earman - carnap, kuhn, and the philosophy of scientific methodology

Upload: picogordo

Post on 03-Jun-2018

223 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    1/29

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    2/29

    Carnap, Kuhn,and thePhilosophyof

    Scientific Methodology

    John

    Earman

    /

    1

    Introduction

    For the past tw o decades logical positivismhas served as a w h i p p i n g

    boy.

    B y

    e m p h a s i z i n g th e shor tcomings

    of

    this

    failed

    philosophical,

    pr og r am, the v i r tues of the new

    postpositiyist

    pTi|osop_hy__of_sciencc

    arc m a d e to seem more lustrous. It is, of course, n ot su r p r i s i ng to

    f ind

    such po lemica ldevices emp loyed , s ince they

    are

    c o m m o n

    to

    th e

    rhetor ic of revo lu t ions ,

    w h e th e r political, scientific,

    or philosophical .

    Or so the s t anda r d assessment wou ld go . W h a t I find askew in this

    assessment is the not ion tha t a philosophical revolution asopposed

    to

    an

    evo lu t i on

    has

    taken place. For a l though

    I am no apologist for

    logical posi t iv ism,

    it

    doessccoiJojme t h a t m a n y

    ofthe t h e m e s f jJ T

    so-called

    postpositivist philosophyofjscicnccarcextensionsof ideas

    f o u n d in the

    wr i t i ngsoLCarnap

    an d

    other leading logical positivists

    an d logicalemplficlstC^But m ypurposehere is not to

    cont r ibute

    to

    a

    revisionist history of philosophy. Rather , I aim to pay homage to

    both Carnap

    an d

    K u h n

    b y

    noting some str iking similar i t ies

    an d

    also

    some s t r ik in g di f ferences . Theses imilarities

    an d

    di f ferences

    are

    use-

    ful

    in helping to focus

    some

    of the

    still

    unresolved issues about the

    n a t u r e of

    scientif ic

    methodology .

    2 Logical Positivism, Logical Empiricism,,and

    Kuhn's

    Structure of Scientific

    Revolutions

    T he member s of

    the

    Vienna Circle often took votes on the issues

    they

    debated.

    W h il e

    I

    have

    n o

    documen ta r y ev idence

    to

    of fer

    of an

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    3/29

    J o h n E a r m a n

    ac lu a l

    vole,

    I am m o r a l l ycertain o f

    what

    the

    rcsull

    wo u ld

    have been

    fo r

    ihc question,

    Ver i f ica t ion

    is a

    relation between what

    an d

    w h a t ?

    In x is verif ied by y, j&fs presumably a sentence. An d it istempting

    to lake^jHo

    be a

    fact,stale

    of

    a f fa i r s ,

    or

    something

    in

    iheworldlhal

    makes A C iruc

    and can be

    d i rec t ly ascertained.

    But an

    attempt

    to

    compare language

    and

    iheworld would have slruck iheCircle mem-

    bers

    as of a

    piece w i th

    the

    metaphysics

    thaiihe ver i f iab i l i ly principle

    of meaning wassupposed lo

    banish.Their a l t e r n a t i ve w as

    lo

    lake y

    lo be another sentence, for then the relationjjctwecn x and yis an

    .

    unproblcmalic

    logical

    r c j a t i o n . _T h . 5

    move, however,

    seems

    lo

    leave

    j

    us in

    ihc

    same

    metaphysical

    th i cke l

    since ver i f ical ion would seem

    to

    /

    require thaiyis a true sentence, and is not a truesentenceone that /

    corresponds to the facls?

    The

    escape lhat some

    ofihe

    circle members

    soughlwas a

    resort to

    a

    coherencetheory

    of

    truth. E v e n t u a ll y ,however, Carnap

    abandoned

    resort,

    presumably

    because

    of a

    combinalion

    of

    the

    drawbacks

    of

    thecoherence account of truthand

    the

    allraclivenessof '

    theory of truth. Bui w h a l I wish to emphasize here are ihe

    qual i f i -

    calions that Carnap put on any

    talk

    about comparing stalemenls

    wi lh

    facls. In

    Truth

    and Confirmation (1949) he

    emphasized

    lhat he

    preferred lospeak of

    confronling

    slatementswilh facts:

    There has

    been

    agood deal of dispute as to whether in ihc procedure

    scientific

    test ing

    slatements must becompared

    with

    facts or as lo whe the r such

    comparisons

    be

    unnecessary ,

    if

    nol impossible. If "comparison of s lalerncnl

    wilh

    fact"

    m e a n s

    ihc

    p rocedure

    which

    we

    called

    ihc

    firsl

    opcralio^rylhcn

    it

    mus

    be

    adin i l lcd

    lhal ihis

    procedure

    is nol

    on ly

    possible,

    b ul

    even indis-

    pensable

    for

    scientific

    testing. Y el

    ilm u s

    be remarked

    lhal

    ih c

    fo rmula t ion

    "comparison

    of

    s t a temen t

    an d

    fact"

    is nol

    unobjeclionable . First,

    ihe

    conccpl

    "comparison" is not qu i l c appropr ia te here. T wo objecls can be compared

    in regard lo a proper ly

    which m

    ir r j jarnr l n r j ~ r them in varia

    We

    ihcrefore

    prefer lo speak of "cwnfronlalihH"

    ra lhcr ihan^companso l

    Confron ta t ion isun ders tood toconsX^jrjJiMnng out as to

    fact

    is

    such

    as isdescribed in

    the

    s ta tem ent , or, lo

    express

    it

    differently ,

    as

    lo whe the r th e

    s ta tement

    is

    true

    to

    fact.

    (1949, 125)

    Carnap then continued w i th a

    passage

    that might haveservedas an

    advertisement for Kuhn's S t ruc t u re

    o f

    Scientific Revo lu t i ons .

    Fur the rmore , ihc

    formula l ion

    in icrms of "comparison," in speak ing of

    "facls" or

    "realities"easily

    Icmpts one inlo th e absolutislic

    view

    according lo

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    4/29

    JJ

    C a r n a p , K u l i n , an d

    the

    Philosophyof Scientific

    Methodology

    which

    we

    arc

    said

    to

    search

    for an

    absolulc reality whose n a t u re

    is

    assumed

    as

    fixed i n d e p e n d e n t l y

    of th el anguagechosen for itsdescr ipt ion .Thea n s w e r

    to

    aques t ionc o n c e r n i n g

    reality

    however

    depends

    n o t

    on ly upon

    that"reality"

    or upon

    th e

    facts, but a lso upon the s t ructure (and the set

    concepts)

    of the

    l a ng u a g e used for

    the

    descr ipt ion . In t rans la t ingone l a n gua ge i n t o a n o t he r

    the

    fac tua l

    con ten t o f an empir ica l s ta tement c a n n o t a lways

    be preserved

    u n c h a n g e d .Such

    c ha n ges

    a rcinevitableifthe

    s t ructures

    o fthetw ol anguages

    di f fe r

    .inessential

    po in t s . (1949, 125-126)

    H e r e

    we

    havetw oof the key theses

    oTthe^gostpositivisl

    ph i losophyi

    of science:, the

    noncx i s t cnce

    of ne u t r a l

    facts

    and

    i n c o m m e n su r a b i l l y

    in the foriTiof ' ' f tiftn^TrofiriKrrtTanshrtabHfly. NotcTttMrt-tucsc theses

    were p ropou n ded i n the m id 1930s/for a l though I

    have,

    fo r thesake

    ofconven ience ,quoted f rom the 1949 version o f

    C a rnap ' s

    paper , th e

    re l evan t passageis

    also

    in

    "W ahrhci l

    u n d B e w a h r u n g "

    (1936)./*

    |

    Given

    these K u h n i a n themesor should wer a t h e r s ay Ca r n ap i an

    th e me s? one

    m i g ht predic t th a t Ca r n ap wou l d h av e f ou n dStruc ture

    phi losophical ly congen i a l . That

    this

    w as

    indeed the

    case has been

    d o c u m e n t e d b y

    Rcisch

    (1991).

    St ruc tur e

    was publ ished as par t of

    the

    I n t e r n a t i o n a l Encyc loped ia of Un i f i ed Science, of

    which

    Ca r nap w as

    an

    associateedi tor .A f t e r r ead ing the comple ted manusc r ip tfo r

    Struc -

    ture , Ca r nap wr o te to K u h n in A p r i lo f 1962.The text of

    the

    let ter

    is reproduced in

    Reisch

    1991. I

    will

    quote f rom notes wr i t ten in

    Carnap ' s a rchaics h o r th a n d .Carn ap beg ins wi th

    a

    piece

    o fD a r w i n ia n

    evolu t ion

    an d

    t hen adds,

    c o n c e r n i n g

    K u h n ' s

    thesis,

    In

    a n a logy

    to

    this

    one

    has

    to

    un de r s t a n d t he de ve lopme n t

    o f

    scientific

    the-

    ories:

    n ot

    directed to an ideal[ true] theory, the

    o n e

    t rue theoryof the wo r ld ,

    but

    evolu t ion as a

    step

    to a

    bel ter f o r m ,

    by

    selection

    of

    one

    ou l of

    several

    compe t ing forms .The selection is

    m a d e

    on

    ihc

    basis of preference in

    ihc

    c o m m u n i t y

    o f

    scient is ts . M an y

    factors,

    sociological,

    c u l t u r a l , . . . , a re involved.

    Nol :

    v

    w e

    a re a pp r oa c h in g i r u lh , bu t : we a rc i m p r o v i n gan instrument

    An other im po r tan t though large ly tac it them e of S t ruc t u r e ,a

    holist ic

    view

    of

    m e a n i n g ,

    c an

    also

    be

    seen

    as

    emerging f rom

    the

    wr i t ings

    of

    the logical empir icists in the

    1950s.

    Hcmpe l , for example, took to

    heart Quine 's at tack on the

    analyt ic /synthet ic

    d i s t i nc t ion ,which m ay

    be taken to e m b o d y the thesis that there is asharp d is t inc t ion to b e

    d r a w n be tween two f u nc t i on s o f

    l anguage :

    one to specify m e a n i n g ,

    the other to make empir ica l asser t ions . Applying the mora l to sci-

    ent i f ic

    theories, one arr ives

    a t

    the conclus ion tha t there i s no p r inc i -

    ,*>

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    5/29

    1 2

    J o h n

    E a r m a i i

    pled

    way to

    d i s t inguish those postulates

    of

    th e

    theory

    tha t

    m ay

    proper ly

    b e

    d u b b e d m e a n i n g postulates.

    It is

    then

    but a

    seemingly

    short

    an d t e m p t i n g

    step

    to the

    fur ther conclus ion tha t

    all

    the

    pos-

    tulatesof the

    theory

    function to specifythe mean ing of the constit-

    u e n t

    te rm s

    a n d

    thus tha t

    an y

    s ignif icant change

    in

    the theory

    implies

    a

    change

    in me an i ng .

    This route

    to

    seman t ic hol ism cann ot

    betraced to any of

    Carnap 's

    writings. Indeed, in his response to HempePs contr ibut ion to the

    Schi lpp volume (1963), Carnap at tempted to use the not ion of the

    Ramsey

    sentence of the theory to

    ident i fy

    the postulates of the theory

    tha t

    "merely

    represent

    meaning relations"

    (1963a,

    965).

    And in h is

    last bo o k , Phi losophica l Foundat ions o f Physics

    (1966), Carnap mai iv

    ta ined th a t a sh a r p analyt ic-synthet ic dist inct ionis ofs u p r em e im-

    portance for the phi losophy of science" (1966, 257). There

    is,

    however, another C arn apian route to sem an t ic hol ism, bu t tha t route

    m u s t be

    traced

    all the w ay

    back

    to

    Carnap ' s a t t e m p t

    in the Aufbau

    (1928) to expla in how scientific objectivity can

    emerge

    from a

    recon-

    struction

    tha t

    starts from

    a

    phcnom cna l i st ic

    basis.

    A n

    explora t ion

    of

    this

    m a t te r

    w ou ld take

    m e too far

    afield;

    I

    willsim ply refer

    the

    reader

    to Michael

    F r i edman ' s (1987)

    i l lumina t ing discussion.7

    ^ JV

    /

    3 Carnap's Relativism

    losophy an d

    Logical

    S y n t a x " (1935)

    proclainicd the

    relat ivi ty

    ol

    a ll

    philosophical

    theses tol anguage .This

    relativity

    w as

    supposed

    tohold

    the key to

    so lv ing ,

    or

    rather dissolving, t rad i t ion al phi losophical dis-

    putes .

    Suppose,

    for

    example ,

    on e

    phi losopher

    asserts,

    " N u m b e rs

    are -

    primit iveentities,"

    whi le

    another proclaims, "Numbers are classes of

    classes." They

    m ay," C arn ap w ri tes, "philosophize w itho ut

    en d

    abou t

    the

    question

    of

    what numbers rea l ly are ,

    but in

    this

    w ay

    they

    will

    never

    come

    to an

    agreement

    (1935, 450).

    If,

    however, they

    are

    acute

    en o ugh to

    recognize Carnap's relativity principle, they

    will

    quickly

    realize

    that one is asser t ing, "In Language LI (Peano), numerical

    expressions are elementary expressions," whi le the

    other

    ism a i n t a i n -

    ing, "In

    Language

    L?

    (Russell) numerical expressions

    are

    class

    ex-

    pressions of the secondorder.

    "Now these

    assertionsare

    compat ible j

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    6/29

    C a r n a p , K u l i n ,

    an d

    th e P h i l o s o p h y

    o f Scienti f ic

    M e t h o d o lo g y

    wi th each o th e r an d bo th a rc t r u e ; the cont roversy has ceased to

    exist"

    (1935,451).T h is m o d e l for resolving phi losop hical dispu tes in

    the

    ph i losophy

    of

    m a t h em a t ic s

    w as

    supposed

    by

    C a r n a p

    to be

    cx tend-

    iblc q u i te b road ly to phi losophical disputes, such as p h e nom e na l ism

    versus

    mater ia l ism an d the quest ion of whether space- t ime poin ts

    have

    an

    ex i s tence i ndependen t

    of

    physical events .

    Some, like Donald Davidson (1973), have found an air of paradox

    in the

    fact

    tha t say ing i n one brea th (as Ca r nap th ou g h t he could)

    tha t 5 is t rue in L \,

    LS,

    Las, . but false in L ? ,4, .. . seems to

    presuppose

    a

    n e u t r al

    m e ta f ra m e

    wi thin

    wh i chall thelanguage f rames

    can

    be

    treated.

    6

    Others, l ike Michael Fr iedman (1992), have argued

    t ha t

    Carn ap ' s re la t iv ism is un de rcu t byGodel's incomple teness theo-

    rems , wh ich show tha t

    n o

    such neu t r a l me ta f r ame

    is

    avai lable.

    M y

    objections are more localan d tactical.

    Myfirstc o m p l a in tisth a t

    Carnap

    assumesw h a t

    needs

    to be proved .

    Accord ing toCarn ap ' s "pr inc ip le of tolerance," we are free tochoose

    whateve r

    l a n g u a g esystem

    w e

    like.

    T he

    decision

    islargelya

    p r ag m a t ic

    affair , t u r n i n gon such mat ters as efficiency an d

    f ru i t fu lness

    fo r the

    -purposes a t h and . But to a p p l y the slogan o f "free

    to

    choose to

    dissolve,

    say,

    the

    p h e nome na l i sm v e r su s

    m ater ial ism

    deba te assumes

    tha t a p h en om ena l i st ic langu age has been produ ced that shows how

    physical object talk can be reduced to

    talk

    about sensa data or , as

    C arn ap preferred, m om en tary total experiences ("Elementarer lcb-

    nissc ).

    This,

    of course, is exactly what Carnap tr ied to do in the

    Av/lau.

    But by h is own admiss ion ,

    th e

    a t t em pt

    has to coun ted as a

    f a i lure

    if, ash e o r ig ina l l y assumed , the

    reduct ion

    has to

    proceed

    v ia

    explicit def in i t ions

    an d

    explicit Iranslalions. Similar ly,

    to

    a p p l y the

    "free to choose slogan to dissolve disputes about the ontplogical

    status

    of space-t ime points assumes tha t i t can be shown how

    space-

    t ime poin ts can b econstructed out of events, such ascoincidences of

    particles. Advocates

    of

    relat ional theories

    of

    space

    an d

    t ime repeat-

    edly

    claim that this can bedone an d even tha t i t has beendone. B ut

    n o n e

    o f

    the c la ims s tands

    up to

    scrut iny.

    7

    I am

    e mp h a t i c a l l y

    n o t

    c la iming tha t materia l ism

    is

    correct

    or

    that space-t ime points con-

    strued as irreducible enti ties are essential to physics. Rather, I am

    c la iming that the dissolution of the tradi t ional disputes on

    these

    matters is not as easy asCarnap made it seem.

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    7/29

    M

    John E a r m a n

    A n o t h e r

    c o m p l a i n t arises f rom

    the b r ea t h t ak i ngscope of the in-

    t ended appl ica t ion

    of

    Carnap's

    di sso lving s tra tegy . A m on g

    the

    "phi lo-

    sophical" disputes that C a r n a p proposed to treat in th i s way were

    such

    matters as

    whether time

    is finite or

    inf ini te

    an d

    whether

    the

    world isdetermin is t ic .There isobvious lyavery s l ippery s lope here.

    If the quest ionabout the fini lude of t ime is a philosop hical q uestion

    in

    the

    re levantsense, then

    why not the

    q uest ion

    of wh ether the

    world

    began from a b ig-bang s ingular i ty?An d if this latter question is a

    phi losophicalqu est ion

    in the

    relevant sense, then

    w h y n o t

    otherdeep

    ques t ions

    in

    cosmology?

    B ut

    more

    impor tan t , one

    does

    n o t

    have

    to

    go d o w n the slope to recognize the implausibihty of Carn ap 's pro-

    cedure .E ven

    i f one

    agrees

    to

    talk

    about

    t ruth

    in Lrather

    than t ru th

    period,

    there is no plausibi l i ty to the idea that whether t ime is f in i te

    an d whe ther determin ism holds a re mat ters to be settled in L by

    adopt i ng l inguis t ic rules for

    L

    rather than by consul t ing the facts .

    C a r n a p ,

    n o t

    surpr i s ingly , acknowledged

    the

    po in t . Speaking

    of the

    determin ism

    issue, he said,

    Theob jection m aypcriiaps be raised at this point that the form of physical

    laws

    d ep end s upon exper imenta l resu l ts

    of

    physicalinves t iga tion ,

    an d

    tha t

    it

    is not d e t e rm i ned by a merely theoretical syntactical

    consideration.' This

    assertion isqu i te r ight , b ut we

    m u s t bear

    in m i n d the fact

    tha t

    the empir ical

    results

    at which physicis ts arr ive by way of their laboratory exper imen t sby

    no means

    d ictate

    theirchoice

    between

    th e

    determinis t ic

    an d the statistical'fo rm

    of

    laws.

    The

    fo rm

    in

    w h i c h

    a law is

    to be slated

    has

    tobedecided

    by an act

    of

    voli t ion.

    Thisdecision, it ist rue ,

    d ep end s

    u p o n the empir ical resul ts , but

    n ot

    logically,

    on ly

    pract ica l ly .

    The

    results of

    the exper iments show

    merely

    i l l . i l

    on e

    mode

    of fo rmu la t ion wou ld be

    m o r e

    sui table t h a n ano the r . (1935,

    455)

    These s en t imen t s

    resonate with those Carnap expressed three de-

    cades la ter in comment ing on

    K u h n ' s St ruc ture .

    B ut here the senti-

    ment s

    arc not to the point. T he issuei s not

    whether ,

    for D u h e m i a n

    or

    o ther reasons,

    the resultso f

    exper iments ,

    say the

    recen t E ins te in ,

    Rosen, Podolsky, and

    Bell

    type of exper iments ,

    fail

    to dictate the

    acceptance o f

    i nde te rmin i s t ic

    laws. Rather the issue is whether deter-

    min i sm is a scientif ic claim to be argued over the way one argues

    over otherdeepscien t i f ic c laims, n on e

    of

    w hich ever gets

    definit ively

    settled by the dictates of experimental evidence; o rw hether

    deter-

    min ism is a

    c la im that

    can be

    made t rue

    by

    l i ngu i s t i c

    fiat in

    L\

    Lr , ,

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    8/29

    Ca rn a p , K u h n , an d the Philosophy

    of

    Scientific

    Methodology

    35, . . . and false by l inguis t ic fiat in L

    2

    , LT , 37 . . .. . an d then w e

    j u s t

    p a ysour m o n e yan d takeso ur choiceo f language . Aga inI

    re fuse

    to give a global

    a n s w er

    to th i s que ry an d favor instead a

    tactical

    response.All in dica t ion s are tha t the debate over theimp l ica tions for

    deter i j i in ism of the

    Bell

    inequa l i t ies and the

    Aspect exper iments

    be longs

    to

    the f o r m e r r a t h e r than to the la t te r . Indeed , ind ica t ions

    are

    t h a t

    i n any l anguage

    sys tem adequate

    for the

    f o r m u l a t i o n

    o f

    theoriestha tsavethe exper imenta l lyverifiable q ua n tum s ta ti stics ,the

    laws m u s t

    b e

    inde termini s t i c .

    9

    I

    suspect

    t h a t

    Carnap ' s

    relativism

    began

    b y hisbe i n g

    impressed

    b y

    th e ach ievements o f Frege, Russell, an d others in the ph i losophy of

    mathema t i c s

    and was fu r the red by a misplaced zeal for extend ing his

    m o d e l for resolving

    ph i lo soph ica l d i spu te s

    in this area

    to

    a

    broad

    area of ph i losophica lan d scient if ic questions. O f course, wha teve r

    the origins of Carnap's relat ivism, it or

    s om e th i n g

    like it could per-

    hapsb e promoted on the basis of his doct r ine tha t language-neut ra l

    facts do not exist. I find it di f f icul t to assess this matter, since I do

    not f ind in Carnap ' s wr i t i nga he lpfu l explana t ion o f

    this

    In

    th e fol lowing section

    I will

    c o m m e n t

    on the related

    doc t r i ne

    o f

    Feyc ra bc n d ,

    H a n s on ,

    an d

    Kuhn tha t observa t ion

    is

    theory laden .

    In closing this section, Inote tha t Carn ap displayed a con sistency

    on th e

    ma t t e r

    at

    h a n d

    n o t

    the

    consistency that

    is the

    hobgoblin

    of

    l i t t le m i n d s but the magn i f i c en t consistency of a grand v is ionary . In

    his

    c o n t r i bu t i o n t o

    the

    Sch i lpp vo lume fo r Carnap ,

    H e r b e r t Fcigl

    (1963) ske tched a mind-body ident i ty

    theory

    that he was later to

    elaborate

    in his

    f a m o u s

    essay

    The

    'M e n t a l ' an d

    t h e T h ys i -

    caF"(1958). ' Clearly, the politically

    correct th ing for Carnap was to

    endorse Fcigl 'sapproach. Ins tead , he wrote , "it seems preferable to

    m e to formula te the ques t ion [of mind-body ident i ty] in the meta-

    lan guag e, not as a

    factual

    ques t ion abou t the w or ld ,but as aques t ion

    conce rn ing the choice of language . Al though w eprefer a d i f f e r e n t

    language , we m us t adm it tha t a dua l is t ic

    l anguage

    can be con structed

    an d

    used

    w i thou t coming in to con f li c t

    with

    cither

    the

    laws

    of

    logic

    or

    with

    empi r i c a l l y known

    facts"

    (1963b,885-886).

    4 Kuhn's Re lativism

    K u h n resists being labeled a relativist. I use

    the

    labelhere tore fe r to

    three doct r ines o f Struc ture: the theory ladenncss of observat ion , th e

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    9/29

    ]G

    John

    Earnian

    n c o m n i c n s u r a b i l i t y

    o f

    theories,

    an d (l ie d e n i a l t ha t

    there

    is a

    l l i co ry -

    indcpcndcnl

    notion

    of

    truth.

    Pa r t of w h a t w as

    meant

    by the

    theory ladcnncss

    o f observation is

    embodied in the

    thesis that

    what we see depends

    upon

    what we

    believe,athesis

    open

    tochallenge

    (see

    Fodor 1984). I am

    concerned

    rather with

    therelated

    thesis

    of the nonexistence of aneutral

    obser-

    vat ion language

    in w h i c h

    different theories

    can be

    compared.

    M y

    response is once again tactical.

    That

    is, without trying to adjudicate

    thegeneral merits of the

    thesis,

    I claim that things

    aren't

    so bad for

    actual

    historical

    examples.

    Even

    for

    cases

    o f

    major

    scientif ic

    revolu-

    t ions, we

    cari

    find,

    without having

    to go too far

    downward toward

    some t h ing like foundations for knowledge, an observation basethat

    is neu t ra l enough

    fo r

    pu rpos e s

    a t

    hand. A

    nice

    e x a m p l e is

    provided

    by

    Allan Franklin

    (1986,

    110-113), who shows how to construct an

    experiment that

    is

    theory-neutral enough between Newtonian

    and

    special-relativistic

    mechanics to unambiguously

    decide

    between the

    predictions

    of

    these

    theories for elastic

    collisions.

    The two

    theories

    agree on the procedure for measuring the angle between the

    velocity

    vectorsof thescattered particles,and the two

    theories predict

    differ-

    ~

    en t

    angles.

    A b

    More

    generally,

    I

    claim that

    in the

    physical sciences there

    is in

    pr inc iple

    always available

    a

    neutral observation base

    in

    spatial coin-

    cidences,such asdots on photographic plates, pointer positions on

    dials,

    and the like. If intcrsubjective agreement on such

    matters

    were

    n ot

    routine, then physical science

    as we

    k n o w

    it

    would

    no t b e

    possible.

    1 reject, of course, the posilivistic attempt to reduce

    p'hysics

    tosuch

    coincidences.

    A n d I readily acknowledge that such coincidences b y

    themselves

    are

    mute

    witnesses in the

    tribunal

    forjudging theories.

    B ut

    w h a tis required to make these mute witnesses articulate is not a

    Gcstaltexperiencebut a

    constellation

    of techniques,hypotheses,and

    theories: techniquesof

    data

    analysis, hypotheses aboutthe operation

    of measuring instruments,

    and

    auxiliarytheories thatsupportboot-

    strap calculations of values for the relevant theoretical

    parameters

    t ha ttestthecompeting theories.But Iagain assert thatto the

    extent

    tha t

    this process cannot be explicit ly articulated but relies on some

    su igeneris

    form

    of perception,the

    practice

    is not

    science. This

    is not

    tosay, however, thatthevulgar imageofscienceas ab l i nd lyimpartial

    enterprise

    is correct, for the articulation uncovers assumptions to

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    10/29

    17

    Carnap, K u l i n ,

    a nd the

    Phi losophy

    o f

    Scient i f ic Method o log y

    which d i f f e r e n t

    scientists may assign vc fy

    different , degrees

    of con-

    f idence .

    B u t

    this

    sense

    in

    which

    di f ferent scient is ts can

    (mis lcad ing ly )

    be said to see di f f e ren t th ings when looking a t the same phenom -

    enon

    is one with which a

    probabil istic

    or

    Bayesian

    epistemology the

    k i n d

    of

    epis temology w hich

    the

    la ter Carn ap came to

    advoca tem ust

    cope on a routine basis ,

    even

    incases fa r away f rom the boundar ies

    of

    scient if ic

    revolut ions .

    H ow

    these di f ferences

    are resolved is

    pa r t

    of

    the

    Bayes ian ana logue

    of

    K u h n ' s problem

    of

    com m un i ty dec is ion

    on

    theo ry choice. Kuhn 's problem

    will

    b e

    encoun te red

    in

    the

    follow-

    in g section, an d the Bayesiananalogue will be discussed in sections

    8 and 9.

    T he m a t te r o f incom m ensu rab i l i ty i s m uch more diff icult to discuss

    for tw o reasons.

    First ,

    it is tied to di f f icul t is sues about me an in gan d

    reference tha t

    I

    cannot broach

    here.

    Second, issues about incom-

    mensurab i l i t y

    present amorphous and shi f t ing targets. In Struc ture ,

    for

    example , i ncommensurab i l i t y

    was a

    label

    for the

    entire constel-

    lation

    o f

    factors that lead proponents

    of

    d i f f e ren t pa rad igms

    to

    talk

    past on e another . In recen t years Kuhn has come a round to a

    more

    Carnap ian

    or

    l inguis t ic fo rmula t ion

    in

    which i ncommensurab i l i t y

    is

    equated

    wi th

    un t rans l a tab i l i t y . More

    specifically, the

    focus

    has

    shif ted

    from paradigms to theories, and two theories are said

    to

    b ei n c o m -

    mensurab le just in case

    there

    is no common language in to which

    both can be fully translated ( K u h n1989, 10). I have no doubts about

    K uh n ' s cl aims tha t

    theories

    o n d i f f e r en t

    sides

    o f ascientificrevolut ion

    often

    use

    di f ferent " lexicons," that di f ferences

    in

    lexicons

    can

    m a k e

    fo r a

    k i n d

    o f

    un t r a n s l a t a b i l i t y ,

    an d

    tha t

    in

    t u r n this

    exp la in s w hy

    scientists r e ad i ng out-of-date texts of ten

    e n c o u n t e r

    passages tha t

    make

    no

    sense

    (1989,9). But I deny

    thatthere

    is

    i n comm e nsu ra -

    bi l i ty /untransla tabi l i ty

    tha t makes

    for

    insuperable difficulties

    for

    con-

    firmation or

    theory choice

    (a

    phrase

    I

    don't l ike

    for

    reasons

    to be

    given below)

    in the

    s tandardly c i ted cases

    of

    scientific revolut ions

    such as the t ran si t ion f rom N ew ton ian to special- rela t ivis tic m echan ics

    an d

    the

    su bse qu e n t transi t ion togeneral rela tivi ty . N ew ton ian , spe-

    cial-relativistic,

    gcncral-relativistic, and

    m a n y

    other theoriescan all

    be

    f o rm u l a t ed

    in a

    common language,

    the

    language

    of d i f fe ren t ia l

    geometry

    on a

    four -d imen s iona l m an i fo ld ,

    and the

    cruciald i f ferences

    in the

    theories

    l ie in the

    dif ferences

    in the

    geometric object

    fields

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    11/29

    J8

    John E a r m a n

    postulated

    an d the m a n n e r i n wh i c hthesef ieldsrelateto such

    t h i ng s

    as

    particle orbits .

    This

    language is

    an achron is t ic

    and so may not be

    th e best device

    to

    use when t r y i n g

    to decide

    various historical dis-

    putes. But i t

    does

    seem to me to be an

    app r op r i a t e vehicle

    for

    f r a m i n g an d an swe r i ng the sorts of quest ions of most concern to

    w or k ing

    physicis ts

    an d philosophersof

    science.

    For

    example,

    on the

    basis of the

    avai lable

    evidence, what is i t reasonable tob elieve about

    the

    s t ruc ture

    o fspace an d t ime and the n a tu re o f gravi ta t ion?This

    is not to saytha t the common language makes for an easy answ er. It

    is

    indeed a

    d i f f icul t

    business, but i t is a business that

    involves

    the

    same sorts o f difficult ies a l ready

    present

    w h en test ing theories t ha t

    lie on the same side of a scient i f ic revolut ion. Finally, so that there

    can be n o m i s un de r s t a n d i n g ,

    let

    m e repeat: I am not c l ai m i n g ( h a t

    w h a t

    I

    call

    a

    common l anguage prov ides wha t K u h n wan t s . It docs

    n o t

    show,

    fo r

    example , tha t

    the

    N e w t o n i a n

    and the

    E i n s t c i n i a n

    can

    b e

    b rought i n to agreemen t about wha t

    is and is not a

    "m ea n i n g f u l "

    quest ion

    a b o u t

    s im ul tane i ty .

    But w ha t I do cla im is that

    these

    res idua l

    e lement s

    of i n c om m en s u r a b i li ty

    d o no tu n d e r m i n es t anda rd accoun t s

    of

    theory test ing

    an d

    con f i rma t ion .

    1 2

    My response

    to

    worries

    about the

    appl icabi l i ty

    of the

    no t ion

    of

    t r u t h

    tow hole theories iss im ilarly localan d

    tactical.

    In the Postscript

    to the second edition

    o f S t ru c tu re ,

    Kuhn wr i t es ,

    There

    i s , I th in k , no

    t h e o ry - i nd e p e n d e n t way to

    recons t ruc t

    phrases like 'reallythere'; the

    not ion

    of a

    ma tch between

    the

    ontology

    of a

    theory

    and its

    ' rea l '

    c o u n t e r p a r t

    in

    n a t u r e

    n ow

    seems

    to me

    illusive

    in pr inc ip le"

    (1970,

    206). I need n o t

    d e m u r

    if " theory" is

    unders tood

    in 'a very broad

    sense to mean something l ike a conceptua l f r a m e w o r k som i n i m a l

    tha t w i tho u tit "the world" would b e un d i f f e r en l i a t ed Ka n t i a nooze.

    B ut

    I do

    d e m u r

    if

    theory

    is

    taken

    in the

    ordinary sense,

    i.e., as

    Newton ' s theory o r special - rela t ivi ty theory o r genera l - re la t iv i tythe-

    ory.

    13

    For scient is ts are current ly working in a f rame in which they

    can

    say, correctly

    I

    t h i n k ,

    tha t

    the

    match between

    the

    ontology

    of

    the

    theory and i ts real counterpar t in n a t u r e is

    better

    for th e special

    theory

    o f

    relativity

    an d evenbetter for the

    gen era l theory.

    O f

    course,

    to get tothis position required tw om a jor coneptua l revolut ions . H ow

    such revolutions affect theory choice, or as I would prefer to say,

    theory testing an d con f i rma t ion , rema ins to be discussed.

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    12/29

    ]9

    C a r n a p , K u h n ,an d the Ph i losophyo fScientif ic Methodology

    5

    Kuhn's

    Accountof

    Scientific Revolutions

    Carnap,

    as wehave

    seen,

    found

    Kuhn's

    Structure

    congenial.

    But

    m a n y

    philosophers

    of the younger

    generation,includingthose

    who

    prided

    themselves on having

    gone

    beyondthe crudities of

    logicalpositivism,

    professed

    shock and

    dismay

    at

    Kuhn'saccount

    of the

    displacement

    of

    an old

    paradigm

    by a new

    one.

    For

    those

    readerswho do not

    have

    a copyofStructure to

    hand,

    hereare someof the

    purplepassages:

    Like

    th e choice between competing poli t ical ins t i tut ions , that

    between

    com-

    pet ing

    parad igms

    proves to

    be a

    choice

    between

    incompat ib le

    modes

    of

    c o m m u n i t y

    life.

    .

    ..W h e n

    parad igmsen ter, as

    they

    m us t , in toa deba te abou t

    parad igm

    choice, the i r role is

    necessarily circular.

    Each group

    uses'

    i ts own

    parad igm to a rgue in t h a t p a r a d i g m ' s

    de fense .

    (P. 94)

    As

    in poli t ica l revolut ions , so in parad igm choicethere i s no s tandard

    h ighe r t h a n th eassentof

    the

    re l evan t

    c o m m u n i t y .

    To discover how

    scientific

    revolu t ions arc

    effected,

    we

    shall

    therefore

    have

    to

    e x a m i n e n o t on ly the

    impact o f n a t u r e and logic, but also the t echn iques of pe rsuas ive a rg um en -

    tation

    w i th i n

    th e

    c jui lc

    special

    groups

    tha t

    cons t i tu te

    th e

    c o m m u n i t y

    of

    sci-

    entis ts . (P. 94)

    The

    p r o p o n e n t s

    of compet ing parad igms prac t ice the i r

    trades

    in d i f fe ren t

    worlds. . . . Prac t ic ing in d i f ferent wor lds , the tw ogroups of scientists sec

    d i f f e r en t t h i n g s w h e n they look from the same point in the

    same

    direct ion.

    (P. 150)

    In thesema t t e r sn e i t h e rproof n orerror is atissue.The

    t r an s fe r

    ofallegiance

    from

    pa r ad igm

    to

    parad igm

    is a

    con version

    exper ience

    tha t

    c a n n o t

    be

    forced.

    (P .151)

    Before they can hope to c o m m u n i c a t e fully, on e group or the o ther mus t

    exper ience th e

    conversion

    tha t we have been cal l ing a paradigm shif t . Jus t

    because it is a

    sh i f t between

    incommensu rab les , the t rans i t ion

    between

    com-

    pet ing

    pa r ad igms

    c a n n o t

    be

    m a d e

    a

    step

    at a

    time, forced

    by

    logic

    an d

    neu t r a l experience. Like a gcslalt switch, it must occur all at once

    ( though

    n o t

    necessarily at an

    i n s t an t )

    or not at al l . (P . 150)

    M a n y

    readers

    saw in

    these

    passages

    an

    open

    i n v i t a t i o n

    to aralio-

    na l i t y if not outright irrationality.Thus Imre

    Lakatos

    took

    K u h n

    to

    besaying that theory choice is a matter of "mob psychology

    (1970,

    178), while DudleyShapcreread Kuhn assayingthatthe decision to

    adopta newparadigm

    cannot

    bebased ongood reasons (1966, 67).

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    13/29

    20

    John

    E a r man

    K u l i n

    inturn w asequ a l lyshocked b ysuch criticisms.In thePostscript

    to thesecond edi t ion o f St ruc ture (1970),he professed

    surprise

    that

    readers could have imposed such unintended interpretationson th e

    above quoted passages.

    I

    will leave aside

    the

    u n f r u i t f u l question

    of

    w h e t h e ror not

    K u h n

    ought tohave

    anticipated

    such interpretations

    an d

    will concentrate instead on what, upon reflection, he i n t e nd e d

    to

    say.

    K u h n ' s

    ow n exp lana t ion in the

    Postscript begins

    wi th the

    common-

    place tha t debate over theory-choicecannot be cast in a form tha t

    resembles

    logical

    o r

    mathemat ica l

    choice

    (1970,

    195).

    B ut

    he

    has tens

    to

    add

    that this commonplace

    doesnot

    imply that there

    are no

    good

    reasons for

    being

    persuaded or that

    these

    reasonsare not

    u l t im ate ly

    decisive

    for the group (1970, 195). T he reasons listed in the Post-

    sc r ip t

    areaccuracy,s implic i ty ,and f ru i t fu lness . The later paper Ob-

    jectivi ty, Value Judgments,

    and

    Theory Choice (1977)

    added two

    f u r t h e r reasons:consistencyand scope.And asKuhn himselfnotes,

    the final

    list

    does

    not

    d i f fer

    (with

    one

    notable exception

    to be

    dis-

    cussed later) from similar lists drawn from standard phi losophy-of-

    scicnce texts (see also Kuhn 1983).

    These soothing sentiments serve todeflate charges ofarationality

    and

    irrationality, but at the same time they also serve to raise the

    ques t ion of how Kuhn's viewsare to be distinguished from the or-

    thodoxy

    that Structurewassupposed to upset.The answer givenin

    the

    Postscript contains

    tw o

    themes, which

    are elaborated in Objec-

    tivity."

    First,

    the

    items

    on

    the

    above

    list

    a re

    said

    to

    function

    as

    values"

    tha t can be

    d i f f e ren t l y app l i ed ,

    i n d iv idua l ly an d

    collectively

    b ym en

    whoconcurinhonoringthem (1970, 199).Thus, thereis noneutral

    algor i thmfor

    theory choice,

    no

    systematic decision procedure which ,

    properly applied, must lead each individualin thegroupto the s ame

    decision.

    Second, it

    (supposedly) follows that

    "it is the

    c o m m u n i t y

    of

    specialists

    rather than the individual members that makes the

    effective

    decision (1970,

    200).

    I

    th ink

    that Kuhniscorrectinlocating objectivityin thecommunity

    of

    sp ecialists,

    atleastin the uncontroversialsensethat intersubjective

    agreement among the relevant experts is a necessary condition for

    objectivity. But how the communityof

    experts

    reaches a decision

    when the individual members d i f fer on the application o f shared

    values is a mys te ry that to m y mind is not

    adequa te ly

    resolved b y

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    14/29

    21

    C a r n a p , K u h n ,

    an d ihc Phi losophy o f

    Scicnlific Mclhodology

    Struc ture or by s u b s e q u e n t wr i t ings . M ystrategy will be to

    explore

    these

    an d related

    issues from

    the

    perspective

    o f

    Carnap's

    cpis tcmology.

    6

    Carnap

    and

    Kuhn Incommensurability?

    The passage Reisch

    (1991)

    quotes from Carnap's letter toKuhnand

    the passage from Carnap's shorthand notes I quoted in section 2

    would seem to ind ica te

    that Carnap

    an d

    K u h n were

    in

    subs tan t ia l

    a g r e e m e n t

    as

    regards

    paradigm

    choice.

    This

    is

    surely

    the

    case

    w h e n

    paradigm is

    interpreted

    to

    m e a n

    something l ikea l inguis t icframe-

    w o r k . A t this

    level

    Carnap wouldagree, indeed, would insist , on th e

    need tochoose, and hewould hold t h a t thechoice

    is'a p r a g m a t i c

    on e

    whosedynamicsm ay well invo lve the

    sorts

    of factors emphas i zed in

    K u h n ' s account. B ut w h e n

    the

    focus shifts to theories, as itdoes in

    K u h n ' s later writings,

    the

    disagreement begins.

    In the f i rs t

    place,

    K u h n ' s list

    ofcriteria fortheory choice isconspicuousfor itsomission

    of any

    reference

    to the

    degrees

    of

    confirmation

    or

    probabilities

    of

    the

    theories.

    This is not an

    oversight,

    of

    course,

    but

    derives both

    from explicit doctrines, suchas thenonexistence of atheory-neutral

    observation language, and the largely tacitbut pervasive anti-induc-

    tivism

    of

    S t ruc t u re . Needless

    to

    say, this shunning

    of

    confirmation

    theory

    is

    most u n - C a r n a p i a n .

    B ut

    even more anomalous from Car-

    nap's

    perspective

    isKuhn's emphasisontheory choiceor

    acceptance,

    for in Carnap's version of epistemology,

    theories

    arc not chosen or

    accepted

    b u t

    o n l y

    p robab i I i f i ed .

    M

    Carnap's

    writingsinthe1940sand

    1950s

    portrayhim as espousing

    a logical

    conception of

    probability.

    But by the

    late 1950s

    an d ear ly

    1960s,

    he

    clearly favored

    a view

    that

    can be t e rmed

    tempered per-

    sonal i sm: probability

    is

    rational degree

    of

    belief.

    15

    I

    will

    h a v e

    more

    to say on

    this matter

    insection 8, but in the

    m e a n t i m e

    I

    will present

    Carnap

    as a

    tempered Bayesian personalist.

    A

    shotgun marriage

    of

    Kuhn

    and

    Carnap

    could

    be

    arranged

    by

    t ak ingCarnap

    to

    supply

    the

    probabilities,

    K u h n to

    supply

    the

    values

    or

    utilit ies,

    and

    then applying

    the

    rule

    of

    maximizing

    the

    expected

    utilityto

    render

    adecisionon

    theory choice.

    16

    But

    likemost shotgun

    marriages, this

    one

    would

    be a

    mistake.

    For

    Carnap

    it

    would

    be a

    mis take because it w o u l d

    invo lve the

    pretense t ha t

    the

    accepted

    the-

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    15/29

    22

    John Carman

    ory

    is certa in even t h o u g h

    one's

    degree of belief in

    the

    theory may

    be less thanone,perhaps substant ia l lyso. For K u h n it would alsobe

    a mis take,

    since

    the

    efficacy

    of his values

    does

    n ot

    depend

    on the

    t ru th

    o f the

    theories,

    so

    estimates

    of the

    probable t ruth

    of the

    theories

    is

    i r relevant

    to K u h n i a n

    theory choice.

    Part

    of the

    wrang le here derives from

    the

    un f o r t un a t e ph ra s e

    "theory choice." Scientists do choose theories, but on beha l f o f Car-

    n a p , Iwould c l aim th a t they

    choose

    themon ly inthei n n o c uo ussense

    that theychoose to devote their t ime an d energy tothem: toart icu-

    la t ing

    them,

    to

    i m p r o v i n g th e m ,

    to

    drawing

    ou t

    their consequen ces,

    to

    confront ing

    them

    withthe results ofobservationand experiment.

    Choice in thissense allows for a reconciliation of

    Bayes

    a n d K u h n ,

    since

    thischoice

    is i n fo rm ed bybo th Baycsian an d Kuhnian fac tors :

    probabil i ty an d

    th e

    valu es of accuracy, consistency,scope, simplicity,

    an d

    f ru i t fu lncss .

    Alas, this reconcil iation israther shallow. Once we are clear tha t

    th e sort of choice involved in

    " theory

    choice" is a p ractical

    one, there

    is

    n o t h i n g

    sacred

    a b o u t

    the

    list

    of

    i tems

    on

    K u h n ' s

    list

    of values.

    Other

    values,

    such as

    ge t t i ng

    an

    N S F

    g r a n t or w i n n i n g the

    No be l

    Prize,

    can and do

    enter.F u r the r,

    the

    k ind

    of

    choice

    in

    quest ion a l lows

    a

    scientist to be bigamous, s ince he can choose to work on two or

    more theories at

    once,

    and i t al lows him to be fickle, since he can

    oscillate back and forth. The kind of choice Struc tureenvis ioned w as

    m u c h more p e r m a n e n t ; indeed,

    the

    impression given there

    is tha t

    norma l

    science

    is not

    possible

    without tying Cathol ic

    bonds

    to a

    theory,b o n d s

    tha t

    can o n l ybe broken b yl eav ingthe C h u r c h , i.e., by

    creat ing a revo lu t ion .

    Is there no way to b r idge the gap be tween Carnap an d K u h non

    this

    issue? T o see howba f f l ing the Bay esian f inds the not ion of theory

    acceptance, con sider the case of Einstein 's gen eral theory of relativity

    ( G TR ) ,

    a rguab ly the leading theory o f gravitation an d thus the top

    candidate for acceptance. Marie, a research worker in the field fa-

    miliar

    with

    all

    of the

    re levan t exper imenta l

    f indings ,

    does

    some

    in -

    trospection and finds

    that

    her degreeof belief in GTR isp.

    Case

    1: p is1 or so

    n e a r

    1 a s makes no

    odds . Here

    there

    is a n a t u r a l

    sense in which the Bayesian can say that Marie accepts GTR. Such

    cases,however,arc so

    rare

    as to const i tute anomalies .Ofcourse,one

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    16/29

    23

    C a r n a p ,

    K u h n ,

    an d

    llic Phi losophy

    of

    Scientif ic Mclhodology

    can cite any number of cases f rom the his tory of

    science

    w h e r e

    scientistsseem

    to besayingfor

    their

    pet

    theories

    that theysetp= 1.

    Here

    I

    would

    urge

    the need

    to dis t ing uish

    careful ly

    between

    scien tists

    as advocates

    of

    theories versus scientists

    asjudges of

    theories.

    T he

    latter

    roleconcern sushere,and in

    that

    role

    scientists

    know,or should

    k n o w ,

    tha ton ly in v ery exceptiona l

    cases

    does the evidence rat ion al ly

    suppor t a

    full

    belief in a theory. Let us move on to case 2.

    Case

    2: p is , say , .75. Subsequent ly Marie decides to

    accept

    G T R o n

    the

    basis

    of her

    probabil i ty

    assignments and the

    values

    she attaches

    to GTR and its

    competitors.

    W h at

    could

    th i s mean?

    Subcase 2a .

    W h e n

    she

    accepts GTR, Marie changes

    her degree of

    belief from .75 to 1.

    This

    i s no th ing

    short

    of

    folly, s ince

    she has

    a l ready

    m a d e

    a considered judgment about evident ial

    support

    an d

    no new

    relev an t evidence occasioning

    a

    r e j u d g m e n t

    has

    come

    in .

    Suitcase 2b . W h e n

    she

    accepts

    G T R ,

    Mar ie

    docs

    n ot

    c h a n g e

    her de-

    gree of

    belief f rom

    .75 to 1 , bu t she

    acts a sz / a l l doub t were

    swep t

    away

    in

    t ha t

    she

    devotes eve ry w ak in g hour

    to

    show ing tha t var ious

    p u z z l i n g

    as t ronomica l

    observations

    can be exp la ined by the

    theory ,

    she

    assigns her graduate s tudents research projects that presuppose

    the correctness of the theory, she wri tes a textbook ongrav i ta t ion al

    research

    that

    isdevoted

    almost exclusively

    to

    GTR, etc.

    But at this

    p o i n t

    w e

    have come

    full

    circle back

    to a

    sense

    of

    theory acceptance

    t h a t

    is

    really

    a

    m i s n o m e r ,

    for

    w h a t

    isinvolved is a

    practicaldecision

    about the allocation of

    personal

    and insti tutional resources and not

    a decis ion about the

    cpis tcmic sta tus

    of the theory.

    This ra ther pedant ic d ia t r ibe on theory acceptance would b e best

    forgotten were

    it not for

    its impl icat ions

    for our

    p ic ture

    o f

    n o r m a l

    science. Aswe have seen, theory

    choice

    or "acceptance" can refer

    cither to adopting an epislemic

    attitude

    or to mak ing a practical

    choice. In the form er case there is n o n atu ra l Bay esian explication

    of theory acceptance save in the case where the probabi l i ty of the

    theory isone.

    Since scientists

    asjudgesoftheoriesare

    almost never

    in

    a

    position

    to

    ju s t i fy

    such

    an

    acceptance,

    th e

    Bayesian predict ion

    i s

    t h a t rarely is a theo ryaccepted in the epis temicsense.S imilarly,w h e n

    theory choice is a

    m a t te r

    ofdeciding w hat theory todevote

    one'sl im e

    an d energy to, the Bayesian predict ion is tha t in typical s i tuat ions

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    17/29

    John

    l .arnian

    where members of the c o m m un i t y a s s i gn d i f f e r en t

    utilities

    to such

    devotions,

    they

    will

    m a k e

    di f ferent choices .

    Thus

    from

    e i ther

    the

    cpistcmic

    or

    practical-decision

    perspective,

    the

    Bay esian

    predic t ion

    is

    diversity.

    This

    predict ion

    is, I

    t h i n k ,borne

    out by

    actual

    scientific

    practice.

    In

    section

    9below

    Iwilla rgue that insofar

    as

    normal science

    implies

    a

    shared pa rad igm,

    the

    pa rad igm need

    not and in fact

    of ten

    is

    not so

    specific

    as to i nc lude a pa r t i cu l a r

    ( accepted ) theory .

    I

    w i l l

    also

    hazard a

    proposal

    for a

    m i n i m a lsense

    of

    "shared p a r a d i g m "

    tha t

    yields

    a less

    strai t- jacketed image

    of

    n o r m a l

    science an d

    that also

    d imin i shes

    wi thout ob l i t e ra t i ng

    the

    di f ference between normal

    an d

    revolut ionary

    science.

    By way o f closing this section an d

    i n t r od u c i ng

    the

    nex t ,

    I

    will

    cons ider a f inal way of reconci l ing K u h n an d C a r n a p on theory

    choice. Radically n ew theories, so the story goes, carry with them

    di f fe ren t l inguis t ic /conceptua l f rameworks . Thus,

    even

    seriously

    lo

    enter ta in the new theory involves the decision to

    adopt,

    if on ly t en -

    tatively,

    the new framework, and this decis ion is for Carnap a

    prag-

    matic on e that involves the sorts of factors emphasized i n K u h n ' s

    account o f paradigm

    replacement.

    In

    response

    I would

    repeat

    w h a t

    I have

    a l ready

    said insection 4: major scientific revolut ions

    such

    as

    the

    t rans i t i on f rom Newton ian to special-relativistic physics- an d

    thence lo genera l rela t ivi tyneedn't be seen as forc ing a choice be-

    tween i n c o m m e n s u r ab l el ing uist ic /con ceptualsystems, since

    it is of ten

    possible lo f i t

    ihc possibilities in to

    a

    la rger scheme tha i m a kes

    llic

    theories c o m m e n s u r a b l e lo the

    ex ten l

    lhal

    conf i rmal ion

    ques t ions

    can

    be

    posed

    in t e rm sof an observat ion

    base lhal

    isn c u i r a l e n o u g h

    for assessingihe

    re la l ive conf i rmat ion

    of

    the

    theories.

    However,

    ihe

    rccognil ion of ihe

    larger

    possibil i tyset canproduce adrastic

    c h a n g e

    in prob abi l i ty va lues , achan ge best

    described

    in K u h n i a n

    terms.

    7 Revolutions andB elief Shifts

    A mild

    f orm of scient i f ic revo lut ion occurs w ithihe in l roducl ion of

    a new

    llieory lhal articulates possibil i t ies

    thai lie

    wi lh inihe b o u n d -

    aries of

    ihe

    space of iheories to be taken seriously b ut that , because

    of the fai lure of actual scientists to be logicallyom nisc ien l , had pre-

    viously been unrecognized as explicil possibilities.T he more radical

    form

    of revolulion occursw h e n ihe spaceof possibilities itself needs

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    18/29

    25

    C a r n a p , K u h n , an d

    ihc

    Ph i losophy

    o f Scicnl i f ic

    Methodology

    to be s ign i f ican t ly al tered to encompass

    the

    n ew theory . In practice

    the

    d is t inc t ion

    between

    the two forms of revolu t ion may

    be b lu r r ed ,

    perhaps even hopelessly so, but I w i l l begind iscussion by

    p r e te n d i n g

    t ha t

    we can per form a

    separat ion

    ofcases.

    Even the mi ld form of revolu t ion may induce a non-Bayes ian shi f t

    in belief func t i ons . By non-Bayes i an I

    m e a n

    that no form of condi-

    t iona l i za l ion , whether s t r ic t o rJeff rey or some natura l ex tens ion o f

    these, w i l l suffice to expla in

    the

    ch ang e . For cond i t iona l i z i ng ( in any

    recognizable sense of

    the t e r m ) on the i n fo rm at ion tha t j u s t n o w a

    here tofore una r l i cu l a ted

    theory

    T

    has

    been

    i n t roduced

    is

    l i terally

    nonsens ica l ,

    becausesuch acon di t ion al iza t ion

    presupposes

    that pr ior

    to this t ime there was a w el l-defined probab i l ity for th i s i n for m at ion

    an d t h u sfo r T , wh ichisexactly wh at th efai lureof logical om niscience

    rules

    out.

    W e can t ry to acknowledge the

    f a i l u re

    of

    logical

    omnisc ience b y

    m e a n sof A b n e r

    Sh i m on y ' s

    (1970) deviceof acatch-all hy poth esis

    H

    f

    ,

    which

    asserts in e f fec t tha t someth ing , we know not what , beyond

    th e

    previously formulated theories

    T\

    T z,

    . . . ,

    T

    T

    is

    t rue.

    Now

    suppose tha t a new theory T is introduced an d tha t as a result the

    old degrce-of-bcl ief f u n c t i o n Pr ischanged to Pr ' . T he most conser-

    vative

    way the

    sh if t f rom

    Pr to

    Pr' could take

    place

    is by the

    process

    I will

    call

    sha ving

    o f f , n a m e l y ,Pr(T,)

    = .P r ' ( T i ) for i = 1, 2, . . . ,qan d

    Pr'(T) = r > 0 and

    Pr'(//

    e

    )

    = Pr(//

    c

    )- r.Thatis,u n d e r shav in g o f f ,

    H

    f

    serves

    as a well

    for init ial

    probabilities for as y et u n b o r n

    theories,

    an d the

    ac tua l

    i n t roduc t ion of new

    theories resul ts only

    in

    d r a w i n g

    u p o n

    this

    well w i t hou t d i s t u r b i n g th e probabi l i t ies o f

    previously

    for-

    mu la ted theories . U n fo r tun a te l y , such conse rva ti sm even tua l ly leads

    to the a s s i g n m e n t of ever smal ler

    in i t ia l

    probabi l i t ies to successive

    waves

    of n ew

    theories

    u n t i l a

    p o i n t

    isreached

    where

    the new

    theory

    has

    such

    a low

    ini t ial probab i l i ty

    as to

    s tand

    n ot

    m u c h

    of a fighting

    chance .

    Cer t a in ly s h a v i n g

    off is a factual ly

    inadequate descr ip t ion

    of

    w h a t

    h a p p e n s

    in

    m an y scient i f ic revolut ions , especial ly

    of the

    more radical

    type . Th ink o f w h a t happened fo l l owing the in t roduct ion of E i n -

    stein's special theory

    of

    relativi ty (STR)

    in

    1905. Between 1905

    an d

    1915 little n ewempir ical evidence in favor o f S T R wa srecorded, an d

    yet th e probabi l i ty of compet ing theories, such asthose of Lorentz

    an d A b r a h a m , set in classical

    space

    an d t ime,

    fell

    in the estimates of

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    19/29

    26

    John Ea r m a n

    most

    o f

    th e m e m b e r s

    of the

    E u r o p ea n p h ys ic s c o m m u n i ty ,

    and the

    probab i l i t y

    subtracted

    from

    these

    e lect ron theor ies

    w as

    t rans fe r red

    to E ins te in ' sSTR.The probabi l i t iesof au xi l ia ry hypothesesmayalso

    be a f fec ted , as i l lustrated by the in t roduc t ion of the general theory

    of relat ivity

    (GTR).

    When Eins te in showed tha t

    GTR

    accounted

    for

    the exac t am ou n tof the anomalous advance ofM ercury ' s pe r ihe l ion ,

    the

    hypothesis of an amount of zodiacal

    matter suf f ic ien t

    to

    affect

    Merc u ry ' s per ihel ion dropped dramat ica l ly in the estimates of mos t

    of the

    phys ics communi ty ( see Earman

    and

    Glymour 1991) .

    In u s i n g

    the

    term non-Bayesian

    to describe

    such noncond i t ion -

    alization bel ief chan ges , w hether of the conservative shaving-off type

    or

    some more rad ica l fo rm,

    I do not

    mean

    to

    imp ly tha t

    the

    changes

    are not i n f o r m e d b y

    Bayesian

    considerat ions . Indeed, the problem

    of the t rans i t ion f rom Pr to Pr' can be t hough t of as no more and

    no less than the fami l i a r Bayesian problem of ass ign ing ini tial

    prob-

    abili ties, on ly n ow

    wi th

    a new in i t ia l

    si tuat ion

    i nvo lv ing a newset of

    possibilities

    and a

    n ew

    in fo rm at io n bas is . B ut the

    problem

    we

    arc

    n ow f ac ing isq u i t eu n l i k ethose a lleged ly solved b yclassical pr in cip les

    of

    ind i f fe rence

    or

    modern var ian t s the reof , such

    as E. T.

    Jayncs 's

    m a x i m u m - e n t r o p y

    p r inc ip le , where

    it is

    assumed

    w e

    k n o w n o t h in g

    o r

    very

    little ab ou t the

    possibilities

    in

    question.

    In

    typical

    cases the

    scientific

    c o m m u n i ty willpossessa vas tstoreo f relevan t exper im en ta l

    an d

    theore t ica l in format ion . Us ing tha t in format ion

    to

    i n f o r m

    the

    red is t r ibu t ion

    of

    probabil i t ies over

    the

    competing

    theories

    on the

    occasion

    of

    thei n t r o d u c t i o n o f

    th e

    new theory ortheories is a

    process

    t ha t , in the str ict

    sense

    o f the t e r m ,

    is\o?Slipnal:

    i t cannot 'be accom-

    plished

    by some nea t fo rm al ru les o r ,

    T o

    u s e K u h n ' s

    term,_bvan

    a lgor i thm.

    On the

    otherjjand,

    the

    process

    is far f rom

    beirgjrrationa>>

    since it is informecf by reasons. But the

    reasons,

    as

    K u h n

    Tias~crrf-

    phasized, come in

    the

    f o rm

    ofpersuasions

    ra ther than proof. In

    Bayesian

    te rms ,

    the

    reasons

    are

    marsha led

    in the

    guise

    of

    ptausiblTily

    a r g u m e n t s .The d e p l o y m e n tof plausibi l i tya r g u m e n tsis anart form

    for which there

    current ly exis ts

    n o

    t axonomy .

    A n d

    cons ider ing

    the

    l imitless variety of such a rgumen t s , it isun l i ke ly t h a t a n y t h i n g m o r e

    t h a n

    asup erf ic ia l t axon om y can be deve loped . E ins te in , the consum -

    mate mas te r of th isart fo rm, appea led to analogies), symmet ry con-

    s iderat ions ,

    thought exper iments , heur i s t ic

    principles

    such

    as

    the

    pr inc ip le

    o f equ iva lence ,

    etc.

    All of

    these

    considerat ions, I am sug-

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    20/29

    27

    C a r n a p , K u h n , an d the

    Ph i lo sophy

    o f Scientific

    M ethodology

    gcs t ing on

    be ha l f

    of th e

    Baycsians ,

    were deployed to n udg e a ssign -

    m e n t s

    of

    in i t ia l

    probabi l i t ies in

    favor

    of

    the

    theories Eins te in was

    i n t r o d u c i n g

    in the

    ear ly

    decades

    of

    this cen tury . E instein 's success

    in

    this

    regard

    is no

    less important than experimental evidence

    in ex-

    p l a i n i ng

    th e recept ion of his theories.

    T o s u m m a r i z e , K u h n ' s pu rp le passages do no t

    seem

    overb lown

    w h e n

    applied to revolut ions in the st rong sense d ist inguished

    above.

    T he persuasions that lead to the adoption of the newshape fo r

    the

    possibility

    space can no t a m ou n t to proofs . Certa in ly for the

    Bayesian

    they

    can no t cons is t o f indu c t iveproofs, since the very

    a s signmen t

    of

    degrees

    of

    belief

    presupposes

    the

    adoption

    of

    such

    a

    space.

    After

    a

    revolut ion has taken place, the newand o ld theories can often be

    fi t ted

    i n to

    a common f r ame tha t be l i e s an y vicious fo rm of i nc o m -

    mensurab i l i ty (as I tried to illustrate in section 4 for N e w t o n i a n an d

    relativistic theories). But this retrospective

    view

    tends to disguise the

    shake-up in our system of beliefs occasioned by the adoption of the

    n ew

    shape

    fo r

    the possibi l i tyspace.Baycs ian i sm b r ing s

    the

    shake-up

    to

    l ight , albei t

    in a way

    tha t unde rcu t s

    the

    s t anda rd fo rm

    o f

    the

    doctr ine .

    I have no way of kn ow in g wh e the r Ca rn ap w ou ld have app roved

    of my

    B ayes ian read ing

    o f

    K u h n .

    But I do

    claim tha t

    it is a

    read ing

    t ha t

    fi ts

    na tu ra l l y wi th Carnap 's mature v iews

    on

    probabil i ty

    an d

    induc t ion .

    8 Objectivityand the Problem of

    Consensus

    I haveendorsed a Bayesianized version of Kuhn ' s c l a im tha t in sci-

    enti f ic revolut ions persuasion ra ther than proof is the order o f the

    d a y :

    revolut ions

    involve the in t roduct ion of new possibilities; this

    in t roduc t ion causes the redistribution of probabilit ies; the redistri-

    but ion isguided b y

    plausibi l i ty

    a r g u m e n t s ; an d such a rguments be -

    long to the art of persuasion.

    This

    endo r semen t

    is

    conf ined

    to the firststage of the

    revolut ion,

    when

    the

    ini t ia l

    probabilit ies are established for the expanded pos-

    sibility set. The Bayes ian fo lk lo re would have it that after thisfirst

    stage, s o m e t h i n g

    more

    ak in

    toproof

    than persuasion operates.

    The

    idea

    is

    that

    an

    evidence-driven consensus emerges

    as a

    result

    of the

    Bayesian l e a rn ing model:degrees of belief change by conditional -

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    21/29

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    22/29

    2 )

    C a r n a p , K u l i i i , a n d th e Philosophyof

    Scienti f ic

    Methodo logy

    a p robab i l i t y f u n c l i o n . If th i s were

    corrccl, ihc liaycsian

    ver s ion o f

    llie

    problem

    o f

    scicnl i f ic

    objectivi ty

    would

    be

    made

    correspondingly

    easier.

    However,

    I do not

    think

    that Carnapmanaged tostakeout a

    d e f ens i b l e position, as can be brought out by the question of how

    one recognizes wh i ch probability functionsare rational. Carnap's

    a n s w e r

    w as toappeal towhat

    he

    variously called inductive

    i n t u i l i o n "

    and induclivc common

    sense.

    The trouble, of course, isthat one

    person's i n d u c t i v e common sense

    is

    another's i n duc t i ve non-sense.

    So the appea l to i n t u i t i o n reveals

    very

    diffcrenl opinions as lo

    whelhcr

    i t is rat ional to

    learn from

    experience

    at all

    and,

    if so, at

    w h a t rate.

    A t

    th isjuncture

    il

    wil l

    b e

    he l p fu l

    to

    review

    a

    mechanism

    proposed

    by L e h r e i an d Wagner in

    Ra t i ona l

    C o n s e n s u s in Science a n d Society

    (1981) for achieving agroupconsensus.Their mechanism requires

    t h a t

    th e

    members of ihc community

    change ihcir

    degrees o f bel ief

    in

    accordance wi lh

    a

    wcighled-aggrcgalion

    ru le .

    Suppose that

    a t

    the

    i n i t i a l

    m o m e n t , person

    i has a

    degree

    o f bel ief /;, in the theory in

    question.

    Each

    person i is

    assumed

    to

    assign

    a

    weigh t

    w/

    0 to

    every

    person

    _ ; ' , w h i c h can be

    taken

    as an index of i ' s

    opinion

    as to

    th e

    re l iab i l i ty

    of/s opinions. According toLchrcr a n d Wagner's r u l e , i

    t he n improves her i n i l i a lopinion /> ? b ychanging it topi = X,w,y/>".

    If there arc

    still

    differences of opinion, the aggregation processis

    repeated

    w i th

    the /;,' to obtain

    f u r t h e r

    improved probabilities

    /;?,

    etc., u n t i l e v e n t u a l l y the

    probabi l i t ies

    for a l l

    members

    fall

    into

    l ine .

    Lchrcr and

    Wagner

    o f f e r aconsistencya rg u m e n t for

    their

    aggre-

    ga t ion ru le : If a

    person re fuses

    toaggregate,

    though

    hedoes

    assign

    a

    posi t ivew e i g h t

    to

    other

    members,he is

    acting

    as

    though heassigned

    aweightof

    one

    toh imse l fand aweightofzerotoevery

    other

    member

    of

    thegroup.If, in fact,he assignspositiveweightto

    other

    members

    of th egroup, ihenheshould nolbeha veas ifheassigned zero we igh t

    lo them (1981, 22).Thisargumenthas the flavor of When arc you

    going

    to

    slop b e a t i n gyour

    wife ." I d o

    assign

    a ,

    positive weight

    to the

    o p i n i o n s

    of

    others,

    but as a

    liaycsian

    I do

    this

    not by

    means

    of

    weigh ted aggregation b u t

    by c on d i t i on a l i z a t i on :

    I co nd i t i o na l i zc on

    i n f o r m a t i o n about the opinions o f m y

    peers,

    a n d I notice that th e

    result

    is a sh i f t in mydegreesof belief toward thedegreesof belief

    of those I respect.When I was ayoungstudent,

    these shif ts

    brought

    .m y

    opinions

    closely in

    line

    wi th

    those

    belonging topeople Iregarded

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    23/29

    3

    John

    lirmun

    as the expert s , but as a m at ur e m em ber of the com m un i ty , I f ind

    tha t

    such

    shifts,

    whi le

    still

    n onn egl ig ib lc , do no t

    c o n f o rm

    m y

    o p i n i o n s

    lo

    those

    of

    others,

    a t

    least

    no t on mat ters

    where

    I now

    regard myself

    as an expert . A n d I res is t any further

    a t t em pt

    to

    bend

    m y

    careful ly

    considered opinions .

    There

    are tw o

    reasons,

    i n d e p e n d e n t

    o f

    Bayes ian ism,

    to be

    u n h a p p y

    with Lehrer an d

    Wagner 's proposal

    an d ones like i t . The first is

    t h a t

    it is

    descriptively

    false, as shown by the very

    e x amp l e

    they

    use

    to

    motivate the i r proposal. In the 1970s Robert Dicke claimed that

    optical

    measurement s

    of the

    solar disk revealed

    an

    oblateness large

    enou g h to accoun t for 3" to 5" of arc in Mercury ' s centenary per i -

    helion ad v ance an d thus to throw in to

    doubt

    Eins te in ' s explanat ion

    of

    th e

    a d v a n c e . W h e n

    o th e r

    as trophysicis ts disagreed with Dicke ' s

    conclusions the

    d i f ferences were

    n o t

    smoothed over

    b y

    p r od u c ing

    a

    consensual probabi l i ty

    by

    means

    of a

    w eighted aggreg ation process.

    The d i s a g reem en t

    remains unreso lved

    to

    this day.

    T he

    weight

    of

    op in ion

    docs

    seem

    lo

    be

    go ing

    aga ins t

    D icke's in lcrp rc ta t ion , but

    this

    part ial ag r e e me n t

    is in

    fact

    due not toag gregation but to the acq ui-

    sition

    of

    addi t ional ev idence .

    Of course,Lchrcr an d W a g n e r are

    perfectly

    aw ar e of these facts,

    an d

    the

    descr ip t ive

    inadequac ies

    of the i r proposal do no t concern

    t hem,s ince they

    take

    them selves to be off er in g a n orm ativeproposal.

    B ut

    even

    in

    ihcsc t e r ms

    the

    proposal should

    be

    f au l t ed .

    It is

    f u n d a -

    m en ta l

    lo science thai opin ions be evidence-dr iven . Differences of

    opin ion

    need

    not

    constilutc

    an

    emb arrassmen t that

    needs

    lo

    be

    quashed ,

    for ihesc

    d i f fe rences

    can

    serve

    as a

    spur

    lo

    fu r the r

    iheo-

    relical

    an d experimental research, and the new in fo rmat ion p ro -

    duced may d r ive a gen u in e scientific consensus . The

    al ternat ive,

    an

    a t l cmpl lo m a n u f a c lu r e aconsensus by a w eighted-aggrega tion pro-

    cedure, smacks

    of the

    "mob psychology"

    of

    which

    K u h n w as

    criticized.

    This

    last point generalizes. Bayesianism

    an d

    other approaches

    to

    scienlific in fe rence

    aswell

    suggest that unless

    there is

    some evidence-

    dr iven

    process that

    operates

    on the level of ind iv idualscientists to

    produceagroupconsensus ,ihe

    consensus willa m o u n l

    lo

    someth ing

    tha t ,

    if not mob psychology, is nevertheless a social art ifact not de-

    serving ei ther of the labels "rational" or "scienlific."

    Thus,

    con l rary

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    24/29

    C a r n a p ,

    K u l i n ,

    a n d

    the

    Phi losophy of Scientif ic Methodology

    to K u h n ' s idea,

    th egroupc a n n o t

    decideit

    can no t r a t ion a l ly dec ide

    to

    agree if

    the i n d i v i d u a l s

    disagree.

    I do not see how

    th is con clus ion

    can be escaped

    u n l e s ssome

    y et tobe a r t icula ted

    collcct ivisl m e th o d -

    ology is show n lobe viable .

    9 A

    Partial Resolution

    to the Problem ofConsensus

    Part of the

    an s w e r

    to the Bayes ian

    version

    of the

    problem

    of

    consen-

    sus isthat q ui te of ten itdoes n o t exist an d does n o t

    need

    toexist for

    normal sc ient i f ic

    research

    to

    take place.

    S t ruc t u r e

    warned

    of the

    d a n -

    ger of

    t ak ing t ex tbook science as our image of how real

    science

    actual ly operates,

    and in

    par t icu lar ,

    it

    showed

    how

    textbook science

    t e n d s lo m a k e scienti fic r evo l u t i on s

    i nv i s ib le

    b y p a i n t i n g an ov e r l y

    rosy p ic tureof asm ooth ly ac cu m ula t in g s tockp ileof scientific k n o w l -

    edge. B u t

    I t h i n k t h a t St ruc ture fai led to emphas ize how textbook

    science also disguises

    the

    d ivers i ty of opin ions and approaches that

    f lour i sh in n o n r c v o l u t i o n a r y science.

    If I had the space, 1w o u l d

    o f f e r

    as a case s t u d y the

    d e v e l op m e n t

    of relativisticg r av i t a t ion a lresearch over the last

    seven ty-f ive-years .

    19

    Textbooks

    in th is

    area

    have t ended to

    be

    books on E in s t e i n ' s G TR ,

    t h u s fos ter ing

    th e i l lusion t ha t

    G T R h a sachieved

    the

    s tatus of

    para -

    d igm

    h e g e m o n y .

    In addi t ion , ear ly textbooks n o t on ly d ow np lay ed

    the exis tence o f r ival theories b u t disguised ser ious difficul t ies w i t h

    tw o

    of

    the

    p r i nc ip a le x p e r i m e n t al tests ofG T R , the red

    shif t

    an d

    the

    b e n d i n g

    o f

    l ig h t . N o r m a l

    scientif ic

    research

    in

    this

    field

    c o n t in u e d

    in

    the face of

    bo th

    a cha l lenge lo the th i rd exper imenta l

    leg

    o f G T R

    d e r i v i n g from D icke' ssolar-oblatenessm easurem en ts and a lso an ever

    g r o w i n g n u m b e r o f

    r ival theories

    o f

    gravi tat ion.

    This and s im i l a r

    e x a m p l e ssuggest

    t h a t n o r m a lscience

    is possiblew h e n thec o m m u n i ty

    ofexperts

    share

    a

    parad igm

    in the

    weak sense

    of

    ag r eemen t

    on the

    ex p l ana t o r y d oma in

    of the field, on the

    c i rcumscr ip t ion

    of the

    space

    of

    possible theories

    to be

    considered

    as

    ser ious candidates

    for

    cov-

    ering

    the

    ex p l ana t o r y d oma in ,

    on

    exemplars

    of

    explanatory success,

    and on key aux i l i a ryhypotheses. (I am

    t empted

    to say

    tha t this

    is the

    m i n i m a l

    sense o f parad igm needed to

    u n d e r w r i t e

    normal sc ience ,

    b u t h is tor ians o f sc ience probably have counterexamples w a i t i n g in

    thewings . )

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    25/29

    John Kaim an

    One could a rgue t ha t n o t h a v i n g a pa rad igm in th e stricter sense

    of

    a shared

    theory

    of

    gravi ta t ion has

    lowered

    the puzzle-solving

    efficiency

    of normal science. One can recal lThornca n d Will 's (1971)

    l a m e n t

    thai , faced wi th

    a zoo of

    a l tern a t iv e theor ies

    of

    g r a v i t a t i o n ,

    astrophysicists where

    hamstrung in thei r model -bui ld ing activity.

    While I

    t h i n k t ha t this

    is a fa ir

    observa t ion ,

    I

    also

    t h i n k

    tha t there

    is

    more

    toprogressinn o rm a l

    science

    tha n puzzle solving. In particular,

    I would

    emphas ize

    the conceptua l advances derived f rom

    the

    explo-

    ration of the

    space

    of

    possible theories,

    a

    po in t tha t br ings

    me to the

    second part

    o f my

    par t ia l answer

    to the

    problem

    of

    consensus.

    Again , if I had the space, I wo uld argue tha t in sofar as a consensus

    is

    established, it is often due to a

    process

    akin to the much

    maligned

    idea of e l imina t ivc i n d u c t i o n . T h is process isoften accomp an ied b y

    a proliferation of

    theories,

    not as an exercise in

    Feyerabendian

    an-

    a rchy

    or

    D a d a i s m ,

    but as a

    m e a n s

    of

    p ro b i n g

    the

    possibilities

    and as

    a p r e l i m i n a r yto deve lop ing a classification scheme tha t ma kes sys-

    tematic

    e l imina t ion

    a t ractable

    exercise.

    20

    T he

    e l i m i n a t i o n

    is no t

    of

    the s i m p l c m i n d c d Sher lock Holmes var ie ty ,

    for it

    involves

    B ayesian

    e lements , especially

    in the

    assessment

    of the

    auxi l i a ry a s sumpt ions

    needed to b r i n g a b o u t a conf ron ta t ion o f theory an d e x p e r i m e n t .

    Thus

    the Baycsianizcd versionof the

    problem

    ofconsensus

    remains .

    An d a t the p r e sen t

    t i m e

    I do n ot see any

    reso lut ion tha tdoes

    n ot

    f a l l

    back

    on s o m e t h i n g l ike the def in i t iona l so lu t ion , which I casually

    dismissed in th e preceding sec t ion . Such a fallback un de rm i n es sci-

    en t i f i c

    objectivi ty

    in a way tha t

    wo u l d

    n o t

    have pleased

    C a r n a p

    a n d ,

    I

    p r e s u m e , docs n o t please

    K u h n

    c i t he r .

    10

    Conclusion

    I

    was a

    d is tan t

    s t u d e n t of C a rn a p and a c lose s tudent of K u h n .B u t

    the two seemed to me so d i f f er en t in s tyle and concerns that I placed

    them in d i f f e ren t pa r t s of the phi losophical f i rmament . O n l y n ow

    have

    I begun to apprec ia te how mi sgu ided m y p l acemen t was and

    how m u c h phi losophyof science can be

    enr iched

    b ycons ider ing how

    the ideas of these tw o gian ts in terac t . I have

    presented

    one way to

    stage the in terac t ion .There are su rely bet ter ones. Iurge more able

    hands

    to

    take

    up the task.

    21

  • 8/11/2019 Earman - Carnap, Kuhn, And the Philosophy of Scientific Methodology

    26/29

    33

    C a r n a p , K u l i n , an d

    th e

    Phi losophy

    of Scientific

    Methodology

    Notes

    Sections6-9

    of

    th is

    paper arc