arendt's concept and description of totalitarism - kohn.pdf

Upload: tuere-sunbobo

Post on 01-Jun-2018

220 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    1/37

    Arendt s Concept

    and Description of

    Totalitarianism

    JL HE enorm ous complexity of H annah Arend t's

    he

    rigins

    of

    Totalitarianism arises in large measure from its interweaving of a

    concept of totalitarianism with a description of the totalitarian

    regimes of Hitler and Stalin.^ Today, after the disappearance of

    those regimes, the former concern may seem the more impor-

    tant; yet to neglect the reason that Arendt wrote her bookthe

    fact that Nazism and Stalinism appeared in the world in the sec-

    ond quarter of the twentieth century as events without historical

    precedentis to risk conceptual emptiness.'^ The intertwining

    and overlapping of concept and description have given rise to dif-

    ficult questions and genuine confusion. Was Arendt crediting

    Hitler and Stalin, let alone any of the ir henc hm en , with an aware-

    ness ofACT-conceptof totalitarianism? Indeed, how likely is it that

    these nonp ersons and nonentities, as she called them both,

    were conceptually guided at all? Or, on the contrary, was Arendt

    herself aware that her concept of totalitarianism could become

    fully meaningful only after the regimes she described had come

    to an end? What I hope to suggest in this essay is the relevance of

    Arendt's writing on totalitarianism for politics today, especially

    her understanding of the status of the totalitarian crime against

    hum anity and he r concomitant notion of the right to have rights.

    I think tha i many of us have hea rd enou gh about an evil

    em pire and more recently about an axis of evil to question in

    those expressions, and in those who employ them, what precisely

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    2/37

    622 SOC IAL RESEARC H

    radical evii in ways that have become increasingly cogent and

    alarming. She gives her readers no comfort at all, either in trac-

    ing the conditions of that evil, or in delineating the sort of person

    who is capable today and in the future, and anywhere on earth , of

    performing crimes against humanity. Nor does she shrink from

    the task of spelling out how the recurrence of such crimes can be

    prevented, which would entail the urgent but extremely prob-

    lematic enforcement byal nations ofthe right to have rights, the

    right of llhuman beings "to act together concerning things that

    are of equal concem to each." Some of these considerations will

    lead beyond

    Origins

    to several parts of

    Eichmann in Jerusalem: A

    Report on

    the

    B anality of Evil

    and to one passage from

    The Human

    Condition

    but the primary focus of this paper wil l remain on the

    earlier work.

    I:

    TheInversion of Politics

    The scope of Arendt's conceptual objectives, in

    rigins

    and

    related works from the same period generally, may be summa-

    rized as follows. First, as she insists again and again, totalitarian-

    ism made clear once and for all the uselessness of causality as a

    category of historical thought, as it also exploded our standards

    of political ju dg m en t insofar as they are grounded in traditional

    moral and legal principles. Thus for her the

    difficulty

    of under-

    standing totalitarianism conceptually was from the beginning

    inherent in totalitarian phenomena. Second, the conceptual

    background of her thought is the different kinds of govemment

    as first formulated by Plato and, after many centuries, Mon-

    tesquieu's addition to that formulation of each kind of govern-

    ment's principle of action, along with the human experiences in

    which those principles are embedded. Third, Arendt makes three

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    3/37

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    4/37

    624 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    few scruples over slaughtering the indigenous inhabitants of the

    phantom world of the dark continent to obtain it. Th e subject

    matter of Conrad's work, in which the story told by the always

    ambiguous Marlow is recounted by a shadowy narrator, is the

    encounter of Africans by superfluous Europeans spat out of

    their societies. As the author of the whole tale as well as the story

    within the tale, Conrad was intent

    not

    to hint however subtly or

    tentatively at

    n ltern tivefr meofreference

    by which we may judg e

    the actions and opinions of his characters. ^ Marlow, a character

    doubly distanced from the reader, in fact realizes that the con-

    quest of the earth, which mostly means the taking it away from

    those who have a different complexion or slighdy flatter noses

    than ourselves, is no t a pretty thing. It is in the person of the

    remarkab le and eloquent Mr. Kurtz tha t Marlow seeks the

    idea thatwillreconcile him to the conquest: An idea at the back

    of it, not a sentimental pretense but an idea; and an unselfish

    belief in the idea.

    As Marlow's steamer penetrates deepe r and deep er into the

    heart of darkness in search of Kurtz's remote trading station,

    Africa becomes increasingly impenetrable to hum an thought.

    In a crucial passage cited yArendt, Marlow observes the Africans

    on the shore:

    Th e prehistoric man was cursing us, praying to us, welcom-

    ing uswho could tell? We. . .glided past like phantoms,

    wondering and secretly appalled, as sane men would be,

    before an enthusiastic outbreak in a madhouse. We could

    not understand because we were too far and could not

    remember, because we were traveling in the night of the

    flrstages,of those ages that a re go ne leaving hardly a sign

    and no memories. . . . The earth seemed unearthly. . .and

    the men were. . .No, they were not inhuman. Well, you

    know, that was the worst of itthis suspicion of their not

    being inhuman. It would come slowly to one. They howled

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    5/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 62 5

    thrilled you was just the thoug ht of their bumanity like

    yoursthe thought of your remote kinship with this wild

    an d passionate uproa r {Conrad, 1988: 37-38).

    Tbe next sentence consists of one word"Ugly"and tbat

    word leads directly to the discovery of Rurtz and his "idea," the

    object of Marlow's quest. He reads a report that Kurtz, who exem

    plifies the European imperialist ("All Europe contributed to [his]

    making"), bas written to the "International Society for the Sup-

    pression of Savage Customs." It is a report in the name of

    progress, of "good practically unbounded," and it gives Marlow a

    sense "of an exotic Immensity ruled by an August Benevolence."

    Except that at tbe bottom of the repo rt's last page, "luminous and

    terrifying like a flash of lightning in a serene sky," Kurtz has

    scrawled "Exterminate all the brutes " Thus no edifying rationale

    of the conquest but sheer r cismisrevealed as the "idea" that M ar-

    low sought, and the darkness of Kurtz's heart becomes the real

    "heart of darkness," rather than the uncivilized but not inhuman

    darkness of Africa.

    The horrific details follow, the decapitated beads of Africans

    stuck on poles, "black, dried, sunken" and "smiling" toward

    Kurtz's dwelling, the Company's "Inner Station." Kurtz is an

    "extremist," his methods "unsound," and, moreover,

    useless

    from

    the point of view of the Manager, according to whom "Mr. Kurtz

    has done more harm than good to the Company." Marlow

    attempts to account forKurtz s"lack of restraint": "the

    wilderness..

    .had

    whispered to him things about himself which he did not know," a

    whisper that "echoed loudly within him because he was hollow at

    the core ." But it is questionab le whether Marlow is m ucb less hol-

    low when, at the climax of his story, he is driven to lie about the

    last words of the dying Kurtz, words spoken in delirium tbat tell

    the plain truth of his exp erience : "The horro r Th e horror " In

    "fright" as well as "infinite pity" Marlow supplants those words

    with wbat Kurtz's "Intended" wisbes tbem to have been, her own

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    6/37

    626 SOCIAL RESEARC H

    As the tale concludes, the indeterminate narrator of Marlow's

    story is leit before the heart of an imm ense darkness, and like-

    wise,

    as the reader apprehends and judges Marlow's story, Con-

    rad's indelible image of racism looms in his consciousness.

    Because Heart of Darkness is a work of imagination that re-pre-

    sents to the reader's mind what is deliberately twice removed

    ro

    his senses, its illumination of race experience is more

    durable and ineluctable than any time-bound chronicle of the

    atrocities com mitted in Leopold IFs Congo , from 1890 to 1910,

    can ever be.'' Not the subject matter but themeaningof this great

    work of art discloses racism as a structural element of a world in

    which it seeks to hide its face, the same world in which totalitari-

    anism, n ot m any years later, made its appearan ce as a new form of

    government.

    Arend t, however, is no t saying that racism or any other elem ent

    of totalitarianism causedthe regimes of Hitler or Stalin, but rath er

    that those hidden elements, which include anti-Semitism, the

    dec line o fth e nation-state, expansionism for its own sake, and the

    alliance between capital and mob, crystallized in the movements

    from whicb those regimes arose. Reflecting on her book when its

    second edition ap peared in 1958, Arend t said that he r inten tions

    presented themselves to he r in the form of an ever recurrin g

    image: I felt as though I dealt with a crystallized structure which I

    had to break up into its constituent elements in order to destroy

    it. This presented a problem because she saw it as an impossible

    task to write history, no t in ord er to save and conserve and rend er

    fit for remembrance, but, on the contrary, in order to destroy.

    Thus regardless of her historical analyses it dawned on he r that

    rigins wasnot a historical. . .but a political book, in which what-

    ever there was of past history not only was seen from the vantage

    point of the present, but would not have become visible at all

    without the light which the event, the emergence of totalitarian-

    ism, shed on it. Th e origins are no t causes; they only becam e

    originsantecedents after the event had taken place. Analyz-

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    7/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 627

    its constituent elemen ts. The impo rtance of this proc edure is

    among the fundamental points Arendt made in the chapter writ-

    ten in 1953 and added to all subsequent editions of Origins Ide-

    ology and Terror: A Novel Form of Government :

    If it strue that the elements of totalitarianism can be found

    by retracing the history and analyzing the political implica-

    tions of what we usually call the crisis of our century, then

    the conclusion is unavoidable that this crisis is no mere

    threat from the outside, no mere result of some aggressive

    foreign policy of either Germany or Russia, and that it will

    no more disappear with the deatb of Stalin than it disap-

    peared with the fall of Nazi Germany. It may even be that

    the true predicaments of our time will assume their authen-

    tic formthough not necessarily tbe cruelestonly when

    totalitarianism has become a thing ofthe past (1973:460).

    According to Aiend t, the disturbing relevance of totalitarian

    regimes. . .is that the true problems of our time cannot be under-

    stood, let alone solved, without the acknowledgment that totali-

    tarianism became this century's curse only because it so

    terrifyingly took care of tsproblem s, problem s raised in one way

    or another by the existence of superfluous or worldless people.

    Her description of the living dead , the inanim ate inmates of

    concentration camps who experienced the full force of the total-

    itarian solution a solution that altered their natu re as hum an

    beingswas and remains at least as shocking as the photographs

    of tbe ditches filled with tbe distorted bodies of the already dead.

    She made her readers realize that there are torments worse than

    de ath , which she evokes in terms ofth e long ing for dea th by those

    who in former times were thought to bave been condemned to

    the eternal punishments of hell. Sbe meant her vision of hell to

    be taken literally and not allegorically, for now hell bad been

    established, no t by divine ju dgm en t in an afterlife, b ut he re on

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    8/37

    628 SOC IAL RESEARC H

    But her further point is that the rejection of the totalitarian

    solution per se provides no answer to the problem that arises

    when raceor religious belief or ethnicityis considered the

    source of human diversity. Hider and Stalin's annihilation of

    superfluous peop le, of naturally dete rm ined inferior races and

    historically de term ine d dying classes, leaves us today, on an

    overcrowded and shrinking planet, with the great and unsolved

    political perplexity of how human plurality c n be conceived, of

    how groups of human beings, historically and culturally distinct

    from one another, c n live together and share a common world.

    Arendt's read ers are left with both tbe trembling insight that

    hum an natu re is not unchangeable and tbe perhaps slightly more

    enc ouraging knowledge that far more is possible than we ha d

    ever thought.

    Arendt adds totalitarianism to the kinds of government previ-

    ously known: monarchy (the rule of one) and its perversion in

    tyranny; aristocracy (the rule of tbe best) and its corruption in oli-

    garchy or the rule of cliques; and democracy (the rule of many)

    and its distortion in ochlocracy or mob rule. The hallmark of

    totalitarianism, a form of rule

    supportedhy

    uprooted masses who

    ironically and also tragically sought a world in which they would

    enjoy public recognition, was the appearance of wbat Arendt, in

    Origins

    called radical and absolute evil. In tha t sense totali-

    tarian regimes are not the opposite of any previously realized

    kind of government, or only of the vain attempts made through-

    ou t the long centuries of Christian belieft realize the city of God

    as a dwelling place for human beings. The lack of any actual

    opposite, which if there were one would establish the place of

    totalitarianism within a new categorical schem e, may be the surest

    way of seeing it as a novel form of government, and as such tbe

    central event not only ofth e twentieth century but o fthe present,

    post-totalitarian world as well.

    When Arendt noted that causality, the explanation of an event

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    9/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 629

    to it, is an altoge ther alien and falsifying category in the histori-

    cal sciences, she mean t that no historical event is ever pre-

    dictable. Although with hindsight it is possible to discern a

    sequence of events, there is always a grotesque disparity between

    that sequence and a particular event's

    meaning.

    What the princi-

    ple of causality ignores or denies is the contingency of human

    affairs; that is, the human capacity

    to begin something new,

    and

    therefore not only the meaning but also the existence of what it

    seeks to explain. It is no t the objective historical scientist bu t the

    impartial judgethe Hotneric

    histor,

    the original historian, was a

    judge^for whom the existence and meaning of events are deci-

    sive.Only then the antecedents of those events can be told in sto-

    ries,

    whose beginnings are never causes and whose conclusions a re

    never determ ined in advan ce.'

    Her rejection of causality and insistence on contingent factors

    in th e course of history inform Arend t's jud gm en t of totalitarian

    crimes against humanity as unpredictable, unpardonable, and in

    the end ungraspable by the human mind. Regarding such crimes

    the old saying

    tout

    comprendrec est

    tout pardonnei'

    as if to under-

    stand an offense, say by its psychological motive, were to excuse

    itdoubly misrepresents the reconciliation that understanding

    does in fact seek. What may be possible is reconciliation

    to the

    world in which totalitarian crimes were committed, which is one

    reason that in

    rigins

    and thereafter Arendt expended so much

    effort in trying to understand that world. But it is important not

    to forget that Arendt's outrage at totalitarianism is not a subjec-

    tive em otiona l reaction foisted on a purportedly value free sci-

    entific analysis;^ her anger is inherent in her judgment of form

    of government that defaced the human world on whose behalf

    she sought to expose Nazism and Stalinism for what they were and

    what they did.

    Yet as usual in Arendt, there is another side to that project.

    Even before she wrote riginsshe spoke of the desperate need to

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    10/37

    630 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    Not only because these facts have changed and poisoned

    the very air we breathe, not only because they now inhabit

    our dreams at night and permeate our thoughts during the

    daybut also because they have become the basic experi-

    ence and tbe basic misery of ou r times. Only from this foun-

    dation, on which a new knowledge of man will rest, can our

    new insights, our new m emories, ou r new deeds, take the ir

    poin t of de pa rture (1994: 200).

    The beginning called for here, if there is to be one, will arise

    from the jud gm en t and actions of m en an d women who know the

    na ture of totalitarianism and agree tbat, for the sake o fth e world,

    it

    must

    not occur again not only in the specific forms in which it

    has already occurred, which may be unlikely, but in any form

    whatsoever. The significance of the story Arendt tells in riginsis

    political, no t only because she wanted to destroy what history con-

    serves, bu t also because her method of storytelling goes against

    the grain of social scientists who purport to explain totalitarian-

    ism objectively, that is, in terms that for Arendt explain away its

    meaning.^ Reflecting some 20 years later on the moment in 1943

    when she first learned about Auschwitz, Arendt said:

    This

    ought

    not to

    havehappened. Tha t ought is not based in transc end ent

    moral values but rather constitutes as strong as possible a state-

    ment that there was something irremissibly wrong with the world

    in which Auschwitz could and did happen, and that that wrong

    must be righted.

    Reconciliation to the world requires that totalitarianism be

    judged,not by subsuming it und er traditional moral, legal, or

    political categories, but by recognizing that it had no precedent,

    that its elements still persist, and that every indication of its

    reem ergence can be resisted. Such judg m en t is possible for

    beings whose essence is beg inning, and reconciliation may fol-

    low only if new roots are struck in the world. Ju dg m en t is the

    oth er side of action and as such the reverse of resignation. It

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    11/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 631

    cal processes that did not cause but led to its emergence would

    remain intact and the bu rde n of ou r time be reaccumulated.^^

    A quotation from Karl Jaspe rs that struck Arend t right in the

    heart and which she chose as the epigraph for rigins stresses

    that what matters is not to give oneself over to the despair of the

    past or the Utopian hop e of the future, bu t to rem ain wholly in

    the present, the temporal dimension of action. Totalitarianism is

    the crisis of our times insofar as the demise of the regimes of

    Hitler and Stalin becomes a turnin g point for thepresentworld, a

    felt political need for the construction of a new world fit for the

    common habitation of all human beings.

    The principle condition of the possibility of such a world, the

    right of every human being to have rights, will be discussed later

    in this essay, but first Arendt's understanding of totalitarianism

    needs to be distinguished from its frequent identification as a par-

    ticularly brutal form of tyranny or despotism. In a tyrannical polit-

    ical realm, which hardly can be called

    public

    the tyrant and the

    people exist in isolation from each other. Due to the lack of

    rap-

    port or legal communication between the people and the tyrant,

    all action in a tyranny manifests a moving princip le of mutua l

    fear: the tyrant's fear ofthe people on one side, and the people's

    fear of the tyrant, or, as Arendt pu t it, their despair over the

    impossibility of jo in ing toge ther to act at all, on the other. It is in

    this sense that tyranny is a contradictory and futile form of gov-

    ernment, one that generates not power but impotence. Hence,

    according to Montesquieu, whose acute observations Arendt drew

    on in these matters, it is a form of government that, unlike con-

    stitutional republics or monarchies, corrupts

    itself

    cultivating

    within itself the seeds of its own destruction . Therefore, the essen-

    tial impotence of a tyrannically ruled state, however fiamboyant

    and spectacular its dying throes maybe ,and regardless of the cru-

    elty and suffering it may infiict on its peop le, presents no menace

    of destruction to the world at large.

    In the early revolutionary stages of development and whenever

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    12/37

    632 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    employ tyrannical measures of force and violence, but their

    nature differs from that of tyrannies precisely in the enormity of

    their thre at of world destruction. That threat has often bee n seen

    as the total politic liz tionof llphases oflife. But Arend t saw it as

    the inversion of the genuinely political: a phenomenon of total

    depolitic liz tion

    {Entpolitisierung

    that appeared for the first time

    in the regimes of Stalin after 1929 and Hider after 1938. Totali-

    tarianism 's radical atomization ofth e whole of society differs from

    the political isolation, or desert as Arendt called it, of

    tyranny.

    It

    eliminates not only free action, which is political by definition,

    but also the element of action, of initiating anything at all, from

    every human activity. Individual spontaneityin thinking, in

    aspiring, and in every creative undertakingwhich sustains and

    renews the human world, is obliterated in totalitarianism. Totali-

    tarianism destroys every potentiality of human life, including

    those of solitude and isolation, which can and frequently bave

    flourished in the circumscribed political realm of tyranny.^'

    In totalitarian society hum an freedom , private as well as pub lic,

    is not even an illusion. Fear is omnipresent but not the source of

    suspicion that in tyranny appears iess as an emotion than as tbe

    principle of the tyrant's action and the people's nonaction.

    Wbereas tyranny, pitting the ruler and his subjects against each

    other, is ultimately powerless, totalitarianism generates immense

    power. It is a new sort of power, no t only exceeding bu t different

    in kind from outward coercive force. In tbe name of ideological

    necessity totalitarian terror dominates human beings

    fromwithin,

    thereby mocking the appearance and also the disappearance, the

    lives and the deaths of distinct and potentially free men and

    wom en. It mocks the world that only a plurality of free individu-

    als can continuously renew and share with one another, and it

    mocks the earth as tbe natural home of such beings. Totalitarian-

    ism mocks everything that is

    given,

    everything that the totalitari-

    ans do not themselves

    make.

    The profound paradox that lies

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    13/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 63 3

    ity, of hum an freedom, of spontaneity and beginning , and the fact

    that thepossibility of that eradication is itself something entirely

    new, made an d bro ught into the world by human beings, must be

    faced, for it lies at the core of Arendt's concept of totalitarianism.

    As Arendt understiinds totalitarianism, its nature is the combi-

    nation of its essence of terror and its principle of logicality. As

    essence terro r must be total more than a means of suppressing

    opposition and more than the most extreme resentment or vin-

    dictiveness. Total terror is, if not reasonable, the rational and con-

    sistent displacement of the role played by positive laws in

    constitutional governments. The result is neither lawless anarchy,

    the war of all against ail, nor the tyrannical abrogation of law, for

    just as a govem ment of laws would becom e perfect in the

    absence of transgressions, so terro r rules suprem e when nobody

    any longer stands in its way. Positive laws in constitu tional gov-

    ernm ents seek to mediate, to translate and realize higher uni-

    versal laws, unalterable divine commandments or fixed natural

    law, but terror is designed to translate in to reality the law of move-

    ment of histoiy or na ture directly, no t in a delimited body politic

    bu t thro ughout mankind. The murderous justice of the laws of

    the motion of history and nature is not mediated but executed

    immediately: for Arend t that is the meaning of totalitarian terror.

    If totalitarianism were perfected, if the entire plurality of

    human beings were to become theembodiment

    of th

    forces of nat-

    ural and historical movement, then its essence of terror would suf-

    fice as its principle of motion. But as long as totalitarianism exists

    in a no n to tali tarian world, it needs the processes of logical or

    dialectical deduction to coerce the hum an m ind into imitating

    and becoming integrated into those suprahum an forces. ^ In

    oth er words, onceit yiel sto thelogic l development

    of th

    idea, not

    as the content but as thepremise

    of

    n ideology, the human mind

    will move as inevitably as natural and historical processes them-

    selves move, against which nothing stands bu t the great capacity

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    14/37

    634 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    alter the direction of their m om entum by starting something

    new. ^^ The twin freedoms of acting and thinking can always pre-

    vent the vise of terror and logicality from closing, which is the rea-

    son that at all costs totalitarian regimes eliminate their every

    manifestation . Yet it is not the political isolation, which frustrates

    action, but the social loneliness of uprooted masses, the loss of

    their

    common

    sense thatis,their sense of comm unity and comm u-

    nication, th at attracts them to ideologicalpre dictationsoi thegoals

    of na ture and history in the first p lac e.''' Impervious to the reality

    of shared ex perien ce, those who have no place in the world, rec-

    ognized and guaranteed by others, are inwardly, benea th th e

    crust of their lives, prepared for totalitarian organization and,

    ultimately, for total domination.

    Both Hider and Stalin came to realize that it was possible to

    eradicate the unpredictability of hum an affairs in the true cen tral

    institution of totalitarian organizational power : the concentration

    camp. What Arendt saw is that eradicating unpredictability

    requires altering the nature of human beings. In the camps the

    internees' deprivation of all rights, even of the ability to make a

    conscientious choice, does

    w y with

    the dynam ic conflict between

    the legality of particular positive laws and the idea of justice on

    which, in constitutional governments, an open and unpredictable

    future depends. On the one hand, in Arendt's concept of totali-

    tarianism, hum an freedom is seen as inconsequential to the

    unden iable autom atism of natural and historical processes, or at

    most as an im pedim ent toi tarfreedom. On the other, when the

    iron band of terro r destroys hum an diversity, so totally dom inat-

    ing human beings that they cease to be individuals and become a

    m ere mass of identical, interchangeable specimens ofthe animal-

    species man, those processes are provided with an incomparable

    instrum ent of acceleration. Terror and logicality welded together

    equip totalitarian regimes witli a previously undreamed of power

    to dominate. But above all it is Arendt's description of how the

    totalitarian systems of Hitler and Stalin inverted political life, of

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    15/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 63 5

    how they subverted the consciences and destroyed the uniqueness

    of hum an beings, which leads directly to the apprehension of what

    she recognized as their crime against humanity.

    The

    rime

    Against Hum anity and The Right

    To

    H ave Rights

    In 963Arendt said that she had been thinking for many years,

    or, to be specific, for thirty years, abou t the na ture of evil. It was

    30 years since the Reichstag was burned in Berlin, an event fol-

    lowed immediately by the Nazis' illegal arrest of thousands of

    their political opponents, mainly but not exclusively communists.

    Innocent of any crime, those detained were taken to the cellars of

    the Cestapo or to concentration camps and subjected to what

    Arend t called monstrous treatm ent. With his political opposi-

    tion effectively forestalled. Hitler could dictate as a matter of pol-

    icy the Jew hatred that in his case was obvious to anyone who

    bothered to read

    Mein

    Kampf the diatribe he dictated in prison

    and publisbed in 1925.Which is to say that with the conso lidation

    of Nazi power anti-Semitism ceased to be merely a social preju-

    dice and became a virulent form of racism: Germany would be

    made judenrein racially purified, first by demoting Jews to the

    status of second-class citizens, then by ridding them of their citi-

    zenship altogether, deporting them, and finally by killing them.

    From that m om ent on Arendt said she felt responsible. But

    responsible for what? She hardly meant that she was responsible

    for having been bo rn a Jew, but that, unlike m any others, she

    could no longer be simply a bystander and would

    respond

    as a

    Jewto tbe attacks on Jewish citizens of her native land. Eventually

    she was led to confront a new kind of criminality, one bent on

    destroying not only Jews bu t h um an plurality as such; and still

    later to determ ine the principlebywhich thislawfulcriminality, in

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    16/37

    636 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    punished. When Hitlerw sdefeated in 1945 incontrovertible evi-

    dence of Nazi factories of exterm ination came to light, and at

    the same time information concerning slave labor camps in the

    Soviet Gulag emerged. Struck by the structural similarity of those

    institutions, Arendt turned her attention to their function in

    Nazism and Stalinism. The camps haunted Arendt's writing until

    Stalin's death in 1953; and then eight years later reemerged on

    the horizon of her thought in the trial of Adolf Eichmann in

    Jerusalem. In one way or another the Nazi camps played a major

    role in the controversy that followed the publication

    of

    ichmann

    In Jerusalem A

    Report

    on

    the

    Banality ofEv ilm 1963, and , al tho ugh

    she ceased to write directly about them after 1966, it is fair to say

    that the overpowering reality of the camps lay behind her pre-

    occupation with the problem of evil that lasted until the end of

    her life.

    Although the containment and brutal elimination of political

    opposition had been a factor in the camps during the revolution-

    ary stages of the rise to power of totalitarian movements, it is in

    the postrevolutionary period, when H itler and Stalin had becom e

    the unopposed leaders of huge populations, that Arendt brought

    them into focus as entirely new phenomena. So-called objective

    enemiesthose guilty of no crime, or of

    possible

    but no t actual

    crimes^were incarcerated without even the pretense of the

    always equivocal legal concept of protective custody. She called

    the knowledge of what acttially transpired in the camps the real

    secret of the secret police that in both cases administered them,

    and she considered, disturbingly, the extent to which this secret

    knowledge corresponds to the secret desires and the secret com-

    plicities of the masses in our time

    (1973:

    437).

    Arendt was not a survivor of the camps, nor did she write in

    empathy (to ber an ethical and cognitive presum ption ) with

    those who had actually experienced total terror. In a revealing

    passage she

    says:

    Only the fearful imag ination of those who have

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    17/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 637

    smitten in their own fiesh, of those who are consequently free

    from the bestial, desperate terror which. . .inexorably paralyzes

    everything that is not mere reaction, can afford to keep thinking

    about horrors, adding that such thinking is useful only for the

    perception of political contexts and the mobilization of political

    passions (1973: 441). The trouble with most accounts from rec-

    ollection or by eyewitnesses is that in direct propordon to their

    authenticity they are unable to com municate things that evade

    hum an understand ing and hum an experience. They are

    doomed to fail if they attempt to explain psychologically or socio-

    logically what cannot be explained either way; that is, to explain

    in terms tha t make sense in the h um an world what does no t make

    sense the re. Moreover, survivors who have resolutely return ed

    to the world of common sense tend to recall the camps as if they

    had m istaken a nightm are for reality. The camps were indeed a

    phantom world Arendt deliberately echoes the appearance of

    Africa to Co nrad 's adventurers that had materialized with all

    the sensual data of reality, bu t to he r that meant not that the sur-

    vivors had experienced a terrifying dream but that they had been

    the victims ofapreviously unknown c rime. On e ofthe underlying

    reasons for the controversy created by Arendt's book on Eich-

    m ann was and remains the failure of many readers, both Jews and

    non-Jews, to transcend the fate of their own peoplebe it doom

    or escapein orde r to judg e what was pernicious for hum anity

    its lf

    The notion ofa crime against humanity had been introduced

    in the Nuremberg trials of major war criminals in 1946, but in

    Arend t's opin ion it was confused the re with crimes against

    peace and war crimes certainly grievous transgressions but

    not crimes against every human beingand had never been

    clearly defined nor its perpetrators properly identified with

    regard to what it was they had done. To Arendt the genocide of

    the

    ews

    throughout Nazi-controlled Europe was a crime against

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    18/37

    6 3 8 S O C I A L R E S E A R C H

    pe op le which violated the or de r of m an kin d. . .and an al to-

    ge the r different com mun ity, namely, the comity ofall the natio ns

    of the world. It req uires b oth imag ination a nd the steadfastness of

    h u m a n solidarity to face what A ren dt m ea nt by the absolute evil

    of totalitarianism, to see that, in the case of the Nazis, what is

    at tributa ble to the long history of Jew-h atred an d anti-Semitism

    is only the choice of victims [an d] n ot the na tu re of the c rime.

    In the cam ps H itler an d Stalin fully realized mo der nity's con-

    te m pt for reality, for wh at is given and no t self-made, go ing far

    bey ond the cynical an d nihilistic no tion th at everything is per-

    m itted to the insane prop osit ion that everything is possible.

    A re nd t un de rsto od the camp s as laboratories in which experi-

    m ents were condu cted to tes t that proposi t ion, and what those

    expe rimen ts dem ons trated was that the om nipo tenc e of

    man

    can be bo ug ht at the price of the superfluity of

    men.

    In the

    cam ps hu m an beings were m ad e into one utterly pred ictable liv-

    ing corpse, a body per m an en tly in the process of dying. M en

    and wo me n were red uce d to the lowest com m on de no m ina tor of

    organ ic l ife, re nd er ed equal in the sense of be ing

    interchange-

    able,

    an inh um an equality that stands in the sharpe st possible

    contrast to political equality. If political equality is an equality of

    peers ,

    the achievement of a plurality of distinct individuals who of

    their own will join tog eth er to ge ne rate the pow er requ ired to

    affect the cours e of the ir wo rld, th en the equality of the cam ps

    is of un diffe ren tiated hu m an being s dep rived of every relation to

    an yth ing like a wo rld: in A ren dt's words, to be sup erflu ous

    means not to belong to the world at all .

    H um an exis tence, accord ing to Are ndt , is in part con di t ioned

    and in part free, but in the camps terror corroded the part that is

    free. Unlike fear that is intelligible in its relation to an object in

    the world, or to the objectivity of a threatening world, terror

    con-

    ditions

    hu m an beings in mu ch the same way that the beh avior of

    animals can be conditioned by electric shock. Systematically

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    19/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 63 9

    in the ho pe of being fed, much as Pavlov's dog (to Arendt a per-

    verted animal) was conditione d to salivate not when it was hun-

    gry but when a bell was rung.^^ In the contrived, inhuman, but

    rationally consistent nonw orld of the camps, innocence is

    beyond virtue and guilt is beyond crime : the categories of inno-

    cence and guilt, right and wrong, virtue and vice, and almost

    everything else that since time immemorial has been associated

    with the specific natu re of hum an beings ceased to make sense. As

    yet, at least as far as is known, the totalitarian camps are the only

    places on earth where the dehumanization of man was scientifi-

    cally implemented and systematically carried out, not for any

    com prehensible purpose but for its own sake.

    When com pared with its insane end-result, the assault on

    human nature in the camps was methodological and threefold.

    The first, essential step was the destruction of jur idica l or polit-

    ical man by disfranchisement; second, the moral person was

    destroyed by rendering his or her conscience impotent; and

    third , the unique identity of the individual was obliterated by

    annihilating the human capacity for spontaneity in thought and

    action. Disfranchisement means the elim ination of every legal sta-

    tus, including that of ordinary criminals. Human beings are sub-

    jected to torment not only unfit for any conceivable crime but

    also unconnected to anything they have done; they are punished

    for having been born a Jew, for being the representative of a dying

    class,

    for being asocial, or mentally ill, or the carrier of a disease.

    New categories would have to be invented when old categories

    became exhausted, or victims would have to be selected

    randomly

    as in fact they were in Stalin's more perfect system. The arbi-

    trariness of the choice of victims aims at destroying the civil

    rights of the whole population , and that destruction is carried

    ou t ne ithe r by indo ctrination no r brainwashing, for it is no t con-

    sent {which implies the possihility of dissent) tha t is wanted b ut

    only discipline. The destruction of jurid ical or political man is

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    20/37

    640 SOC IAL RESEARC H

    Next, the ability to make a conscientious choice is eliminated.

    Prisoners are made to choose not between good and evil but

    between evil and evil. When a mother is forced to choose one of

    her children to be murdered in order to save the life (or post-

    pone the death) of another, she is implicated in the crime com-

    mitted against her. Martyrdom is not possible since the camps are

    what Arendt called holes of oblivion, places completely cut off

    from the outside world in which a martyr's story might be told,

    remembered, and become an example for others. The dead are

    imm ediately forgotten as if they had never existed, their deaths

    as superfluous as their lives had been. Einally, the concentration

    of human beings, massing them together and binding them in

    terror's band of iron, destroys every relation to and distinction

    from one another. They are submitted to torture, not to learn

    what they know but to so hu rt them that they become bund les of

    insensate flesh. Their spontaneityis,as it were, wm ng from them :

    ren dered incapable of acting or thinking, they drift 'like dum -

    mies to their death,' ^^ no more than living fuel for the engines

    of destruction. In the slave labor camps of the Gulag, with their

    supposed economic rationale,'^ the

    l borers

    are starved or frozen

    to death, at once replaced by others whose lives and deaths are

    made no less superfluous than those of their predecessors.

    To grasp the evil of totalitarian criminality requires a mental

    perspective in which the experience of being superfluousthe

    loneliness of not belonging to the world, the sense of the futility

    of livingis reflected. That experience was forced by terror on

    those condemned to die, but Arendt saw further that the func-

    tioning of the laboratories of extermination dep ended on the

    changed nature of the condemners. She was of course aware of

    the gulf in terms of human suffering that separates the two, but

    her point was that the condemners themselves were superfluous

    as human beings. S.S. officers were selected by photographs, by

    objective racial characteristics rath er than by interviews in

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    21/37

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    22/37

    642 SOC IAL RESEARC H

    There is no ready answer to that questioiT. In the Nazi case it is

    well known that Hitler's inexorable will to dehumanize those who

    presen ted no threat to him hin de red his ability to fight effectively

    against his real enemies at the end of World War II. What is the

    po int of dom inating men at any cost, not as they

    are,

    no t for any

    utilitarian purp ose, but in ord er to change the ir very nature ? If

    it is for th e sake of the consistency of a lying world order, as

    Arendt went on to suggest, what is the sense of system that even

    if it succeeded in destroying the hum an world ouldno t end in the

    creation of a thousand-year Reich or Messianic Age but only

    in self-destruction? For the sheer destructive momentum of total-

    itarianism is like a jugg erna ut or fireball that if unchecked could

    ravage and reduce the hum an world to ashes until therew snoth-

    ing left for it but to wield on and consumeitself (In an admittedly

    minorw ythis anti-utilitarianism is foreshadowed in Co nrad's Mr.

    Kurtz, whose extremism did more harm than good to the Com-

    pany for which he worked.)

    Tha t totalitarianism appeared in two major Eu ropean countries

    at almost the same time is an irrevocable reality in the history of

    our world. Because its reappearance in some form is more easily

    imagined than its first occurrences ever were, there are certainly

    important lessons to be learned from its origins or elements.

    Today the widespread existence of uprooted masses, of millions

    and in some areas of the world generations of homeless, unedu-

    cated refugees, alienated from anything like a com mon world and

    ripe for th e logical dictates of one or ano the r ideology, constitutes

    such a lesson. But it must also be remembered that from first to

    last for Arendt, the evildoing of totalitarian domination was

    beyond sinfulness and without hum anly com prehensible

    motives. It is one th ing to conceive totalitarianism as a novel

    form of government, but to account for men whose acts are

    inconceivable is another.

    When Eichmann was taken captive in Argentina by agents of

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    23/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 64 3

    saw an opportunity, unusual for philosophers, to confront the

    realm of hu m an affairs and hu m an deeds. . .directly. She

    reported on the trial forThe New

    Yorker im^dzine

    and shortly after

    ichmann in ferusalemwas published, prom pted hy questions suh-

    mitted by a journa list, she reflected on why she, a writer and

    teacher of political philosophy. . .had. . .undertaken a reporter's

    job (1963b). It was, she said, because the trial offered her the

    opportunity to encou nte r in the flesh a notorious Nazi criminal,

    and she was eager to grasp, if possible, hisindividual^\\\\i whyhe

    had done what he did, which, she adde d, was not relevant to he r

    m ore theoretical considerations in

    Origins.

    In the earlier work she

    had dea lt with the type of totalitarian criminal, bu t now she

    sought to know Who was Eichmann? and What were his deeds,

    not insofar as his crimes were part and parcel of the Nazi system

    bu t insofar as he was a hum an being? She had , she said, the wish

    to expose myselfnot to the deeds which, after all, were well

    knownbut to the evildoer

    himself.

    She maintained that her report of the trial did not go beyond

    the evidence p resen ted in testimony, but she fit that evidence into

    an ominously meaningful story. The facts alone tend to become

    less and less significant with the passage of time; their recitation

    today all too often makes them seem unreal, as if listening to

    them after many years set up a shield against the experiences of

    terror and human destruction that they circumstantiate. Arendt's

    story provides no such shield. It enabled her, as it may enab le us,

    to see in Eichmann a most unexpected perpetrator of this new

    criminality and by judging him forswear the processes of dehu-

    manization in a world in which their possibility nevertheless

    remains real.

    There are several important respects in which Eichmann in

    ferusalem

    differs from

    Origins

    and Arendt laid considerable

    emphasis on these differences in a number of letters. To Mary

    McCarthy she mentioned three (Arendt, 1995). She wrote, first,

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    24/37

    644 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    because there are simply too many people in the world to make

    oblivion possible. Second, she realized that Eichmann was

    m uch less infiuenced by ideology than she would have assumed

    before attend ing the trial: exterm ination per se, she found, did

    not depend on an ideology or its logic. Third, she said that the

    phrase the banality of evil stands in contrast to. . .'radical evil.'

    She developed this contrast in greater detail in a letter to Ger-

    shom Scholem (Arendt, 1978b): It is indeed my opinion now

    that evil is never 'radical,' that it is only extrem e. Thoug ht tries

    to reach some depth, to go to the roots, and the moment it con-

    cerns itself with evil, it is frustrated. Th at th ere is no thing in evil

    for thought to latch on to is what Arendt m eant by the banality of

    evil: not that Eichm ann's acts are com monplace, hu t that the mas-

    siveness ofthe evil he infiicted on the world

    defies

    thoughO^

    In a subsequent letter to McCarthy, who had written of the

    mor l exhil r tion that reading

    Eichmann Inferusalem

    afforded her,

    Arend t noted: you were the only reader to understand what oth-

    erwise I have never admittednamely that I wrote this book in a

    state of euph oria. In a letter to a Germ an corresp ond ent, she

    said that 20 years after she had learned of the existence of

    Auschwitz she experienced acur

    posterior

    thatis,a healing of he r

    inability to think through to its roo t in the acts of men the evil of

    totalitarian criminality. The posterior or later cure is also impor-

    tant in the sense that for Arendt the terrible injury infiicted on

    the Jewish peo ple would at long last ppe r as a crime against

    humanity, and the exemplary criminal capable of that incom-

    prehen sihle crime, in the person of Eichm ann, who

    w s

    not even

    an anti-Semite, be identified.

    Arendt saw Eichm ann , on trial for his life, as a buffoon whose

    inability to speak was closely connected with an inability to

    think

    namely, to think from the standpoint of somebody

    else.

    No com munication was possible with him, not because

    he lied bu t because he was surro unded by the most reliable

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    25/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 645

    ers, and henc e against reality as such. . . . [It was] proof

    against reason and argument and information and insight

    of any kind (1963a: 49, 78).

    But, and this is what is ominous, his inability to reflect on and

    judge his own acts also led Arendt to see that Eichmann was not

    corruptible. Having overcome and in his case even forgotten

    any natural inclination he may once have had to hinder the trans-

    portation of millions of innocent Jews to their ann ihilation in

    Auschwitz, Eichmann boasted that he had done his duty to the

    end. Unlike those mem bers of the S.S. who attem pted to negoti-

    ate with the enemy when it becam e clear that the Nazi cause was

    lost, Eichm ann declared that he had lived his whole life. .

    .according to a Kantian definition of

    duty ;

    and to the surprise of

    everybody, [he] cam e up with an approximately correct definition

    of [Kant's] categorical imperative, even though he had dis-

    torted it in practice. Arendt recognized , moreover, that Eich-

    mann's distortion agrees with what he called the version of Kant

    'for the househ old use of the little m an ,' the identification of

    one's will with the source of law, which for Eichm ann was no t

    pure practical reason but, and regardless of its logicality, simply

    what theFUhrerw lWed. He supported and carried out the physi-

    cal destruction of European Jewiy and would have done the same

    for any group or anyone at all whom a power he deemed higher

    than himself had decreed unfit to live. He could be relied on to

    do whatever his conscience assured him was his duty.

    Perhaps the most provocative aspect of ichmann

    in

    ferusalem is

    its account of human conscience. Th e refusal of the court to con-

    sider seriously the question of Eichm ann's conscience resulted in

    its failure to confront w hat Arend t called the central moral, legal,

    and political ph en om en a of our century. Th e Israeli judg es

    understood conscience traditionally as the voice of God orlumen

    naturale speaking or shining in every human soul, telling or illu-

    m inating the difference between righ t and

    wrong.

    This simply did

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    26/37

    646 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    an d it seems to have ftinctioned in the expected way for a few

    weeks after he became engaged in the transport of

    Jews,

    and then,

    when he heard no voice saying hou shall not killbut on the con-

    trary every voice saying hou shallkill it began to function the

    oth er way aroun d. If the phen om eno n of a changeable con-

    science indicates a moral collapse, Arend tw sconvinced by tes-

    timony presented at the trial that this collapse was widespread

    throughout Europe, from which even respected members of the

    Jevidsh leadership were not exempt.'^ And if this collapse led her

    subsequently to dismantle moral philosophy, not to reveal moral

    phenomena as ilkisory (as Nietzsche had attempted to do) but to

    strip them of their traditional trappings, for her it also lay at the

    core of the proceedings in Jerusalem .

    Eichmann was neither stupid nor hostile: he knew and for the

    most part admitted his acts but could no more reflect on their

    m eaning in Jerusalem than durin g his career in the S.S. He con-

    tradicted himself constantly b ut he d id not lie, his conscience was

    clear, and he did not suffer from rem orse: He knew that what he

    had once called his duty

    w s

    now called a crime, and be accepted

    this new code of Jud gm ent as if it were noth ing btit ano the r lan-

    guage rule. ^*^ From the m om ent he was cap tured he expected to

    die,

    but on what

    legalground

    could his criminality be judge d to

    warrant the death sentence? If, as Arend t believed, intent to do

    wrong was no t proved against Eichmann, and if therefore the

    court's judg m en t was anything like a language rule expressing

    the Justice, if not of the victor, then of the injureda kind of

    vengeancethen that Judgm ent could not be gro und ed at all:

    after another war with a different outcome it could change to

    ano ther language rule, and go on and on changing.

    Vengeance was a topic tbat Arendt had considered in

    The

    Human Condition

    published three years before the Eichmann

    trial. There she interpreted Jesus of Nazareth's injunction to for-

    give trespasses as the buman power to break an otherwise irre-

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    27/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 647

    previous ones, ad infinitum. Forgiveness is no mere reaction to a

    trespass but an unpredictable, spontaneous, free action marking

    an end to what is forgiven and opening the way to a new begin-

    ning. As a human action forgiveness is not unconditional: it can

    only take place between the trespasser who "repents," changes his

    mind, and wants to start anew, and the forgiver who releases him.

    Yet in th e same passage Arendt also cites Jesus on certain offenses

    or stumbling blocks {scandala that, unlike trespasses, cannot be

    forgiven: "Woe un to him, through w hom they com e It were bet-

    ter for him that a millstone were hanged about his neck, and he

    cast into the sea." To Ai-endt this meant tha t such offensesshe

    was clearly thinking o fth e radical evil of totalitarianism also can-

    not be punished, for to imprison or peremptorily terminate the

    finite life of a mass murderer is ludicrous as an act of retribudon

    (tha t is, as adequate or jus t p un ishm ent) because of its lack of

    symmetry with the crime in question.^^ She concludes that the

    inability to forgive an oftense that cannot be punished, and vice

    versa, is an important "structural element in the realm of human

    affairs," for such offenses "transcend [that] realm. . .and the

    potentialities of human power, both of which they radically

    destroy wherever they make their appearance." What cannot be

    forgiven, pardoned,^'^ or punished would therefore presumably

    hinde r th e hum an power to start anew, although that is no t stated

    explicitly in this passage (1958c: 238-41).

    When Arendtw spresent at Eichm ann's trial in Jerusalem , this

    same matter arose in far greater specificity. She objected thatjus-

    tice would not appear to be done in the Israeli court's judgment

    that Eichmann be executed because he intended wrong to the

    Jewish peopleas if his conscience "must" have told him that

    what he was doing transgressed the commandment "Thou shall

    not kill"and therefore was morally guilty of capital crimes

    against Jews. She then substituted he r own jud gm en t of Eich-

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    28/37

    648 SOCIAL RESEARC H

    [ ]

    ust

    as

    you supported and carried ou t a policy of no t want-

    ing to share the ea rth with the Jewish peop le and the peo-

    ple of a number of other nationsas though you and your

    superiors had any right to determine who should and who

    should not inhabit the worldwe find tbat no one, that is,

    no m emb er of the hu m an race, can be expected to want to

    share the earth with you. This is the reason, and the only

    reason, you must hang

    (1963:

    279).

    Arend t's Jud gm ent cann ot be mistaken for a "language rule":

    it entails nothing like a tit for a tat, nothing like revenge, nor

    does it imply that the death sentence is an adequate punishment

    for E ichman n's unpa rdon able deeds. The power of the Judg-

    ment she exercised, however, may be considered an act of ret-

    ributive Justice, but only if its symmetry with Eichm ann's crimes

    is seen on a political ra tbe r than a moral level. For even if he did

    not intend wrong be nevertheless violated tbe status of every

    human being, including his own, not only by supporting tbe

    extermination of a specific people or peoples, but by violating

    the plurality "of mankind in its entirety." For her this is the real

    politi l crime against humanity, that is, against the human con-

    dition and the human world, against "human diversity as such. .

    .without wbich the very words 'm an kin d' or 'hum anity' w ould be

    devoid of meaning."

    Having listened to Eichmann, whose psychological profile was

    normal, Arendt determined that he was not a "monster" but dis-

    tinguished from most bu t by no m eans al othe r people only by

    his "authentic" incapacity for ordinary reflective tbought. Arendt

    saw this incapacity as the negation of human plurality; as such it

    gave birtb to tbe expression "the banality of evil," the use of which

    she la ter felt th e need to Justify philosophically because of its

    widespread and perhaps understandable misrepresentation as a

    trivialization, or even exculpation, of the criminality of Eich-

    mann. Hardly a hint of what became her immense final task can

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    29/37

    AREND T ON TOTALITARIANISM 64 9

    covery that what traditional morality had tho ught of as the

    voice of

    conscience is in fact theactualizationof consciousness in the activ-

    ity of thinking. That discovery, prompted by Eichmann's mean-

    ingless words, rendered concrete the relation of thoughtlessness

    to evildoing and opened the way to the justification she sought.

    What is most elusive and difficult to grasp is tha t Arendt m eant lit-

    erally the ctivityof thinking and not its results, no t things

    though t no m atter how profound they mightbe.She certainlyw s

    not stating a new moral theorem from which new rules might be

    derived, which in turn could only dissolve in further thinking, or

    becom e customs and habits as changeable as table m anners or

    Eichmann's coascience.

    What Arendt meant by the

    actualization

    of consciousness was

    not consciousness in the psychological sense but a knowing-with-

    oneself

    {con-scientia

    that imposes limits when it is experienced.

    The crucial point is that the activity of thinking provides an

    intense a nd ineluctab le ex^mence of

    plurality:

    the activity of think-

    ing, that is, the actuality of the silent dialogue with

    oneself

    dis-

    closes a difference within the identity of the thinker. At a speed

    greater than lightn ing these two-in-one, as she called them , con-

    verse as long as the activity of thinking lasts. She further found

    that these thinking partners have to be on good terms, essen-

    tially in agreement, because they cannot

    go on

    or

    resume

    thinking

    if they contradict and become estranged from one other. Arendt

    grounded, existentially, the law of contradiction, of which Eich-

    m ann was entirely oblivious, in this congeniality ofthe two-in-one.

    By the same token it is in the activity of thinking that the specifi-

    cally

    human

    relationship between a plurality, though it be only of

    two,

    is philosophically established as the

    political

    condition of the

    great plurality of mankind. The reahty ofthe concept of human-

    ity, no ted as ugly by Marlow in Conrad's tale, became horrify-

    ingly explicit in Hider and S talin's claim to global rule, bu t here

    it is the sheer activity of thinking that makes a human being not

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    30/37

    650 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    right of oth er hu m an beings to inhabit the world and share the

    earth. Socrates, who lived thoughtfully with himself in solitude

    and in public\nth the citizens of Athens, was convinced that itw s

    better for him to take his own life than to renounce the thinking

    that bound him to himself

    and

    to his city, a renunciation that

    would have left him in abject loneliness. In the many references

    to him in Arendt's late work Socrates stands forth as the diamet-

    ric opposite of Eich mann , no t because of any doc trine, of which

    he had none, but because he cared more for the activity of think-

    ing, with himself and others, than for a life without meaning.

    In he r critical lectures on moral philosophy delivered after and

    largely in response to the storm of controversy unleashed by her

    accotxnt of the Eicbm ann trial, Arendt repeats the saying of Jesvis

    cited earlier, emphasizing that It were be tterfor

    him

    that a mill-

    stone were hanged about his neck, and he cast into tbe sea.

    Because he sent millions of human beings to die in Auschwitz by

    failing to recognize their humanity, even or especially if he was

    incapable of that recognition, from the po int of view of the world

    it vifasbetter for ichmannthat he be rid of his life. That is neithe r

    pardon no r pu nishmen t, but Justice rend ered according to what

    was for Arendt tbe immanent political law of buman plurality:

    the fact that men, not Man, live on the earth and inhabit the

    world. Had Arendt's Judgm ent been th e court's Judgm ent, Jus-

    tice, a political virtue, would not only have been done in

    Jerusalem but also would have been seen to be done throughout

    tbe w orld. And what is most imp ortant, the hum an power of Jews

    and others, including their enemies, to make a new beginning

    would have been revivified, and maybe even actualized, if in the

    world's eyes Eicbmann had appeared as

    hostis humanisgeneris

    an

    enemy of every hum an being.

    With the establishm ent of the state of Israel Jews were finally

    able to sit in judg m en t on crimes comm itted against their own

    people ; they no longer needed to appeal to others for protec-

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    31/37

    AREND T ON TOTALITARIANISM 651

    of the rights of man. When she wrote rigins Arendt already

    knew that universal human rights are a chimera for those

    excluded from the power required to enforce them. She knew

    from her own experience that despite any proclamation of their

    universality such rights are not indepen den t of hum an plurality,

    are

    not

    innate, and are

    not

    possessed by hu m an beings expelled

    from the hum an comm unity. In rigins shetherefore spoke of a

    righ t to have rights, a right to live in a framework where one is

    jud ged by one 's actions and opinions, and it was that right that

    she strove to make visible as the fundamental principle of hum an

    solidarity, the new foundation of human com munity as such.

    Were that community to arise it would stand in positive opposi-

    tion to totalitarianism. Unlike the traditional way of reading the

    categorical scheme of forms of government, however, this world

    political community, which wouldnotaspire to global ru le, would

    succeed totalitarianism, of which Arendt believed it alone could

    right the terrible wrong.

    She wrote:

    Corresponding to the one crime against humanity is the

    one human right. Like all other rights, it can exist only

    through mutual agreement and guarantee. Transcending

    the rights ofthe citizenbeing the right of man to citizen-

    shipthis right is the only one that can and can only be

    gua ranteed by the comity of nations.

    (1951;

    437)

    As the source of the rights of freedom and justice , the right to

    have rights can be politically secu red only if it is established as

    the principal tene t of international law, a law above nations , the

    enforcem ent of which would be legally bind ing on all peoples an d

    all nations , supersed ing any rules of sovereignty. ' - Tha t may

    seem unlikely to occur, bu t it surely is no t impossible in a world in

    which we know totalitarianism to be possible. In fact, it is unlikely

    only insofar as we continue to think politically and make political

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    32/37

    652 SOC IAL RESEARC H

    adventof totalitarianism demonstrated that utilitarian thinkingis

    no longerofuseinrespondingto theproblemsand perplexities

    ofourworld. What Arendt called the oldutilitarian equationof

    the good withthe 'goodfor' some pre-existing given entity can-

    not suffice

    for a

    eginning

    as

    unprecedented

    as

    totalitarianism

    itself. It is of

    this beginning that

    in

    time totalitarianism would

    unequivocally

    be

    seen

    as the

    inversion, jus t

    as

    tyranny m ore than

    two millennia

    ago was

    seen

    as the

    perversion

    of the

    monarchy

    that historicallyitpreceded. W hatismeantis not the restoration

    of anything like

    a

    monarchical form

    of

    government,

    but

    rather

    thatthe oneprinciple,themonos arche of the beginning Arendt

    calledforwouldbe the rightto thehuman conditionitself, the

    prepolitical, prelegal, and so to speak, the prehistorical

    foundation of aworldin which human beings live together with

    some degree offreedom and justice, even if not in perpetual

    peace.

    All

    rights spring from human plurality, including

    the

    transcending right

    to

    have rights, which c ann ot

    be

    conceived

    as

    a moral right

    in any

    traditional sense,

    lt is the one

    right directly

    derived from Arendt's philosophic establishment

    of the

    imma-

    nent lawof human pluralityon earth.

    Well before

    she

    went

    t

    Jerusalem

    to

    report

    on the

    Eichmann

    trial Arendt had spoken of the thunder of the explosion of

    totalitarian domination that nevertheless leavesussilent when-

    ever we dare

    to ask, not

    'What

    are we

    fighting

    against

    but

    'What

    arewefighting/or?' ^ She did not answer that question directly,

    perhaps becauseat thetimeshe did notknowhow toformulatea

    more compelling answer thanshe had already given in Origins

    and perhaps because

    she

    wanted

    her

    readers

    to

    think

    the

    ques-

    tion through

    and

    answer

    it for

    themselves.

    Be

    that

    as it may, I

    believe that after having recognized

    the

    limitless potentiality

    of

    evil

    in

    sheer thoughtlessness Arendt cons idered fighting/or''

    the

    political confirmation ofthe human right

    to

    have rights

    the

    high-

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    33/37

    ARENDT ON TOTALITARIANISM 65 3

    Notes

    ^There is also the complexity of the relation of the book's first two

    parts on Antisemitism and Imperialism to its third on Totalitarian-

    ism, which is not treated here. Tam iniaux's and Tsao's papers in this

    issue ofSocial Researchdeal with some of the pertinent issues.

    ^This would no t be the em ptiness, of course, of Heidegger's idealized

    understanding of National Socialism in the 1930s, but more like what

    Margaret Canovan has written, in a brilliant and challenging article,

    about viewing Nazism and Stalinism. . .as inca rna tions of an alien pres-

    ence,

    vehicles through which the monster 'totalitarianism' worked its

    mysterious will. See Canovan (2000: 38).

    ^For one view of the positive relationship of hum an freedom to poli-

    tics,

    see Kohn (2000).

    *Which Chinua Achebe says he ought to have done; see Conrad

    (1988:256, emphasis a dd ed ).

    ^'Writing in 1917 for a new edition ofHeartof

    D arkness,

    first published

    in 1899, Com ad said that its composition had been more than a feat of

    memory. Itw slike ano ther art altogether. Tha t somber them e had to

    be given a sinister resonance, a tonality ofitsown, a con tinue d vibration

    that, I hoped, would hang on the air and dwell on the ear after the last

    no te had been struck (Conrad, 1988: 4) .

    *^Cf. Arendt {1978a: 216).

    'Considerably later Arendt restates this point. To he meaningful, even

    to exist at ail, facts must be fitted into a story, for they have no con-

    clusive reason for being what they are; they could always have been oth-

    erwise Arendt. Truth and Politics (1968a: 238, 242).

    '^Such a view, as Arendt points out, accurately describes many histori-

    cal accounts of anti-Semitism and, it may be added, none more so than

    D.

    J . Goldhagen 's

    Hitler s Willing Executioners: Ordinary Germans and the

    Holocaust(1996).

    ^ The story reveals the meaning of what otherwise would remain an

    imbearable sequence of sheer happenings. . .storytelling reveals mean-

    ing without committing the error of defining it [and] brings about. .

    .reconciliation with things as they really are . Stories tell again and

    again how at the end we shall be privileged to jud ge . Arendt (1968b:

    104-05).

    ^^

    The urden

    of

    Our Time was

    the title ofthe first British edition (Lon-

    don, 1951) of

    7 he Origins of Totalitarianism.

    ^'For Arendt it is of no small importance that such a flourishing

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    34/37

    654 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    ^^According to Arendt, stringent logicality as a guide to action [was]

    exclusively the work of Hitler and Stalin, indeed their only add ition to

    the ideas and propaga nda slogans of their movements.

    ^%ee Arendt's later discussion of the miracle of such interruptive

    action in What Is Freedom ? (1968a: 168-71).

    *In fact, Aren dt sees the movem ent of history and the m ovem ent of

    na ture [as] one and the same. Nature is swept into history when bio-

    logical life is viewed as an inevitable development (1973:463).

    ^^Arendt quotes the Polish poet Tadeusz Borowski on his experience

    in Auschwitz: 'Never before was hope stronge r than m an, and never

    before did hope result in so much evil. . . . We were taught not to give

    up hope . That is why we die in the gas oven.' Agreeing that

    hope

    stronger than

    man is destructive of the veiy humanity of man, she adds

    that the victims' innocence , even from the viewpoint of their persecu-

    tors, further dehum anizes them : that their apathy toward their own

    dea th is the almost physical, automatic response to the challenge of

    absolutemeaninglessness.

    See Arendt (1964a: 90).

    ^'^Rousset (1947), quoted by Arendt (1973).

    ''The only time this rationale was partially adhered to was during

    World War II.

    ^^From the first the notion of the

    banality

    of

    evil

    proved highly con-

    tentious and it is still a problem for some of the most astute expositors

    of Arendt's thought.

    ^ A year later writing about Rolf Hoc hhuth 's

    The

    Deputy, Aiendt

    found that the wartime Roman Catholic pope, Pius XII, was not exempt

    either. See Arendt (1964b).

    ' As Arendt pu t it later in Thinking and Moral Considerations: A

    Lecture (1971:417).

    ^*In the same vein regarding the Nuremberg trials, Rene Char wrote

    with great force: The extent of the crime renders the crime un think-

    able, but its science perceptible. To evaluate it is to admit the hypothe-

    sis of the crim inal's irresponsibility. Yetanyman,fortuitously or not, can

    be hanged. This equality is intolerable. Quoted in Caws (1977: 31).

    '^^In a letter to W. H. Auden, dated 14 February 1960, Arendt admit-

    ted You are entirely right (and I was entirely wrong) tha t pu nish ment

    is a necessary alternative only to jud icial pardon . But this shows only

    that Arendt

    w s

    already po inting to the public, political na ture of crimes

    against humanity, crimes that transcend the realm of Christian charity

    to which, in the same letter and unlike her correspondent, though

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    35/37

    A R E N D T O N T O T A L I T A R I A N I S M 6 5 5

    the rare cases of extreme evil. Roy Tsao has addressed this important

    issue in an unpublished article, Arendt and Auden: Finding Hom e and

    Facing Evil in the Modern World.

    ^^Arendt consistently opposed sovereignty, in nations as in individu-

    als,

    as a power above law, in both cases contrad icting the law of hum an

    plurality.

    ^^ Tradition and the M odern Age in Arendt {1968a: 27). This essay

    is taken in its entirety from Arendt's Marx manuscripts of 1953-54.

    References

    Arendt, Hannah.The Chiginsof Totalitarianism. 1st. ed. New

    York

    1951.

    . Totalitarianism.

    The Meridian

    (Fall 1958a).

    . Freiheitund

    Politik.

    Die neue Rundschau69:4 (1958b).

    .The Human Condition. Chicago, 1958c.

    . Le tter to W. H. Auden (1960). Arendt C ollection. Library of

    Congress, Manuscript Division, Washington, D.C.

    .Eichmann inferusalem. New York, 1963a.

    . Samuel Gratton document (1963b). Arendt Collection. Library

    of Congress, Manuscript Division, Washington, D.C.

    . The Destruction of Six Million. . .Why did the World Rem ain

    Silent?

    Thefewish World

    (September, 1964a).

    . The

    Deputy.

    Guilt by Silence. The Storm Over the

    Deputy.

    Ed. E.

    Bentley.

    ew

    York 1964b: 85-94.

    .Betiveen Pastand Future.New York, 1968a.

    ,Men In Dark Times.New York, 1968b.

    . Thinking and Moral Considerations: A Lecture. Social Research

    38:3 (Fall 1971).

    .The Originsof Totalitarianism. 5th ed. New York, 1973.

    .The Lifeofthe

    Mind.

    Vol. I:

    Thinking.

    New York, 1978a.

    . Letter to Cershom Scholem, 24 July 1963.Thefeiu AsPariah:fetD-

    ish IdentityandPolitics in the ModemAge.Ed. R. Feldman. ewYork,

    1978b.

    .

    Hannah

    Arendt,

    Karl faspers:

    Correspondence 1926-1969. Eds. L.

    Kohler and H. Saner. New York, 1992.

    .Essays inUnderstanding, 1930-1954. Ed. J. Kohn.

    ew

    York 1994.

    Han?iahArendt, Mary McCarthy:Betxoeen Friends. Correspondence

    1949-1975. ewYork 1995.

    Caws, Mary Ann.Rene

    Char.

    Boston, 1977.

    Conrad, Joseph.Heartof Darkness. Norton Critical Ed. Sd ed. Ed. Robert

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    36/37

    656 SOCIAL RESEARCH

    Cano van, Margaret . Aren dt 's Th eory of Total i tar ianism.

    The ambridge

    Companion to Hannah Arendt

    Ed. D. Villa. Cambridge, 2000.

    Go ldhagen, D . J .

    Hitler s W illing Executioners: Ordinary Cermans and the

    Holocaust. N ew York, 19 96.

    K oh n, J. Fre edo m : T he Priority of the Political. The

    ambridge

    Com-

    panion to Hanna h Arendt Ed. D. Villa. Cambridge, 2000: 113-129.

    Rousset, David.

    Les jours denotremoit

    Paris, 1947.

  • 8/9/2019 Arendt's Concept and Description of Totalitarism - Kohn.pdf

    37/37