chihara c._the semantic paradoxes - a diagnostic investigation

30
The Semantic Paradoxes: A Diagnostic Investigation Charles Chihara The Philosophical Review, Vol. 88, No. 4 (Oct., 1979), 590-618. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=003 1-8108%28 1979 10%2988%3A4%3C590%3ATSPADI%3E2.O.CO%3B2-V The Philosophical Review is currently published by Cornell University. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/sageschool.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on JSTOR contact [email protected]. 02003 JSTOR http://www.jstor.org/ Sun Nov 16 15:58:58 2003

Upload: ramiro-schere

Post on 26-Nov-2015

17 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

The Semantic Paradoxes: A Diagnostic Investigation

Charles Chihara

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 88, No. 4 (Oct., 1979), 590-618.

Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=003 1-8108%28 1979 10%2988%3A4%3C590%3ATSPADI%3E2.O.CO%3B2-V

The Philosophical Review is currently published by Cornell University.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/sageschool.html.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

For more information on JSTOR contact [email protected].

02003 JSTOR

http://www.jstor.org/ Sun Nov 16 15:58:58 2003

Page 2: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

The Philosophzcal Reuiew, LXXXVIII, No. 4 (October 1979).

THE SEMANTIC PARADOXES:

A Diagnostic Investigation

Charles Chihara

I n this paper, I shall give "diagnoses" of the principal semantic paradoxes (or antinomies) that have played such a significant

role in developments in the foundations of logic and mathe- matics.' I use the term 'diagnoses' rather than the more stan- dard 'solutions' for two principal reasons. First of all, I wish to indicate that I am concerned with only one of two closely related problems raised by the paradoxes. Alfred Tarski once remarked: "The appearance of an antinomy is for me a symptom of dis- ease."2 But what disease? That is the diagnostic problem. We have an argument that begins with premises that appear to be clearly true, that proceeds according to inference rules that appear to be valid, but that ends in a contradiction. Evidently, something appears to be the case that isn't. The problem of pin- pointing that which is deceiving us and, if possible, explaining how and why the deception was produced is what I wish to call 'the diagnostic problem of the paradox'. The related problem of de-

- --

I Many of the basic ideas of this paper are contained, in an obscure and inchoate form, in an article I wrote many years ago (1973) entitled "A Diag- nosis of the Liar and Other Semantical Vicious-Circle Paradoxesn-here- after, "A Diagnosis." In The Bertrand Russell Memorial Volumes, Vol. I, edited by George Roberts, Allen & Unwin (London, 1979), 52-80. Although the present paper is self-contained, the reader may wish to consult the earlier paper for additional references and for certain details that I have omitted in this paper. I have been discussing my diagnoses of the paradoxes in my phi- losophy of mathematics course for the past four years. In addition, versions of this paper were read at U.C.L.A., Reed College, and at Berkeley. Many who attended my talks or my course lectures have aided me in clarifying my thoughts on the subject, and for this I am most grateful. I would also like to thank Robert Martin, Brian Skyrms, Carol Chihara, a referee, and the editors of this journal for their useful criticisms and suggestions. This paper was written while I was on sabbatical leave with financial support from the University of California Humanities Research Fellowship Program: I wish to express my gratitude to the university for this opportunity.

The conventions I use for "mentioning" linguistic entities are those of Benson Mates' Elementary Logic, 2nd ed., Oxford University Press (New York, 1972). ' "Truth and Proof,"Scientz/ic American 220 ('June, 1969), p. 66.

Page 3: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

vising languages or logical systems which capture certain essential or useful features of the relevant semantical concepts, but within which the paradox cannot arise, I shall call 'the preventative problem of the ~aradox'.~ Now, if an attractive solution to the preventative problem of a paradox is found, one cannot infer that the diag- nostic problem of that paradox has been solved. Furthermore, it is clear that nothing should be called a solution (or resolution) of the paradox that does not solve its diagnostic problem. Confusion about these matters can be found, even in the writings of spe- cialists. For example, Irving Copi has argued that Principia Mathematica resolves the semantic paradoxes, on the grounds that none of these paradoxes can be reproduced within its logical ~ y s t e m . ~ But since there are many systems within which the paradoxes cannot be constructed, additional arguments are needed to show that this particular solution to the preventative problem provides us with genuine insights into what is generating the paradoxical consequences. In this paper, I put forward solu- tions only to diagnostic problems; to mark this fact, I call the solutions 'diagnoses'.

My second reason for using the term 'diagnoses' is connected with the tendency of many people to think that any acceptable solution to the paradoxes must have a certain quality-a quality which I am inclined to express by the words "Of course, that's it." For many paradoxes, it is true that when a correct solution is proposed, things click, and the fallacy or error stands out dis- t i n ~ t l y . ~ But there is no good reason for supposing that all para- doxes should be solvable in this way, especially those that have resisted solution for over two thousand years. Hopefully, my use of the term 'diagnoses' will make it clear that the solutions I propose here are not intended to have the "Of course, that's it" quality;

3 variation of the preventative problem might be stated so as to require, roughly, the capturing of "all the really important features" of the relevant concepts (where what are really important features would be specified as the result ofconceptual analysis). Note: the characterization of the preventative problem presented here differs slightly from that given in "A Diagnosis," p. 53.

See his Theory of Logical Types, Routledge & Kegan Paul (London, 1971), 88, 91. Cf. the Three Salesman paradox and its solution described in my

Ontology and the Vicious-Circle Principle, Cornell University Press (Ithaca and London, 1973), pp. 2-3.

Page 4: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

for a physician diagnosing a puzzling illness need not believe he (she) has found an irresistibly correct diagnosis in order to be convinced that some particular one is right. I intend to build a case for accepting my diagnoses, realizing that there is room for differences of judgment on these matters.

Suppose a person tells us that he is going to define 'glub'. He says: "An animal is a glub if, and only if, it is not a mouse; and it is not a glub if, and only if, it is neither a mouse nor different from itself." As a result, we then state: [*I For every animal x,

[a.l] x is a glub iff x is not a mouse; and

[a.2] x is not a glub iff x is neither a mouse nor different from x.

Suppose, for some reason, we were blind to the defects of this def- inition. Then, the following might seem paradoxical.

[I] Lassie is a glub (assumption) [2] Lassie is not a mouse ([I] and [a.l] of [*I) [3] Lassie is not different (identity theory)

from itself [4] Lassie is not a glub ([21, [31, and [ a 4 of [*I) [5] Therefore, Lassie is not (reductio ad absurdum of [I])

a glub [6] Therefore, Lassie is a ([5] and [a.l] of [*I)

mouse [7] Therefore, Lassie is a ([6] and [a.2] of [*I)

glub A proper diagnosis of this "paradox" would point out that [*I, which expresses the definition of 'glub', is inconsistent. It would then be easy to see why we can derive a contradiction from it. After all, the dangers of introducing contradictions into one's theories by means of "creative definitions" are well-known.6 Why would the above reasoning seem paradoxical to those who fail to see the defects of the definition? Because it would appear that a contradiction has been derived from true premises using

--

For more on "creative definitions," see Mates, Elementary L o g ~ , 2nd ed., pp. 197-203.

Page 5: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

only valid rules of inference. Thus, pointing out that [*I is incon- sistent makes it obvious that one of the premises used in the argument is not true-indeed could not be true since no inconsistent statement could be true.'

Another example of the "illness" I have in mind is generated when two clubs, A and B, set down their rules. Among A's rules, one finds: "Any person is eligible to join this club if, and only if, he (she) is eligible to join club B." But B's rules state: "Any person is eligible to join this club if, and only if, he (she) is not eligible to join club A." By the usual sort of reasoning, one can construct a paradox. In other words, from

[i] For every person x, x is eligible to join A iff x is eligible to join B.

[ii] For every person x, x is eligible to join B iff x is not eligible to join A.

we can derive a contradiction. But [i] and [ii] form an incon- sistent pair of statements and hence cannot both be true. Again we have not inferred a contradiction from true premises.

But why, it might be wondered, do people tend to think [i] and [ii] are true? Evidently, because they state the eligibility conditions given by the rules of the clubs: [i] and [ii] seem to be true byftat, as did [*I. Of course, no inconsistent pair of statements can be true; so a fortiori, no such pair can be true by fiat.

Consider now a full-fledged semantic paradox. Imagine a situa- tion in which many clubs have hired secretaries but have es:

It has been frequently objected that the above definition of 'glub' only results in the specification of a n empty extension for the predicate and is not significantly different from the following, which has been generally regarded as permissible by logicians a t least since the time of Frege:

For every object x, x is a glob iff x is a mouse & x is not a mouse.

This definition, I agree, is perfectly in order. But I do not agree that it is not significantly different from that of 'glub'. For it is a simple matter to show (by the usual logical tests) that [*I is not satisfiable whereas a sentence expressing the latter definition is satisfiable. So unless one is willing to espouse the absurd view that there is no significant difference between a satisfiable and an unsatisfiable statement, the above objection cannot be sustained.

Page 6: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHA R A

tablished rules excluding such secretaries from membership. Sup- pose that these secretaries form their own club, Secretary Libera- tion (or "Sec Lib" for short), the rules of which state: "A person is eligible to join this club if, and only if, he (she) is secretary of a club which he (she) is not eligible to join." All goes well for the club until it hires itself a secretary, a certain Ms. Fineline, who has the misfortune of being secretary of no other club. The paradox arises: Is she, or is she not, eligible to join Sec Lib? On the assumption that she is, it follows that she is not; and if she is not, she

The contradiction is derived from: [I] For every person x, x is eligible to join Sec Lib iff there

is a club of which x is a secretary and which x is not eligible to join.

[2] Ms. Fineline is secretary of Sec. Lib. [3] Ms. Fineline is not secretary of any other club.

[2] and [3] are just given facts that are empirically determinable. So this suggests that [I] is false. But why is one inclined to think that [I] is true? As in the previous paradox, it would seem that [I] has been made true by fiat: after all, that is what the rules say. In the previous cases, it was thought that one could make an inconsistent pair of statements true by fiat. In this case, it is thought that one can make a statement that is inconsistent with statements of fact true by fiat. But one can no more do the latter than one can the former. Hence, we should reject [I].

But there are special reasons why most people do-not think of questioning [I]. It is hard to question the premise since the eligibility rules seem to be in order, as can be seen from the fact that they work in general: in most situations, Sec Lib's rules function

W n e might argue that this paradox is not, strictly speaking, a semantic paradox, on the grounds that 'eligible to join' is not a semantic relation. But the expression 'semantic paradox' has come to denote any paradox of the sort Russell called 'vicious-circle paradox' that is not purely logical or mathematical in nature, and it is for this reason I call the Sec Lib a semantic paradox. Historically, F. P. Ramsey divided the vicious-circle paradoxes into two groups and attributed the contradictions of the second (which corresponds to the semantic paradoxes) to "epistemology" (in his "The Foundations of Mathematics," The Foundations of Mathematics and other Logical Essays, Routledge & Kegan Paul (London, 1954), p. 21). The Sec Lib is due to Frank Cioffi, who evidently got the idea for it from some science fiction story. A slightly different version of the paradox can be found in "A Diagnosis."

Page 7: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

without difficulty, leaving no doubt as to whether or not a can- didate is eligible. The idea that a general rule might be perfectly adequate in most situations and yet defective, or even incon- sistent, when applied to some special case is not a familiar one. Yet it is easy to construct such rules once the possibility is r a i ~ e d . ~

The above diagnosis explains why the Sec Lib is more puzzling than the following version of Bertrand Russell's Barber para- dox:'' The village council decrees that the village barber is to shave any inhabitant of the village if, and only if, that inhabitant does not shave himself. Since the village barber happens to be an inhabitant of this village, one might argue to the paradoxical conclusion that this barber shaves himself if, and only if, he does not shave himself. The argument, however, is not very paradox- ical. For the crucial premise states that the barber shaves any inhabitant of the village if, and only if, that inhabitant does not shave himself; and we haven't been given strong reasons for believing it. Of course, the village council did decree that the vil- lage barber is to do just that. But since it is impossible for him to do it, there is little temptation to think that the decree made the premise true by fiat. It does not even seem to be the sort of state- ment that is made true by fiat." The Sec Lib is more puzzling because [ I ] does seem to be the sort of premise that can be made true by decree: the officials of the club do seem to have the au- thority to make it true by simply laying down the rules of eligi- bility that way.

For an example, see "A Diagnosis," pp. 60-1. lo Although the Barber is generally attributed to Russell, the version

I take up here is due to Evert Beth, The Foundations of Mathematics, North- Holland (Amsterdam, 1959), pp. 491-2. Cf. the version I give in "A Diagno- sis," p. 55.

I' However, there is the remarkable House Bill No. 246 of the Indiana State Legislature (1897), authored by a certain Edwin J. Goodwin, which introduced the new "mathematical truth" that the area of a circle is to the square of the quadrant of its circumference as the area of a square is to the square of one of its sides. (This was "offered as a contribution to education to be used only by the State of Indiana. . .") Perhaps some people believed that one could bring it about by legislation that a = 4! I should also mention that the Barber is sometimes classified as a "pseudo-paradox," presumably because its solution seems so obvious.

Page 8: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHA RA

In this section, I develop a test which can be used to confirm or disconfirm the sort of diagnoses I have given above. I wish to decrease the probability of making the sort of error, committed in the following, of attributing to a premise (supposedly true by fiat) the defects of something else, such as a general rule of logical inference. Imagine that the following rule of logical inference (affirming the consequent) has been accepted:

[AC] From 'If p, then q1 and q, infer p. The predicate 'is a flub' is defined:

[Dl For every object x, x is a flub iff x is a two-headed dog. And it is established empirically that

[A.1] Lassie is a dog and

[A.2] Lassie is not two-headed.

A contradiction can now be derived from the above. Let us call such a derivation 'the Flub paradox'. A diagnosis that at- tributed the Flub to [Dl would be erroneous. But such an error can be avoided, generally, by applying a procedure (to be called 'the first-order test') that consists of translating the relevant premises (those thought to be true by fiat, in addition to the "axioms") into some standard first-order quantificational lan- guage and then testing the set of sentences for satisfiability. Thus, using Benson Mates' language L, [Dl, [A.l], and [A.2] of the Flub get translated into:

(x) (Fx t, (Dx & Tx)) Da - Ta

and this set can be shown to be satisfiable. Hence, we have good reason for thinking that the definition of 'flub' is not incompat- ible with the other axioms and hence is not producing the contra- diction. The other sort of result (a "positive result") from the first-order test would suggest that the premises thought to be true by fiat are actually inconsistent or, as the case may be, actually do conflict with the other premises. Thus, applying the test to the Sec Lib, we obtain confirmation of the diagnosis: the set of translations of [I], [2], and [3] (of section 2) consists of

Page 9: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

(Ex5 0 ( 3 Y) (SYJ & -&Y)) sjs

(x) (sjx -+ X = s) and can easily be shown to be unsatisfiable.12

We begin with some definitions. A predicate c$ applies to predi- cate I/ if, and only if, the result of appending c$ to a quote name of I/ is a true sentence. And a predicate is heterological if, and only if, it does not apply to itself. As a result of these "defining speech acts," we are inclined to assert:

[I] A predicate is heterological iff it does not apply to itself. [2] For every predicate x, 'is heterological' applies to x iff x

is heterological. If it is asked why [I] and [2] are held to be true, there seems to be no answer possible but "That is how I understand the definitions given" or "That is what the definitions say." So [I] and [2] seem to be true by definition (or fiat). But from [I] and [2], a contradic- tion is easily derived. So we have a paradox.

As in the previous cases, I propose to analyze the paradox as resting on the mistaken belief that certain crucial premises, namely [I] and [2], are true by fiat: Such a diagnosis may seem controversial since it differs significantly from the typical ones given. As James Thomson points out:

[A111 the 'solutions' of this paradox which are usually discussed come to the same thing. . . . The essential thing in each case is that the word 'heterological' is so explained that for it itself to be heterological it is necessary and sufficient that it both be not heterological and also satisfy some other condition. Then we seek to avoid the by denying, with or without argument, that this further condition is satisfied.'"

It needs to be emphasized that, in many cases, a positive result from the first-order test may not provide decisive confirmation. The test is con- firming in so far as a certain sort of error is found to be less likely. One can always challenge the test itself by challenging the translations involved. Also I do not wish to suggest that all semantic paradoxes can be confirmed by such a method: certain modal semantic paradoxes may not be appropriately tested in this way. Finally, another test called "the elimination test" is given in "A Diagnosis," p. 63. It can be verified that the elimination test can be applied to all the paradoxes discussed in this paper to yield additional con- firmation. 'v. Thomson, "On Some Paradoxes," Analytic Philosophy, edited by R. J.

Page 10: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHA RA

Thomson then goes on to point out that these "solutions" are generally felt to be unsatisfactory, partly because such declara- tions of what 'heterological' must mean have an air of dogmatism. Surprisingly, Thomson's own "solution" has such an "air of dogmatism" aboui it. For after presenting an analysis under which a predicate is taken to be a special kind of function, he suggests that the simplest way out of the difficulty is to say that the "function" denoted by ' x is heterological' is not defined for itself as an argument.14 According to Thomson, "we may have a wrong conception of what the word's meaning is." l5 But again, I would want to ask: "Why must the definition of'is heterological' be such as to preclude its being defined for itself as an argument?" Basically, Thomson's answer is that, otherwise the definition would contradict a certain law of first-order logic.16 But this comes down to little more than replying that, otherwise, a paradox will result. So far as I can see, Thomson's stipulation about the meaning of 'heterological' cannot be justified by semantic laws that are either intuitively correct or empirically justified. I prefer, therefore, to allow the possibility that the argu- ment range of the definition of 'is heterological' does include 'is heterological'. After all, that is the natural way of taking the definition-indeed that is how we all understand the definition when we are first presented with the paradox.

Another reason for not resorting to the definitional doctrines advocated by Thomson is this: even if he is right about the defini- tion of 'heterological', [ I] and [2] would still have to be rejected, and it would still be reasonable to hold that these premises are thought to be true because they are thought to express (part of) what has been laid down in the definitions. So the acceptance of Thomson's view of definitions would not change the basic diagnosis I have given. This shows that the resort to such a view is not needed after all to remove ourselves from the paradoxical situation in which a contradiction is apparently derived from true premises according to valid rules of inference. Since Thom-

Butler, Basil Blackwell (Oxford, 1962), p. 113. The "usually discussed" solutions Thomson is referring to above include Russell's, Ryle's and the hierarchy of language solution based on Tarski's work.

l4 Ibid., pp. 110, 112, 114. l5 Ibid., p. 110. '"bid., p. 110.

Page 11: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

son's view of definitions is motivated primarily by the desire to find a way out of such paradoxical situations, the view loses much of its plausibility.

Finally, there are definite advantages to allowing the sort of "inconsistency of definitions" that the definitional doctrines were brought in to preclude-advantages which will emerge later (in section 7) when a "strengthened" version of the Liar paradox is analyzed.

I should mention here that although my diagnosis can be con- firmed by the first-order test (as the reader can verify), such con- firmation does little to decide the issue between Thomson and myself since both diagnoses imply that [ I ] and [2] are mistakenly thought to be true by fiat.

Unlike the preceding paradoxes, the Berry does not provide us with an explicit definition or rule for analysis. Russell presents the paradox in the following way:

'[Tlhe least integer not nameable in fewer than nineteen syllables' is itself a name consisting of eighteen syllables; hence the least integer not nameable in fewer than nineteen syllables can be named in eighteen syllables, which is a contradiction. "

There is a certain looseness in this statement of the paradox, which makes it difficult to diagnose. What is meant by 'name- able'? It is nowhere said. Clearly, whether the argument is valid or not depends on what is meant by this crucial term. It is not difficult to provide a reasonable definition of the term, the appeal to which will not engender the above contradiction. Because of

" In his "Mathematical Logic as Based on a Theory of Types," Logic and Knowledce, edited by Robert Marsh, Allen & Unwin (London, 1956), p. 60. The Berry paradox played a role in the controversy between Poincart and Russell over whether the assumption of the actual infinite gave rise to the paradoxes. Since the set of phrases not nameable in fewer than nineteen syllables is finite, the Berry seems to be a paradox not requiring the actual existence of an infinite set. See my Onto10~py and the Vicious-Circle Principle p. 140. For more on the Berry, its authorship and its origin, see I. Grattan- Guinness, Dear Russell-Dear Jourdaz'n, Columbia University Press (New York, 1977), pp. 50-1. As the Richard and the Konig paradoxes are quite similar to the Berry and can be dealt with in the way the Berry is, I do not take them up in this paper. See "A Diagnosis," p. 79, fn. 21.

Page 12: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHA RA

this unclarity, it is possible that no definitive diagnosis of the paradox can be given. Perhaps one can construe the meaning of 'nameable' in a multitude of ways. For this reason, I propose to examine a more rigorous version of the paradox, which seems to capture all the essential features of the original without in- corporating the vagueness.

I first eliminate the unclarity about the meaning of 'nameable' by using a new expression, 'dginitely describe', which is defined in terms of a precise test:

To obtain necessary and sufficient conditions for it to be the case that phrase a definitely describes natural number P, construct a sentence from the schema

A def2nitely describes B iff B is C by replacing 'A' with the quote name of a , 'B' with the Arabic numeral denoting P, and 'C' with a token of the same

tYPe as P. Thus, 'the first odd prime' definitely describes three. Secondly, instead of talking about the set of phrases consisting of fewer than nineteen syllables (a somewhat vaguely defined set), I shall discuss the set of L-phrases defined as follows:

An L-phrase is either the phrase the least natural number not dejiinitely described by an L-phrase

or is constructable from the schema the natural number greater by two than twice n

by replacing 'n' with an Arabic numeral of a natural number less than a thousand and one.

(Notice that the set of L-phrases has the finiteness property that the set of phrases consisting of fewer than nineteen syllables was supposed to have-a property that figured significantly in the early discussions of the paradox [see footnote 171.) A paradox can then be constructed in, essentially, the above way. We first note that not all natural numbers are definitely described by an L-phrase, since only finitely many natural numbers can be so definitely described. Hence, the set of natural numbers not defi- nitely described by an L-phrase is nonempty. This set must have a least element, since every nonempty set of natural numbers has a least element. Let m be this least element. Then m is the least natural number not definitely described by an L-phrase. So, 'the

Page 13: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

least natural number not definitely described by an L-phrase' definitely describes m. Thus, we have concluded that m both is and is not definitely described by an L-phrase.

This version of the Berry can be given the sort of diagnosis I provided for the previous paradoxes. We can hypothesize that certain statements, which we accept as expressing at least part of what was laid down in the definitions, cannot be true by defini- tion as they seem to be.

However, the first-order test cannot be applied in this case in quite the direct manner it was previously, because of the way the defining conditions were laid down (that is, via a schema). So I propose that the test be applied to statements that express what is obtained by relatively straightforward applications of the defining rules. Thus,

[a] 'the least natural number not definitely described by an L-phrase' definitely describes 1 iff 1 is the least natural number not definitely described by an L-phrase

results from constructing a sentence according to the definition of 'definitely describe' and can reasonably be said to express for the case of a specific phrase and specific natural number what was laid down generally by the definition. Similarly, we obtain

[b] 'the natural number greater by two than twice 1' defi- nitely describes 1 iff 1 is the natural number greater by two than twice 1

and 'the natural number greater by two than twice 2' definitely describes 1 iff 1 is the natural number greater by two than twice 2

and 'the natural number greater by two than twice 1000' definitely describes 1 iff 1 is the natural number greater by two than twice 1000

by applying the definition repeatedly and forming a conjunction. In a similar way,

[c] 'the least natural number not definitely described by an L-phrase' is an L-phrase

and [dl Every L-phrase different from 'the least natural number not definitely described by an L-phrase' is either 'the natural number greater by two than twice 1' or 'the natural number

Page 14: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHA RA

greater by two than twice 2' or . . . or 'the natural number greater by two than twice 1000'

can be said to express what was laid down in the definition of 'L-phrase'. (Note: the ' . . . ' in [b] and [dl are the "dots of lazy- ness. ")

Now it can easily be shown that this set of premises, when augmented by a few theorems from number theory, is unsatis- fiable. The following will indicate how this is done.

D: definitely describes Q L: Q i s an L-phrase A? @is a natural number e: 'the least natural number not definitely described by an

L-phrase' a , : 'the natural number greater by two than twice 1' a,: 'the natural number greater by two than twice 2'

aloo0: 'the natural number greater by two than twice 1000' [I] eD1 t, ( (x) (Lx+-xD1) & (x) ( (Nx &-(3y) (Ly & yDx) )

+ x A 1 ) ) [2] (a,D1-+1 = 2 + 2 . 1) & . . . & ( a l o 0 ~ l + l = 2 + 2. 1000) PI Le [4] (x) ((Lx & xf e) -+ ( x = a , v . . . v x = a loo0) ) [5] (x) (Nx-+x 2 1) [6] (1 # 2 + 2 - 1 ) & ( l f 2 + 2.2)& . . . & ( I 5 2 + 2.1000)

Now [I] - [4] are translations of [a] - [dl respectively; and [5] and [6] are translations of theorems of number theory. The set consisting of [I] - [6] is unsatisfiable.

I now put forward considerations of a general nature that provide additional support for the above diagnoses.

(1) Special Reasons. A good diagnosis should do more than merely provide a way of avoiding the contradictions; for the paradoxes can be blocked in a variety of ways, and one needs special reasons for picking any one of these alternatives as the

Page 15: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

crucial one. l8 Recall, in this light, that I gave independent reasons for thinking both that a certain premise of the Sec Lib was false, and also that it played a crucial role in the paradox; I even pro- vided explanations of why the paradox is puzzling and why the solution is so easily overlooked.

(2) Reproducibility. One way of testing the claim that a par- ticular virus causes cancer is to isolate the virus, apply it to appropriate test organisms, and then see if the disease is pro- duced. One should test proposed solutions to the paradoxes in a similar manner, by seeing if paradoxes result when we repro- duce the conditions that, according to the diagnosis, engender the paradoxes. For example, the claim that the paradoxes are due to self-reference does not pass this test, since many sentences involving self-reference do not generate paradoxes."

My own diagnoses fare much better since, clearly, if one pro- duces some premises, each of which appears to be true by fiat, but that, as a set, is inconsistent (or is incompatible with known facts), then one can generate a paradox. Indeed, once one sees how these semantic paradoxes are produced, not only is it quite easy to construct new ones, but we are given information as to how we can make them either more or less difficult to s01ve.'~

(3) Simplicity. Simplicity considerations also provide support, since an examination of the literature on the paradoxes provides striking evidence that these diagnoses have a kind of simplicity found in few other solutions: no appeal is made to complex logical or semantic theory.

( 4 ) Occam's Razor. In accordance with Occam's principle,

In Although this minimum condition of adequacy may seem obvious once it is stated, it is surprising how many proposed "solutions" fail to meet it. For example, the only reason Frederic Fitch gives (in his "Comments and Suggestions," T h e Paradox of the Liar, edited by Robert Martin, Yale Uni- versity Press (New Haven, 1970), p. 77) for adopting his "solution" to the Liar-a solution which consists in maintaining that the Liar sentences are not well-formed-is the fact that by doing so "there is no resulting well- formed sentence to cause trouble." It is clear that one ought not argue "This must be what is going wrong in the paradoxes, since otherwise one could get a contradiction." Practically any diagnosis could be "defended" in that way. For a sample of the many ways of blocking the paradoxes, see The Paradox of the Liar.

'"or a specific example of a paradox constructed in the light of the sort of diagnoses given here, see "A Diagnosis," pp. 75-6.

Page 16: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHZHARA

scientists are generally reluctant to accept some new law or prin- ciple postulated to explain some phenomenon if there is an explanation of the data, already at hand, which is based on accepted theory. Now many philosophers have appealed to new and largely untested logical or semantic principles to solve the paradoxes.'O My own diagnoses have been made within the framework of classical logic: the essential principles and ideas used in this paper have been part of standard logical theory for years.

(5) Conservation. One consideration that moves reasonable people to prefer a theory to a competitor is whether the accept- ance of the one would require less revision of our presently accepted scientific theories than would acceptance of the other. The diagnoses presented in this paper do not require the rejection or revision of any of our well-established scientific theories, unlike, say, Russell's solutions of the paradoxes.'l

I have saved the most difficult of all these paradoxes for the last for several reasons: (1) I wish to make it clear that the accepta- bility of the preceding diagnoses does not rest upon the accept- ability of my diagnosis of the Liar. (2) The issues surrounding the Liar are more complex and tangled than in the other cases; what has gone before will allow me to omit certain details and concentrate on issues that are not mere variations on previously discussed themes.

Consider the following version: '' Let us use 'L' as the name of:

'O Cf. the various solutions proposed in The Paradox of the Lzar, edited by Martin. Note that many solutions have been proposed utilizing many-valued logic. The following advice of Dana Scott's is relevant to such proposals: ". . . I have yet to see a really workable three-valued logic. I know i tcan be defined, and at least four times a year someone comes up with the idea anew, but it has not really been developed to the point where one could say it is pleasant to work with. Maybe the day will come, but I have yet to be convinced. So my advice is to continue with the two-valued logic because it is easy to understand and easy to use in applications; then when someone has made the other logic workable a switch should be reasonably painless." In his "Advice on Modal Logic," Philosophical Problems in Logic, edited by Karel Lambert, D. Reidel (Dordrecht, Holland, 1970), p. 153.

'' See my Ontology and the Vicious-Circle Principle, Chapter I . 2! This version of the paradox is classified as a "strengthened Liar" (see

Page 17: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

S E M A N T I C P A R A D O X E S

The only sentence in section 7 of this paper which begins with 'The' and in which the Arabic numeral denoting seven occurs is not true.

It can be verified that L is the only sentence in section 7 of this paper which begins with 'The' and in which the Arabic numeral denoting seven occurs. So if L is true, then what is said to be the - case by L is in fact the case, that is, it is the case that the only sentence . . . is not true. So if L is true, L is not true. Thus, L is not true. But in that case, what is said to be the case by L is not the case. Thus, L is true.

Evidently, what is crucial to the above chain of reasoning is, essentially, the principle:

[Tr] A sentence is true if, and only if, what is said to be the case by the sentence is in fact the case.23

Admittedly, [Tr] is somewhat vague. But when we are dealing with sentences of certain sorts, such as those of the form 'A is F', where 'A' is to be replaced by a referring expression and 'F is to be replaced by a predicate of an appropriate kind, the import of the principle may be quite clear.24 In particular, the following restricted version of the principle is not vague:

[TI If a is a sentence consisting of the referring expression p immediately followed by the words 'is not true', and if p denotes the sentence y, then a is true if, and only if, y is not true.25

The Paradox o f the Liar, edited by Martin, p. xiv). The present analysis can also be carried out when the Liar is stated in terms of propositions, state- ments, assertions and the like. It is primarily the advantages of brevity and simplicity that prompt me to disc& the paradox within the framework of the theory that takes truth and falsity to be predicates of sentences. For more on this point, see "A Diagnosis," p. 69.

Alfred Tarski, in his "The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages," Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, translated by J . H. Woodger, Oxford at the Clarendon Press (Oxford, 1956), p. 155, expressed the principle with the words: "a true sentence is one which says that the state o f affairs is so and so, and the state of affazrs indeed is so and so."

24 Cf. Tarski's view: "From the uoint of view of formal correctness. clarity. , . and freedom from ambiguity of expressions occurring in it, the above formu- lation obviously leaves much td be desired. everth he less, its intuitive meaning and general intention seem to be quite clear and intelligible." Ibid.

'"he idea of restricting the scope of the principle to get a clearer and more precise statement of what is intended is, of course, to be found in Tarski's classic paper (ibid.). Not surprisingly, the above statement is close in spirit to Tarski's Convention T.

Page 18: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHARA

Now why are we so inclined to accept [Tr]? T o bring out the significance of this question for our investigations, I shall consider first the analogous question about another version of the Liar-a version formulated in such a way that this analogous question can be easily answered. The paradox begins with a definition: We are told that a sentence is true* if, and only if, what is said to be the case by the sentence is in fact the case. Hence, we can state a principle, [Tr*], which differs from [Tr] only by the fact that 'true*' occurs in [Tr*] where, and only where, 'true' occurs in [Tr]. Furthermore, when we ask for clarification of the defini- tion, we are informed that [Tr*] tells us that 'Snow is white' is true* if, and only if, snow is white. We are also told that the fol- lowing is implied by the principle: If a is a sentence consisting of the referring expression P immediately followed by the words 'is not true*', and if p denotes the sentence y, then a is true* if, and only if, y is not true*. Thus, we are able to state a principle, [T*], which differs from [TI only in the fact that 'true*' occurs in [T*] where, and only where, 'true' occurs in [TI. We then con- struct the sentence L*:

Exactly one sentence in section 7 of this paper begins with the word 'Exactly' and also contains an occurrence of the Arabic numeral denoting seven; and that sentence is not true.

A paradox (which I shall call 'the Defined Liar') can now be generated by essentially the sequence of steps found in the earlier version. In giving a diagnosis of the Defined Liar, we shall want to ask about [Tr*] what we asked, in the beginning of this para- graph, about [Tr]: Why are we so inclined to accept the principle? This time, the answer is obvious: It is because [Tr*] states what was laid down in the definition of 'true*'. Thus, as in all the previously analyzed paradoxes, we have a crucial premise that is thought to be true by fiat. And since it can be shown that [T*], and hence [Tr*], conflict with certain facts of reference, we again have a situation in which a premise thought to be true by defini- tion, convention, or agreement of some sort, turns out not to be true a t all. So in basic structure, the Defined Liar turns out to be essentially no different from the others.

We can confirm this diagnosis via the first-order test: Let the universe of discourse be the set of sentences of this paper; and

Page 19: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

interpret the unary predicate 'T' to hold of all those sentences that are true*. Let the binary predicate 'IT be interpreted to hold of an ordered pair (x, y ) just in the case in which x is a sentence consisting of a referring expression 8 immediately followed by the words 'is not true*', where 8 denotes y. Let the individual constant 'a' denote the sentence L*. Then translating [T*] into this framework yields:

[ l l (x) Cy) (Hxy 0 (Tx- -TY) Also, by direct inspection, we get:

[2] Haa As the set consisting of [I] and [2] is unsatisfiable, the test is posi- tive.

Returning to the undefined Liar, we see that there is no explicit definition of 'true' which can be said to generate the paradox. So the diagnostic problem is more difficult, and there is con- siderable room for speculation regarding why we are so inclined to accept [Tr]. One reason might be: "We are inclined to accept it because it is a generalization which has received a great deal of empirical confirmation, that is, we have examined a large number of sentences, and those found to be true were such that what was said to be so was in fact so; those found not to be true were such that what was said to be the case was in fact not the case." More sophisticated versions of this might suggest that [Tr] is an empirical hypothesis which has received confirmation via its role in explanation and predication, or perhaps by some Bayesian confirmation process. But I have doubts about this general position, for it doesn't account for the special attractiveness of [Tr], its apparent necessity, and its resistance to rejection (there seems to be a definite incoherence involved in rejecting it).

The view that our reasons for accepting [Tr] are simply em- pirical in nature goes hand in hand with another basic position regarding the character of the Liar-a position that is widely held but rarely, if ever, explicitly defended. The vast majority of solutions to the Liar offered thus far presuppose what I shall call 'the consistency view of truth', viz., the view that an accurate statement of what 'true' means will be logically consistent with all known facts, and in particular with all known facts of reference. Indeed, some philosophers build such a consistency view into their statement of adequacy conditions for a solution. Thus,

Page 20: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHA RA

John Pollock has written: "A solution to the Liar paradox must consist of an explanation of the meaning of 'true' and a demon- stration that, given that analysis of 'true', the Liar sentence is not paradoxical." 26

So far as I can see, few philosophers have even argued for the consistency view; it seems to be a sort of unquestioned axiom. Thus, the consistency view is presupposed in much of Donald Davidson's writings on theory of meaning; yet he never seems to feel any need to justify it.27 There is, however, something in the literature which might be construed as an argument for the view. Charles Parsons has suggested that if an irresolvable antinomy arose via formulations of the Liar within the technical language of semantics, then "it might be possible to attribute the contra- diction to the technical semantical concepts and to avoid the claim that ordinary speakers of English are saddled with an in- coherent conceptual a p p a r a t u ~ . " ~ ~ This quotation intimates that an inconsistency view of truth would saddle ordinary speakers with << an incoherent conceptual apparatus." Since it is absurd to suppose that ordinary speakers carry such an impossible load, we can conclude that an inconsistency view must be false-so it might be argued. But as we have already seen, the sort of "incon-

26 John Pollock, "The Truth about Truth: A Reply to Brian Skyrms," The Paradox ofthe Liar, edited by Martin, p. 79. It is clear that Pollock is talking about the &agnostic problem here, for he goes on to say: "Formal investiga- tions concerned with what sorts of restrictions we might make to our ordinarv " reasoning . . . may point the way to an analysis of 'true' that would solve the paradox. But such a formal investigation by itself does not constitute a solution . . ." (and later, he attempts to give an analysis of how 'true' is used in English). Other logicians who participated in the symposium-workshop from which the papers in the Martin volume were collected were also clearly addressing the diagnostic problem. Martin, himself, writes: "I see the Liar as raising questions concerning the concepts of sentence (or statement or propo- sition), truth, negation, reference, etc.; in short as a problem in the philosophy of language-our language-not primarily as a problem having to do with formalized languages. . . . A solution consists in convincing ourselves that a t least one of the assumptions that led to the contradiction is after all not so plausible." "A Category Solution to the Liar," p. 91. See also J. T. Kearns' contribution to the volume, especially p. 47.

See my "Davidson's Extensional Theory of Meaning," Philosophical Studies 25 (1975), 1-15. Note especially C.5, C.6, and C.7 on p. 5. Also see my "Truth, Meaning, and Paradox," Nolis, 10 (1976), 305-312.

2H In his "The Liar Paradox," Journal ofPhilosophica1 Logic, 3 (1974), p. 399.

Page 21: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

sistency" which generates the paradoxes need not make the defi- nitions, rules, decrees, or conventions laid down unintelligible or even unusable. Nor need they lead to any practical difficulties. Thus, had Sec Lib not hired itself a secretary who happened not to be a secretary of some other club which she was not eligible to join, the troublesome case would never have arisen! And once the difficulty arose, it would be a simple matter to change the rules to resolve the problem. In short, it is possible to lay down, follow, and operate with rules, conventions, or definitions that have "singular points," without landing in practical difficulties rendering our behavior incoherent. As J. L. Austin once wrote of "ordinary language":

It embodies . . . the inherited experience and acumen of many generations of men. But then, that acumen has been concentrated primarily on the practical business of life. If a distinction works well for practical purposes in ordinary life (no mean feat, for even ordinary life is full of hard cases), then there is sure to be something in it, . . . yet this is likely enough to be not the best way of arranging things if our interests are more extensive or intellectual than the ordinary . . . And it must be added too, that superstition and error and fantasy of all kinds do become incorporated in ordinary language and even sometimes stand up to the survival test. . . .'"

The point just made is connected with one of the strongest reasons I know for accepting the inconsistency view of truth. For over seventy years logicians and philosophers have attempted to analyze the meaning of 'true' in a way required by the con- sistency view, that is, they have attempted to construct truth- predicates or truth-models that both result in a consistent notion of truth and also preserve most of our basic intuitions regarding

The results have not been encouraging. As Saul Kripke has recently noted, there are very few analyses, carried out in any real detail, which both provide a definition of 'true' for a rich and precisely worked out language and also prevent the con- struction of the Liar within that language. The first analysis of

In his "A Plea for Excuses," Philosophical Papers, Oxford at the Clarendon Press (Oxford, 1961), p. 133.

:IU I say, "in a way required by the consistency viewn-I do not wish to sug- gest that all those who have contributed to this work have actually espoused the consistency view. Certainly, I do not wish to attribute the consistency view to either Tarski or Kripke. Then, one might wonder how their construc- tions of consistent truth-predicates can be seen to bear on the Liar and the nature of truth. This will be taken up later.

Page 22: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHA RA

this sort, found in the classical Tarskian hierarchy of language approach, yields some very counterintuitive result^.^' Subsequent work on this topic directed at providing at least a model of truth which would avoid some of the more counterintuitive features of the Tarskian approach, while precluding the Liar-I would in- clude here kripke's own work on truth-has suggested only very complex and logically sophisticated notions of ' t r~e '~~-not ions which no one (certainly not ordinary speakers of English) could be expected to have learned as children.

It should be noted that any attribution of a highly complex and logically sophisticated concept of truth to ordinary speakers of English would run into the serious difficulty of explaining how they acquire such a complicated notion. Clearly teaching cannot be the explanation. It might be argued, however, that people simply "learn" to apply the notion "instinctively" without being given any real explicit instruction, much as certain birds acquire the ability to sing highly complicated sequences of notes without instructions. In other words, the complications attributed to the concept might be explainable in terms of innateness. But however promising such hypotheses may be in explaining certain sorts of animal behavior, the resort to innateness here runs into serious difficulties. For it is hard to see how "natural selection" could account for the complexities being attributed to the concept. The logician requires such complications to avoid semantical para- doxes. But why should "Nature" select against individuals with the sort of notion postulated by the inconsistency view? What biologically significant difficulties are we to attribute to such individuals-especially during the hundreds of thousands, per- haps millions, of years when man and his faculty of speech were evolving?

The Tarskian inconsistency view presents us with an attractive alternative to the above.33 With this view, we do not have to attribute to ordinary speakers the sophisticated and logically

" Saul Kripke, "Outline of a Theory of Truth", journal of Philosophy 72 (1975), pp. 694-699. '' Cf. ibid., pp. 699-716. ":' I use the term 'Tarskian' here much as one does 'Platonic' or 'Marxist':

the view being discussed has certain features in common with, and is similar to, Tarski's regarding the meaning of 'true' and the .inconsistency of natural

Page 23: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

S E M A N T I C P A R A D O X E S

complex notions of truth suggested by the consistency view. We can then suppose that a basically simple notion is attached to the predicate 'true'-one that conforms to the very intuitive idea expressed by [Tr]. Furthermore, this alternative provides us with an attractive answer to the diagnostic question discussed earlier, which is strikingly similar to the one I gave to the analogous question for the Defined Liar. Although, in this case, there is no explicit definition, we can assume that there are generally accepted conventions which give the meaning of 'true' and which are expressed by [Tr], thus putting the crucial premise of the (undefined) Liar in the same category as that of the Defined Liar. We can now explain why [Tr] is so attractive, why it is so difficult to reject, and why it seems to be a necessary truth. We can also see why the various "consistent" definitions of truth resulting from philosophical analyses of the paradoxes have all seemed in some respects counterintuitive.

Since this diagnosis turns out to be essentially the same as all the others, the additional support described in section 6 carries over to it with varying degrees of persuasiveness: considerations of simplicity, reproducibility, Occam's razor, and conservation increase its plausibility.

I should now like to consider a formidable test for this diagnosis which few, if any, earlier proposals could pass convincingly. A

languages (op. cit., pp. 164-5), but I do not wish to attribute any of my specific theses to him. The idea that [Tr], or something very much like it, expresses part of the meaning of 'true' is to be found in several of Tarski's articles on truth and semantics. For example, in "The Establishment of Scientific Semantics," Logzc, Semantics, Metamathematics, p. 404, he says of statements of the form

the sentence x is true if and only if p (where 'p' is to be replaced by any sentence of the language and ' x ' by a name of that sentence): "[They] can be regarded as partial definitions of the con- cept of truth. They explain in a precise way, and in conformity with common usage, the sense of all special expressions of the type: the sentence x is true." I should add that many philosophers have regarded Tarski's suggestion that natural languages are inconsistent as being either unintelligible or a crude mistake based on confusing a language with a theory formulated in the lan- guage [cf. Hilary Putnam, Mind, L~n~guage and Reality, Cambridge University Press (Cambridge, England, 1975)p. 731. Others, such as Hans Herzberger, have constructed proofs that natural languages must be "consistent," in various senses of that word (see "A Diagnosis," p . 79, fn. 17). Perhaps, the present paper will help to make Tarski's view less mysterious.

Page 24: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHARA

correct diagnosis of the Liar should enable us to see our way through a type of problem that has plagued those adopting the consistency view. Consider again the sentence L. Is it true? If it is claimed that L is meaningless, then since a meaningless sen- tence cannot be true, it would seem to follow that L is not true. Similarly, if L is said to be an indeterminate sentence lacking definite content, it seems to follow that L is not a true sentence. And if L lacks a truth value entirely then, it would seem, L lacks the truth value True and hence is not true. Thus, we find our- selves driven to hold that the question 'Is L true?' must receive either a 'yes' or a 'no7 answer. But if L is true, then L is not. So that alternative does not appear to be open, and it is maintained in most "solutions" that L is not true. Here, we can imagine the paradox solver setting out his solution in his diary, concluding triumphantly with the sentence L# .

L is not true. But L, itself, seems to say just that. So it needs to be explained how the sentence L# constructed by the paradox solver is true, whereas L, which seems to say exactly the same thing, is not. And this is not easy to do, for the referring expressions of the two sentences refer to the same thing, namely L, and. the predicate 'is not true' has the same meaning in the two sentences.34 Clearly, both 'yes' and 'no7 answers have strongly counterintuitive conse- quences. It is the heavy burden of the consistency view to explain away these contradictory intuitions3"

" It was essentially this difficulty that led Brian Skyrms to abandon the principle of substitutivity of identity in his "Notes on Quantification and Self-Reference," The Paradox ?f the Lzar, edited by Martin, p. 68. " Major attempts to deal with this sort of difficulty from within the

framework of the consistency view have been groping, tentative, and decidedly counterintuitive. A case in point is J. L. Mackie's Truth, Probability and Lo<yic, Oxford at the Clarendon Press (Oxford, 1973). Mackie's general approach to the Liar consists in maintaining that the Liar sentences are '" indeterminate." However, to deal with the above sort of difficulty, he feels compelled to deny that every indeterminate sentence is not true. And he concludes that one cannot say of the Liar sentence either that it is true or that it is not true. His position, he admits, is "awkward," and he seems to be far from convinced by his own solution, saying such things as: "We must . . . hope that our study of self-reference has explained why this is so" and "I am not sure that I hive succeeded" (p. 295). For several other attempts to deal with the difficulty, see The Paradox of the LMr, edited by Martin.

Page 25: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMA NTZC PARADOXES

According to the inconsistency view, however, the contradic- tory intuitions are not to be explained away at all, since on that view these intuitions correctly reflect the meaning we have -

given to the word 'true'. The difficulty can be approached from a slightly different perspective: When in the grip of the paradox, one is apt to come back, time and time again, to the question 'Is L true?' "It either is or it isn't" one is apt to think, "and a correct solution will show me which alternative is with- out absurd consequences." Such thoughts flow naturally from the consistency view. But to insist on a 'yes' or 'no' answer to the question is like insisting on a 'yes' or 'no' answer to the question 'Is Lassie a glub?' Clearly, both answers to this latter question will generate counterintuitive results so long as the dgini- tion of 'glub' is accepted and not changed. Similarly, if it is assumed that either a 'yes' or 'no' will be the correct answer to the ques- tion 'Is L* a true* sentence?', where the definition of 'true*' is not questioned, then serious logical problems will arise. This is not surprising from my point of view, since that, after all, is what the diagnosis tells us to expect.36 Again, imagine that it is asked: "Is Ms. Fineline eligible to join Sec Lib?" Both 'yes' and 'no' answers will generate unacceptable implications when the given eligibility rules are applied; this, too, is what my diagnosis leads us to expect. The practical problem for the officers of the club, then, is not to decide the issue in accordance with the given - rules, but to change the rules so as to yield a consistent ruling on the case at issue.

According to the inconsistency view, then, one ought not attempt to preserve all our strong intuitions about truth in attempting to solve the preventative problem of the Liar. Thus, the way is opened for the sort of pragmatic approach to the preventative problem suggested by Quine's view of the post- paradox situation in set theory-a view which pictures founda- tionalists not as trying to preserve all the intuitions behind the original paradoxical set theories, but rather as seeking to engender "a form of logic most convenient for mathematics and the sciences. . ."37 Then, the fact that the Tarskian hierarchy

jb My response in this paper to the above problem differs considerably from the one presented in "A Diagnosis," pp. 73-4. " More fully, Quine has written: ". . . none of these proposals [for recon-

Page 26: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHARA

approach generates a definition of 'true' that is incompatible with certain facts of ordinary English, such as the fact that English speakers do not attach subscripts to their utterances of 'true' and 'false', need not be regarded as a reason for rejecting the approach. By treating the preventative problem in this pragmatic fashion, there should be a variety of acceptable solutions, depending on the different criteria of acceptability which are laid down for achieving different aims.

This brings up a question I considered earlier (in footnote 30) but deferred. How do the logicians' constructions of truth- predicates or truth-models for formal languages bear on the Liar and the nature of truth? Tarski's method of defining truth-predicates, for example, seems to have been developed as part of a solution to the preventative problem, and yet it has been thought, even by such careful thinkers as Alonzo Church, to solve or "resolve" the semantic paradoxes. Surely there is something to this widely held belief. Kripke, on the other hand, tells us that he does not regard his own proposal as either "giving the interpretation of the ordinary use of 'true', or the solution to the semantic paradoxe~."~~ I should like to consider, in this connection, the following suggestion: "Although Tarski's (or Kripke's) account of truth does not reflect the defini- tion or concept which we actually learn, it does say what truth really is, just as a biologist's account may tell us what it really is to be a fish, even if the biologist employs a definition of 'fish' which most people never learn."39

One might reply to this suggestion initially with the query: The biologist's account tells us what it is to be a fish in what sense of 'fish'? If it is the biologist's sense that is intended, then obviously the account tells us what it is to be a fish. It is not so

-

strutting set theory], type theory included, has an intuitive foundation. None has the backing of common sense. Common sense is bankrupt, for it wound up in contradiction. Deprived of his tradition, the logician has had to resort to mythmaking. That myth will be best that engenders a form of logic most convenient for mathematics and the sciences; and perhaps it will become the common sense of another generation." "Whitehead and the Rise of Modern Logic," Srlrcted Lo,qzc Papers. Random House (New York, 1966), p. 27.

'"Kripke, op. cit., p. 699. jy I owe this suggestion to the editors of this journal.

Page 27: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMANTIC PARADOXES

obvious, however, that we are told what it is to be a fish in the ordinary (nonscientific) sense of the word.40 It might be said that the biologist's account shows that the ordinary classification is incorrect and that the person who classifies a dolphin as a fish is simply making a mistake. But here we need to take account of our purposes and interests in classifying things (as Wittgen- steinians have so often pointed out). Clearly, when the term 'fish' came into the language, people were not concerned about classifying animals to reflect evolutionary lines or according to the latest biological classificatory scheme. Quite possibly, the term was used, generally, in connection with such activities as the gathering, distribution, and marketing of food. Relative to the goals and interests involved in such activities, those features of animals used by the biologist to make his classifications may not seem all that important or relevant. Consider in this con- nection the housewife who tells her husband that the basement is crawling with insects. Should she be said to have mistakenly classified spiders as insects? Clearly, her concerns in classifying tiny animals are different from those of the entomologist: in everyday affairs, it is useful to have a term for those pesky little creatures that frequently get into the house and onto the picnic table, which doesn't require detailed and knowledgeable observations in order to make a correct identification. Surely, branding the housewife's statement as mistaken is to impute goals to everyday speech that are much too theoretical and scientific.

Still, I believe that biologists do, in a way, tell us what fish are (even in the nonscientific sense of 'fish'). After all, we learn from them that although the typical fish is a cold-blooded, completely aquatic vertebrate, having gills and fins, some fish are air-breathing, warm-blooded, aquatic animals which suckle their young. The logician's work on truth can be seen in a similar light: by providing detailed information about various explicitly defined logical truth-predicates, which function in certain ways like our natural language truth-predicates, it illuminates, by

"' For purposes o f th i s e x a m p l e , I assume t h a t t h e ordinary sense o f ' f ish ' is given b y : a n y an imal l iv ing exclusively in t h e water ; primarily denot ing vert ibrate an imals provided w i t h fins and des t i tu te o f l i m b s (Oxford En,qlish Dzctzonary, 197 1 ) .

Page 28: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHA RA

way of similarities and contrasts, the nature of truth, itself. But perhaps we get a better analogy from the physical

sciences, where such well-known idealizations as rigid bodies and ideal gas particles have been useful in producing insights into the behavior of material bodies and gases. For the formal languages and truth-predicates the logician works with can be regarded as idealizations from which our natural languages and ordinary truth-predicates, respectively, can be seen to vary in relatively definite ways. So, again, we might say that the logician provides us with insights into the nature of truth.

The logician's truth-predicates can also be seen to be relevant to what might be called 'the treatment problem of the paradoxes': Should natural languages be altered in order to remove the

- -

causes of the paradoxes? In particular, should a new concept of truth be constructed to replace the present one? And if so,

The present situation is, in some respects, like the con- troversial one mathematicians found themselves in during the early development of the Infinitesimal Calculus. Berkeley's polemical work The Analyst can be regarded as generating antinomies in both Newton's Theory of Fluxions and Leibniz's Differential Calculus; and the Eighteenth and Nineteenth -

Century work on the foundations of analysis, which culminated in Weierstrass' E-6 method of defining limits, can be seen as providing one solution to the treatment problem of the various paradoxes of the Calculus that had been un~overed.~'

The Liar situation differs from the above, however, in so far as the concept of truth is employed by ordinary people in everyday commonplace situations and not principally by scientists or mathematicians involved in scientific work, as in the case of the Calculus. Perhaps, then, the treatment problem of the Liar should be subdivided into subproblems depending on the uses to which the "reformed" predicates are to be put: clearly the need for "treatment" will be a function of the probability and

" This problem is alluded to in "The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages" where Tarski discusses "the thankless task of a reform o f ' col- loquial languages (p. 267). " For another sort of solution by means of Nonstandard Analysis, see

A. Robinson's "The Metaphysics of the Calculus," Problems zn the Philosophy of Mathematics, edited by I . Lakatos, North-Holland (Amsterdam, 1967), pp. 28-40.

Page 29: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

SEMA NTZC PARADOXES

the (dis)utility of getting into difficulties as a result of the incon- sistencies. It may be pointless, for example, to reform the man- on-the-street's conckptual scheme so as to preclude his running into logical difficulties as a result of semantic paradoxes. I should think that those who address the treatment problem would be concerned primarily with terms to be used for mainly logical, mathematical, or scientific purposes. Then, Tarski's solution to the preventative problem can be regarded as containing im- plicitly a suggestion of a solution to the treatment problem-at least for those who need a consistent truth-predicate for their philosophical, logical, mathematical, or scientific work: the reformer could "split the language into a series of languages of greater and greater extent, each of which stands in the same relation to the next in which a formalized language stands to its metalanguagesV-a series wherein the truth-predicate of a particular language will be contained in the next.43 Of course, if one were to attempt a reform of this nature to take account of all semantical paradoxes that are constructable in natural languages, the task would be formidable; and as Tarski notes: "It may . . . be doubted whether the language of everyday life, after being 'rationalized' in this way, would still preserve its naturalness and whether it would not rather take on the characteristic features of the formalized language^."^^

Thus, some philosophers who have been influenced by Tarski in these matters have advocated abandoning the use of natural languages in science altogether in favor of formal languages. At this point, the treatment problem and the preventative problem converge. Indeed, one might regard the treatment problem as one of (what Quine calls) 'explication':

We have, to begin with, an expression or form of expression that is somehow troublesome. . . But it also serves certain purposes that are not to be aban- doned. Then we find a way of accomplishing those same purposes through other channels, using other and less troublesome forms of expression. The old perplexities are res01ved.~~

'Tarski , op. cit., p. 267. 44 Ibid., p. 267. " Word and Object, The Technology Press of M.I.T. (New York, 1960),

p. 260.

Page 30: Chihara C._the Semantic Paradoxes - A Diagnostic Investigation

CHARLES CHIHARA

The position advocating abandoning natural languages in science, then, may be seen to provide an extreme sort of explica- tion in which not just a term or form of expression, but the whole language, is replaced (for specialized purposes).

It should be emphasized, however, that I am not advocating such drastic action. For I am not convinced that the trouble involved in, and the problems resulting from, this sort of reform are warranted. After all, the likelihood that a paradoxical semantic premise may be playing a role in the reasoning used to establish, say, the paths of interplanetary rockets seems remote indeed. More generally, it seems unlikely to me that there are definitions, rules, or conventions of the sort that underlie the semantic paradoxes, which are undermining our reasoning in the empirical sciences. So, in the end, it may be wiser to live with the illness than to undergo the kind of surgery needed to remove all paradox-producing elements.

As a concluding thought, I should like to note that the incon- sistency view of truth advocated in this paper, if correct, has far-reaching consequences for philosophy-especially regarding the widely accepted and generally unstated presupposition of much philosophical work that the fundamental notions that permeate our thinking and that give rise to philosophical perplexities, such as knowledge, evidence, rationality, and existence, must be consistent and free from paradox when correctly under- stood and analyzed. It would seem, as a result of the above analysis of the semantic paradoxes, that this presupposition should be seriously questioned.

University of Caltjbrnia, Berkeley