the culture of myth and the myth of culture

40
1 The Culture of Myth and the Myth of Culture Ken Gemes and Chris Sykes A version of this appears in Individual and Community in Nietzsche’s Philosophy, ed. J. Young, Cambridge University Press 2014

Upload: birkbeck

Post on 22-Feb-2023

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

1

The Culture of Myth and the Myth of Culture

Ken Gemes and Chris Sykes

A version of this appears in Individual and Community in Nietzsche’s Philosophy, ed. J. Young, Cambridge University Press 2014

2

Culture [Bildung] is a continuous

replacement of illusions

[Wahnvorstellungen] with more noble

ones. (NF 1870 5[91]2)

1. Introduction

Nietzsche’s Birth of Tragedy(hereafter BT) promotes the claim that illusion is necessary for

“existence and the world to appear justified” (BT 24: p.113). This claim from the early

Nietzsche resonates with the claim of the later Nietzsche of Genealogy of Morals(GM) that

the key function of the religious ascetic ideal, itself clearly an illusion by Nietzsche’s light, is

that it serves to give meaning to existence and thus makes existence bearable (see GM III

28):

[H]e [man] did not know how to justify, explain, affirm himself: he suffered from the

problem of his meaning. He suffered otherwise as ill, he was for the most part a

diseased animal; but the suffering itself was not his problem, rather that the answer

was missing to the scream of his question: “to what end suffering?” Man, the bravest

of animals and the one most accustomed to suffering, does not negate suffering, he

wants it, he even seeks it out, provided one shows him a meaning for it, a to-this-end

of suffering. The meaninglessness of suffering, not suffering itself, was the curse

2 Nietzsche’s notebook entries (Nachgelassene Fragmente [NF] are taken from the Kritische

Gesamtausagabe (ed. G.Colli and M. Montinari 1967-77). Translations are our own, guided

by L.Loeb’s translations in Writings from the Early Notebooks 2009.

3

thus far stretched over humanity. (GM III 28 - italics indicates Nietzsche’ emphasis,

bold indicates our emphasis).

A central claim of this paper is that for Nietzsche it is the question of meaning rather than

the question of suffering that is paramount. This suggests that the recent trend of analysing

Nietzsche through the prism of his relationship to Schopenhauer should be tempered by a

perspective that gives more emphasis to his relationship with Wagner; it is from Wagner,

more than Schopenhauer, that Nietzsche takes the theme that the problem of

meaninglessness is THE problem of modernity.

Another central claim of this paper is that the very values Nietzsche seems to promote as

secular replacements for previous meaning-giving religious values, namely culture and the

cultivation of great individuals or genius, are by the lights of Nietzsche’s BT already

recognized as illusions. Above Nietzsche tells us that culture replaces old illusions with new

ones; this allows that culture itself is one of those very illusions. In subsequent works,

where Nietzsche valorises culture and the great individuals who are the engines of cultural

development, there is little, if any, explicit register that these values are newly minted

illusions. This can give rise to the idea that Nietzsche is positing culture and genius as

objective values or as (his own) subjective values. But if we focus on what is said in BT we

allow the perspective that these values are not naively posited and endorsed but are

consciously deployed as illusions useful for the modern age. From this perspective his key

objection to previous illusions, explicitly the Socratic illusion of rationalism, and, implicitly,

the illusions of Christianity, is not that they are illusions (that are false) but they are no

longer useful illusions for the modern world. The BT of 1872 does not explicitly point the

finger at Christianity, though Nietzsche in his new Preface to BT of 1886 somewhat

4

questionably claims that BT has implicit reference to the illusions of Christianity through “its

consistently cautious and hostile silence about Christianity” (BT, ASC, 5).Nevertheless

Nietzsche is right that the critique of BT can equally be applied to and Christianity and

Socratism, even if BT only explicitly targets the latter. What Nietzsche does not say in ASC is

that his subsequent critiques of Christianity place less emphasis on the claim that

Christianity is no longer a useful illusion (but see Gay Science 125 for a more ambivalent

rendition of this claim) and more on the claim that it is an illusion that is hostile to life (see

GM III passim and Antichrist 56). But this important difference in the emphasis of his later

attack on Christianity should not lead us to lose focus on the claim made explicitly in BT that

the new values of culture and genius are themselves illusions.

Whether the later Nietzsche stills see the newly posited values of culture and genius as

illusions but, perhaps, for motivational and rhetorical reasons, no longer explicitly

emphasises this point, or has come to a new conception of values that would no longer

render them as illusions, or has simply by-passed the whole question of the metaphysical

status of values, is an important question we shall here leave for another day. What we do

want to argue here is that as Nietzsche develops he moves from an optimistic, what Julian

Young (this volume) has called a communitarian view, which sees culture as a value to which

all may aspire, to a more pessimistic view that sees culture as the provenance of a very

restricted elite. From the perspective of BT we might say that the notions of culture and

genius become illusions Nietzsche develops in order to help cultivate the gifted few.

2. Mythical Narratives and Narratives of Myth

5

Nietzsche’s early project of the period 1870-1876 is best viewed as a project of

understanding the ways in which cultures are able to perpetuate myths which allow their

members to affirm life despite its horrors. Specifically, in order for life to be worth living, it

must be meaningful, but man “now sees everywhere only the horror or absurdity of

existence ... now he understands the wisdom of Silenus” (BT 7). This ‘wisdom of Silenus’ is a

placeholder for existential nihilism: life has no meaning, and it is only thanks to culture,

itself a form of illusion, that existence has the semblance of meaning, and is thereby made

bearable.3 Nietzsche’s notebook entries of the time repeatedly make the point;

“Illusions [Wahnvorstellungen]: for those who see through them, art [Kunst] is

the only solace [Trost].” (NF 1870 5[26]).

“Culture [Kultur] – the rule of art over life.” (NF 1872 19[310]). “This proposition

must be established: we live only through illusions [Illusionen]” (NF 1872

19[49]).

“Every kind of culture [Kultur] begins by veiling [verschleiert] many things.”

(19[50]).

3 Nietzsche can be read as holding the substantive thesis that life is meaningless, or

alternatively as claiming that life appears to be meaningless to those ‘nobler natures’ raised

on a diet of Schopenhauerian Weltschmerz and Wagner. On the second reading he is

advancing a psychological thesis that life must appear to have meaning for us, if we are to

be able to live it. In his later philosophy Nietzsche’s focus shifts increasingly towards

psychological questions of the latter kind, to the exclusion of substantive metaphysics. In BT

he often appears to hold both a metaphysical and a psychological thesis.

6

“All that lives, lives on illusion [Schein].” (NF 1870 7[167]).

“Pain, contradiction, is the true being [Sein]. Joy, harmony is illusion [Schein]”

(NF 1870 7[165]).

If existential nihilism is an objective, mind-independent metaphysical fact, it appears that

culture cannot demonstrate to us that life is not absurd; it can merely distract us from the

fact that it is absurd, imposing a semblance of meaning on the chaos. This beautiful

semblance stops short of giving life genuine meaningfulness; existential nihilism is not

defeated but merely taken from view, papered over as it were. As discussed below, when

Nietzsche proposes that “[t]he individual must be consecrated to something higher than

himself…” (Untimely Meditations IV, hereafter Untimely Meditations are referred to as UM),

(this something being ‘culture’), this proposition can be read as Nietzsche’s new illusion.

Culture is not in fact ‘higher’ than the individual in a metaphysical sense; it is higher in an

affective, hence psychologically motivating and existentially consoling, sense.

Both the “artiste’s metaphysics” (BT ASC 2) of BT and the narrative of culture in the UM are

self-consciously written as mythic narratives which aim to make existence bearable. These

works move between the perspectives of a meta-narrative which outlines the overarching

framework of illusion required in order to find life meaningful, and various first-order

narratives which seek to provide such illusions.4 In the first eighteen sections of BT there is

a first order narrative of metaphysical redemption as experienced by the Attic Greeks. In

the later sections of BT and in UM there is a first order narrative of culture and genius,

4 For more on the different levels of narrative see the excellent discussion in Poellner

(1998).

7

conceived of as an analogue of the myths of Attic Greece useful for contemporary culture.

Both of these first order narratives offer the “metaphysical solace” which Nietzsche in the

early works takes to be necessary for the affirmation of existence. Myth is not only that

which can seduce us back to life in spite of its horrors, it is a pre-requisite for cultural

flourishing since

without myth every culture loses the healthy natural power of its creativity: only a

horizon defined by myths completes and unifies a whole cultural movement. (BT 24)

While Nietzsche never actually gives an account of what he means by myth his usage

suggests the following as a serviceable definition of his core notion: Myth is a literally fictive

narrative encompassing symbolical archetypes that help provide a structural unity to

experience and life.6

The need for solace provided by myth is contingent on a pessimistic understanding of

(phenomenal) reality as comprised of instrumental, self-serving desire; an endless ‘flux’

devoid of ‘higher ideals’. The natural world does not contain the kind of values which we

take to be necessary to give meaning to our lives, and this leads Nietzsche to the conclusion

6Poellner (1998) identifies three senses of ‘myth’ which are operative in the early Nietzsche:

Myth as a narrative which connects day to day reality with an underlying a-temporal

metaphysical ground in an oblique fashion not fully discursively interrogable; myth as a

narrative that juxtaposes transient human life to this ground in a manner which allows this

life to be viewed “in a certain sense, sub specie aeterni” (Poellner 1998: 64); and, finally,

myth as a false story.

8

that illusion (in the texts variously Illusionen, Wahn and Schein), and specifically myth, are

necessary to make bearable one’s experience of the world. The pessimism of BT is

manifested in the claim that philosophical theodicy – the enterprise of offering a rational

justification for existence, is impossible.7 This pessimism is to be overcome through artistic

illusion:

The only possibility of life: art. Otherwise a turning away from life. The complete

annihilation of illusion [Illusion] is the drive of the sciences: it would be followed by

quietism – were it not for art.” (NF 1869 3[60]);

My philosophy is an inverted Platonism: the further something is from true being,

the purer, the more beautiful, the better it is. Living in illusion [Schein] as the goal.”

(NF 1870 7[156])

3. Nietzsche and Wagner versus Schopenhauer on the Problem of Pessimism

Nietzsche’s early admiration for Schopenhauer is well known, and is clearly demonstrated

by the “Schopenhauerian formulations” (BT ASC 6) in which much of BT is couched. This has

7 There is a distinction to be made between an epistemically rational justification and the

kind of prudential justification predicated on the necessity of illusion that Nietzsche

recommends. Deliberate use of illusion can only be part of a prudential, not epistemic,

justification. We may be prudentially justified in accepting illusions which are evidentially

unwarranted but we cannot be epistemically justified in accepting such illusions.

9

led some to claim that in BT Nietzsche helps himself to Schopenhauer’s metaphysics.8 It

appears that the ‘wisdom of Silenus’ is Schopenhauer’s pessimistic conception of reality as a

manifestation of a raging and unquenchable will expressed in terms of ‘folk wisdom’, rather

than in terms of transcendental metaphysics. Schopenhauer conceives of phenomenal

reality as the expression of the metaphysical Will’s endless ‘blind striving’. To will is to

suffer; so, being essentially creatures of will, we necessarily suffer. Satisfaction can only be

conceived of negatively, as the absence of such striving. Although the diagnosis that life

appears to be meaningless looks like a direct borrowing from Schopenhauer, we should

note two qualifications. On the one hand, the claim that life has no value might be made,

not from the perspective of a metaphysician, but from the perspective of a cultural critic.

Our modern predicament, is that we now no longer view life as having meaning, and it is

8 See, for example, Young (1992: 26), Soll (1988: 109). However Chris Janaway’s essay

“Nietzsche as Schopenhauer’s Educator” in Janaway (1998) and Appendix I of Janaway

(1998), being Janaway’s translation of Nietzsche’ unpunished essay of 1868, “On

Schopenhauer”, also published in Writings from the Early Notebooks (WEN: 1-9), clearly

demonstrate Nietzsche’s early skepticism towards Schopenhauer’s metaphysics of the will

as thing-in-itself. A similar claim is made in Staten (1990). Indeed, we would argue that in

BT Nietzsche disingenuously peddles this Schopenhauerian metaphysics primarily as a way

of elevating Wagner. Schopenhauer claims music is the highest art form as it allows the

most direct access possible to the Will. So Wagner, in Nietzsche’s BT is presented as the

modern musician par excellence; a conduit to the allegedly most profound knowledge. This

is part of Nietzsche’s deliberate Wagner mythology.

10

this Weltanshauung that needs to be addressed, rather than any alleged metaphysical fact

about the meaninglessness of existence. Secondly, there is an important difference in

emphasis between Schopenhauer and Nietzsche’s respective accounts of the

meaninglessness of life. Life is meaningless, for Schopenhauer, because desire cannot

achieve final satisfaction. Life would have meaning, conversely, if we could attain whatever

it is that we fundamentally desire. For Schopenhauer there is not a qualitative distinction

between the will’s different potential ends. The various different ends individuals may have

are, in effect, legitimated by the individuals’ desire for them. This meaninglessness would

indeed be overcome if in fact those desires could be satisfied. In the final analysis, though,

this is impossible, according to Schopenhauer, and so life cannot have meaning. Any

illusions we might have to the contrary are pernicious, as they give us false hope that our

endeavours can be justified.

Nietzsche differs importantly in how he understands the existential problem of meaning.

Already in the early works, there is an implicit qualitative distinction in the kinds of goals

that we might pursue. What makes life objectively meaningless, is the lack of the kinds of

goals that would give it true significance. He champions myth as the means of overcoming

nihilistic feelings because myth offers a way of addressing this existential need. Myth

provides narratives which links up an otherwise insignificant life to an overarching

metaphysical worldview. Hence, as observed above, it is not the suffering (the unquenched

desires) which human beings have to endure which causes people to despair of life but its

insignificance:

…a people – or for that matter, a human being – only has value to the extent

that it is able to put the stamp of the eternal on its experiences; for in doing so it

11

sheds, one might say, its worldliness and reveals its unconscious, inner

conviction that time is relative and that the true meaning of life is metaphysical.

(BT 23)

Note, Nietzsche does not here assert that the meaning of life is metaphysical. He

merely highlights the function of the conviction that the meaning of life is

metaphysical. The Greeks are Nietzsche’s paradigm of a people saturated in myth

who were “compelled to connect everything they experienced, immediately and

involuntarily, to their myths…thereby even the most immediate present was bound to

appear to them straight away sub specie aeterni and, in a certain sense, as timeless.”

(BT 23). This paean to myth is certainly not limited to BT. It occurs repeatedly in the

early works. Only by internalizing a narrative, which gives one a sense of significance

over and above everyday reality, can the individual succeed in overcoming their

existential malaise:

All living things require an atmosphere around them, a mysterious misty vapor;

if they are deprived of this envelope, if a religion, an art, a genius is condemned

to revolve as a star without an atmosphere, we should no longer be surprised if

they quickly wither and grow unfruitful. It is the same with all great things,

‘which never succeed without illusion [Wahn]’, as Hans Sachs says in the

Meistersinger. (UM II, Section 7)

This reference to Wagner’s opera is revealing. The slant that Nietzsche places on

Schopenhauerian pessimism can plausibly be seen as owing much to Wagner’s own

idiosyncratic interpretation of Schopenhauer the philosopher. As we discuss below,

Wagner’s mythologies can be seen as attempting to imbue the all-too-human with a

12

magnificence and grandeur that life viewed outside of the aesthetic experience of the

theatre appeared to lack. Myth similarly occupies the central role in early Nietzsche for

fulfilling this distinctive role. In his discussion of Schopenhauer in UM III, Nietzsche himself

indicates that what he learned from Schopenhauer was precisely this feeling of the

meaninglessness of existence as the genuine pessimistic challenge, rather than the lack of

hedonic satisfaction which life provides;

[Schopenhauer]…teaches us to distinguish between those things that really

promote human happiness and those that only appear to do so: how neither

riches nor honors nor erudition can lift the individual out of the profound

depression he feels at the valuelessness of his existence, and how striving after

these valued things acquires meaning only through an exalted and

transfiguring overall goal: to acquire power so as to aid the evolution of the

physis and to be for a while the corrector of its follies and ineptitudes. At first

only for yourself, to be sure; but through yourself in the end for everyone… (UM

III p.142, bold added).

Think of the case of Sisyphus’s goal of pushing his boulder up to the top of a hill, which is

doomed to fail in perpetuity as it is cursed always to roll down again before it can reach the

top. If Sisyphus could reach the top, on Schopenhauer’s understanding, then the boulder

rolling would be meaningful. In contrast to this, Nietzsche tends towards seeing the boulder

rolling as meaningless because the goal itself is meaningless, and reaching the goal would

not change this fact. Enduring the suffering that addends boulder-rolling is possible, only if

the rolling is set in the context of an “exalted and transfiguring overall goal”. Suffering is a

problem for modern culture, according to Nietzsche, because, unlike the Attic Greeks, we

13

lack a compelling narrative in which to contextualise suffering, and give the suffering

meaning. His proposed ideal of working towards culture and the genius can be seen as a

narrative that can provide us with a sense of meaningfulness that we lack.

“For the question is this: how can your life, the individual life, receive the highest

value, the deepest significance? How can it least be squandered? Certainly only

by your living for the good of the rarest and most valuable exemplars, and not

for the good of the majority, that is to say those who, taken individually, are the

least valuable exemplars.” (UM III:6).

4. Three Types of Comforting Illusion

Nietzsche analyses three distinct types of illusion which work at the level of culture as

“exquisite stimulants” (BT 18), by which the individual is “tricked” into believing life has

meaning, and is thus worth living. He concludes “[e]verything we call culture consists in

such stimulants” (BT 18):

It is an eternal phenomenon: by means of an illusion [Illusion] spread over

things, the greedy Will always finds some way of detaining its creatures in life

and forcing them to carry on living. One person is held fast by the Socratic

pleasure in understanding and by the illusion [Wahn] that he can thereby heal

the eternal wound of existence; another is ensnared by art’s seductive veil of

beauty fluttering before his eyes; a third by the metaphysical solace that eternal

life flows on indestructibly beneath the turmoil of appearances - to say nothing

of the commoner and almost more powerful illusions [Illusionen] which the Will

14

constantly holds in readiness. Indeed, these three levels of illusion

[Illusionenstufen] are only for those equipped with nobler natures, who

generally feel the burden and heaviness of being with more profound aversion

and who have been tricked by exquisite stimulants into ignoring their aversion.

Everything we call culture consists of such stimulants; depending on the

proportion of the mixture, we have a culture which is predominately Socratic or

artistic or tragic; or, if historical illustrations are permitted, a culture is either

Alexandrian or Hellenic or Buddhistic. (BT 18, emphasis ours)

The Socratic illusion is the illusion most pertinent to the hyper-rationalism and scientism of

modernity. It works by propagating the false belief that “the depths of nature can be

fathomed and knowledge can heal all ills.” (BT 17). An artistic (or Apollonian) culture diverts

our attention away from the objectionable nature of life by focussing our energies on the

adoration of beautiful form. The tragic works by the illusion of a “metaphysical solace”. It

fosters the belief in a unity which underlies the apparent world, and offers the myth that in

death, the individual will find redemption and reunification with the reality beneath

appearance.

Socratic man in his nobler mode does not view knowledge and science instrumentally, as

the means of getting what he wants. Socratism in its higher manifestations (e.g. as in the

case of Socrates himself) is a ‘faith’ [glaube] in the ultimate value of knowledge. In Kantian

terminology, for the noble Socratic man, the pursuit of knowledge is an end in itself.

Science and knowledge are not venerated in noble Socratic culture simply for their

perceived instrumental utility, but for their being constitutive of what is truly valuable. It is

for this reason that Nietzsche describes Socrates as the “mystagogue of wisdom

15

[Mystagogen der Wissenschaft] (BT 15). He is the high priest of a new kind of quasi-religious

‘ideal’. As mystagogue, he is the initiator into what is effectively a new mystery cult, one

premised on the intrinsic value of Wissenschaft. Socrates is

“the first man who was capable, not just of living by the instinct of science, but

also, and this is much more, of dying by it. This is why the image of the dying

Socrates, of a man liberated from fear of death by reasons and knowledge, is the

heraldic shield over the portals of wisdom, reminding everyone of its purpose,

which is to make existence appear comprehensible and thus justified; and if

reasons are insufficient to achieve that end, then it must ultimately be served by

myth – which I have just defined as the necessary consequence, indeed

intention, of science.” (BT 15)

To the extent that we are ‘held fast by our faith in science’ and ‘the Socratic pleasure in

understanding’, our life takes on the appearance of meaningfulness.Socrates is

the teacher of an altogether new form of ‘Greek cheerfulness’ and blissful affirmation

of existence [„griechischen Heiterkeit“ und Daseinsseligkeit] that seeks to discharge

itself in actions – most often in maieutic and educational influences on noble youths,

with a view to eventually producing a genius. (BT 15)

Noble Socratism is clearly a form of mystification, a false narrative which nevertheless gives

a sense of meaning and purpose to existence: “Even then that metaphysical drive still

attempts to create for itself a kind of transfiguration [Verklärung], albeit in a much weaker

form, in the Socratism of wisdom…” (BT 23)

16

Late Socratic culture, as manifested in the modern world, rests less on noble Socratics claim

that truth is valuable in itself and more on the belief that reality is correctable through the

application of knowledge.12 Suffering is interpreted as the result of a contingent state of

ignorance which reason has the power to overcome. It expresses “a profound illusion

[Wahnvorstellung]… that thought … is capable not simply of understanding existence, but

even of correcting it.” (BT 15). As Nietzsche describes,

…it puts in the place of a metaphysical solace a form of earthly harmony, indeed

its very own deus ex machine, namely the god of machines and smelting

furnaces, i.e. the energies of the spirit of nature, understood and applied in the

service of higher egotism; it believes in correcting the world through knowledge,

in life led by science. (BT 17).

Nietzsche offers two main reasons why late Socratism is declining, and why any new myth

which would replace it cannot be parasitic on its central elements. Socratism valorises the

pursuit of truth as life’s most valuable activity. But pursuing truth has the side-effect of

uncovering the falsity of the very presuppositions on which the Socratic high estimation of

truth is built. As we come to understand the true nature of life we realize the inevitability of

suffering and thus uncover the lie of Socratic optimism.14 Nietzsche also claims that late

12Nietzsche does not explicitly distinguish between noble Socratism in its vital, healthy form,

and Socratism in its late, degenerate or decadent manifestation. Nevertheless the

distinction is implicit.

14 This foreshadows Nietzsche’s later understanding of the will to truth as a sublimated form

of self-cruelty. “Has not man’s self-deprecation, his will to self-deprecation, been

17

Socratism is socially and politically unstable. Its ‘optimism’ gives rise to unrealistic social

aspirations on the part of the disaffected members of society, or ‘slave’ class. Socratism’s

characteristic ‘optimism’ – the belief that earthly harmony and happiness are attainable

goals – expresses belief in a worldly ‘deus ex machina’. Whereas religion typically consoles

through the belief that a god will right wrongs in a life to come, the Socratic worldview

hopes for restitution and justice in the here and now. The empirical world is felt to operate

according to moral principles, such that through the passage of time and the application of

human endeavour, ‘things will turn out for the best.’ This widely held belief, when

manifested at the local level of the socially disaffected and politically ostracised ‘slave class’,

breeds the false belief that “earthly happiness for all” (BT 18) is a viable political goal. This,

however, is false since society requires, according to Nietzsche’s draconian view, a slave

class for its continuation. This class has until now been held in check by ideological false

beliefs which reinforce the existing social order; for example the belief in the ‘dignity of

work’. As this illusion collapses, the slave class demands a reconfiguration of society, which

is in fact impossible.

…[T]he fruits of this optimism ripen, when the acid of this kind of culture trickles

down to the very lowest levels of our society, so that it gradually beings to

tremble from burgeoning surges and desires, when the belief in the earthly

happiness of all, when the belief that such a general culture of knowledge is

unstoppably on the increase since Copernicus?” (GM III 25). The will to truth eventually

uncovers its own mendacious roots, for while it presents itself as a will to objectively

understand it is eventually exposed as a highly subjective manifestation of the life denying

ascetic ideal.

18

possible, gradually transforms itself into the menacing demand for such

Alexandrian happiness on earth, into the invocation of a Euripidean deus ex

machina! It should be noted that Alexandrian culture needs a slave-class in

order to exist in the long term; as it views existence optimistically however, it

denies the necessity of such a class and is therefore heading towards horrifying

extinction when the effects of its fire words of seduction and pacification, such

as ‘human dignity’ and ‘the dignity of labour’, are exhausted. (BT 18)

This early foray of Nietzsche’s into social commentary may strike the reader as somewhat

naive. He does not sufficiently explain why such a slave class is necessary for the

continuation of modern culture, or, indeed, why the demands of this class are irreconcilable

with the interests of the wider culture, though it is worth noting here that by Nietzsche’s

expansive notion of the slave modern workers who enjoy various nominal freedoms would

still count as the proverbial wage salves. In an unpublished work of 1871, “The Greek State:

Preface” he partially fleshes this out, intimating that a slave class is required in order to

provide for men of culture.15 Here Nietzsche, probably intentionally, fails to distinguish

between society’s goal by his lights (the propagation of geniuses), and the goals internal to

late Socratic culture (broad based general felicity –what the later Nietzsche disparagingly

calls “herd happiness”). Socratism need not fall apart from internal contradictions and

political strife. Indeed, the realization of the deep robustness of modern philistine, Socratic,

that is, scientific, “culture” is a fundamental source of the later Nietzsche’s profound

pessimism about the possibility of a general cultural renewal.

15 This essay fragment is in KSA, 1:765-777; KGW CV-CV3

19

Nietzsche’s central argument against Socratism is not that it is false, or that it possesses any

intrinsic defect (e.g. it being ‘anti-myth’). Socratism is attacked because it is no longer a

viable illusion around which to base a future German culture. Late Socratism loses its faith

because the notion of general felicity is allegedly exposed as a myth and more noble forms

of Socratism fail because the goal of truth as valuable in itself no longer has any traction as

an ideal which suffices to make existence meaningful. The Nietzsche of BT is not so clear on

why this noble Socraticsm is no longer viable, explaining metaphorically that “science,

spurred by its powerful illusion, speeds irresistibly towards its limits where its optimism, concealed

in the essence of logic, suffers shipwreck” (BT 15). The later Nietzsche of GM is more explicit in

arguing that the will to truth turns on itself and comes to see that the supreme exhalation

of truth is itself ungrounded and hence an illusion (see GM III, 23).16

16 In fact, it is not at all clear that the late Socratism of modernity, the belief that knowledge

is of great instrumental value because it paves the way to general felicity, is not a viable

notion. One gets a sense of Nietzsche’s awareness of this from his repeated expressions of

disgust with, and fear of, the triumph of the ideals of herd happiness and the prevalence of

the last man. If Nietzsche were seriously wedded to Schopenhauer account of desire and its

consequent dismissal of the possibility of any real felicity then perhaps he would have an

argument against late Socratism. But his acknowledgment that the last man achieves his

desired pedestrian herd happiness suggests that he was not totally wedded to

Schopenhauer’s account. One suspects that Nietzsche is aware that he has no ultimate

argument against the last man and is simply disgusted at his lack of ambition. In fact , the

last man is someone who has evaded Nietzsche’s dictum that man seeks meaning over

20

Nietzsche’s argument prefigures his later critique of Christianity, which is not that

Christianity is false, but that it is spent. To be ‘in the service of life’, to ‘seduce us to life,’ an

value or ideal has to have affective grip on us, and in both BT and GM Nietzsche takes

himself to have identified signs of enervation and exhaustion in contemporary culture owing

to the degeneration of hitherto hegemonic ideals. In GM Nietzsche claims that

All great things bring about their own self destruction through an act of self-

overcoming [Selbstaufhebung]: thus the law of life will have it, the law of the

necessity of ‘self-overcoming’ [Selbstüberwindung] in the nature of life – the

lawgiver himself eventually receives the call: ‘paterelegem, quam ipse tulisti’

[submit to the law you yourself proposed] (GM III 27)

Christianity, by fostering the spirit of truthfulness, creates the conditions for its overcoming,

as this truthfulness, deployed against its presuppositions,undermines belief in itself.By 1887,

Nietzsche understands such late Christian culture as an example of ‘degeneration’, or

‘decadence’. Although many of the outward trappings, institutions and manners remain in

place, the spirit which previously animated them has gone. By the time of GM, Nietzsche

has of course developed further arguments, most notably that Christianity may be especially

‘hostile to life’, but in BT his equivalent problem with Socratism is that it is enervated. It is

clear from Nietzsche’s description of Socratism that it has fulfilled a vital cultural role up

until the present day. Whereas a philosophe (and later Nietzsche) would take issue with

Socratic culture’s covert religiosity, its existentially grounding ‘faith’ in science and the

‘quest for truth’, BT’s sole criterion is ‘to what extent does this allow us to keep living and

happiness and exposes it to be as much a normative claim than a descriptive claim. We

might say it is Nietzsche’s own ultimate illusion.

21

ward off pessimism?’ It seems abundantly clear that Socratism has been highly successful at

this, for much of Western history. To criticise an ideal solely in terms of its falsity clearly

runs counter to the spirit of BT, since BT, as we have seen champions the need for illusions.

If it was not for Socratism’s re-direction of the will towards the attainment of knowledge

universal wars of annihilation and continual migrations of peoples would probably have

weakened the instinctive lust for life to such an extent that suicide would have become a

general custom […] a practical pessimism […] which incidentally is, and was, present in the

world wherever art did not appear in some form – especially as religion and science – as a

remedy and a preventive for this breath of pestilence. (BT 15, emphasis added)

Religion and science are both forms of myth which have prevented the enervation of the

will. Socratic faith was for a long time a very successful means by which the ‘will’ has

compelled us to continue to live.

5. Schopenhauer, Wagner and Nietzsche on the Function of Illusions

In order to grasp the role which Nietzsche envisions for art, in providing illusions which

sustain the individual it is helpful to isolate Schopenhauer’s notion of ‘illusion’ (Wahn) as

developed in the section titled ‘On the Metaphysics of Sexual Love’ (WWR II). The sex drive

is the most direct presentation of the will-to-live; “…the ultimate goal of almost all human

effort.” (WWR II p.533). Furthermore, ‘instinct’ is the means by which the ‘will of the

species’ succeeds in subverting the individual’s own egotistically driven ends, towards the

end of the species:

…nature can attain her end only by implanting in the individual a certain illusion

[Wahn], and by virtue of this, that which in truth is merely a good thing for the species

22

seems to him to be a good thing for himself, so that he serves the species, whereas he

is under the illusion that he is serving himself. In this process a mere chimera, which

vanishes immediately afterwards, floats before him, and, as motive, takes the place of

a reality. This illusion is instinct. In the great majority of cases, instinct is to be

regarded as the sense of the species which presents to the will what is useful to it.

(WWR II p.538).

This instinct is “an illusion that conceals the service of the species under the mask of an

egotistical end.” (WWR II p.541). Putting aside the question of how a ‘blind striving’ such as

the Will could manifest such seeming intentionality, the interesting import of this is the

notion that the species acts through the individual, deluding him into acts which serve its

perpetuation. The species’ ‘interest’ is straightforwardly its continuation.18 This is a

repeated theme in Schopenhauer. It is built into our nature as creatures with desires that

we are not simply deluded about the possibility of the satisfaction of desire, we are also

deluded about the relation between our desires and our interests. Our genuine interests,

claims Schopenhauer, are not served by pursuing our desires; in fact, they only achieved

through the cessation of desire.

Wagner was clearly struck by Schopenhauer’s use of the concept of Wahn, most famously in

Die Meistersinger von Nürnberg. The ‘Wahn monologue’ of the protagonist Hans Sachs

18 Nietzsche seems to allude to a mechanism similar to this in numerous places both in BT

and UM. Similarly, in his late work as well there is the repeated notion that “[the Will]

would rather will nothingness than not will” (GM III 1). What appear to be life denying

actions are in fact deeply sublimated forms of willing that allow individuals to go on living.

23

declares that life is permeated by Wahn. Sachs’s challenge as expressed in the libretto of Die

Meistersinger is to attempt to “guide illusion [Wahn] to subtly to perform a nobler task.”

(Warrack 1994:156, our translation) The crucial difference between Wagner’s and

Schopenhauer’s conception of Wahn is that for Wagner Wahn is not unambiguously

pernicious. 20Indeed Wagner, in extolling the redemptive power of illusion, even goes so far

as to coin the striking expression ‘wahrster Wahn’ [truest illusion].21 In the theoretical work

‘On State and Religion’, which Nietzsche read at the time of writing BT, Wagner attempts to

explain this strange notion of useful Wahn. He draws distinctions both between creative

and destructive forms of Wahn (in particular in the political sphere), and between two forms

of Wahn which differ in the scope of their mystification. On the one hand there is ‘worldly’

Wahn. In the example of patriotism, the individual sacrifices himself for an object over and

above his immediate interests. He is deluded into identifying his egoistic ends with the ends

of the state. His illusion is twofold: First, he believes that his real interests are identical

with those of the state, second he shares the general illusion that a final satisfaction of

desire is possible. Wagner identifies a different kind of Wahn which he associates with

religion. Unlike worldly Wahn, which remains entirely submerged in desires concerning

20 This perversion of Schopenhauer is perhaps most conspicuous in Tristan and Isolde.

There, the lovers find redemption precisely through the Wahn of sexual love, whereas King

Marke, in resisting this illusion, is denied the possibility of metaphysical redemption. See

Borchmeyer (1991:365-366)

21 In BT 1 Nietzsche gives a full quotation of the passage from Die Meistersinger which

contains this unusual phrase. For more on Wagner, Nietzsche, and Wahn, see the

interesting account in Shaw (1960).

24

everyday reality, religion attains a perspective from which it sees the fleeting, and ultimately

futile, nature of earthly desires. Religion displays an awareness that all such goals cannot

touch on the problem of existence:

[Religion’s]…basis is a feeling of the unblessedness of human being, of the

State’s profound inadequacy to still the purely-human need. Its inmost kernel is

denial of the world – i.e. recognition of the world as a fleeting and dreamlike

state reposing merely on illusion (auf einerTäuschung) – and struggle for

Redemption from it, prepared-for by renunciation, attained by Faith. (AP: 23-24)

This seems to be simply an iteration of Schopenhauer’s assessment of revelation; the

capacity to pierce the veil of individuation, and see the nature of reality as Will. The

‘religious eye’ (der religiösenVorstellung) comprehends that satisfaction cannot be attained

in this world “…and hence requires another world for its redemption.” (AP: 24). Just as the

more simple individual’s existence requires the consolations of religion or patriotism, so the

noble individual needs an illusion worthy of his powers. It is thus the

…work of that man-redeeming Wahn which spreads its wonders wherever the

individual’s normal mode of view can help itself no farther. But in this instance

the Wahn must be entirely candid; it must confess itself in advance for an

illusion, if it is to be willingly embraced by the man who really longs for

distraction and illusion in the high and correct sense we mean. The Wahn-

picture brought before him must never afford a loop-hole for re-summoning the

earnestness of life through any possible dispute about its actuality and provable

foundation upon fact, as religious Dogma does: no, it must exercise its specific

virtue through its very setting of the conscious Wahn in place of the reality. This

25

office is fulfilled by Art; and in conclusion…Art [is] the kindly life-saviour who

does not really and wholly lead us out beyond this life, but, within it, lifts us up

above it and shows it as itself a game of play, a game that, take it ne’er so

terrible and earnest an appearance, yet here again is shown us as a mere Wahn-

picture, as which it comforts us and wafts us from the common truth of our

distress (Noth) (AP: 33)

It is art’s job to provide the illusions by which we are able to find the world bearable.

Despite the ‘common truth of our distress’ we perceive life as a ‘game of play’. We thus still

recognise the nature of life, but apprehend this fact in a fashion which somehow makes it

bearable.22 For Wagner, and Nietzsche following him, art has the role of offering solace to

the individual who has grasped a ‘terrible truth’. This solace is not through any putative

knowledge of a metaphysical reality. Our strivings in the phenomenal world ultimately

appear insignificant, lacking the necessary gravitas we desire. We need metaphysical

illusion, as this is a supplement which lends the phenomenal world the necessary

‘colouring’. Nietzsche uses Schopenhauerian language to engage with Wagner, rather than

Schopenhauer. The immediate significance of Wagner’s piece for BT is Wagner’s idea that

art affords the most sophisticated ‘illusion of the will’, which seduces us back to life even

22 Wagner highlights the paradoxical nature of the claim that a certain kind of illusion

actually enables us to grasp an otherwise unbearable truth; “The nothingness of the world,

here it is harmless, avowed as though in smiling: for our willing purpose to deceive

ourselves had led us on to recognise the world’s real state without a shadow of illusion.”

(AP: 34)

26

when we are fully cognisant of the world’s lack of fit with our desires.23 A metaphysical

illusion, not metaphysical knowledge as per Schopenhauer, enables us to cope with the

nature of phenomenal reality. This is exactly the stance of Nietzsche’s BT as expressed in BT

18 (see above) and here:24

The Hellene, by nature profound and uniquely capable of the most exquisite and

most severe suffering…has gazed with keen eye into the midst of the fearful,

destructive havoc of so-called world history, and has seen the cruelty of nature,

and is in danger of longing to deny the will as the Buddhist does. Art saves him,

and through art life saves him – for itself. (BT 7)

When comparing Wagner to Schopenhauer on the value of art and illusion one is struck by

the affirmative character which Wagner gives them. Schopenhauer takes art to provide a

means to a, at least temporary, release one from the bondage of the Will, and he takes this

to be good. For Wagner art and illusion leads one to affirm life and hence willing, and he

takes this to be good. In this essential point Nietzsche is a follower of Wagner, not

Schopenhauer. Relatedly, Nietzsche’s idiosyncratic use of the term ‘Wahn’ follows that of

Wagner rather than Schopenhauer. For Nietzsche and Wagner there is a positive sense of

Wahn. For Nietzsche, following Wagner, it is through Wahn that art performs the positive

23

BT similarly reflects Wagner’s thoughts on art’s essentially affirmative nature. For

instance, Wagner claims: “…Art is pleasure in itself, in existence, in community…” (RA: 36).

See also (OP:155-156, 161) and (RA:32, 34-35).

24See also NF 1870 7[121]

27

task of wooing us back to life, In ordinary German and in Schopenhauer’s usage ‘Wahn’ has

strongly negative connotations of falsity thus it is most aptly translated as ‘delusion’. 25

Where Schopenhauer is in a sense an ahistorical, and, hence, global thinker, Nietzsche and

Wagner are, in a certain sense, local thinkers. While Schopenhauer was concerned with the

eternal problem of suffering, Wagner and Nietzsche were very much concerned with a

cultural malaise they took to be endemic to their current time.26 This was part of their

shared romantic inheritance. Nietzsche took over Wagner’s obsession with the perceived

degeneration of current culture and followed Wagner in attempting to revitalize that culture

through the deliberate constructions of new life affirming myths. However Nietzsche

eventually came to see Wagner as a sign of, rather than answer to, degenerate culture.

Wagner sought in his operas, especially his Ring cycle, to provide a new mythology which

25 English editions of BT consistently translate ‘Wahn’ as ‘illusion’ rather than ‘delusion ’. In

keeping with what is said above regarding the positive nature of Wahn for Nietzsche this

translation is perfectly justified. However this means that the English text fails to duplicate

the full oddity that Nietzsche’s use of ‘Wahn’ presents to German readers. More generally,

in this essay we have translated “Wahn”, Illusion”, “Schein” and “Wahnvorstellungen” as

they occur in Nietzsche’s texts as “illusion”. In fact one might argue that different

translations, for instance “delusion”, are appropriate in some cases. But this would involve a

whole essay in itself; in particular it would involve trying to untangle the ordinary valences

attending such terms from Nietzsche’s somewhat idiosyncratic valences.

26 Of course Nietzsche does make claims about past cultures, for instance in BT, UM and

GM. But his primary purpose in doing so is to sharpen the focus on what he perceives to be

our current cultural malaise. For more on this theme see Gemes (2006).

28

could lead to cultural renewal. However Nietzsche, after initially endorsing Wagner in BT as

the elect agent of cultural renewal, came to see Wagner, especially the Wagner of Parsifal,

as falling into the life denying solace of religious consolation. This goes some way to

explaining Nietzsche’s puzzling insistence that Thus Spoke Zarathustra is his key work and

that those of us who are not touched by it (including the present authors) have not

understood him.27 Nietzsche well before that book had already dismissed Wagner as a

possible provider of a new mythology that would allow for a Dionysian revival of high

culture. We may surmise that Nietzsche himself took up this task with his Thus Spoke

Zarathustra.28 One gets a sense of his trajectory from the last the last lines of Twilight of

the Idols:

27

It is pertinent to bear in mind here that for Nietzsche even the objectivity-prizing scholar,

say a Professor of Philosophy, is basically an under-labourer he is “only an instrument. Let

us say: He is a mirror - he is no ‘end in himself’” (BGE 207). For more on the theme of the

scholar as a passive mirror see Gemes 2006, especially pages 194-5.

28 Here we are interpreting both Wagner’s Ring opera cycle and Nietzsche’s Zarathustra in

light of Schelling’s claim that “the modern world has no real epic, and that, since mythology

becomes established only in the epic as such, it also has no self-enclosed mythology”

(Schelling 1989, p. 71). This is not to say that Nietzsche was directly aware of Schelling’s

claim. Nietzsche’s understanding of the need for a modern epic came from his engagement

with Wagner and Hölderlin. In 1861 while still at high school Nietzsche had written an essay

in praise of Hölderlin. Defining his mission Zarathustra’s says

when my eyes flee from the present to the past, it always discovers the same thing:

fragments and limbs and dreadful chances - but no men! … I walk among men as

29

I again return to the place from which I set out - the Birth of Tragedy was my first

revaluation of all values ... I again plant myself in the soil out of which I draw all that I

will and can – I, the last disciple of Dionysus – I, the teacher of the eternal recurrence.

The eternal recurrence is of course the means by which Zarathustra hopes to reinvigorate

his followers and ward of the threat of suicidal nihilism; as such it functions as Nietzsche’s

grand attempt at a final life affirming myth.

6. The value of culture

The idea that the current age needs a deliberate, constructed myth as a means of self-

affirmation was integral to a romantic strain of thought expressed in thinkers such as

Schelling, Schlegel, Novalis and Hölderlin. They believed that what gave integrity and centre

to Greek culture, the highest culture that man had yet achieved, was their naïve belief in the

Homeric gods. The problem confronting us moderns is that we are no longer capable of

among fragments of the future: of the future which I scan. And it is my art and aim,

to compose into one and bring together what is fragment and riddle and dreadful

chance.(Z, II, 21)

Here Nietzsche almost certainly had in mind the following passage in Hölderlin’sHyperion,

itself a self-conscious attempt at creating a mythologizing epic poem,

I can think of no people more at odds with themselves than the Germans. You see

artisans, but no men, thinkers, but no men … is this not like a battlefield on which

hacked-off hands and arms and every other limb scattered about. (Hölderlin (1952:

420) – our translation).

30

naïve belief in such unifying mythologies. They concluded that what was needed was a new

deliberately constructed mythology. Thus Schlegel wrote to Hölderlin “Perhaps you have the

choice my friend to be either the last Christian, the Brutus of the old religion, or the Christ of

a new gospel” (cited in Williamson (2004:51).29Hölderlin’s Hyperion is just such an attempt

to create a new mythology. Exactly how this could work was a deeply vexing question:

after all if one deliberately invents a mythology how is one capable of actually literally

believing it, and in the absence of such genuine belief how can that mythology provide a

meaning and centre to one’s life?30 In his unpublished early essay “The Philosopher:

29 Indeed a month earlier Schlegel in another letter to Novalis had assigned this task to

himself, thus he wrote of his desire to “write a new bible and wander in the footsteps of

Mohammed and Luther”. (Williamson 2004:55)

30 The first essay of Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morality tells a story of the seemingly

deliberate Jewish invention of Christian mythology. Notoriously this idea of a deliberately

invented myth brings with it the question of how the inventors of that myth could

themselves have believed it (see, for instance, Bittner (1994). Wagner’s solution to a similar

problem was that through a literal sensory bombardment rational faculties could be

bypassed. It was Wagner’s intention that the four operas of the Ring cycle, some of which

run over five hours long, are to be experienced over four consecutive nights so that his

audience would be totally overwhelmed, thereby the themes of his work could penetrate to

a level deep below their conscious rational faculties, and there take root. As Wagner himself

put it “the public, that representative of daily life, forgets the confines of the auditorium,

and lives and breathes now only in the artwork which seems to it as Life itself, and on the

31

Reflections on the Struggle Between Art and Knowledge” Nietzsche exclaims “One must

even want illusions - that is what is tragic” and goes on to ask “might not art perhaps itself

be capable of creating a religion or giving birth to a myth?”(KSA 7: 427-9) The early

Nietzsche took up the romantic idea that a new constructed mythology was the core to a

rebirth of culture. As we have seen in BT he argued that mythology is the core of any

genuine culture. There he argued that Wagner was to be the creator of a new mythology

necessary for a rebirth of German culture;

Let no one believe that the German spirit has lost its mythical homeland forever

when it still clearly understands the voice of the bird that speaks of that homeland.

One day it will awake in the morning freshness from a deep sleep. Then it will kill

the dragon, destroy the malicious dwarf, and awaken Brünhilde – and even Wotan’s

spear will not block its path. (BT 24)31

stage which seems the wide expanse of the whole World” (AF: 185). We might question

Wagner’s confidence that this state might persist outside the confines of the auditorium.

31 As Chris Raymond has pointed out to us in conversation and an e-mail correspondence;

many Nietzsche scholars follow Kaufmann (see, for instance, Kaufman 1974:394) in taking

seriously only the first fifteen sections of the Birth of Tragedy, which deal, among other

things, with the birth, death and function of Greek tragedy. Again, following Kaufmann,

they tend to dismiss the last ten sections, which deal with Wagner, as embarrassing

apologetics. Raymond makes the case that if we see the whole book as heralding the

rebirth of tragedy in Wagnerian music drama we have an understanding of why in the first

fifteen sections of the book he makes certain claims about Greek tragedians which seem

fairly ungrounded and are in marked disagreement with lectures he was giving more or less

32

By1876 when Nietzsche came to the inaugural Bayreuth Festival his hopes of a rebirth of

high culture through Wagner, hopes to which he had made great sacrifices, possibly

including that of his academic career, had been completely dashed. Thus by the time of the

first of his so-called middle period works Human, All too Human Nietzsche found himself

devoid of any grand normative project. In his 1886 preface to the second volume of HAH he

writes

My task – where had it gone? What? Was it now not as if my task had withdrawn from

me, as though I would for a long time come to cease to have any right to it?” (HAH II,

Preface 3)

Indeed HAH is suffused with a strong awareness of the inevitable continuing triumph of

philistine culture:

contemporaneously (cf. KGW, II, 3, pp. 1-57). According to Raymond, Nietzsche “constructs

a narrative of the birth and decline of Greek tragedy that makes music essential to tragedy -

to persuade his reader that true tragedy can only be reborn once its musical ground has

been re-established (hence 'The Birth of Tragedy out of the Spirit of Music')”. To this end,

Nietzsche pictures a decline from Aeschylus to Sophocles to Euripides, because Aeschylus is

the earliest and most musical of the tragedians, and hence closest to its Dionysian origins”

(private communication). The suggestion, then, is that with BT Nietzsche is attempting to

create a kind of inspirational Wagner mythology, or what Nietzsche in the second essay of

his Untimely Meditations refers to as a “monumental” historical narrative (see UM, 2,

especially section 2) about tragedy which places Wagner as its heir.

33

The demagogic character and the intention to appeal to the masses is at present

common to all political parties: on account of this intention they are all competing to

transform their principles into great al fresco stupidities and thus to paint them on

the wall. This is no longer alterable (HAH I 438).

When in his later works he takes up a normative project it is of a much more limited scope.

7. Affirmation and Zarathustra

If this narrative of Nietzsche’s development is to be accepted one must explain the position

of Nietzsche’s self-proclaimed masterwork Thus Spoke Zarathustra in his cannon. For if by

HAH he had already despaired of the project of inaugurating a rebirth of high culture, and

thus presumably given up on the idea of the need for a new mythology to instigate such a

rebirth, why then does he create his own mythological narrative with Zarathustra, a work

which post-dates HAH? First, it is worth noting that after he had given up on the idea of

Wagner as the herald of a new mythology he seems to have implicitly nominated himself as

the new champion of something like this task. Thus in 1883 upon first hearing of Wagner’s

death he wrote

Ultimately, it was against the aged Wagner I had to defend myself; as regards the

authentic Wagner, I will to a good extent become his heir. (Sämtliche Briefe 6:333-4)

The aged Wagner is the Wagner who in Nietzsche’s eyes had “sunk down helpless and

shattered before the cross” (HAH II, Preface, 3). Is then Zarathustra Nietzsche’s attempt to

become the heir of the authentic Wagner? And heir of what exactly? Surely not, given the

recognition of the inevitable triumph of democratic, bourgeois, philistine culture, the

34

romantic project of instigating a new elevated general culture? We believe the answer is

that Nietzsche now had redefined the project: He now aimed not for an elevated general

culture but an elite culture open to only an initiate few. Indeed, while the early German

romantics typically extolled the idea of a rebirth of a general German culture through myths,

there was a strain that claimed that a cultural revival was only possible for an enlightened

elite. As Williamson nicely puts it:

The notion that the chosen few constituted a “pure” or “invisible church” found

heightened expression among the early Romantics… In their private writings they

often referred to the Elysian mysteries as a model of religious-philosophical education

that could be confined to a few adepts. (2004:50-51).

The realization that the road to a higher culture can only be travelled by a very select few is

one of the great realizations of Nietzsche’s Zarathustra; he quickly comes to see that he is

mistaken in trying to instruct the rabble. In the Prologue to Zarathustra, after leaving his

cave Zarathustra comes to the town and attempts to instruct the “people assembled in the

market-place”. They of course are oblivious to his message and laugh at his discourse on

the need to go beyond man to the superman. Thereupon Zarathustra comes to a great

revelation:

A light has dawned for me: Zarathustra shall not speak to the people but to companions! Zarathustra shall not be herdsman and dog to the herd!

. . .

To lure many from the herd — that is why I have come. The people and the herd shall be angry with me: the herdsmen shall call Zarathustra a robber.

The creator seeks companions not corpses or herds or believers. The creator seeks fellow creators, those who inscribe new values on new tables.

35

. . .

I will not be a herdsman or gravedigger. I will not speak again to the people: I have spoken to a dead man for the last time. (Z, Prologue, 9)

Zarathustra, then, is not a work which Nietzsche hoped would pave the way for a general

cultural renewal through inspiration of the citizenry in general. For Nietzsche the aspiration

to such a general culture died with Wagner’s Bayreuth fiasco. Zarathustra is aimed at

inspiring a select few to genuine and full life-affirmation. That is why Nietzsche can only

aspire to be “to a good extent” Wagner’s heir. As to the mechanics of that inspiration, it is

not aimed at inspiring through arguing for particular theses, even theses of a revolutionary

content, (theses concerning the superman, the eternal recurrence, the primacy of will to

power, etc). Nor is it aiming to provide a new mythology that is, per impossible, to be

literally believed. Rather, it takes off from Wagner’s notion of a deep poetic inspiration. For

Nietzsche, Zarathustra with its rhythmic incantations and its repeated chorus like refrain

“Thus Spoke Zarathustra” constituted a kind of music. In Ecce Homo in his summary of

Zarathustra he says “[p]erhaps the whole of Zarathustra may be reckoned as music” (EH,

‘Thus Spoke Zarathustra’, 1). Indeed, Nietzsche’s claim to have become Wagner’s heir was

made just after he had finished the first three parts of Zarathustra.33 He took Zarathustra to

be his most important work. In Ecce Homo Nietzsche says

Among my writings my Zarathustra stands to my mind by itself. With that I have

given mankind the greatest present that has ever been made to it so far. This book,

with a voice bridging centuries, is not only the highest book there is, the book that is

33 The letter where Nietzsche makes that claim was written on February 18, 1883 and,

indeed, in that very letter he also refers to “the ten gay and fresh January days in which my

Zarathustra came into being”.

36

truly characterized by the air of the heights—the whole fact of man lies beneath it at

a tremendous distance—, it is also the deepest, born out of the innermost wealth of

truth, an inexhaustible well to which no pail descends without coming up again filled

with gold and goodness. Here no "prophet" is speaking, none of those gruesome

hybrids of sickness and will to power whom people call founders of religions. Above

all, one must hear aright the tone that comes from this mouth, the halcyon tone, lest

one should do wretched injustice to the meaning of its wisdom. (EH, Preface 4).

Nietzsche believed that those who could hear rightly would thereby find an inspiration that

could unlock their deepest longings. Those who are so inspired would now express,

presumably through sublimated forms, those creative drives that they had formerly

repressed under the influence of the dominant ascetic ideal.34 Indeed, this kind of poetic

inspiration is exactly the influence Zarathustra had on many (Rainer Maria Rilke, Stephan

George, Thomas Mann, Herman Hesse, to name just a few), especially in the first 50 years

after its publication. These are, by Nietzschean lights, readers of genius who develop and

keep the flame of culture alive. Nietzsche still, in a certain sense, aspires to a general

culture, but it is one that only the elite directly participate in. For the Nietzsche of

Zarathustra, as with the earlier Nietzsche of BT high culture is what gives meaning to the

lives of both members of the elite and members of the herd. The difference is that the early

Nietzsche optimistically hoped that the common people could be educated (by Wagner or

whoever) into a position where they could appreciate and thereby in some sense participate

34 For an account of the importance of the notion of sublimation in Nietzsche’s thought and

a contrast between Nietzsche’s and Freud’s concepts and mechanics of sublimation see

Gemes (2009).

37

in higher culture; whereas the later Nietzsche saw the idea of the herd’s participation in, or

genuine appreciation of, higher culture to be a chimera. In this case the herd’s existence,

being a precondition for the higher types – wage slaves are still needed to keep society

functioning - would have a meaning, albeit one that members of the herd would, typically,

have no awareness of.36

Julian Young has argued (this volume) that Nietzsche is fundamentally a communitarian

thinker. If we are right this claim may be true of the early Nietzsche who endorsed the

Wagnerian project. But of the later Nietzsche it is only true if we take the relevant

community to be defined, not synchronically in terms of Nietzsche’s contemporary society,

but diachronically in terms of the geniuses, who talk to each other, “each giant calling to his

brother through the desolate intervals of time”, and who are real the engines of genuine

cultural renewal and development. (KSA 1:804) As Nietzsche himself puts it: “There is an

invisible bridge from genius to genius which constitutes the genuinely real “history” of a

people”. (KSA 7:417) Even here we must be cautious and recognise the possibility that this

very notion of the diachronically defined culture of genius, this “history”, is, by Nietzsche’s

refracted lights, itself just one more inspirational myth, or in Nietzsche’s own words a

“beautiful illusion”.

36 These last paragraphs owes a lot to conversations with Gudrun von Tevenar, and to a

reading of her essay “Zarathustra: ‘That Malicious Dionysian’” in Gemes and Richardson

(2013) and to conversations with Andrew Huddleston and a reading of his "Nietzsche's

Cultural Perfectionism" in Nietzsche’s Values, eds. K. Gemes and C. Janaway (forthcoming).

38

Bibliography of Works Cited

Borchmeyer, Dieter. Richard Wagner: Theory and Theatre, Oxford: Oxford University Press,

1991.

Gemes, Ken and Richardson, John, The Oxford Handbook of Nietzsche, Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 2013

Gemes, Ken and Janaway, Christopher, Nietzsche’s Value, Oxford: Oxford University Press,

forthcoming.

Gemes, Ken, “Freud and Nietzsche on Sublimation”, Journal of Nietzsche Studies, 38: 38-59,

2009

______, “We Remain of Necessity Stranger to Ourselves”: The Key Message of Nietzsche’s

Geneology”, pp. 191-208 in Acampora, Christa Davis, ed. Nietzsche's On the Genealogy

of Morals: Critical Essays. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2006.

Hölderlin, F. Dichtungen und Briefe, Munich: Winkler-Verlag, 1952.

Janaway, Christopher. ed., Willingness and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche’s

Educator, Oxford: Clarenden Press, 1998.

Nietzsche, Friedrich., Writings from the Early Notebooks, (WEN), eds. Raymond Geuss and

Alexander Nehamas, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2009

_______, Beyond Good and Evil, (BGE),.ed. Rolf-Peter Horstmann and Judith Norman, trans.

Judith Norman, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.

_______, On the Genealogy of Morality, (GM), trans. Maudemarie Clark and Alan J.

Swensen, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1998.

39

_______, Untimely Meditations, (UM), trans. R. J. Hollingdale, Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press, 1986.

_______, The Birth of Tragedy, (BT), ed. Raymond Geuss and Ronald Speirs, trans. Ronald

Speirs. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999.

_______, The Gay Science, (GS), ed. Bernard Williams, trans. Josephine Nauckhoff and

Adrian del Caro, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.

_______, Human, All Too Human, (HAH), ed. Richard Schacht, trans. R. J. Hollingdale,

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

_______, SämtlicheWerke: Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 Einzelbänden, (KSA), ed. G. Colli

and M. Montinari, de Gruyter 1988

_______, Sämtliche Briefe: Kritische Studienausgabe in 8 Bänden, (SB), ed. G. Colli and M.

Montinari, Berlin: de Gruyter 1986

Poellner, Peter. “Myth, Art and Illusion in Nietzsche”, in Myth and the Making of Modernity.

The Problem of Grounding in Early Twentieth-Century Literature, eds. Michael Bell

and Peter Poellner, Amsterdam-Atlanta: Rodopi, 1998.

Schelling, Freidrich, The Philosophy of Art, ed. and transl. by Douglass Scott, Minneapolis:

University of Minneapolis Press, 1989

Shaw, Leroy R.,‘The Noble Deception. ‘Wahn’, Wagner, and ‘Die Meistersinger von

Nürnberg’, Monatshefte, 52:97-112, 1960.

40

Soll, Ivan., "Pessimism and the Tragic View of Life: Reconsiderations of Nietzsche's Birth of

Tragedy," pp. 104-132 in Reading Nietzsche, eds. Robert Solomon, Kathleen Higgins,

Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.

Staten, Henry. Nietzsche’s Voice, Ithica: Cornell University Press, 1990.

Wagner, Richard. Religion and Art, (RA), London: University of Nebraska Press, 1994

_______, Art and Politics, (AP), London: University of Nebraska Press, 1995.

Warrack, John, (ed.) Die Meistersinger Von Nurnberg, Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 1994.

Williamson, George S..The Longing for Myth in Germany: Religion and Aesthetic Culture from

Romanticism to Nietzsche, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004.

Young, Julian. Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Art, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.