evolutionary dynamics, game theory, and psychology

187
Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Upload: derica

Post on 24-Feb-2016

147 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology. Today and next Tues: we will show you some work we are doing at PED -that uses evolutionary dynamics game theory experiments - to understand human psychology, e.g. Altruistic motives Sense of beauty Why we are “principled” . - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Page 2: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Today and next Tues:

we will show you some work we are doing at PED-that uses

evolutionary dynamics game theory experiments

-to understand human psychology, e.g. Altruistic motivesSense of beautyWhy we are “principled”

Page 3: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Will start off “philosophical” (in order to set the stage)

Then will present ongoing research…

This is work done at PED, with Erez, Oliver, Carl, Alex, Matthiajs, Martin …

Page 4: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Topic 1: Charitable Giving

Page 5: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We give A LOT ~2% of GDP are donated to charity~ 2-4% of hours worked are volunteered

Page 6: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

But we don’t always give in the most effective way…

Page 7: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 8: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Habitat for Humanity: college educated 19 year oldswho’ve never held a hammerfly halfway across the world

To build new homes in places where there is plenty of cheap, qualified labor!

Page 9: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Is this just because we don’t realize how ineffective Habitat for Humanity is?

Or do we not care how effective we are?

Page 10: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

IF we ACTUALLY care about being effective…we should give more when our gifts are matched, no?

And even more so our gifts are tripled, no?

Do we?

Page 11: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Some economists ran a study where they collected $ for charity…

And they manipulated the “matching rate”

Page 12: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 13: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

What impact did the matching rate have?

None…

Page 14: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 15: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We ask…Why don’t we care about effectiveness?How can we make giving more effective?

More generally…Why are our altruistic preferences so funny? Can we characterize our altruistic preferences? And can we use this knowledge to increase

giving? Or to make giving more impactful?

Page 16: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Topic 2: Beauty

Page 17: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

A few facts about beauty…

Page 18: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Fact 1: varies by culture

Page 19: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

e.g., let’s learn about the ideal body weight in some indigenous populations in Nigeria...

Page 20: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Clearly, ideal body weight isn’t the same there as here.

Why not?

Random cultural variation?

Page 21: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Likewise, ideal skin tone varies by culture…

In Eastern countries, un-tanned skin is considered more attractive …

Page 22: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 23: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

And likewise, in the West in the old days…

Page 24: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 25: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

But nowadays in the West we seem to prefer tanned skin…

Page 26: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 27: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Why did our preferences change? Why do they differ between East and West?

Random fluctuations?

Page 28: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Even our ideal finger nail length varies by culture…

Here’s what finger nails look like on some men among the Khasi in N.E. India

Page 29: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 30: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Fact 2: We like art that is “authentic” (even if looks the same!)

Page 31: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Let me tell you about a study that illustrated this…

Page 32: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Researchers showed subjects two paintings

Page 33: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Some subjects were told the second painting was purposely designed by a different artist, making the second painting a forgery.

Some subjects were told the same artist painted both.

Within each group, half the subjects were told painting A was created first.

Page 34: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

When the second painting was “created by the same artist,” it was rated higher

making the second painting a “replica.”

Source: Newman and bloom (2011)

Same artist Different artist

making the second painting a “replica.”

Page 35: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Why do we like our art to be “original”?

Page 36: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Perhaps this has nothing to do with aesthetics…

Well…when the study was repeated with an artifact (e.g. a car) instead of paintings, there was no effect…

Page 37: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Source: Newman and bloom (2011)

Page 38: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Topic 3: “Principles”

Page 39: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Why do we like people who are principled?

Page 40: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

For instance, this statesmen in the West Wing who returns a card that can save his life...out of principle

And we admire him for it…even though turning down the card helps no one

Page 41: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

In contrast, people who are strategic and calculating,

like this cop from “the wire” who prefer “better stats” to solving murders

…are repulsive. Even though his strategic actions don’t harm you…

Page 42: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Why do we like people who are principled/idealistic and dislike those who are strategic/calculated/Machiavellian, regardless of whether their actions help or harm us?

Page 43: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

More generally…

Where do our preferences and ideologies come from?

Page 44: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

In our research…

We try to understand from where such preferences and ideologies come from.

Using evolutionary dynamics + game theory + experiments

Page 45: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Quick review: what is game theory?

Page 46: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Game theory models behavior in any social interaction

Social interaction=my payoffs depend on what I do as well as what others do.

Let me illustrate using a simple game…

Page 47: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

5, 6 8, 4

3, 2 0, -3

U

D

L RThe simplest “game” can be represented by the following “payoff matrix”

Page 48: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

5,6 8, 4

3, 2 0, -3

U

D

L RPlayer 1 chooses between two actions

Page 49: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

5, 6 8, 4

3, 2 0, -3

U

D

L RPlayer 2 simultaneously chooses between 2 actions

Page 50: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

5, 6 8, 4

3, 2 0, -3

U

D

L RThe payoffs to player 1 are determined by her action as well as the action of player 2

Page 51: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

5, 6 8, 4

3, 2 0, -3

U

D

L RThe payoffs to player 2 are determined by her action as well as the action of player 2

Page 52: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

The main insight of game theory comes from the “Nash equilibria”

Which often have counterintuitive properties, or allows us to clarify things we already “know.”

Page 53: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

5, 6 8, 4

3, 2 0, -3

U

D

L RThis game can be “solved” by finding the “Nash equilibrium”

Page 54: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

5, 6 8, 4

3, 2 0, -3

U

D

L R(U, L) is a Nash Equilibrium b/c neither can benefit by unilaterally deviating

Page 55: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

“Predictions” of game theory:

If both “expected” (U,L), both would play (U,L)!

(Nash is “self enforcing”)

Page 56: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

5, 6 8, 4

3, 2 0, -3

U

D

L R(U,R) is NOT a Nash Equilibrium b/c 2 can benefit by unilaterally deviating

to L

Page 57: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Game theory “predicts”:

If both expected (U,R), player 2 would deviate!

(I.e. if not Nash, cannot be “stable”)

Page 58: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Nash makes sense (arguably) if…

-Uber-rational

-Calculating

Page 59: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Such as Auctions…

Page 60: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Or Oligopolies…

Page 61: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Nash also makes sense (as 1st approx.) if:

1) strategies that yield higher payoffs, reproduce faster

2) evolutionary dynamics Nash

Page 62: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

e.g. Fisher and Sex Ratios

Page 63: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

e.g. Maynard-Smith and territoriality

Page 64: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

E.g. Zahavi’s handicap principle

Page 65: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

But why would game theory matter for our preferences/ideologies?

We don’t “choose” what to find beautiful?

We didn’t “evolve” to like long finger nails?

Page 66: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

But…

If preferences/ideologies learned/evolve…

Nash becomes relevant…

Here’s why:

Page 67: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Our thesis (in a few steps):

Page 68: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

1) Reinforcement learning/or prestige biased imitation causes behaviors that do well to grow in frequency…

Page 69: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

T=0 T=1

More successful behaviors imitated more

Prestige Biased

Imitation

Page 70: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

T=0 T=1

Reinforcement Learning

More successful behaviors held more tenaciously

Page 71: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

2) If one behavior is ALWAYS best…this will eventually lead to that behavior dominating…

Page 72: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

T=0 T=1 T=2 T=3

Page 73: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

3) If however, the behavior is a strategy in a game…strategies still become more frequent if they fair well…

But whether they do well could depend on what other’s are doing…so things can be a bit more complicated…nevertheless…

The dynamics often (Not always! Must Check!) settle on a NE

Page 74: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

T=0 T=1 T=2 T=3

L

L

L

L L

L

L

L

R

RR

RR

R R

L

L

L

L L

L

L

L

R

RL

R R

LL

L

L

Page 75: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

4) Suppose now that instead of choosing actions in a game…people merely act in accordance with their ideologies or preferences…

But ideologies and preferences ALSO can be (at least partially!) imitated or learned…

Page 76: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

E.g.

PL is preferences that causes action L to be taken…

Page 77: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

T=0 T=1

PL

PL

PL

PL PL

PL

PL

PL

PR

PRPR

PRPR

PR PR

PL

Feelings/beliefs that do better become more frequent

Page 78: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Then behavior will end up “at a NE”

Page 79: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

T=0 T=1 T=2 T=3

PL

PL

PL

PL PL

PL

PL

PL

PR

PRPR

PRPR

PR PR

PL

PL

PL

PL PL

PL

PL

PL

PL

PRPL

PR PR

PLPL

PL

PL

Page 80: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Then behavior will end up “at a NE”…

Notice:

-At NE with respect to the original payoffs, not the learned preferences!)-IF dynamicsnash!)-no need to be aware of “why” we have these preferences/ideologies(philosophers can spin their wheels on how these ideologies are “right”)-IF dynamicsnash under weak selection/high mutation, then don’t even need to believe preferences/ideologies are THAT responsive to payoffs…just a little bit…

And preferences/ideologies will have all sorts of (predictable) quirks that Nash has…-e.g. might like wasteful displays, if preferred partners can display at lower cost…-e.g. might desire to cooperate but not care about effectiveness...

Page 81: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

OK…

What can this approach teach us?

What work needs to be done?

Page 82: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Some game theory modeling, demonstrating the quirky preferences/ideologies consistent with NE

Some evolutionary dynamics, demonstrating the NE emerges from dynamic processes.

Some experiments, testing the predictions of the models.

Page 83: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We will present examples of each:

1) Evolutionary dynamics costly signals (Which can explain why we evolved/learned to like authentic art…or why Indians like long nails)

2) Game Theory Model + Evolutionary Dynamics of “cooperate without looking”

(which can explain why we like those who are principled. And also why love blinds us…and why we find markets for kidneys gross…And also leads to valuable prescriptions!)

3) Experiment demonstrating that people give more efficiently when efficiency “commonly known”

(which is consistent with the ED+GT model of why we give inefficiently…and also leads to valuable prescription!)

Page 84: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Project 1: Experiment on (In)efficient Giving

-(preliminary) experiment demonstrating that people give more efficiently when efficiency “commonly known” -(brief) discussion of ED+GT model

Page 85: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Here’s the idea …

If preferences/ideologies that motivate us to give evolved/learned because of “reciprocity” or “partner choice”…

Then private information about effectiveness cannot matter

Why? Because others don’t know that information so can’t reciprocate, punish, match etc. based on it

Page 86: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Ran a simple MTurk experiment showing that people give more effectively not only when they know efficiency, but when efficiency is commonly known

Page 87: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Design:

Ask participants to distribute donations across a list of similar charities (in one of four categories)

Subjects were told their contributions would be observed by a third party

Page 88: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We obtained ratings for charities by scraping

www.charitynavigator.org

Page 89: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 90: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Three treatments:

No Ratings: subjects provided no information about charity effectiveness

Private Ratings: subjects given ratings by an external rating source, but told 3rd party would not be given ratings

Public Ratings: subjects given ratings and told 3rd party would also be given ratings

Page 91: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Private Information – Condition

Page 92: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Public Information – Condition

Page 93: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 94: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 95: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 96: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Note: can explain why we are not impacted by-matching -or scope-and give to inefficient charities like habitat for humanity…

EVEN IF we knew (in)efficiency, since efficiency not commonly known!

Page 97: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Note: NOT just useless theorizing…leads to valuable prescription:

To “nudge” the most impact out of existing prosocial motives, need to make information about effectiveness not just known but ALSO commonly known.

Page 98: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Project 2: Evolutionary Dynamics of Costly Signals

Page 99: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Recall…

Page 100: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

First let’s argue that long fingernails yield behavior consistent with Nash in a costly signaling model

(and also ideal weight, skin tans, and authentic art)

Page 101: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Recall Zahavi’s explanation for the peacock tail

Tail is costly for all, more costly for unfit males. So is NE where females more likely to mateWith males with long tails, and only fit males find it worth the extra mating to grow long tail

Page 102: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Similarly for long nails…

Long nails costly for all (tail hinders flight)

More costly for farmers than teachers (more hindrance for unfit males)

Females prefer mating with teachers (peahens prefer fit males)

Page 103: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

This, we will argue is WHY Khasi females find long nails beautiful

(we will later discuss how the same model can explain our other puzzles about beauty)

Page 104: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

However, for this explanation to work, we need to be confident this Nash emerges in a dynamic model.

(No one chooses what to find beautiful, they simply “learn,” via RL or PBI)

Page 105: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We -created stylized costly signaling model, in which there are costly signaling equilibria (“separating equilibria” … as well as other less interesting equilibria)-We investigate various dynamics and find conditions under which separating equilibrium emerges.

Page 106: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Here is the stylized model…

Page 107: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

1

High

Low

P

1

S0

S1

S2

S3

2

Accept

Reject

Page 108: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

1

High

Low

P

Page 109: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

1

High

Low

P

1

2

Page 110: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

1

High

Low

P

1

S0

S1

S2

S3

1

2

Sn< Sn+1

Sn<<< Sn+1 if low

Page 111: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

1

High

Low

P

1

S0

S1

S2

S3

2

1

2

Sn< Sn+1

Sn<<< Sn+1 if low

Page 112: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

1

2 2

1

High

Low

P

1

S0

S1

S2

S3

2

Accept

Reject

Sn< Sn+1

Sn<<< Sn+1 if low

Page 113: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

1

2 2

1

High

Low

P

1

S0

S1

S2

S3

2

Accept

Reject

Sn< Sn+1

Sn<<< Sn+1 if low

e.g. 0,3,6,9 and 0,1,2,3e.g. 5,5,-5

e.g. P=1/3

Page 114: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Examples of Strategy Profiles and Payoffs

<s0, s1, {s2, s3}>(0,-1,0)

<s3, s1, {s3}>(-1,-1,-10/3)

Page 115: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Nash Equilibrium = < , , > s.t. none benefit by unilaterally deviating

<s0, s2, {s2, s3}><s0, s3, {s3}><s0, s0, {}><s0, s1, {s1, s2 , s3}>

Page 116: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We will investigate the dynamics

E.g. Moran

Page 117: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

s2

s2

s3

s0

s3

High 1’s

s0

s1

s1s1

s0

s1

s0

Low 1’s

{s2,s3}

{s2,s3}

2’s

{s2,s3}

{s2,s3}

e.g.NL=100 NH=100 N2=150

{s2,s3}

{s2,s3}

{s2,s3}

Page 118: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

s0

s1

s1s1

s0

s1

s0

Low 1’s

-3-3

-3 -3

0

0

0

Page 119: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

s0

s1

s1s1

s0

s1

s0

1-w+w(payoffs) e.g. w=.1

.6.6

.6 .6

.9

.9

.9

Page 120: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

s0

s1

s1s1

s1

s1

s0

.

Page 121: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

s0

s1

s1s1

s3

s1

s0

.

With probably μ choose random strategy

Page 122: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

<s0, s2, {s2, s3}>

Page 123: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

<s0, s0, {}>

Page 124: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

<s0, s3, {s3}>

Page 125: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

mu w

Page 126: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Efficient separating!

Page 127: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

And if we aggregate across time, and many simulation runs?

Page 128: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

X

XX

Page 129: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 130: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Why is this equilibrium emerging? Because it is hard to get out of, compared to the other equilibrium.

Page 131: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

As soon as receiver drifts to accepting 2 or 3 Enough receivers must have “neutrally drifted” to accept 1 so worth for good but not bad types

Since good but not bad sending 1, receivers start accepting 1, to point where bad start sending

Very quicklyAfter bad start Sending 1, receivers stop Accepting 1

If in meantimeReceivers stopAccepting 2(by drift), thenBoth good and Bad better Sending 0

As soon as receiver drifts to accepting 1 or 2

Page 132: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 133: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Is this result robust?

Page 134: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

1) payoffs 2) noise3) experimentation rate4) reinforcement learning

Page 135: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Reinforcement Learning

Page 136: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Even works for super high experimentation rates!

Page 137: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Does depend on interesting new condition:

Do females prefer to pair with random male?

P=1/2<s0, s0, {}><s0, s0, {s0}><s0, s2, {s2, s3}><s0, s3, {s3}>No longer easy to leave pooling!

Page 138: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 139: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

How can we interpret this condition?

What if there aren’t that many farmers…e.g. in the U.S.?

won’t be attracted to long finger nails!

Page 140: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Similarly if, signals not costly (art that is replica?)

Or if more costly for high type (sun exposure in U.S. today vs past vs China?)

Page 141: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology
Page 142: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Conclusion:

Even though don’t “choose what’s beautiful”

Some aspects can still be explained by costly signaling…

Provided (ever so slightly) more likely to imitate successful people’s notion of beauty, or (even if just a tiny bit ) more likely to adhere to notions of beauty when lead to nice outcomes…

Page 143: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

But for this conclusion…

We needed to show how evolutionary dynamics work in costly signaling games

Page 144: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Project 3: Game Theory model + Evo Dynamics of “Cooperating without Looking”

(recall: principled vs. strategic)

Page 145: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Suppose a friend asks you to proofread a paper…

You hesitate while thinking about how big a pain it is and say, “Hmm. Um. Well, OK.”

You get less credit than if you agreed w/o hesitation

Page 146: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Colleague asks you to attend his talk.

You ask, “will this benefit my research?” before agreeing to attend.

You get less credit than if you agreed without asking

Page 147: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Why do you get less credit for cooperating when you deliberate (“look”)?

Page 148: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Note: cannot be explained by existing models of repeated games, like repeated prisoner’s dilemma

(In such models, players can only attend to your past actions not “deliberation” process)

Page 149: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Intuitively…

Cooperators who don’t look (cwol) can be trusted to cooperate even when the temptation to defect is high

But how do we know this added trust is worth the cost of losing out on missed opportunities to defect?

Page 150: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We will…1) Describe a simple model, “the envelope game”

2) Find (natural, intuitive) conditions under which CWOL is an equilibrium of this game

3) Show that even if agents are not consciously choosing their strategies but instead strategies are learned or evolved (replicator dynamic), cwol still emerges (i.e. has a sizeable basin of attraction)

4) Interpret these results in terms of some less straightforward social applications, such as why we:

1) like politicians who appear principled2) shun taboo tradeoffs3) are blinded by love

For which… Our equilibrium condition will yield novel predictionsThis analysis will also lead to some useful prescriptions

Page 151: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Here is our model…

Page 152: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

“The Envelope Game”

Page 153: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

First…

We model variation in costs of cooperation as follows:

• With probability p, Low Temptation “card” is chosen and stuffed in envelope

• With probability 1-p, High Temptation is chosen

Page 154: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Second…

• We model player 1’s choice of whether to “look”

• 1 chooses whether or not to open the envelope

Crucially we assume others (player 2) can observe whether the envelope was opened

2

Page 155: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

2 Third…

1 then chooses whether or not toCooperate

2 is again able to observe

Page 156: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Fourth…

We model others’ “trust” in Player 1

Player 2 chooses whether to continue the interaction or exit

(If he continues, the game repeats, with future payoffs discounted by w)

Page 157: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We assume the payoffs have the following properties:

1) Cooperation is costly for Player 1, especially when the temptation is high

2) Both players like cooperative interactions, but Player 2 would prefer no interaction to one in which Player 1 sometimes defects

Page 158: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

a, b a, b

cH, d cL, d

C

D

High Temptation Low Temptation

We represent this using the following variables:

Page 159: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

a, b a, bcH, d cL, d

CD

High Temptation Low Temptation

Our assumptions then amount to: 1) cH >cL > a> 0

2) b*p + d*(1–p) < 0 < b

Page 160: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Result 1:

1 cooperates without looking (CWOL)2 continues iff 1 CWOL

is an equilibrium, provided: a/(1-w) > cLp + cH(1-p)

Page 161: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Intuition:

If 1 deviates to look, might as well defect, in which case expect c1p + c2(1-p) today and 0 ever after

If CWOL, get a today and henceforth, i.e. a/(1-w)

CWOL is an equilibrium iff a/(1-w) > cLp + cH(1-p)

Interpretation:

CWOL is an equilibrium iff EXPECTED gains from defecting today are less than the value of maintaining a cooperative interaction

Page 162: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Let’s contrast this with equilibrium conditions for “cooperate with looking” (CWL) to see when looking matters

Now player 1 may be tempted to deviate when she knows the temptation is high, in which case she would get cH

So we need a/(1-w) > cH

I.e. CWL is an equilibrium iff MAXIMAL gains from defecting today are less than the value of maintaining a cooperative interaction

Hence we predict “Looking” will matter when the expected gains from defecting are small but the maximal gains are large

Page 163: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Likewise, if we relax our assumption thatb*p+d*(1–p)<0<b, (but retain d<0<b)

We get another equilibrium where player 1 looks and defects when the temptation is high and player 2 exits iff 1 defects and the temptation is low

For looking to matter we ALSO need that defection is sufficiently bad for 2 that he doesn’t want to interact with 1s who even seldomly defect

Page 164: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

What if strategies are not consciously calculated?

For instance, we might trust people based on a “gut feeling” or we might refuse to interact with people who disobey our ethics. Or we might just have a heuristic that tells us not to look

That’s where the main thesis of last class fits in!

We assume that feelings, ethics, heuristics that yield higher payoffs are more likely to be imitated (prestige biased imitation), reproduce (natural selection), or held tenaciously (reinforcement learning)

We will model this using the replicator dynamic, and show CWOL also emerges in the relevant parameter region

Page 165: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

In the replicator dynamic…-an infinite population of each Player 1’s and player 2’s-at any point in time, each strategy has a certain frequency -payoffs are determined based on the expected opponent’s play, given this frequency-strategies reproduce proportional to their payoffs

Page 166: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Note: -Replicator requires few strategies, so we restrict to 7 that include all “important deviants”-Replicator cannot be solved analytically; we numerically estimate in computer simulation-We will need to classify strategies into those that are behaviorally equivalent

Page 167: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Restricted Strategy Space

Page 168: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Classifying Populations

Page 169: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Simulation

For each of many parameter values…

For each of 5,000 trials…

We seed the population with random mixtures of strategies

Numerically estimate the replicator dynamic (which is an ODE)

Wait for the population to stabilize

Then classify the outcomes (ignoring small errors)

Page 170: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We find…

Population ends up at CWOL fairly often in relevant parameter region

Page 171: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

a*=cH/cLp + cH(1-p),)a**=cH/(1-w)

Page 172: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Now let’s discuss some social applications…

Page 173: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

First application: Why do we like politicians who have “principles” and not those who are “strategic” (e.g. those who “flip flop”)?

(and more generally, why do we like those who are principled? And when will we care?)

Page 174: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We argue…

Someone who is “strategic” is likely to choose the policy that benefits himself when given the power

When will we care if others are strategic? Not if incentives sufficiently aligned that won’t ever be in a position where tempted to drastically harm us(i.e. b*p+d*(1–p)<0<b)

E.g., crucial that girlfriend/boyfriend is principled, but not so crucial that doubles partner is, because she has no occasions where tempted to really harm you

Page 175: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Second application: Taboo tradeoffs

I.e. unwillingness to tradeoff sacred (e.g. life), against mundane (e.g. money)

E.g. many find economists perverse for applying cost benefit to value of life

Taboo to CONSIDER tradeoff

Page 176: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We find such tradeoffs disgusting because…

Such tradeoffs signal a willingness to look at the benefits of defectingdisgust signals we wouldn’t look, or wouldn’t interact with looker

When will we find such tradeoffs disgusting?

Usually not worth transgressing, but sometimes very beneficial i.e. cH>a/(1-w) > cLp + cH(1-p)

(And those transgressions harmful)

Page 177: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

This has an important policy implication:

While politicians might want to signal that they would never trade lives for money

The gains from appearing trustworthy accrue to the politicians while costs accrue to us

We should force policymakers and lawyers to tackle these admittedly hard-to-fathom tradeoffs

Page 178: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Third application: love

Love has the property that it “blinds us” to the costs and benefits of doing good to our partner (e.g., don’t cheat regardless of opportunity)

Page 179: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Why does love have this property?

Because those in love can be trusted, so will make better long-term partners

Page 180: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Gives three new predictions about love

Page 181: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

First…

Falling in or out of love depends on the distribution of temptations, but not their immediate realizations

That is, people may fall out of love when there is a permanent change in opportunities, but not an immediate temptation

Page 182: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Second…

Love comes with a cost–the cost of ignored temptations–and suggests that this cost must be compensated with commensurate investment in the relationship

Only sometimes is it worthwhile for the recipient of love to compensate a suitor for such missed opportunities, o/w will prefer suitor not fall in love

Page 183: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Third…

Just looking at the costs or benefits can hasten the demise of a relationship, even if don’t defect

Perhaps why partner may get upset if sees you “looking” even if never act on temptation

Or why get upset when partners suggest a pre-nup

Page 184: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

General conclusion:

Page 185: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

In our research…

We try to understand from where such preferences and ideologies come from.

Using evolutionary dynamics + game theory + experiments

Page 186: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

Some game theory modeling, demonstrating the quirky preferences/ideologies consistent with NE

Some evolutionary dynamics, demonstrating the NE emerges from dynamic processes.

Some experiments, testing the predictions of the models.

Page 187: Evolutionary Dynamics, Game Theory, and Psychology

We will present examples of each:

1) Evolutionary dynamics costly signals (Which can explain why we evolved/learned to like authentic art…or why Indians like long nails)

2) Game Theory Model + Evolutionary Dynamics of “cooperate without looking”

(which can explain why we like those who are principled. And also why love blinds us…and why we find markets for kidneys gross…And also leads to valuable prescriptions!)

3) Experiment demonstrating that people give more efficiently when efficiency “commonly known”

(which is consistent with the ED+GT model of why we give inefficiently…and also leads to valuable prescription!)