george sher, approximate justice. studies in non-ideal theory

4
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3: 213–215, 2000. BOOK REVIEW George Sher, Approximate Justice: Studies in Non-Ideal Theory . Maryland, U.S.A.: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 1997, xiv + 185 pp. ISBN 0-847-68753-8. In the preface to his book, George Sher tells the unsuspecting reader that he will be defending some ‘unpopular decisions’ in contemporary moral and legal philosophy. The papers comprising the book, all except one of which having appeared in professional journals over the last 23 years, bear testament to this. Despite being a collection, the book is coherent and covers issues including compensation, anti-discrimination legislation, preferential treatment, the moral standing of groups and subsidised abortion. In ‘Ancient wrongs and modern rights’, Sher argues for restrictions on compensation resulting from misdeeds which pre-date the lives of claimants, e.g., blacks whose forebears were enslaved in the U.S. The theme is continued in ‘Compensation and transworld personal identity’: if compensation is to be based on comparing a person’s well-being after having been discriminated against with that in a possible world in which no such discrimination befalls the person, then a condition for valid comparison is that the person’s identity be sufficiently similar across worlds, something which may be vitiated by the discrimination itself. Perhaps the well-being of similarly-placed people should form the yardstick, an idea which Sher pursues in all its ramifications. Further restrictions on compensation are heralded in ‘Justifying reverse discrimination in employment’ in which Sher advocates that only cases in which individuals are rendered less able to compete with others be apt for positive discrimination, not cases characterised by disinclination amongst members of a certain group to seek employment in certain sectors, e.g., women in academic, political and higher-managerial professions. Neither, in instances of competitive disadvantage, may individuals, by virtue of their membership of a particular group, be subjects of reverse discrimination, a topic to which essay 4 is dedicated. Sher’s arguments manifest rigor, whilst maintaining contact with our intuitions. They nevertheless hover in a space somewhat adrift from political practice. A sign of this is the frequent allusion to epistemological

Upload: mark-peacock

Post on 03-Aug-2016

212 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

BOOK REVIEW 213

Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3: 213–215, 2000.

BOOK REVIEW

George Sher, Approximate Justice: Studies in Non-Ideal Theory.Maryland, U.S.A.: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 1997, xiv+ 185 pp. ISBN 0-847-68753-8.

In the preface to his book, George Sher tells the unsuspecting readerthat he will be defending some ‘unpopular decisions’ in contemporarymoral and legal philosophy. The papers comprising the book, all exceptone of which having appeared in professional journals over the last23 years, bear testament to this. Despite being a collection, the bookis coherent and covers issues including compensation, anti-discriminationlegislation, preferential treatment, the moral standing of groups andsubsidised abortion.

In ‘Ancient wrongs and modern rights’, Sher argues for restrictionson compensation resulting from misdeeds which pre-date the lives ofclaimants, e.g., blacks whose forebears were enslaved in the U.S. Thetheme is continued in ‘Compensation and transworld personal identity’:if compensation is to be based on comparing a person’s well-beingafter having been discriminated against with that in a possible worldin which no such discrimination befalls the person, then a conditionfor valid comparison is that the person’s identity be sufficiently similaracross worlds, something which may be vitiated by the discriminationitself. Perhaps the well-being of similarly-placed people should formthe yardstick, an idea which Sher pursues in all its ramifications. Furtherrestrictions on compensation are heralded in ‘Justifying reversediscrimination in employment’ in which Sher advocates that only casesin which individuals are rendered less able to compete with others beapt for positive discrimination, not cases characterised by disinclinationamongst members of a certain group to seek employment in certainsectors, e.g., women in academic, political and higher-managerialprofessions. Neither, in instances of competitive disadvantage, mayindividuals, by virtue of their membership of a particular group, be subjectsof reverse discrimination, a topic to which essay 4 is dedicated.

Sher’s arguments manifest rigor, whilst maintaining contact with ourintuitions. They nevertheless hover in a space somewhat adrift frompolitical practice. A sign of this is the frequent allusion to epistemological

BOOK REVIEW214

limitations in deciding what the right policy is. Without denying theimportance of such factors, I found myself asking whether they areof such significance to issues the natural habitat of which is politics.If, that is, Sher’s book is to be of relevance outside the academy, hemust tackle his themes on a different terrain. It is one thing, forexample, to argue that Millian utilitarianism does not justify feministclaims that there is something wrong with ‘women’s traditionalpreferences’ (essay 8), but another altogether to combat (should oneso wish) the claims of feminists in practice, where the terms of debatediffer from those in philosophy.

These tensions are particularly manifest in the book’s later essays,e.g., ‘Predicting performance’, in which Sher considers assessmentmethods for job applicants. His target here is Thurow, who sees theinevitability of employers’ use of ‘group membership’ as a criterion forselection and who further writes that the state must distinguish betweenlegitimate and illegitimate group membership criteria. However, Thurowprovides no answer to the question: ‘Which groups?’ De facto, theanswer is: ‘Whichever group has the requisite means for politicalorganisation’. Sher’s dissatisfaction with this is admirably argued, but howgreat is the chance that the political terrain will be changed by philosophicalargument?

In ‘Subsidized abortion’, we find Sher at his most prescriptive. Headvocates compromise in the war between pro- and anti-abortionists basedon a mutual acknowledgement of the fallibility of the positions which eachside holds. That abortions are permitted implies that ‘we have in effectreached a societal judgment that the practice is not seriously wrong’(156),something which, in Sher’s mind, blocks a blanket appeal to the rights ofa foetus to life. On the other hand, if the government were to initiatecontraception and expanded adoption programmes, thus reducing thenumber of abortions necessary, then we may ‘reasonably ask’ of thosewho oppose abortion that they abjure those tactics which are moreapposite in civil war than moral debate. We can be grateful that bothsides have their share of those who accept such compromises andtolerate their opponents. But do they do so because of the epistemologicalfallibility of their position, or do our moral intuitions become formedbefore, and independently of, their epistemological grounds? And whatof those anti-abortionists who conceive Sher’s ‘societal judgment’ tobe a license for mass murder? It is too facile to see the de factoexistence of abortion as a stable starting point which all parties to thedebate must de jure accept.

BOOK REVIEW 215

There is many a salutary lesson to be drawn from Sher’s book, andphilosophers would do well to follow his lead in examining the politicaldebates of our time with all their sobering consequences.

MARK S. PEACOCKLehrstuhl für Volkswirtschaft und PhilosophieUniversität Witten/HerdeckeGermany

and

Wolfson CollegeUniversity of CambridgeUK

BOOK REVIEW216