chari, anita - tward a political critique of reification

Upload: douglas-carvalho-ribeiro

Post on 13-Apr-2018

219 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    1/21

    http://psc.sagepub.com/

    Philosophy & Social Criticism

    http://psc.sagepub.com/content/36/5/587

    Theonline version of this article can be foundat:

    DOI: 10.1177/01914537103635822010 36: 587Philosophy Social Criticism

    Anita Charicritical theory

    Toward a political critique of reification: Lukcs, Honneth and the aims of

    Published by:

    http://www.sagepublications.com

    can be found at:Philosophy & Social CriticismAdditional services and information for

    http://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts:

    http://psc.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

    http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/content/36/5/587http://psc.sagepub.com/content/36/5/587http://psc.sagepub.com/content/36/5/587http://www.sagepublications.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://psc.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://psc.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navhttp://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navhttp://psc.sagepub.com/subscriptionshttp://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/alertshttp://www.sagepublications.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/content/36/5/587http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    2/21

    Toward a political critiqueof reification: Lukacs,Honneth and the aims ofcritical theory

    Anita ChariSocial Sciences Division, University of Chicago, USA

    AbstractThis article engages Axel Honneths recent work on Georg Lukacs concept of reification in order

    to formulate a politically relevant and historically specific critique of capitalism that is applicable to

    theorizing contemporary democratic practice. I argue that Honneths attempt to reorient the

    critique of reification within the terms of a theory of recognition has done so at the cost of

    sacrificing the core of the concept, which forged a connection between the socio-political analysisof capitalist domination and an analysis of the unengaged, spectatorial stance of human beings

    toward the world, showing how they together impede emancipatory social transformation. In

    order to accomplish the unfinished task of rendering the critique of reification applicable to con-

    temporary critical theory, I seek to synthesize the advantages of Honneths approach, which

    focuses on the normative aspects of the critique of reification, with Lukacs emphasis on the prac-

    tical, political-economic dimensions of reification and the historically specific pathologies of the

    capitalist social form.

    Keywordscapitalism, Axel Honneth, Georg Lukacs, recognition, reification

    After decades of neglect, there has recently been a growing awareness in the field of

    political theory that a sophisticated critique of capitalism is crucial to understanding the

    limits and possibilities of democratic practice in the context of the contemporary

    neo-liberal conjuncture. Along these lines, a recent work by the philosopher Axel

    Honneth seeks to recuperate a concept that was central to the critique of capitalism

    Corresponding author:

    Anita Chari, Social Sciences Division, The Society of Fellows, University of Chicago, 5845 South Ellis Avenue,

    Gates-Blake Hall, 305, Chicago, IL, 60637, USA.

    Email: [email protected]

    Philosophy and Social Criticism

    36(5) 587606

    The Author(s) 2010Reprints and permissions:

    sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav

    DOI: 10.1177/0191453710363582psc.sagepub.com

    587

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    3/21

    prevalent in a strand of western Marxism reification in order to highlight its relevance

    for understanding features of contemporary social reality. Rather than simply returning

    to the influential analysis of reification by Georg Lukacs, Honneth invokes the category

    of reification with a crucial twist. Lukacs used the concept to link a particular form ofeconomic life, capitalism, with an unengaged and passive stance that individuals take

    toward the social world that is prevalent, even socially necessitated, in capitalist society.

    By contrast, Honneth argues that the most important aspects of reification can be under-

    stood in the terms of a theory ofrecognition, as a wholly intersubjective phenomenon

    whereby human beings lose sight of their originary affective and engaged relation with

    others in their social world. In this article, I argue that Honneths attempt to reorient the

    critique of reification within the terms of a theory of recognition has done so at the cost

    of sacrificing the core of the concept, which forged a connection between the socio-

    economic structure of capitalist domination and the unengaged, spectatorial stance

    human beings take toward the social world, showing how they together impede emanci-

    patory social transformation. While Honneths turn to reification is no doubt motivated

    by the intuition that the concept has relevance for the analysis of social injustices related

    to the structure of social life in contemporary capitalism, his decisive separation of the

    critique of reification from the critique of political economy leaves him with too thin an

    understanding of the socio-economic aspects of capitalist domination that the category of

    reification is intended to describe and critique.

    If this is the case, the question of why Honneth operates with such an emaciated

    understanding of the processes of reification remains, and it is a question that is crucial

    to understanding the central challenge that critical theory faces today: to formulate apolitically relevant and historically specific critique of capitalism. I go about answering

    this question by exploring the way in which Honneths theory of recognition both

    responds to problems generated by the communicative turn of critical theory initiated

    by Jurgen Habermas, and yet unintentionally reproduces them. An analysis of Honneths

    work on reification invites a discussion of how the concept of reification has been refor-

    mulated prior to the first generation of the Frankfurt School. My study reveals that

    Honneths concept of reification inherits a repressed version of the distinction between

    Habermas concepts of system and lifeworld that tends to effect a sharp distinction

    between intersubjectivity and communicative action on the one hand, and the structuralcritique of capitalism on the other. Honneth therefore deprioritizes the socio-economic

    aspects of reification on the basis of a purified concept of intersubjectivity. Purged of its

    material mediations, Honneths approach to intersubjectivity leads to a concept of reifi-

    cation that is inadequate to the task of criticizing capitalist forms of domination or to the-

    orizing radical democratic political practice today. To the extent that critical theory

    remains bound to the dichotomizing framework of the communicative turn, I argue that

    it will be unable to formulate a politically relevant critique of contemporary neo-liberal

    capitalism, as the borders between the economy and the political are being articulated in

    new ways that confound its assumptions.1

    In order to accomplish the unfinished task of rendering the critique of reification

    applicable to contemporary critical theory, I seek to synthesize the advantages of Hon-

    neths approach, which emphasizes the normative aspects of the critique of reification,

    with Lukacs emphasis on the practical, political-economic dimensions of reification and

    588 Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(5)

    588

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    4/21

    the historically specific pathologies of the capitalist social form. By bringing together

    Honneths and Lukacs approaches rather than opposing them, I develop a critique of

    reification that reconnects the social-theoretic, normative and political aspects of reifica-

    tion and lays the groundwork for a political critique of capitalism that can aid us inrethinking the possibilities for democratic practice in the present.

    In this article I first gloss Lukacs and Honneths theories of reification, highlighting

    their differences. Then I review Habermas formulation of the critique of reification in

    order to show the ways in which his communicative paradigm leads to a dichotomizing

    theory of reification. I contend that a dichotomy similar to the Habermasian system/life-

    world distinction remains problematic in Honneths theory despite his attempts to

    resolve the issue. Finally, I indicate how a more politically relevant critique of reification

    might be developed through a synthesis of Honneths and Lukacs theories, in particular

    by recognizing the distinct ideas about intersubjectivity implied by their respective

    theories.

    Lukacs: reification and capitalist subjectivity

    In Reification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat, Lukacs argues that reification is

    the central social pathology of capitalist society.2 Reification is above all an unengaged,

    spectatorial stance that individuals take toward the social world and toward their own

    practices. Reification is characterized by a lack of participatory involvement (Teilnahm-

    slosigkeit) in social objects, whereby humans apprehend things in the world as inert

    objects to which human consciousness merely conforms rather than actively constructs.More specifically, according to Lukacs, reification is a form of consciousness that is

    uniquely constitutive of capitalism. It is the subjective stance that individuals take

    toward a society in which the economy exists as a separate, self-grounding and autono-

    mous realm of social life, operating in a way that is seemingly independent of human

    will. By drawing attention to the ways in which the independence and objectivity of the

    economy function as a form of appearance or illusion that itself perpetuates the dominat-

    ing social structure of capitalism, Lukacs makes explicit an unconscious link between

    subjects everyday practices and the dynamic of the capitalist economy. The concept

    of reification therefore describes the ways in which individuals in capitalist society failto recognize that the economy is constituted by human practices, even as it appears to be

    an autonomous and self-perpetuating dynamic.

    Lukacs explicitly relates the critique of reification to the critique of commodity

    fetishism, theorized by Marx as a form of relation between humans that is disguised

    as a relation between things. Taking Marxs lead, Lukacs claims that if the unengaged

    attitude of reification characterizes human consciousness in capitalism, this has some-

    thing to do with the peculiar structure of capitalist social life itself. In Capital, Marx

    referred to this field of problems with the idea of fetishism, which describes how social

    relations in capitalist society appear in the form of things as commodities whoseactions and movements come to be regarded as beyond the domain of human agency.3

    Commodities take on a life of their own, alienated and separated from the laborers that

    produce them. According to Marx, the fetish character of the commodity, which veils

    the social labor that produces the objects of human need, is the central structural feature

    Chari 589

    589

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    5/21

  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    6/21

    Honneths critique of Lukacs: reification as misrecognition

    Although History and Class Consciousness is a foundational text for the Frankfurt

    School of critical theory, the theory of reification has tended to be neglected in contem-

    porary discussions. An important exception to this rule is a recent work by AxelHonneth,Reification: A New Look at an Old Idea, which reinterprets the critique of rei-

    fication within the terms of his theory of recognition to render it usable for contempo-

    rary social philosophy.8 Honneth responds to what has been perceived as a normative

    deficit stemming from the Marxist orientation of Lukacs work and the consequent

    neglect of the intersubjective dimensions of reification. To rise to the challenge of for-

    mulating the concept anew, Honneth translates the concept of reification into the terms

    of a theory ofrecognition, which emphasizes the phenomena of reification at the level

    of intersubjectivity. In Honneths framework, reification consists in the forgetting of the

    antecedent stance of recognition which is presupposed by our knowledge of andengagement with other persons and objects in the social world. I take issue with Hon-

    neths reconstruction of the critique of reification on two points. First, I argue that Hon-

    neths separation of the critique of reification from an analysis of the social form of

    capitalism results in an ahistorical concept of reification that is inadequate for theoriz-

    ing contemporary political possibilities. Secondly, I contend that by separating the nor-

    mative aspects of reification from an analysis of their socio-economic basis, Honneth

    evacuates much of the critical potential of the concept of reification for political theory,

    reducing reification to a phenomenon of intersubjectivity, whereby intersubjectivity is

    conceived too narrowly to ground a critique of social domination in capitalism. Ratherthan pose Honneths theory against Lukacs, I argue that Honneths work is more use-

    fully seen as an effort to render explicit the implicit normative basis of Lukacs

    analysis.

    A full presentation of the architecture of Honneths theory of recognition goes

    beyond the scope of this article. I will only briefly gloss the basic points relevant to

    the discussion of reification, focusing particularly on Honneths restatement of his the-

    ory of recognition in his recent debate with Nancy Fraser, which sought to clarify the

    extent to which a theory of recognition could take over the theoretical role filled by the

    critique of capitalism in the more modest terms of that exchange, by claims forredistribution.9

    Honneths theory of recognition seeks to reveal the moral constraints underlying

    social interaction and is based on the presupposition that the inclusion of members of

    society will always proceed through the mechanism of mutual recognition, whereby indi-

    viduals are normatively incorporated into society by learning to view themselves as

    socially recognized in light of certain characteristics.10 Honneth argues that social theory

    requires concepts that can grasp social injustice in terms of subjects normative expec-

    tations of how society conditions their personal integrity. Therefore, he writes, the expe-

    rience of a withdrawal of social recognition of degradation and disrespect must be at

    the center of a meaningful concept of socially caused suffering and injustice.11 For

    Honneth, the importance of social misrecognition as a motivation for social struggle

    is an empirical finding of social theoretic relevance, but it also indicates a normative

    principle of recognition that transcends these empirical instances. It therefore indicates a

    Chari 591

    591

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    7/21

    much-needed point of contact between social theory and the everyday expressions of

    injustice and disrespect, which has long been a blind spot in critical theory. Honneth

    writes:

    This difficulty a legacy of the sociological anti-normativism that also prevailed in the

    older Frankfurt School must now stand at the beginning of any renewal of critical social

    theory. For without a categorical opening to the normative standpoint from which subjects

    themselves evaluate the social order, theory remains completely cut off from a dimension of

    social discontent that it should always be able to call upon. . . . What is needed is a basic

    conceptual shift to the normative premises of a theory of recognition that locates the core of

    all experiences of injustice in the withdrawal of social recognition, in the phenomena of

    humiliation and disrespect.12

    Honneths reformulation of Lukacs concept of reification takes its lead from thephenomenology of misrecognition, which stands at the center of Honneths theory.

    Accordingly, Honneth effects a theoretical shift from what he perceives as the econo-

    mism of Lukacs concept of reification to the analysis of reification in terms of recog-

    nition. Without such a reformulation, Honneth argues, the theory of reification is

    divorced from an account of the normative criteria by which the phenomena of reifica-

    tion can be criticized as well as an understanding of how reification can be experientially

    grasped. These normative criteria, on Honneths account, elude a theory that seeks to

    ground itself in an immanent critique of capitalism alone, since even the institutions

    of the capitalist economy are to some degree dependent upon the normative expectationsplaced upon them by members of a society. Honneth writes:

    . . . even structural transformations in the economic sphere are not independent of the nor-

    mative expectations of those affected, but depend at least on their tacit consent. Like the

    integration of all other spheres, the development of the capitalist market can only occur

    in the form of a process of symbolically mediated negotiation directed toward the interpre-

    tation of underlying normative principles.13

    Honneth therefore diverges sharply from Lukacs in his decisive decoupling of the pro-

    blematic of reification from the critique of the social form of capitalism.Honneth observes a fundamental problem in Lukacs argumentative strategy, which

    relies on a social ontology of practice in order to explain precisely why reification is a

    form of domination. Reification is meant to refer to a deformed, pathological structure

    of practice, a passivity of the subject in relation to other human beings and the objective

    world. On this reading, reification appears to be problematic, and thereby subject to cri-

    tique, insofar as it violates certain ontological presuppositions of human activity. Hon-

    neth claims that Lukacs measures pathological, reified practice against the standard of a

    non-reified form of practice, a fundamental, originary, active form of interaction

    between the human being and the world. Insofar as we relate to the world passively or as Lukacs called it, contemplatively we deviate from the form of practice that is

    proper to the rationality of our form of life. In this sense, Honneth argues that Lukacs

    critique of reification is insufficiently justified by his social ontological critique: reified

    592 Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(5)

    592

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    8/21

    forms of practice merit critique not primarily because they contradict certain descriptive

    elements of social ontology, but rather because they violate certain moral principles.14

    The forgetfulness of recognition

    Honneth sees a more fruitful social theory of reification in Lukacs analysis of the sub-

    jective dimensions of reification, that is, the changes in the way subjects practically

    relate to the social world, rather than in the analysis of commodity fetishism. The key

    point that Honneth distills from Lukacs in this regard is the notion ofTeilnahmslosigkeit,

    or lack of participatory involvement. This term refers to a form of interaction whereby

    subjects lose sight of their fundamentally active, engaged, and sympathetic engagement

    with the world, and instead act as detached observers, contemplating the world passively,

    without existential or emotional involvement.15

    Honneth argues that in the critique ofTeilnahmslosigkeit,lies an alternative, unoffi-

    cial version of the critique of reification, which is based not on an idealist, demiurgic

    theory of human agency, but rather upon a normative standard of intersubjective praxis

    that, far from fully eroded in the present by the generalization of commodity exchange,

    forms an ineradicable kernel of human being in the world.16 In these moments, Lukacs

    doesnt contrast reifying praxis with a collective subjects production of an object, but

    with another, intersubjective attitude on the part of the subject.17 For Honneth, this

    unofficial strand of Lukacs argument suggests a way of recuperating the critique of

    reification from totalization: reification does not eliminate engaged, non-reified praxis

    altogether, it has merely concealed it from our awareness.18

    Armed with this insight, Honneth proposes to reinterpret reification in recognition-

    theoretic terms, arguing that the disinterested, contemplative forms of practice referred

    to as reified obscure but never fully eliminate the primary, interested, active stance of the

    human being toward the world. Honneth proposes to think this stance as a primary recog-

    nitionalstance, which enjoys a genetic and categorial priority over all other attitudes

    toward the self and the world.19 Honneths critique of reification is based upon the pri-

    ority of a recognitive, empathetic, interested relation of the human being to the world

    over a merely cognitive, passive attitude. Taking a suggestive line from Dialectic of

    Enlightenmentas his inspiration, Honneth proposes to think reification anew as the for-getfulness of recognition, which indicates the process by which humans beings lose con-

    sciousness of the antecedent stance of care and recognition that underlies knowledge of

    other persons and of the world. This priority of recognition, according to Honneth, is

    both genetic and categorial. Using the insights of developmental psychology and

    socialization research, Honneth locates the chronological priority of recognition over

    mere cognition in the experience of affective relationships with significant others in

    childhood to show how a critique of reification can be rooted in learning processes that

    reveal the emotional conditions of thought processes.20 Honneth turns to Heidegger and

    Dewey to show the conceptual priority of recognition to cognition, which he argues isimplicit in Lukacs theory as well.

    While Honneth develops a concept of reification that may be more analytically

    nuanced than Lukacs, demanding a higher level of empirical specificity in differentiat-

    ing the phenomena of reification, it is hardly possible to overlook one crucial absence in

    Chari 593

    593

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    9/21

    Honneths theory of reification: it no longer views itself as a critique of socio-political

    relations in capitalism, which in Lukacs account formed the basis of the critique of

    social domination and of the elusiveness of self-determination. Why does Honneth distill

    such a narrow concept of reification from Lukacs theory, one which remains confined tosuch a small range of phenomena and which severs the tight link between the phenomena

    of reification and the structure of capitalist society? I contend that this question can be

    answered by viewing the critique of reification within the tradition of critical theory

    more broadly, paying particular attention to the way in which the concept of intersubjec-

    tivity has been theorized by Habermas and then Honneth as an attempt to reorient critical

    theory away from the normative model of the philosophy of the subject.21 Honneths

    reformulation of the critique of reification is an instance of a larger paradigm shift in crit-

    ical theory towards communication and intersubjectivity and away from the structural

    critique of capitalism. The concept of reification, however, is useful only insofar as it

    calls into question this opposition. I will go on to argue that elements of Lukacs critique

    of reification indicate a more expansive way of theorizing intersubjectivity that avoids

    the stark distinction between intersubjectivity and materiality at the heart of Habermas

    and Honneths analyses.

    The communicative turn of critical theory: beyond the

    production paradigm

    For better or for worse, the contemporary reception of Lukacs is mediated largely

    through the work of the first-generation theorists of the Frankfurt School, who weregreatly influenced by Lukacs critique of reification. The collapse of the Frankfurt

    School into idle pessimism is widely believed to be a result of their adoption of the thesis

    of total reification, in which the standpoint of critical theory is consumed by a thoroughly

    administered society. Lukacs, writing from the perspective of a revolutionary situation,

    addressed his analysis of reification to the practical questions that arose in the course of

    political struggle and he was oriented toward theorizing the possibility of revolutionary

    agency.22 By contrast, the early Frankfurt School theorists, discarding Lukacs positing

    of a revolutionary subject of history, saw in the concept of reification the key to why

    revolution had faltered. The critique of reification assumed a role in critical theory sim-ilar to that of psychoanalytic theory it was a tool to explain why the working class

    failed to assume their historical role, persisting in their enslavement to the ruling ideol-

    ogy. This was especially true of the works of Adorno and Horkheimer produced in the

    1940s under the influence of Friedrich Pollocks state capitalism thesis, which diagnosed

    a new phase of capitalism in which state intervention and the primacy of the political

    over the economic had effectively absorbed the immanent contradictions that were pre-

    viously present in the liberal phase of capitalism.23 In the hands of Horkheimer and

    Adorno, in their classic workDialectic of Enlightenment(1944), the critique of reifica-

    tion is detached from its basis in the Marxian analysis of the historically specific com-modity form, and instead is deployed in the service of a critique of reason as such, which

    is now identified with instrumental rationality.24 Dialectic of Enlightenment, according

    to this familiar history, posits reification as a feature of all human societies, from the ear-

    liest shamanic rituals to the most recent manipulations of science, and thus capitulates to

    594 Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(5)

    594

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    10/21

    the myth of a social form without contradictions, where society supposedly no longer

    generates the standards for its own criticism. The reception of Lukacs own theory of

    reification has been tarred by its association with the pessimism of the Frankfurt School

    critique of reification. This tends to foreclose a real confrontation with the theory of rei-fication at the conceptual level.

    Habermas reorientation of critical theory away from the paradigm of instrumental

    reason, which he argued was bound to an all-encompassing theory of reification,

    attempts to redeem the project of immanent critique by recuperating the perspective

    of communicative reason. The communicative turn of critical theory is an attempt to

    counter the pessimism of early critical theory by revealing the concealed presuppositions

    of its critique of modernity, which, according to Habermas, relies on a normative

    standard of communicative reason that is immanent in everyday practice. Central to

    Habermas project is the rejection of the paradigm of production, the normative model

    of human agency underlying the left-Hegelian project of Marx and early critical theory.

    The production paradigm of agency, according to Habermas, is at the core of what has

    been referred to as the philosophy of the subject, a normative model in which history is

    understood as the activity of a collective subject that exteriorizes itself through its pro-

    ductive activity and then reappropriates that which it has exteriorized.25 The general

    thrust of de-reifying critique, as theorized by Lukacs, which proceeds by revealing the

    historically constituted nature of existing social forms in order to comprehend the pos-

    sibility of their transformation, is regarded as part of this problematic tradition of the phi-

    losophy of the subject. According to Habermas, this tradition restricts the concept of

    practice in a way that is unable to account for the immanence of reason to communica-tive relations themselves, which provides the practical standpoint of critique and

    discloses the proper sphere of social transformation. Habermas writes:

    . . . the emancipatory perspective proceeds precisely not from the production paradigm, but

    from the paradigm of action oriented toward mutual understanding. It is the form of inter-

    action processes that must be altered if one wants to discover practically what the members

    of a society in any given situation might want and what they should do in their common

    interest.26

    Habermas thus reinterprets the critique of reification in the terms of communicative

    action, which he argues could succeed in grounding the normative standpoint of critique

    where the paradigm of production had failed. But insofar as Habermas critical project

    throughout relies on a sharp opposition between his intersubjective concept of interac-

    tion and the Marxian concept of work (Arbeit), which Habermas accuses of conflating

    instrumental and social action, I contend that his concept of intersubjectivity becomes

    abstracted from its material conditions of possibility.27 This will have implications for

    the way in which Habermas, and later Honneth, theorize the critique of reification.

    Reification as the colonization of the lifeworld

    Habermas describes his Theory of Communicative Action as a reformulation of the rei-

    fication problematic in terms of systematically induced lifeworld pathologies.28 By

    Chari 595

    595

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    11/21

    reinterpreting reification from the perspective of communicative action, or, in other

    words, as a phenomenon of a lifeworldthat is invaded by autonomous, norm-free sys-

    temic institutions, Habermas places the dimension of intersubjectivity at the center of the

    theory of reification. In effect, he argues that reification is comprehensible only as whathe calls the colonization of the lifeworld by systemic rationalization the analysis of

    fetish forms is absent. Habermas reinterpretation of reification along these lines, I argue,

    has the problematic effect of sharply demarcating the intersubjective realm of the reified

    lifeworld from the denormativized sphere of systemic rationalization, without theorizing

    the ways in which the two are fundamentally intertwined without recognizing, in

    effect, both that the system is far from denormativized, and that the normativity of the

    lifeworld is materially constituted. Furthermore, I will show that Honneths attempt to

    address the shortcomings of Habermas theory, to set the theory back on its feet as

    Honneth puts it,29 nevertheless inherits from Habermas a constrained concept of inter-

    subjectivity, implicitly generated by some (repressed) version of the opposition between

    system and lifeworld, which is ultimately responsible for Honneths narrow understand-

    ing of reification.

    What Habermas finds insightful in Lukacs is his analysis of reification as a systemic

    problem. As long as the production of goods is organized as the production of exchange-

    values, which is accompanied by the commodification of labor power itself, economi-

    cally relevant action orientations are detached from lifeworld contexts and linked with

    the medium of exchange value (or money).30 Interaction in such societies is coordinated

    through an external mechanism, rather than through the values and norms which prop-

    erly characterize the sphere of interaction itself. On Habermas reading, Lukacs insightis to illuminate the connection between the sphere of the capitalist economy, mediated

    through the principle of (exchange-) value, and the deformation of what Habermas calls

    thelifeworld, that is, the horizon of communicative, social action.31 In Habermas terms,

    this connection, which is the core of the phenomenon of reification, can be stated as fol-

    lows: The form of objectivity that predominates in capitalist society prejudices the

    world-relations, the way in which speaking and acting subjects can relate to things in the

    objective, the social, and their own subjective worlds.32 Habermas proposes to under-

    stand these quasi-objective mechanisms for coordinating action, such as the dimensions

    of the economy and the state, with the concept of system. Systemic integration is coor-dinated not through norms and values, but rather through the denormativized and auton-

    omous steering media of money and power. In the system,

    The mechanism for coordinating action is itself encountered as something external. Trans-

    actions that proceed through the medium of exchange value fall outside of the intersubjec-

    tivity of reaching understanding through language; they become something that takes place

    in the objective world a pseudonature.33

    Apparently independent of human intersubjective constitution, the system takes on aself-grounding, thingly character.

    While Habermas credits Lukacs for challenging Max Webers pessimistic diagnosis

    of modernity, thereby implying an alternative theory of rationalization, which is not sim-

    ply identified with reification, Habermas central critical point is that Lukacs relies on a

    596 Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(5)

    596

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    12/21

    too undifferentiated notion of rationalization. In effect, Habermas claims, Lukacs

    analyzes all processes of societal rationalization in light of the generalization of the com-

    modity form and the abstraction of exchange. He writes:

    As Lukacs takes only one medium into consideration, viz. exchange value, and traces rei-

    fication to the abstraction of exchange alone, he interpretsallmanifestations of Occidental

    rationalism as symptoms of a process in which the whole of society is rationalized through

    and through.34

    To give an account of its own normative foundations, Habermas contends, the critique of

    reification must appeal to the notion of communicative action in order to comprehend the

    standard of communicative rationality as itself inherent to the social lifeworld, even

    under conditions of reification.

    The main point of Habermas reformulation of Lukacs theory of reification is to dis-tinguish between systemic components that remain within boundaries, and those sys-

    temic mechanisms which force their way into the domains of cultural reproduction,

    social integration, and socialization the sphere of the lifeworld.35 This overstepping

    of boundaries constitutes a colonization of the lifeworld, which, according to

    Habermas, refers to a more specific and differentiated notion of reification than the one

    Lukacs presents. Systemic integration, which Habermas posits as a functional require-

    ment of complex societies, is not in itself problematic, nor does it constitute a form of

    reification. It is only when the steering media of the system overstep their boundaries

    and penetrate the communicative realm of the lifeworld that the problem of reificationoccurs. Habermas concept of society as system and lifeworld therefore aims to under-

    stand reification as the colonization of the lifeworld, without resulting in a totalizing

    critique of rationalization as such. He can thereby claim that some form of systemic inte-

    gration that is, of economy and state will be necessary to all complex societies, as

    long as systemic structures do not penetrate the symbolically mediated lifeworld.

    His criticisms of Lukacs notwithstanding, Habermas explicitly says that his attempt to

    reinterpret the problematic of reification is fundamentally influenced by the Marxian cri-

    tique of capitalism. However, it should be clear that his approach diverges in significant

    ways from that of Lukacs, particularly with regard to the way in which communicativeaction is conceived as immanent to the structures of linguistically mediated interaction:

    the critique of reification in capitalist society is rooted in the structures of communica-

    tion itself, which contain an ineradicable potential for resistance to the lifeworld-

    colonizing systemic structures.

    Two concepts of intersubjectivity

    Habermas reorientation of critical theory within the terms of a theory of communicative

    action forms the horizon of Honneths own reworking of critical theory along the lines ofa theory of recognition. InThe Critique of Power, Honneth takes issue with Habermas

    conception of the system as a denormativized form of integration, arguing that this posi-

    tion obfuscates the ways in which normative structures of interaction are always

    embedded in social and political institutions.36 Honneths turn to recognition seeks to

    Chari 597

    597

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    13/21

    avoid the dualism inherent in Habermas theory, which concedes too much to

    systems-theoretic analysis. However, contrary to his own intention, Honneths theory

    tends to address the problem by reducing the field of phenomena referred to by

    Habermas with the concept of system to the lifeworld, that is, the sphere of social inte-gration, which, rather than solving the conceptual problem, merely displaces it to a higher

    level. This helps to illuminate the curious way in which Honneth theorizes reification with

    reference to lifeworld concepts alone, as the forgetfulness of recognition, without account-

    ing for the commodity dynamic. Honneths reinterpretation of reification confines the cri-

    tique of reification to the plane of a purified intersubjectivity. He therefore does not grasp

    the critical core of the concept, whose original intent was precisely to explain the peculiar-

    ity of capitalism as a system in which intersubjective relations appear as relations between

    non-human objects and thereby exert an abstract form of compulsion upon human action.

    In order to recuperate the concept of reification for contemporary political theory,

    Honneth is certainly correct that the intersubjective dimensions of reification, which

    reveal the normative logic of reification, must be theorized in a more explicit way than

    in Lukacs text. However, it becomes clear in the exchange between Lukacs and

    Honneth, that two competing notions of intersubjectivity must be differentiated. On the

    one hand, Honneth theorizes intersubjectivity on the model of interaction between

    individuals: in his theory, recognition is essentially extra-institutional in character.

    Institutions (in the most general sense of the word) are not themselves the place of

    recognition; recognition takes place in the field of interaction between individuals.

    Jean-Philippe Deranty and Emmanuel Renault refer to this as an expressive concept

    of recognition, whereby institutions are conceived as an external, rather than internal,condition of recognition and, indeed, of subjectivation itself.37 Institutions can express

    or deny recognition, but this very way of figuring the problem tends to render the insti-

    tutional contexts of recognition supplementary to, rather than constitutive of, individual

    demands for recognition. While Honneths expressive theory of recognition captures the

    normative content of demands for recognition, its reliance upon an interactionist concept

    of intersubjectivity is less able to grasp the material conditions of social struggles. On the

    other hand, the notion of intersubjectivity that can be distilled from Lukacs theory is one

    in which institutions, the institution of capital, for example, can be understood as veiled

    forms of social relations which are in some sense constitutedby intersubjective agency.Therefore, institutions do not merely express or deny recognition in some way that is

    external to their constitution, nor can this concept of intersubjectivity be understood

    within the model of interaction that is presupposed by Honneths theory. Lukacs pushes

    beyond the terms of the purely interhuman intersubjectivity present in Honneths model,

    instead understanding interaction in a thicker sense, which can begin to theorize the

    material mediations of intersubjective interaction. Furthermore, the stark dichotomy

    between system and lifeworld is explicitly ruled out by the Lukacsian position, insofar

    as the critique proceeds by revealing supposedly denormativized systemic structures

    to be self-obscuring forms of social relations, which can be criticized insofar as they are,in some sense, a product of human agency, and thus not merely given, necessary, or

    objective.

    It will perhaps be objected that my attempt to reactualize the critique of reification by

    recourse to the Lukacsian model of intersubjectivity harkens back to untenable

    598 Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(5)

    598

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    14/21

    productivist normative presuppositions, which reinstate the long-ago discredited per-

    spective of transsubjectivity. My objective, however, is to begin to unsettle the very

    assumptions of the communicative turn of critical theory, which have expelled the pro-

    ductivist model of intersubjectivity outlined by Lukacs from contemporary debates, aswell as the dimension of materiality along with it. One need not reduce this model of

    agency to a pseudo-Hegelian caricature whereby de-reified practice is conceived as

    nothing less than mind and world coinciding to take the insight that de-reified practice

    will have something to do with making social institutions more reflective of human self-

    determination by making individuals conscious of the non-conscious forms of determi-

    nation inherent in capitalist institutions. If the critique of reification is to have any

    relevance for theorizing political practice oriented toward overcoming social domination

    in capitalism, I argue that it must be based on a re-examination of the relation between

    intersubjectivity and social institutions.

    The materiality of reification

    The essence of the fetishism of the commodity, Marx observed, is that a relation between

    human beings takes on the form of a relation between things commodities and

    thereby assumes an autonomous form that conceals its fundamental basis the social

    relations themselves. What is crucial to note in this formulation is that while fetishism

    surely involves a certain kind of misrecognition that is, the misrecognition of the social

    relation masked by the relation between things it is not limited to this misrecognition.

    Moreover, what is rendered thing-like is not only other persons although through thecommodification and mechanization of labor power this is also true. More fundamen-

    tally, it is the social relation itself that is rendered thing-like, objective and apparently

    immutable. To develop this point further, fetishism, as Marx theorized it, takes place

    at the level of social reality itself that is, in the social activity of commodity exchange.

    Although the fetish is an abstraction, it has an objective existence.38 We could under-

    stand this point in terms of Alfred Sohn-Rethels remark: What the commodity owners

    do in the exchange relation is practical solipsism regardless of what they think and say

    about it.39 Or as Slavoj Zizek humorously puts it, in capitalist society, individuals are

    fetishists in practice, not in theory.40

    This is to underscore the crucial point of themate-rialityof reified social practice. Lukacs analyzes the phenomena of reification in terms

    of the mutually constitutive dimensions of subjectivity and objectivity.41 Reification is a

    form of practice that stands in a relation of mutual constitution to the fetish forms of cap-

    ital. Lukacs connects an analysis of the rationalization of the labor process and the

    abstraction and commodification of labor with a theory of the ways in which human con-

    sciousness becomes progressively contemplative, passive, and unable to comprehend the

    dimension of human agency inherent in the dynamic of capitalism, which would provide

    the only means by which the autonomous form of capitalist domination could be over-

    come. I contrast this to Honneths way of addressing the status of macro-social settings,which contends that economic processes, for example, are not only normatively but also

    factually embedded in the normatively structured social order.42 With his theory of

    recognition, Honneth grasps crucial dimensions of the normative order of capitalist

    social relations, but he does so at the cost of neglecting the material constitution of those

    Chari 599

    599

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    15/21

    relations. This has implications for the relevance of his critique of reification to

    contemporary political theory.

    Toward a political critique of reification

    Habermas, Honneths, and Lukacs critiques of reification imply different ways of

    thinking the political through the lens of reification, and I will now delineate the

    respective critical models to which they point. I argue that aspects of Honneths theory

    of reification can be useful in thinking a political critique of reification when taken in

    conjunction with, rather than against, Lukacs theory.

    Habermas reorientation of reification through the concepts of system and lifeworld

    theorizes reification as the effect of systemic mechanisms impinging upon intersubjec-

    tive relations, which should rightfully be directed by communication oriented toward

    reaching mutual understanding. For Habermas, then, reification is not simply a projec-

    tion of the lifeworld. However, with the conceptual dichotomization of society into sys-

    tem and lifeworld, the critical dialectical character of the Lukascian analysis is lost.

    Habermas interprets the system as adenormativizedstructure, rather than as Lukacs had

    theorized it, as an autonomized structure, whose normativity is veiled. Furthermore, with

    his functionalist theory of society as a system, Habermas theory implicitly takes the

    existing forms of economy and state as necessary, and therefore cannot put forth a trans-

    formative politics. By collapsing the realms of the economy and state into the category of

    the system, Habermas cedes the theoretical basis for grounding a conception of radical

    participatory democracy, that is, a de-autonomized form of politics for such a form oftrue democracy would be unthinkable as a political system, in Habermas terms.43 As a

    consequence, Habermas understanding of the political-theoretic significance of the con-

    cept of reification is limited: he can only understand social movements that mobilize

    against forms of reification asboundary-defendingforms of politics, which guard against

    the invasion of the lifeworld rather than transforming the systemic structures that reify

    the lifeworld.

    Honneths theory of reification is ambiguous in terms of its implications for a political

    theory of reification. On one hand, I contend that Honneths move away from the anal-

    ysis of systemic rationalization that was central to Habermas analysis is a fruitfuldirection for the political critique of reification. Honneth rejects the functionalist notion

    of a de-normativized systemic structure at the core of Habermas account, thereby pro-

    viding a pluralized account of reification that is not simply confined to the boundary-

    defending reflexes of agents in the lifeworld. Instead, the specific causes and sites of

    various instances of the forgetfulness of recognition must be separately investigated,

    in order to discover in each case how such forgetting is systematically enabled. Honneth

    writes: If the core of every form of reification consists in forgetfulness of recognition,

    then its social causes must be sought in the practices or mechanisms that enable and sus-

    tain this kind of forgetting.44

    In that case, Honneths theory would not seem to rule outan analysis of the relation between the general structuring principles of society and the

    corresponding and mutually constitutive intersubjective phenomena of reification in

    effect, a project similar to the one Lukacs attempted. Yet at many other points in the

    text, the forgetfulness of recognition is viewed primarily as a cognitive process, and

    600 Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(5)

    600

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    16/21

    so what is needed is an account of how the cognitive process can cause our antecedent

    recognition to be forgotten.45 At such moments, Honneth seems to reduce the phenom-

    enon of reification to the realm of affective intersubjective relations alone, ruling out an

    account of the mediation of social relations with the structures that constitute them. Evenin terms of Honneths own theoretical trajectory, the focus on the affective identification

    of humans with significant others as the basis for a norm of de-reified forms of social

    practice lacks the political connotations of the earlier struggle for recognition. In Hon-

    neths work on reification, the lack of participatory engagement delineated by the con-

    cept of Teilnahmslosigkeit denotes that the primary, active, recognitive stance of the

    human being has merely been forgotten, but it is far from clear how this forgetting could

    be significant for social theory or political theory. When decoupled from the critique of

    fetishism, one must ask whether the concept of reification retains the necessary concep-

    tual force for illuminating contemporary democratic politics.46

    A serious consideration of this question cannot ignore the strengths of Honneths

    approach, which bring to the fore the crucial normative dimension of the critique of rei-

    fication, admittedly undertheorized and only implicit in Lukacs account. Furthermore,

    I would argue that foregrounding the concept ofTeilnahmslosigkeit, as Honneth does,

    should be central to the attempt to think the significance of de-reification as a normative

    standard of political practice in political theory. Focusing on the lack of participatory

    involvement characteristic of reification, this approach could point toward a critique that

    searches for points of intervention in autonomized social processes, translating them into

    the logic of the political or in Honneths terms, into the normative logic of recognition

    by grasping social and economic structures in light of their potential transformation.47

    However, this promising line of inquiry is not pursued by Honneth in his study. His anal-

    ysis indicates the possibility of articulating the normative logic of reification, but a polit-

    ical critique of reification would need to focus on the point of translation between the

    normative level of the theory of recognition and the social-theoretic analysis of the struc-

    ture of capitalism, without reducing capitalism to a system in the Habermasian sense.

    Insofar as Honneth speaks of the structure of capitalism at all, however, he tends to

    operate with a rather problematic understanding of its processes, claiming, for example,

    that even seemingly anonymous economic processes are determinedby normative

    rules.48

    This has left Honneth vulnerable to the charge for example, by Nancy Fraser that he reduces the processes of capitalism to its order of recognition.49 Frasers cri-

    tique raises the important question of whether Honneth grants any exteriority to the rec-

    ognition order of capitalism, or rather whether capitalism is ultimately no more than its

    recognition order.50 Honneth has described his project as guided by a kind of moral

    monism, which argues that any normatively substantial social theory must discover

    principles of normative integration in the institutionalized spheres of society that open

    up the prospect of desirable improvements.51 In other words, as Honneth argues in The

    Struggle for Recognition, recognition is the moral grammar of social conflict. There-

    fore, even struggles that make claims for redistribution in the terms of class struggle,or in anti-capitalism terms, presuppose a moral logic of recognition as the basis of claims

    to redistribution. Marxist theory, according to Honneth, tends to sacrifice the logic of

    recognition to a metapolitical theory of the dynamics of capital to secure its scientific

    claims. This is self-contradictory, he claims, insofar as it must simultaneously conceive

    Chari 601

    601

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    17/21

    of the very same processes as strongly dependent on value-mediated communication in

    order to accommodate immanent moral demands for redistribution within them.52 In

    this sense, one might translate Honneths thesis to say that recognition denotes the struc-

    ture of political emancipation as such, one which refuses the distinction made by theyoung Marx between political and human emancipation.53 To that end, Honneth might

    claim that contrary to the hesitations raised above about the relevance of a recognition-

    theoretic concept of reification to theorizing politics today, only a theory of reification

    retranslated in this way can provide an account of the immanent logic of politics.

    Honneth concedes that his theory of the capitalist recognition order

    . . . is, of course, not sufficient to explain the dynamics of developmental processes in

    contemporary capitalism. But it is only meant to make clear the normative constraints

    embedded in such processes because subjects face them with certain expectation of

    recognition.54

    The recognition-theoretic approach thus appears to be an assertion of the autonomy of

    politics, posed in the terms of a normative social theory.55

    Ultimately, I want to argue that by decoupling the critique of reification from the cri-

    tique of fetishism, Honneth reinforces a problematic separation between the economic

    and the political, which renders the theory unable to grasp the breadth of emancipatory

    political struggles today, limiting politics to the logic of recognition without taking into

    account the dimensions of political movements that struggle for transformation of the

    existing structure of socio-economic relations. Nevertheless, I contend that Honnethspluralized understanding of the social mechanisms of reification suggests a fruitful way

    of comprehending a politics of de-reification, provided that it resists Honneths tendency

    to absorb material structures of domination fully within a lifeworld concept and to oper-

    ate with a purified concept of intersubjectivity. Honneths pluralized account of reifica-

    tion, which begins with the diverse experiencesof reification, can be used to expand the

    Lukacsian account, which contends that the experience of reification is only comprehen-

    sible as such from the perspective of an analysis oftotality. A truly political critique of

    reification would theorize more adequately the transition between these two moments to

    delineate the structure of de-reified practice.With the idea of a political critique of reification I seek to push beyond the terms of

    Frasers and Honneths debate inRedistribution or Recognition?, which tended to grasp

    anti-capitalist struggles as struggles over redistribution, thereby misrecognizing their

    potentially transformative character by construing their claims as claims posed primarily

    in the terms of distributive justice. Anti-capitalist struggles against neo-liberal globaliza-

    tion, for example, make claims that go beyond the demand for social recognition within

    existing institutions and institutionalized principles of legitimation and distribution, even

    if they are indeed motivated by feelings of social disrespect.56 Take the example of the

    landless workers movement (MST) in Brazil, which has organized massive occupations

    of land for use by displaced rural populations, expropriating more than 50,000 square

    kilometers of land for use by landless families. The logic of this movement cannot be

    reduced to a claim for social recognition, although this is obviously an important dimen-

    sion of the struggle. Beyond the claim for recognition, the landless workers struggle

    602 Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(5)

    602

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    18/21

    against the institution of private property itself, setting up democratically organized rural

    cooperatives of agricultural producers on occupied lands.57 The structure of politiciza-

    tion in this movement invokes a translation from the analysis of capitalist domination

    to the forms of intersubjective practice that could alter those structures into de-reifiedpolitical forms. Similarly, the Water Wars against the privatization and commodifica-

    tion of public water in Bolivia, in India, and in other parts of the world are yet another

    example that suggests that many political struggles today cannot be comprehended

    solely within the logic of recognition, nor can they be reduced to claims of redistribution.

    These are struggles against reification and they highlight the importance of a critique of

    reification that takes into account both the intersubjective and material dimensions of

    reification to theorizing democratic struggles in the present.

    AcknowledgmentsI am grateful to Patchen Markell, Axel Honneth, Moishe Postone, John McCormick, Jacinda

    Swanson, and J. J. McFadden, for their suggestions on an earlier draft of this article, as well as

    to the German Academic Exchange Service (DAAD) for fellowship support and the Institut fu r

    Sozialforschung, Frankfurt am Main for office space during the writing of this article.

    Notes

    1. On the neo-liberal articulation of the economy and politics, see Aihwa Ong,Neoliberalism as

    Exception: Mutations in Citizenship and Sovereignty (Durham, NC: Duke University Press,

    2006); David Harvey, A Brief History of Neoliberalism (New York: Oxford University Press,

    2005); and Luc Boltanski, The New Spirit of Capitalism (London: Verso, 2005).

    2. Reification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat, in Georg Lukacs,History and Class Con-

    sciousness; Studies in Marxist Dialectics, trans. R. Livingstone (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,

    1971).

    3. Karl Marx,Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, trans. B. Fowkes (New York: Vintage

    Books, 1977).

    4. See Moishe Postone,Time, Labor, and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of Marxs Crit-

    ical Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), part II, ch. 4, pp. 12383.

    5. Certainly Marxs early writings focus on the question of the subjective stance of the worker inrelation to the object of labor; however, his analysis there is not posed in the terms of a critique

    of commodity fetishism.

    6. On this point see Theodor W. Adorno, The Culture Industry: Selected Essays on Mass Culture

    (London: Routledge, 1991) and Guy Debord, The Society of the Spectacle (New York: Zone

    Books, 1994).

    7. Lukacs,History and Class Consciousness, p. 90.

    8. Axel Honneth,Reification: A New Look at an Old Idea, ed. Martin Jay (Oxford: Oxford Uni-

    versity Press, 2008). On the term social philosophy, which is somewhat different than political

    philosophy or social philosophy, in Honneths usage, see Axel Honneth, Pathologies of theSocial: The Past and Present of Social Philosophy, inThe Handbook of Critical Theory(Cam-

    bridge, MA: Blackwell, 1996), pp. 36998.

    9. Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition?: A Political-Philosophical

    Exchange(London: Verso, 2003).

    Chari 603

    603

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    19/21

    10. Axel Honneth, The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts

    (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995).

    11. Axel Honneth, Redistribution as Recognition, inRedistribution or Recognition?(New York:

    Verso, 2003), p. 132.12. ibid., p. 134.

    13. Axel Honneth, The Point of Recognition, in Redistribution or Recognition? (New York:

    Verso, 2003), pp. 2501.

    14. For a discussion of social-ontological critique, see Honneth, Pathologies of the Social.

    15. Honneth,Reification, p. 24.

    16. The Heideggerian inflection of Honneths reading of Lukacs is noteworthy, although I will not

    deal with this theme in this article. In addition to Honneths chapter (ch. 2) on Heidegger and

    Dewey in the original German version of the work, Axel Honneth, Verdinglichung: Eine aner-

    kennungstheoretische Studie, 2nd edn (Suhrkamp, 2005), see Lucien Goldmann, Lukacs and

    Heidegger: Towards a New Philosophy(London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1977).

    17. Honneth,Reification, p. 27.

    18. ibid., p. 31.

    19. ibid., p. 36.

    20. ibid., pp. 416.

    21. On this point see Seyla Benhabib,Critique, Norm, and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of

    Critical Theory(New York: Columbia University Press, 1986).

    22. See John Rees,The Algebra of Revolution: The Dialectic and the Classical Marxist Tradition,

    Revolutionary Studies series (London: Routledge, 1998); Michael Lowy, Georg Lukacs:

    From Romanticism to Bolshevism(London: NLB, 1979).

    23. Friedrich Pollock, State Capitalism: Its Possibilities and Limitations, inCritical Theory and

    Society: A Reader, ed. Stephen Eric Bronner and Douglas Kellner (New York: Routledge,

    1989), pp. 95118.

    24. Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno,Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Frag-

    ments, trans. E. F. N. Jephcott (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2002).

    25. See Seyla Benhabib, The Origins of Defetishizing Critique, inCritique, Norm, and Utopia:

    A Study of the Foundations of Critical Theory(New York: Columbia University Press, 1986),

    pp. 4469.

    26. Jurgen Habermas, Excursus on the Obsolescence of the Production Paradigm, in The Philo-sophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), p. 82.

    27. On the distinction between labor and interaction, see Jurgen Habermas, Labor and Interaction:

    Remarks on Hegels Jena Phenomenology of Mind, trans. J. Viertel (Boston, MA: Beacon

    Press, 1973), pp. 2678. Before Habermas, Hannah Arendt proposed this distinction explicitly

    in contrast to the Marxian concept of labor. See Hannah Arendt, Karl Marx and the Tradition

    of Western Political Thought, inSocial Research69(2) (Summer 2002): 273319.

    28. Jurgen Habermas,The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1,Reason and the Rationaliza-

    tion of Society(Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1984), p. xxxii.

    29. Honneth, The Point of Recognition, p. 242.30. Habermas,The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1, p. 358.

    31. On the concept of the lifeworld, see Jurgen Habermas,The Theory of Communicative Action,

    vol. 2,Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functionalist Reason(Boston, MA: Beacon Press,

    1987), pt VI.

    604 Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(5)

    604

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    20/21

    32. ibid., p. 359.

    33. ibid., p. 358.

    34. ibid., p. 360.

    35. ibid., p. 374.36. Axel Honneth,The Critique of Power: Reflective Stages in a Critical Social Theory, trans. K.

    Baynes (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991).

    37. Jean-Philippe Deranty and Emmanuel Renault, Politicizing Honneths Ethics of Recogni-

    tion, inThesis Eleven88 (February 2007): 99100.

    38. For a fascinating working-out of this thought, which shows the specific way in which Marx

    sought to expose Hegels logical categories as categories of social existence, see Lucio

    Colletti,Marxism and Hegel, trans. L. Garner (London: NLB, 1973).

    39. Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Geistige Und K~orperliche Arbeit: Zur Epistemologie Der Abendl~an-

    dischen Geschichte(Weinheim: VCH, 1989), p. 37 [my translation].

    40. Slavoj Zizek,The Sublime Object of Ideology(London: Verso, 1989), p. 31.

    41. Luk~acs, History and Class Consciousness, p. 84.

    42. Honneth, The Point of Recognition, p. 256.

    43. On this point see Thomas McCarthy, Complexity and Democracy: or the Seducements of

    Systems Theory, in Communicative Action: Essays on Jurgen Habermass Theory of

    Communicative Action, ed. Axel Honneth and Hans Joas, trans. J. Gaines and D. L. Jones

    (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991). Whether my critique is applicable to Habermas later

    works, in particularBetween Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law

    (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), which does not focus on reification, cannot be addressed

    here.

    44. Honneth,Reification, p. 79.

    45. ibid., p. 58.

    46. On this point see Deranty and Renault, Politicizing Honneths Ethics of Recognition. They

    note that Honneth makes a conscious effort to avoid referring to it [his theory] as a politicsof

    recognition, and that while His reluctance to discuss the political and his focus on the ethical

    has good reasons within his theory, his avoidance of the political is symptomatic of a weak-

    ness (p. 92).

    47. One brilliant attempt at such an analysis is Kojin Karatani,Transcritique: On Kant and Marx

    (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2003).48. Honneth, The Point of Recognition, p. 254 (emphasis added); one exception to this tendency

    is an article delineating the new research program of the Institute for Social Research in Frank-

    furt am Main, where Honneth and Martin Hartmann present a concrete theory of the para-

    doxes of capitalism, in which a certain kind of structural analysis plays a greater role. See

    Martin Hartmann and Axel Honneth, Paradoxes of Capitalism, in Constellations 13(1)

    (2006): 4158.

    49. See both of Nancy Frasers contributions to Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-

    Philosophical Exchange (London: Verso, 2003), for a discussion of this criticism. For a

    thorough discussion of the way in which Honneths theory constitutes a response to theshortcomings of historical materialism, which nevertheless tends to overcompensate for

    these shortcomings and thereby to repress the material mediations with which intersubjective

    interactions are mediated, see Jean-Philippe Deranty, Repressed Materiality: Retrieving the

    Materialism in Axel Honneths Theory of Recognition, in Critical Horizons 7(1) (2006):

    Chari 605

    605

    at CAPES on July 10, 2010psc.sagepub.comDownloaded from

    http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/http://psc.sagepub.com/
  • 7/27/2019 CHARI, Anita - Tward a Political Critique of Reification

    21/21

    11340. See also Jean-Philippe Deranty, Les horizons marxistes de lethique de la reconnais-

    sance, inActuel Marx38 (2005): 15978.

    50. While I concur with Frasers critique, I disagree with her argument that a two-front strategy

    that combines analysis of recognition and redistribution into one normative model suffices tosolve the problem. In my framework, reification undercuts the binary between redistribution

    and recognition, which remains trapped within the framework of a liberal democratic politics.

    51. Honneth, The Point of Recognition, p. 254.

    52. ibid.

    53. In this regard, Honneths theory of recognition looks surprisingly more like Jacques

    Rancieres autonomous conception of politics than is immediately apparent, although

    Ranciere would reject the strong moral overtones of Honneths theory of social struggle as

    well as Honneths Hegelian conception of moral progress. What is somewhat similar in both

    theories is the focus on the experiential dimension of the political, as well as the delineation of

    the structure of emancipation demands for equality, although expressed in economic or

    social terms, contain an immanent political/ethical logic that is not reducible to the economic

    or sociological dimensions of the struggles. See Jacques Ranciere,Disagreement: Politics and

    Philosophy, trans. J. Rose (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999). For Rancieres

    own discussion of the relation of his theory to the theory of recognition, see Max Blechman,

    Anita Chari, and Rafeeq Hasan, Democracy, Dissensus and the Aesthetics of Class Struggle:

    an Exchange with Jacques Ranciere, in Historical Materialism 13(4) (November 2005):

    285301. See also Jean-Philippe Deranty, Jacques Rancieres Contribution to the Ethics of

    Recognition, inPolitical Theory 31(1) (2003): 13656.

    54. Honneth, The Point of Recognition, p. 250.

    55. For a discussion of this point, see Etienne Balibar, Three Concepts of Politics: Emancipation,

    Transformation, Civility, inPolitics and the Other Scene, trans. C. Jones, J. Swenson and C.

    Turner (London: Verso, 2002), pp. 139.

    56. Nancy Fraser has recently addressed this issue with her theory of abnormal justice, which

    diagnoses the contemporary situation as one in which the very metapolitical conditions of

    justice, that is, its subjects, institutional sites and norms of adjudication, are themselves

    placed radically in question. See Nancy Fraser, Abnormal Justice, in Scales of Justice:

    Reimagining Political Space in a Globalizing World(New York: Columbia University Press,

    2008), pp. 4875.57. For a discussion of this movement see David McNally,Another World is Possible: Globaliza-

    tion & Anti-capitalism(Winnipeg: Arbeiter Ring Publishing, 2006), especially ch. 6. See also

    Sue Branford and Jan Rocha,Cutting the Wire: The Story of the Landless Movement in Brazil

    (London: Latin American Bureau, 2002), esp. part II and part IV; and George Meszaros,

    Taking the Law into Their Hands: The Landless Workers Movement and the Brazilian

    State, inJournal of Law and Society 27(4) (2000): 51741.

    606 Philosophy and Social Criticism 36(5)

    606