bohman 2010 paper

Upload: wuwpes

Post on 30-May-2018

223 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    1/29

    DraftComments Welcome

    Intergenerational Democracy:Environmental Insecurity as Intergenerational Domination

    James BohmanSaint Louis University

    Most citizens in existing democracies assume that their polity will remain

    democratic, if not for centuries, at least for the foreseeable future. Most framers of

    constitutions assume that the framework that they formulate will be inherited by future

    generations, even as they very often make it possible for future generations of citizens to

    respond to any imperfections and change the constitution through the amendment

    process. Except in these moments of revision, the workings of democracy are often

    thought of in remarkably atemporal ways. We the People, or more often our

    representatives, are able to decide authoritatively for present and the future. So

    conceived, the democratic political community is doubly bounded: spatially by the

    borders of the demos and temporally by those who now are now assembled. Such a

    narrow temporal interpretation implies that democracies are a succession of independent

    generations. While any generation may know some of the their predecessors and their

    successors, more distant past and future generations are often thought to lie outside of the

    political community. While we have concerns for the lives of our children and their

    children, the temporally narrow scope of the political community makes it possible and

    under certain circumstances (such as global warming) very likely that the current

    generation dominates future generations. Such domination may even make it difficult for

    future generations not only to live well but also to inherit the democratic constitution.

    1

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    2/29

    It might be thought that intergenerational democracy falls directly out of the idea

    of self-rule. However, an adequate treatment of the problem of intergenerational

    domination demands a transformation of many current understandings of self rule,

    including concepts such as popular sovereignty. These difficulties are structural in two

    respects. First, democracy, especially majoritarian democracy, is inherently biased

    toward the present. Given this bias, the greater the temporal distance between present and

    future generations, the less likely it is that the interests of the latter will be taken into

    account. Furthermore, simply because of the arrow of time is directional, an enormous

    asymmetry of power exists between present generations on the one hand and past and

    future generations on the other. When coupled with myopia and other institutional

    failures, this temporal bias of democracy can result in the tyranny of thepresent, a

    problem that is only exacerbated by the preeminence of aggregative decision making.

    This bias is not merely a version of the tyranny of the (present) majority, which always

    disadvantages a segment of the present political community and potentially leads to the

    domination of some citizens over others, but also the lives and well being of people in the

    future political community. If they are dominated, then the overall prospects of fulfilling

    the democratic ideal are greatly diminished. Rawls, for example, argues that any

    democratic conception of justice must include a provision for the just claims of future

    generations precisely because of the peculiar features of democracy and majority rule.1

    Any argument for an intergenerational conception of democracy must consider at

    least four main issues, each of which comprises a step in my overall argument. First, the

    protective effects of democracy from domination seem limited, even in existing

    democracies, to those who are citizens. When this status is defined in a temporally and

    2

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    3/29

    spatially restrictive way, citizens may come to dominate noncitizens both inside and

    outside their borders and generations. Second, in light of the possibility that democracies

    can dominate future generations as they do noncitizens, some version of Burkes view of

    a political community as a partnership across generations should be extended in a variety

    of ways; for example, popular sovereignty can only be made intergenerational if each

    generation regards itself, in Burkes terms, as the temporary possessor of democratic

    power and thus will not act as its entire master. Against various objections, I argue that

    such a partnership is not metaphysically impossible. Third, when this limitation of

    temporary possession of democratic power is violated, not only are future generations

    subjected to domination by those who are supposed to be trustees of democratic

    institutions so too are many living citizens. They are insecure in their nondomination, and

    this lack of security extends, most importantly for our purposes, to rights and entitlements

    to natural resources that can only be attained in practices of intergenerational

    management that see the inherent relationship between the natural environment and

    human well being. The insecurity of democratic nondomination can be avoided only if

    each generation has both forward- and backward- looking rights and obligations to other

    generations (and not simply to past and future individuals). As a shared form of freedom,

    environmental security is that no spatial or temporal demos assert some final authority

    over the past, the present and the future. Next I consider the more minimal claim that

    security is an instrumental benefit of democratic nondomination, including environmental

    security from the effects of climate change.

    Democracy, Nondomination, and Security

    3

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    4/29

    I have argued that certain forms of democracy are temporally biased, such as

    those with the provision that the electorate should have the final say about the choice of

    the current regime who in turn may or may not be able to enact just and effective

    legislation to deal with long term social problems. As Rawls puts it, the choice here is

    simply that such a regime is as a practical matter more likely to be right than a

    government empowered to override its wishes.2 The reason why in a democracy must

    take just claims of future generations into account is that democracy is an imperfect

    procedure. For example, they may enact laws the cause irreversible harms and thereby

    perpetuate grave injustices to future generations that may not have occurred in other

    forms of government. We could call such harms intergenerational domination, and it is

    important to know that without principles of intergenerational justice democratic

    procedures cannot rule out this possibility.

    We can add to this assessment of democracy if we go beyond its decision

    procedure and examine its many benefits, both instrumental and constitutive. The

    constitutive benefits are tied to the status of citizenship as a way to realize freedom and

    equality. Prominent among the instrumental benefits of democracy related to citizenship

    are many of the basic forms of security, which, among other things, result from

    possessing the ability to avoid the great ills of domination. Indeed, two of the most well-

    known social scientific generalizations about democracy concern the absence of two such

    evils: war and famine.3The relative absence of these two great causes of human suffering

    can be tied to the operation of distinctive features of democracy. Without some fine-

    grained explanation of the mechanisms that produce these benefits, there is no reason to

    believe that these generalizations have always held or will always hold in the future.

    4

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    5/29

    When considering famines Sen argues that behind these positive generalizations is the

    protective reach of democracy, 4 and thus a kind of security that is directly tied to the

    unique workings of democratic institutions. The rule of law might be an alternative

    explanation, but, as Sen argues, starvation deaths can reflect legality with a vengeance.5

    Famine prevention could then be gained through fairly simple democratic mechanisms of

    accountability such as competitive elections and a free press that distribute effective

    agency among citizens more widely than in their absence. Environmental security, or the

    security of entitlements and rights related to the contributions of natural resources to

    human well being, might also be part of instrumental benefits the protective reach of

    familiar democratic institutions of free and open communication and a robust public

    sphere in which the awareness of the consequences of various policies and laws can

    shape the opinions of citizens. Do this form of security and the protective reach of

    democracy extend across generations?

    The single clearest contemporary example of harming future generations and

    doing irreversible damage is global warming, the consequences of which are likely to be

    very bad and very difficult to reverse given how long such gases remain in the

    atmosphere. The interglacial period has lasted for roughly ten thousand years, with

    temperature fluctuations of only about one degree Celsius. Given economic growth and

    business as usual, the expected rise in temperature are 2.7 by 2050 and as much as 4.7 by

    2100 even without taking into account feedback effects from warming itself. Although

    predictions of this sort are fraught with uncertainly, within a few decades the global

    average temperature will be higher than at any time since Homo Sapiens first evolved.6

    Among the predicted consequences will be the rise in sea levels, causing massive

    5

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    6/29

    flooding in unprotected river deltas such as in Bangladesh, mass migrations of people,

    summer drying in central areas of food production, increase incidence of various

    diseases. We can expect then that global warming will kill large numbers of people,

    shorten the lives of many others, and cause large scale displacement of people over the

    next century. Even given uncertainty, prudence alone would suggest policies to reduce

    greenhouse gases for much the same reasons that we buy flood and earthquake insurance.

    While our children and our childrens children will likely be affected, the most serious

    consequences emerge for even later generations. On what basis do we have an obligation

    to prevent these harms from happening? Certainly, if these predictions are even close to

    being accurate, there is at least the very least strong moral obligation to prevent them

    from happening. Since public goods and bads are at stake, political institutions must be

    the primary actors. Given that every increment of greenhouse gases is bad for the

    atmosphere as a whole, these are not just public bads, but also global bads and so require

    transnational coordination in order to mitigate and limit global warming.

    The guiding idea that most people who have not read Derek Parfit have about

    these obligation is that we owe it to all those people who will suffer great harms if we

    continue to pollute the atmosphere, who plausibly have a right to a safe environment, not

    to suffer premature morbidity, and so on. Such a justification is problematic not merely

    because there may or may not be such rights, but because it misstates the harm that is

    involved: it is not the violation of any particular right, however intuitively plausible that

    may seem, but rather that the present generation in this instance dominates future

    generations and in so doing disregards their interests in continuing their just and

    democratic institutions. The claim that there are some putative rights for future

    6

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    7/29

    individuals also raises the nonidentity problem, the force of which is that we cannot owe

    this obligation to particular future individuals.

    The nonidentity problem is often thought to show a contradiction in the very

    idea of obligations to future people. To use an example from John Broome, suppose we

    accept that we have an obligation to curb travel in richer countries. That would mean that

    a generation of people would marry different people and then have different children. In

    this and similar cases, after some decades nearly all the people living would be different

    individuals from those who will be living if we continue to pollute in our present

    profligate way. It would seem then that we do not have an obligation to control pollution

    because of obligations to particular persons. For some the argument entails, falsely, that

    we have no obligations to future generations at all. However, it does not follow, since to

    lack one kind of obligation does not mean we have no obligations. With respect to

    climate change we have obligations to future generations. Thus, the rights that are at

    stake are not to individuals butgenerations in either of the two scenarios. Similarly, the

    point of a just savings rate across generations is not merely to increase wealth or well-

    being, but to make it possible for the next generation to have just and democratic

    institutions. The harm in this case is the harm of intergenerational domination; the

    generation that does nothing in the face of global warming dominates future generations

    by disregarding their interests as a future, temporary possessor of power in democratic

    institutions.

    In the context of democracy, the obligations are intergenerational, and the present

    generation, if it fails to act, arbitrarily shifts the costs and burdens of global warming to

    future generations. It is more than mere unfairness; it is usurping the powers and choices

    7

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    8/29

    of future citizens. In the same way, France imposed huge costs on Haiti after its

    successful slave revolt, and in this way continued its domination of Haiti for generations

    through institutional failures. It is because of the structural possibility of such

    intergenerational nondomination that the current generation must act in such a way to

    enable future generations to sustain just and democratic institutions. This means that the

    current generation share sovereignty with future generation, primarily by refraining from

    injustices that undermine the inheritance of democratic institutions. This right applies

    collectively to any future generation as such, whoever they are, to have the status of a self

    governing demos that is able to exercise their non-exclusive sovereignty by extending to

    future generations the same protective reach of democratic institutions that they enjoy.

    Rawls is thus fundamentally correct, not because there is a right to democracy as such but

    because of the unique character of democratic institutions the rule through imperfect

    procedures such as majority rule. Just as we cannot allow that the sacrifices of a few can

    be outweighed by the advantages enjoyed by others, we cannot say that the benefits to the

    present generation can outweigh the loss of freedom of those in the future. Or, we might

    think of it as Aristotle did as refraining frompleonexia, that each generation must refrain

    from denying the next that which is due to them.

    The typical democratic solution to the general problem of domination--political

    inclusion--does not easily extend the protections of democracy temporally, since

    democracies are now clearly among those who harm and dominate past and future

    generations. Because of intergenerational domination, many of those democracies are

    now insecure in many different ways, leaving both transition and future generations

    vulnerable to domination by the past, by our generation, whose degradation of the

    8

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    9/29

    environment violated the stricture that it must regard itself as the temporary possessor of

    democratic power. But how can past, present and future generations be brought into a

    partnership in democratic decision making?

    On the Supposed Impossibility of Intergenerational Democracy

    For many, the idea of an intergenerational democracy is a nonstarter. It asks us to

    think the impossible. There are two main objections. The first we may call metaphysical.

    Whatever the causal influences and normative inheritances of other generations, the

    democratic community exists only in the present, among those who are citizens now.

    Even if we regard them as part of our community (say because they are in some way

    immortal), it is said, neither the past nor the future are part of the electorate, nor can they

    participate in decisions made at a time when they do not exist. The second set of

    objections is more practical. Given the lack of possible reciprocity between generations

    as they become more and more remote, it is difficult to imagine that people will sacrifice

    in the present for benefits which will only be experienced in the future. It would be

    rational, they say, to discount the value of such benefits, especially if there are pressing

    concerns that need to be addressed in the current generation. Or, as Al Gore has put it,

    The past whispers, while the present shouts.7 This argument is the temporal equivalent

    of a common objection to cosmopolitanism: our obligations are always to those near and

    dear. Both of these arguments miss the real issue, since they fail too address those

    asymmetries of power that make it possible for the present to dominate past and future

    citizens. They ignore other temporal facts: allgenerations are vulnerable to domination,

    since every generation is a future to some past and a past to some future.

    9

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    10/29

    Others argue against giving the natural environment such a prominent place

    within democratic deliberation. This bias is pervasive in economics, particularly when it

    is concerned with issues and policies related to well being. The problem is not simply that

    measures of wealth focus on production and consumption indices, but that even to

    broader measures of well being, such as the UN Human Development Index, focus

    entirely on current well being. However much such indices represent improvements over

    previous measures, such as GDP, their emphasis on the present leaves out the important

    contributions of the natural environment to human well being. The environment

    contributes most directly to long term processes of change and development, so that its

    degradation directly affects the security of democratic institutions and individual well

    being. There is a high correlation between poverty and environment degradation,

    particularly in areas where people depend on the natural provision of many valuable

    goods, such as fertile soil, drinkable water, and other basic necessities, which Parttha

    Dasgupta aptly calls ecological services. Indeed, large migration from the countrywide

    to urban areas most often occurs when local common-property resources degrade to the

    point where life at home is impossible.8 According to Dasgupta, when forests and

    watersheds suffer degradation and the environment loses biodiversity and resilience, the

    poorest in a society suffer the most due to their more direct dependence on such

    environmental services. Because of these blind spots in our understanding of the role of

    nature in human well being and because our tendency to discount future well being due to

    the assumption that economic growth always increases rather than decreases over long

    time spans, democracy does not necessarily ensure environmental security in the same

    way that it is to security from war and forms of political indifference such as famines.

    10

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    11/29

    How might we solve this more general problem of intergenerational domination?

    One possibility is a partnership among generations to be created constitutionally, as when

    the constitution binds each generation to respect the well being of the future. Just as

    Ulysses allows himself to be bound to the mast, democracy might seek to require that

    each generation not to dominate the future by temporally limiting its effective political

    power. Such worries may lead them to adopt the Stephen Holmes and Jon Elsters view

    that constitutions act as precommitments, so that the constitution is Peter sober, while

    the electorate is Peter drunk.9 This precommitment, however, is not a stable a device of

    political self-limitation, since subsequent generations may as Thomas Jefferson did, reject

    these commitments as domination of the past. Because a constitution is not a suicide pact,

    such shackles can be undone for republican reasons. When self-limitation is thought of

    involving longer time scales and past and future actors, precommitments create an

    intergenerational game of competing interests, in which asymmetries between past and

    future assure that there is no credible mechanism to ensure compliance. The present wins,

    since future benefits may be discounted relative to present costs.

    Domination can also extend from the present to the past, effectively breaking the

    intergenerational partnership of a continuous democracy. Past injustices may be regarded

    as closed by the current generation, since those who suffered these injustices, in virtue of

    being dead, are no longer considered true members of the democratic community and

    thus unable to demand recourse. Similarly, future injustices can be justified in the same

    way, since such injustices only affect potential people whose very existence depends on

    our actions. This might lead citizens to delay sacrifices to halt global warming, the worst

    impacts of which will be felt only by future generations who as a result will be limited in

    11

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    12/29

    their range of choices and in their well-being freedom. Thus, precommitments do little to

    change the conflicts among generations by trying to remove them from the purview of

    democratic decision-making. If such conflicts are taken to be part of democracy that

    requires of itself that future generations as such can make legitimate claims, then the

    structural difficulties of generational temporality must be addressed head on: popular

    sovereignty must be practically realized in a different way, as pooled or shared across

    generations, in order that the manifest injustices of intergenerational domination be

    avoided.

    It is instructive to turn first to the intergenerational significance of the past,

    perhaps because interaction between past and future generations seems unavoidably

    mediated by the present. In fact, the past often has political claims upon the present,

    usually related to past injustices and harms. But such claims are always intergenerational,

    in the sense that they are as much about the future as the past. Intergenerational

    democracy requires that the past is not closed, at least in the sense that those living in the

    present can make legitimate claims based on ongoing domination in the present. This

    means that dealing with claims of past generation can change the polity in the present.

    Indeed, the very attempt to close the past inevitably reopens it democratically and

    potentially creates a novel past from which new claims of justice may emerge. This has

    been the case in New Zealand, where treaty violations are not merely matters of the past,

    but now seen as ongoing into the future. Intergenerational democracy thus resists closure

    and finality within the democratic community, leaving it open to change in both temporal

    directions as deliberators construct the ongoing relations between past, present and

    future. The atemporal character of current democracy is actually a form of temporal bias

    12

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    13/29

    which entrenches enormous asymmetries of power among generations. If the past of a

    democracy is closed in cases of intergenerational domination, then so is its future.

    I have already discussed the need for majoritarian democracy to accept legitimate

    intergenerational claims to justice, particularly those which have to do with

    intergenerational domination. decide as the sovereign, each with final authority. This

    might be justified by a particular conception of self-rule, in which the people are the

    authors and subjects of the laws. This interpretation might be thought to be sufficient for

    the nondomination of each generation because of its final authority. But this kind of

    independence is rather narrow and limited in scope. However admirably political equality

    is expressed by this idea of the self-legislating People, an atemporal understanding of the

    subjects of the law cannot be sufficient for nondomination. As Dennis Thompson puts it,

    even if no values except popular sovereignty were at stake, the principle cannot give any

    particular majority final authority.10Since the claims of future sovereigns are

    undervalued in current, it is not surprising that they are left to fend for themselves,

    despite the fact that many decisions not only pose significant constraints on the future but

    are may last for many generations or even be irreversible.

    The democratic bias in favor of the current generation might simply be reversed

    by appealing to some intertemporal majority principle. But since future generations will

    inevitably outnumber the present generation, then over the course of the democratic

    processes taken as a whole, the bias would simply shift to the future, imposing undue

    burdens on the present. In order to overcome these epistemic difficulties, Thompson

    proposes that citizens see themselves as part of a temporal series of sovereigns, in which

    the form of future democracy is left open. Nonetheless, given the ways that the present

    13

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    14/29

    generation can still affect future democratic sovereigns, each generation should

    institutionally represent future sovereigns by acting as trustees of the democratic

    process.11Each generation is thus entrusted to hand democracy on to the future

    sovereign people, allowing them to exercise competent control. The notion that the

    present generation is a trustee holding past, present and future sovereignty in trust, is an

    appropriate development of Burkes idea of an intergenerational polity. However, this is

    not captured by a representational device, particularly in the form of a third party

    representation (or Tribunate for Posterity on the Roman model of the protector of the

    plebs) which seeks to protect the general interests of the future.

    12

    This Tribunate is not an

    intergenerational solution at all, but a way of dividing power among the current

    generation and hoping that it makes some difference to the future. Instead, each

    generation as a whole is a trustee for future generations in their deliberation. Rather than

    some proxy, the future is part of the indefinite audience to which the public addresses its

    justifications, giving them a similar political status in present deliberation.

    Thompsons approach recognizes all the metaphysical difficulties in representing

    the future and accepts that third party representation (or a variety of some such offices,

    devices and strategies) is the only feasible proposal. While the epistemic limits he

    discusses certainly hold for representatives of the future who simply cannot know the

    interests of those whom they represent, the proper solution should aim to give statuses to

    the present which can be incorporated in a variety of institutions; as has already been

    done with respect to claims made for past injustices. It should be similarly possible in the

    present to make basic claims in light of manifest future injustices, as I am trying to for

    forms of domination that undermine basic environmental security and well being

    14

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    15/29

    freedom. The public availability of many such claims made on behalf of the past and the

    future is not anything mysterious. While our political community has a stronger sense of

    the reality of the future than the past, the Maori and others are more genuinely

    intergenerational political communities, which could see sovereignty as always de facto

    in the present, but regard it normatively as essentially shared across time. The presentist

    bias of current democracy is thus a social rather than a metaphysical fact, and many

    democracies now are seeking to rectify past wrongs. But the recognition of claims to

    justice is not the only way in which sovereignty ought to be shared. There are also

    instrumental benefits of democracy that cannot be achieved without recognizing the inter-

    temporal character of sovereignty. This aspect of democracy should also serve to develop

    a fuller account of intergenerational domination.

    Insecure Democracy and Intergenerational Domination

    In order to understand intergenerational domination, we might first examine

    Philip Pettits notion of domination as the dominators capacity to interfere on an

    arbitrary basis in the choices of another. Pettit includes among these capacities financial

    clout, political authority, social connections, communal standing, informational access,

    ideological positions, cultural legitimation and the like.13 But the capacity to interfere is

    not a necessary condition for domination, precisely because such a capacity can be

    exercised by a nonmastering interferer (55), such as a government that acts in

    accordance to the rule of law and also tracks the opinions and interests of those who are

    interfered with. In order to avoid domination, I must enjoy a secure and resilient form of

    noninterference, and thus must be in a position where no one has that power of

    arbitrary interference and I am correspondingly powerful (69). These powers derive

    15

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    16/29

    from the status of being a citizen, the great benefit of which is the possession of the

    power to prevent certain ills from happening (69). Given the myriad sources of

    domination, agents must be very powerful indeed. The ability to plan ones life and to

    live it is impossible when one is dominated, so that not to be free in this way is to live

    without the security that we associate with a worthwhile human life. Nondomination is a

    condition for such security. In this section, I discuss the idea of environmental security as

    a necessary condition possessing the power to prevent great ills from happening across

    borders and generations. Environmental insecurity is a clear indicator of intergenerational

    domination.

    Pettits conception of domination is thought of primarily in terms of the relations

    among individuals. This runs afoul of the non-identity problem. What is needed is a more

    institutional understanding of domination, and a nonmastering interferer is a good

    definition of pooled sovereignty. In the context of democracy, I propose that domination

    is the use of authoritative normative powers to impose obligations and change

    entitlements without recourse or remedy. In light of this requirement, Pettit argues that a

    suitable legal regime (35) is necessary for nondomination in the sense that these rights

    and duties, or normative statuses more generally, do not depend on the good will of

    others. Democracy itself is then the joint exercise of these powers and capacities, so that

    no one is under the control of any given individual or group of citizens. Such powers

    must be redefined jointly and creatively when the circumstances of domination change.

    While current citizens can by use of the normative powers of citizenship resist the

    imposition of obligations, the suitable legal regime that would be necessary for

    intergenerational nondomination would permit agents such as judges or representatives,

    16

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    17/29

    to act on behalf of future generations just as they have acted on behalf of the present

    generations who still suffer under past harms. What is the legal equivalent for the future

    harms?

    The clearest analogy for the legal recognition of the valid claims for future

    generations is international law, broadly understood. The key to the analogy is that the

    sovereign accepts obligations to others outside of the political community, and not

    merely for strategic reasons but precisely for the sake of justice and to create conditions

    of mutual recognition and nondomination. But this often means that the agreement to

    such laws demands restrictions on sovereignty and the acceptance of the valid claims of

    others that are not members of the sovereign people but are extraterritorial and thus

    outside the current political community. The acceptance of these claims is not based

    merely on contingent benefits, but on the recognition of valid claims outside the political

    community is a requirement of justice. It is also because of a concern for justice that there

    ought to be an explicit recognition of legal claims and status both outside and inside the

    community. Among the people who have no status and thus cannot prevent being

    dominated include illegal immigrants and squatters, prisoners and illegal enemy

    combatants, and all others who can make no claims to justice or right because there is no

    one to whom they may appeal their appeal. Even if they do not have the authorial status

    of democratic citizenship, their legal status as persons give them an important editorial

    capacity to revise decisions and policies that deny their rights and the worth of their

    freedom. But if we consider the possibility of the domination of noncitizens by citizens

    that is now a pervasive fact of modern societies, then it is clear that many of these powers

    and liberties must be shared by all within a republican polity. Without shared liberties,

    17

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    18/29

    both citizens and noncitizens are insecure in their own nondomination qua persons.

    Without this legal dimension, freedom from domination remains irreducibly contingent

    across important spatial boundaries. This kind of extraterritorial legal protection could

    also recognize the temporal contingencies of nondomination.

    The problem of insecurity crosses borders in a similar sort of way. Environmental

    security is now a global public good, so that conceptualizing security in terms of

    sovereign states no longer illuminates the scope of the issues. Environmental security

    with regard to global warming is shared, in the sense that it is achievable only if all

    possess it. Thus, from the perspective of shared freedom the natural environment

    contributes to well being in the same way that a safe epidemiological environment

    contributes to health. In the case of global warming, environmental security applies

    across political communities, and thus is worsened because of the lack of effective

    collective action. Issues of environmental security are truly global problems that cannot

    easily be solved by the current state system that seeks to protect the sovereignty of its

    members. It is not clear that the exercise of authority by a global sovereign would be any

    more effective.

    It is easy to see the effects of the absence of such security: there is a strong

    negative correlation at work between environmental degradation on the one hand and

    poverty on the other hand. One explanation offered by economists is that the poor

    degrade their resource base, since they discount the future at high rates for the sake of

    current income. But the alternative explanation is based on the failure of current

    institutions to supply the needed security of the rights and entitlements for poor citizens

    to secure their commonly held natural resources, such as water and grazing land that they

    18

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    19/29

    have often managed sustainably for centuries. As Partha Dasgupta argues, the loss of

    such entitlements and rights is most often due to political instability, a direct cause of

    environmental degradation.14 The entitlements here are not rights to ownership, but the

    rights of access to and to the intergenerational management of environmental resources,

    in the absence of which there is no assurance that more powerful actors will not

    expropriate the commons and deny existing rights to their use by local communities.

    With the degradation of the local resource base, local people then lack the well being

    freedom that enabled them to sustainably use these resources and preserve them for

    future generations.

    The insecurity of the well-being freedom of local groups is directly related to the

    domination of future generation through the shift in the long run away from the commons

    to more industrial, resource-intensive technologies of resource management. Such

    substitutions prove very costly, in comparison to other solutions, as the large financial

    difference between the preservation of the watershed for New York City and the the

    otherwise necessary filtration systems shows.15 These institutional shifts no longer

    provide environmental security to the worst off. They also permit the domination of the

    these groups for the indefinite future by denying the inheritance of property rights based

    on sharing a resource (rights of use) as opposed to practices based on private ownership.

    They dominate the future to the extent that these resources are further degraded by new

    practices that employ industrial extraction of natural resources and the substitution of

    resource intensive technologies that restrict the options and opportunities of future

    generations. The self-defeating negative feedback relationships exist in this case as they

    did with regard to other temporary forms of security that are achieved through

    19

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    20/29

    domination. Attempts to control the Mississippi river watershed industrially, for example,

    have led to less, rather than more, environmental security.

    Given the kinds of ecological effects that human beings are now capable of

    wreaking on their shared environment, the potential for domination with the resultant

    insecurities exists at many different levels. Environmental security crosses borders, and

    the state system has not been effective in creating the capacity to regulate climate change

    and other long term processes across borders. Most of all, among the many problems of

    environmental security as a public good follow upon processes of global warming, the

    effects of which will surely produce more domination, even as the states and the current

    state system are unable to control them. It is also true that the greatest insecurity will be

    felt several generations in the future as they worsen and become irreversible as the

    atmosphere is not longer able to regenerate itself. As Barry Holden correctly argues,

    global warming requires extending democracy and popular control both spatially and

    temporally, since it affects all the people of the world.16 Here we must remember that

    popular control can be dominating, and hence its expansion must be aimed at making

    well being freedom more robust across generations and institutional levels. Robustness

    here is here a measure of the security of right and entitlements, and their multiple

    realizations across various levels makes them more secure; in the example of resource

    degradation discussed above, rights and entitlements at the state and the local levels often

    work against each other. Rather than positively making each more secure, rights of use

    are undermined by legally rights of ownership. Environmental security is a global public

    good, in which none have the freedom to live in a secure environment unless all have it,

    so that the global people is a community of sharing the same fate and atmosphere.

    20

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    21/29

    Given that security in republican terms is a shared freedom analogous to a public

    good, how should we think of the new framework for global popular control? One way to

    share freedom is to think of the global demos as the basis for a new framework for

    nondomination, supported by the emerging human political community that is established

    in global institutions of security, whether they are concerned with war, the environment

    or grave violations of human rights. But such a spatially global demos does not

    necessarily expand the temporal dimensions of democratic sovereignty, and thus they

    leaves intergenerational domination unresolved. In the case of environmental security we

    see numerous intersecting and interacting futures, all of which have claims to make upon

    those global institutions that pool sovereignty in order to gain security. As the case of

    those dependent on the local commons shows, what is needed is something more like a

    conception ofdemoi rather than a global demos, so that global democracy, too, will not

    act as an intergenerational dominator. In the face of global warming, a democracy of a

    singular demos may well make us less rather than more secure. In order to overcome

    insecure democracy, a democracy of demoi is required more than a global demos,

    however important global level institutions are for environmental insecurity.

    Even if it is clear that sovereignty must be pooled and that security is a public

    good held across generations, it is not clear how to institutionalize these relationships

    temporally. It seems clear that some form of trusteeship in both temporal directions is

    necessary; at the same time, the presentist bias of current democracy seems to undermine

    such a possibility. The issue is as much structural as it is epistemic. Thompsons

    conception of a Tribunate does not fundamentally address the structural causes for the

    presentist bias of democracy that undermine trusteeship. Nor does it make much sense to

    21

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    22/29

    have biased institutions and expect some representative of the past or future to be able to

    effectively make claims on their behalf, or even to know what their interests are. Here the

    focus should be on nondomination; we can assume that domination is a cause of great ills

    experienced by future generations. Thus we might think of transnational institutions as

    providing a certain analogy. The European Union establishes a transnational polity, rather

    than a system of representation; and thus, a transgenerational democracy cannot simply

    establish an embassy for future generations. The EU offers a political order that allows

    for a positive feedback relationship of pooled sovereignty that enables democratization to

    occur, in which it is precisely the transnational-level institutions that enhance democracy

    at the lower levels. With such mutual interaction across levels and locations, a highly

    differentiated polity works not merely in policy areas, but also in creating a regime of

    human rights that can multiply realize the powers of citizenship and make them more

    rather than less robust.

    The founding moment of the EU, as articulated by Spinelli and others, was

    intergenerational, in which the experience of the war by multiple generations demanded

    the transformation of democracy beyond individual states. Thus present can be a trustee

    for democracy, ensuring not merely that democracy is possible in the future, but that it

    rule itself in such a way so as not to dominate the past or the future, so that it cannot

    envisage a future in which it is the past dominating the present. The transnational public

    must see itself as communicating across time with the future, who form part of the

    indefinite audience to whom the present owes justifications, with whom it shares basic

    liberties. Thus we can see security as a kind of primary good, as that public good that any

    generation at any temporal location would seek if it attempts to realize self rule. Or, to

    22

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    23/29

    use Rawls first principle, each generation must see to it that the future is able to make

    use of the fair value of its liberty.

    Two objections can be made against such a conception. One might think that

    simple guardianship is superior to pooled intergenerational democratic control over the

    environment. One might also argue that a world divided into many separate

    intergenerational communities or peoples is superior to a global democracy ofdemoi.

    Both alternatives simply reinforce existing patters of democratic domination. The

    alternative that I am advocating here is temporal as well as spatial cosmopolitanism in the

    consideration legitimate claims to the protective reach of democracy.

    One might argue that actual democratic control over decisions that make such

    security possible is not necessary. Sen argues that the people do not need to exercise

    democratic control over such decisions as whether to live in an epidemic-free

    environment, so long as the levers of control are systematically exercised in line with

    what we would choose and for that exact reason.17 Once we introduce the possibility of

    generational conflicts, it is doubtful that generations would choose a policy for the exact

    same reason. Similarly, Pettit does not require that people actually deliberate when

    decisions are made for just those reasons that all could accept. In many democracies, he

    argues, some decisions are depoliticized to the extent that control over them is handed

    over to independent commissions so long as the conditions of hypothetical mutuality and

    simultaneity can reasonably be expected to be met.18 In addition, Thompson and Holden

    think that independent commissions and other such bodies can often best represent the

    interests of future generation, who cannot themselves vote or in any way exercise control

    over who will represent them and their interests. For all of these arguments, such

    23

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    24/29

    commissions are antimajoritarian devices that are not necessarily democratic; they give

    democratic control over to an independent body precisely to omit democratic power.

    This argument for the limitation of democracy fills an obvious gap in representation, but

    without correcting the presentist bias of current democracy and ignores the benefits of

    actual deliberation in testing alternative and novel futures. Such forms of depoliticized

    deliberation would ultimately reinforce current biases, since it does not necessarily see its

    task as the achievement of environmental security for all demoi.

    Actual deliberation in the present about global warming has many undeniable

    benefits over guardian checks on the system of representation. By participating in public

    deliberation, citizens could better assess the threats to environmental security, the need

    for immediate and long term actions, and the degree to which sacrifices in the well being

    of the present generation are involved. Because policies related to the means to achieve

    the reduction of greenhouse gases require deliberation by citizens themselves to confer

    legitimacy, a better form of trusteeship would be the use of minipublics that cut across

    various demoi. In this way, actual transnational deliberation has the further benefits of

    diversity, so that the gains, losses, and sacrifices are put in a longer context in which the

    future is anticipated.

    The second objection raises the issue of the nature of an intergenerational political

    community. Avner de Shalit argues that communities must meet three main conditions:

    interaction among people in everyday life, cultural interaction, and moral similarity.19

    While the first of these conditions cannot be met except in the present, the future people

    can meet the second condition of community. Much as traditional conceptions of

    democracy are rooted in the state, this conception of community is based on the nation as

    24

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    25/29

    a cultural entity. This allows us to see the future generations as consisting of those born

    into similar cultural and moral circumstances as we are in the present. But this conception

    of community only recreates the current problem of environmental security, which these

    communities must share without the help of de Shalits two conditions. That all human

    beings are affected by global warming, the moral similarities with the future are not

    based on a shared tradition or culture. A recurrent feature of democracy is the idea that

    democracy will be better and more extensive in the future. For this reason, Burkes idea

    of an intergenerational partnership is much richer, to the extent that it makes explicit the

    relations to the past and future that are constitutive of any just political community.

    However, his conception of an intergenerational community is often too backward-

    looking, to the extent to which it emphasizes continuity with the past. But if democracy

    requires that no generation has final authority, then both the past and the future must be

    seen as in a partnership subject to continuous change and renegotiation in both directions.

    Without this openness, temporal bias is reintroduced and the potential for domination by

    the past over succeeding generations is a real possibility.

    Conclusion

    Unless modified to become a global and intergenerational democracy based on

    pooled sovereignty and shared freedom from domination, modern democracy suffers two

    deficits with respect to its own sustainability. The first is that the asymmetries of power

    between the present and future and past generations are endemic to its bounded forms and

    lead unavoidably to domination. This domination undermines the continued existence of

    democracy over time, since the future generations may not be able to exercise their

    capacities for political freedom and well being freedom. I have discussed various biases

    25

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    26/29

    built into current democratic practice that lead to deficits in problem solving and in the

    capability of democracies to see their own tendency toward domination. Some devices of

    trusteeship are better than others in helping to achieve intergenerational democracy

    without the costs of guardianship. Trusteeship requires the broadening of the temporal

    horizon of decision making so as to exclude costs and obligations that future generations

    could reasonably reject. However, without being guided by a larger conception of pooled

    sovereignty and intergenerational partnership, representation by itself is insufficient to

    overcome pervasive biases and potential for domination. The European Union would not

    achieve security from war simply by having each Member State represent foreigners in

    some particular office or body.

    Many have remarked that environmental problems such as global warming

    demand extending the scope of democracy across both space and time: given that these

    problems are truly global; and they are also intergenerational. Understood in terms of the

    requirements of nondomination, these extensions of democracy are quite similar, if in

    different registers. Both are solved only if democracies understand and overcome their

    potential to be dominators of their own citizens, of other democracies and of past and

    future generations.Along with sovereignty, the capacity to initiate deliberation about the

    terms of democracy itself must also be distributed among various units, levels and

    generations. Without this sort of institutional structure, current circumstances make

    democracies insecure and subject to temporary possessors of democratic power that act as

    their entire master. Political inclusion has worked to make visible the claims of the past to

    justice. With respect to the future, we, the temporary possessors of pooled democratic

    sovereignty, are the greatest threat to their well being freedom and environmental

    26

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    27/29

    security. To achieve the security that comes from nondomination, the current generation

    of any democracy should not view itself as a final authority or master of the whole.

    These arguments concerning the intergenerational public good of security do not

    exhaust the possible justifications for intergenerational and transnational democracy. It

    could also be thought to be instrumentally valuable to the extent that intergenerational

    democracy is a necessary means to achieve particular valuable ends or to avoid terrible

    evils. Some of the worst evils can be addressed by new forms of political and

    environmental security, both of which may be the result of domination. In the case of

    such forms of domination, the case for intergenerational democracy is much clearer even

    than for transnational democracy. The metaphysical impossibility arguments can be given

    a positive, practical twist: even in a fully intergenerational democracy, the generations

    cannot for obvious metaphysical reasons be mutually and simultaneously together in an

    act of self-constitution. Given that in both cases there are many valuable intersecting and

    overlapping forms of political order for promoting nondomination, a democracy of demoi

    makes sense spatially and temporally. When a democracy declares itself to be the final

    sovereign authority, it cannot as a dominator realize unavoidably shared goods such as

    freedom and security. The first step in any argument for intergenerational democracy is to

    abandon the assumption that democracies cannot be dominators. In the temporal case,

    this domination begins at home, in this generation that has produced insecure and

    unsustainable democracy. A secure and sustainable democracy is on my account a matter

    of achieving intergenerational nondomination.

    27

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    28/29

    1Notes

    Rawls, Theory of Justice, 296.

    2 Rawls, Ibid.3

    As Russett puts it: Depending on precise criteria, only twelve to fifteen states qualified as democracies at the

    end of the nineteenth century. The empirical significance of the rarity of war between democracies emerges only

    in the first half of the twentieth century, with at least twice the number of democracies as earlier, and especially

    with the existence of perhaps sixty democracies by the mid-1980s. See Bruce Russett, Grasping the

    Democratic Peace (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), 20.

    4 Sen,Development as Freedom (New York: Knopf, 1999), 184.

    5 Amartya Sen,Poverty and Famine (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1986), p. 165-166.

    6 See John Broome, Counting the Cost of Global Warming(Cambridge: The White Horse Press, 1993), 13.

    7 Barry Holden,Democracy and Global Warming(London: Continuum, 2004), 59.

    8 Partha Dasgupta,Human Well Being and the Natural Environment(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001),

    192.

    9 See Barry Holden.Democracy and Global Warming, 67; Holden thinks introducing policies to curb global

    warming is a form of self-limitation and hence precommitment. See Stephen Holmes, Precommitment and the

    Paradox of Democracy, in Constitutionalism and Democracy, ed. J. Elster and R. Slagstad (Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press, 1993), 199.

    10 Dennis Thompson, Democracy in Time: Popular Sovereignty and Temporal Representation, Constellations

    12 (2005), 246.

    11 Thompson, 248.

    12 Thompson, 256-257.

    13 Philip Pettit,Republicanism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), 52. All references in this paragraph are

    to this work.

    14 Dasgupta,Human Well Being and the Natural Environment, 113.

    15 See G. Chinchilnisky and G.M. Heal, Economic Returns from the Biosphere, Social Choice and Welfare 13

    (2996), 231-257. The difference in cost is large, with $8 billion for technologies of filtration and only 300

  • 8/14/2019 Bohman 2010 Paper

    29/29

    million for watershed preservation.

    16 Holden, 117.

    17 Amartya Sen,Inequality Reexamined(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 65.

    18 Philip Pettit, Depoliticizing Democracy, inDeliberative Democracy and its Discontents, ed. S. Besson and J.

    Marti (London: Ashgate, 2006), 96.

    19 Avner De Shalit, Why Posterity Matters (London: Routledge, 1995), 22