is the composite

    organized effect of innumerable chemical events at the molecular level; in much the same way, the

    mind is the composite effect of innumerable events at the neuronal and molecular level. To clarify

    this thought, here is a simple example of an epiphenomenon (my thanks to Douglas R. Hofstadter,

    from whose book ''Godel, Escher, Bach'' I borrowed the idea): NNNNN E E UUUUU R R OOOOO N

    N SSSSS N E E U U R R O N N S

    N EEEEE U U R R O OOO NNNNN S

    N E E U U R R O O N N S

    N E E UUUUU RRRRR OOOOO N N S

    Now to the second problem: How can this epiphenomenon, mind, be conscious of itself? A lens is

    used to see other objects, but it cannot see itself; if the mind is made up of thought processes, how

    does it manage to perceive itself? If it consists of thoughts, how can it experience itself as something

    unique? Whence comes the ''I'' that is unarguably real to each of us? This entrancing and murky

    subject, long considered fit only for philosophers, is now given serious consideration by cognitive

    scientists, at least at the level of hypothesis if not experiment.

    Some of them say that consciousness of self is an interaction effect -it is what happens when one part

    of the mind interacts with another: an epi-epiphenomenon, so to speak.

    Others say it is a feedback effect -what Hofstadter calls a ''strange loop of the mind,'' a self-

    reinforcing resonance. ''The self,'' he writes, ''comes into being at the moment it has the power to

    reflect itself.'' We are aware of our thoughts, but the awareness is itself a thought and the foundation

    of consciousness.

    A somewhat different way of saying much the same thing comes from child-development studies. As

    the child grows, it becomes aware of two worlds - the one outside and the one within. Throughout

    life we continually experience the difference: We see the face across the table, but we can also see it

    in the mind's eye - and recognize which is whic h. It is this experience of both the outer world and

    ourinternal vers ion of it that results in our awareness of ourselves.

    Thus has Descartes's fundamental premise, ''I think; therefore I am,'' been translated into

    contemporary terms and philosophy been put back into science.

    Illustrations: diagram of the Semantic Network problem solving diagram photo of Merry Bullock

    with 3-year-old in cause and effect test photo of Andrea Di Sessa diagram of memory as information

  • 7/15/11 9:59 PMHOW THE MIND WORKS - The New York Times

    Page 14 of 14http://www.nytimes.com/1982/01/24/magazine/how-the-mind-works.html?pagewanted=print

    processor drawing of cat, human and computer thoughts

    Copyright 2011 The New York Times Company Home Privacy Policy Search Corrections XML Help Contact UsBack to Top