fetal relationality in feminist philosophy-an anthropological critique

Upload: anjcaicedosa

Post on 06-Jul-2018

217 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    1/25

     Hypatia, Inc. and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Hypatia.

    http://www.jstor.org

    Hypatia Inc.

    Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy: An Anthropological CritiqueAuthor(s): Lynn M. MorganSource: Hypatia, Vol. 11, No. 3 (Summer, 1996), pp. 47-70Published by: on behalf ofWiley Hypatia, Inc.Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3810321Accessed: 22-02-2016 04:17 UTC

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/  info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/publisher/blackhttp://www.jstor.org/publisher/hypatiainchttp://www.jstor.org/stable/3810321http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/3810321http://www.jstor.org/publisher/hypatiainchttp://www.jstor.org/publisher/blackhttp://www.jstor.org/

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    2/25

    FetalRelationalityn Feminist

    Philosophy:

    An

    Anthropological

    Critique

    LYNN M. MORGAN

    This

    essay

    critiques

    eminist

    treatments

    f

    maternal-fetal relationality

    hat

    unwittingly

    eplicate

    eatures

    of

    Western

    ndividualism

    for

    example,

    he

    Cartesian

    divisionbetween he

    asocial

    body

    and the

    social-cognitive

    erson,

    or the

    conflation f

    socialand

    biological

    irth).

    I

    argue

    or

    a more

    reflexive

    erspective

    n

    relationality

    thatwould

    acknowledge

    ow

    we

    produce ersons hrough

    ur actionsand rhetoric.

    Personhood

    nd

    relationality

    an

    be better

    nalyzed

    s

    dynamic,

    negotiated ualities

    realized

    hrough

    ocial

    practice.

    As

    fetuses

    figure

    ever more

    prominently

    in

    the American

    social

    imaginary,

    feminist theorists arecompelledto take notice. The manypathsthroughthis

    politically charged

    errain

    are

    all

    lined with

    contradictions,

    creating

    a seriesof

    persistent

    conundrums or

    feminist

    analysis.

    One oft-traveled

    road steersclear

    of fetuses as an

    object

    of

    study;

    ts

    proponentsargue

    that

    to

    put

    the unborn

    at the

    center of

    analysis

    is to

    be

    co-opted

    by

    pro-life

    strategies

    ntended to

    divert

    attention from women in

    the debate over

    abortion.Susan

    Sherwin,

    for

    example, suggests

    that a

    focus on

    the fetus is the

    defining

    characteristicof

    nonfeminists

    (1992,

    101),

    and

    Janice

    G.

    Raymondargues

    hat

    feministsand

    fetalists arenot alignedin anyway (1987, 65).1A morerecentlyblazedtrail

    acknowledges

    hat fetuses

    attain social

    meaning through

    events

    not

    necessar-

    ily directly

    related to

    abortion.

    One

    fork

    of this

    trail winds

    through

    cultural

    studies,

    where authors

    analyze

    fetal texts

    and

    social

    scripts

    to

    show

    that,

    as

    metaphors,

    etuses wield

    increasing

    social

    power

    (Berlant 1994;

    Duden

    1993;

    Franklin

    1992;

    Hartouni

    1991,

    1993, 1994).

    Another

    fork

    leads into

    sociolog-

    ical

    territory,

    where

    the

    identification,

    commodification,

    medicalization,

    and

    legalization

    of

    fetuses is

    documented and

    scrutinized

    (Boling

    1995;

    Casper

    1994; Daniels 1993; Franklin and Ragone n.d.; Ginsburgand Rapp 1995;

    Hypatia

    ol.

    11,

    no. 3

    (Summer

    996)

    ?

    by

    Lynn

    M.

    Morgan

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    relacionalidad entre madre y feto

    que replica categorías del

    individualismo

    perspectiva más reflexiva respecto a relacionalidad ...personas a

    través de acciones y retórican

    terrenopolíticamentecargado

    posiciones:poner al fetocomo objetoes caer enestrategiapro vida

    adquierensignificadossociales nonecesariamente respectoa aborto

    desdesociología,donde lamedicalización ylegalizaciónde los fetos

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    3/25

    Hypatia

    Morgan

    n.d.;

    Rapp

    1987,1988,1990,1993;

    Roth

    1993;

    Rothman

    1986;

    Taylor

    1992). These authors, all writing from a feminist perspective, document

    society's

    current obsession with

    fetuses,

    but,

    with a

    few

    exceptions,

    do

    not

    examine the

    practical implications

    of this trend for feminist

    analysis.

    There

    is

    another

    trail,

    narrow

    and

    steep.

    The

    explorers

    who venture here

    have become convinced

    that

    feminism's

    ong-standing

    nattention

    to

    fetuses

    has

    become a

    political liability.

    It is

    unwise,

    they

    argue,

    for feminism to

    continue

    to

    deny

    the

    increasing

    and

    undeniable

    moral and social

    importance

    given

    to fetuses

    n

    European

    and North American

    society.

    They

    point

    out that

    the old maps-the ones that circumventfetal terrain-lead us unwittinglyto

    collude

    with

    architects

    of the

    anti-woman backlash

    who

    portray

    eminists as

    anti-mothersand child killers.

    As

    feminists, therefore,

    they

    are

    beginning

    to

    place

    fetusescloser

    to

    the center

    of

    analysis.

    Susan

    Bordo,

    or

    example,

    asserts

    that we

    should

    never have

    permitted

    the

    debate

    over the status of the fetus

    to have achieved

    center

    stage

    in the

    public

    imagination,

    but

    ought,

    rather,

    o

    have

    attempted

    to

    preempt

    that

    debate

    with a

    strong

    feministperspective

    acknowledging

    and

    articulating

    he ethical and emotional value

    of

    the fetus

    (1993, 95;

    emphasis

    n

    original). Increasingly,

    eminist social scientists,histo-

    rians,

    and

    philosophers

    are

    beginning

    to confront

    directly

    the

    disquieting

    implications

    for

    feminist

    analysis

    of the

    increasing

    social

    value accorded

    fetuses.

    They

    submit-tentatively,

    and

    fully cognizant

    of the

    political

    quag-

    mires that

    lie ahead-that

    the

    old

    paths

    lead to sites

    we

    no

    longer

    wish to

    inhabit

    because

    they

    leave out

    significant

    dimensions of women's

    experience

    (see

    Addelson

    1987,

    1994;

    C.

    Condit

    1990;

    Daniels

    1993;

    Porter

    1994;

    Shrage

    1994;

    Tsing

    1990).

    The

    time

    has come

    to

    move toward Bordo's

    vision of

    feminist

    perspectives

    on fetuses.

    There

    is much

    to

    intrigue

    and excite within this

    new

    region

    of feminist

    inquiry.

    Barbara

    Katz Rothman was

    a

    pioneer

    with

    her

    1986

    book,

    The

    Tentative

    Pregnancy,

    which directed us to the

    changing

    notions

    of

    incipient

    (fetal

    and

    infant)

    personhood

    being

    made

    possible

    by

    the

    widespread

    use of

    reproductive

    imaging

    technologies.

    Rosalind

    Petchesky,

    another

    pioneer,

    addressed

    the dilemmas

    of fetal

    personhood

    in

    her classic

    Abortion

    and

    Woman's

    Choice

    1985).

    Linda

    Layne's

    workon

    pregnancy

    oss reminds

    us

    that

    we

    have at best

    ignored

    (and

    at worst

    deliberately

    silenced)

    an

    important

    dimension

    of the lived

    experiences

    of women who cherish fetal

    life

    (Layne

    1990,

    1992).

    Elisabeth

    Porter

    (1994)

    argues

    or

    a moral

    praxis approach

    o

    abortion

    ethics that

    would make moral

    judgments

    about abortion

    contingent

    on a wide

    variety

    of

    specific, pragmatic

    considerations.

    But

    my

    explorations

    along

    this route also

    uncovered a

    line of

    reasoning

    I

    find

    problematic,

    f well-intentioned.

    Acknowledging

    the fetal

    realpolitik

    of

    our

    times,

    some feminist

    philosophers

    are

    attempting

    to

    construct

    a vision of

    fetal

    morality

    and

    personhood

    consistent

    with

    woman-centered,

    pro-choice

    politics.

    I

    will

    be

    taking

    issue with one dimension

    of their

    work,

    namely,

    their

    48

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    propuesta esexaminar lasimplicaciones prácticasde esto parael análisisfeminista

    Problema deestereconocimie

    nto:visión moralde

    personhood,centrada enmujeres ypro-choice

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    4/25

    Lynn

    M.

    Morgan

    arguments

    concerning

    the moral

    superiority

    of relational over

    individualistic

    oncepts

    of

    personhood.

    They use this point to arguethat

    fetuses,

    devoid

    of

    sociality

    and

    relationality,

    cannot and should

    not

    be

    consid-

    ered

    persons

    until

    birth.

    Anticipating

    the

    critique

    that

    follows,

    I

    should

    state

    here that

    I commend and

    support

    their efforts

    to situate women

    (including

    pregnant

    women)

    and

    fetuses

    in

    ethical

    frameworks,

    paying

    attention

    always

    to women's

    location in a matrix of

    power. They

    are

    fully

    aware of

    how

    pregnancy,

    childbirth,

    and motherhood

    enforce

    women's

    powerlessness

    (Burgess-Jackson,

    personal

    communication).

    Their

    voices

    are essential,

    especially

    now, when androcentric ethics and anti-woman

    policymaking

    are all too

    pervasive.

    When I

    critique

    their

    work, then,

    I

    do

    so in a

    constructive

    spirit,

    in

    pursuit

    of our common

    goal:

    to

    develop strong,

    defensible,

    culturally

    sensitive

    theoretical foundations

    for

    designing

    better

    social

    policies

    affecting

    women.

    This

    essay

    offersa

    feminist

    anthropologist's

    eading

    of the notion

    of

    fetal-

    social

    relationality

    as

    it is

    unfolding

    in

    selected works

    by

    Caroline Whitbeck

    (1984),

    Susan Sherwin

    (1992),

    Mary

    Anne Warren

    (1989),

    and others.

    I will

    contrasttheir

    interpretations

    with some of those foundin the

    anthropological

    literatureon

    person

    and

    self

    (Battaglia

    1995a; Carrithers,Collins,

    and Luke

    1985;

    Strather

    1992a, 1992b),

    to

    argue

    that the renditions of

    relationality

    and fetal

    personhood promoted by

    these

    philosophers

    are

    problematic

    on

    severalcounts.

    First,

    and in

    spite

    of the authors'

    attempts

    o shed androcentric

    Western

    biases,

    their

    relationality

    remains

    fundamentally,paradoxically,

    nd

    uncritically

    rooted in the Western ndividualismand Cartesiandualism

    they

    assail.

    Second,

    their discussionsof the moral

    significance

    of birth

    (Warren

    1989)

    are

    being outpaced

    by

    social and

    technological developments,

    and lack

    the universal

    applicabilityespoused

    by

    some.

    Third,

    the

    perspective

    as cur-

    rently

    unfolding

    could be more

    reflexive,

    acknowledging

    he social and histor-

    ical

    context that

    gives

    us

    the

    categories

    we use to

    think

    about

    social-,

    parental-,

    and maternal-fetal

    relationships,

    and about the social construction

    of

    relationality

    more

    generally.

    will

    conclude

    by

    arguing

    hat

    personhood

    hould

    be seen as

    a

    negotiated, dynamic concept currentlybeing

    contested

    through

    many overlappingpublic

    discourses

    concerning

    fetuses.

    Feminist

    analyses

    of

    fetal

    personhood,

    I will

    argue,

    shouldbe

    sociologically

    informed,

    self-critical,

    and

    aggressive

    about

    recuperating

    eminist

    renderings

    of fetuses. This

    argu-

    ment is

    consistent

    with

    Porter's

    (1994)

    recent

    plea

    for a

    reflexive,

    socially

    conscientious moral

    pragmatics

    f

    abortion.

    49

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    sus argumentos están ensuperioridad moral de conceptosrelacionales sobre individualisticos

    críticas

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    5/25

    Hypatia

    INDIVIDUALISM:

    HE

    ROOT OF ALL EVIL?

    Abortion

    challenges

    feminists to come to termswith the

    contradictions

    n

    their

    own

    thought,

    notably

    the

    contradiction

    between the commitment

    to

    community

    and

    nurtureand the commitment to individual

    right.

    (ElizabethFox-Genovese,

    FeminismWithout llusions:

    A

    Critique

    f

    Individualism)

    Feministphilosopherswho address he moralstatusof the fetus do so at least

    partly

    because

    they

    care about women and are

    disturbedand

    angered

    by

    the

    erasureof

    pregnant

    women from an

    array

    of

    public

    discourses

    including

    those

    concering

    abortion,

    poverty,

    infant

    mortality,

    and substance

    abuse).

    They

    watch

    uneasily

    as the American

    public

    is

    distracted,

    enthralled, incited,

    and

    sometimes

    literally

    crazed

    by proliferating images

    of

    fetuses,

    increasingly

    depicted

    as

    free-floating,

    disembodied little babies at

    the

    mercy

    of their

    uncaring

    or

    vindictive mothers. Feminist

    philosophers

    rightly

    want

    to

    bring

    womenback,literally into the picture, o point out once more that afetus

    inhabits a

    woman's

    body

    and is

    wholly

    dependent

    on

    her

    unique

    contribution

    to its maintenance

    (Sherwin 1992, 106).

    The

    philosophers

    I select for attention

    here,

    however,

    are

    working

    within

    the constraintsof

    a

    continuum

    established

    ong ago

    in the

    literature.

    One

    end

    is marked

    by

    those

    who

    posit

    that fetuseshave

    no value

    whatsoever,

    while

    the

    other end

    is

    marked

    by

    those

    who

    insist that

    fetuses

    are full

    persons

    from the

    earliest

    stages

    of

    gestation.2

    The

    fetuses

    have no

    value

    end of the

    spectrum

    is

    commonly

    identifiedwith

    writings

    n the

    early

    1970s

    by

    Michael

    Tooley

    and

    Mary

    Anne

    Warren,

    who were accused of

    supporting

    nfanticide for

    pointing

    out that

    newborns

    possessed

    ew

    attributes hat

    late-gestation

    fetuses

    did not.

    The

    other end of the continuum

    is

    exemplified,

    of

    course,

    by

    some

    theologians

    and

    others

    in

    the

    pro-life

    movement,

    whose membersbelieve fetuses

    to be full

    human

    beings

    from

    the moment

    of

    conception

    (Noonan

    1979).

    The feminist

    philosophers

    I refer to

    seek to

    position

    themselves

    along

    this

    continuum,

    to

    devise

    a view

    of

    fetal

    personhood

    which would

    permit

    elective abortion

    throughout

    he

    gestational

    cycle

    while

    condemning

    infanticide.3Warrenand

    others

    writing

    n

    the

    same vein force

    a

    wedge

    into this narrowniche

    by

    arguing

    that

    biological

    birth marks a

    morally significant

    division between

    persons

    and

    nonpersons.

    Although

    Warren concedes that most

    contemporary

    philosophers

    believe

    that birth cannot

    make a

    difference

    to

    moral

    rights,

    she

    argues

    that

    contrasting biological

    and

    social

    relationships

    make

    even

    relatively

    late

    abortion

    morally

    different from

    infanticide

    (Warren

    1989,

    46;

    emphasis

    added).

    The

    philosophical

    argument

    distinguishing

    nfanticide from

    abortion,

    and

    prebirth

    rom

    postbirth

    status,

    is rooted in discussions

    of individualistic

    versus

    50

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    filósofasfeministasquierentraer amujeres alpanorama

    peroterminanenmarcadasen marcostradicionales1. fetos notienen ningúnvalor2. personas

    completas

    Warren,límite denacimientomarca unadivisiónmoral entrepersona-nopersona

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    6/25

    Lynn

    M.

    Morgan

    relational

    models

    of

    personhood.

    Moral

    philosophy

    and

    ethics,

    feminists

    note,

    are traditionallyderived from male models in which rational,self-interested

    actors

    arriveat

    universalmoral

    principles

    after

    indulging

    n

    abstract

    hought.

    Influenced

    by

    Carol

    Gilligan's

    (1982)

    work on the

    gendered

    dimensions

    of

    moral

    development,

    several

    theorists

    argue

    hat

    individualist

    deologies

    create

    a climate in

    which social

    relationships

    are

    denigrated

    and devalued.

    Whitbeck

    (1984),

    for

    example,

    argues

    hat

    individualismand

    patriarchy

    re

    coterminous,

    and

    that in both social

    relations are

    inherently

    oppositional, dyadic,

    and

    antagonistic.

    Fox-Genovese

    argues

    hat

    pervasive,historically

    rooted individ-

    ualistic ideologieshave left a perniciouslegacy: Individualism ctuallyper-

    verts the

    idea of the

    socially

    obligated

    and

    personally

    responsible

    reedom

    hat

    constitutes the

    only

    freedom

    worthy

    of

    the name or

    indeed

    historically

    possible

    (1991, 7).

    These

    authors

    (along

    with

    many

    others)

    argue

    that as

    feminists we

    must resist

    individualistic

    deologies

    to construct a

    viable

    philo-

    sophical

    and

    political

    alternative.

    PRIVILEGING

    ELATIONALITY

    Relationality

    is the

    preferred

    eminist

    antidote to

    individualism,

    as

    Sherwin

    asserts: The

    general

    consensus

    of female

    theorists

    is

    that

    [moral]

    theories

    should

    involve models of

    human interaction

    that

    parallel

    he

    rich

    complexity

    of actual

    human

    relationships

    and should

    recognize

    the moral

    significance

    of

    the

    actual ties

    that bind

    people

    in

    their

    various

    relationships

    Sherwin

    1992,

    49).

    Relationality

    is

    presented

    as

    an

    ideologically

    undervalued

    but

    experien-

    tially

    accurate dimension

    of

    social interaction. It is

    the basis for

    Whitbeck's

    proposed

    feminist

    ontology,

    n which

    a

    self-others istinction

    replaces

    he

    dyadic

    self-other

    distinction,

    because

    relationships,past

    and

    present,

    real-

    ized

    and

    sought,

    are

    constitutive of the

    self,

    and so the actions

    of a

    person

    reflect

    the more-

    or

    less-successful

    ttempt

    to

    respond

    o the

    whole

    configura-

    tion of

    relationships

    Whitbeck

    1984, 76).

    The

    approach

    of

    these

    authors,

    as

    Kroeger-Mappes

    oints

    out

    (1994, 123),

    is to

    valorize

    elationality,

    o offer

    it as the

    superior

    alternative

    to

    individualism.

    Discussionsof

    individualismversus

    relationalism ind

    expression

    n feminist

    discussionsof

    the fetus

    in

    the

    following ways.

    In the continuum

    mentioned

    above,

    the

    pro-life

    position

    holds

    that fetuses

    are full

    persons

    rom

    conception

    because

    they

    possess

    intrinsic

    properties.

    This,

    Sherwin

    (1992)

    argues,

    s an

    example

    of

    the

    unfortunate

    results

    of

    individualistic

    thinking.

    Sherwin

    says

    that

    individualism

    provides

    the

    ideological justification

    for

    presuming

    that

    persons including

    fetal

    persons)

    must be

    wholly,

    corporeally

    and

    ontologi-

    cally

    constituted,

    or else

    wholly insignificant.

    The

    argument

    proceeds:

    if

    persons

    are

    conceived not

    as

    self-maximizing

    automatonsbut

    as

    relationally

    constituted

    and

    socially

    embedded

    beings,

    then

    the

    maternal-fetal

    nexus

    need

    not

    be

    modeled in termsof

    either-or etal

    personhood

    or

    inevitable mater-

    51

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    Distinción filosófica entre aborto einfanticidio está en la discusión entreindividualismo vs modelo relacional depersona

    Esta vía propone que comofeministas debemos resistirnosa ideologías individualisticaspara construir una viaalternativa

    antídotoseríarelacionalidad

    complejaconfiguración derelacionesque seformalizaen el "yo"

    individualismo encarnadoen visión delfeto comovidacompleta yautocontenida

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    7/25

    Hypatia

    nal-fetal

    conflict.4

    In

    relational

    terms,

    Sherwin and

    others

    argue,

    fetuses

    necessarily move through pregnant women. A fetus is a unique sort of

    human

    entity,

    then,

    for it cannot form

    relationships

    reely

    with

    others,

    and

    others cannot

    readily

    form

    relationships

    with

    it. A fetus

    has

    a

    primary

    and

    particularly

    ntimate

    sort

    of

    'relationship'

    with the woman

    in

    whose womb

    it

    develops;

    connections

    with

    any

    other

    persons

    are

    necessarily

    ndirectand must

    be

    mediated

    through

    the

    pregnant

    woman

    (Sherwin

    1992,

    110).

    Fetuses,

    therefore,

    cannot

    be

    granted

    ull

    personhood,

    because

    they

    exist

    as

    compound,

    dependent

    ontological

    entities rather

    than as

    capable

    of

    relationships.

    Relationalitythus becomes the philosophicaland moralbasis forgranting(or

    not

    granting)

    personhood

    and social value to fetuses

    and

    infants.

    It is worth

    considering

    in

    greater

    detail

    precisely

    what Sherwin

    means

    by

    relationality.

    Where

    does she locate

    relationality

    (and

    where

    does she situate

    herself)?

    This

    is

    by

    no

    means an

    easy question

    to

    answer,

    because the

    philo-

    sophical

    basis

    for

    relationality

    is located

    in

    a

    particularly

    horny

    thicket,

    and

    many

    philosophers

    are

    inconsistent

    and

    contradictory

    on this

    point.

    Sherwin,

    for

    example,

    seems to vacillate between

    biological

    and

    psychological

    bases

    for

    relationality.

    She

    puts

    the

    biological argument

    first: Fetuseshave a

    unique

    physical

    status-within

    and

    dependent

    on

    particular

    women. That

    gives

    them

    also a

    unique

    social status.Howevermuch

    some

    might

    prefer

    t

    to

    be

    otherwise,

    no

    one

    other than the

    pregnant

    woman in

    question

    can

    do

    anything

    to

    support

    or harm

    a

    fetus

    without

    doing

    something

    to the woman who

    nurtures

    it.

    Because

    of

    this

    inexorable

    iological

    eality,

    the

    responsibility

    and

    privilege

    of

    determining

    a fetus's

    specific

    social status

    and value must rest with

    the woman

    carrying

    t

    (1992,

    110;

    emphasis

    added).

    Biological

    explanations

    make sense

    because

    North American cultural

    deologies

    coax us to look for social

    meaning

    (such

    as

    explanations

    for

    crime

    or

    poverty

    or

    homosexuality)

    in

    biological

    phenomena.

    Yet it would be

    exceedingly

    problematic

    to

    locate

    relationality

    solely

    n

    biology,

    as Sherwin

    is

    well aware.

    The

    question

    of

    agency

    becomes critical

    here. There

    is

    a

    tension

    in

    these

    writings

    about where

    to locate

    relationality,

    about

    how to

    imagine

    an abstrac-

    tion

    that

    cannot,

    by

    definition,

    reside

    within a

    single

    individual.

    Relationality

    is an

    intangiblebond,

    a

    glue

    that links individuals o one

    another

    (Strather

    1992b, 125).

    Yet some

    of these writers eem to

    link

    relationality

    o

    individual

    cognitive

    or

    corporeal

    attributes.

    Sometimes

    they

    locate it

    in

    the

    fetus/infant,

    which,

    it

    is

    argued,

    annot

    participate

    n

    or form

    relationships

    until

    it

    possesses

    some sine

    qua

    non

    of

    personhood.

    This is a time-honored

    pro-choice

    feminist

    strategy:

    Those who defend

    a

    woman's

    moral

    right

    to abort

    argue

    hat fetuses

    lack

    one or more

    morally

    relevant

    characteristicsand hence

    fall short of

    full

    moral

    personhood,

    rightholder

    status,

    and

    membership

    n the moral

    commu-

    nity-as

    a result

    of which women are

    permitted

    to abort

    (Burgess-Jackson

    1994,

    142).

    Sherwin uses

    this

    strategy

    when,

    citing

    Petchesky

    (1985, 341),

    she

    modifies her

    biological explanation

    by arguing

    that

    personality

    ( conscious-

    52

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    en términos relacionales, losfetos se mueven a través de lamujer embarazada

    fetosexistencomocombinación

    el problemade estarelacionalidad es la

    oscilaciónentre lobiológico y lopsicológico

    la cuestiónde laagencia sevuelve crítica

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    8/25

    Lynn

    M.

    Morgan

    ness and

    sociability,

    n

    Petchesky's

    erms)

    is also a

    necessarycomponent

    of

    personhood (Sherwin 1992, 109). Whitbeck notes (albeit parenthetically):

    (Newborns

    cannot have

    any responsibilities,

    and for that reason

    may

    be

    regarded

    s

    immanent

    [sic]

    people)

    (1984, 80).5

    Relationality,

    n

    other

    words,

    must be

    reciprocal,

    but

    because

    fetuses are ineffective relational

    agents,

    a

    relationship

    s

    impossible.

    On other

    occasions,

    these same theorists

    place

    the onus for

    relationality

    on

    the

    pregnant

    woman.

    Petchesky,

    or

    example,

    is

    willing

    to attributerelational-

    ity

    at least

    partly

    o a

    pregnant

    woman'sawareness

    f it:

    'Relationship'

    means,

    first,that there is

    interdependence;

    nd second, that there is a consciousness f

    this,

    even

    if that

    consciousness is

    one-sided

    [i.e.,

    from

    pregnant

    woman to

    fetus]

    for a time

    (1985, 346).

    And

    later,

    What is irreducibleand

    indispens-

    able in this

    humanization

    process

    (the

    formationof the

    'person')

    s

    the

    subjec-

    tivityof

    the

    pregnant

    woman,

    her consciousness

    of

    existing

    in a

    relationship

    with

    the

    fetus

    (1985, 347).

    Gilligan puts

    it

    slightly differently,

    mphasizing

    mater-

    nal-fetal

    impartibility

    rather than the

    capacity

    of one or another

    party

    to

    develop relationships:

    The connection between

    the

    fetus

    and the

    pregnant

    woman becomes the focus ofattention and the

    question

    becomes whether it is

    responsible

    or

    irresponsible, aring

    or

    careless,

    o extend or to end this connec-

    tion. In this

    construction,

    the abortion

    dilemma

    arises

    because there is no

    way

    not to

    act,

    and no

    way

    of

    acting

    that

    does

    not

    alter the connection

    between

    self

    and others

    (Gilligan

    1987, 25).

    There is

    a third

    approach,

    which

    would

    locate

    relationality

    neither in the

    pregnant

    woman nor the fetus

    (that

    culturallyprivilegeddyad),

    but

    in a

    larger

    social network.

    Warren,

    for

    example,

    while

    citing

    fetal/infant

    sentience as

    one

    plausible prerequisite

    o

    personhood,

    also

    argues,

    It is

    doubtful that a

    child reared in

    total isolation from human or other

    sentient

    (or

    apparently

    sentient)

    beings

    could

    develop

    the

    capacities

    for

    self-awarenessand social

    interaction that are

    essential to

    personhood

    1989, 62).

    Social

    relationships

    elaborated after

    birth,

    in

    other

    words,

    complete

    the achievement of full

    personhood

    in

    Warren's erms.

    Whitbeck,

    like

    Warren,

    allows

    agency

    to be

    diffused

    through

    a network of

    already

    iving persons

    who

    constitute,

    and

    are

    constituted

    by,

    others in a

    historically changing

    social

    world. Her

    feminist

    ontology

    is characterized

    by

    the

    core

    practice

    ... of

    the

    (mutual)

    realization

    of

    people

    (Whitbeck

    1984, 65).

    This

    third

    point,

    however,

    reveals

    an under-

    lying

    contradiction

    that Whitbeck and

    others

    may

    be loathe

    to articulate.

    For

    understandable

    practical political

    reasons,

    they

    would

    prefer

    to situate

    relationality

    either in

    intrinsic

    properties

    of the

    fetus

    or

    pregnancy,

    or

    in the

    pregnant

    woman

    herself,

    or both.

    They

    are

    reluctant to allow

    relationality

    to

    leakout into a

    pregnant

    woman'ssocial

    world

    (e.g.,

    father,

    parents,

    riends,

    governmentagencies)

    because

    shared

    relationalitymight provide

    a

    justifica-

    tion for

    undercutting

    her

    sovereign

    control over the

    fate of her

    pregnancy.

    Sherwin,

    for

    example, argues

    that choices are

    never

    made outside a

    social

    53

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    Relacionalidad debe ser recíproca pero ahí se meten en el problema de laagencia...ESTO SE RESUELVE CON HARAWAY CON LATOUR

    agenciaen redsocialescapando de diada

    esimportantepensar enla preguntade laagencia

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    9/25

    Hypatia

    context,

    yet

    she also

    argues

    that

    pregnant

    women should retain exclusive

    control over reproductivedecisions (1992, 102). So even though a woman's

    life circumstances

    and

    the

    pregnancy

    tself)

    are embeddedwithin and deter-

    mined

    by

    a

    larger

    social

    context,

    Sherwin's

    analysis

    solates

    the

    woman from

    that

    context in

    order

    to

    justify

    granting

    her

    control

    over

    reproductive

    deci-

    sions. This creates a series of

    problems,

    especially

    with

    respect

    to

    underprivi-

    leged

    women. As Daniels

    points

    out:

    The

    right

    to

    self-sovereignty

    also means

    the

    right

    to be

    a

    free

    decision-maker n one'sprivatelife, to have a realmin which

    one can be

    self-determining.

    Yet a retreat into

    privacy,espe-

    cially

    for

    poor

    women,

    can

    never securethe

    power

    of self-deter-

    mination. The

    power

    to

    be a free

    decision-maker

    arisesnot in

    isolation,

    but in

    social onnectiono a whole web of

    relationships

    that can

    empower

    women in the

    context of

    poverty

    and domi-

    nation.

    Self-sovereignty

    hus is

    indivisible

    from

    social

    empow-

    erment.

    (Daniels 1993, 134;

    see also Porter

    1994, 78)

    If our

    analyses

    isolate women from

    society,

    even

    for the sole

    purpose

    of

    allowing

    her to control

    reproductive

    decisions,

    we will

    have

    to

    accept any

    unsavory onsequences.

    Such

    analysesprivatize

    decision

    making,

    and could be

    interpreted

    as

    absolving society

    of

    responsibility

    to

    foster social

    climates

    conducive to

    bearing

    (or not)

    and

    raising

    children. This is but one

    example

    of

    the

    paradoxes

    and contradictionsthat

    invariablyemerge

    when

    we

    argue-as

    we must-for both

    sociality

    and individualism.

    An alternative

    approach

    o

    the

    problem

    of

    locating agency

    (i.e.,

    the locus

    of action

    and

    responsibility)

    questions

    the

    premise

    that

    it

    can be located

    at

    all

    through

    a

    process

    of

    philosophical inquiry.

    Monica

    Casper

    (1994),

    a

    sociologist analyzing

    deas about

    the volition attributed o

    fetuses,

    argues

    hat

    agency

    is not an

    alreadyexisting

    fact

    (ontological

    or

    otherwise)

    to be discov-

    ered

    or revealed but is rather

    a

    social

    project.

    There are

    many

    sites,

    she

    says,

    where

    agency

    is

    discursively

    and

    concretely configured

    and enacted.

    Casper

    notes that in the case of fetal surgery, gency slipsaround, lidingfromfetuses,

    for

    example,

    to

    pregnant

    women,

    to

    medical

    practitioners

    and

    others,

    depend-

    ing

    on

    where

    the actors

    fit into the

    power

    matrix.

    A

    feminist

    program

    hat

    explicitly

    rejects

    the

    possibility

    of fetal

    agency

    has to

    be

    understood as

    a

    response

    to

    competing

    discoursesthat

    grant

    active

    agency

    to fetuses.6

    This

    political

    context

    undoubtedly

    affects feminist

    philosophizing

    (and

    anthropologizing).

    Acknowledging

    the

    power

    relations inherent

    in

    assigning

    agency might

    enable us to be more

    explicit

    about

    why

    we

    might

    be

    compelled,

    right

    now,

    to

    emphasize

    relationality

    and maternal

    agency

    over individualism

    and fetal

    agency.

    54

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    según la autora hay una contradicción entrelas formas de relacionalidad contextuales y eldeterminismo biológico para asegurar lasdecisiones biológicas

    Problemas respecto amujeres de bajos privilegios

    poder deautodeterminación encondiciones depobreza no sonseguras,autodeterminación noes una cosa aislada,conexión social

    problemade aislar amujeres desociedad

    privatización de lasdecisiones

    el asunto sepuede pensarmás bien alcuestionarsesi agenciapuede serlocalizada através de lafilosofía

    Casper:feto no esontológico,es unproyectosocial,agencia seactúa, seconcretadiscursivamente

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    10/25

    Lynn

    M.

    Morgan

    CULTURE-BOUND

    EMINISTELATIONALITY

    Their effortsat culturaldestabilization

    notwithstanding,

    Sherwin,

    Warren,

    and Whitbeck are

    steeped

    in

    the same Western

    individualism

    they

    seek

    to

    undercut;

    so

    steeped,

    in

    fact,

    that

    they

    may

    not

    recognize

    the culture-bound

    tenor of their

    arguments.

    The

    Western

    ethnobiological

    view

    of

    personhood

    holds

    that

    relationality

    is

    superimposedupon

    a

    developing, naturally

    given

    mind-body.

    The

    Western view also holds that

    persons,

    once formed

    (or

    embodied ),

    are

    corporeally

    immutable

    and

    fixed,

    rather than

    susceptible

    to continuing social influences (Conklin and Morgan n.d.; Strathern

    1992a;

    Turner

    1994).

    Persons,

    once

    established,

    retain this

    fundamentally

    unchangeable

    essence. The critical

    analytic problem,

    therefore,

    is

    not

    to

    account

    for

    the

    coming

    into

    being

    of

    bodies,

    which are

    natural,

    but

    the

    coming

    into

    being

    of

    persons,

    which

    are,

    presumably,uniquely

    social

    and

    historical.

    Relationality

    is

    considered

    by

    these authors as

    integral

    to

    person-

    hood,

    but

    not

    to

    the

    body

    itself. I will

    untangle

    the

    problematics

    of each of

    these issues n turn.

    First,

    Western ndividualism

    equires

    asa

    precursor

    o human

    personhood

    an

    already existing

    material

    corporeality;

    biological

    existence

    must

    always pre-

    cede

    sociality.

    In

    Warren's

    words,

    The infant at birth

    enters the human social

    world,

    where,

    if

    it

    lives,

    it becomes

    involved in social

    relationships

    with

    others,

    of kinds

    that

    can

    only

    be

    dimly

    foreshadowed before birth

    (1989, 56).

    Corporeal integrity

    and

    skin-encapsulation

    thus

    prefigure

    the

    person;

    the

    individual

    body

    is viewed as a

    biopsychological

    blank slate

    upon

    which

    people

    later write. In Mackenzie's

    words,

    The more

    physically complex

    and

    devel-

    oped

    the

    being

    is,

    the more value we

    attribute

    o

    its

    potential

    for

    personhood

    (1992, 145).

    This

    biological-social

    developmental

    dualism extends to

    the

    mind,

    too,

    which

    comes to

    possess

    its

    morally meaningful

    qualities (e.g.,

    sentience,

    consciousness,

    responsibility) hrough

    physioneurological

    rocesses

    considered

    argely

    asocial and

    unstoppable.

    Sherwin

    argues

    in

    this vein that

    fetal

    relationality

    is

    impossible during

    pregnancy,

    becausethe

    fetus's

    ability

    to form

    tsown

    relationships

    s

    forestalled

    by

    the

    presence

    of the

    pregnant

    woman's

    body.

    She

    implies

    that

    relationships,

    in

    order to be

    morally

    valid,

    should

    be held

    by

    individuals

    (what

    we

    might

    think of as

    in-dividu-ables ).

    ikewiseWhitbeck

    asserts hat the

    relations f

    the self to others

    are relations

    among analogous

    beings

    1984, 76).

    By

    this she

    means

    that

    persons

    are created

    through mutually

    constitutive,

    reciprocal,

    communicative

    processes

    rather than

    through

    domination

    or

    annihilation

    (1984, 76),

    but I

    interpreted

    he

    phrase analogous

    beings

    also

    to mean that

    these

    beings

    should be

    biologically independent

    of

    each other.

    Whitbeck's

    self-others

    cheme does not

    problematize

    he

    autonomous

    Western

    person

    or

    self.

    A

    wholly

    realized

    relationality

    hinges,

    in

    the views of Sherwin

    and

    Whitbeck,

    on

    the notion

    of

    corporealautonomy.

    55

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    rekacionalidad es sobre personas y no sobre cuerpos que serían fijos

    cuerpoindividuales basepara

    relacionesposteriores

    implícitamente que

    relaciones,para sermoralmenteválidasdeben serentreindividuos.No seproblematiza la personaoccidentalautónoma

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    11/25

    Hypatia

    An

    alternative

    view

    ofpersonhood might interpret

    bodies not as blank slates

    but as the literal instantiationof socialrelations.These more radicalvisions of

    the relational

    body-person

    can

    best

    be illustrated

    by examples

    from societies

    where the

    body

    is

    thought

    to

    be more

    than a materialsubstrate

    upon

    which

    meaning

    is encoded

    (see

    Butler

    1990, 129),

    specifically

    and

    predictably),

    with

    examples

    from non-Western

    societies.7In the

    Brazilian

    Amazon,

    for

    example,

    indigenous

    peoples commonly emphasize

    he father's

    contribution

    to

    forming

    a child. The Shavante

    say

    that the father

    literally

    orms

    he

    fetus from semen.

    Frequent

    ntercourse,

    specially

    during

    the fifth

    month,

    is

    required

    o

    effect

    a

    pregnancy.

    As one Shavante

    explained

    the

    process

    . . . while

    ticking

    the

    months

    off with his

    fingers: Copulate.

    Copulate,

    copulate, copulate,

    copulate

    a lot.

    Pregnant.Copulate, copulate,

    copulate.

    Born'

    (Maybury-Lewis

    967,

    63,

    quoted

    in

    Scheper-Hughes

    and Lock

    1987,

    19).

    Beth

    Ann Conklin

    points

    out that

    among

    the

    Wari'

    of the western

    Amazon,

    the father's

    ommitment

    to

    creating

    a

    child's

    body/person hrough repeated

    coitus means

    that

    pregnancy

    can

    never

    be a

    mistake ;

    very

    pregnancy

    s instead the

    result of

    deliberate,

    concerted social

    initiative

    (Conklin

    and

    Morgan

    n.d.;

    Conklin

    1995).

    Many

    non-Westernvariantsof relational

    personhood

    stressthe

    permeability

    of bod-

    ies

    in

    nature-culture

    ransformations;

    or

    example,

    The

    Suya

    cosmology

    does

    not mark

    two

    distinct

    poles

    of

    nature and

    culture

    standing

    in

    permanent

    opposition.

    Rather there are

    degrees

    of naturalnessand

    degrees

    of socialness.

    Social

    life is thus

    a constant socialization

    or naturalization

    of human

    beings,

    bodies,

    animals,

    and

    space

    (Seeger

    1981,

    119).

    The

    person --even

    before

    birth

    and after death-is

    never

    perceived

    as a natural

    r asocial

    entity.

    The

    physical

    substance

    of

    the

    body-flesh,

    blood,

    and

    bones,

    as

    well as

    personal-

    ity-is

    literally

    constructed-and

    continually

    reconstructed-by

    and under

    the watchful

    care

    of others

    in

    a

    social world.The

    body

    and the

    person

    are thus

    coterminous,

    and the

    body/person

    s

    valued

    socially

    precisely

    because

    t is

    the

    product

    of

    specific

    social

    interactions.

    One

    other

    difference

    between non-Wester

    relationality

    and

    Western

    em-

    inist

    relationality

    concerns

    the

    role

    of

    physiological

    nurturance

    n

    creating

    persons.

    By physiological

    nurturance

    am

    referring

    o

    more than

    the ethic

    of

    caring

    for children

    and others

    (so

    often stressed

    n the

    West);

    people

    in

    many

    non-Wester societies

    insist

    that the

    exchange

    of

    food and

    body

    substances

    actually

    create

    kinship

    and

    personhood

    Meigs

    1984).

    They

    often tie

    gradients

    of

    personhood

    to the

    exchange

    of

    body

    substances

    (such

    as

    blood, sweat,

    or

    breast

    milk),

    rather

    than

    to

    the

    ability

    of newboms

    to

    interact,

    respond,

    or

    form social bonds

    as

    in

    Western

    societies. Yet Whitbeck

    (1984,

    65),

    for

    one,

    shies

    away

    rom

    the term

    nurturing

    ecause t

    connotes feminine

    selflessness.

    The

    Reagan-era

    social

    context

    of her

    remarks

    needs to be

    kept

    in

    mind,

    yet

    one wonders

    about

    denying

    the

    importance

    of nurturance

    n

    creating

    children

    just

    because

    the

    concept

    has

    historically

    been

    used

    to

    oppress

    women.

    A

    child

    advocacy

    slogan

    currently

    in

    vogue

    says,

    It takes

    a whole

    village

    to raise

    a

    56

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    personacomoinstanciade

    relacionessocialesvisionesmásradiacales-Butler-donde elcuerpo esmás queunsubstratomaterial.

    el embarazono puede ser

    un error,procedimientos del padrecontinuos, esel resultadode unainciativadeliberada yconcertada

    sociedaddonde noexiste cuerpo-natural puesse construyey re construye

    rol decrianzapsicológicaesdemasiadooccidental

    crianzacomoaltruismo-feminidad

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    12/25

    Lynn

    M.

    Morgan

    child.

    The cross-cultural

    omparison

    remindsus that

    nurturing

    s not

    every-

    where or automaticallylinked to the self-sacrificingmother (see Scheper-

    Hughes

    1992),

    but can rather

    be conceived as

    a

    quality

    distributed

    hroughout

    communities

    of men and

    women,

    which hold

    a

    collective

    responsibility

    or

    bringing

    other

    people

    into

    being.

    Marilyn

    Strather

    notes

    that

    in Melanesia

    incipient persons

    contain

    other

    persons,

    have

    other

    persons

    implied

    in

    [their]

    constitution

    (1992b,

    152).

    Reproduction

    n

    Melanesia, then,

    as in

    many

    non-Western

    societies,

    is not a

    process

    of

    linking

    etuses

    and/or

    infants with other

    persons-of superimposing

    sociality

    over a

    biological

    substrate-but

    of

    differentiating

    he

    new

    person

    from

    the

    others

    (including supernatural

    beings

    and

    animal

    persons,

    as well as

    parents

    and other

    kin)

    who contributed

    to

    the creation

    of this nascent

    being.

    Whereas

    Sherwin

    might

    locate the

    essence

    of

    personhood

    in

    a

    fetus/infant's

    corporeality

    or in its

    ability

    to communicate and

    respond

    (1992, 111),

    an

    alternative

    perspective might

    view

    the

    fetus/infant

    as

    a

    motley

    amalgam

    of

    many

    social influences which enable

    its

    constitution. These

    might

    include

    social events (such as the failing contraceptionor acquisitionof a better-pay-

    ing job),

    personality

    traits inherited from

    important persons

    (such

    as

    the

    whistling

    grandmother

    or

    gardening

    dad),

    and substances

    (such

    as

    prenatal

    vitamins,

    or

    peanut

    butter

    on

    seven-grain

    bread).

    In

    other

    words,

    an

    alterna-

    tive view of

    personhood

    could

    perceive body

    substance

    and

    not

    just

    the

    cognitive

    self)

    as

    socially

    constituted.

    Relationships

    could then be

    implied

    and

    highlighted

    at

    every stage

    of

    potential,

    incipient,

    and

    emergent personhood,

    from the social context

    of

    courtship

    and

    sexuality through

    conception

    and

    early gestationthroughbirth, socialization,education,and initiation through

    to the end of the life

    cycle.

    The claim that

    body/persons

    are

    created

    through

    physiological

    nurturance

    has

    implications

    for how

    we

    might

    reframe

    pregnancy

    termination and

    fetal

    death.

    A

    woman

    (or

    her

    partner[s],

    or

    relevant others in her

    social

    world)

    might

    elect

    not

    to sustain

    or

    nurture he fetal or

    infant

    body.

    This would

    not

    constitute

    active

    killing

    (the

    terms in which

    induced abortion is so

    often

    described),

    but the

    failure

    to

    complete

    the

    social

    process

    of

    producing

    body/persons.The ethnographic iteraturecontains numerous

    descriptions

    of

    sickly

    or

    stillborn

    infants

    whose dis-ease is attributed to

    failures

    of

    social

    nurturance in

    utero

    (Conklin

    and

    Morgan

    n.d.;

    Scheper-Hughes

    1992).

    I

    should

    emphasize,

    however,

    that

    the

    decision to discontinue an

    emergent

    person

    n

    non-Westernsocieties

    is

    rarely

    a freechoice

    undertaken

    by

    women

    acting

    in

    their own

    individualisticbest

    interests,

    as

    Westernfeminists

    might

    imagine

    it.

    Such a

    decision is more

    likely

    to

    be the cumulative

    result of

    a

    number

    of

    unstable or

    unpredictable

    ocial

    contingencies

    (such

    as the

    illness,

    absence,

    or death

    of

    relevant

    parties,

    or

    the

    inability

    of

    the social

    group

    to

    generate

    the kin

    commitmentsneeded to

    nurture

    a

    future

    child).

    As

    such,

    the

    57

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    no se puede universalizar crianzaoccidental

    una visiónalternativaentoncespuede serel cuerposubstanciacomosocialmenteconstituido

    cuerpo/ persona através decrianzatienemuchasimplicaciones sobremarco delembarazo

    resultadode

    contingenciassociales

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    13/25

    Hypatia

    discontinuation

    or termination of

    a

    prospective

    etal or infant

    body/person

    s

    an eminently social anddynamicprocess.

    Cross-cultural ariations

    n

    ideologies

    of

    personhood

    are

    important

    o this

    argument

    not

    (just)

    because I write as an

    anthropologist,

    but because

    my

    anthropological

    sensibilities are unsettled

    by

    the claims of

    some

    feminist

    philosophers

    who

    plant flags

    on

    pancultural

    erritory.

    Whitbeck,

    for

    example,

    argues

    hat her

    responsibilities

    pproach

    o ethics has

    a

    greater

    potential

    for

    cross-cultural

    applicability

    than does the

    rights

    approach

    1984,

    80).

    This

    may

    be

    true

    in

    the limited

    sense,

    but Whitbeck does

    not

    acknowledge

    the

    extent to

    which the

    responsibilities

    pproach

    erives rom a

    historically

    and

    culturally pecific

    rather han

    a

    universalnotion of

    personhood.

    One wonders

    whether

    Whitbeck

    privatizes

    moral

    agency (qua personhood)by

    locating

    it

    in

    individuals

    i.e.,

    in discrete

    persons/bodies)

    rather than in social

    groups,

    hus

    overlooking

    the connections

    among

    rather

    than

    between)

    people

    that under-

    lie

    social

    organization

    n

    many

    societies. Can a

    philosophy

    that

    normalizesa

    particular

    ultural

    ormever account for

    negotiated

    enactments

    of

    personhood

    in relation to changing configurationsof poweracrossthe globe?How could

    such a

    philosophy

    account for

    relationshipsamong

    groups

    such

    as Arabs and

    Jews),

    whose

    identities are

    continually reconfigured

    by

    politics?

    How can we

    think about

    societies where moral

    agency

    extends

    beyond

    the human

    realm,

    for

    example,

    when animals or ancestors are considered

    moral

    agents?

    We

    should

    be

    skeptical

    of

    any

    approach

    hat

    essentializes ndividual

    bodies/persons

    in

    uniquely

    Western

    ways.

    THE MORALAMBIGUITY

    OF BIRTH

    Being

    awareof the historical

    [and

    cultural]

    articularity

    f

    moral

    concepts

    allows us

    to

    adopt

    a

    healthy

    caution

    about

    absolutist

    positions

    and to

    question

    ongoing

    moraldebate.

    (ElisabethPorter,

    Abortion

    Ethics:

    Rights

    and

    Responsibilities )

    One avenue

    of feminist

    response

    to abortion

    politics

    has been to reassert

    what

    Virginia

    Held

    (1987,

    122)

    and

    Mary

    Anne Warren

    (1989)

    call the

    moral

    ignificance

    of

    birth.

    Birth

    is

    morally significant

    because it marks

    the end of

    one

    relationship

    and

    the

    beginnings

    of

    others ....

    Although

    the

    infant

    is not

    instantly

    transformed

    nto a

    person

    at the moment

    of

    birth,

    it does

    become

    a

    biologically

    separate

    human

    being.

    As

    such,

    it

    can

    be known and cared

    for

    as

    a

    particular

    ndividual.

    (Warren

    1989, 62;

    my emphasis)

    58

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    descontinuación de fetocuerpo/persona es unproceso socialvariaciones culturales!!

    noción deresponsabilidad vienede unanociónuniversalde persona

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    14/25

    Lynn

    M.

    Morgan

    Likewise,

    Sherwin

    argues

    that fetuses

    differ

    from

    newborns,

    who

    immedi-

    ately begin to develop into persons by virtue of their place as subjects in

    human

    relationships

    (1992, 111).

    The

    dividing

    line between full

    persons

    and

    non-persons

    should be

    drawn,

    say

    Held,

    Warren,

    and

    Sherwin,

    at

    biological

    birth.

    This

    argument

    s

    problematic

    on

    at

    least three counts.

    First,

    as discussed

    above,

    it

    relies on

    a

    biological

    reductionism

    by using

    physical autonomy

    (i.e.,

    separateness)

    as the

    most

    important

    qualification

    for

    personhood.

    Second,

    it

    romanticizesa

    disappearing

    poch

    in which

    biological

    birthdid

    mark he

    social

    beginning

    of

    personhood,

    and

    ignores

    an

    emerging discontinuity

    between

    social and

    biological

    birth in North American

    society.

    And

    third,

    it

    does

    not

    allow for

    gradations

    n

    value

    which

    make ate

    gestation

    fetusesmore

    significant

    than

    early gestation

    fetuses.

    There was a time not

    long ago

    in the United States when

    biological

    birth

    did mark the social

    (as

    well as

    legal) beginnings

    of

    personhood.

    Parents-to-

    be

    typically

    had to wait until

    biological

    birth to know the

    baby

    and

    bestow its selected

    gender-specific

    name.

    Biological

    birth

    was

    ritualized-

    phone

    calls

    in

    the wee

    hours,

    cigars,

    gifts,

    announcements,

    photographs-

    in

    recognition

    that the occasion

    marked the

    beginnings

    of social

    identity

    and

    personhood.

    Whereas

    many

    non-Western societies have

    traditionally

    distinguished

    between

    biological

    and

    social birth

    (see

    Morgan

    1989),

    in

    the

    United States

    the two were

    historically

    conflated.8 The social

    reality

    has

    since

    changed.

    Social and

    biological

    birth have

    become

    uncoupled

    in

    the United States

    over the last twodecades.As a resultofreproductive maging echnologies,the

    commodificationof

    babies,

    and other social

    changes,

    the

    attributionof

    person-

    hood

    (what

    I

    call

    social

    birth )

    can now

    precede biological

    birth. The result

    is a

    new,

    unprecedentedcategory

    of fetal

    persons

    (see

    Duden

    1993;

    Petchesky

    1987;

    Rothman

    1986).

    These

    late-gestation

    fetuses are

    gendered

    and

    named;

    their

    pictorialrepresentations ppeal

    frombillboards

    and

    hang

    (in

    the form of

    ultrasound

    cans)

    on walls and

    refrigerators.

    n

    the media

    they

    are

    increasingly

    depicted

    as

    active,

    technologically sophisticatedagents,

    shown on

    television

    (in an AT&T ad) talking on the telephone (Taylorn.d.), or convincing

    adults to

    buy

    a

    particular

    kind of car

    (Taylor

    1992).

    It

    is

    my

    contention

    that

    those who

    set

    off to

    prove

    the natural

    mportance

    of

    birth

    forgot

    to

    keep

    an

    eye

    on

    the weather.

    Their rhetoric

    of

    birth

    as the

    moral

    dividing

    line between

    persons

    and

    nonpersons

    is

    simply unconvincing

    in an

    era when

    ever

    greater

    ocial

    value is

    being

    attached to fetuses

    (especially

    wanted, viable,

    third-trimester

    fetuses).

    Furthermore

    (and

    here

    I

    para-

    phrase

    Sawicki

    1991,

    86),

    arguments

    or the

    moral

    ignificance

    of

    birth are

    doomed to

    be

    politically

    ineffective

    because

    they

    do not

    resonate with the

    experiences

    of

    women who

    desire and

    create fetal

    personhood through

    their

    59

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    según varias, la línea divisoria entre personascompletas y no-personas debería ser trazada en elnacimiento biológico. PERO ESTO ESPROBLEMÁTICO

    i.reduccionismobiológico,autonomíacomo lomásimportante

    para serpersonaii.lo biológicocomomarca queignoranuevastecnologíasiii.no haygradosentre fetosmásgrandes ymáspequeños

    en eeuu elnacimientosocial y elbiológico se

    separaron...tecnologías...

    "fetalpersons"

    momentoen el que sele estádando granvalor sociala los fetosTECNOLOGÍAS

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    15/25

    Hypatia

    avid

    consumption

    of

    infertility

    treatments, amniocentesis,

    ultrasound,

    and

    in-uterovideo services.

    Fetal

    personhoodpresentsundeniably

    difficult

    challenges

    for

    feminist

    anal-

    ysis,

    but

    ignoring

    or

    denying

    the

    phenomenon

    will

    not make it

    disappear.

    Rather than

    stating categorically

    that

    fetuses,

    after

    all,

    are

    not

    yet

    persons

    (Purdy

    1990, 278),

    we

    need now

    to

    direct attention to the

    morally

    relevant

    gradations

    that

    occur within

    the

    gestational

    period (Noddings

    1989;

    Porter

    1994).

    Distinctions

    between

    early-

    and

    late-gestation

    fetuses

    are

    critical

    to

    abortion

    politics.

    Yet

    Sherwin dismisses he semantic

    (and

    thus

    the

    practical

    andmoral)distinction between

    embryo

    nd fetus,

    xplaining

    that she will

    use the

    term

    fetus

    o

    cover the entire

    period

    of

    development

    from

    concep-

    tion to the end of

    pregnancy

    (1992, 251).

    This is

    unfortunate,

    because

    Sherwin's

    metonymic

    reduction forces even the

    sympathetic

    reader

    to

    invoke

    a

    mental

    image

    that

    lumps together

    viable

    late-gestation

    fetuses

    (which

    can be

    read as social

    persons)

    with

    unformed

    early-gestation

    embryos

    (see

    C.

    Condit

    1990, 83).

    Whereas

    Sherwin talks about the fetus as an undifferentiated

    or

    mono-

    lithic

    entity,

    other feminist social scientists are

    analyzing

    the social

    prac-

    tices that work to establish

    (or

    to

    resist)

    different

    kinds,

    qualities,

    and

    degrees

    of

    fetal

    personhood (Casper

    1994;

    Morton

    1994).

    The fetus can

    symbolize

    and

    encapsulate

    a

    number

    of

    timely

    social issues

    (Oaks n.d.).

    Although

    the abortion

    debate

    is

    the most contentious

    public

    context

    influencing

    our

    society's

    views of fetuses

    today,

    it should be noted that

    multiple

    new

    meanings, emerging

    from

    developments

    in

    law,

    medicine,

    religion,

    and

    popular

    culture,

    are

    being generated

    and affect

    the

    way

    we

    think about fetuses. These

    overlapping

    discoursesneed to be identified and

    disentangled,

    lest

    they

    all be

    erroneously

    construed

    as

    variations

    on the

    abortion debate.

    The so-called

    infertility

    epidemic,

    for

    example,

    has

    gener-

    ated

    its own narratives

    of

    pregnancy

    loss and attendant

    meanings

    of

    fetuses

    (Inhorn

    1994;

    Layne

    1990, 1992;

    Sandelowski

    1993).

    There

    is

    intense

    negotiation

    over

    meanings

    in fetal

    surgery

    units as fetuses become

    objects

    of

    work

    (Casper

    1994),

    and

    in courtrooms as

    lawyers

    debate

    the

    legal

    status of the unborn

    (D.

    Condit

    1995;

    Gallagher

    1987).

    As

    the

    contexts

    for

    fetal discourse

    proliferate,

    it will be

    increasingly

    clear that we cannot talk

    about

    the fetus but rather need to talk

    about a

    diversity

    of

    situations

    and

    perspectives

    which

    carry

    with them

    many

    different

    meanings.9

    60

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    tenemosque poneratención alos gradosque seestándando en el

    períodogestacional

    "el feto"estánombrando unacantidaddecuestionessociales

    en cirugíasfetales, seconviertenen objetosde trabajo yobjeto dedebate en

    lasCORTES

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    16/25

    Lynn

    M.

    Morgan

    THE

    USES

    OF FETUS ALK

    An

    approach

    o

    selfhood

    as an embodied and

    historically

    situated

    practical

    knowledge

    ...

    prompts

    a

    larger

    question

    of

    rhetoric,

    namely,

    what

    use

    a

    particular

    notion of self has for

    someone

    or for

    some

    collectivity.

    (Debbora

    Battaglia,

    Problematizing

    he

    Self: A Thematic

    Introduction )

    If we

    apply

    Battaglia's insight

    to the motivations of feminist theorists

    thinkingaboutincipientpersonhood,we can better understandwhywe could

    be reluctant to

    engage

    in

    fetus

    talk. We know

    that

    our discursive

    practices

    (including

    our

    silences)

    have

    social

    consequences.

    If

    we talk

    about

    fetuses,

    then,

    or

    write

    about them in the

    pages

    of

    our

    journals,

    we

    come

    dangerously

    close

    to

    ceding territory

    to

    pro-life

    activists

    who benefit from the reifica-

    tion

    of

    fetal

    persons

    (see

    Pollitt

    1992).

    The threats to

    reproductive rights

    are real and must not be

    underestimated,

    but the

    pro-choice

    philosophical

    discourse

    I

    have described here carries another set

    of

    disquieting

    social

    and

    political implications.

    Consider

    the

    problematicconsequences

    of

    positing

    biological

    birth as the

    normative,natural,

    and most sensiblemoral

    dividing

    ine between

    persons

    and

    nonpersons.

    First,

    this assertion

    collapses

    a

    potentially

    useful distinction

    between

    biological

    and social birth which

    might help

    make

    sense

    of contem-

    porary

    hifts in the

    social

    (and

    moral)

    significance

    of

    biological

    birth and the

    social construction of

    early personhood

    in

    Europe

    and the

    United States.

    Second,

    emphasizingbiological

    birth

    ipso

    facto divides women into

    categories,

    natural

    mothers

    being

    those who

    respect

    the

    moral

    significance

    of

    birth,

    unnatural mothers

    implicitly

    those who do not

    (for

    example,

    those who

    deposit

    their

    newborns in trashcansor abandon

    them

    in

    hospital

    nurseries).

    Warren

    allies herself

    with

    women

    possessed

    of

    something

    akin to a maternal

    instinct

    when she

    says,

    Most women

    readily accept

    the

    responsibility

    or

    doing

    whatever

    they

    can to

    ensurethat their

    (voluntarily

    continued)

    pregnan-

    cies

    are

    successful,

    and

    that no

    avoidableharm comes to the fetus

    (1989, 58).

    While it

    may

    be

    unfair o take Warren's

    omment out

    of

    context-she was

    not,

    after

    all,

    writing

    about

    fetal abuse

    or

    the

    punitive

    actions taken

    against

    pregnant

    substance

    abusers-her statement

    is

    unfortunately

    and

    unintention-

    ally,

    I

    hope)

    consistent with a

    dichotomy emerging

    n

    the

    popular

    press

    that

    distinguishes

    good

    mothers romthe bad

    mothers who

    victimize

    their

    own

    children.

    But

    we

    live

    in

    treacherous

    imes,

    when we can

    expect

    our own words

    to be used

    against

    us. Rather

    than

    interrogating

    the

    nefarious

    dichotomy

    between

    good

    and bad

    mothers,

    or

    noting

    the backlashor

    the

    privatized

    moral

    economy

    embedded within

    it,

    Warren

    uncritically accepts

    a

    stereotype

    of

    criminalmonster

    motherswho

    neglect,

    abuse,

    abandon,

    or kill their

    newborns

    or

    children

    (Tsing

    1990;

    see also

    Boling

    1995).1?

    The monster

    mothers'

    per-

    61

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    implicaciones de hablar o nohablar de fetos

    partobiológicocomo lo másnatural y lomás positvoes doblefilo---terminaesencializan

    do el instintomaternaltambién

    Warrenterminaaceptandoacriticamente elestereotipo de lamadre-monstruo

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    17/25

    Hypatia

    sonal

    stories,

    no

    matter how

    grim,

    can

    never be made to

    justify

    their actions.

    Held argues,similarly,that the capacity for mothering emerges from the

    natural acts.

    Using

    that

    logic,

    she denies on

    biological

    grounds

    the

    male

    potential

    for

    adequateparenting:

    Since

    men,

    then,

    do not

    give

    birth,

    and

    do

    not

    experience

    the

    responsibility,

    he

    pain,

    and momentousnessof

    childbirth,

    they

    lack the

    particular

    motives to value

    the child that

    may spring

    from this

    capacity

    and this

    fact

    (Held 1987,

    125).

    This

    kind

    of

    rhetoric

    implicitly

    reinforces

    he

    assumption

    hat all women who have babies are

    good

    moth-

    ers.1

    It

    also

    severely

    imits

    the

    creative

    possibilities

    or

    co-parenting,

    commu-

    nal

    parenting,adoptive parenting,

    or other formsof

    raising

    children

    by

    those

    who are not

    the

    birth mothers.

    The

    emphasis

    on

    biological

    birth

    creates

    a

    third

    problem.

    It denies

    legiti-

    macy

    to

    a

    growing

    number

    of

    people (including pro-choice

    women and

    men)

    who

    may occasionally

    attribute

    personhood

    to

    late-gestation

    fetuses. Their

    experiences

    and

    logic

    are sometimes

    sensitively

    portrayed

    n the

    ethnographic

    literature

    (Rapp

    1987, 1990;

    Rothman

    1986;

    Sandelowski

    1993),

    but would

    not

    fit

    comfortably

    nto the

    philosophical

    iteraturediscussed

    here. If

    biologi-

    cal

    birth marks he

    beginnings

    of

    personhood,

    s

    there room within feminism

    for those

    who

    deeply

    mourn

    early miscarriage,

    or

    those

    who bestow

    person-

    hood

    on

    late-gestation

    etuses?

    Kathryn

    Addelson,

    citing

    C.

    Wright

    Mills,

    notes

    that the

    explanations

    people

    offer are themselves

    in

    need of

    explanation

    (Addelson 1987,

    91).

    If

    we

    assume that our

    analytic assumptions

    derive

    from

    particular

    social and

    intellectual

    traditions,

    then

    we

    have

    a

    responsibility

    o formulate

    responses

    with a heightened awareness o the historical and culturalidiosyncraciesof

    those

    traditions,

    and

    to

    make

    our

    reflexivityexplicit.

    I

    wish,

    for

    example,

    that

    Warrenor Sherwin

    had

    acknowledged

    how

    difficult

    it is to discussabortionas

    a

    problem

    linked

    to

    qualities

    of the fetus ratherthan

    to

    the

    social context

    of

    parenting

    (see

    Burgess-Jackson

    994,

    15).

    I

    wish

    they

    were more

    attentive

    to

    the

    changing

    social

    significance

    of

    biological

    birth and the

    proliferation

    of

    meanings

    attaching

    to fetuses.

    I

    wish

    they

    could

    imagine

    a

    relationality

    that

    overridesrather

    than

    replicates

    Cartesian

    dualisms,

    or a form of

    relationality

    that mightbe patternedcompletelydifferently n anothersocial,national, or

    historical

    context.

    I wish

    they

    would be as candid about

    their

    political

    moti-

    vations as

    Monica

    Casper,

    who

    states,

    As

    a

    pro-choice

    feminist

    from

    a

    nation

    where abortion

    is

    one

    of the most contentious

    and divisive issues

    n

    the

    public

    arena,

    where the

    fetus has

    emerged

    as a

    major

    cultural con ...

    at

    the

    hands

    of antiabortion orces

    granting

    t

    personhood,

    and

    where

    abortion doctors are

    now

    being

    murdered

    by pro-life

    error-

    ists,

    I am

    quite

    resistant

    o

    engaging

    in

    any

    practice

    that

    grants

    agency

    to the

    fetus.

    (Casper

    1994,

    851)

    62

    This content downloaded from 168.176.5.118 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 04:17:04 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    esencializar quita la posibilidad de pensar posibilidadescreativas de maternidad-paternidad

    el últimoproblema es

    entonces si

    esta barreraexisteentonces pqla gente seencarniñacon losfetos?

    esfundamental!!! tener encuentacontextos enlos queformulamosrespuestas

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 Fetal Relationality in Feminist Philosophy-An Anthropological Critique

    18/25

    Lynn

    M.

    Morgan

    We need to

    acknowledge

    hat

    we are not

    revealing

    truths bout

    the

    person-

    hood of fetuses (or others), but ratherengaging in the process (historically

    and

    culturally

    situated)

    of

    producing persons

    ourselves,

    through

    our

    actions,

    reactions,

    and

    rhetoric

    (including

    our academic

    rhetoric).

    Our

    actions and

    writings

    create a

    vocabulary,

    a

    rhetoric,

    a set

    of

    meanings

    with

    which

    to

    make sense

    of

    fetal

    personhood

    and

    relationality.

    Precisely

    because the

    political

    stakes

    are so

    high,

    those

    of us who write

    about

    fetal

    relationality

    have

    a

    responsibility

    to

    be

    reflexive

    and

    self-critical,

    to think

    about

    the

    kind

    of

    world we want to

    create.

    OF INSTRUMENTALERSONHOOD

    ND MORAL

    PRAGMATICS

    Formalized otions of

    personhood

    are not to be

    construedas

    descriptive

    of a

    static,

    preordained,

    ocial

    world;

    hey

    are

    instrumentalitieswhich

    people

    actively

    use

    in

    constructing

    and

    reconstructing

    a

    world which

    adjusts

    values and

    goals

    inheritedfromthe pastto the problemsandexigencieswhich

    comprise

    their social existence

    in

    the here and now.

    (Michael

    Jackson

    and

    Ivan

    Karp,

    Personhoodnd

    Agency:

    The

    Experience f Self

    and Other n

    African

    Societies)

    Early

    anthropological investigations

    of

    personhood

    tended to

    overdraw

    discrepancies

    between cultures.

    Non-Western

    cultures were sociocentric

    compared

    o

    egocentric

    Westerncultures

    (Shweder

    and

    Bourne

    1984).

    The

    ideal

    types-approach

    as

    begun

    to fall out of

    favor,however,