tertullian's concept of the soul and his corporealistic ontology (pre-print)

21
43 Tertullian’s Concept of the Soul and His Corporealistic Ontology * Petr KITZLER (Prague) One of the most remarkable theological-philosophical themes occurring in the work of Tertullian of Carthage is his doctrine of the soul 1 , mainly as it is explained in his extensive treatise De anima, the first overall Christian treatment of this topic 2 . * This paper is based on my previous treatment of this topic published in German as “Nihil enim anima si non corpus. Tertullian und die Körperlichkeit der Seele”, Wiener Studien, 122 (2009), p. 145-169. Its essential tenets were introduced for the first time during the Director’s Work-in-Progress Seminar at the Warburg Institute, School of Advanced Study, University of London in 2008. 1 For a systematic treatment of Tertullian’s Seelenlehre cf., e.g., P. BOUËDRON, Quid senserit de natura animae Tertullianus, Nannetibus, 1861; (ANONYMOUS), “Tertullians Seelenlehre”, Der Katholik, 45 (1865), p. 195-231; G. R. HAUSCHILD, Tertullian’s Psychologie und Erkenntnisstheorie, Programm des städtischen Gymnasiums Frankfurt am Main 1879-1880, Frankfurt am Main, 1880; G. ESSER, Die Seelenlehre Tertullians, Paderborn, 1893; F. SEYER, Tertullianus, quae de anima humana senserit, Unpublished Dissertation Wien, 1937; J. H. WASZINK, ed., Tertulliani De anima, Amserdam, 1947; H. KARPP, Probleme altchristlicher Anthropologie. Biblische Anthropologie und philosophische Psychologie bei den Kirchenvätern des dritten Jahrhunderts, Gütersloh, 1950; J. ALEXANDRE, Une chair pour la gloire. L’anthropologie réaliste et mystique de Tertullien, Paris, 2001; J. LEAL, La antropología de Tertuliano. Estudio de los tratados polémicos de los años 207-212 d. C., Roma, 2001; J. BARNES, “Anima Christiana” in Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy, ed. D. FREDE, B. REIS, Berlin New York, 2009, p. 447-464. Cf. also E. GONZALEZ, The Fate of the Dead in Early Third Century North African Christianity, Tübingen, 2014. 2 The fundamental critical edition of this treatise together with an unsurpassed commentary was published by J. H. WASZINK, ed., Tertulliani De anima, Amsterdam, 1947 (reprint Leiden, 2010); Waszink’s Latin text is reprinted with minor corrections also in TERTULLIANUS, Opera omnia, 2, Turnhout, 1954 (Corpus Christianorum, Series Latina [= CCSL], 2), p. 779-869 (the Latin citations of De anima in this paper are taken from this edition); the same author has published also the index to De anima, cf. J. H. WASZINK, Index verborum et

Upload: cas-cz

Post on 24-Nov-2023

0 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

43

Tertullian’s Concept of the Soul and His Corporealistic

Ontology* Petr KITZLER

(Prague)

One of the most remarkable theological-philosophical themes

occurring in the work of Tertullian of Carthage is his doctrine of the

soul1, mainly as it is explained in his extensive treatise De anima, the

first overall Christian treatment of this topic2.

* This paper is based on my previous treatment of this topic published in German

as “Nihil enim anima si non corpus. Tertullian und die Körperlichkeit der Seele”,

Wiener Studien, 122 (2009), p. 145-169. Its essential tenets were introduced for the

first time during the Director’s Work-in-Progress Seminar at the Warburg Institute,

School of Advanced Study, University of London in 2008.

1 For a systematic treatment of Tertullian’s Seelenlehre cf., e.g., P. BOUËDRON,

Quid senserit de natura animae Tertullianus, Nannetibus, 1861; (ANONYMOUS),

“Tertullians Seelenlehre”, Der Katholik, 45 (1865), p. 195-231; G. R. HAUSCHILD,

Tertullian’s Psychologie und Erkenntnisstheorie, Programm des städtischen

Gymnasiums Frankfurt am Main 1879-1880, Frankfurt am Main, 1880; G. ESSER,

Die Seelenlehre Tertullians, Paderborn, 1893; F. SEYER, Tertullianus, quae de

anima humana senserit, Unpublished Dissertation Wien, 1937; J. H. WASZINK,

ed., Tertulliani De anima, Amserdam, 1947; H. KARPP, Probleme altchristlicher

Anthropologie. Biblische Anthropologie und philosophische Psychologie bei den

Kirchenvätern des dritten Jahrhunderts, Gütersloh, 1950; J. ALEXANDRE, Une

chair pour la gloire. L’anthropologie réaliste et mystique de Tertullien, Paris,

2001; J. LEAL, La antropología de Tertuliano. Estudio de los tratados polémicos

de los años 207-212 d. C., Roma, 2001; J. BARNES, “Anima Christiana” in Body

and Soul in Ancient Philosophy, ed. D. FREDE, B. REIS, Berlin – New York, 2009,

p. 447-464. Cf. also E. GONZALEZ, The Fate of the Dead in Early Third Century

North African Christianity, Tübingen, 2014.

2 The fundamental critical edition of this treatise together with an unsurpassed

commentary was published by J. H. WASZINK, ed., Tertulliani De anima,

Amsterdam, 1947 (reprint Leiden, 2010); Waszink’s Latin text is reprinted with

minor corrections also in TERTULLIANUS, Opera omnia, 2, Turnhout, 1954

(Corpus Christianorum, Series Latina [= CCSL], 2), p. 779-869 (the Latin

citations of De anima in this paper are taken from this edition); the same author

has published also the index to De anima, cf. J. H. WASZINK, Index verborum et

44

This writing, influenced by Tertullian’s attachment to Montanism3

and originating from between 203 and 213 A.D.4, is, however,

neither the first Christian systematics nor the first “textbook of

Christian psychology”, as is sometimes imprecisely claimed5. It is

far more Tertullian’s often one-sided reply to the pagan doctrines of

the soul or to the single elements of these doctrines which were used

by the proponents of the different Christian heresies of the second

and third centuries. This reply has, as usual with Tertullian, one

principal aim: to discredit his enemy and to refute his opinion.

Fifty eight chapters of De anima can be divided – apart from

the introduction (exordium, chapters 1-3) and conclusion (peroratio,

chapter 58) – into three bigger thematic clusters. The first part

(chapters 4-21) is dedicated to main qualities of the soul (the

locutionum quae Tertulliani De anima libro continentur, Bonn, 1935 (reprint

Hildesheim – New York, 1971), as well as the German translation of Tertullian’s

all three “psychological” treatises (De anima, De testimonio animae, De censu

animae), together with an introduction and explanatory notes, cf. TERTULLIAN, Die

Seele ist ein Hauch (Über die Seele, Das Zeugnis der Seele, Vom Ursprung der

Seele), eingeleitet, übersetzt und erläutert von J. H. WASZINK, Zürich – München,

19862 (first edition Zürich, 1980). The modern English translation of De anima

(which I quote throughout this paper) was prepared by E. A. QUAIN, and it is

contained within the book TERTULLIAN, Apologetic Works and Minucius Felix

Octavius, Washington, D. C., 1950 (Fathers of the Church, 10), p. 163-309

(reprint 1962). The Italian translation, furnished with Latin original and

explanatory notes was published as TERTULLIANO, L’anima, ed. M. MENGHI,

Venezia, 1988. For the French series Sources chrétiennes [= SC], the new

commented edition and translation of De anima is being prepared by Jerónimo

Leal.

3 Modern Tertullian scholarship has proved convincingly that Tertullian’s

adherence to Montanism does not make him heretic who had left the Church, cf.,

e.g., D. RANKIN, Tertullian and the Church, Cambridge, 1995; CHR. TREVETT,

Montanism: Gender, Authority and the New Prophecy, Cambridge, 1996.

4 The dating between 210 and 213 was established by J. H. WASZINK, ed.,

Tertulliani De anima, p. 5*-6*. H. TRÄNKLE, “Q. Septimius Florens Tertullianus”

in Die Literatur des Umbruchs. Von der römischen zur christlichen Literatur 117

bis 284 n. Chr., ed. K. SALLMANN, München, 1997 (Handbuch der lateinischen

Literatur der Antike, 4), § 474, p. 438-511, here p. 474-475, has pointed out that

De anima must have been written not long after Tertullian’s treatise Adversus

Hermogenem which leads him to date it to ca. 203.

5 This is what e.g. A.-J. FESTUGIÈRE, “La composition et l’esprit du De anima de

Tertullien”, Revue des Sciences Philosophiques et Théologiques, 33 (1949), p.

129-161, here p. 142, points out.

45

beginning in time, corporeality and form, its dynameis and

uniformity); the second (chapters 22-41) focuses on the origin and

dissemination of the individual soul, including Tertullian’s concept

of traducianism (the soul is transmitted through natural generation

along with the body, and an individual’s soul is derived from the

souls of his or her parents6) and refutation of some philosophical

doctrines (Plato’s anamnesis, metempsychosis); the last thematic

section (chapters 42-58) treats the fate of the soul in the period

between death and resurrection.

In this paper, I want to focus on one particular point of Tertullian’s

doctrine of the soul, a point which seems to be rather surprising in

the context of patristic thought: Tertullian claims the soul to be

corporeal and this corporeality (corporalitas) is, according to him,

one of its main qualities7. The overall definition of the soul can be

found in chapter 22 of De anima:

The soul, therefore, we declare to be born of the breath of God,

immortal, corporeal, possessed of a definite form, simple in

substance, conscious of itself, developing in various ways, free in

its choices, liable to accidental change, variable in disposition,

rational, supreme, gifted with foresight, developed out of the one

original soul8.

What should this corporeality, which is placed by Tertullian right

after the divine origin and immortality, mean? The most exhaustive

6 Cf. exhaustively P. KITZLER, “Ex uno homine tota haec animarum redundantia.

Ursprung, Entstehung und Weitergabe der individuellen Seele nach Tertullian”,

Vigiliae Christianae, 64 (2010), p. 353-381, with further references. Cf. also

recently T. G. Petrey, “Semen Stains: Seminal Procreation and the Patrilineal

Genealogy of Salvation in Tertullian”, Journal of Early Christian Studies, 22

(2014), p. 343-372.

7 The term corporalitas is Tertullian’s neologism, cf. H. HOPPE, Beiträge zur

Sprache und Kritik Tertullians, Lund, 1932, p. 134. Besides Tertullian’s treatises it

features only in the work of HILARIUS PICTAVIENSIS, Comm. in Matth. IV,4 / SC

254,132, and Tract. super Psalm., instr. ps. 6 / CCSL 61,7. It is also used in the

treatise De statu animae by Claudianus Mamertus (5th century) who defended the

incorporality of the soul against Faustus of Riez.

8 TERTULLIANUS, De an. 22,2 / CCSL 2,814: Definimus animam dei flatu natam,

immortalem, corporalem, effigiatam, substantia simplicem, de suo sapientem,

varie procedentem, liberam arbitrii, accidentis obnoxiam, per ingenia mutabilem,

rationalem, dominatricem, divinatricem, ex una redundantem.

46

explication is to be found in chapters 5 to 9 of De anima, but before

we deal with the arguments mentioned there, it is necessary to sketch

the general context into which this doctrine of the corporeality of the

soul is put.

Tertullian’s conviction about the corporeality of the soul, or

better to say about the fact that even the soul must have its body

(corpus), is part of his corporealistic ontology, whose principal thesis

is that everything which is distinguished by a real and independent

being must be corporeal.

Yet even when they affirm that the soul was invisible, they

define it as corporeal, as possessing that which is invisible: for

if it possesses nothing invisible how can it be described as

invisible? Indeed it cannot even exist if it possesses nothing by

which to exist. But since it does exist it must of necessity

possess something by which it exists. If it does possess

something by which it exists, this must be its body. Everything

that exists is a body of some kind or another. Nothing is

incorporeal except what does not exist9.

Tertullian borrowed the doctrine of the corporeality of everything

that exists from Stoicism, which has been part of Popularphilosophie

since the first century B.C. and whose ideas were part of cultural

koine10. The ground of Stoic “corporealism”, the thesis that every

being, every substance, must be corporeal11, was Zeno’s notion that

what really exists can only be that which “makes something”

( ) or which “suffers” ( ); these qualities, however,

belong only to corporeal things12. The Stoics considered only four

9 TERTULLIANUS, De carne Chr. 11,3-4 / CCSL 2,895: Et tum, cum invisibilem

[scil. animam] dicunt, corporalem constituunt, habentem quod invisibile sit. Nihil

enim habens invisibile quomodo invisibilis potest dici? Sed nec esse quidem potest,

nihil habens per quod sit. Cum autem sit, habeat necesse est aliquid, per quod est.

Si habet aliquid, per quod est, hoc erit corpus eius. Omne, quod est, corpus est sui

generis. Nihil est incorporale nisi quod non est. English translation by E. EVANS,

Tertullian’s Treatise on the Incarnation, London, 1956, p. 43.

10 Cf. C. MORESCHINI, “Tertulliano tra Stoicismo e Platonismo” in Kerygma und

Logos. Festschrift für Carl Andresen zum 70. Geburtstag, ed. A. M. RITTER,

Göttingen, 1979, p. 367-379, here p. 368.

11 Cf., e.g., J. M. RIST, Stoic Philosophy, Cambridge, 1969, p. 152sqq.

12 Cf. Stoicorum veterum fragmenta (= SVF), ed. I. AB ARNIM, 1-4, Leipzig –

Berlin, 1921-1924, 2,363 (from SEXTUS EMPIRICUS):

47

“things” to be incorporeal: “sayable” ( ), “void” ( ),

“place” ( ) and “time” ( )13 – however, due to their

incorporeality, these were also considered not existent in a full sense.

Whereas the Stoics taught that their first category, ,

or corporeal substance, is the same in all things and the divine in its

materiality does not differ from the universe as a whole14, for

Tertullian all existing things share corporeality (corporalitas), but

this corporeality is in every single thing sui generis. That is also

why, as Tertullian explains, we cannot consider things that do not

conform to our common criterion of corporeality to be incorporeal15.

Tertullian agrees with the Stoics that God is also corporeal because

he really exists. For the Stoics, however, God is “absorbed” into the

body of the material universe and therefore he is neither transcendent

toward it nor “qualitatively” distinguishable from it. For Tertullian,

on the other hand, God’s corporeality too is sui generis: the

substance of God is spirit (spiritus)16, but even this spirit must have

its body in order to really exist. “For who will deny that God is body,

although God is a spirit? For spirit is body, of its own kind, in its

own form.17”

13 Cf. SVF 2,331 (from SEXTUS EMPIRICUS).

14 Cf., e.g., SVF 2,309 (from SEXTUS EMPIRICUS):

…; SVF 2,310 (from CHALCIDIUS): …

… See

also J. BRUNSCHWIG, “The Stoic Theory of the Supreme Genus and Platonic

Ontology” in IDEM, Papers in Hellenistic Philosophy, transl. JANET LLOYD,

Cambridge, 1994, p. 92-157; IDEM, “Stoic Metaphysics” in Cambridge Companion

to the Stoics, ed. B. INWOOD, Cambridge, 2003, p. 206-232; M. E. REESOR, “The

Stoic Categories”, The American Journal of Philology, 78 (1957), p. 63-82.

15 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 8,1 / CCSL 2,790.

16 Cf., e.g. TERTULLIANUS, Apol. 21,11 / CCSL 1,124; De orat. 28,2 / CCSL 1,273

(with reference to John 4,23-24); Adv. Hermog. 32,3 / CCSL 1,424. See also CHR.

STEAD, “Divine Substance in Tertullian”, Journal of Theological Studies, 14

(1963), p. 46-66.

17 TERTULLIANUS, Adv. Prax. 7,8 / CCSL 2,1166-1167: Quis enim negabit Deum

corpus esse, etsi Deus spiritus est? Spiritus enim corpus sui generis in sua effigie.

English translation by ERNEST EVANS, Tertullian’s Treatise against Praxeas,

London, 1948, p. 138.

48

To sum up, using corpus or corporalitas Tertullian refers not

only to the corporeality which characterises man or matter. His

corporealism does not equal materialism: corporalitas sui generis is

at the same time a fundamental prerequisite and condition of being,

something of a supreme category, whose opposite is, strictly

speaking, not incorporeal but non-existent18. Everything which exists

in the full sense of this word must be corporeal (corpus), because if

it were not a body, it would be nothing19. Full being, according to

Tertullian, as well as to the Stoics, belongs, however, only to

substances. For Tertullian the substance, notwithstanding the

problems with its definition20 – is a kind of real substrate, which

does not denote – in contrast to the Stoics – unformed

undifferentiated matter21, but it is something which makes every

existing being exactly what it is. Substance is, for Tertullian, always

a concrete entity, which must be determined by its qualities;

substances cannot merge into each other and they are “the body of

each thing”22.

Let us return now to Tertullian’s treatise De anima. From

chapter five onwards Tertullian argues for the corporeality of the

18 Cf. G. ESSER, Die Seelenlehre Tertullians, p. 67-68.

19 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 7,3 / CCSL 2,790: Nihil enim, si non corpus …; cf.

also SVF 2,359 (from CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA).: ...

20 Cf. R. BRAUN, Deus christianorum. Recherches sur le vocabulaire doctrinal de

Tertullien, Paris, 19772, p. 167-194; J. MOINGT, Théologie trinitaire de Tertullien,

2, Paris, 1966, p. 299-304; P. KITZLER, “Tertullians’s Use of Substantia in De

carne Christi”, Hermes, 142 (2014), p. 505-511.

21 Cf. SVF 1,86 (from CHALCIDIUS): … essentiam vero [scil. dicunt] primam rerum

omnium silvam vel antiquissimum fundamentum earum, suapte natura sine vultu et

informe …Cf. also F. SEYER, Tertullianus, quae de anima humana senserit, p. 18:

“Apud Tertullianum vero substantia non est formanda, sed formata materia, i.e.

materia nondum formata substantiae expers est.”

22 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, Adv. Hermog. 35,2 / CCSL 1,427: ...cum ipsa substantia

corpus sit rei cuiusque. See also W. BENDER, Die Lehre über den heiligen Geist

bei Tertullian, München, 1961, p. 21-25; R. BRAUN, Deus Christianorum, p. 179-

183; G. ESSER, Die Seelenlehre Tertullians, p. 66-71; G. R. HAUSCHILD,

Tertullian’s Psychologie und Erkenntnisstheorie, p. 25; H. KARPP, Probleme

altchristlicher Anthropologie, p. 46-47; F. SEYER, Tertullianus, quae de anima

humana senserit, p. 15-22.

49

soul, and it is the most exhaustive treatment of this topic in the

whole of early Christian literature.

Tertullian finds, of course, the main support for his assertion

about the corporeality of the soul in Stoicism, because the Stoics

“will easily prove that the soul is a body, even though they almost

agree with us in saying that the soul is a spirit; for spirit and breath

are very nearly the same thing”23. In chapters five to seven Tertullian

then reproduces the Stoic arguments about the corporeality of the

soul, which he probably borrowed from his main source, Soranus of

Ephesus24: according to Zeno the soul must be corporeal, because its

departure from the body causes death, and that which by its

departure causes death to a living being must be corporeal, because

the incorporeal cannot even touch the corporeal25. This fact is further

reasserted by Chrysippos, whom Tertullian quotes: incorporeal

things cannot be disjointed from the corporeal because they are

virtually not even in contact with each other. The soul, however,

leaves the body when a human being dies, and therefore it must be

corporeal because, if it was incorporeal, it could not leave the body

at all26. The soul must also be corporeal because the similarity

23 TERTULLIANUS, De an. 5,2 / CCSL 2,786: … qui [scil. Stoici] spiritum

praedicantes animam paene nobiscum, qua proxima inter se flatus et spiritus,

tamen corpus animam facile persuadebunt. For the Stoics, the soul is

, cf. SVF 1,135-140; 2,773 (from NEMESIOS). For Tertullian the soul is

flatus factus ex spiritu (De an. 11,3 / CCSL 2,797).

24 To the difficult question of Tertullian’s sources among which the main place

belonged to the renowned physician of Methodic school, Soranus of Ephesus, who

was strongly influenced by Stoicism himself, cf. H. KARPP, “Sorans vier Bücher

und Tertullians Schrift De anima”, Zeitschrift für die

neutestamentliche Wissenschaft, 33 (1934), p. 31-47; R. POLITO, “I quattro libri

Sull’Anima di Sorano e lo scritto De anima di Tertulliano”, Rivista di storia della

filosofia, 3 (1994), p. 423-468; Z. K. VYSOKÝ, Příspěvky k poznání pramenů spisů

Tertullianových a vzájemných vztahů nejstarší apologetické literatury křesťanské,

Praha, 1937, p. 77-120; J. H. Waszink, ed., Tertulliani De anima, p. 21*-47*; P.

PODOLAK, Soranos von Ephesos, : Sammlung der Testimonien,

Kommentar und Einleitung, Berlin, 2010.

25 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 5,3 / CCSL 2,786-787; cf. also SVF 1,137 (from

NEMESIOS):

26 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 5,6 / CCSL 2,787.

50

between parents and children manifests itself not only

physiognomically, but also in the sphere of the soul; yet only

something corporeal can accept similarity or dissimilarity and the

soul must therefore be corporeal (animam itaque corpus similitudini

vel dissimilitudini obnoxium)27. The corporeality of the soul is,

according to the Stoics, also obvious from the fact that it shares the

feelings and passions of the body (ex corporalium passionum

communione): for example, the fear or shame of the soul is indicated

by the body turning pale or red28.

These arguments, which Tertullian took over without

modification from his sources, are being confused by the Platonics,

as Tertullian explains, rather by subtlety than truth (subtilitate potius

quam veritate), trying to prove that the soul must be incorporeal

(incorporale)29. The Platonics consider every body to be either

animate or inanimate; inanimate bodies are moved from outside,

whereas animate bodies move by themselves. Since the soul, as the

Platonics teach, according to Tertullian, is moved neither from the

outside nor from the inside, it is not possible to declare it corporeal30.

Against this Tertullian objects that this definition cannot even be

applied to the soul, because it is the very soul itself which animates

the body, and therefore it cannot be defined by something which it

establishes itself. Tertullian considers his concluding counter-

argument to be especially valid: the soul moves the body, and if it

was only an “idle, inane thing” (vacua res), which means if it was

incorporeal and without full being, how could it move something

solid (solida propellere)31?

The second argument against the corporeality of the soul

which the Platonics raise is that it is not the bodily senses which

27 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 5,5 / CCSL 2,787.

28 Ibidem.

29 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 6,1 / CCSL 2,787.

30 Cf. PLATO, Phaedr. 245e

31 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 6,1-3 / CCSL 2,787-788. G. SCHELOWSKY, Der

Apologet Tertullianus in seinem Verhältnis zu der griechisch-römischen

Philosophie, Leipzig, 1901, p. 32, suggests that Tertullian uses this argument

(being declared “senseless” in this context by J. H. WASZINK, ed., Tertulliani De

anima, p. 136) to keep up with the Stoic definition of a body as a thing that “makes

something” or “suffers”; cf. also SVF 1,136 (from GALEN):

[scil. ]

51

predicate the soul. If the soul – like other incorporeal qualities, such

as good and evil – can be perceived only by some kind of intellectual

senses, it must be incorporeal32. The bodily senses, as Tertullian

summarises the doctrine of his Platonic antagonists, predicate

corporeal things, yet the soul and its qualities can be conceived only

by the “rational activity of the mind”, which means the intellectual

senses33. The premise that the soul is perceived by the intellectual

senses is unquestionable, even for Tertullian. However, he wants to

reach the conclusion that these intellectual senses can also perceive

something corporeal – for example, the corporeal soul (anima, quae

corporalis, ab incorporalibus renuntietur). He believes that he can

reach this conclusion by means of some kind of very loose analogy,

which logically does not follow from his arguments: if he succeeds

in proving that the bodily senses can perceive even incorporeal

things, he asserts that the intellectual senses can likewise perceive

something corporeal, and therefore that the soul – being perceived by

the intellectual senses – can be corporeal34.

The third argument of the Platonics against the corporeality

of the soul which is recorded and refuted by Tertullian is that

according to them the soul is nourished by incorporeal substances,

by striving for wisdom (sapientiae studiis), or, as Plato puts it, by the

“truth, by that which is divine and not a matter of opinion”35, and

therefore it must be incorporeal. Whereas the refutation of the

previous arguments can be considered to be based on Tertullian’s

own invention, in this case he uses for the same purpose the

authority of Soranus of Ephesus, whose treatise in four

volumes (today lost) was one of his main sources in De anima. The

counter-argument of Soranus, which Tertullian borrows here, is that

on the contrary the soul is nourished by common, that is to say

corporeal, food, because by its lack or absence it departs from the

body. Nourishment by study has, according to Tertullian, no effect

on the substance of the soul (non substantiae proficiunt); it only

cultivates the soul; that is, it modifies it by accident. But even if we

agree that the soul is nourished by the sciences (artes), even these

32 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 6,4 / CCSL 2,784.

33 Cf. PLATO, Phd. 79a-d.

34 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 6,5 / CCSL 2,788.

35 Cf. PLATO, Phd. 84a.

52

sciences are corporeal, according to the Stoics36, and this confirms

the corporeality of the soul37.

The last argument which is refuted by Tertullian is not

attributed to the Platonics but to philosophy in general, which in

Tertullian’s eyes had lost contact with reality, because “the

philosophers are so marvellously abstracted in their speculations that

they can’t see what is in front of them”38. The result is not only the

legendary fall of Thales into the well, which Tertullian does not

neglect to notice spitefully, but also that philosophy (except for the

Stoics) denies the possibility of two bodies existing in one place and,

in consequence, also the corporeality of the soul dwelling in the

body. Tertullian refutes this impossibility of two bodies existing in

one place, observed by Aristotle39, by means of an “ordinary life

argument”; a pregnant woman is, for him, the very example of two

bodies in one place. Everything which is born of something is

actually present in that of which it is born40.

When looking more closely at Tertullian’s arguments refuting

the evidence of the Platonics, it becomes obvious how shaky they

are, which is also a point made by most modern commentators41.

Because we have no time for detailed analysis here, let us say only

that the Stoic proofs of the corporeality of the soul, which Tertullian

borrows, were already being heavily criticised in antiquity (notably

by Alexander of Aphrodisias) and that most of Tertullian’s “counter-

arguments” against the Platonics are probably his own “intellectual

heritage”, as we can judge from their often sophistic form42.

As in his other writings, however, Tertullian cannot be

satisfied with refuting his opponents only by means of “pagan

36 Cf. SVF 2,848 (from PLUTARCH).

37 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 6,6-7 / CCSL 2,788-789.

38 TERTULLIANUS, De an. 6,8 / CCSL 2,789: ... enormis intentio philosophiae solet

plerumque nec prospicere pro pedibus...

39 Cf. ARISTOTELES, De an. 1,5 409b.

40 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 6,8-9 / CCSL 2,789-790. For the Christological

application of this thought cf. Adv. Prax. 8,7 / CCSL 2,1168: Omne quod prodit ex

aliquo, secundum sit eius necesse est de quo prodit, non ideo tamen est separatum.

41 Cf. G. ESSER, Tertullians Seelenlehre, p. 72-73; J. H. WASZINK, ed., Tertulliani

De anima, p. 131-135.

42 Cf. J. H. WASZINK, Tertulliani De anima, p. 132.

53

wisdom”. The supreme argument corroborating the justice of his

statement – that the soul is corporeal – and consequently the climax

of his whole exposition is the word of God: what Scripture says must

be true43. In chapter seven of his De anima Tertullian thus quotes the

story about Lazarus and the rich man as the proof par excellence of

the corporeality of the soul44. The soul of the rich man surely suffers

in the underworld from thirst and longs for the drop of water from

the happier soul of Lazarus. Tertullian’s exegesis of this passage

from Scripture45 is focused on two points. The first one is connected

with its literal meaning, which Tertullian supports. Against the

allegorical interpretation of this parable, which was probably

common (as Clemens of Alexandria testifies)46, Tertullian again

argues somewhat sophistically. If we should understand the whole

story only as a metaphor (imaginem), why is the name of Lazarus

given? But even if it is really a parable, even then it proves the

corporeality of the soul. The image cannot be completely separated

from its model and if the parable mentions bodily limbs, these must

exist in reality. If this was not the case, Scripture must have lied,

which it cannot. Although the image only copies the truth of the

original, the original must already be contained in this image – the

original must first exist in itself in order that the image can be born47.

43 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De carne Chr. 3,9 / CCSL 2,878: ...non potest non fuisse,

quod scriptum est.

44 Cf. Luke 16,19-31.

45 Cf. in general, e.g. R. P. C. HANSON, “Notes on Tertullian’s Interpretation of

Scripture”, Journal of Theological Studies, New Series, 22 (1961), p. 273-279; T.

P. O’Malley, Tertullian and the Bible. Language – Imagery – Exegesis, Nijmegen,

1967; J. H. WASZINK, “Tertullian’s Principles and Methods of Exegesis”, in Early

Christian Literature and the Classical Intellectual Tradition, ed. W. R. SCHOEDEL

et al., Paris, 1979, p. 9-31; CH. KANNENGIESSER, Handbook of Patristic Exegesis.

The Bible in Ancient Christianity, Leiden – Boston, 2006, p. 593-622.

46 Cf. CLEMEMS ALEXANDRINUS, Strom. 4,6,30,4:

47 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 7,1-4 / CCSL 2,790; see also TERTULLIANUS, De

resurr. mort. 30,5 / CCSL 2,959: Nam etsi figmentum veritatis in imagine est,

imago ipsa in veritate est sui: necesse est esse prius sibi id quod alii configuretur.

De vacuo similitudo non conpetit, de nullo parabola non convenit.; Adv. Marc.

V,14,3 / CCSL 1,705: Similitudo autem dicitur, cum est quod videtur. Est enim,

dum alterius par est. Cf. also G. R. HAUSCHILD, Tertullian’s Psychologie, p. 23-

24. As R. H. AYERS, Language, Logic, and Reason in the Church Fathers: A Study

of Tertullian, Augustine, and Aquinas, Hildesheim – New York, 1979, p. 15, sums

54

The second and even more weighty reason why the Lazarus

story must bear witness to the corporeality of the soul is the

scriptural reference to the soul of the rich man being kept in the

underworld (detinetur illic) and tortured there (cruciatur). If the soul

had no body and was a mere nothing, how could it be kept

somewhere and be punished or refreshed there? Only that which has

a body can feel something and if it feels something it must have a

body48.

In the context of early Christian literature Tertullian’s

exegesis of the Lazarus parable is not unique. Irenaeus argues in the

same way, considering this passage to be not a parable but a report

(relatio), which proves that after death souls retain the shape of the

body of the respective deceased, so they can be distinguished from

each other49. At other times Irenaeus claims the soul to be

incorporeal50 or to have the shape of the body in which it dwells,

analogous to water poured into a jar or frozen in a jar which takes

over the jar’s form51. Considering the fact that Tertullian must have

up: “For Tertullian such expressions (scil. figurative or metaphorical) function

inappropriately and are plagued with meaninglessness unless they are capable of

implying literally true statements.”

48 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 7,3-4 / CCSL 2,790.

49 Cf. IRENAEUS, Adv. haer. 2,34,1 / SC 294,354: Plenissime autem Dominus

docuit non solum perseverare non de corpore in corpus transgredientes animas,

sed et characterem corporis in quo etiam adaptantur custodire eundem, et

meminisse eas operum quae egerunt hic et a quibus cessaverunt, in ea relatione

quae scribitur de divite et de Eleazaro eo qui refrigerabat in sinu Abrahae: in qua

ait divitem cognoscere Elazarum post mortem et Abraham autem similiter …

50 Cf. IRENAEUS, Adv. haer. 5,7,1 / SC 153,84-86: Sed incorporales animae,

quantum ad comparationem mortalium corporum: insufflavit enim in faciem

hominis Deus flatum vitae, et factus est homo in animam viventem: flatus autem

vitae incorporalis.

51 Cf. IRENAEUS, Adv. haer. 2,19,6 / SC 294,192-194: Non enim Angelorum

habebit [sc. semen] similitudinem et speciem, sed animarum in quibus et formatur,

quomodo aqua in vas missa ipsius vasi habebit formam et iam, si gelaverit in eo,

speciem habebit vasculi in quo gelavit, quando ipsae animae corporis habeant

figuram … To Irenaeus’s concept of the soul see especially D. WYRWA,

Seelenverständnis bei Irenäus von Lyon, in – Seele – anima. Festschrift für

Karin Alt zum 7. Mai 1998, ed. J. HOLZHAUSEN, Stuttgart – Leipzig, 1998, p. 301-

334, here especially p. 309-311.

55

known Irenaeus’ works52, he could have borrowed some of his ideas

here and thought them through radically. It is no surprise that it was

Vincentius Victor, one of the few known consistent adherents of

Tertullian’s doctrine of the corporeality of the soul, who insisted also

upon the literal exegesis of the parable of Lazarus and the rich man,

as we know from Augustine53.

The soul must also have its body, as Tertullian thinks, in

order to be able to be punished or rewarded after death. The souls of

all the deceased descend into Hades after death, where they wait for

the Last Judgement, the only exception being the souls of martyrs,

which go directly to heaven54. The Czech scholar Zdeněk K. Vysoký

has drawn attention to the fact55 that the capability of the soul to

accept punishment or reward was equally important for Justin,

whose treatise , which today is lost, he considers to be

one of the main Christian sources of Tertullian’s De anima56. Justin

says of the soul that what is incorporeal cannot feel anything57,

which suggests, as Vysoký remarks, that Justin himself could have

thought of the soul as corporeal and that he could have been one of

Tertullian’s inspiratory sources.

After summarising all the arguments in favour of the

corporeality of the soul, in chapter eight Tertullian focuses on the

other objections of those who claim the soul to be incorporeal. The

main content of this chapter is the invisibility of the soul, which,

52 Cf. A. VON HARNACK, Tertullians Bibliothek christlicher Schriften, in IDEM,

Kleine Schriften zur Alten Kirche, 2, Leipzig, 1980, p. 227-258.

53 Cf. AUGUSTINUS, De nat. et orig. an. 4,16,23 / Corpus scriptorum

ecclesiasticorum latinorum (= CSEL) 60,402. Tertullian’s polemics against

Vicentius Victor is analysed in detail by A. C. DE VEER, “Aux origines du De

natura et origine animae de saint Augustin”, Revue des études augustiniennes, 19

(1973), p. 121-157. Other authors who interpreted this scriptural passage in a way

similar to Tertullian are listed by J. H. WASZINK, ed., Tertulliani De anima, p. 148-

149.

54 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 55,5 / CCSL 2,863.

55 Z. K. VYSOKÝ, Příspěvky k poznání, p. 88.

56 Cf. A. VON HARNACK, Tertullians Bibliothek, p. 242-243.

57 Cf. IUSTINUS, Dial. c. Tryph. 1,5:

56

however, does not preclude its corporeality. As we have seen earlier,

in order even to be, the soul must possess something by which it

exists, and when the soul is invisible, it must possess something by

which it is invisible and this something must be its body58. This

invisibility is actually only relative, because the soul is not visible to

the human body, or to the eyes of the body, but it is visible to the

Spirit of God, to itself, or to God’s elected ones (John sees the souls

of martyrs in Apoc. 6, 9)59.

The fact that the soul is invisible flows from the nature of its

corporeal substance and is determined by its own nature. Besides,

of its very nature it is destined to be invisible to certain things60.

The soul is also a body sui generis, just like every other substance

that really exists. Some of its qualities, such as invisibility, are

different from other bodies, but it must share other qualities with the

other bodies. According to this logic Tertullian must attribute to the

soul qualities by which other bodies are characterised, which he

indeed tries to do in chapter nine. Strictly speaking, Tertullian

contradicts himself in this point, since he declared the soul to be a

body sui generis, which means that it must not share the qualities of

other bodies. Tertullian writes that the soul possesses “the cardinal

attributes of bodies”61: it has coherence (habitum), definiteness

(terminum), it is delimited by three dimensions (trifariam

distantivum), and it also has form (effigiem) and colour (colorem).

As the main evidence that the soul has form, which is denied by

Plato (because for him the form implies composition and what is

composite is liable to disintegration and cannot be immortal, while

the soul is immortal)62, Tertullian somewhat curiously introduces a

vision of a fellow-Christian, who, in ecstasy, saw the human soul,

58 Cf. above, note 9.

59 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 8,5 / CCSL 2,791; 53,6 / CCL 2,861.

60 TERTULLIANUS, De an. 8,4 / CCSL 2,791: Ceterum etsi invisibilis anima, et pro

condicione corporis sui et proprietate substantiae et pro natura etiam eorum

quibus invisiblis esse sortita est.

61 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 9,1 / CCSL 2,792: ...sollemniora quaeque et

omnimodo debita corpulentiae adesse animae...

62 J. H. WASZINK, ed., Tertulliani De anima, p. 165, points out that this syllogism

does not feature in such a form in the works of Plato, cf. PLATO, Phd. 78b-c;

Phaedr. 247c.

57

which was “soft and light and of an ethereal color, and in shape

altogether like a human being”63. Notwithstanding the importance of

this passage of De anima for the whole complex of theological-

historical questions connected with Tertullian’s Montanism and his

place in the Christian community of Carthage, from the

philosophical point of view it does not yield anything substantive,

and therefore I will not examine it here64.

However, Tertullian considers this vision to be authoritative

because, inspired by the Holy Ghost, it bears witness to the other

specific qualities of the soul: it has the colour of lucid air (aerium ac

lucidum), and this is also confirmed by the fact that the soul is a

“breath” (flatus) and a “sprout” (tradux), originating from the Spirit

of God, and everything which is light and fine resembles the air. The

air is nevertheless not the substance (substantia) of the soul, as many

Greek philosophers believed65. Tertullian tries to find the

confirmation of his conviction that the soul has shape, the shape of

the actual body which it “wears” (eius corporis quod … circumtulit),

in the Old Testament story about the Creation (Gn 2, 7)66: God has

breathed into the face of the first man the breath of life (flatum vitae)

and man became a “living soul” (animam vivam). This breath of

God’s does not equal the Spirit of God or God Himself; it is neither

part of his substance, nor his emanation, but it is an individual

substance, which is the “product” of God’s spirit67, thanks to which

man acquires his substantial kinship and similarity to God and

becomes his image68. This breath of God entered the body of man

through his face and diffused here. At the same time this breath filled

63 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 9,4 / CCSL 2,793: ...tenera et lucida et aerii coloris,

et forma per omnia humana.

64 For an exhaustive commentary ad locum cf. J. H. WASZINKK, ed., Tertulliani De

anima, p. 167-173; cf also, e.g., L. NASRALLAH, An Ecstasy of Folly. Prophecy

and Authority in Early Christianity, Cambridge (Mass.), 2003.

65 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 9,5-6 / CCSL 2,792-793.

66 To the extraordinary authority the book of Genesis has for Tertullian, cf. G. T.

Armstrong, Die Genesis in der alten Kirche. Die drei Kirchenväter, Tübingen,

1962, p. 100-101, to Tertullian’s doctrinbe of the soul p. 112-117.

67 Cf. H. KARPP, Probleme altchristlicher Anthropologie, p. 53.

68 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, Adv. Marc. 2,9,2-3 / CCSL 1,484-485: Capit etiam

imaginem spiritus dicere flatum. Nam et ideo homo imago dei, id est spiritus; deus

enim spiritus.

58

up all the inner spaces of the body69. This breath also became thick

and so it took up the shapes of these inner spaces of the body and

solidified, creating a kind of a form70. By this process the exact

casting of the body was created, which fills it completely so that it

has the same limbs as the “real” body, using them when thinking or

dreaming, and therefore Lazarus can have fingers in the underworld

and the rich man can have a tongue. This “casting” is finally the

“inner man” (homo interior) mentioned by St. Paul71; Tertullian is

thus probably the first to interpret this Pauline term

anthropologically, not ethically72. One more thing needs to be

clarified: the existence of two bodies in one place, in this case the

“casting” and the real human body, makes no trouble for Tertullian –

he uses the Stoic notion of mixing,

Even in the matter of the soul’s shape Tertullian could have

used some of the thought parallels in the works of his above-

mentioned Greek predecessors. Irenaeus, for example, explicitly

asserts that souls have the shapes of the human bodies they

inhabited, and so they can be distinguished from each other74. This

topic, however, was elaborated by Tertullian with such consistency

that we can hardly find any parallel in the extant early Christian

literature. The only exception is the above-mentioned Vincentius

69 Also for the Stoics the soul permeates the whole body, cf. SVF 1,145 (from

THEMISTIUS): … ’

70 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, De an. 9,7 / CCSL 2,793: … per faciem statim flatum illum

in interiora transmissum et per universa corporis spatia diffusum simulque divina

aspiratione densatum omni intu linea expressum esse, quam densatus impleverat,

et velut in forma gelasse.

71 Cf. 2Cor 4,16; Rom 7,22.

72 Thus G. SCHELOWSKY, Der Apologet Tertullianus, p. 49.

73 Cf. SVF 2,471 (from STOBAEUS); or is for Stoics such kind of a

mixture when the two constituents permeat perfectly, without, however, loosing

their distinctive qualities. Tertullian is well aware of this “mixture” that he uses in

the Christological and Trinitarian context to explain both natures of Christ, cf.

TERTULLIANUS, Adv. Prax. 27,11 / CCSL 2,1199: ... duplicem statum, non

confusum, sed coniunctum in una persona, deum et hominem Iesum... Cf. also R.

BRAUN, Deus Christianorum, p. 313sqq.; M. L. COLISH, The Stoic Tradition from

Antiquity to the Early Middle Ages, 2: Stoicism in Christian Latin Thought through

the Sixth Century, Leiden, 1985, p. 23-24.

74 Cf. above, note 49.

59

Victor, who even in this matter adhered rigidly to his model: he

speaks about the soul which filled up the body and solidified here,

thus creating the “inner man”75.

4.

Tertullian’s corporealism, which he used by means of Stoic

philosophy in order to give a definition of the human soul and of the

Christian God, did not win out. This, however, does not mean that

his concept of the corporeality of everything which exists found no

response76. Augustine, the first to place Tertullian in his list of

heretics (even though he does not connect his heresy primarily with

his corporealism, but with his adherence to Montanism)77, mentions

his own youthful thoughts, which were not different to what

Tertullian thought. Augustine imagined evil to be not only a

substance but even something corporeal, and he was able to imagine

the mind only as corporeal, too78. It seemed to him that corporeality

belongs not only to the soul but also to God himself79.

75 Cf. AUGUSTINUS, De nat. et orig. an. 4,14,20 / CSEL 60,399-400; 4,20,33 /

CSEL 60,411.

76 Besides Vincentius Victor, the main adherents of the corporeality of the soul,

apparently inspired by Tertullian, were Cassianus, Hilarius Pictaviensis and

Faustus of Riez, cf. M. L. COLISH, Stoic Tradition, 2, p. 121-122, 124-125 and

128-129. To the doctrine of Faustus of Riez and its critique by Claudius

Mammertus cf. E. L. FRONTIN, Christianisme et culture philosophique au

cinquième siècle. La querelle de l’âme humaine en Occident, Paris, 1959.

77 Cf. AUGUSTINUS, De haer. 86 / CCSL 46,338-339.

78 Cf. AUGUSTINUS, Confess. 5,10,20 / CCSL 27,69: … quod [scil. malum] mihi

nescienti non solum aliqua substantia, sed etiam corporea videbatur, quia et

mentem cogitare non noveram nisi eam subtile corpus esse, quod tamen per loci

spatia diffunderetur …

79 Cf. AUGUSTINUS, Solil. 2,17,31 / Patrologia latina (= PL) 32,900: Viderentur, si

aut inane nihil esse certum haberem, aut ipsum animum inter corpora

numerandum arbitrarer, aut etiam Deum corpus aliquod esse crederem. Cf. also

AUGUSTINUS, Ep. 166,2,4 / CSEL 44,550,13: … si corpus est omnis substantia vel

essentia vel si quid aptius nuncupatur id, quod aliquo modo est in se ipso, corpus

est anima; see also Confess. 7,1,1 / CCSL 27,92. The first to have proved that the

idea of corporealism (belief in a corporeal God) was not so rare in the early

Church as has been suggested was D. L. PAULSEN, “Early Christian Belief in a

Corporeal Deity: Origen and Augustine as Reluctant Witnesess”, The Harvard

Theological Review, 83 (1990), p. 105-116, who claims that (p. 105): “…ordinary

60

Although Augustine, like almost all early Christian thinkers,

became attached to the side of Tertullian’s opponents in the question

of the corporeality of the soul80, it seems that in considering his own

spiritual progression he had some sympathy for Tertullian’s doctrine

and he even defends it in a way. According to his words, Tertullian

thought the soul and God to be corporeal because he was not able to

think of them as incorporeal and he was afraid that if they were not a

body, they would be nothing and would not exist at all81. Besides,

Augustine continues, God can be called a body, a body sui generis,

in the sense that God really exists, he is something and he is not the

quality of the soul or body82.

Tertullian’s motivation for proclaiming the soul to be

corporeal, however, is apparently more complex. His primary goal

was to eliminate Gnostic and related doctrines inspired by Platonism

(e.g. the Valentinians, Hermogenes, or Marcion) because in his eyes

it is, for example, the very Platonism, with its mistrust in the fidelity

Christians for at least the first three centuries of the current era commonly (and

perhaps generally) believed God to be corporeal.” See also C. W. GRIFFIN, D. L.

PAULSEN, “Augustine and the Corporeality of God”, The Harvard Theological

Review, 95 (2002), p 97-118, who conclude: “the conception of an

anthropomorphic/corporeal deity was the only theology Augustine had known …

before Milan” (p. 118).

80 Cf. AUGUSTINUS, De beata vita, 1,4 / CCSL 29,67: … cum de deo cogitaretur,

nihil omnino corporis esse cogitandum, neque cum de anima; nam id est unum in

rebus proximum deo. On Augustine’s own hesitating attitude to the question of

ensoulment cf. also L. KARFÍKOVÁ, Grace and the Will according to Tertullian,

Leiden, 2012, p. 214-224; cf. also the overview of D. A. JONES, The Soul of the

Embryo. An Enquiry into the Status of the Human Embryo in the Christian

Tradition, London – New York, 2004, p. 92-108.

81 Cf. AUGUSTINUS, De Gen. ad litt. 10,25 / CSEL 28.1,328: Denique Tertullianus,

quia corpus esse animam credidit non ob aliud, nisi quod eam incorpoream

cogitare non potuit et ideo timuit, ne nihil esset, si corpus non esset, nec de deo

valuit aliter sapere: qui sane quoniam est acutus interdum contra opinionem suam

visa veritate superatur.

82 Cf. AUGUSTINUS, De haer. 86 / CCSL 46,338: Posset enim quoquo modo putari

ipsam naturam substantiamque divinam corpus vocare, non tale corpus cuius

partes aliae maiores, aliae minores valeant vel debeant cogitari, qualia sunt

omnia quae proprie dicimus corpora, quamvis de anima tale aliquid sentiat. Sed

potuit, ut dixi, propterea putari corpus deum dicere, quia non est nihil, non est

inanitas, non est corporis vel animae qualitas, sed ubique totus, et per locorum

spatia nulla partitus, in sua tamen natura atque substantia incommutabiliter

permanet.

61

of the senses, which is the source of Gnostic Docetism or of the

effort to separate God from the material world and to deny God’s

obvious connection with what he created83. The suspicion that

Tertullian developed his concept of the corporeal soul as a direct

response to refute his heretic opponents seems to be confirmed by

the fact that it is in his anti-heretic treatises where it appears for the

first time84. In his Apologeticum, which is one of his earliest

writings, Tertullian says that when the Judgement Day will come,

the souls alone would not be able to feel any punishment would they

be deprived of materia stabilis, that is of body85. This belief which

clearly contradicts his attitude expressed in De anima, Tertullian

repeats also in De resurrectione mortuorum, but this time he ascribes

it to “ordinary people” (vulgus) and – in polemics against the

Gnostics who denied the resurrection of the flesh – claims himself to

be an adherent of the corporeality of the soul formulated in his De

anima86.

The concept of the corporeality of the soul that Tertullian

defends fiercely in his De anima to refute the dangers of Gnostic

“idealism”, has, however, also a positive corollary for other difficult

aspects of the nascent early Christian theology. According to

83 Cf. M. L. COLISH, The Stoic Tradition, 2, p. 19. For (early) modern implications

of Tertullian’s notion of the corporeal soul, cf. R. BRENNAN, “Has a Frog Human a

Soul – Huxley, Tertullian, Physicalism and the soul. Some Historical

Antecedents”, Scottish Journal of Theology, 66 (2013), p. 400-413.

84 Already P. BOUËDRON, Quid senserit de natura animae Tertullianus, p. 66-74,

has pointed this out.

85 Cf. TERTULLIANUS, Apol. 48,4 / CCSL 1,166: Ideoque repraesentabuntur et

corpora, quia neque pati quicquam potest anima sola sine materia stabili, id est

carne...

86 Cf. TERTULLIAN, De resurr. mort. 17,1-2 / CCSL 2,941: Simplicior quisque

fautor sententiae nostrae putabit carnem etiam idcirco repraesentandam esse

iudicio, quia aliter anima non capiat passionem tormenti seu refrigerii, utpote

incorporalis; hoc enim vulgus existimat. Nos autem animam corporalem et hic

profitemur et in suo volumine probavimus, habentem proprium genus

[substantiae] soliditatis, per quam quid et sentire et pati possit. Nam et nunc

animas torqueri foverique penes inferos, licet nudas, licet adhuc exules carnis,

probabit <E>l<e>azari exemplum. Cf., however, P. SINISCALCO, “Anima sine

materia stabili. Per la storia dell’interpretazione di alcuni passi di Tertulliano

(Apol. 48,4; Test. 4,1)” in Hommage à René Braun, 2: Autour de Tertullien, ed. J.

GRANAROLO, M. BIRAUD, Nice, 1990, p. 111-128, who tries to reconcile these

contradictions asserting that Tertullian’s doctrine remained unchanged.

62

Tertullian, the soul must be corporeal because it has its origin in the

corporeal God. If then the nature of God is corporeal, it helps

Tertullian to solve the problem of both the natures of Christ, which,

according to the principle of Stoic , can co-exist as two

corporeal components in one person without being confused or

without losing their individual substance. The logical consequence of

this concept is also a doctrine of the corporeality of the soul, which

will be analogically mixed with the body.

Though Tertullian found the most effective weapons against

his opponents in Stoicism, it is not precise to call him “the

Heraclitean Stoic”, as Eric Osborn does87. Tertullian was not

“primarily or exclusively a supporter, an enemy, or a transformer of

Stoicism. He does all of these things simultaneously and to

approximately the same degree88.” His use of the Stoic tradition, as

well as of the antique cultural tradition in general, is utilitarian and

eclectic, always with respect to the context and specific opponent he

wants to refute. At the same time, there is something more in his

approach: he also uses this cultural tradition, which he belongs to, as

a tool for exploring the Christian faith; he redefines this tradition in

terms of the new Christian religion and its needs and contributes – in

the words of Jean-Claude Fredouille – to its final “conversion”89.

87 E. OSBORN, Tertullian, First Theologian of the West, Cambridge, 1997, p. 163.

88 M. L. COLISH, The Stoic Tradition, 2, p. 13.

89 Cf. J.-CL. FREDOUILLE, Tertullien et la conversion de la culture antique, Paris,

1972.

63

Summary

This paper focuses on Tertullian’s concept of the human soul (as

treated mainly in his De anima), and especially on Tertullian’s

notion of its corporeality (corporalitas) which he advocates and

which can seem surprising at the first glance. First, the philosophical

context of this idea is examined: according to Tertullian’s

“corporealistic ontology” borrowed from Stoicism, the corporeality

is a necessary prerequisite of everything that really is, including God

and soul that have to have its “bodies” (corpus) in order to exist in

the first place. These bodies, however, are always sui generis, and

Tertullian’s corporealism thus does not equal materialism. From the

subsequent analysis of Tertullian’s arguments in favour of the soul’s

corporeality it follows that the Carthaginian probably developed this

doctrine only later in his life as a direct response to refute his

“heretic” opponents inspired by Platonism, and he could probably

draw on similar thoughts expressed by Justin. Although his concept

did not win out and found only extremely limited response in later

centuries, it cannot be considered an isolated thought experiment

only, which is testified to at least by remarks by Augustine that he

had dealt with similar problems in his youth.