econ 522 economics of law dan quint spring 2014 lecture 20

54
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

Upload: lewis-woods

Post on 12-Jan-2016

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

Econ 522Economics of Law

Dan Quint

Spring 2014

Lecture 20

Page 2: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

2

Second midterm is next Wednesday (4/16) Exam is cumulative – includes property law, contract law, and the

beginning of tort law (Includes what we’ve done so far – the “basic” tort setup and

results – but not the extensions we’ll cover this week)

No lecture next Monday, no office hours next Tuesday

HW4 online – not due until April 31

Logistics

Page 3: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

3

Relaxing the assumptionsof our model

Page 4: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

4

So far, our model has assumed:

People are rational

Injurers pay damages in full They don’t run out of money and go bankrupt

There are no regulations in place other than the liability rule

There is no insurance

Litigation is costless

We can think about what would happen when each of these assumptions is violated

Our model thus far has assumed…

Page 5: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

5

Behavioral economics: people systematically misjudge value of probabilistic events

Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky, “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk” 45% chance of $6,000 versus 90% chance of $3,000 Most people (86%) chose the second 0.1% chance of $6,000 versus 0.2% chance of $3,000 Most people (73%) chose the first But under expected utility, either u(6000) > 2 u(3000), or it’s not So people don’t actually seem to be maximizing expected utility And the “errors” have to do with how people evaluate probabilities

Assumption 1: Rationality

Page 6: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

6

People seem to overestimate chance of unlikely events with well-publicized, catastrophic events

Freakonomics: people fixate on exotic, unlikely risks, rather than more commonplace ones that are more dangerous

Assumption 1: Rationality

Page 7: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

7

People seem to overestimate chance of unlikely events with well-publicized, catastrophic events

Freakonomics: people fixate on exotic, unlikely risks, rather than more commonplace ones that are more dangerous

How to apply this: accidents with power tools Could be designed safer, could be used more cautiously Suppose consumers underestimate risk of an accident Negligence with defense of contributory negligence: would lead to tools which

are very safe when used correctly But would lead to too many accidents when consumers are irrational Strict liability would lead to products which were less likely to cause accidents

even when used recklessly

Assumption 1: Rationality

Page 8: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

8

Another type of irrationality: unintended lapses

“Many accidents result from tangled feet, quavering hands, distracted eyes, slips of the tongue, wandering minds, weak wills, emotional outbursts, misjudged distances, or miscalculated consequences”

Assumption 1: Rationality

Page 9: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

9

Strict liability: injurer internalizes expected harm done, leading to efficient precaution

But what if… Harm done is $1,000,000 Injurer only has $100,000 So injurer can only pay $100,000 But if he anticipates this, he knows D << A… …so he doesn’t internalize full cost of harm… …so he takes inefficiently little precaution

Injurer whose liability is limited by bankruptcy is called judgment-proof

Assumption 2: Injurers pay damages in full

Page 10: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

10

Owner of an oil tanker Any accident would be an environmental catastrophe, doing

$50,000,000 of harm Upgraded navigation system would cost $225,000, and reduce

likelihood of an accident from 1/100 to 1/500 Precaution reduces expected harm from $500,000 to $100,000, costs

$225,000, so efficient to take precaution If company would be forced to pay $50,000,000 after an accident, then

under strict liability, would choose to buy new nav system

Suppose the business is only worth $5,000,000 If there’s an accident, pay the $5,000,000 and go out of business Now nav system reduces expected damages from $50,000 to $10,000 – not

worth the cost So judgment-proof business would take too little precaution

Example of judgment-proofness(from old final exam)

Page 11: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

11

What stops me from speeding? If I cause an accident, I’ll have to pay for it Even if I don’t cause an accident, I might get a speeding ticket

Similarly, fire regulations might require a store to have a working fire extinguisher

Regulations supply additional incentive to take precaution

Assumption 3: No regulation

Page 12: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

12

We saw, if business is only worth $5,000,000, liability does not create enough incentive to upgrade nav system

Now suppose government passes regulation requiring modern navigation systems on all oil tankers If business doesn’t upgrade, 1 in 5 chance of being caught by safety

inspector and having to pay a $1,000,000 fine

Now, combining liability with regulation… Upgrade: cost of new nav system is $225,000, expected damages

are $10,000 private cost is $235,000 Don’t upgrade: expected damages are $50,000, expected

government fine is $200,000 private cost is $250,000 Liability + regulation gives enough incentive to take precaution, even

though either one alone would not be enough

Continuing the example of judgment-proofness from before…

Page 13: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

13

When liability > injurer’s wealth, liability does not create enough incentive for efficient precaution

Regulations which require efficient precaution solve the problem

Regulations also work better than liability when accidents impose small harm on large group of people

Assumption 3: No regulation

Page 14: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

14

We assumed injurer or victim actually bears cost of accident

When injurer or victim has insurance, they no longer have incentive to take precaution

But, insurance tends not to be complete

Assumption 4: No insurance

Page 15: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

15

Insurance reduces incentive to take precaution Moral hazard

Insurance companies have ways to reduce moral hazard Deductibles, copayments Increasing premiums after accidents Insurers may impose safety standards that policyholders must meet

Assumption 4: No insurance

Page 16: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

16

If litigation is costly, this affects incentives in both directions

If lawsuits are costly for victims, they may bring fewer suits

Some accidents “unpunished” less incentive for precaution

But if being sued is costly for injurers, they internalize more than the cost of the accident

So more incentive for precaution

Assumption 5: Litigation costs nothing

Page 17: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

17

I hit you with my car and did $10,000 worth of damage We both know I was negligent But courts aren’t perfect If we go to trial, 80% chance I’ll be found liable, 20% I won’t If I’m held liable, damages are correctly set at $10,000 So on average, if we go to trial, you expect to recover $8,000

But if we go to trial, we both have to hire lawyers Suppose this costs us each $3,000 Now your expected gain from going to trial is $8,000 – 3,000 = 5,000 And my expected cost is $8,000 + 3,000 = 11,000

An example from Polinsky, “An Introduction to Law and Economics”

Page 18: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

18

Under strict liability… We said injurers internalize cost of accidents efficient precaution But this assumes cost of being sued = damage done If courts are unpredictable and litigation is costly, private cost of being

sued for damages could be > or < cost of accident Which could lead to too much or too little precaution

But also… If we can’t settle out of court and cases go to trial… …then social cost of an accident includes both the harm done,

and the resources expended during the trial! If trial costs $6,000, then social cost of the accident isn’t $10,000, but

$16,000 – which increases the efficient level of precaution

Why does costly litigation matter?

Page 19: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

19

Nuisance suit – lawsuit with no legal merit, purely meant to extract an out-of-court settlement Suppose trial costs $10,000 for plaintiff but $50,000 for defendant If case goes to trial, plaintiff will get nothing Threat points are -10,000 and -50,000 Gains from cooperation if settlement reached are 60,000 If gains are split evenly, defendant pays settlement of $20,000,

even though case had no merit

With costly litigation comes possibility of “nuisance suit”

Page 20: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

20

In U.K., loser in a lawsuit often pays legal expenses of winner Discourages nuisance suits But also discourages suits where there was actual harm that may

be hard to prove

In U.S., each side generally pays own legal costs But some states have rules that change this under certain

circumstances

Who pays the costs of a trial?

Page 21: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

21

Rule 68 of Federal Rules of Civil Procedure“At any time more than 10 days before the trial begins, a party defending against a claim may serve upon the adverse party an offer [for a settlement]…

If the judgment finally obtained by the offeree is not more favorable than the offer, the offeree must pay the costs incurred after the making of the offer.”

“Fee shifting rule” Example

I hit you with my car, you sue Before trial, I offer to settle for $6,000, you refuse If you win at trial, but damages are only $5,000… …then under Rule 68, you would have to pay me for all my legal

expenses after I made the offer

Who pays the costs of a trial?

Page 22: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

22

Rule 68 does two things to encourage settlements: Gives me added incentive to make a serious settlement offer Gives you added incentive to accept my offer

But not actually as generous as it sounds Not all expenses are covered

Asymmetric Plaintiff is penalized for rejecting defendant’s offer Defendant is not penalized for rejecting offer from plaintiff

Who pays the costs of a trial?

Page 23: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

23

At the start of every lawsuit, flip a coin

Heads: lawsuit proceeds, damages are doubled

Tails: lawsuit immediately dismissed

Expected damages are the same same incentives for precaution

But half as many lawsuits to deal with!

A clever (but unrealistic) way to reduce litigation costs

Page 24: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

24

PerfectCompensation

Page 25: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

25

Perfect compensatory damages (D = A) Returns victim to original level of well-being (Works like insurance) And sets correct incentive for injurers

But in some cases, hard to determine level Might be no price at which you’d be willing to give up a leg Certainly no price at which a parent would be indifferent toward

losing a child

Perfect compensation

Page 26: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

26

Recommended jury instructions, Massachusetts: “Recovery for wrongful death represents damages to the survivors for

the loss of value of decedent’s life. There is no special formula under the law to assess the plaintiff’s damages…

It is your obligation to assess what is fair, adequate, and just. You must use your wisdom and judgment and your sense of basic

justice to translate into dollars and cents the amount which will fully, fairly, and reasonably compensate the next of kin for the death of the decedent.

You must be guided by your common sense and your conscience on the evidence of the case…”

And from California: “…You should award reasonable compensation for the loss of love,

companionship, comfort, affection, society, solace or moral support.”

Perfect compensation

Page 27: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

27

Most people would rather be horribly injured than killed

Which means killing someone does more damage than injuring someone

But compensatory damages tend to be lower for a fatal accident than an accident which crippled someone When someone is badly injured, may require huge amount of

money to compensate them In wrongful-death case, damages compensate victim’s loved ones,

but no attempt to compensate victim So these damages tend to be smaller

One other odd feature of compensatory damages…

Page 28: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

28

What’s a lifeworth?

Page 29: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

29

Assessing damages in a wrongful death lawsuit requires some notion of what a life is worth

Safety regulators also need some notion of what a life is worth Kip Viscusi, The Value of Risks to Life and Health

Regulators need to decide “where to draw the line”

What’s a life worth?

$72,000,000,000Proposed OSHA formaldehyde standard

$ 104,200,000EPA asbestos regulations

$ 89,300,000OSHA asbestos regulations

$ 1,300,000Car side door protection standards

$ 200,000Airplane cabin fire protection

Estimated cost per life savedRegulation

Page 30: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

30

Let w be starting wealth, p probability of death There might be some amount of money M such that

Breaks down when p = 1 not because can’t equate death with compensation, but because second term vanishes

If we can find M, we can “solve for” u(death)! Ask a bunch of people how much money they would need to take a

1/1000 chance of death? Do a lab experiment where you expose people to a risk of death? Better idea: impute how much compensation people require from the

real-life choices they make

Kip Viscusi, The Value of Risks to Life and Health

p u(death) + (1 – p) u(w+M) = u(w)

Page 31: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

31

Lots of day-to-day choices increase or decrease our risk of death Choose between Volvo and sports car with fiberglass body Take a job washing skyscraper windows, or office job that pays less Buy smoke detectors and fire extinguishers, or don’t

“Hand Rule Damages” Hand Rule: precaution is cost-justified if

cost of precaution < reduction in accidents X cost of accident Suppose side-curtain airbags reduce risk of fatal accident by 1/1000 If someone pays $1,000 extra for a car with side-curtain airbags, it must

mean that

$1,000 < 1/1000 * value of their life or, implicitly, they value their life more than $1,000,000

Kip Viscusi, The Value of Risks to Life and Health

Page 32: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

32

Viscusi surveys lots of existing studies which impute value of life from peoples’ decisions

Many use wage differentials How much higher are wages for risky jobs compared to safe jobs?

Others look at… Decisions to speed, wear seatbelts, buy smoke detectors, smoke

cigarettes Decision to live in very polluted areas (comparing property values) Prices of newer, safer cars versus older, more dangerous ones

Some used surveys to ask how people would make tradeoffs between money and safety

Each paper reaches some estimate for implicit value people attach to their lives

Kip Viscusi, The Value of Risks to Life and Health

Page 33: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

33

What does Viscusi find?

Page 34: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

34

What does Viscusi find?24 studies based on wage differentials

0

5,000,000

10,000,000

15,000,000

20,000,000

Kniesn

er &

Lee

th (1

991)

Smith

& G

ilber

t (19

84)

Thaler

& R

osen

(197

6)

Arnou

ld & N

ichols

(198

3)

Dilling

ham

(198

5)

Butler

(198

3)

Brown

(198

0)

Gegax

et.

al. (1

991)

Moo

re &

Visc

usi (

1988

)

Mar

in & P

sach

arsp

oulos

(198

2)

Kniesn

er &

Lee

th (1

991)

Cousin

eau

et a

l (19

88)

Dilling

ham

(198

5)

Viscus

i (19

78, 1

979)

Smith

(197

6)

Olson

(198

1)

Viscus

i (19

81)

Smith

(197

4)

Moo

re &

Visc

usi (

1988

)

Moo

re &

Visc

usi (

1988

)

Kniesn

er &

Lee

th (1

991)

Viscus

i & M

oore

(198

9

Herzo

g & S

chlot

tman

(198

7)

Leigh

& F

olso

m (1

984)

Leigh

& F

olso

m (1

984)

Leigh

(198

7)

Garen

(198

8)

Moo

re &

Visc

usi (

1990

)

Moo

re &

Visc

usi (

1990

)

Implicitvalueof life

Page 35: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

35

What does Viscusi find?7 studies using other risk-money tradeoffs

4.0Prices of new automobilesAutomobile accident risks, 1986

2.0Purchase price of smoke detector

Fire fatality risks without smoke detectors, 1968-1985

0.7Estimated monetary equivalent of effect of risk info

Cigarette smoking risks, 1980

0.8Property values in Allegheny Co., PA

Mortality effects of air pollution, 1978

0.6Purchase price of smoke detectors

Fire fatality risks without smoke detectors, 1974-1979

1.2Estimated disutility of seat belts

Automobile death risks, 1972

0.07Value of driver time based on wage rates

Highway speed-related accident risk, 1973

Implicit Value of life($ millions)

Component of theMonetary Tradeoff

Nature of Risk,Year

Page 36: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

36

What does Viscusi find?6 studies based on surveys

1.2Series of contingent valuation questions, New Zealand survey, 1989-1990

Traffic safety

2.7 (median)9.7 (mean)

Interactive computer program with pairwise auto risk-living cost tradeoffs until indifference achieved, 1987

Automobile accident risks

3.8Willingness to pay for risk reduction, U.K. survey, 1982

Motor vehicle accidents

3.4 (pay),8.8 (accept)

Willingness to pay, willingness to accept change in job risk in mail survey, 1984

Job fatality risk

15.6Mail survey willingness to accept increased risk, small (30) U.K. sample, 1975

Airline safety and locational life expectancy risks

0.1Willingness to pay question, door-to-door small (36) Boston sample

Improved ambulance service, post-heart attack lives

Implicit Value of Life ($ millions)

SurveyMethodology

Nature ofRisk

Page 37: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

37

Wide range of results Most suggest value of life between $1,000,000 and $10,000,000 Many clustered between $3,000,000 and $7,000,000

Even with wide range, he argues this is very useful: “In practice, value-of-life debates seldom focus on whether the

appropriate value of life should be $3 or $4 million… However, the estimates do provide guidance as to whether risk reduction

efforts that cost $50,000 per life saved or $50 million per life saved are warranted.”

“The threshold for the Office of Management and Budget to be successful in rejecting proposed risk regulations has been in excess of $100 million.”

C&U: NHTSA uses $2.5 million for value of traffic fatality Current: EPA $9.1 MM, FDA $7.9 MM, Transpo Dept $6 MM

What does Viscusi find?

Page 38: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

38

More twistson liability

Page 39: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

39

Vicarious liability is when one person is held liablefor harm caused by another Parents may be liable for harm caused by their child Employer may be liable for harm caused by employee

Respondeat superior – “let the master answer”

Employer is liable for torts of employee if employee was acting within the scope of his employment

Vicarious Liability

Page 40: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

40

Gives employers incentive to... be more careful who they hire be more careful what they assign employees to do supervise employees more carefully

Employers may be better able to make these decisions than employees…

…and employees may be judgment-proof

Vicarious Liability

Page 41: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

41

Vicarious liability can be implemented through… Strict liability rule: employer liable for any harm caused by

employee (as long as employee was acting within scope of employment)

Negligence rule: employer is only liable if he was negligent in supervising employee

Which is better? It depends. If proving negligent supervision is too hard, strict vicarious liability

might work better But an example favoring negligent vicarious liability…

Vicarious Liability

Page 42: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

42

Suppose you were harmed by accident caused by two injurers

Joint liability: you can sue them both together

Several liability: you can sue each one separately Several liability with contribution: each is only liable for his share of

damage

Joint and several liability: you can sue either one for the full amount of the harm Joint and several liability with contribution: the one you sued could

then sue his friend to get back half his money

Joint and Several Liability

Page 43: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

43

Joint and several liability holds under common law when… Defendants acted together to cause the harm, or… Harm was indivisible (impossible to tell who was at fault)

Good for the victim, because… No need to prove exactly who caused harm Greater chance of collecting full level of

damages Instead of suing person most responsible,

could sue person most likely to be able to pay

Joint and Several Liability

Page 44: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

4444

Punitivedamages

Page 45: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

4545

Damage awards vary greatly across countries, even across individual cases

We saw last week: As long as damages are correct on average, random inconsistency

doesn’t affect incentives (under either strict liability or negligence)

But, if appropriate level of damages isn’t well-established, more incentive to spend more fighting

Inconsistency of damages

Page 46: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

4646

Example: each side can hire cheap lawyer or expensive lawyer

Cheap lawyer costs $10, expensive lawyer costs $45 If two lawyers are equally good, expected judgment is $100 If one is better, expected judgment is doubled or halved

One problem with inconsistent damages: more incentive to fight hard

90, -110 40, -95

155, -210 55, -145

Cheap Expensive

Cheap Lawyer

Expensive Lawyer

Defendant

Pla

intif

f

Page 47: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

4747

What we’ve discussed so far: compensatory damages Meant to “make victim whole”/compensate for actual damage done

In addition, courts sometimes award punitive damages Additional damages meant to punish injurer Create stronger incentive to avoid initial harm

Punitive damages generally not awarded for innocent mistakes, but may be used when injurer’s behavior was

“malicious, oppressive, gross, willful and wanton, or fraudulent”

Punitive damages

Page 48: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

4848

Calculation of punitive damages even less well-defined than compensatory damages

Level of punitive damages supposed to bear “reasonable relationship” to level of compensatory damages Not clear exactly what this means U.S. Supreme Court: punitive damages more than ten times

compensatory damages will attract “close scrutiny,” but not explicitly ruled out

Punitive damages

Page 49: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

4949

Stella Liebeck was badly burned when she spilled a cup of McDonalds coffee in her lap

Awarded $160,000 in compensatory damages, plus $2.9 million in punitive damages

Case became “poster child” for excessive damages, but…

Example of punitive damages: Liebeck v McDonalds (1994) (“the coffee cup case”)

Page 50: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

5050

Stella Liebeck dumped coffee in her lap while adding cream/sugar Third degree burns, 8 days in hospital, skin grafts, 2 years treatment Initially sued for $20,000, mostly for medical costs McDonalds offered to settle for $800

McDonalds serves coffee at 180-190 degrees At 180 degrees, coffee can cause a third-degree burn requiring skin grafts

in 12-15 seconds Lower temperature would increase length of exposure necessary McDonalds had received 700 prior complaints of burns, and had settled

with some of the victims Quality control manager testified that 700 complaints, given how many cups

of coffee McDonalds serves, was not sufficient for McDonalds to reexamine practices

Liebeck v McDonalds (1994)

Page 51: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

5151

Rule in place was comparative negligence Jury found both parties negligent, McDonalds 80% responsible Calculated compensatory damages of $200,000 times 80% gives $160,000 Added $2.9 million in punitive damages Judge reduced punitive damages to 3X compensatory, making total

damages $640,000 During appeal, parties settled out of court for some smaller amount

Jury seemed to be using punitive damages to punish McDonalds for being arrogant and uncaring

Liebeck v McDonalds (1994)

Page 52: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

5252

We’ve said all along: with perfect compensation, incentives for injurer are set correctly. So why punitive damages?

Example… Suppose manufacturer can eliminate 10 accidents a year, each causing

$1,000 in damages, for $9,000 Clearly efficient If every accident victim would sue and win, company has incentive to

take this precaution But if some won’t, then not enough incentive Suppose only half the victims will bring successful lawsuits Compensatory damages would be $5,000; company is better off paying

that then taking efficient precaution One way to fix this: award higher damages in the cases that are brought

What is the economic purpose of punitive damages?

Page 53: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

5353

Punitive damages should be related to compensatory damages, but higher the more likely injurer is to “get away with it” If 50% of accidents will lead to successful lawsuits, total damages

should be 2 X harm Which requires punitive damages = compensatory damages If 10% of accidents lead to awards, damages should be 10 X harm So punitive damages should be 9 X compensatory damages

Seems most appropriate when injurer’s actions were deliberately fraudulent, since may have been based on cost-benefit analysis of chance of being caught

This suggests…

Page 54: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Spring 2014 Lecture 20

5454

“A tort plaintiff succeeded in collecting a large damage judgment.

The defendant’s attorney, confident that the claimed injury was bogus, went over to the plaintiff after the trial

and warned him that if he was ever seen out of his wheelchair he would be back in court on a charge of fraud.

The plaintiff replied that to save the lawyer the cost of having him followed, he would be happy to describe his travel plans.

He reached into his pocket and drew out an airline ticket –

to Lourdes, the site of a Catholic shrine famous for miracles.”

To wrap up tort law, a funny story from Friedman…