framework - georgetown 2014

Upload: charles-miller

Post on 03-Jun-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    1/24

    notes

    None of these cards are highlighted- you should do that yourself so you can familiarize yourself with

    them. The 2nc overview is also more of a guide- you have to fill large parts of that out yourself based on

    what you want from the cards.

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    2/24

    framework

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    3/24

    1nc

    Resolved is legislative

    Parcher 1- Jeff Parcher, former debate coach at Georgetown, Feb 2001

    http://www.ndtceda.com/archives/200102/0790.html

    Pardon me if I turn to a source besides Bill. American Heritage Dictionary: Resolve: 1. To make a firm decision about. 2. Todecide or express by formal vote. 3. To separate something into constiutent parts See Syns at *analyze* (emphasis in orginal) 4. Find a solution

    to. See Syns at *Solve* (emphasis in original) 5. To dispel: resolve a doubt. - n 1. Firmness of purpose; resolution. 2. A determination or

    decision. (2) The very nature of the word "resolution" makes it a question. American Heritage: A course of action determined or

    decided on. A formal statement of a decision, as by a legislature. (3) The resolution is obviously a

    question. Any other conclusion is utterly inconceivable. Why? Context. The debate community

    empowers a topic committee to write a topic for ALTERNATE side debating. The committee is not a

    random group of people coming together to "reserve" themselves about some issue. There is context -

    they are empowered by a community to do something. In their deliberations, the topic community

    attempts to craft a resolution which can be ANSWERED in either direction. They focus on issues like

    ground and fairness because they know the resolution will serve as the basis for debate which will be

    resolved by determining the policy desirablility of that resolution. That's not only what they do, but it's

    what we REQUIRE them to do. We don't just send the topic committee somewhere to adopt their own

    group resolution. It's not the end point of a resolution adopted by a body - it's the preliminary wording

    of a resolution sent to others to be answered or decided upon. (4) Further context: the word resolved is

    used to emphasize the fact that it's policy debate. Resolved comes from the adoption of resolutions by

    legislative bodies. A resolution is either adopted or it is not. It's a question before a legislative body.

    Should this statement be adopted or not. (5) The very terms 'affirmative' and 'negative' support my

    view. One affirms a resolution. Affirmative and negative are the equivalents of 'yes' or 'no' - which, ofcourse, are answers to a question.

    USFG should means the debate is only about government policy

    Ericson 3(Jon M., Dean Emeritus of the College of Liberal ArtsCalifornia Polytechnic U., et al., The

    Debaters Guide, Third Edition, p. 4)

    The Proposition of Policy: Urging Future Action In policy propositions, each topic contains certain key elements,

    although they have slightly different functions from comparable elements of value-orientedpropositions. 1. An agent doing the acting ---The United States in The United States should adopt a policy of freetrade. Like the object of evaluation in a proposition of value, the agent is the subject of the sentence. 2. The verb should the first part of a

    verb phrase that urges action. 3. An action verb to follow should in the should-verb combination. For example, should adopt here means to put

    a program or policy into action though governmental means. 4. A specification of directions or a limitation of the action desired. The phrase

    free trade, for example, gives direction and limits to the topic, which would, for example, eliminate consideration of increasing tariffs,

    discussing diplomatic recognition, or discussing interstate commerce. Propositions of policy deal with future action. Nothing has yet occurred.

    The entire debate is about whether something ought to occur. What you agree to do, then, when you accept the

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    4/24

    affirmative side in such a debate is to offer sufficient and compelling reasons for an audience to perform

    the future action that you propose.

    Voting issue

    Preparation and clashchanging the topic post facto manipulates balance of prep,

    which structurally favors the aff because they are able to choose the initial framework

    for debate and permute non-competitive counter-methodologiesstrategic fairness

    on a limited topic is key to engaging a well-prepared opponentthey force us to give

    up every other pursuit for win debates

    Harris 13(Scott, April 5 This ballot by Scott Harris

    http://www.cedadebate.org/forum/index.php?topic=4762.0, nkj)

    I understand that there has been some criticism of Northwesterns strategy in this debate round. This criticism is premised on the ideathat they ran framework instead of engagingEmporias argument about home and the Wiz. I think this criticism is unfair.

    Northwesterns framework argument did engage Emporias argument. Emporia said that you should

    vote for the team that performatively and methodologically made debate a home. Northwesterns

    argument directly clashed with that contention. My problem in this debate was with aspects of the execution of theargument rather than with the strategy itself. It has always made me angry in debates when people have treated topicality as if it were a less

    important argument than other arguments in debate. Topicality is a real argument. It is a researched strategy. It is an

    argument that challenges many affirmatives. The fact that other arguments could be run in a debate or

    are run in a debate does not make topicality somehow a less important argument. In reality, for many of youthat go on to law school you will spend much of your life running topicality arguments because you will find that words in the law matter. The

    rest of us will experience the ways that word choices matter in contracts, in leases, in writing laws and in many

    aspects of our lives. Kansas ran an affirmative a few years ago about how the location of a comma in alaw led a couple of districts to misinterpret the law into allowing individuals to be incarcerated in jail for

    two days without having any formal charges filed against them. For those individuals the location of the

    comma in the law had major consequences. Debates about words are not insignificant. Debates about

    what kinds of arguments we should or should not be making in debates are not insignificant either. The

    limits debate is an argument that has real pragmatic consequences. I found myself earlier this year judging Harvardseco-pedagogy aff and thought to myselfI could stay up tonight and put a strategy together on eco-pedagogy, but then I thought to myself

    why should I have to? Yes, I could put together a strategy against any random argument somebody makes employing an energy metaphor but

    the reality is there are only so many nights to stay up all night researching. I would like to actually spend time playing catch with my children

    occasionally or maybe even read a book or go to a movie or spend some time with my wife. A world where there are an infinite

    number of affirmatives is a world where the demand to have a specific strategy and not run framework

    is a world that says this community doesnt care whether its participants have a life or do well in school

    or spend time with their families. I know there is a new call abounding for interpreting this NDT as a mandate for broader morediverse topics. The reality is that will create more work to prepare for the teams that choose to debate the topic but will have little to no effect

    on the teams that refuse to debate the topic. Broader topics that do not require positive government action or are

    bidirectional will not make teams that wont debate the topic choose to debate the topic. I think that is a conjob. I am not opposed to broader topics necessarily. I tend to like the way high school topics are written more than the way college topics are

    written. I just think people who take the meaning of the outcome of this NDT as proof that we need to make it so people get to talk about

    anything they want to talk about without having to debate against topicality or framework arguments

    are interested in constructing a world that might make debate an unending nightmare and not a very

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    5/24

    good home in which to live. Limits, to me, are a real impact because I feel their impact in my everyday

    existence.

    Debates a gamefairness and rules come first

    Villa 96Dana Villa Political Theory @ UC Santa Barbara Arendt and Heidegger: the Fate of the

    Political p. 37

    If political action is to be valued for its own sake, then the content of political action must be politics in

    the sense that political action is talk about politics. The circularity of this formulation, given by George Kateb, is

    unavoidable. It helps if we use an analogy that Kateb proposes, the analogy between such a purely political politics and a game. A game,

    writes Kateb, is not about anything outside itself, it is its own sufficient worldthe content of any game is

    itself. What matters in a game is the play itself, and the qualityof this play is utterly dependent upon

    the willingness and ability of the players to enter the world of the game. The Arendtian conception of politics is

    one in which the spirit animating the play (the sharing of words and deeds)comes before all elsebefore personal

    concerns, groups, interests, and even moral claims. If allowed to dominate the game, these elements detracts from

    the play and from the performance of action. A good game happens only when the players submit

    themselves to its spirit and do not allow subjective or external motives to dictate the play. A good

    game, like genuine politics, is played for its own sake.

    A limited topic is key to decision-making and advocacy skills

    Steinberg and Freeley 8*Austin J. Freeley is a Boston based attorney who focuses on criminal,

    personal injury and civil rights law, AND David L. Steinberg , Lecturer of Communication Studies @ U

    Miami, Argumentation and Debate: Critical Thinking for Reasoned Decision Making pp45-

    Debate is a means of settling differences, so there must be a difference of opinion or a conflict of interest before there can be a debate. If

    everyone is in agreement on a tact or value or policy, there is no need for debate: the matter can be settled by unanimous consent. Thus, for

    example, it would be pointless to attempt to debate "Resolved: That two plus two equals four," because there is simply no controversy about

    this statement. (Controversy is an essential prerequisite of debate. Where there is no clash of ideas, proposals, interests, or expressed positions

    on issues, there is no debate. In addition, debate cannot produce effective decisions without clear identification of a question or questions to

    be answered. For example, general argument may occur about the broad topic of illegal immigration. How many illegal immigrants are in the

    United States? What is the impact of illegal immigration and immigrants on our economy? What is their impact on our communities? Do they

    commit crimes? Do they take jobs from American workers? Do they pay taxes? Do they require social services? Is it a problem that some do not

    speak English? Is it the responsibility of employers to discourage illegal immigration by not hiring undocumented workers? Should they have

    the opportunity- to gain citizenship? Docs illegal immigration pose a security threat to our country? Do illegal immigrants do work that

    American workers are unwilling to do? Are their rights as workers and as human beings at risk due to their status? Are they abused by

    employers, law enforcement, housing, and businesses? I low are their families impacted by their status? What is the moral and philosophical

    obligation of a nation state to maintain its borders? Should we build a wall on the Mexican border, establish a national identification can!, or

    enforce existing laws against employers? Should we invite immigrants to become U.S. citizens? Surely you can think of many more concerns to

    be addressed by a conversation about the topic area of illegal immigration. Participation in this "debate" is likely to be emotional and

    intense. However, it is not likely to be productive or useful without focus on a particular question and

    identification of a line demarcating sides in the controversy. To be discussed and resolved effectively,

    controversies must be stated clearly. Vague understanding results in unfocused deliberation and poor

    decisions, frustration, and emotional distress,as evidenced by the failure of the United States Congress to make progress onthe immigration debate during the summer of 2007.

    Someone disturbed by the problem of the growing underclass of poorly educated, socially

    disenfranchised youths mightobserve, "Public schools are doing a terrible job! They are overcrowded, and many teachers are poorly

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    6/24

    qualified in their subject areas. Even the best teachers can do little more than struggle to maintain order in their classrooms." That same

    concerned citizen, facing a complex range of issues, might arrive at an unhelpful decision, such as "We ought to do something about

    this" or. worse. "It's too complicated a problem to deal with." Groups of concerned citizens worried about the state of

    public education could join together to express their frustrations, anger, disillusionment, and emotions

    regarding the schools, but without a focus for their discussions, they could easily agree about the sorry

    state of education without finding points of clarity or potential solutions.A gripe session would follow. But if a

    precise question is posedsuch as "What can be done to improve public education?"then a more profitable area of

    discussion is opened up simply by placing a focus on the search for a concrete solution step.One or morejudgments can be phrased in the form of debate propositions, motions for parliamentary debate, or bills for legislative assemblies. The

    statements "Resolved: That the federal government should implement a program of charter schools in at-risk communities" and "Resolved:

    That the state of Florida should adopt a school voucher program" more clearly identify specific ways of dealing with educational problems in a

    manageable form, suitable for debate. They provide specific policies to be investigated and aid discussants in identifying points of difference.

    To have a productive debate, which facilitates effective decision making by directing and placing limits

    on the decision to be made, the basis for argument should be clearly defined. If we merely talk about"homelessness" or "abortion" or "crime'* or "global warming" we are likely to have an interesting discussion but not to establish profitable

    basis for argument. For example, the statement "Resolved: That the pen is mightier than the sword" is debatable, yet fails to provide much

    basis for clear argumentation. If we take this statement to mean that the written word is more effective than physical force for some purposes,

    we can identify a problem area: the comparative effectiveness of writing or physical force for a specific purpose.

    Although we now have a general subject, we have not yet stated a problem. It is still too broad, too loosely worded to promote well-organized

    argument. What sort of writing are we concerned withpoems, novels, government documents, website development, advertising, or what?

    What does "effectiveness" mean in this context? What kind of physical force is being comparedfists, dueling swords, bazookas, nuclear

    weapons, or what? A more specific question might be. "Would a mutual defense treaty or a visit by our fleet be more effective in assuring

    Liurania of our support in a certain crisis?" The basis for argument could be phrased in a debate proposition such as "Resolved: That the United

    States should enter into a mutual defense treatv with Laurania." Negative advocates might oppose this proposition by arguing that fleet

    maneuvers would be a better solution. This is not to say that debates should completely avoid creative

    interpretation of the controversy by advocates, or that good debates cannot occur over competing

    interpretations of the controversy; in fact, these sorts of debates may be very engaging. The point is that

    debate is best facilitated by the guidance provided by focus on a particular point of difference, which will beoutlined in the following discussion.

    Government policy discussions are key

    Esberg and Sagan 12*Jane Esberg is special assistant to the director at New York University's Center

    on. International Cooperation. She was the winner of 2009 Firestone Medal, AND Scott Sagan is a

    professor of political science and director of Stanford's Center for International Security and

    Cooperation NEGOTIATING NONPROLIFERATION: Scholarship, Pedagogy, and Nuclear Weapons Policy,

    2/17 The Nonproliferation Review, 19:1, 95-108

    These governmentor quasi-government think tank simulationsoften provide very similar lessons for high-level

    players as are learned by students in educational simulations. Government participants learn about the

    importance of understanding foreign perspectives, the need to practice internal coordination, and thenecessity to compromise and coordinate with other governments in negotiations and crises.During the ColdWar, political scientist Robert Mandel noted how crisis exercises and war games forced government officials to overcome bureaucratic

    myopia, moving beyond their normal organizational roles and thinking more creatively about how others might react in a crisis or conflict.6

    The skills of imagination and the subsequent ability to predict foreign interests and reactions remain

    critical for real-world foreign policy makers. For example, simulations of the Iranian nuclear crisis*held in 2009 and 2010 at theBrookings Institutions Saban Center and at Harvard Universitys Belfer Center, and involving former US senior officials and regional

    experts*highlighted the dangers of misunderstanding foreign governments preferences and misinterpreting their subsequent behavior. In both

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    7/24

    simulations, the primary criticism of the US negotiating team lay in a failure to predict accurately how other

    states, both allies and adversaries, would behave in response to US policy initiatives.7

    By university age, students often have a pre-defined view of international affairs, and the literature on

    simulations in education has long emphasized how such exercises force students to challenge their

    assumptions about how other governments behave and how their own government works.8 Since

    simulations became more common as a teaching toolin the late 1950s, educational literature has expounded

    on their benefits, from encouraging engagement by breaking from the typical lecture format, to

    improving communication skills, to promoting teamwork.9 More broadly, simulations can deepen

    understanding by asking students to link fact and theory, providing a context for facts while bringing

    theory into the realm of practice.10 These exercises are particularly valuable in teaching international affairs for many of the same

    reasons they are useful for policy makers: they force participants to grapple with the issues arising from a world in

    flux.11 Simulations have been used successfully to teach students about such disparate topics as European politics, the Kashmir crisis, and

    US response to the mass killings in Darfur.12 Role-playing exercises certainly encourage students to learn political

    and technical facts* but they learn them in a more active style. Rather than sitting in a classroom and

    merely receiving knowledge, students actively research their governments positions and actively

    argue, brief, and negotiate with others.13 Facts can change quickly; simulations teach students how tocontextualize and act on information.14

    Substantive constraints on the debate are key to pluralism and agonistic democracy

    Dryzek 6Professor of Social and Political Theory, The Australian National University (John,

    Reconciling Pluralism and Consensus as Political Ideals, American Journal of Political Science,Vol. 50, No.

    3, July 2006, Pp. 634649)

    Mouffe is a radical pluralist: By pluralism I mean the end of a substantive idea of the good life (1996, 246). But neither Mouffe nor Young

    want to abolish communication in the name of pluralism and difference; much of their work advocates sustained attention to

    communication. Mouffe also cautions against uncritical celebration of difference, for some differencesimply subordination and should therefore be challenged by a radical democratic politics (1996, 247). Mouffe

    raises the question of the terms in which engagement across difference might proceed. Participants should ideally accept that

    the positions of others are legitimate, though not as a result of being persuaded in argument. Instead, it

    is a matter of being open to conversion due to adoption of a particular kind of democratic attitude that

    converts antagonism into agonism, fighting into critical engagement, enemies into adversaries who are

    treated with respect. Respect here is not just (liberal) toleration, but positive validation of the position

    of others. For Young, a communicative democracy would be composed of people showing equal respect,

    under procedural rules of fair discussion and decisionmaking(1996, 126). Schlosberg speaks of agonistic

    respect as a critical pluralist ethos(1999, 70).

    Mouffe and Young both want pluralism to be regulated by a particular kind of attitude, be it respectful, agonistic, or even in Youngs (2000, 16

    51) case reasonable. Thus neither proposes unregulated pluralism as an alternative to (deliberative) consensus.

    This regulation cannot be just procedural, for that would imply anything goes in terms of the

    substance of positions. Recall that Mouffe rejects differences that imply subordination. Agonistic ideals

    demand judgments about what is worthy of respect and what is not. Connolly (1991, 211) worries about dogmaticassertions and denials of identity that fuel existential resentments that would have to be changed to make agonism possible. Young seeks

    transformation of private, self-regarding desires into public appeals to justice (2000, 51). Thus for Mouffe, Connolly, and Young alike,

    regulative principles for democratic communication are not just attitudinal or procedural; they also refer

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    8/24

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    9/24

    searching in the academic databases. There was an unintended effect, however: After doing ... the

    project, instructional group students also felt more confident than the other students in their ability to

    get good information from Yahoo and Google. It may be that the library research experience increased

    self-efficacy for any searching, not just in academic databases. (Larkin 2005, 144)

    Larkin's study substantiates Thomas Worthcn and Gaylcn Pack's (1992, 3) claim that debate in the

    college classroom plays a critical role in fostering the kind of problem-solving skills demanded by the

    increasingly rich media and information environment of modernity. Though their essay was written in

    1992 on the cusp of the eventual explosion of the Internet as a medium, Worthcn and Pack's framing of

    the issue was prescient: the primary question facing today's student has changed from how to best

    research a topic to the crucial question of learning how to best evaluate which arguments to cite and

    rely upon from an easily accessible and veritable cornucopia of materials.

    There are, without a doubt, a number of important criticisms of employing debate as a model for

    democratic deliberation. But cumulatively, the evidence presented here warrants strong support for

    expanding debate practice in the classroom as a technology for enhancing democratic deliberative

    capacities. The unique combination of critical thinking skills, research and information processing skills,

    oral communication skills, and capacities for listening and thoughtful, open engagement with hotly

    contested issues argues for debate as a crucial component of a rich and vital democratic life. In-class

    debate practice both aids students in achieving the best goals of college and university education, and

    serves as an unmatched practice for creating thoughtful, engaged, open-minded and self-critical

    students who are open to the possibilities of meaningful political engagement and new articulations of

    democratic life.

    Expanding this practice is crucial, if only because the more we produce citizens that can actively and

    effectively engage the political process, the more likely we are to produce revisions of democratic life

    that are necessary if democracy is not only to survive, but to thrive. Democracy faces a myriad of

    challenges, including: domestic and international issues of class, gender, and racial justice; wholesale

    environmental destruction and the potential for rapid climate change; emerging threats to international

    stability in the form of terrorism, intervention and new possibilities for great power conflict; and

    increasing challenges of rapid globalization including an increasingly volatile global economic structure.

    More than any specific policy or proposal, an informed and active citizenry that deliberates with greater

    skill and sensitivity provides one of the best hopes for responsive and effective democratic governance,

    and by extension, one of the last best hopes for dealing with the existential challenges to democracy in

    an increasingly complex world.

    Therestopical versions that can use most of the 1ac...changes by debate

    Policymaking is essential to create permanent, codified change at every level of

    society

    Themba-Nixon 2K(Makani, Executive Director of The Praxis Project, a nonprofit organization helping

    communities use media and policy advocacy to advance health equity and justice. Changing the Rules:

    What Public Policy Means for Organizing Colorlines 3.2)

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    10/24

    "This is all about policy," a woman complained to me in a recent conversation. "I'm an organizer." The flourish and passion with which she

    made the distinction said everything. Policy is for wonks, sell-out politicians, and ivory-tower eggheads. Organizing

    is what real, grassroots people do. Common as it may be, this distinction doesn't bear out in the real

    world. Policy is more than law. It is any written agreement(formal or informal) that specifies how an

    institution, governing body, or community will address shared problems or attain shared goals. It spells

    out the terms and the consequences of these agreements and is the codification of the body's values-as

    represented by those present in the policymaking process.Given who's usually present, most policies

    reflect the political agenda of powerful elites. Yet, policy can be a force for change-especially when we

    bring our base and community organizing into the process.In essence, policies are the codification of power

    relationships and resource allocation. Policies are the rules of the world we live in. Changing the world

    means changing the rules. So, if organizing is about changing the rules and building power, how can

    organizing be separated from policies? Can we really speak truth to power, fight the right, stop

    corporate abuses, or win racial justice without contesting the rules and the rulers, the policies and the

    policymakers? The answer is no-and double no for people of color. Today, racism subtly dominates nearly

    every aspect of policymaking.From ballot propositions to city funding priorities,

    policy is increasingly about thecontrol, de-funding, and disfranchisement of communities of color. What Do We Stand For? Take the publicconversation about welfare reform, for example. Most of us know it isn't really about putting people to work. The right's message was framed

    around racial stereotypes of lazy, cheating "welfare queens" whose poverty was "cultural." But the new welfare policy was about moving

    billions of dollars in individual cash payments and direct services from welfare recipients to other, more powerful, social actors. Many of us

    were too busy to tune into the welfare policy drama in Washington, only to find it washed up right on our doorsteps. Our members are

    suffering from workfare policies, new regulations, and cutoffs. Families who were barely getting by under the old rules are being pushed over

    the edge by the new policies. Policy doesn't get more relevant than this. And so we got involved in policy-as

    defense. Yet we have to do more than block their punches. We have to start the fight with initiatives of

    our own. Those who do are finding offense a bit more fun than defense alone.Living wage ordinances, youthdevelopment initiatives, even gun control and alcohol and tobacco policies are finding their way onto the public agenda, thanks to focused

    community organizing that leverages power for community-driven initiatives. - Over 600 local policies have been passed to regulate the

    tobacco industry. Local coalitions have taken the lead by writing ordinances that address local problems and organizing broad support for them.

    - Nearly 100 gun control and violence prevention policies have been enacted since 1991. - Milwaukee, Boston, and Oakland are among thecities that have passed living wage ordinances: local laws that guarantee higher than minimum wages for workers, usually set as the minimum

    needed to keep a family of four above poverty. These are just a few of the examples that demonstrate how organizing for local policy advocacy

    has made inroads in areas where positive national policy had been stalled by conservatives. Increasingly, the local policy arena is where the

    action is and where activists are finding success. Of course, corporate interests-which are usually the target of these

    policies-are gearing up in defense. Tactics include front groups, economic pressure, and the tried and

    true: cold, hard cash. Despite these barriers, grassroots organizing can be very effective at the smaller scale of local politics. At the locallevel, we have greater access to elected officials and officials have a greater reliance on their constituents for reelection. For example, getting

    400 people to show up at city hall in just about any city in the U.S. is quite impressive. On the other hand, 400 people at the state house or the

    Congress would have a less significant impact. Add to that the fact that all 400 people at city hall are usually constituents, and the impact is

    even greater. Recent trends in government underscore the importance of local policy. Congress has enacted a series of measures devolving

    significant power to state and local government. Welfare, health care, and the regulation of food and drinking water safety are among the areas

    where states and localities now have greater rule. Devolution has some negative consequences to be sure. History has taught us that, for social

    services and civil rights in particular, the lack of clear federal standards and mechanisms for accountability lead to uneven enforcement and

    even discriminatory implementation of policies. Still, there are real opportunities for advancing progressive initiatives in this more localized

    environment. Greater local control can mean greater community power to shape and implement important social policies that were heretofore

    out of reach. To do so will require careful attention to the mechanics of local policymaking and a clear blueprint of what we stand for. Getting It

    in Writing Much of the work of framing what we stand for takes place in the shaping of demands. By getting into the policy arena

    in a proactive manner, we can take our demands to the next level. Our demands can become law, with

    real consequences if the agreement is broken. After all the organizing, press work, and effort, a group should leave a

    decisionmaker with more than a handshake and his or her word. Of course, this work requires a certain amount of

    interaction with "the suits," as well as struggles with the bureaucracy, the technical language, and the

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    11/24

    all-too-common resistance by decisionmakers. Still, if it's worth demanding, it's worth having in writing-

    whether as law, regulation, or internal policy. From ballot initiatives on rent control to laws requiring

    worker protections, organizers are leveraging their power into written policies that are making a real

    difference in their communities. Of course, policy workis just one tool in our organizing arsenal, but it is a tool we simply

    can't afford to ignore. Making policy work an integral part of organizing will require a certain amount of

    retrofitting. We will need to develop the capacity to translate our information, data, and experience intostories that are designed to affect the public conversation. Perhaps most important, we will need to

    move beyond fighting problems and on to framing solutions that bring us closer to our vision of how

    things should be. And then we must be committed to making it so.

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    12/24

    2nc feminism

    Framework is totally feminist- we dont preclude you from remaining rooted in your

    identity but common ground is crucial to a communicative ethic that allows us to

    forge a politics of solidarity in difference

    Lister 97(Ruth. Hypatia. Vol 12, No. 4. Citizenship in Feminism: Identity, Action, and Locale. Dialecticsof Citizenship. JSTOR)

    The third plank is a commitment to dialogue. This commitment has been expressed under a number of rubrics;

    most notably, "dialogic," "deliberative," or "communicative" democracy. Underlying them is Habermas's

    notion of a "communicative ethic," which emphasizes the crucial role of free and open public

    communication and deliberation between citizens as the basis of democratic political legitimation. This

    has been used critically by a number of feminist political theorists who envisage such public dialogue as

    the framework for the articulation of difference in which diverse voices, particularly those normally

    excluded from public discourse, have an equal right to be heard. Unlike Habermas himself, for those feministsthe point of such dialogue is not to arrive at agreement on "the" general interest, but instead to

    promote the development of views and the exercise of judgement, having taken account of different

    viewpoints. This commitment to dialogue is premised on the belief that it enables new positions to

    emerge as other viewpoints are acknowledged. The importance of dialogue in which "each group

    becomes better able to consider other groups'" standpointswithout relinquishing the uniqueness of its own standpoint

    or suppressing other groups' partial perspectives is underlinedalso by Patricia Hill Collins as typical of Afrocentric feminist

    thought(1991, 236). Nira Yuval-Davis (1997), drawing on the work of a group of Italian feminists, calls this a process of "rooting" and

    "shifting," in which participants remain rooted in their own identities and values but at the same time are

    willing to shift views in dialogue with those of other identities and values. This,Yuval-Davis suggests,

    represents a "transversal" dialogue or politics, which depends on participants avoiding uncritical

    solidarityand the homogenization of "the other." How to turn such theoretical ideas into practical realities is, of course,another question. As Yuval-Davis warns, in some situations, conflicting interests are not reconcilable in this way and, by and large, political

    systems do not provide the time and space for such dialogue. Moreover, there is a tendency to underestimate the difficulties some groups, in

    particular the poor and economically marginalized, would have in entering the dialogue in the first place. Nevertheless, we can point to

    examples to show that such a transversal politics is possible.To take just two from conflict areas: during the

    period of transition to the new South Africa, a Women's National Coalition was formed, which

    represented an "extraordinary convergence of women across geographical, racial, class, religious and

    political lines" and "a forum through which women who harbored deep animosities could also identify

    common concerns"(Kemp et. al., 1995, 150-51). Through a process of dialogue and negotiation and despite

    fissures and disagreements, the coalitiondrafted a Women's Charter for Effective Equality, which gave women in their

    diversity a voice in the writing of the new constitution. The opportunity to have a voice at such a historic

    time, combined with a focus on a clear, specific goal, is believed to have provided the impetus to workthrough the differences that existed. A second example can be found in Northern Ireland. In a photo essay, titled "Different

    Together," Cynthia Cockbum describes how a form of transversal politics is being pursued by Belfast women's

    centers: Individual women hold on to their political identities-some long for a united Ireland, others feel deeply

    threatened by the idea. But they have identified a commonality in being women, being community based and

    being angry at injustice and inequality, that allows them to affirm and even welcome this and other

    kinds of difference. (1996a, 46) Two Belfast women who gave evidence to the Northern Ireland Opsahl Commission explained that, in

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    13/24

    their experience, cooperation was easier "when the deliberations and activities are directed towards the

    issues which matter" in women's lives, by which they meant the struggle to improve the quality of life in

    the disadvantaged communities in which they lived.5 Cockbum(1996b), drawing also on women's projects in Bosnia and

    Israel, found a number of factors which facilitated working across communal divisions, including a clear

    practical focus and a sensitivity in defining agendas. Each case revealed a commitment to working with

    the "other" and an affirmation of "difference." This was combined with an acknowledgment ofdifferences within each group and of the fluidity of ethnic identities, as well as a willingness to look

    outward; for instance, in Belfast, to women in local Indian and Chinese communities. None of this was easy; but these

    examples suggest that with commitment, it is possible to forge a politics of solidarity in difference.

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    14/24

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    15/24

    at: distancing

    DEBATE roleplay specifically activates agency

    Hanghoj 8

    (http://static.sdu.dk/mediafiles/Files/Information_til/Studerende_ved_SDU/Din_uddannelse/phd_hum/afhandlin

    ger/2009/ThorkilHanghoej.pdfThorkild Hanghj, Copenhagen, 2008 Since this PhD project began in 2004, thepresent author has been affiliated with DREAM (Danish Research Centre on Education and Advanced Media

    Materials), which is located at the Institute of Literature, Media and Cultural Studies at the University of Southern

    Denmark. Research visits have taken place at the Centre for Learning, Knowledge, and Interactive Technologies (L-

    KIT), the Institute of Education at the University of Bristol and the institute formerly known as Learning Lab

    Denmark at the School of Education, University of Aarhus, where I currently work as an assistant professor)

    Thus, debate gamesrequireteachers to balance the centripetal/centrifugal forces of gaming and teaching,to be able toreconfigure their discursive authority, and to orchestrate the multiple voices of a dialogical game space in relation to particular goals. These

    Bakhtinian perspectives provide a valuable analytical framework for describing the discursive interplay between different practices and

    knowledge aspects when enacting (debate) game scenarios. In addition to this, Bakhtins dialogicalphilosophyalso offers an

    explanation of why debate games(and other game types) may be valuablewithin an educational context. One of the central

    features of multi-player games is that players are expected to experience a simultaneously real and imagined scenarioboth in

    relation to an insiders(participant) perspective and to an outsiders(co-participant) perspective.According to Bakhtin, the

    outsiders perspectivereflects a fundamental aspect of human understanding: In order to understand, it is immensely

    important for the person who understands to be located outside the object of his or her creative understanding in time, in space, in culture.

    For one cannot even really see one's own exterior and comprehend it as a whole, and no mirrors or photographs can help; our real exterior can

    be seen and understood only by other people, because they are located outside us in space, and because they are others (Bakhtin, 1986: 7). As

    the quote suggests, every person is influenced by others in an inescapably intertwined way, and consequently no voice can be said to be

    isolated. Thus, it is in the interaction with other voices that individuals are able to reach understanding and find their

    own voice. Bakhtin also refers to the ontological process of finding a voice as ideological becoming, which represents the

    process of selectively assimilating the words of others (Bakhtin, 1981: 341). Thus, by teaching and playing debate scenarios,it is

    possible to support students in their process of becoming not only themselves, but also in becoming articulate and

    responsivecitizens in a democratic society.

    http://static.sdu.dk/mediafiles/Files/Information_til/Studerende_ved_SDU/Din_uddannelse/phd_hum/afhandlinger/2009/ThorkilHanghoej.pdfhttp://static.sdu.dk/mediafiles/Files/Information_til/Studerende_ved_SDU/Din_uddannelse/phd_hum/afhandlinger/2009/ThorkilHanghoej.pdfhttp://static.sdu.dk/mediafiles/Files/Information_til/Studerende_ved_SDU/Din_uddannelse/phd_hum/afhandlinger/2009/ThorkilHanghoej.pdfhttp://static.sdu.dk/mediafiles/Files/Information_til/Studerende_ved_SDU/Din_uddannelse/phd_hum/afhandlinger/2009/ThorkilHanghoej.pdfhttp://static.sdu.dk/mediafiles/Files/Information_til/Studerende_ved_SDU/Din_uddannelse/phd_hum/afhandlinger/2009/ThorkilHanghoej.pdfhttp://static.sdu.dk/mediafiles/Files/Information_til/Studerende_ved_SDU/Din_uddannelse/phd_hum/afhandlinger/2009/ThorkilHanghoej.pdf
  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    16/24

    at: critical pedagogy

    They will always win that the principles of their advocacy are good in the abstract

    we can only debate the merits of their 1AC if they defend specific consequences of

    political implementation

    Michael Ignatieff, Carr professor of human rights at Harvard, 2004Lesser Evils p. 20-1

    As for moral perfectionism, this would be the doctrine that a liberal state should never have truck with dubious moral means and should spare

    its officials the hazard of having to decide between lesser and greater evils. A moral perfectionist position also holds that

    states can spare their officials this hazard simply by adhering to the universal moral standards set out in

    human rights conventions and the laws of war. There are two problems with a perfectionist stance, leaving

    aside the question of whether it is realistic. The first is thatarticulating nonrevocable, nonderogable moral standards

    is relatively easy. The problem is deciding how to apply them in specific cases.What is the line betweeninterrogation and torture, between targeted killing and unlawful assassination, between preemption and aggression? Even when legal and

    moral distinctions between these are clear in the abstract,abstractions are less than helpful when political leaders

    have to choose between them in practice.Furthermore, the problem with perfectionist standards isthat they contradict each other. The same person who shudders, rightly, at the prospect of torturing a suspect might be prepared tokill the same suspect in a preemptive attack on a terrorist base. Equally, the perfectionist commitment to the right to life might preclude such

    attacks altogether and restrict our response to judicial pursuit of offenders through process of law. Judicial responses to the problem of terror

    have their place, but they are no substitute for military operations when terrorists possess bases, training camps, and heavy weapons. To stick

    to a perfectionist commitment to the right to life when under terrorist attack might achieve moral consistency at the price of leaving us

    defenseless in the face of evildoers. Security, moreover, is a human right, and thus respect for one right might lead us to betray another.

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    17/24

    at: rules/predictability bad

    No link to rules or predictability badour argument isn't rules-based in the sense they

    identify, its a set of contestable guidelines for evaluating competitions. Rejecting the

    topic because rules are oppressive doesnt solveand only a standard like the

    resolution is limited enough to enable preparation and testing but has enough internal

    complexity to solve their impact

    Armstrong 2KPaul B. Armstrong, Professor of English and Dean of the College of Arts and Sciences

    at the State University of New York at Stony Brook, Winter 2000, The Politics of Play: The Social

    Implications of Iser's Aesthetic Theory, New Literary History, Vol. 31, No. 1, p. 211-223

    Such a play-spacealso opposes the notion that the only alternative tothe coerciveness of consensus must

    beto advocate the sublime powers of rule-breaking.8 Iser shares Lyotards concern that to privilege harmony and agreement in aworld of heterogeneous language games is to limit their play and to inhibit semantic innovation and the creation of new games. Lyotards

    endorsement of the sublimethe pursuit of the unpresentable by rebelling against restrictions, defying norms, andsmashing the limits of existing paradigmsis undermined by contradictions, however, which Isers explication of play recognizes

    and addresses. The paradox of the unpresentable, as Lyotard acknowledges, is that it can only be manifested through a game

    of representation. The sublime is, consequently, in Isers sense, an instance of doubling. If violating norms creates new

    games, this crossing of boundaries depends onand carries in its wake theconventions and structures it

    oversteps. The sublime may be uncompromising, asocial, and unwilling to be bound by limits, but its pursuit of what is not

    contained in any orderor system makes it dependent on the forms it opposes. The radicalpresumption of the

    sublime is not only terroristic in refusing to recognizethe claims of other games whose rules it declines to

    limit itself by. It isalso naive and self-destructive in itsimpossible imagining that it can do without the

    others it opposes. As a structure of doubling, the sublime pursuit of the unpresentable requires a play-space that includes other, less

    radical games with which it can interact. Such conditions of exchangewould be provided bythe nonconsensual

    reciprocity ofIserian play. Isers notion of play offers a way of conceptualizing power which acknowledges the necessity

    and force ofdisciplinary constraints without seeing them asunequivocally coerciveand determining. The contradictory

    combination of restriction and opennessin how play deploys power is evidentin Isers analysis of regulatory and

    aleatory rules. Even theregulatory rules, which set down the conditionsparticipants submit to in order to play a

    game, permitacertain range of combinationswhile also establishing a code of possible play. . . . Since these rules limit

    thetext game without producing it, they are regulatory but not prescriptive. They do no more than set the aleatory in motion,

    and the aleatory rule differs from the regulatory in that it has no code of its own (FI 273). Submitting tothe discipline of regulatory

    restrictions is both constraining and enabling because it makes possible certain kinds of interaction that

    the rules cannot completely predict or prescribe in advance. Hencethe existence of aleatory rules that are not

    codifiedas part of the game itself but arethe variable customs, procedures, and practices for playing it. Expert facility with

    aleatory rules marks the difference, for example,

    between someone who just knows the rules of a game andanother who really knows how to play it. Aleatory rules are more flexibleand openended and more susceptible to

    variation than regulatory rules, but they too are characterized bya contradictory combination of constraint and

    possibility, limitation and unpredictability,

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    18/24

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    19/24

    Identity politics bad

    1. They force the commodification of autobiography in exchange for the ballot- thissubverts their performance by requiring outsiders become exemplary participants in

    the very culture they criticize

    Coughlin 95(Anne M. Coughlin, Associate Professor of Law, Vanderbilt Law School August, 1995,

    Regulating the Self: Autobiographical Performances in Outsider Scholarship, Virginia Law Review, 81

    Va. L. Rev. 1229, Lexis)

    Although Williams is quick to detect insensitivity and bigotry in remarks made by strangers, colleagues, and friends, her taste for irony fails her

    when it comes to reflection on her relationship with her readers and the material benefits that her autobiographical performances have earned

    for her.196 Perhaps Williams should be more inclined to thank, rather than reprimand, her editors for behaving as readers of autobiography

    invariably do. When we examine this literary faux pas-the incongruity between Williams's condemnation of her editors and the professionalbenefits their publication secured her-we detect yet another contradiction between the outsiders' use of autobiography and their desire to

    transform culture radically. Lejeune's characterization of autobiography as a "contract" reminds us that autobiography

    is a lucrative commodity. In our culture, members of the reading public avidly consume personal stories,197 which surely explains why

    first- rate law journals and academic presses have been eager to market outsider narratives. No matter how

    unruly the self that it records, an autobiographical performance transforms that self into a form of

    "property in a moneyed economy"198 and into a valuable intellectual assetin an academy that requires its members

    to publish.199 Accordingly, we must be skeptical of the assertion that the outsiders' splendid publication

    record is itself sufficient evidence of the success of their endeavor.20 Certainly, publication of a best seller maytransform its author's life, with the resulting commercial success and academic renown.201 As one critic of autobiography puts it, "failures do

    not get pub- lished."202 Whilewriting a successful autobiography may be momentous for the individual author,

    this success has a limited impact on culture. Indeed, the transformation of outsider authors into"success stories" subverts outsiders' radical intentions by constituting them as exemplary participants

    within contemporary culture, willing to market even themselves to literary and academic consumers.203

    What good does this transformation do for outsiders who are less fortunate and less articulatethan middle-

    class law professors?204 Although they style themselves cultural critics, the storytellers generally do not reflect

    on the meaning of their own commercial success, nor ponder its entanglement with the cultural values

    they claim to resist. Rather, for the most part, they seem content simply to take advantage of the peculiarly

    American license, identified by Professor Sacvan Bercovitch, "to have your dissent and make it too."205

    2. Their narrative is centered on the Western idealized notion of the self- thisrecreates the cultural hegemony they criticize by prioritizing the subjectivity of the

    performer over collective solutions for racism

    Coughlin 95(Anne M. Coughlin, Associate Professor of Law, Vanderbilt Law School August, 1995,

    Regulating the Self: Autobiographical Performances in Outsider Scholarship, Virginia Law Review, 81

    Va. L. Rev. 1229, Lexis)

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    20/24

    IV. The Autobiographical Self The outsider narratives do not reflect on another feature of auto-

    biographical discourse that is perhaps the most significant obstacle to their goal to bring to law an

    understanding of the human self that will supersede the liberal individual. Contrary to the outsiders'

    claim that their personalized discourse infuses law with their distinctive experiences and political

    perspectives, numerous historians and critics of autobiography have insisted that those who participate

    in autobiographical discourse speak not in a different voice, but in a common voice that reflects their

    membership in a culture devoted to liberal values.206 As Sacvan Bercovitch puts it, American cultural

    ideals, including specifically the mythic connection between the "heroic individual . . . [and] the values of

    free enterprise," are "epitomized in autobiography."207 In his seminal essay on the subject, Professor

    Georges Gusdorf makes an observation that seems like a prescient warning to outsiders who would

    appropriate autobiography as their voice. He remarks that the practice of writing about one's own self

    reflects a belief in the autonomous individual, which is "peculiar to Western man, a concern that has

    been of good use in his systematic conquest of the universe and that he has communicated to men of

    other cultures; but those men will thereby have been annexed by a sort of intellectual colonizing to a

    mentality that was not their own."208 Similarly, Albert Stone, a critic of American autobiography, arguesthat auto-biographical performances celebrate the Western ideal of individualism, "which places the self

    at the center of its world."209 Stone begins to elucidate the prescriptive character of autobiographical

    discourse as he notes with wonder "the tenacious social ideal whose persistence is all the more

    significant when found repeated in personal histories of Afro-Americans, immigrants, penitentiary

    prisoners, and others whose claims to full individuality have often been denied by our society."'2

    Precisely because it appeals to readers' fascination with the self-sufficiency, resiliency and uniqueness of

    the totemic individual privileged by liberal political theory, there is a risk that autobiographical discourse

    is a fallible, even co-opted, instrument for the social reforms envisioned by the outsiders. By affirming

    the myths of individual success in our culture, autobiography reproduces the political, economic, social

    and psychological structures that attend such success.21' In this light, the outsider autobiographies

    unwittingly deflect attention from collective social responsibility and thwart the development of

    collective solutions for the eradication of racist and sexist harms. Although we may suspect in some

    cases that the author's own sense of self was shaped by a community whose values oppose those of

    liberal individualism, her decision to register her experience in autobiographical discourse will have a

    significant effect on the self she reproduces.212 Her story will solicit the public's attention to the life of

    one individual, and it will privilege her individual desires and rights above the needs and obligations of a

    collectivity. Moreover, literary theorists have remarked the tendency of autobiographical discourse to

    override radical authorial intention. Even where the autobiographer self-consciously determines to

    resist liberal ideology and represents her life story as the occasion to announce an alternative political

    theory, "[t]he relentless individualism of the genre subordinates" her political critique.213 Inevitably, at

    least within American culture, the personal narrative engrosses the readers' imagination. Fascinated bythe travails and triumphs of the developing autobiographical self, readers tend to construe the text's

    political and social observations only as another aspect of the author's personality. Paradoxically,

    although autobiography is the product of a culture that cultivates human individuality, the genre seems

    to make available only a limited number of autobiographical protagonists.214 Many theorists have

    noticed that when an author assumes the task of defining her own, unique subjectivity, she invariably

    reproduces herself as a character with whom culture already is well-acquainted.215 While a variety of

    forces coerce the autobiographer to conform to culturally sanctioned human models,216 the pressures

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    21/24

    exerted by the literary market surely play a significant role. The autobiographer who desires a material

    benefit from her performance must adopt a persona that is intelligible, if not enticing, to her

    audience.217 As I will illustrate in the sections that follow, the outsider narratives capitalize on, rather

    than subvert, autobiographical protagonists that serve the values of liberalism.

    3. Appeals to personal experience replace analysis of group oppression with personal

    testimony. As a result, politics becomes a policing operationthose not in an identity

    group are denied intellectual access and those within the group who dont conform to

    the affs terms are excluded. Over time, this strategy LIMITS politics to ONLY the

    personal. This devastates structural change, and turns the caseit demands that

    political performance assimilate to very limited norms of experience

    Scott 92(Joan Harold F. Linder Professor at the School of Social Science in the Institute for Advanced

    Study in Princeton Multiculturalism and the Politics of Identity October Summer p. 16-19)

    The logic of individualism has structured the approach to multiculturalism in many ways. The call for

    tolerance of difference is framed in terms of respect for individual characteristics and attitudes; group

    differences are conceived categorically and not relationally, as distinct entities rather than

    interconnected structures or systems created through repeated processes of the enunciation of

    difference. Administrators have hired psychological consulting firms to hold diversity workshops which

    teach that conflict resolution is a negotation between dissatisfied individuals. Disciplinary codes that

    punish "hate-speech" justify prohibitions in terms of the protection of individuals from abuse by other

    individuals, not in terms of the protection of members of historically mistreated groups from

    discrimination, nor in terms of the ways language is used to construct and reproduce asymmetries of

    power. The language of protection, moreover, is conceptualized in terms of victimization; the way to

    make a claim or to justify one's protest against perceived mistreatment these days is to take on the

    mantle of the victim. (The so-called Men's Movement is the latest comer to this scene.) Everyone--

    whether an insulted minority or the perpetrator of the insult who feels he is being unjustly accused-

    now claims to be an equal victim before the law. Here we have not only an extreme form of

    individualizing, but a conception of individuals without agency. There is nothing wrong, on the face of it,

    with teaching individuals about how to behave decently in relation to others and about how to

    empathize with each other's pain. The problem is that difficult analyses of how history and social

    standing, privilege, and subordination are involved in personal behavior entirely drop out. Chandra

    Mohanty puts it this way: There has been an erosion of the politics of collectivity through the

    reformulation of race and difference in individualistic terms. The 1960s and '70s slogan "the personal ispolitical" has been recrafted in the 1980s as "the political is personal." In other words, all politics is

    collapsed into the personal, and questions of individual behaviors, attitudes, and life-styles stand in for

    political analysis of the social. Individual political struggles are seen as the only relevant and legitimate

    form of political struggle.5 Paradoxically, individuals then generalize their perceptions and claim to

    speak for a whole group, but the groups are also conceived as unitary and autonomous. This

    individualizing, personalizing conception has also been behind some of the recent identity politics of

    minorities; indeed it gave rise to the intolerant, doctrinaire behavior that was dubbed, initially by its

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    22/24

    internal critics, "political correctness." It is particularly in the notion of "experience" that one sees this

    operating. In much current usage of "experience," references to structure and history are implied but

    not made explicit; instead, personal testimony of oppression replaces analysis, and this testimony comes

    to stand for the experience of the whole group. The fact of belonging to an identity group is taken as

    authority enough for one's speech; the direct experience of a group or culture-that is, membership in it-

    becomes the only test of true knowledge. The exclusionary implications of this are twofold: all those notof the group are denied even intellectual access to it, and those within the group whose experiences or

    interpretations do not conform to the established terms of identity must either suppress their views or

    drop out. An appeal to "experience" of this kind forecloses discussion and criticism and turns politics

    into a policing operation: the borders of identity are patrolled for signs of nonconformity; the test of

    membership in a group becomes less one's willingness to endorse certain principles and engage in

    specific political actions, less one's positioning in specific relationships of power, than one's ability to use

    the prescribed languages that are taken as signs that one is inherently "of" the group. That all of this

    isn't recognized as a highly political process that produces identities is troubling indeed, especially

    because it so closely mimics the politics of the powerful, naturalizing and deeming as discernably

    objective facts the prerequisites for inclusion in any group. Indeed, I would argue more generally that

    separatism, with its strong insistence on an exclusive relationship between group identity and access to

    specialized knowledge (the argument that only women can teach women's literature or only African-

    Americans can teach African-American history, for example), is a simultaneous refusal and imitation of

    the powerful in the present ideological context. At least in universities, the relationship between

    identity-group membership and access to specialized knowledge has been framed as an objection to the

    control by the disciplines of the terms that establish what counts as (important, mainstream, useful,

    collective) knowledge and what does not. This has had an enormously important critical impact,

    exposing the exclusions that have structured claims to universal or comprehensive knowledge. When

    one asks not only where the women or African-Americans are in the history curriculum (for example),

    but why they have been left out and what are the effects of their exclusion, one exposes the process by

    which difference is enunciated. But one of the complicated and contradictory effects of theimplementation of programs in women's studies, African-American studies, Chicano studies, and now

    gay and lesbian studies is to totalize the identity that is the object of study, reiterating its binary

    opposition as minority (or subaltern) in relation to whatever is taken as majority or dominant.

    4. Incorporating personal narratives into debate forces us to do violence against

    ourselves- vote neg to accommodate the interruption of knowability and reject the

    unconscious as recuperable

    Butler 1(Judith is Maxine Elliot Professor in the Departments of Rhetoric and Comparative Literature

    at the University of California, Berkeley, 1 Giving an Account of Oneself, Diacritics 31.4 22-40, Project

    Muse)

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    23/24

    But here, and for the time being, my concern is with a suspect coherence that sometimes attaches to narrative

    and, specifically, with the way in which narrative coherence may foreclose upon an ethical resource,

    namely, an acceptance of the limits of knowability in oneself and others.It may even be that to hold a person

    accountable for his or her life in narrative form is to require a falsification of that life in the name of a

    certain conception of ethics. Indeed, if we require that someone be able to tell in story form the reasons

    why his or her life has taken the path it has, that is, to be a coherent autobiographer, it may be that weprefer the seamlessness of the story to something we might tentatively call the truth of the person, a

    truth which, to a certain degree, and for reasons we have already suggested, is indicated more radically as an

    interruption.It may be that stories have to be interrupted, and that for interruption to take place, a story has to be underway. This bringsme closer to the account of the transference I would like to offer, a transference that might be understood as a repeated ethical practice.

    Indeed, if, in the name of ethics, we require that another do a certain violence to herself, and do it in front

    of us, offering a narrative account or, indeed, a confession, then, conversely, it may be that by

    permitting, sustaining, accommodating the interruption, a certain practice of nonviolence precisely

    follows. If violence is the act by which a subject seeks to reinstall its mastery and unity, then nonviolence may well follow from living thepersistent challenge to mastery that our obligations to others require. Although some would say that to be a split subject, or a subject whose

    access to itself is opaque and not self-grounding, is precisely not to have the grounds for agency and the conditions for accountability, it may be

    that this way in which we are, from the start, interrupted by alterity and not fully recoverable to

    ourselves, indicates the way in which we are, from the start, ethically implicated in the lives of others.The point here is not to celebrate a certain notion of incoherence, but only to consider that our incoherence is ineradicable but nontotalizing,

    and that it establishes the way in which we are implicated, beholden, derived, constituted by what is beyond us and before us. If we say

    that the self must be narrated, that only the narrated self can be intelligible, survivable, then we say that

    we cannot survive with an unconscious. We say, in effect, that the unconscious threatens us with an

    insupportable unintelligibility, and for that reason we must oppose it. The "I" who makes such an utterance will

    surely, in one form or another, be besieged precisely by what it disavows. This stand,and it is a stand, it must

    be a stand, an upright, wakeful, knowing stand, believes that it survives without the unconscious or, if it accepts an

    unconscious, accepts it as something which is thoroughly recuperable by the knowing "I," as a

    possession perhaps, believing that the unconscious can be fully and exhaustively translated into what is

    conscious. It is easy to see this as a defended stance, for it remains to be known in what this particular defense consists. It is, after all, thestand that many make against psychoanalysis itself. Inthe language which articulates the opposition to a non-narrativizable

    beginning resides the fear that the absence of narrative will spell a certain threat, a threat to life, and will pose

    the risk, if not the certainty, of a certain kind of death, the death of a subject who cannot, who can never, fully

    recuperate the conditions of its own emergence. But this death, if it is a death, is only the death of a certain

    kind of subject, one that was never possible to begin with, the death of a fantasy, and so a loss of what

    one never had. One goes to analysis, I presume, to have someone receive one's words, and this produces a quandary, since the one whomight receive the words is unknown in large part, and so the one who receives becomes, in a certain way, an allegory for reception itself, for

    the phantasmatic relation to receiving that is articulated to, or at least in the face of, an Other. But if this is an allegory, it is not reducible to a

    structure of reception that would apply equally well to everyone, although it would give us the general structures within which a particular life

    might be understood. We, as subjects who narrate ourselves in the first person, encounter in common

    something of a predicament. Since I cannot tell the story in a straight line, and I lose my thread, and I start again, and I forgetsomething crucial, and it is to hard to think about how to weave it in, and I start thinking, thinking, there must be some conceptual thread that

    will provide a narrative here, some lost link, some possibility for chronology, and the "I" becomes increasingly conceptual,

    increasingly awake, focused, determined, it is at this point that the thread must fall apart. The "I" who

    narrates finds that it cannot direct its narration, finds that it cannot give an account of its inability to

    narrate, why its narration breaks down, and so it comes to experience itself, or, rather, reexperience

    itself, as radically, if not irretrievably, unknowing about who it is.And then the "I" is no longer imparting

    a narrative to a receiving analyst or Other. The "I" is breaking down in certain very specific ways in front

  • 8/12/2019 Framework - Georgetown 2014

    24/24

    of the Otheror, to anticipate Levinas, in the face of the Other (originally I wrote, "the in face of the Other," indicating that my syntax was

    already breaking down) or, indeed, by virtue of the Other's face. The "I" finds that, in the face of an Other, it is breaking

    down. It does not know itself, and perhaps it never will. But is that the task, to know itself, to achieve an

    adequate narrative account of a life?And should it be? Is the task to cover over the breakage, the rupture,

    which is constitutive of the "I" through a narrative means that quite forcefully binds the elements

    together in a narration that is enacted as if it were perfectly possible, as if the break could be mendedand defensive mastery restored?

    5. Their 1ac author concludes neg- the US is obviously not perfect but were definitely

    not colonialist

    Ferraro 02 (The Ruth C. Lawson Professor of International Politics Mount Holyoke College AB,

    Dartmouth College; MIA, Columbia University; PhD, Massachusetts Institute of Technology) The Myth

    of Engagement: America as an Isolationist World Power April 2002https://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/afp/myth.htm)

    The United States could have chosen to exercise world power along formal imperial lines-it could have

    acquired colonies, and there were many opportunities for it to do so. 3 The United States did annex the

    Philippines, and has a very ambiguous relationship to Puerto Rico, Guam, the Virgin Islands, and other

    American territories. For most of its history, however, the land and peoples that it acquired, with the

    exception of the indigenous nations of North America, were ultimately assimilated as fully equal

    participants in the American government. The deliberate choice to forgo the colonial option is a

    distinctive attribute of American foreign policy, and some American leaders, such as Woodrow Wilson

    and Franklin Roosevelt, injected the idea of self-determination into the discourse of world politics in

    powerful and revolutionary ways. But the choice also made it very difficult for the United States to

    maintain a visible and effective presence abroad. Ultimately, the United States is obliged to maintain

    military bases abroad in order to exercise its power on a global scale, and there are significant problems

    with that approach. 4

    https://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/afp/myth.htmhttps://www.mtholyoke.edu/acad/intrel/afp/myth.htm