cmsc 471 fall 2002

23
1 CMSC 471 CMSC 471 Fall 2002 Fall 2002 Class #19 – Monday, November 4

Upload: floria

Post on 11-Feb-2016

25 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

DESCRIPTION

CMSC 471 Fall 2002. Class #19 – Monday, November 4. Today’s class. (Probability theory) Bayesian inference From the joint distribution Using independence/factoring From sources of evidence Bayesian networks Network structure Conditional probability tables Conditional independence - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

1

CMSC 471CMSC 471Fall 2002Fall 2002

Class #19 – Monday, November 4

Page 2: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

2

Today’s class

• (Probability theory)• Bayesian inference

– From the joint distribution– Using independence/factoring– From sources of evidence

• Bayesian networks– Network structure– Conditional probability tables– Conditional independence– Inference in Bayesian networks

Page 3: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

3

Bayesian Reasoning /Bayesian Reasoning /Bayesian NetworksBayesian Networks

Chapters 14, 15.1-15.2

Page 4: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

4

Why probabilities anyway?• Kolmogorov showed that three simple axioms lead to the

rules of probability theory– De Finetti, Cox, and Carnap have also provided compelling

arguments for these axioms1. All probabilities are between 0 and 1:

• 0 <= P(a) <= 12. Valid propositions (tautologies) have probability 1, and

unsatisfiable propositions have probability 0:• P(true) = 1 ; P(false) = 0

3. The probability of a disjunction is given by:• P(a b) = P(a) + P(b) – P(a b)

aba b

Page 5: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

5

Inference from the joint: Examplealarm ¬alarmearthquake ¬earthquake earthquake ¬earthquake

burglary .001 .008 .0001 .0009¬burglary .01 .09 .001 .79

P(Burglary | alarm) = α P(Burglary, alarm) = α [P(Burglary, alarm, earthquake) + P(Burglary, alarm, ¬earthquake) = α [ (.001, .01) + (.008, .09) ] = α [ (.009, .1) ]

Since P(burglary | alarm) + P(¬burglary | alarm) = 1, α = 1/(.009+.1) = 9.173 (i.e., P(alarm) = 1/α = .109 – quizlet: how can you verify this?)

P(burglary | alarm) = .009 * 9.173 = .08255

P(¬burglary | alarm) = .1 * 9.173 = .9173

Page 6: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

6

Independence• When two sets of propositions do not affect each others’

probabilities, we call them independent, and can easily compute their joint and conditional probability:– Independent (A, B) → P(A B) = P(A) P(B), P(A | B) = P(A)

• For example, {moon-phase, light-level} might be independent of {burglary, alarm, earthquake}– Then again, it might not: Burglars might be more likely to

burglarize houses when there’s a new moon (and hence little light)– But if we know the light level, the moon phase doesn’t affect

whether we are burglarized– Once we’re burglarized, light level doesn’t affect whether the alarm

goes off• We need a more complex notion of independence, and

methods for reasoning about these kinds of relationships

Page 7: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

7

Conditional independence• Absolute independence:

– A and B are independent if P(A B) = P(A) P(B); equivalently, P(A) = P(A | B) and P(B) = P(B | A)

• A and B are conditionally independent given C if– P(A B | C) = P(A | C) P(B | C)

• This lets us decompose the joint distribution:– P(A B C) = P(A | C) P(B | C) P(C)

• Moon-Phase and Burglary are conditionally independent given Light-Level

• Conditional independence is weaker than absolute independence, but still useful in decomposing the full joint probability distribution

Page 8: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

8

Bayes’ rule• Bayes rule is derived from the product rule:

– P(Y | X) = P(X | Y) P(Y) / P(X)

• Often useful for diagnosis: – If X are (observed) effects and Y are (hidden) causes, – We may have a model for how causes lead to effects (P(X | Y))– We may also have prior beliefs (based on experience) about the

frequency of occurrence of effects (P(Y))– Which allows us to reason abductively from effects to causes (P(Y |

X)).

Page 9: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

9

Bayesian inference• In the setting of diagnostic/evidential reasoning

– Know prior probability of hypothesis conditional probability

– Want to compute the posterior probability• Bayes’ theorem (formula 1):

onsanifestatievidence/m

hypotheses

1 mj

i

EEE

H

)(/)|()()|( jijiji EPHEPHPEHP

)( iHP)|( ij HEP

)|( ij HEP

)|( ji EHP

)( iHP

Page 10: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

10

Simple Bayesian diagnostic reasoning

• Knowledge base:– Evidence / manifestations: E1, … Em

– Hypotheses / disorders: H1, … Hn

• Ej and Hi are binary; hypotheses are mutually exclusive (non-overlapping) and exhaustive (cover all possible cases)

– Conditional probabilities: P(Ej | Hi), i = 1, … n; j = 1, … m

• Cases (evidence for a particular instance): E1, …, El

• Goal: Find the hypothesis Hi with the highest posterior– Maxi P(Hi | E1, …, El)

Page 11: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

11

Bayesian diagnostic reasoning II

• Bayes’ rule says that– P(Hi | E1, …, El) = P(E1, …, El | Hi) P(Hi) / P(E1, …, El)

• Assume each piece of evidence Ei is conditionally independent of the others, given a hypothesis Hi, then:– P(E1, …, El | Hi) = l

j=1 P(Ej | Hi)

• If we only care about relative probabilities for the Hi, then we have:– P(Hi | E1, …, El) = α P(Hi) l

j=1 P(Ej | Hi)

Page 12: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

12

Limitations of simple Bayesian inference

• Cannot easily handle multi-fault situation, nor cases where intermediate (hidden) causes exist:– Disease D causes syndrome S, which causes correlated

manifestations M1 and M2

• Consider a composite hypothesis H1 H2, where H1 and H2 are independent. What is the relative posterior?– P(H1 H2 | E1, …, El) = α P(E1, …, El | H1 H2) P(H1 H2)

= α P(E1, …, El | H1 H2) P(H1) P(H2)= α l

j=1 P(Ej | H1 H2) P(H1) P(H2)

• How do we compute P(Ej | H1 H2) ??

Page 13: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

13

Limitations of simple Bayesian inference II

• Assume H1 and H2 are independent, given E1, …, El?– P(H1 H2 | E1, …, El) = P(H1 | E1, …, El) P(H2 | E1, …, El)

• This is a very unreasonable assumption– Earthquake and Burglar are independent, but not given Alarm:

• P(burglar | alarm, earthquake) << P(burglar | alarm)

• Another limitation is that simple application of Bayes’ rule doesn’t allow us to handle causal chaining:– A: year’s weather; B: cotton production; C: next year’s cotton price– A influences C indirectly: A→ B → C– P(C | B, A) = P(C | B)

• Need a richer representation to model interacting hypotheses, conditional independence, and causal chaining

• Next time: conditional independence and Bayesian networks!

Page 14: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

14

Bayesian Belief Networks (BNs)

• Definition: BN = (DAG, CPD) – DAG: directed acyclic graph (BN’s structure)

• Nodes: random variables (typically binary or discrete, but methods also exist to handle continuous variables)

• Arcs: indicate probabilistic dependencies between nodes (lack of link signifies conditional independence)

– CPD: conditional probability distribution (BN’s parameters)• Conditional probabilities at each node, usually stored as a table

(conditional probability table, or CPT)

– Root nodes are a special case – no parents, so just use priors in CPD:

iiii xxP of nodesparent all ofset theis where)|(

)()|( so , iiii xPxP

Page 15: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

15

Example BN

a

b c

d e

P(C|A) = 0.2 P(C|~A) = 0.005P(B|A) = 0.3

P(B|~A) = 0.001

P(A) = 0.001

P(D|B,C) = 0.1 P(D|B,~C) = 0.01P(D|~B,C) = 0.01 P(D|~B,~C) = 0.00001

P(E|C) = 0.4 P(E|~C) = 0.002

Note that we only specify P(A) etc., not P(¬A), since they have to add to one

Page 16: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

16

Topological semantics

• A node is conditionally independent of its non-descendants given its parents

• A node is conditionally independent of all other nodes in the network given its parents, children, and children’s parents (also known as its Markov blanket)

• The method called d-separation can be applied to decide whether a set of nodes X is independent of another set Y, given a third set Z

Page 17: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

17

• Independence assumption–

where q is any set of variables (nodes) other than and its successors

– blocks influence of other nodes on and its successors (q influences onlythrough variables in )

– With this assumption, the complete joint probability distribution of all variables in the network can be represented by (recovered from) local CPD by chaining these CPD

ix

)|(),...,( 11 iinin xPxxP

)|(),|( iiii xPqxP

ix i ix

i q

ix i

Independence and chaining

Page 18: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

18

Chaining: Example

Computing the joint probability for all variables is easy:

P(a, b, c, d, e) = P(e | a, b, c, d) P(a, b, c, d) by Bayes’ theorem= P(e | c) P(a, b, c, d) by indep. assumption= P(e | c) P(d | a, b, c) P(a, b, c) = P(e | c) P(d | b, c) P(c | a, b) P(a, b)= P(e | c) P(d | b, c) P(c | a) P(b | a) P(a)

a

b c

d e

Page 19: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

19

Direct inference with BNs

• Now suppose we just want the probability for one variable• Belief update method• Original belief (no variables are instantiated): Use prior

probability p(xi)

• If xi is a root, then P(xi) is given directly in the BN (CPT at Xi)• Otherwise,

– P(xi) = Σ πi P(xi | πi) P(πi)

• In this equation, P(xi | πi) is given in the CPT, but computing P(πi) is complicated

Page 20: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

20

Computing πi: Example

• P (d) = P(d | b, c) P(b, c)• P(b, c) = P(a, b, c) + P(¬a, b, c) (marginalizing)

= P(b | a, c) p (a, c) + p(b | ¬a, c) p(¬a, c) (product rule)= P(b | a) P(c | a) P(a) + P(b | ¬a) P(c | ¬a) P(¬a)

• If some variables are instantiated, can “plug that in” and reduce amount of marginalization

• Still have to marginalize over all values of uninstantiated parents – not computationally feasible with large networks

a

b c

d e

Page 21: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

21

Representational extensions

• Compactly representing CPTs– Noisy-OR – Noisy-MAX

• Adding continuous variables– Discretization– Use density functions (usually mixtures of Gaussians) to build

hybrid Bayesian networks (with discrete and continuous variables)

Page 22: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

22

Inference tasks• Simple queries: Computer posterior marginal P(Xi | E=e)

– E.g., P(NoGas | Gauge=empty, Lights=on, Starts=false)

• Conjunctive queries: – P(Xi, Xj | E=e) = P(Xi | e=e) P(Xj | Xi, E=e)

• Optimal decisions: Decision networks include utility information; probabilistic inference is required to find P(outcome | action, evidence)

• Value of information: Which evidence should we seek next?• Sensitivity analysis: Which probability values are most

critical?• Explanation: Why do I need a new starter motor?

Page 23: CMSC 471 Fall 2002

23

Approaches to inference

• Exact inference – Enumeration– Variable elimination– Clustering / join tree algorithms

• Approximate inference– Stochastic simulation / sampling methods– Markov chain Monte Carlo methods– Genetic algorithms– Neural networks– Simulated annealing– Mean field theory