givon logic pragmatics epistemology

Upload: idschun

Post on 05-Jul-2018

223 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    1/53

    Journal of Pragmetics 6 ( 1982) 8I=. 23

    Narth~Hailand Publishing Company

    The history of the treatment af bath semantics and pragmatics in Linguistics has been until

    recently a captive of over-Iogiciaation, where the dcduc.i:vc, algorithmic, close-ended,

    I:ontcxt-free

    properties of the system were oa*er-cmphasiaed o the dc’rimeat 01’ more realistic view of facts of

    natural language. A careful survey of even the traditional preoccupations of

    hgicians and

    philosophers of language, such as reference, definite description OPpresupposition, nz vcals hh\t the

    Iogico-dedrxtive treatment of these subjects misrcprcsentcd

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    2/53

    foundations, however, are buried in a facile and superficial analysis of an

    artificially-narrow

    tanp of language faces, culled from a narrower yet range of

    natural

    lmguqes, ancil

    orced into an analytic mould that has little regard for

    the burden of empirical validation. This tradition has persisted in one guise or

    another via the two er;trernist schools of Western eplsternology - P.ationalism

    and Empiricism -

    through the medieval Mc4istae and their Thor& and

    Anselmic descendents, an through the

    Part Rayd se’hd

    and the Age &de

    Raison, then onward through the first formal logicians OS he 19th century,

    eventually coming into full bloom in the Logical Positivists of the early 20th

    century and their anti4nguistic bias. Modern American Linguistics, while

    the frey rr:latively late in the early 1960’s, fell squarely into ;an

    hed formal Isgico-deductive tradition in its approach to the an

    meaning, on both sides of the so-called Great Debate.

    Challenges to the logico-deductive analysis of’ meaning begin with CS.

    Peirce in the second half c the 19th century,, via a tradition that traces it&f

    back to Kant. A simirar challenge was mounted later on by Wittgenstein,

    roughly contemporaneous to the ascent of Logical Positivism. These early

    challenges were quickly neutralized by the growing power and prestige of the

    “more rigorous”

    :formal logicians. Within Positivism itself, the early broader-

    scoped Russell and Whitehead slowly gave way to narrower formalists such as

    Carnap, Tarski and Montague. Iiy #ihenPeirce had been (effectively co-opted by

    social philosophers and the impact of his pragmaitism on epistemology thus

    largely obscured. The early Wittgenstein was admired as a brilliant

    the late Wittgenstein yulasdismissed by the Positivists as impressio

    Formal logicians had of course, b;y then, been en

    ,aged in a rear-guard battle

    agains’t the encroaching shadow of context-depe

    Idence in human Iaqua

    aeducing

    the open-ended complexity of reference and

    defi

    neatly-packaged deductive-logic formulae, while ruminatin

    old-time favorites such as quantification and

    predication.

    language meaning and communicritive use was left largely

    disturbed. Thus

    when American linguistics was at last readly to

    outgrow

    strictures which relegated Semantics to either the natural sciences or to

    Mathematics ( 10lloon~b~ield933: 154, 153), the seductive

    was the only game in town. And so, elaborate deductive-lo

    as the Katz and Fodor “model” soon spra

    ing to represent meanin

    as a closed syste

    “rtiles”.

    When Pragmiatics finally reared its

    ly head in Amc

    entle whimper. The

    Sapir-

    then a cxgent observation (2

    121The original hypthesi:b was two-edged, allowing either that l~~gu~~g~WIS ~ultu~~~~~~nd~slt or

    that culture was language-constrained (W’horf IWd),

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    3/53

    thus context dep ndency of Ian

    e and meaning. Both early and late

    structuralists were not impressed, and soon ma

    the observations to “cultural vocabulary” and tl

    sties at the very mar

    same issues in his

    ian nave , Of the post-

    ed entities shn~h as

    “bekief ‘,

    “interlt”, “judge’“,

    Peters (19759, inter alia).

    very soul of PragmEiics may >e given initially as

    the four properties in tab1

    1,

    c:ontrasted with tieductive logic.

    The implications of Pr matics to the st\;dy of human language and human

    nition are immense, b the Positivist tradition in Logic and its bobsie-twin,

    Generative tradi on in Linguis1ics, seem to force all pragmiktic incursion

    into one or two blin strangulation in irrelevant formalism, or

    toward marginal exist

    le ling-istic system. And

    it seems that no am

    Ie contrary, culled from

    psycho

    uistics, disburse studies, developmental psychology or perception.

    has so

    succeeded in dentin this doctrinaire delusion of modern linguistics

    In this paper I propose to erform an epistemolo cal c-OURk grace upon

    this stale and mis uided tradition. I will first tackle s e OS he more habitual

    Table I

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    4/53

    preserves of the deductive logician, such as reference, definite description and

    presupposition, showing how a deductive-logical analysis, while attractive and

    on occasion self-consistent. has very little to do with the actual meaning system

    used in natural language.

    f

    will then proceed to discuss more complex cases

    which formal logicians have - for good reasons presumably - consistently

    avoided. The main argument I hope to present, that the meaning system in

    natural language is inherently of a pragmatic nature, will be made cumuMvely

    and with an eye to one fundamenttal truth of science - and a fundamental

    feature of pragmatics: that

    cmnplete

    proof is a deceptive mirage, and that

    science is bound

    ‘to

    accept lwi h grace the: pragmatically-tainted

    prep~n~~~rff~~ce

    of evidmce

    [3].

    On the face lof it, this old bastion of logic-bound analysis seems alto

    context-free, depending in no way on entities outside the bounds of the atomic

    proposition -.

    __^_

    or CVCII outside the bounds of tiie quantified argument (NP)

    itself. Logicians could thus with impunity posit an “existential quantifier” that

    would instantiate an. individlual argument into some “real world”, or so it

    seems. One may of course rzise superficial arguments concerning pronouns

    whose co-referents are non-referential, as in:

    (1) I am looking for LJ

    orse,

    and

    rt

    better be white

    But this can be “handled” via the modal ogic of “possible worlds”. And while

    such a treatment involves the tacit assumption that existence and reference do

    not i~~lve mapping into

    the

    real world, but rather into a unioer.se

    o~dismurse,

    the logician could still consi(der the “bulk” of reference to involve

    this

    real

    world, and relegate modal areas to the margins of the system.

    There are other cases, however, which make the predicament involved in

    defining existence in logical terms more acute. The / involve the refer~n~~e-~~in

    properties of many languages, perhaps mo

    a mapping into

    the

    world, nor into a 1

    discourse. Rather. existence dependa upon

    ctantrnuni c~tit~e ntent

    of

    uttering the discourse, specifically on whethe:, a particular individu

    (NP) is going I\Obe

    intportanr~

    nou

    its

    specific identity

    is important,

    o

    encric Q:P~

    ~~~~l~~~ h~~.

    will

    [3] While this work. deals primarily with epistemolo y i t i s on l y to be expected tha t wh a tever valid

    conclusions emcrgtr at the end will bo equally applicable to the philosophy of science. Thus, to the

    extent that a scientific, method aims at obtaining

    crew

    ~s~owl~d~~, it must abide by the

    c~~hsttsoints

    suggestedy Peirce (1955) and Wittl5cnstein (1918).

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    5/53

    85

    illustrate this behavior first with data from Israeli Hebrew, but identical

    ted from ‘Lrkish, Mandarin, H

    arian. Sherpa, Persian,

    Creg,les

    141. n w -zh

    anguages,

    numeral ‘one’ has just

    le NP’s, so that in

    ential interpretations, one

    ani

    r ~~~~~~

    efera~~~?~ he-neevad li

    -for book-one that-lost to-me

    book that I lost’

    bishvil ha-yeled shel-i

    for the-boy of-me

    book for my boy

    further, cannot ark the object of a negative sentence,

    consider:

    i ther be NM-deferential OSreferential=Jefinite

    [ 51.

    Thus

    lo karati et ha-sefer ha-ze

    NIX3 read-1 ACC the-book the-this

    ‘I didn’t read this book’

    ati (af) sefer ha-shavua

    read-1 (any) book the-week

    ‘I didn’t read (any/a) book this week’

    rati sefer-pxad (ha-shavua)

    read-1 book-one (the-wee

    ation or the modal

    ‘1

    nce of their object.

    ch verbs that the on1

    or’,

    most verbs in any

    one would expect in

    ssib%e ontrast would be

    further, in Hebrew the

    e referential-indefinite object in stlch a context, as

    is indeed the ease in:

    (4) (a)

    karati sefer~~~~~ebmol,

    ve-

    .

    [4] For ~~ ~~~ou~d and man) details, see Givbn (

    19’73a, 1978, 198 1a).

    (51 For discussion of the prq~~~tic motivation for this restriction, see Giv6n (1979a: ch. 3).

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    6/53

    So

    fax, then, the: markin

    system in Webrew seems r3th

    the speaker refers to an

    that NP is marked with ‘one’. While if the

    speaker

    particular indiwidual, but rather irr t&in

    less sF specific identity,

    then the NP is

    seemingly clear and

    1

    could also find a &‘ogi

    marked as a etcbn-referent

    sider

    :

    (5) karati sefer letm01,

    ve- . . .

    read-Bbcxik yesterday stmd-

    ‘I read a bodk yesteday, and..

    . ’

    In 1ogicaI terms., both (4a) and (5) must re

    since if one hlaisread it, thal individual book must 1

    been identified. But in terms of discourse-pragma

    radically different. In order* I:Omake this difference expli

    little more ccntext into the narrative, and consider

    th

    below

    :

    (6) COG-REK

    PRAG-RE’f :

    . . . az axarley h a-avoda hi laxti Ia-sifriya ve-yashavti sham

    . . . so

    after the-work webn-1 to-the-library and-sat-I there

    ’ . . . So after work

    I went to the

    library

    an

    ve-karati defer-exam’,

    and-read-l: book-one

    and I read1a book,

    ve-ze baya sefer metsuyan

    . .

    and-it was book excellent .

    . .

    and it was an excellent book..

    . ’

    (7) LOG;-.i?EF, PRA G-IVOIV-R

    . . .

    a2 axarey ha-avoda ha1

    . . . so

    after the-work wentA

    to

    ‘.. . So after work I went to th

    az karati sefer, ve-karati shney

    itonim,

    so rc:ad-I book and-read-1 tw

    so

    I

    read a book, and a

    coup1 n went home..

    . *

    [fi) I am deliberately expressing t heseconditkns hcrc in tern-1s f the 8

    W’s; ntent 01’bdi’ ef

    Logicianscould of course easily convert &an

    imte

    trutha-3atians b~tw~n propaitians, I supple

    via modai logic and possible-worlds.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    7/53

    87

    6) and (7) to ctie

    id~nti~~y s what

    matteredp

    text,

    mast specifL

    where referential-

    aya ici- t a,bo

    -want REF-bask

    ‘I warlt a spec@e bask’

    i cd can&as

    t

    dws not exist, the pragmatic one manifests itself

    us c6

    ~sid~r :

    (IO)

    (a)

    -hook

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    8/53

    88

    A similar situation may

    the contrast of refer%7ntiality3n

    e

    reading is aHowed, by contrasti

    inde pe nd ent NIPS (REP;).

    ‘Ibus

    (11) (a)

    REF:

    (12) (a) REF:

    (b) NON-REF:

    But again where the

    ILogicalcontrast is absent, the

    pnagrrra~ic m

    manifests

    itself and is coded by

    exact1

    the

    same

    devicle

    ‘I want a book (be it an:y)’

    kacb-n py’Qclwa+ (‘urti) pynikya-na

    NEG-I bo&OBJ (that) s~~-N~~~PA~~

    ‘1 didn’t see the book’

    kac6-n p#qva-pvnikyn-na

    N EC&I book-see-N EC&PAST

    ‘I didn’t see a/ur~_)r ook‘

    m;bt sr)’

    The facts II am discrrssi thus, are nst limit

    paradigm, but are ratha

    English, except thi\t

    En

    vs. non-referential inde

    consider:

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    9/53

    hat what we

    have here

    in

    envi ~nrnll~n

    ts

    t, if it were ~~~~~~ted,hen the fact

    ferantiality may appear t y

    r a noun is logi6@y

    rential. Thus, one looks for “(a

    ok does not mztter

    discourse c8n tex

    .

    s

    where the issue is whether

    a purgicuiur book), What we

    / semalwtic feature

    contrast is uugm znred by a

    ion, is not independent of

    involve the components of

    evancci within the dis-

    either havrng in mind

    The fact that

    II

    izcd only Ae extreme case

    ion on tht methodological

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    10/53

    3. Coreference ad dtefinite descripthn

    Logicia.ns have traditionally tried to interpret

    the use

    (and with it ana@ruric pronouns

    problem of establishulg unique ~i ~~r~~~t t iu~

    that didn’t quite masr:h the facts

    concept of

    premppo.v i m,

    construed as 8

    I

    propositions or partip of them, arnd

    son 1950). And various later refin

    notion that definiteness is a matt

    while skirting the intrusion of t

    beliefi

    (Donellan 1966). Logicians, and 1

    classical examples such as:

    ( 16) The king of France is bald

    *here the truth-value of th : sentence .n~y be Fafi-

    WWUPSC~

    i i)iii YVi_l,=iff~iUli

    perspectrves. First, going along with the presupposition that “

    Frxlee”, (16) may 13e udged either true of false in case the

    or not bald, respectively. Alternatively, if one does not

    s

    presupposition,, thrrn ( 16) presumably “has no truth value”. In this

    way,

    logicians reduced dcfini tcness to the realm of presuppositionality 191. t wound

    take a relatively small expansion of the data-base, however, to illustrate how

    definiteness in human language is inherently a

    pragmatic

    ~Il~n~$~

    volving the speaker’s belief about what the hearer is

    l ike tcr

    know

    in, and about ittowM~V t is going to be for the hearer to uniquely i

    referent under consideratilon.

    Logicians have never been forced to wrestle with the

    eat diversity of

    language devices all employed in making unique reference

    These devices, or at least a commonly recognized sub-

    raup

    of them

    f

    lo), may

    be hielparchized according to a continuous,

    non-discr

    termed as either:

    (a) the degree of difficulty that

    th

    speaker assume the hearer will ex

    in identifying the referent uni

    [9] Logrcictns proceed 80 idcdfy two scparatc: interpretations of the

    atian of 6161, .e. ‘The king

    of F: arlcc

    is not balcl’, an

    in ternul one

    which acmpts the pmuppositim but denies the arsmrtion,

    and un

    exrernd

    lone which denies the ussertion knee qf failure of the ~~~~u~~~~iti~~nK

    1969).‘The act

    that anguage

    users tend to admit only the intsrnnl i~~t~~~~~t~ti~n,f such a 11

    .sentcnce

    (Givbn 1979a: ch. 3) seldom bothers Io@ians.

    [ 10) It

    may

    be shown (Giv6a 1979a: ch. 2, and 19801~:ch. 17) that other

    ~~~tr~~t~~n$,

    uch as

    passivkation, Y-movement, indefinite3 and focus-cons,truGtions, as well as the

    VSfSV

    variation observed in Spa&h QSilva4JorvalBn 1977) and Hebrew (Givbn 1976a, 1978

    the same ;ontinuunx

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    11/53

    d~sco~~~nu~t~n the referent-tracking sub-system

    ~ctabiiity in discourse.

    men t

    erlirzhy is massive iind corn

    e exampi;~ from En lish.

    -- ^a

    Consider fhi ik

    uns (or verb agreement)

    m,

    saw Mafy, pulled a

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    12/53

    92

    T. Giwti,~~L agic us. pragntatics

    In ( l&Q, the topic is continuous and no interference from other topics,

    exists. Therefore, except for the first introduction of the referent ‘he?, all other

    references ;~e given as zero

    ampho r a [ 121.

    In (18b),

    we:

    start with the s

    of maximal continuity. But then a break occurs where ‘Mary’ takes over as an

    important to pic/subjeet. And again when the topi~/subj~t switche* b

    ‘he’. All three continuities are broken in these cases, and zero-

    phortr cxnnat

    be used

    ar ly

    more, Rather, the ~n~~~~~~@~p~~#~~~ust bt: u

    [ 13]b ~~~~1~~~

    the sequence: given in (18~) illusttrates the fact that the disc~ntinu~~ty

    nlrst

    have to be due to topic switch, as in (18b), nor to an

    overtly- fest

    discontinuity in the action sequence. It can be purely thematic, simply a way sf

    or&an.idng t’be %ame’ sequence into different, more discontinuous cr;rent~~~~~~~.

    Let us ne:xt illustrate the relative ranking of unstressed vs.

    &-es p K=+

    nOun5:

    ( 19) (a) JoJnn told Bill that he was sick,

    W)

    and that he couldn’t come

    (1~) ohn to”:3 Bill that he was sick,

    (d)

    and that h3 couldn’t come

    (e) .‘fohn told Bill that he was an idiot,

    (f)

    and that hu couldn’t come

    (g) John told Bill that he was an idiot,

    (h)

    and that hh couldn’t come

    (i) John hates Bill, and he hates Mary

    (j) John hates Bill, and h6 hates Mary

    In ( 19a) the first referent of ‘he’ could be either John or Bill, but the second

    unstressed ‘he’, in (19b), must be coreferent to the ‘he’ in ( 19a). On the other

    hand, the

    stressed

    ‘he’ in ( 19d) cannot be coreferent to the unstress

    ( 1%).

    Thus, unstressed pronouns are used when chins of to~?i~-id~nt~t~~re

    broken/disrupted. In (19e), the mere se:-nantics of ‘telli

    you/he is an idiot’ militates strongly

    the object rather than with the subject. And

    must be coreferentt with ‘he’ in ( 19e).

    not

    be coreferent with ‘he” in (1

    with thri: subject ‘John’

    [

    141. But

    stressed

    ‘he’ in (

    B j)

    [ 12) In Eaglish, zero anaphora covers a much narrower

    ran

    of the. continuity scats, and i@

    customarily referred to as

    phrasal conjwctiao,

    eithe

    Hinds, 1978), on the other hand,, zero anaphora c

    functiowl range covered by unsttwed pronouns

    in

    the lattw, further, subject agreement covers the fun

    is obligatory.

    [

    131 The I’unctisnal mnge of unstressed pronouns in English is covcrcd in Spa&~ by

    obh

    subject rlf;reemen\.

    [

    141The verbs ‘tell (to)’

    and ‘hate’ have diffentnt topic-orientation r=haractenstics, since thle subject

    of ‘tell (to)” is datiue-recipietit, but that of ‘hate’ may be inwt and ~ni~~~~ (ix, ‘patient”). This is

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    13/53

    ‘tck-reference - vs.

    nce -

    is att{:sted in

    iated with stress need

    r

    counter

    expectationr.

    draft, but Sohn told ill rtlkwasn’t so sure.

    and unstressed pronouns, here

    from expectations about

    n other -

    thematic - sources.

    pr0r~0tir~1ss. DEWS

    P’s and

    P”s are used when not enough

    le the hearer to identify the

    e either the presence of ot

    a major

    thematrc

    break.

    tlia Prince aud the General.

    H& thanked him profusely.. .

    ed around and sat down. He was tired

    in his chair and waited.

    came into the room, looked around and sat down. The man in the

    se to midclle

    age but still young.

    the pr~se~~~ of ‘prince’ and ‘general’ preclu c refering to ‘king’ as ‘he’,

    so a pronoun may be

    ssed pronoun. In both

    evertheless, in (2 lc) two

    to mark them. But the

    re disruptive:, removing the

    (tts in being tired or

    insteacl

    [

    161. It is thus

    yaidel~tifiable referent INith a DEF-NP

    coxntn ), W e (Ciivbn 198Oa).

    se continuity (see Ciivb 1877; Hopper

    refstritq to the &jwt of ‘tell (to’)‘, Thus, it

    ndntity of topic, but rather

    the

    property

    of M@YJN~~whew datives out&c acmsativ~s (Giv6n

    lW6b .

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    14/53

    94

    The use of right-di .loc81ted DEF-NP”s

    may be likened to an “afterthou

    de vice 171whereby thle speaker first assumes that there is

    eno

    the: discourse to warrant using a pronoun, then ehan

    adds the full DEF-NP as “insurance”. To illustra : this consider:

    (212) (a) The

    danced and sang. Later on

    retired..

    .

    (b) The

    danced, then other people

    rformed.

    Then kle ~~~~~~~~he

    b&g

    did,.

    (c)

    The king danced, and the prince and the

    retired,.

    . . ,

    Irl (Z&I), with full referential continuity, a pronoun is used. In (22b) t~hni~~lly

    there is no referential confusion, but there is Rlready a one-clause

    intrusion of other participants in the subject position. There

    “ungrammatical” with using only a pronoun here, but still it is a typical

    comr;xt for using rig’ht-dislocation in conversation

    [

    181. Finally, in (22~) there is

    w reason to even nedge and use a pronoun first, since referential

    cc,ntinuity/predicta’bility is- broken. So a DFF-NP is used.

    Finally, left-dislocated DEF-NP’s are used primarily over Ion

    absence, where a referent/topic is re-introduced into the d&course. To il-

    lustrate this in contrast with normal DEF-NP’s, consider:

    (X) (a) There once lived a king and a queen in an enchanted forest.

    The k ing was fat and ugly.

    . .

    (b)

    There onc,e Ifved a king in an enchanted fores

    , He ~8s rllurriccf tc:, ;i

    beautiful queen, and she was the real powl:r In the realm. Near the

    forest lived a poor prince, and the queen used to visit him and have

    lunch. NOW t he ki ng. he didn’t like the guy,.

    . .

    One must bear in mind, however, that in

    ti

    tly-plwrmed, written teXt the use

    c f left-dislocatic;:1 is not common, though it

    Ion

    in informal speech

    and conversatiosl (See Ochs (1979).

    Duranti

    and

    (

    ( lY99). ~~~1~~~

    and

    Schieffelin

    (

    1977))

    The prece&ing - albeit encapsulated

    .-

    survey of the major devises

    us

    tilefinite express;ons in human

    langua

    firmly establish that we are Indeed

    oealing with Q sccrle, and that the scale is sensitive to either of the three major

    factors of continuity:

    (i) Topic/referent continuity and identifiability

    (ii) Action continuity in a narrower, sequential sense

    (iii) Thematic, Continuity in a larger sense

    117)The explanarion couched in the term “ufterthought” is due to Mymw ( 1975).

    [ 181Both right- irnd left-dislocation are used primarily in conwrsation and informal spertch (O&s

    1979; Giv6n 197%; Duranti and Ochs 1939).

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    15/53

    nts near and lies

    lity to f~I~~w that continuity;

    of the hearer’s expectation

    s-near to the actual

    .

    diSCourSe

    and the

    scour-se, and assess-

    about themes and

    rounded in either the speaker’s

    of previous encounters

    of the hearer’s

    rsonality

    and computa-

    t of specific facts concerning the hearer‘s

    r’s t~~~pat~~ ability and thus

    “direct access” to the thought

    recesses of the hearer

    [ 191.

    could of course an and an, but it is not rea ly necessary.

    It

    seems quite

    Clear thtrt definite

    sorption is a

    t

    tcr, involving

    gradations,

    ~.~~~~a~~d~d~~~~s

    nd I of the spealrer about the

    m d

    about

    the

    d~~~c~~~;~.~~”

    na “cw I cI

    of course

    nt that when the

    ted and ~~~i~~~t~

    df the system may

    rllth rcs1nflr.c.

    ~~ 11. . *.iU.aVLIS

    buckn, whate

    le who have access to each

    other’s thoughts either

    cptrrhy,

    o meet ea.41

    other after ,J year of absence,

    ‘) wtd

    the other

    replying: “HP is. Wonder who’s

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    16/53

    41.Nonldiscrotenw of reference

    P&ost

    linguists folllow logicians in

    assuming that an

    ar

    referential or generic/non

    evidence from natural la13

    indeed common, one may

    also

    find gr

    like “semi-referentiality” that is bound

    p&e,consider the following contrast:

    (?4] (a) Did you see myth ing there?

    (b) Did\ you see

    something

    there?

    Officially, both expressions in (24) are non-referential, but (24b) is somehow “a

    li .tle bit more referential”’ than (24a). The distinction be

    ween

    the two i~volv

    n>ughly, the

    degree

    to which the speaker is willing to co

    mit himself or

    her

    to a specif;c :individual they have in mind which they s~pcrct - but art’ not sure

    - alay have in fact been involved. *When a speaker uses (24aj, he or she is iess

    committed to having, an individual in mind, while the use of (24b) su

    swcwger ommitment. But the gradation is even more extensive. Thus co

    (Z 5) (a) Did you see

    any

    man there?

    (b) Did you see

    some

    man there

    (c) Did you see a man there?

    (d) Did you see J man there wearing a blue tie with

    rcen ~~~~~-~~ts an

    twirling a silver batorl on his right-foot roe?

    In

    (25), (25cl)

    is practically a u

    ue referential description, at least as it is

    likely to be used in natural

    lang

    One may also show the phe

    enericity”‘, ~a ;r\ the

    following example from Spanish [20]:

    (26)

    (a) Maria siemprle

    hahl 3

    con &u@s

    ‘Mary always talks to sorcerers’

    (bj MaAa siempre habla con &-ubn&as

    (i) ‘Mary always talks to (the) sorcerers

    (ii) ‘Mary always talks to the sorcerers (t

    Sentence (26b) has two readi

    one (26b(~ii))fully d~~i~~it~.

    (26b( i)> is “semigeneric”,

    rou

    , a ~~?~~~l l~ r~~?~~~~~~1

    rom

    any smallerqet group of “brujos” may be pulled out trl fit the d~s~ripti~~~

    [20+]A similar dlistinction s observed in Mandark (Standra

    Th~p~n prs.

    camm.), wheta

    the

    contrast is between %e” and

    “exist”

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    17/53

    87

    5 yews old, blue eyes, brown

    and lives in a suburb of

    tc..

    . . ,

    and he lives nextdoor

    tian can thus be?: rmtkr of fiae

    gradation,

    approaching

    in the s~~~all~stof i~~~e~~ents, each one of which

    unique identifi-

    Cre in W W-questions

    non-referential

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    18/53

    The answer to (29a) may be properly ‘.lohn’, ‘my teacher’, ‘the doctor’ etc., i.e.

    bly some unicluely-referring DEF-NP. While the proper answer to (29b) may be

    ‘a. doctor”,

    ‘ia teacher’ ‘a horse’ et’c.,

    i.e. by an attributive/non-referential

    illdefinite expression. But the non-referenti;;? question - as i

    S] IOWurther gradation, involving roughly the

    degree af ~~~t~in

    about the exact type-membership of the referent. Thus consider:

    (ICI (a) Normal TYPE-identity:

    ‘in

    i

    ‘ark-‘ay In a?

    WH be-PROG t~so,4~~~-~~~J

    ‘What kind (of animate) is this one?’

    (b)

    Unwtain TYPE-identity:

    ‘in i-kwra ‘ar&‘ay “in&

    W H-DO WBT be-PWOG

    this-

    SUBJ

    ‘What kind (of an aliiruate) could this one

    possibly be?’

    Thus, not only can human languages treat “definite identification’* an

    ing unique

    reference” as scalar properties, they can also treat “having unique

    type-meinbership” as a scalar property. While it is true then that

    languages tend to

    code

    major

    extreme

    ends of this system in a see

    discrete fashion, there is inherently nothing pa-titularly discrete ab

    cognitive space of definiteness, referentiality and gsneticity. Rather, it seems to

    bc a continuous, flon-discrete space involvin certainties and probabilities.

    5. Truth, fact and presupposition

    The early history of the notion of “presupposition” in lingui4cs was io direct

    and slavish outcrop of an earlier logico-deductive tradition 1223. Several

    supposed “pragmatic” formulations still strive to represent the cystem as

    closed. tight #anddeductive-looking (see Karttunen (1974),

    rice (

    ).~~$/

    197

    1).

    Glxdon and Lakoff (197 1) or Gaxdar (1979), inter alia), In this s~~ti~n I am

    going to try and show, by citing langu

    e-data from various sources,

    that the

    logicians once again have

    misrepresent the

    general

    thrust of a

    s

    in essence

    pragmatic, by

    rigorously eliminating from their d

    quantities of relevant evidence. I will attempt to show, then,

    t

    tion in language does not involve truth relations

    rather probabilistic assumptions that the speaker makes about

    {2i:] See eg. Keenan (1969, 1971), Horn (1972), ,imr dr~c. Kgartturren (1944) has su

    may formultie i)resupposilion for human language in

    prt~gntrr~ic erms,

    kc. with reference to the

    spcwkds be l ie f

    ather han to

    atomic propositions. But he still formulates presupposition in terms

    of “truth relations** between various beliefs/propositions held by the speaker. This is a rear-guard

    attempt o salvalseome

    eductive properties for

    the

    system.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    19/53

    99

    I

    sub-domains cf the entire field does presupposition

    at& sentences ii1

    r~,~ra~rn~ti~s, so

    or *‘be used apT:qrieitely”,

    aff~~~~ative must have

    e speaker must QSSUFPI~

    at.&,

    ~?l~~~~l~do b& we

    in it,

    tly toward it, etc. As

    (31) (a)

    ~~nl~~~t~

    “Hi, how are ysu, what’s new?”

    Well, my wife is pregnant”

    Well, my wife is not pregnant”

    y

    CVb) ic vised

    ropriately on the bac&%,

    oround of (i) total lgnoralnce of

    s~~lfi~,s, and in addi

    n (ii) the culture-

    ed assumption that women (at

    blast nl~~~~d~ys~re more likely to be UL~-p

    ant than pregnant. On the other

    affirmative is “a

    ng “pragmatic

    logically presupposed”,

    t “N EG-p

    presq~posed

    eahng here with two

    and,

    and disgourse-

    hen severa, facts

    example. many

    s in syntax into two groups (see discus-

    ‘Thus, for

    ivhn

    1975) every assertion is

    rn~~h~l~

    e verb itself is included or

    xcluded from the scogdr

    ?fnlc~~

    asserted. But the following

    constructions are ~utorn~t.~~~~~n~r~~~ for ~~~~~~~~ the verb from the:scope

    of new information:

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    20/53

    too

    (33)

    REL-clauses, VW -questions, CLIWT~asentences, NC

    (including IF-clauses)

    Most of these constructions are “logically p~suppositi~

    sumably “have no truth value? (stx? further ~IQw~~ whit

    course/pragmatic presuppositional or

    are they grouped together9 A.gain, I s

    is a jgc9ze&property hat

    iis

    inherent1

    (34)

    The speaker asswmes that a prclpcsition p is

    ~a~i~~a~ o

    the

    to be be/it~d by the hearer,

    ac~essibie to the

    hearer, withia

    the hearer etc. OR

    whatever grour rds.

    And

    only within a limited subsct of ountext do the

    or belief by the hearer involve something resembli

    obviously still couched - in natural language - in te

    about the hearer’s belief.

    X?. Restr ictivtp relative clauses

    2estrictive relative clauses are one of the

    stro

    est bastions 0f lo

    presupposition in language. On the surface they se quite solid,

    sic that

    the eulbedded sentence in (3%) below, the full sentence iu (3%) must be

    “presupposed”:

    (35) (a)

    The man I saw

    yesterdqy

    left

    (b) I saw a/the man yesterday

    Things begin to blur when one realizes that restrictive relati

    modify non-referential head nouns. Thus eonside r:

    (36)

    (a) I didn’t see anybody wha WCW~blue sb

    +t

    (b) ?Somebody wore a blue shirt

    Logically, there is no way in wh,ich (%a) ~~~~~ ~r~su~)~~s~ 3~b~ u the ~ff~~~

    sense as (35a) presupposed (3%).

    N(orret

    (36b) must hate been the

    ~is~~u~s~-~~ und

    for 98 ~r~~~r use

    perhaps a question such as:

    (37) Did you see anybody weari ng a bhe shi rt1

    This property of backgrounded~ness is thus sha*tbd betw n (35a) and @$a>,

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    21/53

    only to (35a). Consider

    s, its status i snot the

    3ameas

    ay and nobody came i

    ve clauses does not

    ” information, nor

    s to unify srflcases

    nformation that is

    is an extreme case

    11

    other subordinate-

    with the “bi@W’

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    22/53

    102

    presuppositional clauses. But certainly an IF-clause cannot

    tionail, logically it even doesn’t have truth value. If some “presupposition” is

    invo’lved here, it c:ould not be logical, but must be discourse-pragmatic. To

    il us t.ra,te his, consider first:

    (41) (3) Context: What will you do if .I @tie you lke rntme~?

    (b) Reply: If you give me the money, I’ll buy this houEle,

    (c)

    Context:

    Under what coadition.s wifi you buy this h.~~e~

    (,d) Rep/y: I’ll buy this house if you

    ve me the money.

    The repties in (41b,d) are appropriate in their context, but they are noI

    interchafigenble. Logically, the I F-clause is presupposed in neither. But

    pra

    matically it is established as

    backgrtmod

    in (41a), while the ma:co clause IS

    established as background in (41~).

    Such

    variation is pos(r:ble in En

    acivcrbial clauses may either precede or follow their main claus

    impossible in some languages, where ADV-clauses - as well as

    c;rlly-background clauses -

    can only p,rcxede asserted/main

    clau

    languages pre-pose all “topic/background clauses”, includin

    REL-clairses,V-complements (of ‘knolv’ or ‘think’) and other “topic” clauses.

    In other languages, ADV-clauses in text are overwhelming& pre-posed (241.

    Unlike IF-clauses, BECAUSE-claua es are “logically presuppositional”. But

    t.hey tou eshibit the same discourse-pragmatic variation as IF-clauses. Thus

    +zonsider :

    C~mt xt

    What did she do bee.ause he instrlled her?

    Reply: Because he insulted her, she slapped him.

    Context: Why did she s/tip him?

    RepI): She slapped him because he insulted her.

    Mere lo@x~Hy the BECALJSE-clause is presuppositional tn both (4

    (42d). Pragmatica ly, however, it is backgrounded in (42b) but

    for

    (42d). Logical presupposition, involving, ‘“truth values”, is thus a

    phenomenon, often corresponding to - but never id~l~ti~al wi

    cases of pragmatic backgrounded-ncss.

    [23] For an exmplc from C hunve, a clausa.chaining Papwer-Naw

    ( 198Ob).

    [24] Greenberg ( 1966) ha:, crbscrved that in the languages in his survey,

    s

    type,

    he dominant tendency was roughly &I pm~~t of A~V~l~u~ in

    20% post-possd.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    23/53

    103

    The semrmticsf

    co

    tion verbs such as ‘know’ or ‘think’ was an early

    in linguistics. where ohe

    een ‘“factive” (presuppolsi-

    “non-factive” (non

    c,

    (see e.g. Kiparsky

    Given (1973a), inter alia).

    ns to break down when one

    being an “exotic”

    is in fact ~~~~n~~rvas~,ve,lthough its surface coding

    and Nichols in prep.).

    nya Rwanda (see Giv6n and

    hink’ are the same

    resupposed from

    ment ~la~s~. In addition however, Rwanda has an

    evidentiality

    in the

    w something from

    it via

    hem-say

    or

    in~~~~n~~. you use

    another. This is, inherently, a sc&r, non-discrete space

    of .rMbJecticle

    erbnty qf the speaker

    concerning

    An, logical presupposition

    extreme edge

    of a much

    licated.

    Superficially, one would expect a

    “dir

    her certainty” and “fact/truth”.

    tain.

    For example, in Sherpa

    e Life of the Buddha, is

    er that the story-teller

    true i-:h he most absoi

    sense of the word [ZS].

    am other story-tellers.

    ~~~n~~~he ~ef of the hearsay mode.

    ntcd the traditional notion of “subject”.

    one-place predictations,

    nce the predicate (7) is

    t fsf the propositions bound by either an

    referred to as ‘“subject”. Things

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    24/53

    104

    T. ihka/Li@c ws. riqm utics

    become

    more coqdicated, however,

    when the predicate itself is nominal.

    is generic, a logician may yet resort to some type-theory 8

    to explain why one of the two nominals

    in

    the sentence ia

    other the predicate, and thus explain the contrast in 126

    (43)

    (a) John is a farmer

    (b) * A Farmer is John

    But it is doubttul if logicali criteria alone could dcxidc w

    ich ~o~nal is t

    subject and which is the prediicate in cases where both are equally ref~r~nt~~l

    and definite, as in:

    (44) (a) The teacher is the cook

    Ib) The cook is the teacher

    To linguists and speakers, however, (44a: b) are not int

    eablC2: ut they

    depend on the rather nebulous (from the logician’s poin view) cri&rion of

    “what one is talking about”, a notion that cannot be defined within the bounds

    of isolated propositions, but is rather

    discourse-cont,crxtensitiue.

    In handling two-place predicates, the logician could

    notions such as AGENT and PATIENT, then translat

    KILL (John), (Bill),. Blurt his notation will 61ot d

    active and its corresponding passive. The lo

    “atomic” notion SUBJECT, then characterize the active as KILL (J~hn~~~

    (Bill), and the passive as KILL (J~.)hn)~ Bill),. But as

    lire

    would know, “subject”

    is

    not an atomic notion, but ETJ:

    pragmatic entity closely related to the notion “topic’*.

    I have already discussed the use of both subject

    dislocation in discourse, (see section 3 above), and

    s

    agreement is used to refer to the

    amtinuing

    clausal topic, v+ ile left-di$l~~ti~n

    is used to mark the switching/disruptive clausal topic, Consider nail:

    WV

    . Now John, I saw

    him leaving a while back..

    .

    -I- 1___1

    TOP SIJBJ

    In normal conversation context, a constructional such as

    (4

    when ‘John’ is :)eing rc-inhroduced into the discussion

    while ‘I’ repreLents the continued topic. Clearly,

    t

    posiit an atomic, context-free notion “subject’” to d

    that notion is tied together with many other devices along a scak? which we

    (26) All other thing& eing,quaI, the referential

    scope

    f the subject must be nat~owr than that of

    the predicate.See discussion in Giv$n ( 1973a) and Keenan ( 1976).

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    25/53

    ic us,

    105

    dy shown to be discourse-pra

    matic i,n nature. The f;ar;~ hat :%ome

    c sub~sys~em ean be described in seemiq&-

    but it ~erta~~Iy does not justify viewing the

    ordinary-language

    cd. Rather, the material

    s”, ‘Lconve’:nional

    nt the speech-act foundations

    tie system (see @rice ( 196V/ 1975)

    matic precipice to tvhich

    s section li am going to

    e discreteness of

    ation of a clause is marked by vet% suffixes,

    t-point

    continuum between the tw,o extreme

    alive,

    as given in table 2. The difference

    in terlns of the

    see that we are

    rmatory or corrective reapon se.

    which by themselves make the traditional

    atsve a hopeless

    point on the

    au (1973: JO), and was brought to my attenticm by Charlie Sato

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    26/53

    The eight-point oontinuusn between the two extreme points of declaratitsc an’d interrog;;

    -~~

    Particle Traditional label Degree/type of SW

    (I)

    (2)

    0

    -yo

    I%clarati ve

    Ncu tral

    Assertive

    (3

    (4)

    -na

    -kanaa.

    -ne

    Exclama ory

    Confirmative

    (5)

    (6)

    -desyoo

    -daroo

    -kadooka

    Presumptive (polite)

    Presumptive (plain)

    Rhetorical

    in

    0 Informal

    i i ; 3

    -ka

    Formal

    Interrogative

    certainty; not expectin

    High certainty; cxpcotin

    be&g emphatic m order

    surprise (and thus less ~~rt~~nty~

    Low certainty; inviting challsngc or

    comment

    More presupposed question; artswer is

    expected as either yes or no

    Rhetorical qtustion when rcpnti s fairly

    sure of an answer

    Lower corttinty in the answer, more

    reliance on hcorer’s response

    Lowest certainty: f~rtnai nnd deferent to

    the hearer, au;1 thus by implication more”

    dcpeeZcnt 011 response

    exercises cklicate

    pragmaf i c judgmeJr l f

    concerni various probabilities, such 8s

    his or her own certainty and validity of sou of infornx\tion, the hear&s

    kmowledgc:, he hearer’s willingness to respond DenevolentlIy and the he~rec’s

    disposition to attack or challenge. And in Japanese at least, subt.le computa-

    tions of the

    socia l grad ient

    between the speaker and hearer must also

    into account, and those are not fully independent of the more

    considerations.

    Of course, one does not have to stray far to find :;imilar

    tag-questrcws

    in English are clearly an intermediate grade bletween d

    and interrogatives. Further, the normal yes-no question pattern in

    not neutral, but rather is systematically

    brasled

    (Jward either

    negative response (see Bolinger (1975) $‘ordetails and argun~~~,t~.So that only

    the explicit construction below represents total ‘neutrality”:

    (46) Given p and non-p, please tel. me which one is true

    One could also show that the data of

    inchw speda acts

    points toward

    another continuum between dwlarative and

    imperativ

    , where at least the

    followin: graded dimensions must be involved:

    (a) The degree of the speaker’s attempt to elicit action from the hearer

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    27/53

    e information ~~~~~~~r~~~y the speaker is relevant

    ssessed by the speaker)

    ~~t~~ly relevant on top of the

    of the type mentioned

    intruding. The entire

    f non-discreteness and

    e edges of the system

    to logical-deductive

    h topics “hat, in one .Nay or another, have

    iogieians fo;la uite a while. But C~FT of

    from the use of

    human

    language in

    en touched by logicians. One of those is the

    an NP CK phr,sse: or a larger chunk - as a

    8 “comment” in a s sequent sentence. As a fairly

    consider the followi left-dislocated example in ti

    I like Reagan.

    an, how do you like

    the sky is blue,

    uld say that. in principle anything could

    that is within the cognitive network

    within the network, and the only

    is “‘b,y whaq

    de e?“, “by how many

    w, if the cognitive

    ument holds for the paoblem of smunt ic rclatcdness in

    nctwarrks and semantic change. Example

    :%y, bl;4rsrd nd, ud is reminiscent of the

    y childhood, such BD:“Thrxe were QIMXwo brothers, the first

    one was tell and hmdwm, and the wad

    one likaia heese oo”.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    28/53

    nety,+rorkwere a clased, deductive system, then in principle crne c&d specilt”y

    the degree of connectedness in an sxnct way, pointing out to a discrete number

    of

    specific computational steps. B11t t is clear that the kind of ~o~~side~at~ons

    undlerlying relevance judgment in the examples above are totally

    they are sen: itive to anything the spc aker might suspat the hearer

    to, including triviaI and accidental information that belies systematic fsrma&

    zatiort. In principle, then, the problem of topic relevance, which plays a crucial

    role: in the use of language in communication - including the more “syntactic

    lo&ing” processes discussed in section 3 above - cannet be dealt with within b

    lo&A-deductive sys,em, without trivializing it or ma$king its exp

    cat’~ons 291.

    9. The context-depedent, relativiftic nature of texical meaning

    In the analysis of the “purely semantic” lexical meaning. the same Positivist

    tradition of

    radical reduct ion ism

    observed by Quine ( 1953: 20-46) in philsso-

    phy lhas largely prev;.Gled in linguistics. One is thus conditioned to talk about

    %emantic features” as if they are atomic, absolute, primal units of meaning in

    the grand tradition of Carnap (1947) and Katz and Fodor (1963). Everr.people

    f#nr c:moved fr;;m this tradition,

    such as the

    Diverians (see, for example, Garcia

    (

    1975) or Kirsner ( 1979). inter alia), proceed upon the assurrpt ion that it is

    possible to

    segregattt the “core meaning” of words or morphemes, twhiuh is

    invariant and context-free, from “contextual inferences” which are contingent

    and context-sensitive:.

    U’ittgenstein (1953) challenged this tradition of logical atomism from two

    $#e:parateperspectives, and I would like to deal with his second clhallerl

    III hills

    Investigatiorrs,

    Wittgenstein attacks logical atomism by citing

    BOONS nd

    fanlily-~~selnb~~anc~s,

    nd in general vcwnbulary items that are more

    CJbviously culturally-dependent.

    The Positivists and their conscious or unconsci-

    ous followers in inguisti,cs are forced to concede the for

    iirgument, but confine its scope t,o what they consider tea

    c:lf the semantic system, while continu

    to int

    in

    terms of a closed deductive system

    eman

    “projection”,

    “analyticity” and “contradiction” within such a s:fstem. What

    I

    would like to do in this section is demonstrate, with a few rather ~im~l~~mminded

    cxamplcs, how the shoe is on the other foot, and how what Wit

    ein

    demonstrated to be the “less objective” margins of the semantic s

    of

    *natural language is in fact true

    with u vengemce

    for the entire systen~

    Suppose you and I were taking a wallk in ~r~m~~~lurnbiax~lcur.hwestern

    Colorado, and suppo,se we both saw the followin

    (291G&e (1 8/75), for example, includes “relevance” in one of his maxims without further

    6tmplification.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    29/53

    (48) A

    man is slow y walking up a hiil; he reaches the

    to

    , then he kneels

    down ir?r ront of a pile of stones and raises his ~krms o the sky.

    And su

    we had

    ta d

    asked us both: “What was that man doing?“, and

    in

    the event* with you claiming (49a) a,~d I claiming

    1 endeavor to

    show how both “p ng” and “mourning”

    y meani

    constructs. But how

    ts of ~4g)~Ccynsider firs slowly”, and it is easy

    is totally rel~~tivisti~~ clstcrrlt-determined, ft>unded upon

    er, hot fixed but rather depends

    n t/movernen

    t

    involved [301. Wow

    e GriYeria iffctrcntiati tag“walking”

    ” from “running” ? Well, how about “up”? At

    “physical” horizontal plane does

    to move “upward”? And is that irbsolute horizental plane defined in

    mference? In terms of our visu.31

    of the horizon? Next, take “l~ill”, and wonder how it is to be

    ~liff~r~ntiat~d from “mound”, “heap”, “pile”. “peak” or “‘mountain”‘. Size has

    obviously s#methin to do with it, but their there’s nothing absolute about si:ze

    mouse is much I;maller than a smal elephant. Take

    nder about the point where one reaches the top (of

    especially something sue ich does not have a discrejre,

    pex but rather curves

    )roct:ed to “kneel” - how

    eeling? And how elevated

    nd need to bc:” And is kn:+contact neces-

    knee to tht: yoint of con~~t/approach. is

    ? And - horror of horrors - what exactly is the

    At this point the ~‘Qsitivistshoutd be unable to contain him- or herself and

    the objective, sci :ntific nature of our

    nd b,r:tween the femur and the tibia/fibula,

    m what perspective are he femur and

    e a b~n.c~i/j~int between them” Let us consider

    (see fig.

    1

    b 1, and mac~*o (see fig.

    abi;,ut optical trick:-; and the finesse of

    Plrdee

    1 wish to

    defer the discussion1 of

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    30/53

    whether scientific truth is in any sense subject to less-pragmatic imd more-ob-

    jective criteria of meaning (see discussion in C3iv6n 19’7%: c6 8). But the

    cognitive map represented in language clearly judges wheths:r objects are

    A

    ‘;

    Fig. 1. Three perspectives of the knee: (a) normal, (h) micro, and (c) macro.

    strnight or bent in a ~h-m~e-dqw~~dm~ way given a

    p

    rticular per.,; 2

    * tivc an

    utilitarian context.

    Let us &I;; in to invest ion of “in frant’“, and we

    fine? that different cultures construe it di

    ith

    respect to

    the position

    of the observer/reporter, the physical ~hara~t~risti~s of t~hdt

    w

    vo’rved, and their relative position v:ls4+is each other [3

    1).

    And

    thzse three dimensions is potentially a continuum, We ma

    now, and face the same relativistic problems as with

    “1

    “stones”. and worrv how different they are from ‘kxks” or

    *‘I

    to “raksiqg’?,

    where we must worry about what an

    (3 11 Hill (1974) illustrates such differcncws between &q&h and Wausa ia their constrwtian of

    spatial relation terms.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    31/53

    ’ to hold, And on to ‘%rm” where similar problesns as seen above for

    critlekl angks, visual field etc.

    the

    moment separate -

    matterr is the envy

    lllrfboth biologists and behav-

    cur ~~~~~~~ -- become, the more and finer

    dently of the inst~m~nt~ti~n. Thcrt reality may indeed exist, but v&; is the

    in any sense “objective”? Obviously, clnlv from

    at is in principle denkd to us (331 - C:CN& ne

    support such a faith. The specifics certainly have not

    is in principle a pragmatic matter, a,

    mo;st concede the great areas in our

    frames have: been establishe:J by

    tk

    that they etre forever

    ty is rerr;.i.ve in two

    tivistic areas in our cognitive map; and

    and context-sensi+ %terwon

    of re ative areas of

    prkgmati:: map of

    hi8

    qwat fqt tke

    Bhwal in *Mattltiiessen1978).

    to stimulating axc:hmp with Tan Bikmn and

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    32/53

    reality is a useful feature of su~~iu~zl, functional ~w&.s

    operandi

    of bi~~~~nti~nt

    sys terns:

    no rapid

    dechion making, action schemata and c~t~~~~i~~ ~~/~~

    & oices for survival are possible othefwise. The ~bj~:tiv~tio~

    alization of reality is a prime SW a&linked feature slf such syi

    manifesting itself repeatedly at

    evels of percll:ption and

    c

    re-creating itself -

    out of the inherently pragmatic,

    discreteness, by re-framing or

    re-adjustin

    exisl~~;~frames

    shaill see directly below, Fluch

    re-ad.justme:

    is a f~l~d~~e~~t

    and language change.

    IO. Pra;gmat~cs

    Ever since Saussure:, linguists have tended to s~gregute dja~hr~~nic from syn-

    chronic study, pretending that it was possib e to appreciatt: langu

    . . .

    any fpen porn :t was C* *Ab.w 3JJbWll .

    f;v&q c.,,c*fim” jp.:lr, ;r :n 4am.P.tfi4 a-.-t :a

    v ra.llc~1c 1.3LBUC; ciuac bUW1 IU

    a

    necessary methodol~~jcal-heuristic stelp (see discussion in Givbn 1979a:

    ch. 6), it is still the fact that language - within the minds of speakers, rather

    than as some abstract system of lartlpage

    lexicon/meaning, syntax, morphology and

    map is thus not only a system of codin

    system of re-cuding, modifying and re-

    integrating into it newly-acquired lcnow

    tradition, such modification is often repre as a purely forma

    permuting and re-combining a fixed inventory of atomic primitiv

    the order of relati~~ely-fixed formal rulsec,

    hus

    totally trivializing

    language change (see, for example,

    1976b)), and also making diachronic ii

    logico-deductive dogma.

    There are three aspects of aiachronic ch t that would be incom

    with a formal/deductive approach to meani

    (i)

    T/w system-parts dependmcy: III 11 10

    primitives are fixed, and any “change

    involving formal deductions from exi

    1918). Further, the primitives in suclh

    value and are thus

    not

    system~d~~~~nd~nt.

    show ; rathe).* Aearly that in human

    tan

    subtritct&, split or merged, and that

    further,

    a

    syste*m eqkes re-definition of the entire system.

    (ii) Ohen-ende&Js; Aside from Goedel’s abservat ions r’n~~~~~~~~~~~

    edueti

    systems are closed and can absorb no new primitives,

    tions that are not deducible from existing ones. The hum

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    33/53

    9 clearly attests to the open-

    ity to absorb new knuwledge without

    e a number of typical examples of diachronic ~zhange

    word-order and syntactic structure, In each close I

    -deductive analysis of whilt goes on is in

    matic characterization i$; im

    of the argument will remain

    as the system of knowledge represent ation

    it could not possibly be a. deductive-based

    e evolution will be

    h “know’ and ‘can’

    , WC

    Anttils ( 1977) and An Jersen

    vernaldcvdopments ts(>k place mostly based

    an aorist-perfcxl stem

    Ided Modern E

    know. On tke

    other hand,

    (OHG km, Modem G kcran, inlinitive

    which &a yieldccl Moden E WI. The

    the 0 mm ‘lmtm’

    and OE

    cemm and

    ccnmm.; this fbtnote

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    34/53

    114

    T.

    Giorin/ l ogic OS.

    pragma ics

    SO) If one knows how tcl do something,

    thea the probability is higher tlat one

    cari do

    it.

    That the inference in (50) is probabilistic/inductive rather than deductive is

    easy to see, since “ability to do” involves not only “‘knswin how to ~~~~~ut

    also possibly “having the physical power to”, “having the ll-pawer to” or

    “being physically/mentally un-restrained”. NOW, if the senzz “be aMe to”’ can

    be pragmatically/contextually inferred, then presumably “know” at that his-

    torical stage in English may be described as ~~A”~entotrs, oughly

    alon

    following lines:

    (51) KNOW +

    ‘be able to’/‘know how to pIerform an act’

    -+ ‘know’/elsewhere

    In (51), then, ‘know’ is the “core rneanin~,“’ and ‘can’ a special case in a

    narrower context, still pragmatically inferable as in (SO). Next what must have

    occurred is a ~&?~J&?&~&,ogjf&yg?? Cg?,

    gain,

    pr~~mat,ic,/inAnlry;up in fia p,

    a**UUY*1 Y

    roughly on the line:

    (52) If one

    can

    do something because one kmvs how to do it, perhaps one can

    do it for other reasons as well, such a’s (i) physical/mental power, or (ii)

    being unrestrained.

    Deductively such an inference is absolutel,y unwarranted, but irtdz~ctive

    t

    proceeds along a “family resemblnnce” cline, noting the “similari iy” between

    the three sense: of ‘ability’ (qinowledg,e

    how,

    power and litck of

    outside

    restraint). Once such an infererce has czcurred, however, the structure of the

    lexical item KNOW as in (51) - with ‘ability’ defined as a contextual variant of

    ‘knowledge’ -

    is now disrupted, since the (:ther senses of ability have nothing

    to do with knowledge. At this stage spe&ers face

    t, between the

    semantic domain of ABILITY and that irlf KNOW bcth of which

    overlap at one point, namely the sense “knowing how to”. The conflict, in this

    particular case, was resolved by t&in advantage of the phone

    kann,/catt, which (presumably by so inferential/inductive st

    all its ‘know’ senses except “know how to do’ - and absorbed the other ‘can9

    senses. of power and lack of rzsraint.

    ‘I’lhis

    restructuring may be thus sum-

    marized as:

    (53) KNOW 4 ‘know’

    CAN

    -+ (i) ‘be able to because) of knowled

    (ii) ‘be able to because of power’

    (iii) ‘be He to for lack of restraint’

    But the fortuitous appearance of an l~tymological v~related stem is not a

    prerequisite for the restructuring, Rather, a senzantically-related stem cc&i do

    just as well. This was presumably the c:Ebsen German, where 3Lhe

    know

    that’

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    35/53

    t o wissen

    with

    k t in rw

    ut wissep l ome :

    d is attested irr the L. tIi&-re ‘see’,

    at see was the original

    le: the perfect-resultative

    nd t&us know’. And this

    tion’““

    is again itself the

    e original situat’.on may

    tic i~du~ti~~~

    nf

    nee must have then proceeded:

    The inference from physical. perception to mental cognition is of course lot

    and musi be a human universal [36]. Nevertheless, it is noi. a

    ut rather inductive-probabilistic. Presumably. the next

    ‘,ee’ to ‘know’ in *WI% involved a

    general i zi ng i nferewe

    (56) If one u~~der~~~~r~dsomethin

    because of prior perception/seeing, ma rbe

    then one u~d~~.stands it for other reasons as well, s&r as hearing,

    explanation, inti-ospection, &ine inspiration etc.

    once

    in we hnve an overlap

    betw

    en

    two semantic ofmains, of “cognition”

    with the point of overlap

    which cements the

    fandy

    “understanding due to seeiqg”.

    al variant form, the perfective

    form to carry the restructured

    ) the sti:nse of ‘see anc,l

    loa

    verb

    War’ -wwfw~ms also used for

    .

    Ihit even mom concrete expressions

    ding,/cognition. Tlhus in Amhanc ‘“it

    I

    get/got it” has a similar sense. In

    upon @Othic

    s van,

    QE

    s r,

    etc., themsd’ves

    via exactly the 881HB ype Of

    p~@Tli?W

    inference,

    i.e. 3: QW follows with the eyes (pcial context of 6follow”) tOlenone sees”. Etc. Etc. Etc.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    36/53

    Consider the folJlo~ng gradual ejctension of the ~eanin

    originally a physical-tastcrl- djst IVC:

    (57) (a) sweet apple (physical-taste,

    (b) sweet music ~a~l~io/abstr~~c

    (c) sweet victory (abstract, be~efi~ial/re

    At first glance, one may argue tha.t we have here a straight case of

    ~~~~nti~~

    bleaching, whereby ‘sweet’ has the CXW~~,aniq

    the extensions are

    contextual injeremxs

    from that core

    bleaching the more physical/concrete aspects of meani

    linguist would argue rather strenuously that no semanti

    at all between (57a), (57b) and (57c), bat only a widenmg o

    contextual inferrences (see e.g. arguments in Garcia (197S) and Kirsner (2979)

    inter alia). But the concept of “‘core me,aning” becomes nebulous when one

    considers the fact that the very same h:xical item may mutate in different

    diirections, using glifferent components af its total meani

    cluster as the

    so-calleld “core m.eaning”. IYI his connection, see the discu n of the muta-

    tions o.f the verb ‘sit’, further t>elow. In other words,

    II

    ing withiln the

    semantic field,‘dlomain of a \,xicaJ item can be consider*ed either “core” or

    “‘contextually in1eiSeS” meaning, given particular

    co?mJ:ts.

    But the role of

    context in this casc~ s lo &ffincl

    what is rdmant

    lwithia the domain, what will be

    held cons tan

    t

    anfd thus considered “lzorc:”

    as against what will be mutated and

    thus considered “*contextual inference”. This determinrhtion is

    in pnnciplt~

    nom-deductive,

    bult

    rather involves the pragmatic ju

    me:at of ‘relevana:’ and

    “similarity’. Further, much like the c‘ascs discussed

    10.1

    &tave - ujQc:h a,,t”cz

    *after ah metaphoric in very much tl te

    sam

    resemblance

    rather than with objectiflre/core

    I would like to claim here that all semanti

    kind as metaphoric extension, and

    that

    “semantically related words” simply

    co

    eyes of some scholars. Thus, consider

    extension of the

    Hebrew root

    Vb,

    ‘sit’:

    (58) (a)

    Early stqpB: ib

    ‘sit’

    (b)

    Late4p tqgtr: y-.fb

    ‘sit’

    Jb-t

    ‘rest” -) rest from work’ -+‘st; ike’

    The split between “sit” and ‘rest’ is obviously a cent

    xtual i~f~ren~~ from ‘sit”,

    as are the later extensions of ‘res#t’ oward ‘rest rotn work”

    “strike’. The added

    ~v~~t~~ly

    phonolo cal differentiation most likely

    :

    horn the

    Gnperfeci third-lpelrson ms. sg. prefix y- for ‘sit’

    d the

    ~~~~~~~~g suffix ..t

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    37/53

    essiveuqxct. The

    matit: inference” is

    , where an erstwhile ltm tive-directional

    rzes next the dative/ben+b:factivc marker

    ~~~Q~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~arker, as in lhe case of the

    initia~l~~, proixcds by bleachmg, along a well-

    and the rncw$: Tro

    locative to da t,ive-benefactive

    I ~~~~ati~ steps of’ in~er~~~e involved in ( Sa-d)

    may be

    bjcct

    moves that person

    n, the Arabic guatr’ sit’ has become the

    of Iocatic~ned o temporal

    cxprcs-

    or Givh (I 9’73b). inter dia. The

    ,n widely documented

    (sc:c summary in Givbn,

    b). Similar chanp, up to at least the

    10, Baatu

    ku-,

    Ht:brew Ie-, Sherpa Jr,

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    38/53

    118

    T. Givcin/Logz’c es. prugnwt ics

    (ii)

    If a

    person can be a conscious-recipient o

    conc:r~ti objects, that

    person could aIso ble a conscious/recipient of aEst~aet ideas.

    (iii) If a person is the recipient of anything, chances are he/she is the

    possesmr

    of that thing.

    (iv) Whoever

    possesses

    an object most likely also ~~~~e~~~rom that

    object.

    The probzini istic nature of these inferences, and the family-r~~sembiance char-

    acter 0% the verb-continuum along which

    hey progress, need no further

    elaboration. But how did the inference psogress further

    dative/ benef ac-

    tive to human-accusative? Three facts ab(Dut dative/hen

    tives are involved

    here:

    (a i They are in text overwhelmingly

    human (see

    discussion in Given 1976b,

    1979a: ch. 2):

    (c4) They nre in text overwhelmingly definite (see discussion in Oivon 1976b,

    i 979a ch. 2);

    (c) They have a high probability in discourse/text of undergoing a “dativc-

    shift” and thus being promoted to

    direct

    o@ect/accusatiloe (see discussion

    in Giv6n 1979a: ch. 4).

    Now, in Engfish dative-shifting involves the loss of the

    tposition *to/

    for’,

    but in Spanish it does not. Thus compare the two co

    variant and In& -**wcbc,-u*bject variant,

    in table 3. The an;

    resemblance” nature of this inflerential space next gave rise in Spanish to the

    following inferences:

    (6 1) (a) ‘If an object is

    dative, 1

    has a high probability of also bein

    *and

    def ine e.

    (b’j If an object is

    dat”ue-humarL -deji ’ ,tite,

    t has a hi

    h probability 01’also

    being

    direct object.

    This purely probabilistic re,itsoning i

    s

    responsible for re-a

    others, a.

    human-ac.wat;ve

    marker. But the very same i

    lead 1.0#another resolution. In Swahili, I:‘orexample, (s

    1076b) l;he object agreement/proniun first marked dative objects,

    tlhen

    was

    extended to definite direct objects. ,tnd finally was further ~xt~~d~d

    .- within

    one gender only -

    to be the mnrlier of

    htrmm direct ok$wts,

    indefinite alike. The more general e;utenr;ion in Swahili, then, went from dative

    to dqfirrife-direct object, rather than from dative to )runlcrrr+=Clirectbject.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    39/53

    Direct-objeez vwial?a

    Indirect-object variant

    hat the functional domain of

    ins that overlap in the passive

    (62) (a) th? topic-

    ntiwnt

    domain:

    here a non-agent gets ‘promoted’ to the

    /topic position. Other members of this domain are, e.g.

    ronouns, definitization, right and left dislocation, etc.;

    atisn

    domain: here the iderltity of the agent is sup-

    p~esse~i in various ways. Other members of this domain are various

    rson~)./neut~~l constructions;

    (c)

    the

    stcrtive)l/dc7t~~rasitiveomain:

    here

    an event is construed as a

    st.ate, its “active” p

    erties thus suppressed. Other members

    omain

    are stative-a

    ctivals,

    ref exives, reciprocals, perfec-

    tive-resultatives, etc.

    Now, in ~~iachr~~nic~l~nge giving rise to passive corn>tructions of the “classical”

    ts properties of all three functional domains of

    where the passive arises from constructions

    wit~n eiach d,~m~n that are

    not

    er se passive

    constructions, but rather

    one of the $three domains. Undergoing

    &ly

    acquire some of the properties characteristic of the

    irtvolve the folLowin

    inductive/probabilis-

    t is to bat suppress~rd, he next most likely

    will be likely to become the

    topic of the

    nduc, aqxxt 0% the

    action is to be focused upon,

    the

    staous/identity

    q f

    he agent Is lefss

    important.

    (c) If the clatlse-tcapic is u noti-agent,

    then it is most likely that the

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    40/53

    12 3

    T. xbr/ Lo gic s. pragmatics

    patient-related properties of the event, such as

    state, are /focused upon.

    iits being a uesu&ng

    InEcrence

    (63a)

    leads from the agent-identity-suppression

    1

    domain to

    the topic-

    identification domain. Inference (63h) leads from the st~,tive~iIlt~~ns~~ve o-

    m;lin to the agent-identity-suppression domain. And inferewe (63~) leads from

    t

    hit topic-identification don,ain to the stative-detransitive doma,in. Each is in

    Ijrinciple pragmatic, and each is supported by a wet&h of cross4in

    A’ .5. Word-order change

    lin Old Biblical Hebrew (OBH, see Givoa 1977) the “unmarked” word order

    TNasVSO and a special marked order -

    either an “‘anterior” break in

    -the

    action sequence or a topic-switch - was SVO. In

    rew

    (LBH), the two orders changed their valuation, wit

    the

    unmarked word order -

    in context of both action and topi@ continuity _I_ nd

    VSO assuming specialized, oft-semi-frozen, values (though not the original

    perfect/anterior/topic-switch value of the QBH SVO). This re-analysis also

    inl~~olves crucial change in

    the tense-aspect system, from a perfect-aspect

    system to a past-tense system, whereby the OBH “perfect’” than

    Gon from “anterior” to “past”, while the OBH “imperfect”’

    valuation from “preterit” to “future/non-punctual”. Both UK

    tense-aspect change ; niay be characterized 1s “over-use” prc>8essesof de-mark-

    (b)

    Over-use of the mere marked left-dislocated SW word-order to

    identify subjects that are easier to identify and represent h&$er

    pvdictability/continuity

    than those normally marked by

    left-disl

    tion (see section 3 above). This de-marked the SVO wordmorder:

    Over-use of the anterior “prior to” value that firs/: involved a

    specific

    look-back function

    of “perfect” 8r

    “pluperfect”,

    maki

    mlore general “in the past” :narker. This de-marked t

    and made it a past tense.

    Both changes are well attested elseINhere, mostly il~d~~~~~~l~~,tf each

    other

    [40].Both represent

    an “over-kill” communicative strategy, whereby the speak-e1

    decides

    i

    ha t

    - just for satefy’s sake - he will use a

    more m(arked

    insure beyond ;a shred ,sf doubt tillat thr: hearer

    da-marking or

    deualtrativg

    that device. A

    similar

    de-marking the right-dislocated VS word-order and

    ev

    [M) See Givh

    (I

    911Ob) or the perfect-to-pm change, and Givbn ( 1976b) flor the clc-mwking af

    1~ t-dislocate4 constructions.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    41/53

    T. Gi vbnJLo\gic vs. prapnutics

    121

    e from SV to VS “neutral” word-o

    -r(see discussion in Slobin 1.1977)

    input into such a decision by the

    riety of probabilities, cone erning

    i sepal-interactive factors all per-

    the message without inordinate

    irich a decision procedure could be

    s;rstem. It is inherently a context-

    the child’s acquisi-

    e same kind as the

    in ( 1977) and Givirn

    and enlargement of

    d and of his/her

    necessarily open-

    a Iogico-deductive descriljtion.

    discussion in Givbn 1979a: ch. 7),

    f human language

    and ontogenetic

    only is a deductive-base j account incapable of characteriz-

    age is undergoing at all times, but

    way language has evolved. In this

    sense, thus, ~hornsky’~, profoundly anti-evolutionary view of human language

    is certainly compatible with his view of

    rammar as a closed aigorithmic

    system f4

    11.

    systems,

    ein and

    iucc

    Bert rmd F~uss~ll, n his f Dreword to Wi it

    enstein’s Tractatus, acknowledges

    eductive syste.ms, yet

    noting; that for someone who argued that

    anaged

    to say quite

    nent was of course

    ndamentally misdirected, since

    though Russell’s

    worthy model of

    g been made some

    [4\] TO wit: “,.t It is quite senseless to s&se the prciblem of erplaining the evolution of human

    language ftcrtn more pnmitiw sysre+ns of wmmunication that appeared It lower levels of

    intellectwl crap&y.. . *’ (Chomsky 1968: 59).

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    42/53

    decades earlier by Peirce (see Peirce ( 1455) and discussion in Anrtila (1977)).

    Both saw c;learly that a deductive, axiomatic system cannot express new

    information, but only

    tau3Qlugies

    totally familiar knowledge) or

    c~~ntrud~cti~n~

    (totally

    strange and un-integrable knowledge). Peirce

    went on to win the tam

    “abduction” to characterize the kind (Dfnon-de

    uctive inference, inductian or

    intu iti ve I eap

    that must

    un

    quisitioa of new in~o~~tion~ Still,

    Wittgenstein, perhaps inadv

    down tile foundlations for

    neral

    theory of injbrmation

    within any

    c

    municativc* system - ~ert~nly within

    natusmal language - w3ere

    ‘“new information” alwa ys operates ~me~vhere

    between the two extrr:mes of tautology and contradiction: it cannot be

    t~tul~

    new and thus incompatible with all previous knowledge (Le. ‘~~ontr~~dicto~~‘~.

    And it cannot be

    totally

    old and thus redundant and of no interest (i.e.

    “:autological’“). Wi&in such extreme bounds, one

    coulld

    conceive of the

    seemingly

    logical

    impropriety of tautologies and contradicuons such 8s;

    (65) (a) Joe is a teacher;

    he is tl teacher

    (tautology)

    (b) Joe is a teacher;

    he’ s not a teacher

    (contradictlion)

    as being merely the extreme margins of the system. But the bulk of the system

    of linguistic communications operates somewhere bex~~n these two extremes,

    where “degree of redundancy” and “degree of newness/surprise*’ cannot be

    ruled upon by deductive means, but TL*Iuste inferred

    prqmatico& .

    There ore

    three empirically-based argunlrenlis that militate for such conclusions:

    (; ) The cuntext-dependency argument:

    The logician would consider (ir9a. b)

    above, closed systems, and thus pretend that the contradketory or tauto-

    logical second proposition in each is that way becztuse of the first

    proposition. But the use of language in communicative context is r&e

    open

    in two distinct senses: First,

    generica& ,

    any itelm of shared knowl-

    edge within the culture/lexicon can potentially be an

    im@cit part

    of the

    context for

    any

    prop0

    Second, any span of the “specific/

    context the speaker

    s to be

    within reach

    of the rhea

    legitimate context for a proposition. Decisions on both

    principle

    probabilastic and pragmatic, given the total

    spa

    “context” [42].

    (ii)

    The speaker-hearer argument:

    For logicians, eontext is ‘~obj~tiv~~‘,

    overtly-listed premises. They are never comfortable with “I

    But in language and communication, it is the “I” thett ma

    about what

    -. generically and specifically -- can be taken us the ~~~~~~~

    context for “you”,

    and this horror of subjective, inductive inference would

    (421 Logicians, of COUIBB~reate a sanitized notion of context by listing: a finite number

    of

    propose

    ims as “premises”.

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    43/53

    uctive system wide

    open. In addition, sooner or later the

    with the “‘I” create the classic infinite-

    s paradox), and while a logician may

    s done [43], that does not make the

    section 8, above, even

    diate, visible, proposi-

    o get the logician off

    the hook, This is so

    visible, immed.~ate context is judged by the

    :lance as context. And as we have seen

    t is in prizrrciple crpen-ended and pragmatic.

    ic may define the u pel: boundis of

    systems (the l~~~t~ern~ases), the bulk of the actual

    atic irr nature, where “new” and “o;ld” informa-

    U@ct open ended generic nd specific contexts.

    mv

    context

    m to take symqvmy for granted as d matter of

    iat would find it extrt:mely hard to identify a bona fide case of

    her lexicon or grammar. Marchand (1964) refers to the seeming

    nymq in;l he lexicon 2~s the eccxxmy principle”, and that may

    ect ~~p~~~ati~n, at letrst in part, since one would be hard put to

    ex~~,~~nwhy speak rs should store two forms coding exactly the same meanrng

    or function. Appa nt cases of synonymy tend to dissolve, on closer examina-

    tion, into more subtle semantk, pralirnati:, socia

    istic, dialectal variation.

    On the ather harlkd

    and grammatical ity in sentences olrt of

    cantext -. is much

    ier to document,

    being indeed one of the most pervasive

    s of 1exiCOR n

    types of diachronic changes discussed in

    this, so that in fact language change at all

    Jly-dependent proliferation of senses and

    e two extra @??. oles of the system of

    cOai’n$j

    is the extreme case 01

    ~l;ecoding, where the very same

    one csei e

    bnits. While polysemy is the

    sage units - presumably along

    domain -. are coded by only

    seem to avoid the one extreme so con-

    1’~p~r~dc~~

    nd

    its implications for epis emology and pragmatks in

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    44/53

    fjjistently d indut sistently? The answer,

    1

    clearly abides by this dictum,

    the polysemy/ambiguity end?

    On

    n it violates it so ~~~si~

    If language were a closed, deductive system d~a~in

    meaning, this question would indeed be bafflin

    I believe, already established that lexical and

    in language is

    open-ended

    and

    context-smsitix. Thus t

    can tolerate the seemingly hi incidence of p~ly~~erny

    must be that they constarttly make use of the context ta disa

    while a small core or “m;~rgins” of the semantic syst

    they are absolute and context free”, the bulk is conte.~t-dependent, at least

    --

    when one considers the actuai facts of language use. Gtven su

    ?,nguage, it seems that it &GS indeed “strive to operate” by

    one-to-one correlation between code and message, Either tota

    an infinite number + f:ode-units expressing the same message) or total

    ambiguity (i.e. an infinit c number of messa coded by a sin c~d~~u~~it)

    would be a communicative nightmare. The

    t

    would impose enormou~q

    and non-functional MVIKV~:~’ur&rr. While the ond would impose

    t~~t~~

    ciependenqv cm con ext. I

    seems to me that Ila in fact 8 ~~~_~~~~~

    c*ompror~t~~e

    ystem, relying to some extent on m en - where items

    and rules can be memorized in a relatively “atomic”, context-free

    fmhion

    while to some extent rel>ting on disambi tion via context, where items a&

    rules shift their meaning /usage depend

    That such a compromise should be root

    anism seems too obvious to require further COI

    When one considers the ont

    struck by the fact that

    carlie

    polysemy/ambiguity and

    t

    And that from those earli

    eny of human lan

    more the extreme

    umbiguotrs

    and HIOIV

    ich& coded. I t

    is

    communication and primates communica

    in the extreme (see discussion in Givbn 16

    here-and-now, visible topics and

    I-and-you.

    One may

    thus

    of language, both phylogenetically and

    s:mtax out of discourse, “core meaning” out contextual rn6ani

    out of pragmati:s, and thus - in very much the same s

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    45/53

    c3f context-free,

    n the human organism

    le, .is their fundam~nt~~~ connection and constant interchange

    nt ext-free automated routines and context-sensi-

    First are uscd~ along established, routine path-

    nrajor

    ch.w’ficl;rtory

    nodes of the system, where pre-

    ulate about what \h analytic scannin

    native device is on automatic pilot. One

    tional level - at the

    theme

    the ht urcr - in order to

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    46/53

    14.1. Lmgutqy, cw t tmunicati on nd prugmat ic:l ; s. ogrc

    I think an txnpiricul study of language data, without idea

    or abstracting use, context and eomm

    points out clearly to the fact that 3,@

    stripe can achieve little in eithelr de

    cognition. This is not to say, howevtr, &at

    col;itdstitig

    them with pragmatic ones from

    the

    informatior./cornmunication theory, cannot

    yield some in

    about the parameters that bound cogGtion

    differences betwlcen the two systems ma;y be su

    The fact that a fundamentally prag

    the human orglinism nevertheless gives rise, repeatedly and in various sub-

    systems. to islands of relative firm~~ment/dedu~tabi~ity, is an important evolu-

    tionary and epktemological fact. The hybrid system that is thus treated is

    t-annhlFi fif aAnr9tino tr\ turfi rncaiplr nar-aml*t*rc fif banvirnnmant sank-4 ckrrwiuul*

    YUps”.b V* U”UyCIa.@ Z” b”” “.‘UJ”.

    puW1a.“bY.” Va V*a.*.Va.a.aYI*. w4‘U VU+. .* .U‘W

    Flexi bi l i t y, change and i ndet ermi nacy:

    this is a fundamental fact of reatity,

    and only an organism capable of dealing with it could survive in a real

    universe.

    (ii)

    Speed of decision making, planning and action:

    this is a fundamel~ta~

    Table 4

    Pragmntic processing

    .-

    Ikductive processin

    Spuce

    Context relution

    System bounds

    WC& of inference

    Mode of proof

    Mode of data-

    prwwsing

    Functional distri-

    bution

    Spead of processing

    hlemory/hardwart:

    d cpendence

    Pro~rerm/software

    d~~pendence

    Continuum

    Con tcx dapcnden

    t

    Open-anded, chan~eablc

    Inductive/abductive

    Pwponderonca of cvidencc,

    open

    Analytic

    certainty und high corn--

    plcxi ty

    ‘L,ow p

    Low dapcndcrrce

    Low dependence

    Catc~orial/discrcte

    Context fr

    Closed, fixwl

    uc: ive

    uctive proof, cslosed

    Automatic, ~l~~rjthmic

    certainty crud low corn-

    plexi ty

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    47/53

    in a potentially hostile universe,

    action

    is of the esseracec

    do not reveal a measure of rnutinized

    nis:m in its cognitive evolution has been

    the syntacticized vs. the

    h. 5). it seemed to me then

    , one

    reflective of general

    r the last few years, it has been gratifying to

    find out how that initial hunch indeed pans out. The psychological

    with works on the auto~~at~~ation/rout~nizati~~n of percep-

    ast literature exists concerning the routini-

    neurolo#cal literature

    f feedback-free circuits is

    ard ~11 hese phenomena

    suggest hkolds for the

    t such compartmentalism is bound to be self-defeat-

    rstanding of both what

    ition is now as well as -

    ow it evolved out of so-c

    Q6. itn#tiC ~r~~~~~i~&n perccptkinelnd caglition, alcc

    Kbin ( 1973),

    Pssner

    wd Snyder (19’14). Atkinson arld

    rin (1947),

    inter aNa. Fur

    autsnlatizutiorr nJ rautinizuti0t7

    t (1975,1930),

    hapiro

    nd Ghmidt (in press), Shapwj

    in press), rrsf~dia.

    For the ncurolagical basis f’or

    Margain ( 1950) or Pkllard ( I 960), n, ter

    cd

    routines/reflexes, see Smith (

    I 980) ,

  • 8/15/2019 Givon Logic Pragmatics Epistemology

    48/53

    128

    T. Givh,/ Logic vs. prugntutics

    ability to react to feedback and fast-changing feedback, the copin

    indeterminacies and imponderables.

    Ultimately, think, we must elaborate not only a theory of human co

    as it is now, but aiso a theory ey;plaining the rise of h an cognition 8s m

    ~O/M~UMJ~,biological process. What I believe will em

    as p=t of such a

    theory is a hierarchic view of the evolution of organismic

    functions, whereby

    simple, “lower” functions get routinized via repetition and the eventual catee

    gorization of tokens of both stimulus and behavior as

    “be

    a more

    general typ8 X”.

    This categorization makes routin~~~d of the

    response/behavior possible, thus freeing the analytic, f~~back-dependent

    capacity to seek, create and pursue higher levels of organization. But eventually

    those higher levels get similarly categorized and eventually routinized, etc.,

    perh,aps potentially ad infini~~r?l. Categorization into hieriuchic

    tok~naty~e

    syste.m:; may thus be viewed as the prerquisite for routinization,

    parcel of the same

    eneral process of systems creatioa And

    routini

    processing is what makes it possible, in turn, to keep increasing the

    depth of

    the

    processing system, by freeing the analytic capacity to pursue the next

    level.

    14.3. TIie rise

    of order out of chaos: C’ arnup and Wittgenstein revisited

    To some extent, the rise of deductive, closed, well-ordered, discrete and

    algorith,mic systems out of the non-discrete, chaotic mire of pragmatics must

    remain a fundamental mystery of the sentient organism. Philosophical exm

    tremists since time immemorial, be they Western epistcmolo

    ts and

    latter-day

    logical a tomists or mushy mystics and late-Wit -outs of whs tevcr

    stripe, have all striven to represent the roots o

    gnition as one of the extreme

    poles. Ia’epistemology is